Skip to main content

Full text of "A system of logic, ratiocinative and inductive : being a connected view of the principles of evidence and the methods of scientific investigation"

See other formats


A 


SYSTEM OF LOGIC 

RATIOCINATIVE AND INDUCTIVE 


BEING A CONNECTED VIEW OF THE 


PRINCIPLES OF EVIDENCE 
AND THE 


METHODS OF SCIENTIFIC INVESTIGATION 


JOHN STU 



MILL 


IN TWO VOLUMES 
VOL. I. 

SEVENTH EDITION' 


LONDON: 

LONGMANS, GREEN, READER, AND DYER 


MDCCCLXVIII 



Class No. 



Book No 





PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION. 


This book makes no pretence of giving to the 
world a new theory of the intellectual operations. 
Its claim to attention, if it possess any, is grounded 
on the fact that it is an attempt not to supersede, but 
to embody and systematize,' the best ideas which have 
been either promulgated on its subject by speculative 
writers, or conformed' to by accurate thinkers in their 
scientific inquiries. 

To cement together the detached fragments of a 
subject, never yet treated as a whole; to harmonize 
the true portions of discordant theories, by supplying 
the links of thought necessary to connect them, and 
by disentangling them from the errors with which 
they are always more or less interwoven; must 
necessarily require a considerable amount of original 
speculation. To other originality than this, the pre¬ 
sent work lays no claim. In the existing state of 
the cultivation of the sciences, there would be a very 
strong presumption against any one who should 
imagine that he had effected a revolution m the 
theory of the investigation of truth, or added any 
fundamentally new process to the practice of it. 
The improvement which remains to be effected in 
the methods of philosophizing (and the author be¬ 
lieves that they have much need of improvement) 
can only consist in performing, more systematically 

b 2 



VI 


PREFACE. 


and accurately, operations with which, at least in 
their elementary form, the human intellect in some 
one or other of its employments is already familiar. 

In the portion of the work which treats of Batio- 
cination, the author has not deemed it necessary to 
enter into technical details which may he obtained in 
so perfect a shape from the existing treatises on what 
is termed the Logic of the Schools In the contempt 
entertained by many modem philosophers for the 
syllogistic art, it will be seen that he by no means 
participates, though the scientific theory on which 
its defence is usually rested appears to him erro¬ 
neous : and the view which he has suggested of the 
nature and functions of the Syllogism may, perhaps, 
afford the means of conciliating the principles of the 
art with as much as is well grounded in the doctrines 
and objections of its assailants. 

The same abstinence from details could not be 
observed m the First Book, on Names and Proposi¬ 
tions; because many useful principles and distinc¬ 
tions which were contained in the old Logic, have 
been gradually omitted from the writings of its later 
teachers, and it appeared desirable both to revive 
these, and to reform and rationalize the philosophical 
foundation on which they stood. The earlier chap¬ 
ters of this preliminary Book will consequently 
appear, to some readers, needlessly elementary and 
scholastic But those who know in what darkness 
the nature of our knowledge, and of the processes by 
which it is obtained, is often involved by a confused 
apprehension of the import of the different classes of 
"Words and Assertions, will not regard these discus¬ 
sions as either frivolous, or irrelevant to the topics 
considered in the later Books. 



PREFACE. 


Vll 


On the subj ect of Induction, the task to be per¬ 
formed was that of generalizing the modes of investi¬ 
gating truth and estimating evidence, by which so 
many important and recondite laws of nature have, 
in the various sciences, been aggregated to the stock 
of human knowledge That this is not a task free 
from difficulty may be presumed from the fact, that 
even at a very recent period, eminent writers (among 
whom it is sufficient to name Archbishop Whately, 
and the author of a celebrated article on Bacon in 
the Edinburgh Review) have not scrupled to pro¬ 
nounce it impossible * The author has endeavoured 
to combat their theory in the manner in which 
Diogenes confuted the sceptical reasonings against 
the possibility of motion; remembering that Dio¬ 
genes’ argument would have been equally conclusive, 
though his individual perambulations might not have 
extended beyond the circuit of his own tub. 

Whatever may be the value of what the author 
has succeeded in effecting on this branch of his sub¬ 
ject, it is a duty to acknowledge that for much of it 


* In the later editions of Archbishop Whately’s Logic, he states 
his meaning to he, not that “ rules” for the ascertainment of truths 
by inductive investigation cannot be laid down, or that they may 
not be “ of eminent service,” but that they “ must always be com¬ 
paratively vague and general, and incapable of bemg built up into 
a regular demonstrative theory like that of the Syllogism.” (Book 
iv. ch. iv. § 3.) And he observes, that to devise a system for this 
purpose, capable of being “ brought into a scientific form,” would 
be an achievement which “ he must be more sanguine than scien¬ 
tific who expects.” (Book rv. ch. 11 § 4.) To effect this, however, 
being the express object of the portion of the present work which 
treats of Induction, the words m the text are no overstatement of 
the difference of opinion between Archbishop Whately and me on 
the subject 




vni 


PREFACE. 


he lias been indebted to several important treatises, 
partly historical and partly philosophical, on the 
generalities and processes of physical science, which 
have been published within the last few years. To 
these treatises, and to their authors, he has endea¬ 
voured to do justice in the body of the work. But 
as with one of these writers. Dr. Whewell, he has 
occasion frequently to express differences of opinion, 
it is more particularly incumbent on him in this 
place to declare, that without the aid derived from 
the facts and ideas contained in that gentleman’s 
History of the Inductive Sciences , the corresponding 
portion of this work would probably not have been 
written. 

The concluding Book is an attempt to contribute 
towards the solution of a question, which the decay 
of old opinions, and the agitation that disturbs Euro¬ 
pean society to its inmost depths, render as impor¬ 
tant in the present day to the practical interests of 
human life, as it must at all times be to the com¬ 
pleteness of our speculative knowledge . viz. Whether 
moral and social phenomena are really exceptions to 
the general certainty and uniformity of the course of 
nature; and how far the methods, by which so many 
of the laws of the physical world have been numbered 
among truths irrevocably acquired and universally 
assented to, can be made instrumental to the forma¬ 
tion of a similar body of received doctrine in moral 
and political science. 



PEEFACE TO THE THIED AND POHETH 
EDITIONS. 


Several criticisms, of a more or less controversial 
character, on this work, have appeared since the pub¬ 
lication of the second edition ; and Dr. Whewell has 
lately published a reply to those parts of it in which 
some of his opinions were controverted.* 

I have carefully reconsidered all the points on 
which my conclusions have been assailed. But I 
have not to announce a change of opinion on any 
matter of importance. Such minor oversights as 
have been detected, either by myself or by my 
critics, I have, in general silently, corrected: but 
it is not to be inferred that I agree with the objec¬ 
tions which have been made to a passage, in every 
instance m which I have altered or cancelled it. I 
have often done so, merely that it might not remain 
a stumbling-block, when the amount of discussion 
necessary to place the matter in its true light would 
have exceeded what was suitable to the occasion. 

To several of the arguments which have been 
urged against me, I have thought it useful to reply 
with some degree of minuteness; not from any taste 


* Now forming a chapter in his volume on The Philosophy 
of Discovery. * 



X 


PREFACE. 


for controversy, but because the opportunity was 
favourable for placing my own conclusions, and tbe 
grounds of tbem, more clearly and completely before 
the reader Truth, on these subjects, is militant, 
and can only establish itself by means of conflict. 
The most opposite opinions can make a plausible 
show of evidence while each has the statement of its 
own case, and it is only possible to ascertain which 
of them is in the right, after hearing and comparing 
what each can say against the other, and what the 
other can urge in its defence. 

Even lhe criticisms from which I most dissent 
have been of great service to me, by showing in what 
places the exposition most needed to be improved, or 
the argument strengthened. And I should have 
been well pleased if the book had undergone a much 
greater amount of attack; as in that case I should 
probably have been enabled to improve it still more 
than I believe I have now done. 


In the subsequent editions, the attempt to improve 
the work by additions and corrections, suggested by 
criticism or by thought, has been continued. In the 
present (seventh) edition, a few further corrections 
have been made, but no material additions. 



CONTENTS 


OF 

THE FIRST VOLUME. 


INTRODUCTION 

PAGE 

§ 1. A definition at tlie commencement of a subject must be 

provisional ...... I 

2 Is logic tbe art and science of reasoning ? . . .2 

3. Or tbe art and science of tbe pursuit of truth P 3 

4. Logic is concerned with inferences, not with intuitive truths 5 

5. Relation,oflogicLdiQj^ , . .8 

6. Its utility, how shown . . . . .10 

7. Definition of logic stated and illustrated • . .11 

BOOK I 

OP NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 

Chafteb I. Of the Necessity of commencing with an Analysis of 


Language* 

§ 1. Theory of names, why a necessary part of logic . . 17 

2. First step m the analysis of Propositions . . .18 

3. Names must be studied before Things . . .21 

Chaptee II. Of Names. 

§ 1. Names are names of things, not of our ideas . . 23 

2. Words which are not names, but parts of names . . 24 

3 General and Singular names . . . .26 

4. Concrete and Abstract . . , . .29 

5. Connotative and Non-connotative . . , .31 

6. Positive and Negative , . . , .42 

7. Relative and Absolute . . . . .44 

8. Univocal and ^Equivocal , « . . .47 







dl 


CONTENTS. 


Chapter HI Of the Things denoted* hy Names 

PAGE 

§ 1. Necessity of an enumeration of tameable Tbmgs. The 


Categories of Aristotle . . . . ,49 

2. Ambiguity of the most general names . . .51 

3. Peelings, or states of consciousness . . ,54 

4. Peelings must be distinguished from their physical antece¬ 

dents. Perceptions, what . . . .56 

5. "Volitions, and Actions, what . . . 58 

6. Substance and Attribute . . . . .59 

7. Body . . . « . . .61 

8. Mind . . . . . . ,67 

9. Qualities ....... 69 

10. Relations ... 72 

11. Resemblance , . . . . .74 

12. Quantity .... ... 78 

13. All attributes of bodies are grounded on states of con¬ 

sciousness . . . . . .79 

14. So also all attributes of mind . . . .80 

15 Recapitulation .... . 81 


Chapter IV. Of Proposition* 


§ 1. Nature and office of the copula . . 85 

2. Affirmative and Negative propositions . . .87 

3. Simple and Complex . . . . .89 

4. Universal, Particular, and Singular . . .93 


Chapter V, Of the Import of Propositions, 

§ 1. Doctrine that a proposition is the expression of a relation 

between two ideas . . . . .96 

2. Doctrine that it is the expression of a relation between the 

meanings of two names . . . . .99 

3. Doctrine that it consists in referring something to, or ex¬ 

cluding something from, a class , . . 103 

4 "What it really is ...... 107 

5. It asserts (or denies) a sequence, a coexistence, a simple 

existence, a causation , 110 

6 — or a resemblance ..... 112 

7. Propositions of which the terms are abstract . . 115 







CONTENTS. 


XXII 


Chapteb YL Of Propositions merely Verba l. 

PAGE 

§ 1. Essential and Accidental propositions . . . 119 

2. All essential propositions are identical propositions . 120 

3. Individuals liave no essences .... 124 

4. Heal propositions, how distinguished from verbal . 126 

5. Two modes of representing the import of a Beal proposition 127 


Chapteb YII. Of the Nature of Classification, and the 
Five Predicables . 


§ 1. Classification, how connected with Naming . . 129 

2. The Predicables, what ..... 131 

3. Genus and Species ...... 131 

4. Kinds have a real existence in nature . . . 134 

5. Differentia ....... 139 

6. Differentiae for general purposes, and differentiae for special 

or technical purposes ..... 141 

7. Proprium ....... 144 

8. Accidens ....... 146 


Chapteb Till. Of Definition . 

§ 1. A definition, what ..... 148 

2. Every name can be defined, whose meaning is susceptible 

of analysis ...... 150 

3. Complete, how distinguished from incomplete definitions. 152 
3. — and from descriptions ..... 154 

5. What are called definitions of Things, are definitions of 

Names with an implied assumption of the existence of 
Things corresponding to them .... 157 

6. — even when such things do not in reality exist . . 165 

7. Definitions, though of names only, must be grounded on 

knowledge of the corresponding Things . .167 



XIV 


CONTENTS. 


BOOK II 

OF SEASONING. 

Chapteb I. Of Inference, or Reasoning, m general* 

PAGE 

§ I. Setrospect of the precedmg book . . . 175 

2 . Inferences improperly so called .... 177 

3. Inferences proper, distinguished mto inductions and ratio¬ 

cinations ....... isi 

Chapteb II, Of Ratiocination, or Syllogism . 

§ 1. Analysis of the Syllogism ..... 184 

2. The dictum de omnt not the foundation of reasoning, but 

a mere identical proposition .... 191 

3. What is the really fundamental axiom of [Ratiocination . 196 

4. The other form of the axiom .... 199 

Chapteb III. Of the Functions, and Logical Value, of the 
Syllogism. 

§ 1 . Is the syllogism a.petitio pmncipii ? . . . 202 

2 Insufficiency of the common theory . . . 203 

3. All mference is from particulars to particulars . . 205 

, <4. General propositions are a record of such inferences, and 
the rules of the syllogism are rules for the interpretation 
of the record ...... 214 

5. The syllogism not the type of reasoning, but a test of it . 218 

6 The true type, what . . . . .222 

7. [Relation between Induction and Deduction . . 226 

8 Objections answered ..... 227 
9. Of Formal Logic, and its relation to the Logic of Truth . 231 

Chapteb IV. Of Trains of Reasoning, and Reductive 
Sciences. 

§ 1. For what purpose trams of reasoning exist . . 234 

2 . A train of reasoning is a series of inductive inferences , 234 

8 . — from particulars to particulars through marks of marks 237 
4 Why there are deductive sciences .... 240 

5. Why other sciences still remain experimental . . 244 

6 . Experimental sciences may become deductive by the pro¬ 

gress of experiment . . . . .246 

7. In what manner this usually takes place . . . 247 



CONTENTS. 



XV 


Chapter V. Of Demonstration , and Necessary Truths 

PAGE 

§ 1. The Theorems of geometry are necessary truths only in 

the sense of necessarily following from hypotheses . 251 
2 Those hypotheses are real facts with some of their circum¬ 
stances exaggerated or omitted .... 255 

3 . Some of the first principles of geometry are axioms, and 

these are not hypothetical .... 256 

4 . — hut are experimental truths .... 258 

5 . An objection answered ..... 261 

6 . Dr. WhewelTs opimons on axioms examined . . 264 


Chapteb VI. The same Subject continued 

§ 1 All deductive sciences are inductive . . 281 y* 

2 The propositions of the science of number are not verbal, 

but generalizations from experience . . . 284 ^ 

3. In what sense hypothetical..... 289 ^ 

4 The characteristic property of demonstrative science is to 

be hypothetical ...... 290 

5. Definition of demonstrative evidence *. . . 292 ^ 


Chapter VII. Examination of some Opinions 
the preceding doctrines. 

§ 1. Doctrine of the Universal Postulate 

2. The test of inconceivability does not represent 

gate of past experience 

3. — nor is implied m every process of thought 

4. Sir W. Hamilton’s opinion on the Principles 

diction and Excluded Middle 


opposed to 




294 

y 

the aggre- 



m 

296 


* 

299 

y 

of Contra- 




306 



BOOK III. 

OP INDUCTION - . 

Chapter I. 'Preliminary Observations on Induction m general. 

§ 1 . Importance of an Inductive Logic .... 313 ^ 
2 The logic of science is also that of business and life . 314 

Chapter II. Of Inductions improperly so called. 


§ 1 Inductions distinguished from verbal transformations . 319 

2 . — from inductions, falsely so called, in mathematics . 321 

3. — and from descriptions ..... 323 

4 Examination of Dr. WhewelTs theory of Induction . 326 

5. Eurther illustration of the preceding remarks . . 336 



CONTEXTS. 


m 


Chapter HI. On the Ground of Induction. 

PAGE 

§ 1. Axiom of tlie uniformity of the course of nature . . 341 

2 Not true in every sense Induction j per enumerationem 

stmpltcem 346 

3. The question of Inductive Logie stated . . . 348 

Chapter IV. Of Laws of Nature. 

§ 1. The general regularity in nature is a tissue of partial re¬ 
gularities, called laws ..... 351 

2. Scientific induction must be grounded on previous spon¬ 

taneous inductions . . . .355 

3 . Are there any inductions fitted to be a test of all others ? 357 

Chapter V, Of the Law of TTnwersal Causation. 

§ 1. The universal law of successive phenomena is the Law of 

Causation ....... 360 

2 . — L e. the law that every consequent has an invariable 

antecedent ...... 363 

3. The cause of a phenomenon is the assemblage of its con¬ 

ditions ....... 365 

4. The distinction of agent and patient illusory . . 373 

5. The cause is not the invariable antecedent, but the uncon - 

ditional invariable antecedent . . . .375 

6. Can a cause be simultaneous with its effect P . . 380 

7. Idea of a Permanent Cause, or original natural agent . 383 
8 * "Uniformities of coexistence between effects of different 

permanent causes, are not laws .... 386 
9 . Doctrine that volition is an efficient cause, examined . 387 

Chapter VI. Of the Composition of Causes. 

§ 1. Two modes of the conjunct action of causes, the mechani¬ 
cal and the chemical ..... 405 

2. The composition of causes the general rule; the other case 

exceptional 408 

3. Are effects proportional to their causes ? . . .412 

Chapter VII. Of Observation and Experiment. 

§ 1. The first step of inductive inquiry is a mental analysis of 

complex phenomena into their elements . . 414 

2. The next is an actual separation of those elements . 416 

3. Advantages of experiment over observation . . 417 

4. Advantages of observation over experiment . . 420 




CONTENTS. 


XVII 


§ 


Chapter Yin. 


Of the Four Methods of Experimental 
Inquiry . 


PAGE 


1 . Method of Agreement ..... 425 

2. Method of Difference ..... 428 

3 Mutual relation of these two methods . . . 429 

4 . Joint Method of Agreement and Difference . 433 

5. Method of Residues ..... 436 

6 . Method of Concomitant Variations . • . 437 

7. Limitations of this last method .... 443 


Chapter IX. Miscellaneous Examples of the Four Methods . 


§ 1 . Liebig’s theory of metallic poisons . . . 449 

2. Theory of induced electricity .... 453 
3 Dr. Wells* theory of dew ..... 457 

4. Dr. Brown-Sequard’s theory of cadaveric rigidity . 465 

5. Examples of the Method of Residues . . . 471 

6 . Dr. WhewelTs objections to the Eour Methods . . 475 


Chapter X. Of Plurality of Causes; and of the Intermixture 
of Effects . 

§ 1 One effect may have several causes , . . 482 

2 — which is the source of a characteristic imperfection of 

the Method of Agreement .... 483 

3 Plurality of Causes, how ascertained . . 487 

4 Concurrence of Causes which do not compound their effects 489 

5 Difficulties of the investigation, when causes compound 

their effects ..... 494 

6 . Three modes of investigating the laws of complex effects 499 

7. The method of simple observation inapplicable . . 500 

8 The purely experimental method inapplicable . . 501 


Chapter XI. Of the Deductive Method . 

§ 1 . Pirn stage; ascertainment of the laws of the separate 

causes by direct induction .... 507 

2 . Second stage; ratiocination from the simple laws of the 

complex cases ...... 512 

3. Third stage; verification by specific experience . . 514 




CONTENTS. 


<111 


Chapteb XII. Of the Explanation of Laws of Nature . 

PAGE 

§ 1 . Explanation defined ..... 518 
2 First mode of explanation, by resolving tbe law of a com¬ 
plex effect into tbe laws of tbe concurrent causes and 
tbe fact of tbeir coexistence .... 518 

3. Second mode, by tbe detection of an intermediate lrnk in 

tbe sequence ..... 519 

4. Laws are always resolved into laws more general than 

themselves ...... 520 

5 Third mode ; tbe subsumption of less general laws under 

a more general one ..... 524 

6 . What tbe explanation of a law of nature amounts to . 526 

Chapteb XIII. Miscellaneous Examples of the Explanation of ^ 


Laws of Nature, 

§ 1 . Tbe general theories of tbe sciences . . . 529 

2 . Examples from chemical speculations . . . 531 

3. Example from Dr. Brown-S equard’s researches on tbe 

nervous system ...... 533 

4 Examples of following newly-discovered laws into tbeir 

complex manifestations . . . . .534 

5. Examples of empirical generalizations, afterwards con¬ 

firmed and explained deductively . . . 536 

6 . Example from mental science .... 538 

7. Tendency of all tbe sciences to become deductive . 539 



INTRODUCTION. 


§ 1. There is as great diversity among authors in the 
nodes which they have adopted of defining logic, as m their 
treatment of the details of it. This is what might naturally 
>e expected on any subject on which writers have availed them- 
>elves of the same language as a means of delivering different 
deas Ethics and jurisprudence are liable to the remark m 
jommon with logic Almost every writer having taken a 
lifferent view of some of the particulai s which these branches 
»f knowledge are usually understood to include, each has so 
ramed his definition as to indicate beforehand his own peculiar 
enets, and sometimes to beg the question in their favour 
This diversity is not so much an evil to be complained of, 
s an inevitable and m some degree a proper result of the 
mperfect state of those sciences. It is not to he expected that 
here should he agreement about the definition of anything, 
ntil there is agreement about the thing itself. To define, is 
3 select from among all the properties of a thing, those 
r hich shall he understood to he designated and declared 
y its name; and the properties must he well known to us 
efore we can he competent to deteimme which of them are 
ttest to he chosen for this purpose Accordingly, in the case 
f so complex an aggregation of particulars as are compre- 
ended in anything which can he called a science, the defim- 
on we set out with is seldom that which a more extensive 
nowledge of the subject shows to be the most appropriate, 
fftil we know the particulars themselves, we cannot fix upon 
ie most correct and compact mode of circumscribing them by 
general description It was not until after an extensive and 
icurate acquaintance with the details of chemical phenomena, 

' VOL. I, 1 



2 


INTRODUCTION. 


that it was found possible to frame a rational definition of 
chemistiy, and the definition of the science of life and orga¬ 
nization is still a matter of dispute. So long as the sciences 
are imperfect, the definitions must partake of then imperfec¬ 
tion , and if the former are progressive, the latter ought to be 
so too. As much, therefore, as is to be expected from a defi¬ 
nition placed at the commencement of a subject, is that it 
should define the scope of our inquiries: and the definition 
which I am about to offer of the science of logic, pretends to 
nothing more, than to be a statement of the question which I 
have put to myself, and which this book is an attempt to 
resolve. The reader is at liberty to object to it as a definition 
of logic, but it is at all events a correct definition of the sub¬ 
ject of these volumes. 

§ 2. Logic has often been called the Art of Reasoning. 
A writer* who has done more than any other person to lestore 
this study to the rank from which it had fallen m the esti¬ 
mation of the cultivated class m our own country, has adopted 
the above definition with an amendment; he has defined Logic 
to he the Science, as well as the Art, of reasoning, meaning 
by the former term, the analysis of the mental process which 
takes place whenever we leason, and by the latter, the rules, 
grounded on that analysis, for conducting the process cor¬ 
rectly. There can be no doubt as to the propriety of the 
emendation. A right understanding of the mental process 
itself, of the conditions it depends on, and the steps of which 
it consists, is the only basis on which a system of rules, fitted 
for the direction of the process, can possibly be founded. Art 
necessarily presupposes knowledge; art, in any but its infant 
state, presupposes scientific knowledge and if every art does 
not bear the name of a science, it is only because several 
sciences are often necessary to form the groundwork of a single 
art. So complicated are the conditions which govern our prac¬ 
tical agency, that to enable one thing to be done, it is often 
requisite to know the nature and properties of many things. 


Archbishop Whately. 



DEFINITION AND PROVINCE OF LOGIC. 


Logic, then, compuses the science of reasoning, as well ai 
an art, founded on that science. But the word Reasoning 
again, like most other scientific terms m popular use, abound} 
in ambiguities In one of its acceptations, it means syllogizing 
or the mode of inference which may be called (with sufficiem 
accuiacy for the present purpose) concluding from generals tc 
particulars In another of its senses, to leason is simply tc 
infer any asseition, from assertions already admitted. and lr 
this sense induction is as much entitled to be called reasoning 
as the demonstrations of geometry. 

Writers on logic have generally preferred the former accep 
tation of the term : the latter, and more extensive significa¬ 
tion is that m which I mean to use it. I do this by virtue o] 
the right I claim for every author, to give whatever provi¬ 
sional definition he pleases of his own subject. But sufficienl 
reasons will, I believe, unfold themselves as we advance, why 
this should be not only the provisional but the final definition, 
It involves, at all events, no arbitrary change m the meaning 
of the word, for, with the general usage of the English lan¬ 
guage, the wider signification, I believe, accords better than 
the more restricted one 

§ 3 But Reasoning, even m the widest sense of which 
the word is susceptible, does not seem to comprehend all that 
is included, either in the best, or even m the most current, 
conception of the scope and province of our science The 
-employment of the word Logic to denote the theory of argu¬ 
mentation, is derived from the Aristotelian, or, as they are 
commonly termed, the scholastic, logicians Yet even with 
them, in their systematic treatises, argumentation was the 
subj'ect only of the third part: the two former treated of 
Terms, and of Propositions, under one or other of which heads 
were also included Definition and Division By some, indeed, 
these previous topics were professedly introduced only on 
account of their connexion with .reasoning, and as a prepara¬ 
tion for the doctrine and rules of the syllogism. Yet they 
were treated with greater minuteness, and dwelt on at greater 
length, than was required for that purpose alone. More recent 

1—2 



i 


INTRODUCTION. 


writers on logic have generally understood the term as it was 
employed hy the able author of the Port Royal Logic; viz* 
as equivalent to the Art of Thinking. Nor is this acceptation 
confined to books, and scientific inquiries. Even m ordinary 
conversation, the ideas connected with the word Logic include 
at least precision of language, and accuracy of classification : 
and we perhaps oftener hear persons speak of a logical arrange¬ 
ment, or of expressions logically defined, than of conclusions 
logically deduced from premises. Again, a man is often called 
a great logician, or a man of powerful logic, not for the accu¬ 
racy of his deductions, but for the extent of his command 
over premises ; because the general piopositions required for 
explaining a difficulty or refuting a sophism, copiously and 
promptly occur to him because, m short, his knowledge, 
besides being ample, is well under his command for argumen¬ 
tative use. Whether, therefore, we conform to the practice of 
those who have made the subject then particular study, or to 
that of popular writers and common discourse, the province 
of logic will include several operations of the intellect not 
usually considered to fall within the meaning of the terms 
Reasoning and Argumentation. 

These various operations might be brought within the com¬ 
pass of the science, and the additional advantage be obtained 
of a very simple definition, if, by an extension of the term, 
sanctioned by high authorities, we were to define logic as the 
science which treats of the operations of the human under¬ 
standing in the pursuit of truth. For to this ultimate end, 
naming, classification, definition, and all other operations over 
which logic has ever claimed jurisdiction, are essentially sub¬ 
sidiary. They may all be regarded as contrivances for enabling 
a person to know the truths which are needful to him, and to 
know them at the precise moment at which they are needful* 
Other purposes, indeed, are also served by these operations; 
for instance, that of imparting our knowledge to others. But, 
viewed with regard to this purpose, they have never been con¬ 
sidered as within the province of the logician. The sole object 
of Logic is the guidance of one's own thoughts: the com¬ 
munication of those thoughts to others falls under the con- 



DEFINITION AND PROVINCE OF LOGIC* 


5 


sideration of Rhetoric, m the large sense m which that art 
was conceived by the ancients; or of the still more extensive 
art of Education. Logic takes cognizance of our intellectual 
operations, only as they conduce to our own knowledge, and 
to our command over that knowledge for our own uses. If 
there were but one rational being m the universe, that being 
might be a perfect logician, and the science and art of logic 
would be the same for that one peison as for the whole 
human race. 

§ 4. But, if the definition which we formerly examined 
included too little, that which is now suggested has the oppo¬ 
site fault of including too much. 

Truths are known to us m two ways: some are known 
directly, and of themselvessome through the medium of 
other truths The former are the subject-of Intuition, or Con¬ 
sciousness ,* the latter, of Inference. The truths known^by 
intuition are the original premises from which all otheis aie 
inferred. Our assent to the conclusion being grounded on the 
truth of the premises, we never could arrive at any knowledge 
by reasoning, unless something could be known antecedently 
to all reasoning 

' Examples of truths known to us by immediate conscious¬ 
ness, are our own bodily sensations and mental feelings. I 
know directly, and of my own knowledge, that I was vexed 
yesterday, or that I am hungry to-day. Examples of truths 
which we know only by way of inference, are occurrences 
which took place while we were absent, the events recorded m 
history, or the theorems of mathematics. The two former we 
infer from the testimony adduced, or from the traces of those 
past occurrences which still exist; the latter, from the pre¬ 
mises laid down in books of geometry, under the title of defi¬ 
nitions and axioms. Whatever we are capable of knowing 


* I use these terms indiscriminately, because, for the purpose in view, there 
is no need for making any distinction between them. But metaphysicians 
usually restrict the name Intuition to the direct knowledge we are supposed to 
have of things external to oui minds, and Consciousness to our knowledge of 
our own mental phenomena. 



6 


Introduction. 


must belong to the one class or to the other; must be in the 
number of the primitive data, or of the conclusions which can 
be drawn from these 

With the original data, or ultimate premises of our know¬ 
ledge , with their numbei or natuie, the mode m which they 
are obtained, or the tests by which they may be distinguished, 
logic, m a direct way at least, has, m the sense m which I con¬ 
ceive the science, nothing to do These questions are partly 
not a subject of science at all, partly that of a very different 
science 

Whatever is known to us by consciousness, is known be¬ 
yond possibility of question. What one sees or feels, whether 
bodily or mentally, one cannot but be sure that one sees or 
feels No science is required for the purpose of establishing 
such tiuths, no rules of art can render our knowledge of them 
more ceitam than it is m itself. There is no logic for this 
portion of oui knowledge. 

But we may fancy that we see or feel what we m reality 
infer A tiuth, or supposed tiuth, which is really the result 
of a very lapid inference, may seem to be appiehended intui¬ 
tively. It has long been agreed by thinkers of the most oppo¬ 
site schools, that this mistake is actually made m so familiar 
an instance as that of the eyesight There is nothing of which 
we appear to ourselves to be more directly conscious, than the 
distance of an object fiom us Yet it has long been ascertained, 
that what is perceived by the eye, is at most nothing more 
than a variously coloured surface ; that when we fancy we see 
distance, all we really see is certain variations of apparent size, 
and degrees of faintness of colour, that our estimate of the 
object s distance from ns is the result partly of a rapid inference 
from the muscular sensations accompanying the adjustment of 
the focal distance of the eye to objects unequally remote from 
us, and paitly of a comparison (made with so much rapidity 
that we aie unconscious of making it) between the size and 
colour of the object as they appear at the time, and the size 
and colour of the same or of similar objects as they appeared 
when close at hand, or when their degree of remoteness was 
known by other evidence. The perception of distance by the 



DEFINITION AND PROVINCE OF LOGIC. ^ 

eye, which seems so like intuition, is thus, m reality, an infe¬ 
rence grounded on experience, an inference, too, which we 
learn to make, and which we make with more and more cor¬ 
rectness as our experience increases, though m familiar cases 
it takes place so rapidly as to appear exactly on a par with, 
those perceptions of sight which are really intuitive, our per¬ 
ceptions of colour.**" 

Of the science, therefore, which expounds the operations of 
the human understanding m the pursuit of truth, one essential 
part is the inquiry. What are the facts which are the objects 
of intuition or consciousness, and what are those which we 
merely infer ? But this inquiry has never been considered a 
portion of logic. Its place is m another and a perfectly distinct 
department of science, to which the name metaphysics mote 
paiticuiarly belongs. that portion of mental philosophy which 
attempts to determine what part of the furniture of the mind 
belongs to it originally, and what part is constructed out of 
materials furnished to it from without. To this science appei - 
tain the great and much debated questions of the existence of 
matter, the existence of spirit, and of a distinction between it 
and matter, the reality of time and space, as things without 
the mind, and distinguishable from the objects which are said 
to exist m them. Tor m the present state of the discussion on 
these topics, it is almost universally allowed that the existence 
of matter or of spirit, of space or of time, is m its nature un¬ 
susceptible of being proved ; and that if anything is known of 
them, it must be by immediate intuition. To the same science 
belong the inquiries into the nature of Conception, Perception, 
Memory, and Belief, all of which are operations of the undei- 
standmg m the pursuit of truth, but with which, as phenomena 
of the mind, or with the possibility which may or may not 
exist of analysing any of them into simpler phenomena, the 


* This important theory has of late been called, xn question by a writer of 
deserved reputation, Mr. Samuel Bailey, but I do not conceive that the grounds 
on which it has been admitted as an established doctrine for a century past, 
have been at all shaken by that gentleman’s objections. I have elsewhere said 
what appeared to me necessary in reply to his arguments (Westminster Review 
for October 1842; reprinted in Dissertations and Discussions, vol, 11 ) 



8 


INTRODUCTION. 


logician as such has no concern. To this science must also he 
referred the following, and all analogous questions * To what 
extent our intellectual faculties and our emotions are innate— 
to what extent the result of association: Whether God, and 
duty, are realities, the existence of which is manifest to us 
a prion by the constitution of our rational faculty , or whether 
our ideas of them are acquired notions, the origin of which we 
are able to trace and explain, and the reality of the objects 
themselves a question not of consciousness or intuition, but of 
evidence and reasoning 

The province of logic must be restricted to that portion of 
our knowledge which consists of inferences from truths pre¬ 
viously known, whether those antecedent data be general pro¬ 
positions, or particular observations and perceptions. Logic 
is not the science of Belief, but the science of Proof, or Evi¬ 
dence. In so far as belief professes to be founded on proof, 
the office of logic is to supply a test for ascertaining whether 
or not the belief is well grounded. With the claims which any 
proposition has to belief on the evidence of consciousness, that 
is, without evidence in the proper sense of the word, logic has 
nothing to do 

§ 5. By far the greatest portion of our knowledge, 
whether of general truths or of particular facts, being avowedly 
matter of inference, nearly the whole, not only of science, but 
of human conduct, is amenable to the authority of logic. To 
draw inferences has been said to be the great business of life. 
Every one has daily, hourly, and momentary need of ascertain¬ 
ing facts which he has not directly observed; not from any 
general purpose of adding to his stock of knowledge, but 
because the facts themselves are of importance to his interests 
or to his occupations. The business of the magistrate, of the 
military commander, of the navigator, of the physician, of the 
agriculturist, is merely to judge of evidence, and to act accord¬ 
ingly. They all have to ascertain certain facts, in order that 
they may afterwards apply certain rules, either devised by 
themselves, or prescribed for their guidance by others; and as 
they do this well or ill, so they discharge well or ill the duties 



DEFINITION AND PROVINCE OF LOGIC. 


9 


of their several callings It is the only occupation m which 
the mind never ceases to be engaged, and is the subject, not 
of logic, but of knowledge m general. 

Logic, however, is not the same thing with knowledge, 
though the field of logic is coextensive with the field of know¬ 
ledge. Logic is the common judge and arbiter of all parti¬ 
cular investigations. It does not undertake to find evidence, 
but to determine whether it has been found. Logic neither 
observes, nor invents, nor discovers, but judges It is no part 
of the business of logic to inform the surgeon what appearances 
are found to accompany a violent death. This he must learn 
from his own experience and observation, or from that of 
others, his predecessors in his peculiar pursuit. But logic sits 
in judgment on the sufficiency of that observation and expe¬ 
rience to justify his rules, and on the sufficiency of his rules 
to justify his conduct. It does not give him proofs, but 
teaches him what makes them proofs, and how he is to judge 
of them. It does not teach that any particular fact proves any 
other, but points out to what conditions all facts must con¬ 
form, m order that they may prove other facts. To decide 
whether any given fact fulfils these conditions, or whether facts 
can be found which fulfil them in a given case, belongs ex¬ 
clusively to the particular art or science, or to our knowledge 
of the particular subject. 

It is in this sense that logic is, what Bacon so expressively 
called it, ars artium ; the science of science itself. All science 
consists of data and conclusions from those data, of proofs and 
what they prove: now logic points out what relations must 
subsist between data and whatever can be concluded from 
them, between proof and everything which it can prove. If 
there be any such indispensable relations, and if these can be 
precisely determined, every particular branch of science, as 
well as every individual in the guidance of his conduct, is 
bound to conform to those relations, under the penalty of 
making false inferences, of drawing conclusions which are not 
grounded m the realities of things. Whatever has at any 
time been concluded justly, whatever knowledge has been 
acquired otherwise than by immediate intuition, depended on 



10 


INTRODUCTION. 


the observance of the laws which it is the province of logic to 
investigate. If the conclusions are just, and the knowledge 
real, those laws, whether known or not, have been observed. 

§ 6. We need not, therefore, seek any farther for a solu¬ 
tion of the question, so often agitated, lespectmg the utility 
of logic. If a science of logic exists, or is capable of existing, 
it must be useful. If there be rules to which every mind 
consciously or unconsciously conforms m every instance m 
which it infers rightly, there seems little necessity for dis¬ 
cussing whether a peison is more likely to observe those rules, 
when he knows the rules, than when he is unacquainted with 
them. 

A science may undoubtedly be brought to a certain, not 
inconsiderable, stage of advancement, without the application 
of any other logic to it than what all persons, who are said to 
have a sound understanding, acquire empirically m the course 
of their studies. Mankind judged of evidence, and often 
correctly, before logic was a science, 01 they never could ha\e 
made it one. And they executed great mechanical works 
befoie they understood the laws of mechanics. But there are 
limits both to what mechanicians can do without principles of 
mechanics, and to what thinkers can do without principles of 
logic. A few individuals, by extraordinary genius, or by the 
accidental acquisition of a good set of intellectual habits, may 
work without principles m the same way, or nearly the same 
wav, m which they would have worked if they had been m 
possession of principles. But the bulk of mankind require 
either to understand the theory of what they are doing, or to 
have rules laid down for them by those who have understood 
the theory, In the progress of science from its easiest to its 
more difficult problems, each great step m advance has usually 
had either as its precursor, or as its accompaniment and neces¬ 
sary condition, a corresponding improvement m the notions 
and principles of logic received among the most advanced 
thinkers. And if seveial of the more difficult sciences aie 
still m so defective a state; if not only so little is proved, hut 
c|isputation has not terminated even about the little which 



/ 0* 

/ r 

DEFINITION AND PROVINCE OF LOGIC, jf 11 

seemed to be so, the leason perhaps is, that men’s- logical 
notions have not yet acquned the degree of extension,of 
accuracy, requisite for the estimation of the evidence proper 
to those particular depaitments of knowledge. 

§ 7 Logic, then, is the science of the operations of the 
understanding which are subservient to the estimation of 
evidence both the process itself of advancing from known 
truths to unknown, and all other intellectual operations m so 
far as auxiliary to this. It includes, therefore, the operation 
of Naming, foi language is an instrument of thought, as well 
as a means of communicating our thoughts It includes, also. 
Definition, and Classification Lor, the use of these operations 
(putting all other minds than one’s own out of consideiation) 
is to serve not only for keeping our evidences and the conclu¬ 
sions from them permanent and readily accessible in the 
memory, but for so marshalling the facts which we may at 
any time be engaged m investigating, as to enable us to 
perceive more clearly what evidence there is, and to judge with 
fewer chances of error whether it be sufficient These, there¬ 
fore, ftre operations specially instrumental to the estimation of 
evidence, and, as such, are within the province of Logic. 
There are other more elementary processes, concerned m all 
thinking, such as Conception, Memory, and the like; but of 
these it is not necessary that Logic should take any peculiar' 
cognizance, since they have no special connexion with the 
pioblem of Evidence, fmther than that, like all other problems 
addiessed to the undeistanding, it presupposes them. 

Our object, then, will be, to attempt a conect analysis of 
the intellectual process called Reasoning or Inference, and of 
such othei mental operations as are intended to facilitate this: 
as well as, on the foundation of this analysis, and pan passu 
with it, to bring together or frame a set of rules or canons for 
testing the sufficiency of any given evidence to prove any 
given proposition. 

With respect to the first pait of this undertaking, I do 
not attempt to decompose the mental operations in question 
into their ultimate elements. It is enough if the analysis as 



12 


INTRODUCTION, 


far as it goes is correct, and if it goes far enough for the 
practical purposes of logic considered as an art. The separa¬ 
tion of a complicated phenomenon into its component parts is 
not like a connected and interdependent chain of proof. If 
one link of an argument breaks, the whole drops to the ground; 
but one step towards an analysis holds good and has an inde¬ 
pendent value, though we should never he able to make a 
second. The results which have been obtained by analytical 
chemistry are not the less valuable, though it should be dis¬ 
covered that all which we now call simple substances are really 
compounds All other things are at any rate compounded of 
those elements: whether the elements themselves admit of 
decomposition, is an important inquiry, but does not affect the 
certainty of the science up to that point. 

I shall, accordingly, attempt to analyse the process of 
inference, and the processes subordinate to inference, so far 
only as may be requisite for ascertaining the difference between 
a correct and an incorrect performance of those processes. 
The reason for thus limiting our design, is evident. It has 
been said by objectors to logic, that we do not learn to use 
our muscles by studying their anatomy The fact is not quite 
fairly stated; for if the action of any of our muscles were 
vitiated by local weakness, or other physical defect, a know¬ 
ledge of their anatomy might be very necessary for effecting a 
cure. But we should be justly liable to the criticism involved 
in this objection, were we, m a treatise on logic, to carry the 
analysis of the leasoning process beyond the point at which 
any inaccuracy which may have crept into it must become 
visible. In learning bodily exercises (to carry on the same 
illustration) we do, and must, analyse the bodily motions so 
far as is necessary for distinguishing those which ought to be 
performed from those which ought not To a similar extent, 
and no further, it is necessary that the logician should analyse 
the mental processes with which Logic is concerned. Logic 
has no interest m carrying the analysis beyond the point at 
which it becomes appaient whether the operations have m any 
individual case been rightly or wrongly performed. in the 
same manner as the science of music teaches us to discriminate 



DEFINITION AND PROVINCE OF LOGIC, 


13 


between musical notes, and to know the combinations of which 
they are susceptible, but not what number of vibrations m a 
second correspond to each, which, though useful to be known, 
is useful for totally different purposes. The extension of 
Logic as a Science is determined by its necessities as an Art: 
whatever it does not need for its practical ends, it leaves to the 
larger science which may be said to correspond, not to any 
particular art, but to art m general, the science which deals 
with the constitution of the human faculties, and to which, in 
the part of our mental nature which concerns Logic, as weil as 
in all other parts, it belongs to decide what are ultimate facts, 
and what are resolvable into other facts. And I believe it will 
be found that most of the conclusions arrived at in this work 
have no necessary connexion with any particular views re¬ 
specting the ulterior analysis. Logic is common ground on 
which the partisans of Hartley and of Eeid, of Locke and of 
Kant, may meet and join hands. Particular and detached 
opinions of all these thinkers will no doubt occasionally be 
controverted, since all of them were logicians as well as meta¬ 
physicians , but the field on which their principal battles have 
been fought, lies beyond the boundaries of our science. 

It cannot, indeed, be pretended that logical principles can 
be altogether irrelevant to those more abstruse discussions; 
nor is it possible but that the view we are led to take of the 
problem which logic proposes, must have a tendency favour¬ 
able to the adoption of some one opinion, on these controverted 
subjects, rather than another. For metaphysics, m endeavour¬ 
ing to solve its own peculiar problem, must employ means, the 
validity of which falls under the cognizance of logic. It pro¬ 
ceeds, no doubt, as far as possible, merely by a closer and more 
attentive interrogation of our consciousness, or more properly 
speaking, of our memory, and so far is not amenable to logic. 
But wherever this method is insufficient to attain the end of 
its inquiries, it must proceed, like other sciences, by means of 
evidence. Now, the moment this science begins to draw in¬ 
ferences from evidence, logic becomes the sovereign judge 
whether its inferences are well grounded, or what other in¬ 
ferences would be so. 



14 


INTRODUCTION. 


This, however, constitutes no nearer or other relation be¬ 
tween logic and metaphysics, than that which exists between 
logic and every other science And I can conscientiously 
affirm, that no one proposition laid down in this work has 
been adopted for the sake of establishing, or with any reference 
to its fitness for being employed m establishing, preconceived 
opinions m any department of knowledge or of inquiry on 
which the speculative world is still undecided.* 


* The view taken in the text, of the definition and purpose of Logic, stands 
in marked opposition to that of the school of philosophy which, m this country, 
is represented by the writings of Sir William Hamilton and of his numerous 
pupils Logic, as this school conceives it, is ec the Science of the Formal Laws 
of Thought”, a definition framed for the express purpose of excluding, as irre¬ 
levant to Logic, whatever relates to Belief and Disbelief, or to the pursuit of 
truth as such, and restricting the science to that very limited portion of its 
total province, which has reference to the conditions, not of Truth, but of Con¬ 
sistency. What I have thought it useful to say m opposition to this limitation 
of the field of Logic, has been said at some length m a separate work, first 
published in 1865, and entitled An Examination of Sir William Hamilton?$ 
Philosophy, and of the Principal Philosophical Questions discussed in Ms 
Writings For the purposes of the present Treatise, I am content that the 
justification of the latger extension which I give to the domain of the science, 
should rest on the sequel of the Treatise itself. Some remarks on the relation 
which the Logic of Consistency bears to the Logic of Truth, and on the place 
which that particular part occupies in the whole to which it belongs, will be 
found m the present volume (Book II chap m § 9) 



BOOK I. 


OF NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 



‘La scolastique, qui produisit dans la logique, comme dans la morale, et 
dans nne partie de la m^taphysique, nne subtiktd, une precision d’id€es, dont 
1’habitude mconnue aux anciens, a contribud plus qu’on ne croit au progres 
de la bonne philosophie.’— Condoecet, Vie de Turgot, 

‘To the schoolmen the vulgar languages are principally indebted for what 
precision and analyse subtlety they possess 9 — Sie W. Hamilton, Discussions 
m Philosophy 



CHAPTER I. 


OF THE NECESSITY OF COMMENCING WITH AN 
ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE. 

§ 1. It is so much the established practice of writers on 
logic to commence their treatises by a few general observations 
(m most cases, it is true, rather meagre) on Terms and their 
varieties, that it will, perhaps, scarcely be required from me 
in merely following the common usage, to be as particular m 
assigning my reasons, as it is usually expected that those 
should, be who deviate from it. 

The practice, indeed, is recommended by considerations 
far too obvious to require a formal justification Logic is a 
portion of the Art of Thinking Language is evidently, and 
by the admission of all philosophers, one of the principal m- 
stiuments or helps of thought, and any imperfection m the 
instrument, or m the mode of employing it, is confessedly 
liable, still more than m almost any other art, to confuse and 
impede the process^and destroy all ground of confidence m the 
result For a mind not previously versed in the meaning and 
right use of the various kinds of words, to attempt the study 
of methods of philosophizing, would be as if some one should 
attempt to become an astronomical observer, having never 
learned to adjust the focal distance of his optical instruments 
so as to see distinctly. 

Since Reasoning, or Inference, the principal subject of 
logic, is an operation which usually takes place by means of 
words, and m complicated cases can take place m no other 
way, those who have not a thorough insight into the significa¬ 
tion and purposes of words, will be under chances, amounting 
almost to certainty, of reasoning or inferring incorrectly. And 
logicians have generally felt that unless, m the very first stage, 
they removed this source of error, unless they taught their 

VOL i. 2 



18 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


pupil to put away the glasses which distort the object, and to 
use those which are adapted to his purpose in such a manner 
as to assist, not perplex, his vision, he would not he m a con¬ 
dition to practise the remaining part of their discipline with 
any prospect of advantage. Therefore it is that an inquiry 
into language, so far as is needful to guard against the errors 
to which it gives rise, has at all times been deemed a necessary 
preliminary to the study of logic. 

But there is another reason, of a still more fundamental 
nature, why the import of words should be the earliest subj'ect 
of the logician’s consideration because without it he cannot 
examine into the import of Propositions. Now this is a 
subject which stands on the very threshold of the science of 
logic 

The object of logic, as defined m the Introductory Chapter, * 
is to ascertain how we come by that portion of our knowledge 
(much the greatest portion) which is not intuitive. and by 
what criterion we can, m matters not self-evident, distinguish 
between things proved and things not proved, between what 
is worthy and what is unworthy of belief. Of the various 
questions which piesent themselves to our inquiring faculties, 
some receive an answer from direct consciousness, others, if 
resolved at all, can only be resolved by means of evidence. 
Logic is concerned with these last. But before inquiring into 
the mode of resolving questions, it is necessary to inquire what 
are those which offer themselves; what questions are conceiv¬ 
able , what inquiries are there, to which mankind have either 
obtained, or been able to imagine it possible that they should 
obtain, an answer. This point is best ascertained by a survey 
and analysis of Propositions. 

§ 2. The answer to every question which it is possible to 
frame, must be contained m a Proposition, or Assertion. 
Whatever can be an object of belief, or even ^disbelief, must, 
when put into words, assume the form of a proposition. All 
truth and all error lie in propositions. What, by a convenient 
misapplication of an abstract term, we call a Truth, means 
simply a True Proposition, and errors are false propositions. 



NECESSITY OF AN ANALYSIS OF NAMES. 


19 


To know the import of all possible propositions, would be to 
know all questions which can be raised, all matters which are 
susceptible of being either believed or disbelieved. How many 
kinds of inquiries can be propounded, how many kinds of 
judgments can be made, and how many kinds of propositions 
it is possible to frame with a meaning, are but different forms 
of one and the same question. Since, then, the objects of all 
Belief and of all Inquiry express themselves in propositions, 
a sufficient scrutiny of Propositions and of,their varieties will 
apprize us what questions mankind have actually asked of 
themselves, and what, m the nature of answers to those 
questions, they have actually thought they had grounds to 
believe. 

Now the fust glance at a proppsition shows that it is 
formed by putting together two names. A proposition, ac¬ 
cording to the common simple definition, which is sufficient 
for our purpose, is, discourse, m which something is affirmed 
or denied of something. Thus, m the proposition, Gold is 
yellow, the quality yellow is affirmed of the substance gold 
In the proposition, Franklin was not born m England, the 
fact expressed by the words horn m England is denied of the 
man Franklin. 

Every proposition consists of three parts* the Subject, the 
Predicate, and the Copula. The predicate is the name denoting 
that which is affirmed or denied The subject is the name 
denoting the person or thing which something is affirmed or 
denied of. The copula is the sign denoting that there is an 
affirmation or denial; and thereby enabling the hearer or 
reader to distinguish a proposition from any other kind of 
discourse. Thus, m the proposition, The earth is round, the 
Predicate is the word round , which denotes the quality affirmed, 
or (as the phrase is) predicated * the earth, words denoting the 
object which that quality is affirmed of, compose the Subject, 
the word is, which serves as the connecting mark between the 
subject and predicate, to show that one of them is affirmed of 
the other, is called the Copula. ^ 

Dismissing, for the present, the copula, of which more will 
be said hereafter, every proposition, then, consists of at least 

2—2 



20 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


two names; brings together two names, m a particular manner 
This is already a first step towards what we are m quest of 
It appears from this, that for an act of belief, one object is not 
sufficient, the simplest act of belief supposes, and has some¬ 
thing to do with, two objects: two names, to say the least, 
and (since the names must be names of something) two name- 
able things. A large class of thinkers would cut the matter 
short by saymg, two ideas. They would say, that the subject 
and predicate are both of them names of ideas, the idea of 
gold, for instance, and the idea of yellow, and that what 
takes place (or part of what takes place) m the act of belief, 
consists m bringing (as it is often expressed) one of these 
ideas under the other But this we are not yet m a condition 
to say: whether such be the correct mode of describing the 
phenomenon, is an after consideration. The result with which 
for the present we must he contented, is, that m every act 
of belief two objects are m some manner taken cognizance 
of, that there can be no belief claimed, or question pro¬ 
pounded, which does not embrace two distinct (either material 
or intellectual) subjects of thought, each of them capable, or 
not, of being conceived by itself, but incapable of being be¬ 
lieved by itself 

I may say, for instance, “the sun." The word has a 
meaning, and suggests that meaning to the mind of any one 
who is listening to me But suppose I ask him, Whether it 
is true whether he believes it ? He can give no answer. 
There is as yet nothing to believe, or to disbelieve. Now, 
however, let me make, of all possible assertions respecting the 
sun, the one which involves the least of reference to any object 
besides itself, let me say, “the sun exists " Here, at once, is 
something which a person can say he believes. But here, in¬ 
stead of only one, we find two distinct objects of conception 
the sun is one object; existence is another. Let it not be 
said that this second conception, existence, is involved in the 
first, for the sun may be conceived as no longer existing. 
“ The sun" does not convey all the meaning that is conveyed 
by “the sun exists " “my father" does not include all the 
meaning of “ my father exists," for he may be dead; “ a round 



NECESSITY OF AN ANALYSIS OF NAMES. 


21 


square” does not include the meaning of “ a round square 
exists,” for it does not and cannot exist. When I say “ the 
sun,” “ my father,” or a “ round square,” I do not call upon 
the hearer for any belief or disbelief, nor can either the one or 
the other be afforded me, but if I say, “the sun exists,” “ my 
father exists, * or “ a round square exists,” I call for belief, 
and should, m the fiist of the three instances, meet with it, 
m the second, with belief or disbelief, as the case might be, m 
the third, with disbelief. 

§ 3. This fiist step m the analysis of the object of belief, 
which, though so obvious, will be found to be not unimportant, 
is the only one which we shall find it practicable to make with¬ 
out a preliminary survey of language. If we attempt to pio- 
ceed further m the same path, that is, to analyse any further 
the import of Propositions, we find forced upon us, as a sub¬ 
ject of previous consideration, the import of Names. For 
every proposition consists of two names, and every proposition 
affirms or denies one of these names, of the other. Now what 
we do, what passes m our mind, when we affirm or deny two 
names of one another, must depend on what they are names 
of; since it is with reference to that, and not to the mere 
names themselves, that we make the affirmation or denial. 
Here, therefore, we find a new reason why the signification of 
names, and the 1 elation generally between names and the 
things signified by them, must occupy the preliminary stage 
of the inquiry we are engaged m 

It may be objected that the meaning of names can guide 
us at most only to the opinions, possibly the foolish and 
groundless opinions, which mankind have formed concerning 
things, and that as the object of philosophy is truth, not 
opinion, the philosopher should dismiss words and look into 
things themselves, to ascertain what questions can be asked 
and answered m regard to them. This advice (which no one 
has it m his power to follow) is m reality an exhortation to 
discard the whole fruits of the labours of his predecessors, and 
conduct himself as if he were the first person who had ever 
turned an inquiring eye upon nature. What does any one s 



22 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


personal knowledge of Things amount to, after subtracting 
all which he has acquired by means of the words of other 
people ? Even after he has learned as much as people 
usually do learn from others, will the notions of things con¬ 
tained m his individual mmd afford as sufficient a basis for a 
catalogue raisonne as the notions which are m the minds of all 
mankind ? 

In any enumeration and classification of Things, which 
does not set out from their names, no varieties of things will 
of course be compi eh ended but those recognised by the par¬ 
ticular inquirer; and it will still remain to be established, by 
a subsequent examination of names, that the enumeration has 
omitted nothing which ought to have been included But if 
we begin with names, and use them as our clue to the things, 
we bnng at once before us all the distinctions which have been 
recognised, not by a single inquirer, but by all inquirers taken 
together. It doubtless may, and I believe it will, be found, 
that mankind have multiplied the varieties unnecessarily, and 
have imagined distinctions among things, where there were 
only distinctions m the manner of naming them. But we are 
not entitled to assume this m the commencement. We must 
begin by recognising the distinctions made by ordinary lan¬ 
guage. If some of these appear, on a close examination, not 
to be fundamental, the enumeration of the different kinds of 
realities may be abridged accordingly. But to impose upon 
the facts m the first instance the yoke of a theory, while 
the grounds of the theoiy are reserved for discussion m a sub¬ 
sequent stage, is not a course which a logician can reasonably 
adopt. 



CHAPTEE II. 


OF NAMES. 

§ 1. “A name,” says Hobbes,-fc “is a word taken at 
pleasure to serve for a maik which may raise m our mind a 
thought like to some thought we had before, and which being 
pronounced to others, may be to them a sign of what thought 
the speaker hadf before m his mind.” This simple definition 
of a name, as a word (or set of words) serving the double pur¬ 
pose of a mark to recall to ourselves the likeness of a former 
thought, and a sign to make it known to others, appears un¬ 
exceptionable. Names, indeed, do much more than this ; but 
whatever else they do, grows out of, and is the result of this : 
as will appear m its proper place. 

Are names more properly said to be the names of things, 
or of our ideas of things ? The first is the expression in com¬ 
mon use, the last is that of some metaphysicians, who con¬ 
ceived that m adopting it they were introducing a highly 
important distinction. The eminent thinker, just quoted, 
seems to countenance the latter opinion. “ But seeing,” he 
continues, “names ordered m speech (as is defined) are signs 
of our conceptions, it is manifest they are not signs of the 
things themselves ,* for that the sound of this word stone should 
be the sign of a stone, cannot be understood in any sense but 
this, that he that hears it collects that he that pronounces it 
thinks of a stone.” 

If it be merely meant that the conception alone, and not 
the thing itself, is recalled by the name, or imparted to the 
hearer, this of course cannot he denied. Nevertheless, there 
seems good reason for adhering to the common usage, and 


* Computation or Logic , chap u. 

+ la the original “ had, or had not These last words, as involving a 
subtlety foreign to our present purpose, I have forborne to quote. 




NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


£4 

calling the word sun the name of the sun, and not the name 
of our idea of the sun. For names are not intended only to 
make the hearer conceive what we conceive, hut also to in¬ 
form him what we "believe. Now, when I use a name for the 
purpose of expressing a belief, it is a belief concerning the 
thing itself, not concerning my idea of it When I say, “the 
sun is the cause of day/' I do not mean that my idea of the 
sun causes or excites m me the idea of day, or m other 
words, that thmking of the sun makes me think of day I 
mean, that a certain physical fact, which is called the sun s 
presence (and which, m the ultimate analysis, resolves itself 
into sensations, not ideas) causes another physical fact, which 
is called day. It seems proper to consider a word as the 
name of that which we intend to be understood by it when 
we use it; of that which any fact that we assert of it is to be 
understood of, that, m short, concerning which, when we 
employ the word, we intend to give information. Names, 
therefore, shall always be spoken of m this work as the names 
of things themselves, and not merely of our ideas of things. 

But the question now arises, of what things ? and to 
answer this it is necessary to take into consideration the 
different kinds of names. 

§ 2. It is usual, before examining the various classes into 
which names are commonly divided, to begin by distinguishing 
from names of every description, those words which are not 
names, but only parts of names. Among such are reckoned 
particles, as of, to, truly, often; the inflected cases of nouns 
substantive, as me, him> Johns ; and even adjectives, as large, 
heavy. These words do not express things of which anything 
can be affirmed or denied We cannot say, Heavy fell, or A 
heavy fell, Truly, or A truly, was asserted, Of, or An of, was 
in the room. Unless, indeed, we are speaking of the mere 
words themselves, as when we say, Truly is an English word, 
or. Heavy is an adjective. In that case they are complete 
names, viz. names of those particular sounds, or of those 
particular collections of written characters. This employment 
of a word to denote the mere letters and syllables of which it 



NAMES. 


25 


is composed, was termed by the schoolmen the suppositio 
matenalis of the word. In any other sense we cannot intro¬ 
duce one of these words into the subject of a proposition, 
unless m combination with other words, as, A heavy body 
fell, A truly important fact was asserted, A member of parlia* 
ment was m the room. 

An adjective, however, is capable of standing by itself as 
the predicate of a proposition; as when we say, Snow is white, 
and occasionally even as the subject, for we may say, White is 
an agreeable colour. The adjective is often said to be so used 
by a grammatical ellipsis * Snow is white, instead of Snow is 
a white object. White is an agreeable colour, instead of, A 
white colour, or, The colour white, is agreeable. The Greeks 
and Romans were allowed, by the rules of their language, to 
employ this ellipsis universally m the subject as well as m the 
predicate of a proposition In English this cannot, generally 
speaking, be done. We may say, The earth is round ; but we 
cannot say, Round is easily moved; we must say, A round 
object This distinction, however, is rather grammatical than 
logical. Since there is no difference of meaning between 
round, and a round object, it is only custom which prescribes 
that on any given occasion one shall be used, and not the 
other We shall, therefore, without scruple, speak of adjec¬ 
tives as names, whether m their own right, or as representative 
of the more circuitous forms of expression above exemplified. 
The other classes of subsidiary words have no title whatever 
to be considered as names. An adverb, or an accusative case, 
cannot under any circumstances (except when their mere letters 
and syllables are spoken of) figure as one of the terms of a 
proposition. 

Words which are not capable of being used as names, but 
■only as parts of names, were called by some of the schoolmen 
Syncategorematic terms; from ow, with, and (car^yopew, to 
predicate, because it was only with some other word that they 
could be predicated. A word which could be used either as 
the subject or predicate of a proposition without being accom¬ 
panied by any other word, was termed by the same authorities 
a Categorematic term. A combination of one or more Cate- 



26 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


gorematic, and one or more Syncategorematic words, as A 
heavy body, or A court of justice, they sometimes called a 
mixed term, but this seems a needless multiplication of 
technical expressions A mixed term is, in the only useful 
sense of the word, Categorematic. It belongs to the class of 
what have been called many-worded names. 

For, as one word is frequently not a name, but only part 
of a name, so a number of words often compose one single 
name, and no more. These words, “the place which the 
wisdom or policy of antiquity had destined for the residence 
of the Abyssinian princes,” form in the estimation of the 
logician only one name; one Categorematic term. A mode 
of determining whether any set of words makes only one 
name, or more than one, is by predicating something of it, 
and observing whether, by this predication, we make only one 
assertion or several. Thus, when we say, John Nokes, who 
was the mayor of the town, died yesterday—by this predica¬ 
tion we make but one assertion, whence it appears that 
“John Nokes, who was the mayor of the town,” is no more 
than one name It is true that m this proposition, besides 
the assertion that John Nokes died vesteiday, theie is included 
another assertion, namely, that John Nokes was mayor of the 
town. But this last assertion was already made . we did not 
make it by adding the predicate, “ died yesterday.” Suppose, 
however, that the words had been, John Nokes and the mayor 
of the town, they would have formed two names instead of 
one For when we say, John Nokes and the mayor of the 
town died yesterday, we make two assertions; one, that John 
Nokes died yesterday; the other, that the mayor of the town 
died yesterday. 

It being needless to illustrate at any greater length the 
subject of many-worded names, we proceed to the distinctions 
which have been established among names, not according to 
the words they are composed of, but according to their 
signification. 

§ 3. All names are names of something, real or imagi¬ 
nary ; but all things have not names appropriated to them 



NAMES. 


27 


individually. For some individual objects we require, and 
consequently have, separate distinguishing names, there is a 
name for every person, and for every remarkable place Other 
objects, of which we have not occasion to speak so frequently, 
we do not designate by a name of their own, but when the 
necessity arises for naming them, we do so by putting together 
seveial woids, each of which, by itself, might be and is used 
for an indefinite number of other objects, as when I say, this 
stone “this” and “stone” being, each of them, names that 
may be used of many other objects besides the particular one 
meant, though the only object of which they can both be used 
at the given moment, consistently with their signification, may 
be the one of which I wish to speak. 

Were this the sole purpose for which names, that are 
common to more things than one, could he employed, if they 
only served, by mutually limiting each other, to afford a 
designation for such individual objects as have no names of 
their own, they could only be ranked among contrivances for 
economizing the use of language. But it is evident that this 
is not their sole function. It is by their means that we are 
enabled to assert general propositions, to affirm or deny any 
predicate of an indefinite number of things at once. The 
distinction, therefore, between general names, and individual 
or singular names, is fundamental, and may be considered as 
the first grand division of names. 

A general name is familiarly defined, a name which is 
capable of being truly affirmed, in the same sense, of each of 
an indefinite number of things. An individual or singular 
name is a name which is only capable of being truly affirmed, 
in the same sense, of one thing. 

Thus, man is capable of being truly affirmed of John, 
George, Mary, and other persons without assignable limit; 
and it is affirmed of all of them m the same sense, for the 
word man expresses certain qualities, and when we predicate 
it of those persons, we assert that they all possess those 
quahties. But John is only capable of being truly affirmed of 
one single person, at least m the same sense. For though 
there are many persons who bear that name, it is not conferred 



28 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


upon them to indicate any qualities, or anything which be¬ 
longs to them m common ; and cannot be said to be affirmed 
of them m any sense at all, consequently not m the same 
sense. “ The king who succeeded William the Conqueror,” is 
also an individual name For, that there cannot be more than 
one person of whom it nan be truly affirmed, is implied m the 
meaning of the words. Even “ the king,” when the occasion 
or the context defines the individual of whom it is to be 
understood, may justly be regarded as an individual name. 

It is not unusual, by way of explaining what is meant by 
a genera] name, to say that it is the name of a class . But 
this, though a convenient mode of expression for some pur¬ 
poses, is objectionable as a definition, since it explains the 
clearer of two things by the more obscure. It would be more 
logical to reverse the proposition, and turn it into a definition 
of the word elass “ A class is the indefinite multitude of 
individuals denoted by a general name.” 

It is necessary to distinguish general from collective 
names. A geneial name is one which can be piedicated of 
each individual of a multitude, a collective name cannot be 
predicated of each separately, but only of all taken together. 
£ * The 76th regiment of foot m the British army,” which is a 
collective name, is not a general but an individual name, for 
though it can be predicated of a multitude of individual 
soldiers taken jointly, it cannot be predicated of them severally. 
We may say, Jones is a soldier, and Thompson is a soldier, 
and Smith is a soldier, but we cannot say, Jones is the 76th 
regiment, and Thompson is the 76th regiment, and Smith is 
the 76th regiment. We can only say, Jones, and Thompson, 
and Smith, and Brown, and so forth (enumerating all the 
soldiers), are the 76th regiment. 

“ The 76th regiment” is a collective name, but not a 
general one “ a regiment” is both a collective and a general 
name. General with respect to all individual regiments, of 
each of which separately it can be affirmed, collective with 
respect to the individual soldiers of whom any regiment is 
composed. 



NAMES. 


29 


§ 4 The second general division of names is into con¬ 
crete and abstract. A concrete name is a name which stands 
for a thing; an abstract name is a name which stands for an 
attribute of a thing. Thus John, the sea, this table, are names 
of things. White, also, is a name of a thing, or rather of 
things. Whiteness, again, is the name of a quality or attri¬ 
bute of those things. Man is a name of many things, 
humanity is a name of an attribute of those things. Old 
is a name of things; old age is a name of one of their 
attributes. 

I have used the words concrete and abstract in the sense 
annexed to them by the schoolmen, who, notwithstanding the 
imperfections of their philosophy, were unrivalled m the con¬ 
struction of technical language, and whose definitions, in logic 
at least, though they never went more than a little way into 
the subject, have seldom, I think, been altered but to be 
spoiled. A practice, however, has grown up m more modern 
times, which, if not introduced by Locke, has gained currency 
chiefly from his example, of applying the expression “ abstract 
name” to all names which are the result of abstraction or 
generalization, and consequently to all general names, instead 
of confining it to the names of attributes The metaphysicians 
of the Condillac school,—whose admiration of Locke, passing 
over the profoundest speculations of that truly original genius, 
usually fastens with peculiar eagerness upon his weakest 
points,—have gone on imitating him m this abuse of language, 

^ until there is now some difficulty m restoring the word to its 
original signification A more wanton alteration m the mean¬ 
ing of a word is rarely to be met with; for the expression 
general name, the exact equivalent of which exists m all lan¬ 
guages I am acquainted with, was already available for the 
purpose to which abstract has been misappropriated, while the 
misappropriation leaves that important class of words, the 
names of attributes, without any compact distinctive appella¬ 
tion The old acceptation, however, has not gone so com¬ 
pletely out of use, as to deprive those who still adhere to it of 
all chance of being understood By abstract, then, I shall 
always, in Logic, mean the opposite of concrete: by an ab- 



so 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


struct name, the name of an attribute , by a concrete name, the 
name of an object. 

Do abstract names belong to tbe class of general, or to 
that of singular names ? Some of them are certainly general. 
I mean those which are names not of one single and definite 
attribute, but of a class of attributes. Such is the word colour, 
which is a name common to whiteness, redness, &c. Such is 
even the woid whiteness, m respect of the diffeient shades of 
whiteness to which it is applied m common, the word magni¬ 
tude, m respect of the various degrees of magnitude and the 
various dimensions of space, the word weight, m respect of 
the various degrees of weight. Such also is the word attribute 
itself, the common name of all particular attributes. But 
when only one attribute, neither variable in degree nor m 
kind, is designated by the name, as visibleness; tangibleness, 
equality, squareness; milkwhiteness, then the name can 
hardly be considered general, for though it denotes an attri¬ 
bute of many different objects, the attribute itself is always 
conceived as one, not many * To avoid needless logomachies, 
the best course would probably be to consider these names as 
neither general nor individual, and to place them m a class 
apart. 

It may be objected to our definition of an abstract name, 
that not only the names which we have called abstract, but 
adjectives, which we have placed m the concrete class, aie 
names of attributes, that white , for example, is as much the 
name of the colour as whiteness is. But (as before remarked) 
a word ought to be considered as the name of that which we 
intend to be understood by it when we put it to its principal 
use, that is, when we employ it m predication When we say 
snow is white, milk is white, linen is white, we do not mean 
it to be understood that snow, or lmen, or milk, is a colour. 
We mean that they are things having the colour. The reverse 
is the case with the word whiteness, what we affirm to be 
whiteness is not snow, but the colour of snow. Whiteness, 
therefore, is the name of the colour exclusively: white is a 


Yide infra, note at the end of § 3, book 11 . ch u. 



NAMES. 


31 


name of all things whatever having the colour, a name, not of 
the quality whiteness, hut of every white object It is true, 
this name was given to all those various ohjects on account of 
the quality, and we may therefore say, without impropriety, 
that the quality forms part of its signification, but a name 
can only be said to stand for, or to be a name of, the things of 
which it can be predicated. We shall presently see that all 
names which can be said to have any signification, all names 
by applying which to an individual we give any information 
respecting that individual, may be said to imply an attribute 
of some sort, but they are not names of the attribute, it has 
its own proper abstract name. 

§ 5. This leads to the consideration of a third great 
division of names, into connotative and non-connotative, the 
latter sometimes, but improperly, called absolute. This is one 
of the most important distinctions which we shall have occa¬ 
sion to point out, and one of those which go deepest into the 
nature of language. 

A non-connotative term is one which signifies a subject 
only, or an attribute only. A connotative term is one which 
denotes a subject, and implies an attribute. By a subject is 
here meant anything which possesses attributes Thus John, 
or London, or England, are names which signify a subject 
only. Whiteness, length, virtue, signify an attribute only. 
None of these names, therefore, are connotative. But white, 
long, mituous, aie connotative. The word white, denotes all 
white things, as snow, paper, the foam of the sea, &c, and 
implies, or as it was termed by the schoolmen, connotes* the 
attribute whiteness . The word white is not predicated of the 
attribute, but of the subjects, snow, &c., but when we predi¬ 
cate it of them, we imply, or connote, that the attribute white¬ 
ness belongs to them. The same may be said of the other 
words above cited. Virtuous, for example, is the name of a 
class, which includes Socrates, Howard, the Man of Boss, and 


* Notar e, to mark; cm motare, to mark along with, to mark one thing with 
or m addition to another. 



32 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


an undefinable number of other individuals, past, present, and 
to come. These individuals, collect] vely and severally, can 
alone be said with propriety to he denoted by the word of 
them alone can it properly be said to be a name But it is a 
name applied to all of them m consequence of an attribute 
which they aie supposed to possess in common, the attribute 
which has received the name of virtue. It is applied to all 
beings that are considered to possess this attribute; and to 
none which are not so considered. 

All concrete general names are connotative. The word 
man, for example, denotes Peter, Jane, John, and an indefinite 
number of other individuals, of whom, taken as a class, it is 
the name. But it is applied to them, because they possess, 
and to signify that they possess, certain attributes These 
seem to be, corporeity, animal life, rationality, and a certain 
external form, which for distinction we call the human. Every 
existing thing, which possessed all these attributes, would be 
called a man, and anything which possessed none of them, or 
only one, or two, or even three of them without the fourth, 
would not be so called Eor example, if m the interior of 
Africa there were to be discovered a race of animals possessing 
reason equal to that of human beings, but with the form of an 
elephant, they would not be called men Swift’s Houyhnhnms 
would not be so called Or if such newly-discovered beings 
possessed the form of man without any vestige of reason, it is 
probable that some other name than that of man would be 
found for them. How it happens that there can be any doubt 
about the matter, will appear hereafter. The word man, 
therefore, signifies all these attributes, and all subjects which 
possess these attributes. But it can be predicated only of the 
subjects What we call men, are the subjects, the individual 
Stiles and Notes , not the qualities by which their humanity 
is constituted The nam&, therefore, is said to signify the 
subjects directly , the attributes indirectly; it denotes the 
subjects, and implies, or involves, or indicates, or as we shall 
say henceforth connotes, the attubutes. It is a connotative 
name. 

Connotative names have hence been also called denominative. 



NAMES. 


33 


because the subject which they denote is denominated by, or 
receives a name from, the attribute which they connote. Snow, 
and other objects, receive the name white, because they possess 
the attribute which is called whiteness, Peter, James, and 
others receive the name man, because they possess the attri¬ 
butes which are considered to constitute humanity. The 
attribute, or attributes, may theiefore be said to denominate 
those objects, or to give them a common name> 

It has been seen that all concrete general names are conno- 
tative. Even abstract names, though the names only of attri¬ 
butes, may m some instances be justly considered as connota- 
tive, for attributes themselves may have attributes ascribed to 
them; and a word which denotes attributes may connote an 
attribute of those attnbutes. Of this description, for example, 
is such a word as fault , equivalent to bad or hurtful quahty . 
This woid is a name common to many attnbutes, and connotes 
hurtfulness, an attnbute of those various attributes. When, 
for example, we say that slowness, m a horse, is a fault, we 
do not mean that the slow movement, the actual change of 
place of the slow horse, is a bad thing, but that the property 
or peculiarity of the horse, from which it derives that name, 
the quality of being a slow mover, is an undesirable peculiarity. 

In regard to those concrete names which are not general 
but individual, a distinction must be made. 

Proper names are not connotative: they denote the indi¬ 
viduals who aie called by them, but they do not indicate or 
imply any attnbutes as belonging to those individuals. When 
we name a child by the name Paul, or a dog by the name 
Csesar, these names are simply marks used to enable those 
individuals to be made subjects of discourse. It may be said, 
indeed, that we must have had some reason for giving them 


* Archbishop Whately, who, m the later editions of tus Elements of Log%c } 
aided m reviving the important distinction tieated of m the text, pioposes the 
term “Attributive” as a substitute for "Connotative” (p 22, 9th ed) The 
expiession is, m itself, appropnate, but as it has not the advantage of being 
connected with any verb, of so markedly distinctive a character as 4 Ho connote,” 
it is not, I think, fitted to supply the place of the word Connotative m scienti¬ 
fic use. 


VOL. I, 


3 



34 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


those names rather than any others, and this is true, hut 
the name, once given, is independent of the reason A man 
may have been named John, because that was the name of his 
father, a town may have been named Dartmouth, because it 
is situated at the mouth of the Dart. But it is no part of the 
signification of the woid John, that the father of the person so 
called bore the same name, noi even of the word Dartmouth, 
to be situated at the mouth of the Dait. If sand should choke 
up the mouth of the river, or an eaithquake change its course, 
and lemove it to a distance from the town, the name of the 
town would not necessarily be changed. That fact, therefore, 
can foim no part of the signification of the woid, for other¬ 
wise, when the fact confessedly ceased to be true, no one would 
any longer thmk of applying the name Proper names aie 
attached to the objects themselves, and aie not dependent on 
the continuance of any attribute of the object 

But there is another kind of names, which, although they 
are individual names, that is, predicable only of one object, 
are really connotative For, though we may give to an in¬ 
dividual a name utterly unmeaning, which we call a proper 
name,—a woid which answeis the purpose of showing what 
thing it is we are talking about, but not of telling anything 
about it, yet a name peculiar to an individual is not neces¬ 
sarily of this description. It may be significant of some 
attribute, or some union of attnbutes, which, being possessed 
by no object but one, determines the name exclusively to that 
individual. “ The sun” is a name of this description, “ God,” 
when used by a monotheist, is another These, however, are 
scaicely examples of what we are now attempting to illus¬ 
trate, being, in strictness of language, general, not individual 
names- for, however they may be m fact predicable only of 
one object, there is nothing m the meaning of the words 
themselves which implies this and, accordingly, when we 
aie imagining and not affirming, we may speak of many suns, 
and the majority of mankind have believed, and still believe, 
that there are many gods. But it is easy to produce words 
which are real instances of connotative individual names. It 
may be part of the meaning of the connotative name itself, 



NAMES. 


35 


that there can exist but one individual possessing the attribute 
winch it connotes as, foi instance, “ the only sou of John 
Stiles“ the fast emperor of Borne.” Or the attiibute 
connoted may be a connexion with some determinate event, 
and the connexion may be of such a kind as only one individual 
could have, 01 may at least be such as only one individual 
actually had, and this may be implied m the form of the 
expression “ The father of Socrates ” is an example of the 
one kind (since Socrates could not have had two fathers) , 
“ the authoi of the Iliad,” “ the murderer of Henri Quatie,” 
of the second. For, though it is conceivable that more 
persons than one might have participated m the authoi ship of 
the Iliad, or m the murder of Henri Quatre, the employment 
of the aiticle the implies that, m fact, this was not the case 
What is here done by the word the , is done m othei cases by 
the context thus, “ Caesar’s army ” is an individual name, if 
it appeals fiom the context that the army meant is that which 
Caesar commanded in a paiticular battle The still more 
general expressions, “the Boman army,” or “the Christian 
army,” may be individualized in a similar manner. Another 
case of frequent occurrence has already been noticed , it is the 
following The name, being a many-worded one, may consist, 
m the first place, of a general n^me, capable therefoie in itself 
of being afihmed of more things than one, but which is, m the 
second place, so limited b} othei woids joined with it, that the 
entire expression can only be predicated of one object, consis¬ 
tently with the meaning of the general term This is exem¬ 
plified m such an instance as the following * “ the present 
prime minister of England.” Prime Minister of England is a 
general name, the attributes which it connotes may be pos¬ 
sessed by an indefinite number of persons m succession 
however, not simultaneously, since the meaning of the name 
itself imports (among other things) that there can be only 
one such person at a time This being the case, and the 
application of the name being afterwards limited by the aiticle 
and the word present, to such individuals as possess the 
attributes at one indivisible point of time, it becomes applicable 
only to one individual. And as this appears from the 

3—2 


mean- 



36 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


ing of the name, without any extrinsic proof, it is strictly an 
individual name. 

Fxom the preceding observations it will easily be collected, 
that whenever the names given to objects convey any in¬ 
formation, that is, whenevei they have propeily any meaning, 
the meaning resides not m what they denote, hut m what they 
connote. The only names of objects which connote nothing 
aie proper names , and these have, stnctiy speaking, no signi¬ 
fication.* 

If, like the robber m the Arabian Nights, we make a mark 
with chalk on a house to enable us to know it again, the mark 
has a purpose, but it has not propeily any meaning The 
chalk does not declaie anything about the house; it does not 
mean, This is such a person’s house, or This is a house which 
contains booty. The object of making the mark is merely dis¬ 
tinction I say to myself, All these houses aie so nearly alike 
that if I lose sight of them I shall not again be able to dis¬ 
tinguish that which I am now looking at, from any of the 
others, I must therefore contuve to make the appealance of 
this one house unlike that of the others, that I may hereafter 
know, when I see the maik—not indeed any attribute of the 
house—but simply that it is the same house which I am now 
looking at. Morgiana chalked all the other houses m a similar 
manner, and defeated the scheme how 9 simply by obliterating 
the difference of appearance between that house and the others. 
The chalk was still there, but it no longer served the purpose 
of a distmctive'mark. 

When we impose a proper name, we perform an operation 


* A writer who entitles his book Philosophy ; 07 , the Science of Truth, 
chaiges me m his very first page (lefemng at the foot of it to this passage) 
with asserting that general names have properly no signification And he 
repeats this statement many times in the course of his volume, with comments, 
not at allflatteung, thereon. It is well to be now and then reminded to how 
great a length perverse misquotation (for, strange as it appears, I do not believe 
that the writei is dishonest) can sometimes go It is a warning to leaders, 
when they see an author accused, with volume and page refened to, and the 
apparent guarantee of inverted commas, of maintaining something more than 
commonly absurd, not to give implicit credence to the assertion without veri¬ 
fying the reference. 



NAMES. 


37 


in some degree analogous to what the robher intended m chalk¬ 
ing the house We put a mark, not indeed upon the object 
itself, but, so to speak, upon the idea of the object A proper 
name is but an unmeaning mark which we connect m our 
minds with the idea of the object, m order that whenever the 
mark meets our eyes or occurs to our thoughts, we may think 
of that individual object Not being attached to the thing 
itself, it does not, like the chalk, enable us to distinguish the 
object when we see it, but it enables us to distinguish it 
when it is spoken of, either m the records of our own ex- 
penence, 01 m the discourse of others, to know that what we 
find asserted m any proposition of which it is the subj ect, is 
asserted of the individual thing with which we were previously 
acquainted. 

When we predicate of anything its proper name, when 
we say, pointing to a man, this is Brown or Smith, or point¬ 
ing to a city, that it is York, we do not, merely by so doing, 
convey to the heaier any information about them, except that 
those are their names. By enabling him to identify the in¬ 
dividuals, we may connect them with information previously 
possessed by him, by saying, This is York, we may tell him 
that it contains the Minster. But this is m virtue of what 
he has previously heard concerning York; not by anything 
implied m the name. It is otherwise when objects are spoken 
of by connotative names When we say, The town is built 
of marble, we give the hearer what may be entirely new in¬ 
formation, and this merely by the signification of the maiiy- 
worded connotative name, <c built of marble.” Such names 
are not signs of the mere objects, invented because we have 
occasion to think and speak of those objects individually; 
but signs which accompany an attribute a kind of livery m 
which the attribute clothes all objects which are recognised as, 
possessing it They are not mere marks, but more, that is to 
say, significant marks, and the connotation is what constitutes 
their significance. 

As a proper name is said to be the name of the one indi¬ 
vidual which it is predicated of, so (as well from the importance 
of adhering to analogy, as for the other reasons formerly as- 



58 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


signed) a connotative name ought to he consideied a name of 
all the vaiious individuals which it is predicable of, 01 m other 
woids denotes, and not of what it connotes But by learning 
what things it is a name of, we do not learn the meaning of 
the name foi to the same thing we may, with equal propriety, 
apply many names, not equivalent m meaning Thus, I call 
a certain man by the name Sophiomscus I call him by 
another name, The father of Socrates. Both these are names 
of the same individual, hut their meaning is altogether dif¬ 
ferent, they are applied to that individual for two different 
purposes, the one, merely to distinguish him from other per¬ 
sons who aie spoken of, the other to indicate a fact relating 
to him, the fact that Sociates was Ins son I further apply to 
him these other expressions a man, a Greek, an Athenian, a 
sculptor, an old man, an honest man, a biave man All these 
are, or may be, names of Sophroniscus, not indeed of him 
alone, but of him and each of an indefinite number of othei 
human beings Each of these names is applied to Sophro- 
niscus for a diffeient reason, and by each whoever understands 
its meaning is apprised of a distinct fact or number of facts 
concerning him, but those who knew nothing about the names 
except that they were applicable to Sophroniscus, would be al¬ 
together ignorant of their meaning It is even possible that I 
might know eveiy single individual of whom a given name 
could be with tiuth affirmed, and yet could not be said to know 
the meaning of the name A child knows who are its brothers 
and sisters, long before it has any definite conception of the 
nature of the facts which are involved m the signification of 
those words. 

In some cases it is not easy to decide precisely how much 
a paiticular word does or does not connote , that is, we do not 
exactly know (the case not having arisen) what degree of dif¬ 
ference m the object would occasion a difference m the name 
Thus, it is clear that the word man, besides animal life and 
rationality, connotes also a ceitain external form, but it would 
be impossible to say precisely what form, that is, to decide 
how great a deviation from the form ordinarily found m the 
beings whom we are accustomed to call men, would suffice m 



NAMES. 


39 


a newly-discovered race to make us refuse them the name of 
man. Rationality, also, being a quality which admits of de- 
giees, it has never been settled what is the lowest degiee of 
that quality which would entitle any cieature to he con¬ 
sidered a human being In all such cases, the meaning of the 
general name is so fai unsettled and vague, mankind have not 
come to any positive agreement about the matter When we 
come to ti eat of Classification, we shall have occasion to show 
under what conditions this vagueness may exist without 
piactical inconvenience, and cases will appear m which the 
ends of language are better promoted by it than by complete 
piecision , m order that, m natural history for instance, indi¬ 
viduals or species of no very marked character may be ranged 
with those moie stiongly characterized individuals 01 species 
to which, m all their properties taken together, they bear the 
neaiest resemblance. 

But this partial uncertainty m the connotation of names 
can only be free from mischief when guarded by strict precau¬ 
tions. One of the chief sources, indeed, of lax habits of thought, 
is the custom of using connotative terms without a distinctly 
ascertained connotation, and with no more precise notion of 
their meaning than can be loosely collected from observing 
what objects they are used to denote It is m this manner that 
we all acquire, and inevitably so, our first knowledge of our 
vernacular language. A child learns the meaning of the 
words man , or tvhite, by hearing them applied to a variety of 
individual objects, and finding out, by a piocess of generali¬ 
zation and analysis which he could not himself describe, 
what those different objects have m common. In the case of 
these two words the process is so easy as to require no as¬ 
sistance fiom culture, the objects called human beings, and 
the objects called white, differing from all otheis by qualities 
of a peculiarly definite and obvious character. But m many 
other cases, objects bear a general resemblance to one another, 
which leads to their being familiarly classed together under a 
common name, while, without more analytic habits than the 
generality of mankind possess, it is not immediately apparent 
what are the particular attributes, upon the possession of which 



40 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


m common by them all, their general resemblance depends. 
When this is the case, people use the name without any re¬ 
cognised connotation, that is, without any precise meaning; 
they talk, and consequently think, vaguely, and remain con¬ 
tented to attach only the same degree of significance to their 
own words, which a child three years old attaches to the words 
brother and sister. The child at least is seldom puzzled by 
the starting up of new individuals, on whom he is ignorant 
whether or not to confer the title, because there is usually an 
authority close at hand competent to solve all doubts But a 
similar resource does not exist m the generality of cases, and 
new objects are continually presenting themselves to men, 
women, and children, which they are called upon to class pro- 
pno motu. They, accordingly, do this on no other principle 
than that of superficial similanty, giving to each new object 
the name of that familiar obj ect, the idea of which it most 
readily recalls, or which, on a cursory inspection, it seems to 
them most to resemble. as an unknown substance found in 
the ground will be called, according to its texture, earth, sand, 
or a stone. In this manner, names cieep on from subject to 
subject, until all traces of a common meaning sometimes dis¬ 
appear, and the word comes to denote a number of things not 
only independently of any common attribute, but which have 
actually no attribute m common, or none but what is shared 
by other things to which the name is capriciously refused. 
Even scientific writers have aided m this perversion of general 
language from its purpose, sometimes because, like the vulgar, 
they knew no better; and sometimes m deference to that 
aversion to admit new words, which induces mankind, on all 
subjects not considered technical, to attempt to make the 
original stock of names serve with but little augmentation to 
express a constantly increasing number of objects and distinc¬ 
tions, and, consequently, to express them m a manner pro¬ 
gressively more and more imperfect, s/ 

To what a degree this loose mode of classing and denomi¬ 
nating objects has rendered the vocabulary of mental and moral 
philosophy unfit for the purposes of accurate thinking, is best 
known to whoever has most meditated on the present condi- 



NAMES. 


41 


tion of those branches of knowledge. Since, however, the 
introduction of a new technical language as the vehicle of 
speculations on subjects belonging to the domain of daily dis¬ 
cussion, is extremely difficult to effect, and would not he free 
from inconvenience even if effected, the problem for the philo¬ 
sopher, and one of the most difficult which he has to resolve, 
is, m retaining the existing phraseology, how best to alleviate 
its impeifections. This can only he accomplished by giving to 
every general concrete name which there is frequent occasion 
to predicate, a definite and fixed connotation, m order that it 
may he known what attributes, when we call an object by that 
name, we really mean to predicate of the object And the 
question of most nicety is, how to give this fixed connotation 
to a name, with the least possible change m the objects which 
the name is habitually employed to denote, with the least 
possible disarrangement, either by adding or subtraction, of 
the group of obj'ects which, m however imperfect a manner, it 
serves to circumscribe and hold together, and with the least 
vitiation of the truth of any propositions which are commonly 
received as true. 

This desirable purpose, of giving a fixed connotation where 
it is wanting, is the end aimed at whenever any one attempts 
to give a definition of a general name already in use; every 
definition of a connotative name being an attempt either 
merely to declare, or to declare and analyse, the connotation of 
the name And the fact, that no questions which have arisen 
in the moral sciences have been subjects of keener controversy 
than the definitions of almost all the leading expressions, is a 
proof how great an extent the evil to which we have adverted 
has attained. 

Names with indeterminate connotation are not to he con¬ 
founded with names which have more than one connotation, 
that is to say, ambiguous words. A word may have several 
meanings, but all of them fixed and recognised ones; as the 
word post , for example, or the word box, the various senses of 
which it would he endless to enumerate. And the paucity of 
existing names, in comparison with the demand for them, may 
often render it advisable and even necessary to retain a name 



42 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


m tins multiplicity of acceptations, distinguishing these so 
clearly as to prevent their being confounded with one another. 
Such a woid may he considered as two or moie names, acci¬ 
dentally written and spoken alike + 

§ 6 The fourth principal division of names, is into posi¬ 
tive and negative . Positive, as man, tree, good; negative, as 
not-man, not-tiee, not-good. To every positive concrete name, 
a corresponding negative one might he framed. After giving 
a name to any one thing, or to any plurality of things, we 
might create a second name which should he a name of all 
things whatever, except that particular thing or things These 
negative names are employed whenever we have occasion 
to speak collectively of all things other than some thing or 
class of things When the positive name is connotative, the 
corresponding negative name is connotative likewise , hut m 
a peculiar way, connoting not the presence but the absence of 
an attribute. Thus, not-white denotes all things whatever 
except white things; and connotes the attribute of not possess- 


* Before quitting the subject of connotative names, it is proper to observe, 
that the first writer who, m our times, has adopted from the schoolmen the 
word to connote, Mr James Mill, m his Analysis of the Phenomena of the 
Human Mind, employs it m a signification different from that in which it is 
here used He uses the word m a sense coextensive with its etymology, apply¬ 
ing it to every case m which a name, while pointing directly to one thing, 
(which is consequently termed its signification,) includes also a tacit reference 
to some other thing In the case considered m the text, that of concrete gene¬ 
ral names, his language and mine are the conveise of one another Consideung 
(very justly) the signification of the name to lie m the attribute, he speaks of 
the word as noting the attribute, and connoting the things possessing the attn- 
bute. And he describes abstiact names as being properly concrete names with 
their connotation diopped. whereas, m my view, it is the denotation which 
would be said to be dropped, what was previously connoted becoming the whole 8 
signification 

In adopting a phraseology at variance with that which so high an authority, 
and one which I am less likely than any othei peison to undervalue, has deli¬ 
berately sanctioned, I have been influenced by the urgent necessity for a term 
exclusively appropnated to express the manner m which a concrete general 
name serves to mark the attributes which are involved in its signification, This 
necessity can scarcely be felt m its full force by any one who has not found by 
experience how vain is the attempt to communicate clear ideas on the philo¬ 
sophy of language without such a woid It is hardly an exaggeiation to say, 



NAMES. 


43 


mg whiteness For the non-possession of any given attribute 
is also an attubute, and may leceive a name as such, and thus 
negative conciete names may obtain negative abstract names 
to conespond to them. 

Names which aie positive m form are often negative m 
reality, and otheis are really positive though their foim is 
negative The word inconvenient , for example, does not 
expiess the mere absence of convenience, it expresses a posi¬ 
tive attnbute, that of being the cause of discomfort 01 annoy¬ 
ance So the word unpleasant, notwithstanding its negative 
foim, does not connote the mere absence of pleasantness, but 
a less degree of what is signified by the woid painful , which, 
it is haidly necessaiy to say, is positive. Idle , on the other 
hand, is a woid which, though positive m form, expresses 
nothing but what would be signified either by the phrase not 
ivorking, or by the phrase not disposed to woik; and sober, 
eithei by not drunk or by not drunken. 

There is a class of names called pnvative A privative 
name is equivalent m its signification to a positive and a nega- 


tliat some of the most pievalent of the errors with which logic has been infected, 
and a large part of the cloudiness and confusion of ideas which have enveloped 
it, would, m all piobability, have been avoided, if a term had been m common 
use to express exactly what I have signified by the term to connote And the 
schoolmen, to whom we are indebted for the greater part of our logical language, 
gave us this also, and m this very sense Eor though some of their general 
expressions countenance the use of the word m the more extensive and vague 
acceptation m which it is taken by Mr Mill, yet when they had to define it 
specifically as a technical term, and to fix its meaning as such, with that admir¬ 
able precision which always characterizes their definitions, they clearly explained 
that nothing was said to be connoted except forms, which woid may generally, 
m their wntmgs, be undeistood as synonymous with attributes 
* Now, if the v ord to connote, so well suited to the purpose to which they 
applied it, be diverted from that purpose by being taken to fulfil another, 
for which it does not seem to me to be at all required, I am unable to find any 
expression to replace it, but such as are commonly employed m a sense so much 
moie general, that it would be useless attempting to associate them peculiarly 
with this precise idea Such are the words, to involve, to imply, &c By em¬ 
ploying these, I should fail of attaining the object for which alone the name is 
needed, namely, to distinguish this particular kind of involving and implying 
from all other kinds, and to assure to it the degree of habitual attention which 
its importance demands. 



44 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


tive name taken together; being the name of something which 
has once had a paiticular attribute, or for some othei reason 
might have been expected to have it, but which has it not. 
Such is the word blind, which is not equivalent to not seeing , 
or to not capable of seeing, foi it would not, except by a poetical 
or rhetorical figure, be applied to stocks and stones. A thing 
is not usually said to be blind, unless the class to which it is 
most familiarly referred, or to which it is referied on the par¬ 
ticular occasion, be chiefly composed of things which can see, 
as m the case of a blind man, or a blind horse, or unless it is 
supposed for any leason that it ought to see; as m saying of 
a man, that he rushed blindly into an abyss, or of philosophers 
or the clergy that the greater part of them aie blind guides. 
The names called privative, therefore, connote two things the 
absence of certain attributes, and the presence of others, from 
which the presence also of the former might naturally have 
been expected. 

§ 7 The fifth leading division of names is into relative 
and absolute, or let us rather say, relative and non-relative; 
for the word absolute is put upon much too haid duty m me- 
itaphysies, not to be willingly spared when its services can be 
dispensed with It resembles the word civil m the language 
of jurisprudence, which stands for the opposite of criminal, the 
opposite of ecclesiastical, the opposite of military, the opposite 
of political—m short, the opposite of any positive word which 
wants a negative. 

Relative names are such as father, son; ruler, subject; 
like; equal, unlike; unequal, longer, shorter, cause, effect. 
Their characteristic property is, that they are always given m 
pairs. Every relative name which is predicated of an object, 
supposes another object (or objects), of which we may predicate 
either that same name or another relative name which is said 
to be the correlative of the former. Thus, when we call any 
person a son, we suppose other persons who must be called 
parents. When we call any event a cause, we suppose another 
event which is an effect. When we say of any distance that 
it is longer, we suppose another distance which is shorter. 



NAMES. 


45 


When we say of any object that it is like, we mean that it is 
like some other object, which is also said to be like the first. 
In this last case both objects receive the same name , the rela¬ 
tive term is its own correlative. 

It is evident that these words, when concrete, are, like 
other concrete general names, connotative; they denote a sub¬ 
ject, and connote an attnbute, and each of them has or might 
have a corresponding abstract name, to denote the attnbute 
connoted by the concrete. Thus the concrete like has its 
abstract likeness , the concretes, father and son, have, or might 
have, the abstracts, paternity, and filiety, or sonship. The 
concrete name connotes an attnbute, and the abstract name 
which answeis to it denotes that attribute. But of what 
nature is the attribute ? Wherein consists the peculiarity in 
the connotation of a relative name ? 

The attribute signified by a relative name, say some, is a 
relation, and this they give, if not as a sufficient explanation, 
at least as the only one attainable. If they are asked, What 
then is a relation ? they do not profess to be able to tell. It 
is generally regarded as something peculiarly recondite and 
mysterious. I cannot, however, perceive in what respect it is 
more so than any other attribute, indeed, it appears to me to 
be so m a somewhat less degree. I conceive, rather, that it is 
by examining into the signification of relative names, or, m 
other words, into the nature of the attribute which they con¬ 
note, that a clear insight may best be obtained into the nature 
of all attributes: of all that is meant by an attribute. 

It is obvious, m fact, that if we take any two correlative 
names, father and son for instance, though the objects de¬ 
noted by the names are different, they both, m a certain sense, 
connote the same thing. They cannot, indeed, be said to 
connote the same attribute: to be a father, is not the same 
thing as to be a son. But when we call one man a father, 
another a son, what we mean to affirm is a set of facts, 
■which are exactly the same m both cases. To predicate of A 
that he is the father of B, and of B that he is the son of A, 
is to assert one and the same fact m different words. The 
two propositions are exactly equivalent: neither of them 



46 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


asserts more or asserts lets than the other The paternity of 
A and the fihety of B aie not two facts, but two modes of 
expressing the same fact That fact, when analysed, consists 
of a seiies of physical events or phenomena, m which both A 
and B aie parties concerned, and tom which they both denve 
names. What those names really connote, is this senes of 
events that is the meaning, and the whole meaning, which 
either of them is intended to convey The senes of events may 
be said to constitute the relation, the schoolmen called it the 
foundation of the ielation, fundamentum relatioms. 

In this manner any fact, or senes of facts, m which two 
different objects are implicated, and which is therefore pre¬ 
dicable of both of them, may be either eonsideied as consti¬ 
tuting an attribute of the one, or an attribute of the other. 
According as we consider it m the foimei, or m the latter 
aspect, it is connoted by the one or the other of the two cor¬ 
relative names Father connotes the fact, regarded as consti¬ 
tuting an attnbute of A. son connotes the same fact, as con¬ 
stituting an attnbute of B It may evidently be legarded 
with equal propnety m either light And all that appeals 
necessary to account for the existence of relative names, is, 
that whenevei there is a fact m which two individuals are con¬ 
cerned, an attribute grounded on that fact may be ascribed to 
either of these individuals 

A name, therefore, is said to be relative, when, over and 
above the object which it denotes, it implies m its signification 
the existence of another object, also deriving a denomination 
from the same fact which is the ground of the first name. Or 
(to express the same meaning m other words) a name is rela¬ 
tive, when, being the name of one thing, its signification 
cannot be explained but by mentioning another Or we mav 
state it thus—when the name cannot be employed m discourse 
so as to have a meaning, unless the name of some other thing 
than what it is itself the name of, be either expressed or under¬ 
stood. These definitions aie all, at bottom, equivalent, being 
modes of variously expressing this one distinctive circum¬ 
stance—that every other attribute of an object might, without 
any contiadiction, be conceived still to exist if no object be- 



NAMES. 


4 ? 


sides that one had ever existed ,* hut those of its attributes 
-which are expressed by relative names, would on that supposi¬ 
tion be swept away. 

§ 8 Names have been further distinguished into univocal 
and aqun ocal . these, howevei, are not two kinds of names, 
hut two diffeient modes of employing names. A name is 
univocal, or applied umvocally, with respect to all things of 
which it can be predicated m the same sense: it is equivocal, 
or applied equivocally, as respects those things of which it is 
predicated m diffeient senses It is scarcely necessary to give 
instances of a fact so familial as the double meaning of a word 
In leality, as has been already observed, an equivocal or am¬ 
biguous word is not one name, but two names, accidentally 
coinciding in sound. File meaning a steel instrument, and 
file meaning a line of soldiers, have no more title to be con- 
sideied one word, because written alike, than grease and Greece 
have, because they are pronounced alike. They are one sound, 
appropriated to form two different words. 

An intermediate case is that of a name used analogically 
or metaphoncally, that is, a name which is piedicated of two 
things, not umvocally, or exactly m the same signification, 
but m significations somewhat similar, and which being de¬ 
rived one from the other, one of them may be considered the 
pnmary, and the other a secondary signification As when 
we speak of a brilliant light and a brilliant achievement The 
woid is not applied m the same sense to the light and to th'e 
achievement; but having been applied to the light m its 
original sense, that of brightness to the eye, it is transferred 
to the achievement m a derivative signification, supposed to 
be somewhat like the primitive one. Thewoid, however, is 


Oi rather, all objects except itself and the percipient mind, for, as we 
shall see hereafter, to ascribe any attribute to an object, necessarily implies a 
mind to perceive it 

The simple and clear explanation given m the text, of relation and lelative 
names, a subject so long the oppiobrmm of metaphysics, was given (as far as I 
know) for the first time, by Mr James Mill, m his Analysis of the Phenomena 
of the Human Mind. 



48 


names and propositions. 


just as properly two names instead of one, m this case, as in 
that of the most perfect ambiguity And one of the com¬ 
monest forms of fallacious reasoning arising fiom ambiguity, 
is that of arguing from a metaphorical expression as if it were 
literal; that is, as if a word, when applied metaphorically, 
were the same name as when taken m its ongmal sense. which 
will be seen more particularly m its place. 



CHAPTER III. 


OF THE THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES. 

§ 1 Looking back now to the commencement of onr 
mquny, let us attempt to measure how far it has advanced 
Logic, we found, is the Theory of Proof. But proof supposes 
something provable, which must be a Proposition 01 Assertion , 
since nothing but a Proposition can be an object of belief, or 
theiefore of proof A Proposition is, discouise which affirms 
or denies something of some other thing This is one step 
there must, it seems, be two things concerned m every act of 
belief But what are these Things ? They can be no other 
than those signified by the two names, which being joined 
together by a copula constitute the Proposition. If, therefore, 
we knew what all names signify, we should know everything 
which m the existing state of human knowledge, is capable eithei 
of being made a subject of affirmation or denial, or of being 
itself affirmed or denied of a subject. We have accordingly, 
m the preceding chapter, reviewed the various kinds of Names, 
m order to ascertain what is signified by each of them And 
we have now carried this survey far enough to be able to take 
an acpount of its results, and to exhibit an enumeration of 
all kinds of Things which are, capable of being made predi¬ 
cates, or of having anything predicated of them after which 
to determine the impoit of Predication, that is, of Proposi¬ 
tions, can be no arduous task 

The necessity of an enumeration of Existences, as the basis 
of Logic, did not escape the attention of the schoolmen, and 
of their master, Aristotle, the most comprehensive, if not also 
the most sagacious, of the ancient philosophers. The Cate¬ 
gories, or Predicaments—the former a .Greek word, the latter 
its liteial translation m the L&tin language—weie intended by 
him and his followeis as an enumeration of all things capable 
VOL. j. 4 



50 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS, 


of being named , an enumeration by the summa genera, % e. 
the most extensive classes into which things could be distn- 
buted; which, therefoie, were so many highest Piedicates, 
one 01 other of which was supposed capable of being affiimed 
with truth of every nameable thing whatsoever The follow¬ 
ing aie the classes into which, according to this school of 
philosophy. Things in general might he reduced — 


Qvffia, 
Hocrov, 
JIolov, 
XTpoc ti , 
TXoieiv, 
Hau^iv, 
II oi, 
Hors, 
KucrQcu , 
*E x uv t 


Substantia 

Quantitas 

Quahtas. 

Eelatio. 

Actio 

Passio 

Ubi. 

Qnando 

Situs 

Habitus 


The impelfections of this classification are too obvious to 
requne, and its merits are not sufficient to rewaid, a minute 
examination It is a mere catalogue of the distinctions rudely 
marked out by the language of familiar life, with little or no 
attempt to penetrate, by philosophic analysis, to the lationale 
even of those common distinctions Such an analysis, how- 
evei superficially conducted, would have shown the enumera¬ 
tion to be both redundant and defective. Some objects are 
omitted, and others repeated several times under diffei ent 
heads It is like a division of animals into men, quadrupeds, 
horses, asses, and ponies. That, for instance, could not be a 
very comprehensive view of the nature of Eelation which could 
exdude action, passivity, and local situation from that cate¬ 
gory. The same observation applies to the categories Quando 
(or position m time), and Ubi (or position m space), while 
the distinction between the latter and Situs is merely verbal 
The incongruity of erecting into a summum genus the class 
which forms the tenth category is manifest. On the other 
hand, the enumeration takes no notice of anything besides 
substances and attributes. In what category are we to place 
sensations, or any other feelings and states of mind, as hope, 
joy, fear, sound, smell, taste, pain, pleasure , thought, judg- 



THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES 


51 


merit, conception, and the like ? Probably all these would 
have been placed by the Aristotelian school m the categories 
of actio and passio , and the relation of such of them as are 
active, to their objects, and of such of them as are passive, to 
their causes, would rightly be so placed, but the things 
themselves, the feelings or states of mind, wrongly. Feelings, 
or states of consciousness, aie assuredly to be counted among 
realities, but they cannot be reckoned either among substances 
or attributes. 

§ 2 Before recommencing, under better auspices, the 
attempt made with such imperfect success by the great founder 
of the science of logic, we must take notice of an unfortunate 
ambiguity in all the concrete names which correspond to the 
most general of all abstract terms, the word Existence When 
we have occasion for a name which shall be capable of denoting 
whatever exists, as contradistinguished from non-entity or 
Nothing, there is hardly a word applicable to the purpose 
which is not also, and even more familiarly, taken m a sense 
in which it denotes only substances But substances are not 
all that exists, attributes, if such things are to be spoken of, 
must be said to exist, feelings certainly exist Yet when we 
speak of an object, or of a thing , we are almost always sup¬ 
posed to mean a substance There seems a kind of contra¬ 
diction m using such an expiession as that one thing is merely 
an attribute of another thing And the announcement of a 
Classification of Things would, I believe, prepare most readers 
for an enumeration like those in natural history, beginning 
with the great divisions of animal, vegetable, and mineral, 
and subdividing them into classes and oiders If, rejecting 
the word Thing, we endeavour to find another of a more 
general import, or at least more exclusively confined to that 
general import, a word denoting all that exists, and connoting 
only simple existence; no word might be presumed fitter for 
such a purpose than being * originally the present participle 
of a verb which m one of its meanings is exactly equivalent to 
the verb exists, and therefore suitable, even by its grammatical 
formation, to be the concrete of the abstract existence. But this 

4—2 



52 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


word, strange as the fact may appear, is still more completely 
spoiled for the purpose which it seemed expressly made for, 
than the word Thing. Being is, by custom, exactly synony¬ 
mous with substance, except that it is free fiom a slight tamt 
of a second ambiguity, being applied impartially to matter 
and to mind, while substance, though originally and m strict¬ 
ness applicable to both, is apt to suggest m preference the idea 
of matter Attubutes aie never called Beings, nor are feel¬ 
ings. A Being is that which excites feelings, and which pos¬ 
sesses attributes. The soul is called a Being, God and angels 
are called Beings, but if we weie to say, extension, colour, 
wisdom, virtue, are beings, we should perhaps be suspected of 
thinking with some of the ancients, that the cardinal virtues 
are animals, or, at the least, of holding with the Platonic 
school the doctime of self-existent Ideas, or with the fol¬ 
lowers of Epicmus that of Sensible Forms, which detach 
themselves m every direction iiom bodies, and by coming m 
contact with our organs, cause our perceptions. We should 
be supposed, m short, to believe that Attributes are Substances 
In consequence of this perversion of the woid Being, phi¬ 
losophers looking about for something to supply its place, laid 
their hands upon the word Entity, a piece of baibarous Latin, 
invented by the schoolmen to be used as an abstract name, m 
which class its grammatical form would seem to place it, but 
being seized by logicians m distress to stop a leak m their 
teimmology, it has ever since been used as a concrete name. 
The kindred word essence , born at the same time and of the 
same parents, scarcely underwent a more complete transforma¬ 
tion wlieD, from being the abstract of the verb to be, it came 
to denote something sufficiently concrete to be enclosed m a 
glass bottle. The word Entity, since it settled down into a 
concrete name, has retained its universality of signification 
somewhat less impaired than any of the names befoie men¬ 
tioned. Yet the same gradual decay to which, after a certain 
age, all the language of psychology seems liable, has been at 
work even here If you call vntue an entity, you are indeed 
somewhat less strongly suspected of believing it to be a sub¬ 
stance than if you called it a being; but you are by no means 



THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES. 


53 


free from the suspicion Every word which was originally in¬ 
tended to connote mere existence, seems, after a long time, to 
enlarge its connotation to separate existence, or existence freed 
from the condition of belonging to a substance, which con¬ 
dition being precisely what constitutes an attribute, attributes 
are giadually shut out, and along with them feelings, which 
m ninety-nme cases out of a hundied have no other name than 
that of the attribute which is grounded on them. Strange 
that when the greatest embarrassment felt by all who have 
any considerable number of thoughts to express, is to find a 
sufficient variety of precise words fitted to express them, there 
should be no practice to which even scientific thinkers are 
more addicted than that of taking valuable words to express 
ideas which are sufficiently expressed by other words already 
appropriated to them 

When it is impossible to obtain good tools, the next best 
thing is to understand thoroughly the defects of those we have. 

I have therefore warned the reader of the ambiguity of the 
names which, for want of better, I am necessitated to employ. 
It must now be the writers endeavour so to employ them 
as m no case to leave the meaning doubtful or obscure. No 
one of the above terms being altogether unambiguous, I 
shall not confine myself to any one, but shall employ on each 
occasion the word which seems least likely m the particular 
case to lead to misunderstanding, nor do I pretend to use 
either these or any other words with a rigorous adherence to 
one single sense. To do so would often leave us without a 
word to express what is signified by a known word m some 
one or other of its senses * unless authors had an unlimited 
licence to coin new words, together with (what it would 
be more difficult to assume) unlimited power of making 
readers understand them. Nor would it be wise m a writer, ' 
on a subject involving so much of abstraction, to deny himself 
the advantage derived from even an improper use of a term, 
when, by means of it, some familiar association is called lip 
which brings the meaning home to the mind, as it were by a 
flash. 

The difficulty both to the writer and reader, of the attempt 



54 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


■which must he made to use vague words so as to convey a pie- 
oise meaning; is not wholly a matter of regret. It is not un¬ 
fitting that logical treatises should afford an example of that, 
to facilitate which is among the most impoitant uses of logic. 
Philosophical language will for a long time, and popular lan¬ 
guage still longer, retain so much of vagueness and ambiguity, 
that logic would be of little value if it did not, among its 
other advantages, exercise the understanding m doing its work 
neatly and correctly with these imperfect tools 

After this preamble it is time to proceed to our enumera¬ 
tion. We shall commence with Feelings, the simplest class 
of nameable things, the term Feeling being of course under¬ 
stood m its most enlarged sense. 


I. Feelings, or States oe Consciousness 

§ 3 A Feeling and a State of Consciousness are, m the 
language of philosophy, equivalent expressions everything is 
a feeling of which the mmd is conscious, everything which it 
feels, or, m other words, which forms a part of its own sentient 
existence. In popular language Feeling is not always synony¬ 
mous with State of Consciousness, being often taken more 
peculiarly for those states which are conceived as belonging to 
the sensitive, or to the emotional, phasis of our nature, and 
sometimes, with a still narrower restriction, to the emotional 
alone, as distinguished from what are conceived as belonging 
to the percipient or to the intellectual phasis. But this is an 
admitted departure from correctness of language ; just as, by a 
popular perversion the exact converse of this, the word Mind is 
withdrawn from its rightful generality of signification, and 
restricted to the intellect. The still greater perversion by 
which Feeling is sometimes confined not only to bodily sensa¬ 
tions, but to the sensations of a single sense, that of touch, 
needs not be more particularly adverted to. 

Feeling, m the proper sense of the term, is a genus, of 
which Sensation, Emotion, and Thought, are subordinate 
species. Under the word Thought is here to be included what- 



THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES. 


55 


ever we are internally conscious of when we aie said to think, 
from the consciousness we have when we think of a red colour 
without having it before our eyes, to the most recondite 
thoughts of a philosopher or poet Be it remembered, how¬ 
ever, that by a thought is to be understood what passes m the 
mind itself, and not any object external to the mind, which the 
person is commonly said to be thinking of He may be think- 
mo- of the sun, or of God, but the sun and God are not 
thoughts , his mental image, however, of the sun, and his idea 
of God, aie thoughts, states of his mind, not of the objects 
themselves, and so also is his belief of the existence of the sun, 
or of God , or his disbelief, if the case be so Even imaginary 
objects (which are said to exist only m our ideas) are to be 
distinguished from oui ideas of them I may think of a 
hobgoblin, as I may think of the loaf which was eaten yester¬ 
day, or of the flower which will bloom to-morrow. But the 
hobgoblin which never existed is not the same thing with my 
idea of a hobgoblin, any more than the loaf which once existed 
is the same thing with my idea of a loaf, or the flower which 
does not yet exist, but which will exist, is the same with my 
idea of a flower They are all, not thoughts, but objects of 
thought, though at the present time all the objects are alike 
non-existent. 

In like manner, a Sensation is to be carefully distinguished 
from the object which causes the sensation , our sensation of 
white from a white object, nor is it less to be distinguished 
from the attribute whiteness, which we ascribe to the obj ect m 
consequence of its exciting the sensation. Unfortunately foi 
clearness and due discrimination m considering these subjects, 
our sensations seldom receive separate names. We have a name 
for the objects which produce m us a certain sensation: the 
woid white. We have a name for the quality m those objects, 
to which we ascribe the sensation : the name whiteness. * But 
when we speak of the sensation itself (as we have not occasion 
to do this often except m our scientific speculations), language, 
which adapts itself for the most part only to the common uses 
of life, has provided us with no single-worded or immediate 
designation, we must employ a circumlocution, and say, The 



56 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


sensation of white, or The sensation of whiteness , we must 
denominate the sensation either from the object, or from the 
attribute, by which it is excited. Yet the sensation, though it 
never does, might very well be conceived to exist, without any¬ 
thin g^wb ate vei to excite it We can conceive it as ansing 
spontaneously in the mind. But if it so aiose, we should have 
no name to- denote it which would not be a misnomer In the 
case of our sensations of hearing we are better provided, we 
have the word Sound, and a whole vocabulary of words to denote 
the various kinds of sounds. For as we are often conscious of 
these sensations m the absence of any peiceptible object, we can 
more easily conceive having them m the absence of any object 
whatever. We need only shut our eyes and listen to music, 
to have a conception of an universe with nothing in it except 
sounds, and ourselves hearing them and what is easily con¬ 
ceived sepai ately, easily obtains a separate name. But m general 
oui names of sensations denote indiscriminately the sensation 
and the attribute. Thus, colour stands for the sensations of 
white, led, &c., but also for the quality m the coloured object 
We talk of the colours of things as among their properties 

§ 4 . In the case of sensations, another distinction has also 
to be kept m view, which is often confounded, and never with¬ 
out mischievous consequences. This is, the distinction between 
the sensation itself, and the state of the bodily organs which 
precedes the sensation, and which constitutes the physical 
agency by which it is produced. One of the sources of con¬ 
fusion on this subject is the division commonly made of feelings 
into Bodily and Mental Philosophically speaking, there is no 
foundation at all for this distinction : even sensations are states 
of the sentient mind, not states of the body, as distinguished 
from it What I am conscious of when I see the colour blue, 
is a feeling of blue colour, which is one thing; the picture on 
my retina, or the phenomenon of hitherto mysterious nature 
which takes place m my optic nerve or in my brain, is another 
thing, of which I am not at all conscious, and which scientific 
investigation alone could have apprised me of. These are 
states of my body, but the sensation of blue, which is the con- 



THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES. 


57 


sequence of these states of body, is not a state of body. that 
which perceives and is conscious is called Mmd When sen¬ 
sations are called bodily feelings, it is only as being the class 
of feehngs which are immediately occasioned by bodily states; 
whereas the other kinds of feelings, thoughts, for instance, or 
emotions, aie immediately excited not by anything acting upon 
the bodily organs, but by sensations, or by previous thoughts. 
This, however, is a distinction not m our feelings, hut m the 
agency which produces our feelings all of them when actually 
produced are states of mmd. 

Besides the affection of our bodily organs from without, 
and the sensation thereby produced m our minds, many wiiters 
admit a third link m the chain of phenomena, which they call 
a Perception, and which consists m the recognition of an ex¬ 
ternal object as the exciting cause of the sensation This per¬ 
ception, they say, is an act of the mmd, proceeding fiom its 
own spontaneous activity, while m a sensation the mmd is 
passive, being merely acted upon by the outward object. And 
according to some metaphysicians, it is by an act of the mmd, 
similar to perception, except m not being preceded by any sen¬ 
sation, that the existence of God, the soul, and other hyper¬ 
physical objects is recognised. 

These acts of what is termed perception, whatever be the 
conclusion ultimately come to respecting their nature, must, I 
conceive, take their place among the varieties of feelings or 
states of mmd. In so classing them, I have not the smallest 
intention of declaring or insinuating any theory as to the law 
of mmd in which these mental processes may be supposed to 
originate, or the conditions under which they may be legiti¬ 
mate or the reverse Par less do I mean (as Dr. Whewell 
seems to suppose must be meant in an analogous case**) to in¬ 
dicate that as they are “merely states of mmd/' it is super¬ 
fluous to inquire into their distinguishing peculiarities. I 
abstain from the inquiry as irrelevant to the science of logic. 
In these so-called perceptions, or direct recognitions by the 
mmd, of objects, whether physical or spiritual, which are ex- 


Philosopky of the Tnduchve Sciences, Vol 1. p. 40 . 



58 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


ternal to itself, I can see only cases of belief, but of belief 
•which claims to be intuitive, or independent of external evi¬ 
dence. When a stone lies before me, I am conscious of ceitam 
sensations which I leceive from it, but if I say that these sen¬ 
sations come to me from an external object which I perceive, 
the meaning of these words is, that receiving the sensations, I 
intuitively believe that an external cause of those sensations 
exists. The laws of intuitive belief, and the conditions under 
which it is legitimate, aie a subject which, as we have already 
so often lemaiLed, belongs not to logic, but to the science of 
the ultimate laws of the human mind. 

To the same legion of speculation belongs all that can be 
said respecting the distinction which the German metaphy¬ 
sicians and their French and English followers so elaboi ately 
diaw between the acts of the mind and its merely passive 
states; between what it receives from, and what it gives to, 
the crude materials of its experience. I am aware that with 
reference to the view which those wiiters take of the pumaiy 
elements of thought and knowledge, this distinction is funda¬ 
mental. But for the present purpose, which is to examine, 
not the original groundwork of our knowledge, hut how we 
come by that portion of it which is not original, the difference 
between active and passive states of mind is of secondary im¬ 
portance. For us, they all aie states of mind, they all aie 
feelings, by which, let it be said once more, I mean to imply 
nothing of passivity, but simply that they are psychological 
facts, facts which take place m the mmd, and are to he care¬ 
fully distinguished from the external or physical facts with 
which they may he connected either as effects or as causes 

§ 5 . Among active states of mmd, there is, however, one 
species which merits particular attention, because it foims a 
puncipal part of the connotation of some impoitant classes of 
names. I mean volitions, or acts of the will When we speak 
of sentient beings by relative names, a large portion of the 
connotation of the name usually consists of the actions of those 
beings, actions past, present, and possible or probable future 
Take, for instance, the words Sovereign and Subject What 



THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES. 


59 


meaning do these words convey, but that of innumeiable 
actions, done or to be done by the sovereign and the subjects, 
to or m regard to one another reciprocally ? So with the 
words physician and patient, leader and follower, tutor and 
pupil. In many cases the words also connote actions which 
would be done under certain contingencies by persons other 
than those denoted as the words mortgagor and mortgagee, 
obligor and obligee, and many other words expressive of legal 
relation, which connote what a court of justice would do to 
enforce the legal obligation if not fulfilled. There are also 
words which connote actions previously done by persons other 
than those denoted either by the name itself or by its correla¬ 
tive, as the word brother From these instances, it maybe 
seen how large a portion of the connotation of names consists 
of actions. Now what is an action ? Not one thing, but a 
series of two things * the state of mind called a volition, fol¬ 
lowed by an effect. The volition or intention to produce the 
effect, is one thing, the effect produced m consequence of the 
intention, is another thing, the two together constitute the 
action. I form the purpose of instantly moving my arm, that 
is a state of my mind my arm (not being tied or paralytic) 
moves m obedience to my purpose, that is a physical fact, 
consequent on a state of mind. The intention, followed by the 
fact, 01 (if we prefer the expression) the fact when preceded 
and caused by the intention, is called the action of moving 
my arm 

§ 6 Of the first leading division of nameable things, viz 
Feelings or States of Consciousness, we began by recognising 
three sub-divisions, Sensations, Thoughts, and Emotions 
The first two of these we have illustrated at considerable 
length, the third, Emotions, not being perplexed by similar 
ambiguities, does not lequire similar exemplification. And, 
finally, we have found it necessary to add to these three a 
fourth species, commonly known by the name Volitions. 
Without seeking to prejudge the metaphysical question 
whether any mental state or phenomenon can be found which 
is not included in one or other of these four species, it appears 



60 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


to me that the amount of illustration bestowed upon these may, 
so far as we are concerned, suffice for the whole genus. We 
shall, therefore, proceed to the two remaining classes of name- 
able things, all things which are external to the mind being 
considered as belonging either to the class of Substances or to 
that of Attributes. 


II. Substances. 

Logicians have endeavoured to define Substance and Attri¬ 
bute , but their definitions are not so much attempts to draw 
a distinction between the things themselves, as instructions 
what difference it is customary to make in the grammatical 
structure of the sentence, according as we are speaking of sub¬ 
stances or of attributes. Such definitions are rather lessons of 
English, or of Greek, Latin, or German, than of mental phi¬ 
losophy. An attribute, say the school logicians, must be the 
attribute of something, colour, for example, must be the colour 
of something, goodness must be the goodness of something * 
and if this something should cease to exist, or should cease to 
be connected with the attribute, the existence of the attribute 
would be at an end A substance, on the contrary, is self- 
existent , in speaking about it, we need not put of after its 
name A stone is not the stone of anything, the moon is not 
the moon of anything, but simply the moon. Unless, indeed, 
the name which we choose to give to the substance be a re¬ 
lative name , if so, it must be followed either by of or by some 
other particle, implying, as that preposition does, a reference 
to something else , but then the other characteristic peculiarity 
of an attribute would fail; the something might be destroyed, 
and the substance might still subsist. Thus, a father must be 
the father of something, and so far resembles an attribute, m 
being referred to something besides himself if there were no 
child, there would be no father: but this, when we look into 
the matter, only means that we should not call him father. 
The man called father might still exist though there were no 
child, as he existed before there was a child: and there would 
be no contradiction m supposing him to exist, though the 



THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES. 


61 


whole universe except himself were destroyed But destroy 
all white substances, and where would be the attribute white¬ 
ness ? Whiteness, without any white thing, is a contradiction 
m terms. 

This is the nearest approach to a solution of the difficulty, 
that will be found m the common treatises on logic. It will 
scarcely be thought to be a satisfactory one If an attribute 
is distinguished from a substance by being the attribute of 
something, it seems highly necessary to understand what is 
meant by of, a particle which needs explanation too much 
itself, to be placed m front of the explanation of anything 
else And as for the self-existence of substance, it is very 
tiue that a substance may be conceived to exist without any 
other substance, but so also may an attribute without any 
other attribute * and We can no more imagine a substance 
without attributes than we can imagine attubutes without a 
substance 

Metaphysicians, however, have probed the question deeper, 
and given an account of Substance considerably more satis¬ 
factory than this. Substances are usually distinguished as 
Bodies or Minds Of each of these, philosophers have at 
length provided us with a definition which seems unexcep¬ 
tionable. 


§ 7. A Body, according to the received doctrine of 
modem metaphysicians, may be defined, the external cause to 
which we ascribe oui sensations. When I see and touch a 
piece of gold, I am conscious of a sensation of yellow colour, 
and sensations of hardness and weight; and by varying the 
mode of handling, I may add to these sensations many others 
completely distinct from them. The sensations are all of 
which I am directly conscious, but I consider them as pro¬ 
duced by something not only existing independently of my 
will, but external to my bodily organs and to my mind. This 
external something I call a body. 

It may be asked, how come we to ascube our sensations to 
any external cause ? And is there sufficient ground for so 
ascribing them ? It is known, that there are metaphysicians 



62 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


who have raised a controversy on the point, maintaining that 
we are not warranted in lefeinng our sensations to a cause 
such as we undeistand by the word Body, or to any external 
cause whatevei Though we have no concern here with this 
controversy, nor with the metaphysical niceties on which it 
turns, one of the best ways of showing what is meant by Sub¬ 
stance is, to consider what position it is necessary to take up, 
m order to maintain its existence against opponents 

It is certain, then, that a part of our notion of a body 
consists of the notion of a number of sensations of out own, or 
of other sentient beings, habitually occurung simultaneously. 
My conception of the table at which I am writing is com¬ 
pounded of its visible form and size, which are complex sensa¬ 
tions of sight, its tangible form and size, which are complex 
sensations of our oigans of touch and of our muscles, its 
weight, which is also a sensation of touch and of the muscles ; 
its colour, which is a sensation of sight, its haidness, which is 
a sensation of the muscles, its composition, which is another 
word for all the vaneties of sensation which we receive under 
various circumstances from the wood of which it is made, and 
so forth. All or most of these various sensations frequently 
are, and, as we learn by experience, always might be, expe¬ 
rienced simultaneously, or m many different orders of succes¬ 
sion, at our own choice and hence the thought of any one of 
them makes us think of the others, and the whole becomes 
mentally amalgamated into one mixed state of consciousness, 
which, in the language of the school of Locke and Hartley, is 
termed a Complex Idea. 

Now, there aie philosophers who have argued as follows. 
If we conceive an orange to be divested of its natural colour 
without acquiring any new one; to lose its softness without 
becoming hard, its roundness without becoming square or 
pentagonal, or of any other regular or irregular figure what¬ 
ever , to be deprived of size, of weight, of taste, of smell, to 
lose all its mechanical and all its chemical properties, and 
acquire no new ones, to become, m short, invisible, intangible, 
imperceptible not only by all our senses, but by the senses of 
all other sentient beings, real or possible, nothing, say these 



THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES. 


63 


thinkers, -would remain For of what nature, they ask, could 
he the residuum ? and by what token could it manifest its pre¬ 
sence ? To the unreflecting its existence seems to rest on the 
evidence of the senses. But to the senses nothing is appaient 
except the sensations We know, indeed, that these sensations 
aie bound together by some law, they do not come together 
at random, but according to a systematic order, which is part 
of the order established m the universe. When we experience 
one of these sensations, we usually expenence the otheis also, 
or know that we have it m our power to experience them 
But a fixed law of connexion, making the sensations occur 
together, does not, say these philosophers, necessarily require 
what is called a substratum to support them. The conception 
of a substratum is but one of many possible forms m which 
that connexion presents itself to our imagination , a mode of, 
as it were, realizing the idea. If there be such a substratum, 
suppose it this instant miraculously annihilated, and let the 
sensations continue to occur m the same order, and how would 
the substratum be missed ? By what signs should we be able 
to discover that its existence had terminated ? Should we not 
have as much reason to believe that it still existed as we now 
have ? And if we should not then be warranted m believing it, 
how can we be so now ? A body, therefore, according to these 
metaph} sicians, is not anything intrinsically different from 
the sensations which the body is said to produce m us , it is, 
m short, a set of sensations, or rather, of possibilities of sen¬ 
sation, joined together according to a fixed law 

The controversies to which these speculations have given 
rise, and the doctrines which have been developed m the 
attempt to find a conclusive answer to them, have been fruitful 
of important consequences to the Science of Mmd The sensa¬ 
tions (it was answered) which we are conscious of, and which 
we receive, not at random, but joined together m a certain 
uniform manner, imply not only a law or laws of connexion, 
but a cause external to our mind, which cause, by its own 
laws, determines the laws according to which the sensations 
are connected and experienced. The schoolmen used to call 
this external cause by the name we have already employed, a 



NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


substratum; and its attributes (as they expressed themselves) 
inhered , literally stuck, in it. To this substratum the name 
Matter is usually given m philosophical discussions. It was 
soon, however, acknowledged by all who reflected on the sub¬ 
ject, that the existence of matter cannot be proved by extrinsic 
evidence. The answer, therefore, now usually made to Berkeley 
and his followers, is, that the belief is intuitive , that mankind, 
m all ages, have felt themselves compelled, by a necessity of 
their nature, to refer their sensations to an external cause, 
that even those who deny it in theory, yield to the necessity m 
practice, and both m speech, thought, and feeling, do, equally 
with the vulgar, acknowledge their sensations to he the effects 
of something external to them: this knowledge, theiefoie, it 
is affirmed, is as evidently intuitive as our knowledge of our 
sensations themselves is intuitive And heie the question 
meiges m the fundamental pioblem of metaphysics properly 
so called, to which science we leave it. 

But although the extreme doctrine of the Idealist meta¬ 
physicians, that objects aie nothing but our sensations and 
the laws which connect them, has not been generally adopted 
by subsequent thmkeis, the point of most real impoitance is 
one on which those metaphysicians are now veiy generally 
considered to have made out their case viz, that all we know 
of objects is the sensations which they give us, and the order 
of the occurrence of those sensations Kant himself, on this 
point, is as explicit as Berkeley or Locke. However firmly 
convinced that there exists an universe of “ Things m them¬ 
selves,” totally distinct from the universe of phenomena, or of 
things as they appear to our senses, and even when bringing 
into use a technical expression {Noumenon) to denote what 
the thing is m itself, as contrasted with the representation of 
it in our minds, he allows that this representation (the matter 
of which, he says, consists of our sensations, though the form 
is given by the laws of the mind itself) is all we know of the 
object * and that the real nature of the Thing is, and by the 
constitution of our faculties ever must remain, at least in the 
present state of existence, an impenetrable mystery to us. 
“ Of things absolutely or in themselves/’ says Sir William 



THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES. 


65 


Hamilton,* “be they external, be they internal, we know 
nothing, or know them only as mcognisable , and become 
aware of their incomprehensible existence, only as this is in¬ 
directly and accidentally revealed to us, through ceitam quali¬ 
ties ielated to our faculties of knowledge, and which qualities, 
again, we cannot think as unconditioned, irrelative, existent 
m and of themselves All that we know is therefoie pheno¬ 
menal,—phenomenal of the unknown The same doctrine 
is laid down m the clearest and strongest terms by M Cousin, 
whose observations on the subject are the more worthy of 
attention, as, m consequence of the ultra-German and ontolo¬ 
gical character of his philosophy m other respects, they may 
be regaided as the admissions of an opponent J 

There is not the slightest reason for believing that what 
we call the sensible qualities of the object are a type of any- 


* Discussions on Philosophy , &c Appendix I pp 643-4 
f It is to be regretted that Sn William Hamilton, though he often strenu¬ 
ously insists on this doctrine, and though, m the passage quoted, he states it 
with a comprehensiveness and force which leave nothing to be desited, did not 
consistently adhere to his own doctrine, but maintained along with it opinions 
with which it is utterly irreconcileable See the third and other chapters of 
An Examination of Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy . 

t “ Nous savons qu’il existe quelque chose hors de nous, parceque nous ne 
pouvons expliquer nos perceptions sans les lattacher h des causes distmctes de 
nous-mem.es , nous savons de plus que ces causes, dont nous ne connaissons pas 
d’ailleurs l’essenee, produisent les effets les plus variables, les plus divers, et 
meme les plus contiaires, selon qu’elles rencontrent telle nature ou telle dis¬ 
position du sujet Mats savons-nous quelque chose de plus? et meme, vu le 
caracthre mddtermind des causes que nous concevons dans les corps, y a t-il 
quelque chose de plus h savoir * Y a-t-il heu de nous enqudnr si nous per- 
cevons les choses telles qu’elles sonb ? Non dvidemment . . Je ne dis 

pas que le pioblhme est insoluble, je di3 qu'il est absurde et enfeime une conti a - 
diction Nous ne savons pas ce que ces causes soni en elles-mimes, et la laison 
nous defend de chercher h le connaitre mais ll est bien Evident a prion, qu 'elles 
ne sont pas en elles-mimes ce qu'elles sont par rapport d nous , puisque la presence 
du sujet modihe ndcessanement leur action Supprimez tout sujet sentant, ll 
est certain que ces causes agiraient encore puisqu’elles contmueraient d’exister, 
mais elles agiraient autrement, elles seraient encore des qualit6s et des pro- 
pri^t^s, mais qui ne ressembleraient h rien de ce que nous connaissons Le feu 
ne manifesterait plus aucune des proprietes que nous lui connaissons que 
serait-il? (Test ce que nous ne saurons jamais C'est d'aillems peut-itre un 
probUme qui ne ripugne pas seulement & la nature de noti e esprit , mais & Vessence 
mime des choses Quand m§me en effet on suppnmerait par la pensde tous les 
VOL. I 5 



66 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


thing inherent m itself, or bear any affinity to its own nature. 
A cause does not, as suph, resemble its effects, an east wind 
is not like the feeling of cold, nor heat like the steam of boil¬ 
ing water. Why then should matter resemble our sensations ? 
Why should the inmost nature of fire or water resemble the 
impressions made by those objects upon oui senses Or on 
what principle are we authorized to deduce from the effects, 
anything concerning the cause, except that it is a cause ade¬ 
quate to produce those effects ? It may, theiefore, safe]y be 
laid down as a truth both obvious m itself, and admitted by 
all whom it is at present necessary to take into consideration, 
that, of the outward world, we know and can know absolutely 
nothing, except the sensations which we experience from it f 


sujets sentants, ll faudrait encore admettre qne nul corps ne manifesterait ses 
propndtds autiement qu’en relation avec un sujet quelconque, et dans ce cas 
ses piopnetts ne seuuent encore que relatives en soite qu’il me paralt fort 
raisonnable d admettie que les piopridt^s ddtermmdes des corps n’existent pas 
inddpendamroent d’un sujet quelconque, et que quand on demand© si les pro- 
prnStds de la naatihre sont telJes que nous les percevons, ll faudrait voir aupara- 
vant si elles sont en tant que deterrmndes, et dans quel sens ll est vrai de dire 
qu’elles sont”— Corns d' Mistoire de la Philosophic Mon ale au 18me siecle , 8 me 
le$on. 

* An attempt, indeed, has been made by Reid and others, to establish that 
although some of the properties we ascribe to objects exist only m our sensa¬ 
tions, others exist m the things themselves, being such as cannot possibly be 
copies of any impression upon the senses , and they ask, from what sensations 
our notions of extension and figure have been derived * The gauntlet thrown 
down by Reid was taken up by Biown, who, applying greater powers of ana¬ 
lysis than had previously been applied to the notions of extension and figure, 
pointed out that the sensations ftoni which those notions are denved, aie sen¬ 
sations of touch, combined with sensations of a class previously too little adverted 
to by metaphysicians, those which have their seat m our muscular fiame His 
analysis, which was adopted and followed up by James Mill, has been further 
and greatly impioved upon m Piofessor Bain’s profound work, The Senses and 
the Intellect , and in the chapters on “ Perception ” of a work of eminent ana¬ 
lytic powei, Mi Herbeit Spencer’s Principles of Psychology 

On this point M Cousin may again be cited in favour of the better doctrine. 
M Cousin recognises, m opposition to Reid, the essential subjectivity of our 
conceptions of what are called the primary qualities of matter, as extension, 
solidity, &c , equally with those of colour, heat, and the remainder of the so- 
called secondary qualities — Corns, ut supra, 9me le§on 

■f This doctrine, which is the most complete form of the philosophical theory 
known as the Relativity of Human Knowledge, has, since the lecent revival m 



THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES. 


67 


§ 8 Body having now been defined the external cause, 
and (according to the more reasonable opinion) the unknown 
external cause, to which we refer our sensations; it remains 
to frame a definition of Mind Noi, aftei the preceding ob¬ 
servations, will this be difficult For, as our conception of a 
body is that of an unknown exciting cause of sensations, so 
our conception of a mind is that of an unknown recipient, or 
percipient, of them, and not of them alone, but of all our 
other feelings As body is undei stood to be the mysterious 
something which excites the mind to feel, so mind is the 
mysterious something which feels and thinks. It is unnecessaiy 
to give m the case of mind, as we gave m the case of matter, 


this country of an active interest m metaphysical speculation, been the subject 
of a greatly increased amount of discussion and controveisy , and dissentients 
have manifested themselves m considerably greater number than I bad any 
knowledge of when the passage m the text was written The doctrine has been 
attacked from two sides Some thinkers, among whom are the late Professor 
Femer, mhis Institutes of Metaphysic , and Professor John G-rote m his Explo- 
ratio Philosophica , appear to deny altogether the reality of Noumena, or Things 
m themselves—of an unknowable substratum or support for the sensations 
which we experience, and which, according to the theory, constitute all our 
knowledge of an external world It seems to me, however, that m Professoi 
Grote’s case at least, the denial of Noumena is only apparent, and that he does 
not essentially differ fiom the other class of objectois, including Mr. Bailey m 
his valuable Letteis on the Philosophy of the Human Mind, and (m spire of 
the striking passage quoted m the text) also Sir William Hamilton, who con¬ 
tend for a direct knowledge by the human mind of more than the sensations— 
of certain attributes or pioperties as they exist not in us, but m the Things 
themselves 

With the first of these opinions, that which denies Noumena, I have, as a 
metaphysician, no quarrel, but, whether it be true or false, it is irrelevant to 
Logic. And since all the forms of language are m contradiction to it, nothing 
but confusion could result from its unnecessaiy introduction into a tieatise, 
every essential doctrine of which could stand equally well with the opposite and 
accredited opinion The othei and rival doctrine, that of a direct peiception or 
intuitive knowledge of the outward object as it is m itself, considered as distinct 
from the sensations we receive from it, is of far greater practical moment. But 
even this question, depending on the nature and laws of Intuitive Knowledge, is 
not within the province of Logic Por the grounds of my own opinion con¬ 
cerning it, I must content myself with referring to a woik already mentioned— 
An Examination of Sir William Hamilton’s Philosophy , several chapters of 
which are devoted to a full discussion of the questions and theories relating to 
the supposed direct perception of external objects. 

5—2 



68 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


a particular statement of the sceptical system by which its 
existence as a Thing m itself, distinct fiom the series of what 
are denominated its states, is called m question. But it is \ 
necessaiy to lemaik, that on the inmost nature (whatever be 
meant by inmost nature) of the thinking principle, as well as 
on the inmost nature of matter, we aie, and with our faculties 
must always lemam, entnely m the dark. All which we are 
aware of, even m our own minds, is (in the words of Mi James 
Mill) a certain “ thiead of consciousness a series of feelings, 
that is, of sensations, thoughts, emotions, and volitions, more 
or less numeious and complicated There is a something I call 
Myself, or, by another form of expression, my mind, which I 
consider as distinct fiom these sensations, thoughts, &c.; a 
something which I conceive to be not the thoughts, but the 
being that has the thoughts, and which I can conceive as 
existing for ever m a state of quiescence, without any thoughts 
at all. But what this being is, though it is myself, I have no 
knowledge, other than, the senes of its states of consciousness. 
As bodies manifest themselves to me only through the sensa¬ 
tions of which I regaid them as the causes, so the thinking 
punciple, or mind, m my own nature, makes itself known to 
me only by the feelings of which it is conscious I know 
nothing about myself, save my capacities of feeling or being 
conscious (including, of course, thinking and willing) . and 
were I to learn anything new concerning my own nature, I 
cannot with my present faculties conceive this new mfoimation 
to be anything else, than that I have some additional capa¬ 
cities, as yet unknown to me, of feeling, thinking, or willing 
Thus, then, as body is the unsentient cause to which we 
are naturally prompted to refer a ceitam portion of our feel¬ 
ings, so mind may be described as the sentient subject (in the 
scholastic sense of the term) of all feelings , that which has or 
feels them But of the nature of either body or mind, further 
than the feelings which the former excites, and which the 
latter experiences, we do not, according to the best existing 
doctrine, know anything, and if anything, logic has nothing 
to do with it, or with the manner m which the knowledge is 
acquired. With this result we may conclude this portion of 



THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES. 


69 


our subject, and pass to the third and only remaining class or 
division of Nameable Things. 


Ill Attributes . and, first, Qualities 

§ 9 Fiom what has -already been said of Substance, 
what is to he said of Attribute is easily deducible For if we 
know not, and cannot know, anything of bodies but the sensa¬ 
tions which they excite m us or m others, those sensations 
must he all that we can, at bottom, mean by their attubutes , 
and the distinction which we verbally make between the pro¬ 
perties of things and the sensations we receive fiom them, 
must ongmate m the convenience of discourse rather than m 
the nature of what is signified by the terms 

Attributes are usually distributed under the three heads of 
Quality, Quantity, and Relation We shall come to the two 
lattei presently: m the first place we shall confine ourselves 
to the former 

Let us take, then, as our example, one of what are termed 
the sensible qualities of objects, and let that example be white¬ 
ness When we ascribe whiteness to any substance, as, for 
instance, snow, when we say that snow has the quality white¬ 
ness, what do we really assert ? Simply, that when snow is 
present to our organs, we have a particular sensation, which 
we are accustomed to call the sensation of white. But how do 
I know that snow is present ? Obviously by the sensations 
which I derive from it, and not otherwise. I infer that the 
object is present, because it gives me <a certain assemblage or 
series of sensations. And when I ascribe to it the attnbute 
whiteness, my meaning is only, that, of the sensations com¬ 
posing this group or series, that which I call the sensation of 
white colour is one. 

This is one view which may be taken of the subject But 
there is also another and a different view. It may be said, that 
it is true we know nothing of sensible objects, except the sen¬ 
sations they excite m us, that the fact of our receiving from 
snow the particular sensation which is called a sensation of 



70 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


white, is the ground on which we ascube to that substance the 
quality whiteness, the sole pi oof of its possessing that quality. 
But because one thing may be the sole evidence of the exist¬ 
ence of anothei thing, it does not follow that the two are one 
and the same The- attribute whiteness (it may be said) is not 
the fact of receiving the sensation, but something m the 
object itself; a power inherent m it, somethin gimirtue of 
which the object pioduces the sensation. And when we affirm 
that snow possesses the attribute whiteness., we do not merely 
assert that the presence of snow produces m us that sensation, 
but that it does so thiough, and by reason of, that power or 
quality. 

For the purposes of logic it is not of matenal importance 
which of these opinions we adopt. The full discussion of the 
subject belongs to the other department of scientific inquiry, 
so often alluded to under the name of metaphysics, but it may 
be said here, that for the doctrine of the existence of a peculiar 
species of entities called qualities, I can see no foundation 
except m a tendency of the human mind which is the cause of 
many delusions I mean, the disposition, wherever we meet 
with two names which are not precisely synonymous, to sup¬ 
pose that they must be the names of two different things; 
whereas m reahty they may be names of the same thing viewed 
m two different lights, or under different suppositions as to 
surrounding circumstances. Because quality and sensation 
cannot be put indiscriminately one for the other, it is supposed 
that they cannot both signify the same thing, namely, the 
impression or feeling with which we are affected through our 
senses by the presence of an object, though there is at least 
no absurdity m supposing that this identical impression or 
feeling may be called a sensation when considered merely in 
itself, and a quality when looked at m relation to any one of 
the numerous objects, the presence of which to our organs 
excites in our minds that among various other sensations or 
feelings. And if this be admissible as a supposition, it rests 
with those who contend for an entity per se called a quality, 
to show that their opinion is preferable, or is anything in fact 
but a lingering remnant of the scholastic doctrine of occult 



THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES. 


71 


causes, the very absurdity which Moll ere so happily udiculed 
when he made one of his pedantic physicians account foi the 
fact that “ 1 opium endormit,” by the maxim “ pareequ’il a une 
vertu soporifique ” 

It is evident that when the physician stated that opium 
had “ une vertu soponfique/’ he did not account for, but merely 
asserted over again, the fact that it endormit In like manner, 
when we say that snow is white because it has the quality of 
whiteness, we are only re-asserting m more technical language 
the fact that it excites m us the sensation of white If it be 
said that the sensation must have some cause, I answer, its 
cause is the presence of the assemblage of phenomena which 
is termed the object. When we have asserted that as often as 
the object is present, and our organs m their normal state, the 
sensation takes place, we have stated all that we know about 
the matter. There is no need, after assigning a certain and 
intelligible cause, to suppose an occult cause besides, for the 
purpose of enabling the real cause to produce its effect. If I 
am asked, why does the presence of the object cause this sen¬ 
sation m me, I cannot tell. I can only say that such is my 
nature, and the nature of the object, that the fact forms a 
part of the constitution of things. And to this we must at last 
come, even after interpolating the imaginary entity ‘Whatever 
number of links the chain of causes and effects may consist of, 
how any one link produces the one which is next to it, remains 
equally inexplicable to us. It is as easy to comprehend that 
the object should produce the sensation directly and at once, 
as that it should produce the same sensation by the aid of 
something else called the power of producing it. 

But, as the difficulties which may be felt m adopting this 
view of the subject cannot be removed without discussions 
transcending the bounds of our science, I content myself with 
a passing indication, and shall, for the purposes of logic, adopt 
a language compatible with either view of the nature of quali¬ 
ties. I shall say,—what at least admits of no dispute,—that 
the quality of whiteness ascribed to the object snow, is grounded 
on its exciting m us the sensation of white; and adopting the 
language already used by the school logicians in the case of the 



72 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS* 


kind of attributes called Relations, I shall term the sensation 
of white the foundation of the quality whiteness For logical 
purposes the sensation is the only essential part of what is 
meant by the word, the only part which we ever can be con¬ 
cerned m proving. When that is proved, the quality is proved, 
if an object excites a sensation, it has, of oourse, the power of 
exciting it. 


IY. Relations. 

§ 10. The qualities of a body, we have said, are the 
attributes grounded on the sensations which the presence of 
that particular body to our organs excites m our minds But 
when we ascribe to any object the kind of attribute called a 
Relation, the foundation of the attribute must be something 
m which other objects aie concerned besides itself and the 
percipient. 

As there may with propriety be said to be a relation be¬ 
tween any two things to which two correlative names are or 
may be given, we may expect to discover what constitutes a 
ielation m general, if we enumerate the principal cases m which 
mankind have imposed correlative names, and observe what 
these cases have m common. 

What, then, is the character which is possessed m common 
by states of cn cum stances so heterogeneous and discordant as 
these . one thing like another; one thmg unlike another, one 
thing near another, one thing far from another , one thing 
before, after, along with another, one thing greater, equal, 
less, than another, one thing the cause of another, the effect 
of another; one person the master, servant, child, parent, 
debtor, creditor, sovereign, subject, attorney, client, of another, 
and so on? 

Omitting, for the present, the case of Resemblance, (a re¬ 
lation which requires to be considered separately,) there seems 
to be one thmg common to all these cases, and only one; that 
m each of them there exists or occurs, or has existed or 
occurred, or may be expected to exist or occur, some fact or 
phenomenon, into which the two things which are said to be 



THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES. 


73 


related to each othei, both enter as parties concerned. This 
fact, or phenomenon, is what the Anstotehan logicians called 
the fundamentum relatioms. Thus in the relation of greater 
and less between two magnitudes, the fundamentum relatioms 
is the fact that one of the two magnitudes could, under certain 
conditions, be included m, without entirely filling, the space 
occupied by the other magnitude. In the relation of master 
and servant, the fundamentum relatioms is the fact that the 
one has undertaken, or is compelled, to perform certain services 
for the benefit and at the bidding of the other. Examples 
might be indefinitely multiplied; but it is already obvious 
that whenever two things are said to be related, there is some 
fact, or senes of facts, into which they both enter, and that 
whenever any two things are involved m some one fact, or 
series of facts, we may ascribe to those two things a mutual 
relation grounded on the fact Even if they have nothing m 
common but what is common to all things, that they are 
tnembeis of the universe, we call that a relation, and deno¬ 
minate them fellow-creatures, fellow-beings, or fellow-denizens 
of the universe. But m proportion as the fact into which the 
two objects enter as parts is of a more special and peculiar, or 
of a more complicated nature, so also is the relation grounded 
upon it And there are as many conceivable relations as there 
are conceivable kinds of fact m which two things can be jointly 
concerned 

In the same manner, therefore, as a quality is an attribute 
grounded on the fact that a certain sensation or sensations are 
produced m us by the object, so an attribute grounded on some 
fact into which the object enters jointly with another object, 
is a relation between it and that other object. But the fact m 
the latter case consists of the very same kind of elements as 
the fact m the former; namely, states of consciousness. In 
the case, for example, of any legal relation, as debtor and 
creditor, principal and agent, guardian and ward, the funda¬ 
mentum relatioms consists entirely of thoughts, feelings, and 
volitions (actual or contingent), either of the persons them¬ 
selves or of other persons concerned m the same series of trans¬ 
actions , as, for instance, the intentions which would be formed 



74 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


by a judge, in case a complaint were made to bis tribunal of 
the infringement of any of the legal obligations imposed by 
the relation, and the acts which the judge would perform m 
consequence, acts being (as we have already seen) another 
word for intentions followed by an effect, and that effect being 
but another word for sensations, or some other feelings, occa¬ 
sioned either to the agent himself or to somebody else. There 
is no part of what the names expressive of the ielation imply, 
that is not resolvable into states of consciousness, outward 
objects being, no doubt, supposed throughout as the causes by 
which some of those states of consciousness are excited, and 
minds as the subjects by which all of them are experienced, 
but neither the external objects nor the minds making their 
existence known otherwise than by the states of consciousness. 

Cases of relation are not always so complicated as those to 
which we last alluded. The simplest of all cases of relation 
aie those expressed by the words antecedent and consequent, 
and by the word simultaneous. If we say, for instance, that 
dawn preceded sunrise, the fact m which the two things, dawn 
and sunrise, were jointly concerned, consisted only of the two 
things themselves; no third thing entered into the fact or 
phenomenon at all. Unless, indeed, we choose to call the suc¬ 
cession of the two objects a third thing, but their succession 
is not something added to the things themselves , it is some¬ 
thing involved m them Dawn and sunrise announce them* 
selves to our consciousness by two successive sensations Our 
consciousness of the succession of these sensations is not a third 
sensation or feeling added to them; we have not first the two 
feelings, and then a feeling of their succession. To have two 
feelings at all, implies having them either successively, or else 
simultaneously Sensations, or other feelings, being given, 
succession and simultaneousness aie the two conditions, to the 
alternative of which they are subj ected by the nature of our 
faculties, and no one has been able, or needs expect, to analyse 
the matter any farther. 

§ 11. In a somewhat similar position are two other sorts 
of relations, Likeness and Unlikeness. I have two sensations; 



THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES. 


75 


we will suppose them to he simple ones, two sensations of 
white, or one sensation of white and another of black. I call 
the first two sensations like; the last two unlike. What is 
the fact or phenomenon constituting the fundamentum of this 
relation ? The two sensations first, and then what we call a 
feeling of resemblance, or of want of resemblance. Let ns 
confine ourselves to the foimer case Resemblance is evidently 
a feeling, a state of the consciousness of the observer. Whether 
the feeling of the resemblance of the two colours be a third 
state of consciousness, which I have after having the two sen¬ 
sations of colour, or whether (like the feeling of their succes¬ 
sion) it is involved m the sensations themselves, may be a 
matter of discussion But m either case, these feelings of 
resemblance, and of its opposite dissimilarity, are parts of our 
nature, and parts so far fiom being capable of analysis, that 
they are pre-supposed m every attempt to analyse any of our 
other feelings Likeness and unlikeness, therefore, as well 
as antecedence, sequence, and simultaneousness, must stand 
apart among relations, as things sui generis. They are 
attributes grounded on facts, that is, on states of conscious¬ 
ness, but on states which are peculiar, unresolvable, and 
inexplicable. 

But, though likeness or unlikeness cannot be resolved into 
anything else, complex cases of likeness or unlikeness can be 
resolved into simpler ones. When we say of two things which 
consist of parts, that they are like one another, the likeness of 
the wholes does admit of analysis; it is compounded of like¬ 
nesses between the various parts respectively, and of likeness 
in their arrangement. Of how vast a variety of resemblances 
of parts must that resemblance be composed, which induces 
us to say that a portrait, or a landscape, is like its original. 
If one person mimics another with any success, of how many 
simple likenesses must the general or complex likeness be 
compounded: likeness m a succession of bodily postures; 
likeness in voice, or m the accents and intonations of the 
voice; likeness m the choice of words, and m the thoughts 
or sentiments expressed, whether by word, countenance, or 
gesture. 



76 


>3AMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


All likeness and imlikeness of which we have any cogni¬ 
zance, resolve themselves into likeness and unlikeness between 
states of our own, or some other, mind. When we say that 
one body is like another, (since we know nothing of bodies but 
the sensations which they excite,) we mean really that there is 
a resemblance between the sensations excited by the two bodies, 
or between some portions at least of those sensations. If we 
say that two attributes are like one another, (since we know 
nothing of attubutes except the sensations or states of feeling 
on which they are grounded,) we mean really that those 
sensations, or states of feeling, resemble each other. We may 
also say that two relations are alike The fact of xesemblance 
between relations is sometimes called analogy , forming one of 
the numerous meanings of that woid. The relation in which 
Priam stood to Hector, namely, that of father and son, resem¬ 
bles the relation in which Philip stood to Alexander, resembles 
it so closely that they aie called the same relation. The rela¬ 
tion m which Cromwell stood to England resembles the rela¬ 
tion in which Napoleon stood to France, though not so closely 
as to be called the same relation The meaning in both these 
instances must be, that a resemblance existed between the 
facts which constituted the fundamentum relatioms 

This resemblance may exist m all conceivable gradations, 
from perfect undistinguishableness to something extremely 
slight. When we say, that a thought suggested to the mind 
of a person of genius is like a seed oast into the ground, 
because the former produces a multitude of other thoughts, 
and the latter a multitude of other seeds, this is saying 
that between the relation of an inventive mind to a thought 
contained in it, and the relation of a fertile soil to a seed 
contained m it, there exists a resemblance, the real resem¬ 
blance being m the two fundamenta relatioms , m each 
of -which there occurs a germ, producing by its develop¬ 
ment a multitude of other things similar to itself. And 
as, whenever two objects are j'omtly concerned in a pheno¬ 
menon, this constitutes a relation between those objects, 
so, if we suppose a second pair of objects concerned m a 
second phenomenon, the slightest resemblance between the 



THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES 


77 


two phenomena is sufficient to admit of its being said that 
the two relations resemble, piovided, of course, the points of 
resemblance are found m those poitions of the two phenomena 
respectively which are connoted by the relative names 

While speaking of resemblance, it is necessary to take 
notice of an ambiguity of language, against which scarcely 
any one is sufficiently on his guard. Resemblance, when it 
exists m the highest degree of all, amounting to undis- 
tmguishableness, is often called identity, and the two similar 
things are said to be the same I say often, not always, 
for we do not say that two visible objects, two persons for 
instance, aie the same, because they are so much alike that 
one might be mistaken for the other* but we constantly use 
this mode of expression when speaking of feelings, as when 
I say that the sight of any object gives me the same sensation 
or emotion to-day that it did yesterday, or the same which it 
gives to some other person. This is evidently an incorrect 
application of the word same; for the feeling which I had 
yesterday is gone, never to return ,* what I have to-day is 
anothei feeling, exactly like the foimer perhaps, but dibtmct 
from it, and it is evident that two different persons cannot 
be experiencing the same feeling, m the sense m which we 
say that they aie both sitting at the same table By a 
similar ambiguity we say, that two persons are ill of the 
same disease, that two persons hold the same office, not in 
the sense m which we say that they are engaged m the same 
adventure, or sailing m the same ship, but m the sense that 
they fill offices exactly similar, though, perhaps, m distant 
places Great confusion of ideas is often produced, and 
many fallacies engendered, in otherwise enlightened under¬ 
standings, by not being sufficiently alive to the fact (m itself 
not always to be avoided), that they use the same name to 
express ideas so different as those of identity and undis- 
tinguishable resemblance Among modem writers, Arch¬ 
bishop Whately stands almost alone m having diawn atten¬ 
tion to this distinction, and to the ambiguity connected 
with it. 

Several relations, generally called by other names, are really 



78 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


cases of lesemblance As, for example, equality, which is 
hut another word for the exact resemblance commonly called 
identity, considered as subsisting between things m respect of 
then quantity And this example forms a suitable transition 
to the third and last of the three heads under which, as already 
remaiked. Attributes are commonly arranged. 


V. Quantity. 

§ 12 Let us imagine two things, between which there 
is no difference (that is, no dissimilarity), except m quantity 
alone * for instance, a gallon of water, and more than a 
gallon of water A gallon of water, like any othei external 
object, makes its piesence known to us by a set of sensations 
which it excites. Ten gallons of water are also an external 
object, making its piesence known to us m a similar manner, 
and as we do not mistake ten gallons of watei for a gallon 
of water, it is plain that the set of sensations is more or less 
different m the two cases. In like mannei, a gallon of water, 
and a gallon of wme, aie two external objects, making their 
presence known by two sets of sensations, which sensations 
are diffeient fiom each other In the first case, however, w T e 
say that the diflfeience is m quantity, m the last there is a 
difference m quality, while the quantity of the water and of 
the wme is the same. What is the real distinction between 
the two cases ? It is not the province of Logic to analyse 
it, nor to decide whether it is susceptible of analysis or not. 
Lor us the following considerations are sufficient. It is 
evident that the sensations I receive from the gallon of 
water, and those I receive from the gallon of wme, are not 
the same, that is, not precisely alike; neither are they alto¬ 
gether unlike they are partly similar, partly dissimilar; 
and that m which they resemble is precisely that m which 
alone the gallon of water and the ten gallons do not resemble. 
That in which the gallon of water and the gallon of wme- are 
like each other, and m which the gallon and the ten gallons 
of water are unlike each other, is called their quantity. ^ This 



THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES, 79 

likeness and unlikeness I do not pretend to explain, no more 
than any other kind of likeness or unlikeness But my object 
is to show, that when we say of two things that they differ 
m quantity, just as when we say that they differ m quality, 
the asseition is always grounded on a difference m the sensa¬ 
tions which they excite Nobody, I presume, will say, that 
to see, or to lift, or to drink, ten gallons of water, does 
not include m itself a different set of sensations from those 
of seeing, lifting, or drinking one gallon, or that to see or 
handle a foot-rule, and to see or handle a yard-measure made 
exactly like it, are the same sensations. I do not undertake 
to say what the diffeience m the sensations is. Everybody 
knows, and nobody can tell, no more than any one could tell 
what white is to a person who had never had the sensation 
But the difference, so far as cognizable by our faculties, lies m 
the sensations Whatever difference we say there is m the 
things themselves, is, in this as m all other cases, grounded, 
and grounded exclusively, on a difference m the sensations 
excited by them. 

VI. Attributes Concluded, 

§13. Thus, then, all the attnbutes of bodies which are 
classed under Quality or Quantity, are grounded on the 
sensations which we receive from those bodies, and may be 
defined, the powers which the bodies have of exciting those 
sensations. And the same general explanation has been found 
to apply to most of the attributes usually classed under the 
head of Relation. They, too, are grounded on some fact 
or phenomenon into which the 1 elated objects enter as parts, 
that fact or phenomenon having no meaning and no existence 
to us, except the series of sensations or other states of con¬ 
sciousness by which it makes itself known, and the relation 
being simply the power or capacity which the object possesses 
of taking part along with the correlated object m the produc¬ 
tion of that series of sensations or states of consciousness. 
We have been obliged, indeed, to recognise a somewhat 
different character in certain peculiar relations, those of sue- 



80 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


cession and simultaneity, of likeness and unlikeness These, 
not being grounded on any fact or phenomenon distinct from 
the related objects themselves, do not admit of the same kind 
of analysis But these relations, though not, like other rela¬ 
tions, grounded on states of consciousness, are themselves 
states of consciousness resemblance is nothing but our feeling 
t of resemblance , succession is nothing but our feeling of suc¬ 
cession Or, if this be disputed (and we cannot, without 
transgressing the bounds of our seience, discuss it heie), at 
least our knowledge of these relations, and even our possibility 
of knowledge, is confined to those which subsist between 
sensations, or other states of consciousness, for, though we 
ascribe resemblance, or succession, or simultaneity, to objects 
and to attributes, it is always m virtue of resemblance or suc¬ 
cession or simultaneity m the sensations or states of con¬ 
sciousness which those objects excite, and on which those 
attributes are grounded. 

§ 14 In the preceding investigation we have, for the 
sake of simplicity, considered bodies only, and omitted minds 
But what we have said, is applicable, mutatis imitandis, to the 
latter. The attributes of minds, as well as those of bodies, 
are grounded on states of feeling or consciousness But m 
the case of a mind, we have to consider its own states, as 
well as those which it produces m other minds Every attri¬ 
bute of a mind consists either m being itself affected m a 
certain way, or affecting other minds m a certain way Con¬ 
sidered m itself, we can predicate nothing of it but the series 
of its own feelings When we say of any mind, that it is 
devout, or superstitious, or meditative, or cheerful, we mean 
that the ideas, emotions, or volitions implied m those words, 
form a frequently recurring part of the senes of feelings, or 
states of consciousness, which fill up the sentient existence of 
that mind. 

In addition, however, to those attributes of a mind which 
are grounded on its own states of feeling, attributes may also 
be ascribed to it, in the same manner as to a body, grounded 
on the feelings which it excites m other minds. A mmd does 



THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES 


81 


not, indeed, like a body, excite sensations, but it may excite 
thoughts 01 emotions The most important example of attri¬ 
butes ascribed on this ground, is the employment of terms ex¬ 
pressive of approbation or blame When, foi example, we say 
of any character, or (m other words) of any mind, that it is 
admirable, we mean that the contemplation of it excites the 
sentiment of admiration , and indeed somewhat more, for the 
word implies that we not only feel admiration, but approve 
that sentiment m ourselves In some cases, under the sem¬ 
blance of a single attribute, two aie really predicated * one of 
them, a state of the mind itself, the other, a state with which 
other minds are affected by thinking of it. As when we say 
of any one that he is generous. The word generosity expresses 
a certain state of mind, but being a term of praise, it also ex¬ 
presses that this state of mind excites m us another mental 
state, called approbation. The assertion made, therefore, is 
twofold, and of the following purport Certain feelings form 
habitually a part of this person’s sentient existence, and the 
idea of those feelings of his, excites the sentiment of approba¬ 
tion in ourselves or others 

As we thus ascribe attributes to minds on the ground of 
ideas and emotions, so may we to bodies on similar grounds, 
and not solely on the ground of sensations : as m speaking of 
the beauty of a statue ; since this attribute is grounded on the 
peculiar feeling of pleasure which the statue pioduces m our 
minds, which is not a sensation, but an emotion. 


VII. General Results. 

§ 15. Our suivey of the varieties of Things which have 
been, or which are capable of.bemg, named—which have been, 
or are capable of being, either predicated of other Things, 
or themselves made the subject of predications—is now con¬ 
cluded. 

Our enumeration commenced with Feelings, These we 
scrupulously distinguished from the objects which excite them, 
and from the organs by which they are, or may be supposed 
VOL. i. 6 



82 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS* 


to be, conveyed Feelings are of four sorts Sensations, 
Thoughts, Emotions, and Volitions. What are called Pei- 
ceptions axe merely a paiticular case of Belief, and belief is a 
kind of thought Actions are merely volitions followed by an 
effect. If there he any other kind of mental state not included 
under these subdivisions, we did not think it necessary or 
proper m this place to discuss its existence, or the lank which 
ought to he assigned to it 

After Feelings we proceeded to Substances. These aie 
either Bodies or Minds Without entering into the grounds 
of the metaphysical doubts which have been raised concerning 
the existence of Matter and Mind as obj ective realities, we 
stated as sufficient for us the conclusion m which the best 
thinkers are now for the most part agreed, that all we can 
know of Matter is the sensations which it gives us, and the 
order of occurrence of those sensations, and that while the 
substance Body is the unknown cause of our sensations, the 
substance Mind is the unknown recipient 

The only remaining class of Nameable Things is Attributes, 
and these aie of thiee kinds, Quality, Belation, and Quantity. 
Qualities, like substances, are known to us no otherwise than 
by the sensations or other states of consciousness which they 
excite: and while, m compliance with common usage, we have 
continued to speak of them as a distinct class of Things, we 
showed that m predicating them no one means to predicate 
anything but those sensations or states of consciousness, on 
which they may he said to he grounded, and by which alone 
they can be defined or described. Relations, except the simple 
cases of likeness and unhkeness, succession and simultaneity, 
are similarly grounded on some fact or phenomenon, that is, 
on some senes of sensations or states of consciousness, more 
or less complicated. The third species of Attnbute, Quantity, 
is also manifestly grounded on something in our sensations 
or states of feeling, since there is an indubitable difference m 
the sensations excited by a larger and a smaller bulk, or by a 
greater or a less degree of intensity, m any object of sense or of 
consciousness. All attributes, therefore, are to us nothing but 
either oiu sensations and other states of feeling, or something 



THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES. 


83 


inextricably involved therein , and to this even the peculiar 
and simple relations just adverted to are not exceptions. 
Those peculiar relations, however, are so important, and, even 
if they might m strictness be classed among states of con¬ 
sciousness, are so fundamentally distinct from any other of 
those states, that it would be a vain subtlety to bring them 
under that common description, and it is necessary that they 
should be classed apait 

As the result, therefore, of our analysis, we obtain the fol¬ 
lowing as an enumeration and classification of all Nameable 
Things — 

1st Feelings, or States of Consciousness 

2nd The Minds which experience those feelings 

3rd The Bodies, or external objects, which excite certain 
of those feelings, together with the powers or properties 
whereby they excite them, these last being included rather m 
compliance with common opinion, and because their existence 
is taken for granted m the common language from which I 
cannot piudently deviate, than because the recognition of such 
powers or properties as real existences appears to he warranted 
by a sound philosophy. 

4th, and last The Successions and Co-existences, the 
Likenesses and Unlikenesses, between feelings or states of 
consciousness Those relations, when considered as sub¬ 
sisting between other things, exist m reality only between the 
states of consciousness which those things, if bodies, excite, 
if minds, either excite or experience. 

This, until a better can be suggested, may serve as a sub¬ 
stitute for the aboitive Glassification of Existences, termed 
the Categories of Aristotle. The practical application of it 
will appear when we commence the inquiry into the Import of 
Propositions; in other words, when we inquire what it is 
which the mind actually believes, when it gives what is called 
its assent to a proposition. 

These four classes comprising, if the classification be cor¬ 
rect, all Nameable Things, these or some of them must of 
course compose the signification of all names, and of these, 
or some of them, is made up whatever we call a fact. 

0—2 



NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


84 

For distinction's sake, every fact which is solely composed 
of feelings or states of consciousness considered as such, is 
often called a Psychological or Subjective fact, while every 
fact which is composed, either wholly or m pait, of something 1 

different from these, that is, of substances and attributes, is 
called an Objective fact. We may say, then, that every ob- \ 

j'ective fact is grounded on a corresponding subjective one, 
and has no meaning to us, (apart from the subjective fact 
which corresponds to it,) except as a name for the unknown 
and inscrutable process by which that subjective or psycho¬ 
logical fact is brought to pass. 


I 



CHAPTER IV. 


OF PROPOSITIONS. 

§ 1. In treating of Propositions, as already m treating 
of Names, some considerations of a comparatively elementary 
nature respecting their form and yarieties must be premised, 
before entering upon that analysis of the import conveyed by 
them, which is the real subject and purpose of this preliminary 
book 

A proposition, we have before said, is a portion of discourse 
m which a predicate is affirmed or denied of a subject A 
predicate and a subject are all that is necessarily required to 
make up a proposition * but as we cannot conclude from merely 
seeing two names put together, that they are a predicate and 
a subject, that is, that one of them is intended to be affirmed or 
denied of the other, it is necessary that there should be some 
mode or form of indicating that such is the intention; some 
sign to distinguish a predication from any other kind of dis¬ 
course. This is sometimes done by a slight alteration of one 
of the words, called an inflection , as when we say, Fire 
burns, the change of the second word from burn to burns 
showing that we mean to affirm the predicate burn of the sub¬ 
ject fire. But this function is more commonly fulfilled by the 
word as, when an affirmation is intended, as not , when a 
negation, or by some other part of the verb to be . The word 
which thus serves the purpose of a sign of predication is called, 
as we formerly observed, the copula . It is important that 
there should be no indistinctness in our conception of the 
nature and office of the copula, for confused notions respect¬ 
ing it are among the causes which have spread mysticism 
over the field of logic, and perverted its speculations into 
logomachies. 

It is apt to be supposed that the copula is something more 



86 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


than a mere sign of piedication, that it also signifies existence 
In the proposition, Socrates is just, it may seem to be implied 
not only that the quality just can be affirmed of Socrates, but 
moreover that Socrates is, that is to say, exists This, how¬ 
ever, only shows that there is an ambiguity m the woid is , a 
word which not only performs the function of the copula m 
affirmations, but has also a meaning of its own, m vntue of 
which it may itself be made the predicate of a proposition. 
That the employment of it as a copula does not necessarily 
include the affirmation of existence, appeals from such a pro¬ 
position as this, A centaur is a fiction of the poets , where it 
cannot possibly be implied that a centaur exists, since the 
proposition itself expressly asserts that the thing has no real 
existence. 

Many volumes might be filled with the frivolous specula¬ 
tions concerning the nature of Being, (to ov, ovata, Ens, Enti- 
tas. Essentia, and the like) which have arisen fiom overlook¬ 
ing this double meaning of the word to be , from supposing 
that when it signifies to exist, and when it signifies to be some 
specified thing, as to be a man, to be Socrates, to be seen or 
spoken of, to be a phantom, even to be a nonentity, it must 
still, at bottom, answer to the same idea , and that a meaning 
must be found for it which shall suit all these cases. The fog 
which rose from this narrow spot diffused itself at an early 
period over the whole surface of metaphysics Yet it becomes 
us not to triumph over the great intellects of Plato and Ari¬ 
stotle because we are now able to preserve ourselves from many 
errors into which they, perhaps inevitably, fell. The fire- 
teazer of a modem steam-engine produces by his exertions 
far greater effects than Milo of Crotona could, but he is not 
therefore a stronger man The Greeks seldom knew any 
language but their own. This rendered it far more difficult 
for them than it is for us, to acquire a readiness in detecting 
ambiguities. One of the advantages of having accurately 
studied a plurality of languages, especially of those languages 
which eminent thinkers have used as the vehicle of their 
thoughts, is the practical lesson we learn respecting the ambi¬ 
guities of words, by finding that the same word m one lan- 



PROPOSITIONS. 


87 


guage corresponds, on different occasions, to different words 
m another When not thus exercised, even the strongest 
understandings find it difficult to believe that things which 
have a common name, have not m some respect or other a 
common nature, and often expend much labour very unpio- 
fitably (as was frequently done by the two philosophers just 
mentioned) m vam attempts to discover m what this common 
nature consists But, the habit once foimed, intellects much 
inferior are capable of detecting even ambiguities which are 
common to many languages and it is surprising that the one 
now under considei ation, though it exists m the modem lan¬ 
guages as well as m the ancient, should have been overlooked 
by almost all authors. The quantity of futile speculation 
which had been caused by a misapprehension of the nature 
of the copula, was hinted at by Hobbes, but Mr James Mill 
was, I believe, the first who distinctly characterized the ambi¬ 
guity, and pointed out how many errors m the received systems 
of philosophy it has had to answer for. It has indeed misled 
the moderns scarcely less than the ancients, though their 
mistakes, because our understandings are not yet so com¬ 
pletely emancipated from then influence, do not appear equally 
irrational. 

We shall now briefly review the principal distinctions 
which exist among propositions, and the technical terms most 
commonly m use to express those distinctions 


§2 A proposition being a portion of discourse m which 
something is affirmed or denied of something, the first divi¬ 
sion of propositions is mto affirmative and negative. An 
affirmative proposition is that m which the piedicate is 
affirmed of the subject, as, Caesar is dead A negative pro¬ 
position is that m which the predicate is denied of the subject, 
as, Caesar is not dead. The copula, m this last species of 
proposition, consists of the words is not , which are the sign of 
negation, is being the sign of affirmation. 

Some logicians, among whom may he mentioned Hobbes, 


Analysis of the Human Mind, i. 126 et seq 



88 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


state this distinction differently, they lecognise only one form 
of copula, is, and attach the negative sign to the predicate 
“ Caesar is dead/’ and “ Caesar is not dead/’ according to these 
writers, are piopositions agieemg not m the subject and pre¬ 
dicate, but in the subject only They do not consider fiC dead, 5 ' 
but £t not dead, 55 to be the predicate of the second pioposi- 
tion, and they accordingly define a negative proposition to 
he one in which the predicate is a negative name The point, 
though not of much practical moment, deserves notice as 
an example (not unfrequent m logic) where by means of 
an apparent simplification, hut which is merely verbal, 
matters are made moie complex than before. The notion 
of these writers was, that they could get nd of the distinc¬ 
tion between affirming and denying, by tieating every case 
of denying as the affirming of a negative name. But what 
is meant by a negative name ? A name expiessive of the 
absence of an attribute. So that when we affirm a negative 
name, what we aie really predicating is absence and not 
pie&ence, we aie asseitmg not that anything is, hut that 
something is not, to expiess which operation no word seems 
so proper as the word denying The fundamental distinc¬ 
tion is between a fact and the non-existence of that fact, 
between seeing something and not seeing it, between Caesar’s 
being dead and his not being dead , and if this were a merely 
verbal distinction, the generalization which brings both 
within the same form of assertion would he a real simplifi¬ 
cation the distinction, however, being real, and m the facts, 
it is the generalization confounding the distinction that is 
merely verbal, and tends to obscure the subject, by treating 
the difference between two kinds of truths as if it were only 
a difference between two kinds of words To put things 
together, and to put them or xeep them asunder, will 
remain different operations, whatever tucks we may play with 
language 

A remark of a similar nature may he applied to most of 
those distinctions among propositions which are said to have 
reference to their modality; as, difference of tense or time ; 
the sun did rise, the sun is rising, the sun ivill rise. These 



PROPOSITIONS. 


89 


differences, like that between affirmation and negation, might 
he glossed over by considering the incident of time as a meie 
modification of the piedicate thus, The sun is an object 
having risen, The sun is an object now rising, The sun is an 
object to rise hereafter. But the simplification would be merely 
verbal. Past, present, and future, do not constitute so many 
different kinds of rising; they are designations belonging to 
the event asserted, to the sun's rising to-day. They affect, 
not the predicate, but the applicability of the predicate to the 
particular subject That which we affirm to be past, piesent, 
or future, is not what the subject signifies, nor what the pre¬ 
dicate signifies, but specifically and expressly what the pre¬ 
dication signifies; what is expressed only by the proposition 
as such, and not by either or both of the terms Therefore 
the cncumstance of time is properly considered as attaching 
to the copula, which is the sign of predication, and not to the 
predicate. If the same cannot be said of such modifications 
as these, Caesar may be dead, Caesar is perhaps dead, it is 
possible that Caesar is dead, it is only because these fall alto¬ 
gether under another head, being properly assertions not of 
anything relating to the fact itself, but of the state of our own 
mind in regard to it, namely, our absence of disbelief of it. 
Thus <e Caesar may be dead” means “ I am not sure that Caesar 
is alive ” 

§ 3. The next division of propositions is into Simple 
and Complex. A simple proposition is that m which one 
predicate is affirmed or denied of one subject A complex 
proposition is that m which there is more than one predicate, 
or more than one subject, or both 

At first sight this division has the air of an absurdity; a 
solemn distinction of things into one and more than one, as 
if we were to divide horses into single horses and teams of 
horses. And it is true that what is called a complex propo¬ 
sition is often not a proposition at all, but several proposi¬ 
tions, held together by a conjunction. Such, for example, is 
this. Ceesar is dead, and Brutus is alive: or even this, Caesar 
is dead, but Brutus is alive. There are here two distinct 



) 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS, 


sertions, and we might as well call a stieet a complex 
>use, as these two piopositions a complex proposition. It 
true that the syncategorematic words and and but have a 
eamng, hut that meaning is so far from making the two 
opositions one, that it adds a third proposition to them. 
I particles are abbreviations, and generally abbreviations of 
opositions, a kind of shoit-hand, whereby something which, 
be expiessed fully, would have required a proposition or 
series of propositions, is suggested to the mind at once 
rus the words, Caesar is dead and Brutus is alive, are 
uivalent to these Caesar is dead, Brutus is alive, it is 
sued that the two preceding propositions should be thought 
together If the words wei e, Caesar is dead but Brutus is 
ve, the sense would be equivalent to the same three po¬ 
sitions together with a fourth ; “ between the two preceding 
^positions there exists a contrast ” viz. either between the 
o facts themselves, or between the feelings with which it is 
sired that they should be regaided. 

In the instances cited the two propositions aie kept visibly 
tinct, each subject having its separate predicate, and each 
idicate its separate subject For bievity, however, and to 
nd repetition, the propositions aie often blended together 
m this, “ Peter and James preached at Jerusalem and m 
lilee,” which contains four propositions Peter preached 
Jerusalem, Petei pi eached m Galilee, James preached at 
usaiem, James preached m Galilee 

We have seen that when the two or more propositions 
npnsed m what is called a complex proposition are stated 
>olutely, and not under any condition or proviso, it is not 
rropo&itron at all, but a plurality of propositions; since 
at it expresses is not a single assertion, hut several asser¬ 
ts, which, if true when joined, are true also when separated, 
t there is a kind of proposition which, though it contains 
lurality of subjects and of predicates, and may be said in 
s sense of the word to consist of several propositions, con- 
is hut one assertion, and its truth does not at all imply 
t of the simple propositions which compose it An 
mple of this is, when the simple propositions are con- 



PROPOSITIONS. 


91 


nected by the particle or ; as, Either A is B or C is D 3 or by 
the particle if; as, A is B if C is D In the former case, the 
proposition is called disjunctive , m the latter, conditional: the 
name hypothetical was originally common to both As has 
been well remarked by Archbishop Whately and others, the 
disjunctive form is resolvable into the conditional, every dis¬ 
junctive proposition being equivalent to two or more con¬ 
ditional ones. “Either A is B or C is D,” means, “if A is 
not B, C is D , and if C is not D, A is B ” All hypothetical 
propositions, therefore, though disjunctive in form, are con¬ 
ditional m meaning, and the words hypothetical and condi¬ 
tional may be, as indeed they generally aie, used synony¬ 
mously. Propositions in which the assertion is not dependent 
on a condition, are said, m the language of logicians, to be 
categorical* 

An hypothetical proposition is not, like the pretended com¬ 
plex propositions which we previously considered, a mere 
aggregation of simple propositions The simple propositions 
which form part of the words m which it is couched, form no 
part of the assertion which it conveys. When we say, If the 
| Koran comes fiom God, Mahomet is the prophet of God, we 
do not intend to affirm eithei that the Koran does come from 
God, or that Mahomet is really his prophet Neither of these 
simple propositions may be true, and yet the tiutli of the 
hypothetical proposition may be indisputable. What is 
asserted is not the truth of either of the propositions, but the 
mfernbility of the one from the other. What, then, is the 
subject, and what the predicate of the hypothetical proposi¬ 
tion ? “ The Koran” is not the subject of it, nor is “ Maho¬ 

met .” for nothing is affirmed or denied either of the Koran 
or of Mahomet The real subject of the predication is the 
entire proposition, “Mahomet is the prophet of God,” and. 
the affirmation is, that this is a legitimate inference fiom the 
proposition, “ The Koran comes from God.” The subject and 
predicate, therefore, of an hypothetical proposition are names 
of propositions. The subject is some one proposition. The 
predicate is a general relative name applicable to propositions ; 
of this form—“ an inference from so and so.” A fresh instance 



NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


here afforded of the remark, that particles are abbrevia- 
ms, smce “ If A is B, C is D,” is found to be an abbre- 
ation of the following “ The proposition 0 is D, is a legiti- 
ate inference from the proposition A is B ” 

The distinction* therefore, between hypothetical and cate- 
>ncal propositions, is not so great as it at first appears. In 
iq conditional, as well as m the categorical foim, one predi- 
ite is affirmed of one subject, and no more but a conditional 
oposition is a proposition concerning a proposition, the 
ibject of the assertion is itself an assertion. Nor is this a 
operty peculiar to hypothetical propositions. There are 
ffier classes of assertions concerning propositions. Like other 
ungs, a proposition has attributes which may be predicated 
’ it. The attribute predicated of it m an hypothetical pro- 
DSition, is that of being an inference from a certain other 
coposition But this is only one of many attubutes that 
Light be predicated We may say, That the whole is greater 
lan its pait, is an axiom m mathematics That the Holy 
host proceeds from the Father alone, is a tenet of the Greek 
huich The doctrine of the divine light of kings was 
mounted by Parliament at the Bevolution The infallibility 
P the Pope has no countenance fiom Scripture In all these 
ises the subject of the predication is an entire proposition, 
hat which these different predicates are affirmed of, is the 
reposition , “the whole is greater than its part,” the proposi- 
on, “ the Holy Ghost proceeds from the Father alone the 
r oposition 3 “kings have a divine right,” the proposition, “the 
’ope is infallible.” 

Seeing, then, that there is much less difference between 
ypothetical piopositions and any others, than one might be 
id to imagine from their form, we should be at a loss to 
ccount for the conspicuous position which they have been 
sleeted to fill m treatises on logic, if we did not remember 
rat what they predicate of a proposition, namely, its being 
n inference from something else, is precisely that one of its 
ttributes with which most of all a logician is concerned. 



PROPOSITIONS. 


93 


§ 4. The next of the common divisions of Piopositions is 
into Universal, Particular, Indefinite, and Singular a distinc¬ 
tion founded on the degree of generality m which the name, 
which is the subject of the proposition, is to he understood 
The following are examples: 

All men are mortal— Universal 

Some men are mortal— Particular 

Man is mortal— Indefinite. 

Julius Ccesar is mortal— Singular. 

The proposition is Singular, when the subject is an indi¬ 
vidual name The individual name needs not he a proper name. 
(e The Founder of Chnstianity was crucified,” is as much a 
singular proposition as “ Christ was crucified.” 

When the name which is the subject of the proposition is 
a general name, we may intend to affirm 01 deny the piedicate, 
eithei of all the things that the subject denotes, or only of 
some When the predicate is affirmed or denied of all and 
each of the things denoted by the subject, the proposition is 
universal, when of some undefined portion of them only, it is 
particular. Thus, All men are mortal; Every man is mortal, 
are universal propositions. No man is immortal, is also an 
universal proposition, since the predicate, immortal, is denied 
of each and every individual denoted by the term man, the 
negative proposition being exactly equivalent to the following, 
Every man is not-immortal. But Cf some men are wise,” 
cc some men are not wise,” are particular propositions, the 
predicate wise being m the one case affirmed and m the other 
denied not of each and every individual denoted by the term 
man, but only of each and every one of some portion of those 
individuals, without specifying what portion, for if this were 
specified, the proposition would be changed either into a sin¬ 
gular proposition, or into an universal proposition with a dif- 
feient subject, as, for instance, “ all properly instructed men 
are wise ” There are other forms of particular propositions; 
as, “ Most men are imperfectly educatedit being immaterial 
how large a portion of the subject the piedicate is asserted of, 
as long as it is left uncertain how that portion is to be distin¬ 
guished from the rest. 



NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


4 


When the form of the expression does not clearly show 
hether the general name which is the subject of the pioposi- 
on is meant to stand for all the individuals denoted by it, or 
nly for some of them, the pioposition is, by some logicians, 
ailed Indefinite; but this, as Aichbishop Whately observes, 
i a solecism, of the same nature as that committed by some 
rammanans when m then list of genders they enumerate the 
oubtfwl gendei The speaker must mean to assert the propo- 
ition either as an universal or as a particular proposition, 
rough he has failed to declare which and it often happens 
rat though the words do not show which of the two he 
itends, the context, or the custom of speech, supplies the 
eficiency Thus, when it is affirmed that “ Man is mortal ” 
obody doubts that the assertion is intended of all human 
emgs, and the word indicative of universality is commonly 
mitted, only because the meaning is evident without it In 
le proposition, cc Wine is good,” it is undeistood with equal 
sadmess, though for somewhat different reasons, that the 
ssertion is not intended to be universal, but particular * 
When a general name stands foi each and every individual 
hich it is a name of, or m other words, which it denotes, it 
; said by logicians to be distributed, or taken distubutively. 
'hus, m the pioposition. All men are mortal, the subject, Man, 
\ distributed, because mortality is affirmed of each and every 
lan The predicate, Mortal, is not distubuted, because the 
nly mortals who are spoken of m the proposition aie those 
ho happen to be men, while the word may, for aught that 
ppears, and m fact does, comprehend within it an indefinite 
umber of objects besides men. In the proposition, Some men 
re mortal, both the predicate and the subject are undistributed, 
n the following, No men have wings, both the predicate and 
tie subject are distributed Not only is the attribute of having 
mgs denied of the entire class Man, but that class is severed 
nd cast out from the whole of the class Winged, and not merely 
om some part of that class. 


* It may, however, be considered as equivalent to an universal proposition 
ith a different predicate, viz “All wine is good qud wine,” or “is good in 
spect of the qualities which constitute it wine ” 



PROPOSITIONS. 


95 


This phraseojogy, which is of great service m stating and 
demonstrating the rules of the syllogism, enables ns to express 
very concisely the definitions of an universal and a particular 
proposition. An universal proposition is that of which the 
subject is distributed , a particular proposition is that of which 
the subject is undistributed. 

Theie are many more distinctions among propositions than 
those we have here stated, some of them of considerable im- 
poitance But, for explaining and illustiatmg these, more 
suitable opportunities will occur m the sequel. 



CHAPTER V. 


OF THE IMPORT OF PROPOSITIONS. 

§ 1. An mquny into the nature of propositions must 
we one of two objects to analyse the state of mind called 
elief, or to analyse what is believed. All language recog- 
ises a difference between a doctrine 01 opinion, and the fact 
enter taming the opinion, between assent, and what is 
rented to. 

Logic, accoidmg to the conception here formed of it, has 
3 concern with the nature of the act of judging or believing , 
le consideration of that act, as a phenomenon of the mind, 
slongs to another science. Philosophers, however, from 
'escartes downwards, and especially from the era of Leibnitz 
id Locke, have by no means observed this distinction, and 
ould have treated with great disrespect any attempt to analyse 
te import of Propositions, unless founded on an analysis 
the act of Judgment. A proposition, they would have 
Lid, is but the expression in words of a Judgment. The 
ung expressed, not the mere verbal expression, is the lm- 
Drtant matter When the mind assents to a proposition, 
judges. Let us find out what the mind does when it 
idges, and we shall know what propositions mean, and not 
therwise. 

Conformably to these views, almost all the writers on 
ogic m the last two centuries, whether English, German, or 
rench, have made their theory of Propositions, from one end 
> the other, a theory of Judgments. They considered a 
roposition, or a Judgment, for they used the two words mdis- 
Tminately, to consist in affirming or denying one idea of 
aother. To judge, was to put two ideas together, or to bring 
ae idea under another, or to compare two ideas, or to 
erceive the agreement or disagreement between two ideas. 



IMPORT OF PROPOSITIONS. 


97 


and the whole doctune of Propositions, together with the 
theory of Reasoning, (always necessarily founded on the theory 
of Piopositions,) was stated as if Ideas, or Conceptions, or 
whatever other teim the wnter pieferred as a name for mental 
repiesentations geneially, constituted essentially the subject 
matter and substance of those operations 

It is, of course, tiue, that m any case of judgment, as for 
instance when we judge that gold is yellow, a process takes 
place m our minds, of which some one or other of these theones 
is a paitially coirect account We must have the idea of gold 
and the idea of yellow, and these two ideas must be brought 
together m our mind. But m the first place, it is evident that 
this is only a part of what takes place, foi we may put two 
ideas together without any act of belief, as when we merely 
imagine something, such as a golden mountain, or when we 
actually disbelieve for m order even to disbelieve that 
Mahomet was an apostle of God, we must put the idea of 
Mahomet an t d that of an apostle of God togethei. To determine 
what it is that happens m the case of assent or dissent besides 
putting two ideas togethei, is one of the most intimate of 
metaphysical problems But whatever the solution may be, 
we may venture to assert that it can have nothing whatever 
to do with the import of propositions, for this reason, that 
piopositions (except sometimes when the mind itself is the 
subject treated of) are not assertions respecting our ideas of 
things, but assertions respecting the things themselves In 
order to believe that gold is yellow, I must, indeed, have the 
idea of gold, and the idea of yellow, and something having re¬ 
ference to those ideas must take place in my mind, but my 
belief has not reference to the ideas, it has reference to the 
things What I believe, is a fact relating to the outward 
thing, gold, and to the impression made by that outward thing 
upon the human organs, not a fact relating to my conception 
of gold, which would be a fact m my mental history, not a 
fact of external nature. It is true, that m order to believe 
this fact m external natuie, another fact must take place m 
my mind, a process must be performed upon my ideas, but 
so it must m everything else that I do. I cannot dig the 
vol r. 7 



98 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


ground unless I have the idea of the ground, and of a spade, 
and of all the other things I am opeiating upon, and unless I 
put those ideas together * But it would be a very ridiculous 
description of digging the ground to say that it is putting 
one idea into another Digging is an operation which is 
performed upon the things themselves, though it cannot be 
performed unless I have m my mmd the ideas of them And 
in like manner, believing is an act which has for its subject 
the facts themseh es, though a pievious mental conception 
of the facts is an indispensable condition. When I say that 
iii e causes heat, do I mean that my idea of fire causes my 
idea of heat? No J mean that the natural phenomenon, 
fire, causes the natural phenomenon, heat When I mean 
to assert anything respecting the ideas, I give them their 
proper name, I call them ideas as when I say, that a child’s 
idea of a battle is unlike the reality, or that the ideas enter¬ 
tained of the Deity have a great effect on the characters of 
mankind 

The notion that what is of pnmary importance to the 
logician in a proposition, is the relation between the tvo ideas 
coiresponding to the subject and predicate, (instead of the 
ielation between the two phenomena which they respectively 
express,) seems to me one of the most fatal eirors ever intro¬ 
duced into the philosophy of Logic, and the principal cause 
why the theory of the science has made such inconsiderable 
progress during the last two centuries. The treatises on Logic, 
and on the branches of Mental Philosophy connected with 
Logic, which have been produced since the intrusion of this 
cardinal error, though sometimes written by men of extraor¬ 
dinary abilities and attainments, almost always tacitly imply a 
theory that the investigation of truth consists m contemplating 


* Dr Whewell (Philosophy of Discovery , p. 242) questions this statement, 
and asks, ‘ Are we to say that a mole cannot dig the ground, except he has an 
idea of the ground, and of the snout and paws with which he digs it v r J do 
not know what passes in a mole’s mmd, nor what amount of mental apprehen¬ 
sion may or may not accompany his instinctive actions. But a human being 
does not use a spade by instinct, and he certainly could not use it unless he 
had knowledge of a spade, and of the earth which he uses it upon 



IMPORT OF PROPOSITIONS. 


99 


and handling our ideas, or conceptions of things, instead of 
the things themselves : a doctrine tantamount to the assertion, 
that the only mode of acquiring knowledge of nature is to 
study it at second hand, as repiesented m our own minds 
Meanwhile, mqumes into every kind of natuial phenomena 
were incessantly establishing great and fruitful truths on most 
important subjects, by processes upon which these views of the 
nature of Judgment and Eeasonrng threw no light, and in 
which they afforded no assistance whatever. No wonder that 
those who knew by practical experience how truths are 
arrived at, should deem a science futile, which consisted chiefly 
of such speculations. What has been done for the advance¬ 
ment of Logic since these doctnnes came into vogue, has 
been done not by professed logicians, but by discoverers m 
the other sciences, m whose methods of investigation many 
principles of logic, not previously thought of, have suc¬ 
cessively come foith into light, but who have generally com¬ 
mitted the error of supposing that nothing whatever was known 
of the art of philosophizing by the old logicians, because 
their modern interpreters have written to so little purpose 
respecting it 

We have to inquire, then, on the present occasion, not into 
Judgment, but judgments, not into the act of believing, but 
into the thing believed. What is the immediate object of 
belief m a Proposition? What is the matter of fact signified 
by it ? What is it to which, when I assert the proposition, I 
give my assent, and call upon others to give theirs ? What is 
that which is expressed by the form of discourse called a Pro¬ 
position, and the conformity of which to fact constitutes the 
truth of the proposition ? 

§ 2 One of the clearest and most consecutive thinkers 
whom this country or the world has produced, I mean Hobbes, 
has given the following answer to this question. In every 
proposition (says he) what is signified is, the belief of the 
speaker that the predicate is a name of the same thing of which 
the subject is a name ; and if it really is so, the proposition is 
true. Thus the proposition, All men are living beings (he 

7—2 



100 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS 


would say) is true, because hung being is a name of everything 
of which man is a name. All men are six feet high, is not 
true, because six feet high is not a name of everything (though 
it is of some things) of which man is a name 

What is stated m this theory as the definition of a true 
proposition, must be allowed to be a property which all tine 
propositions possess The subject and predicate being both 
of them names of things,, if they were names of quite different 
things the one name could not, consistently with its significa¬ 
tion, he predicated of the othei If it be true that some men 
aie copper-colouied, it must be true—and the proposition does 
leallv assert—that among the individuals denoted by the name 
man, there are some who are also among those denoted by the 
name copper-coloured If it he true that all oxen ruminate, it 
must be tiue that all the individuals denoted by the name ex 
aie also among those denoted by the name ruminating, and ' 
whoever asseits that all oxen ruminate, undoubtedly does assert 
that this relation subsists between the two names 

The assertion, therefore, which, according to Hohbes, is the 
only one made m any proposition, really is made m every pro¬ 
position and his analysis has consequently one of the requi¬ 
sites for being the tiue one We may go a step farther, it is 
the only analysis that is rigorously true of all propositions 
without exception What he gives as the meaning of propo¬ 
sitions, is part of the meaning of all propositions, and the whole 
meaning of some. This, however, only shows what an ex¬ 
tremely minute fragment of meaning it is quite possible to 
include within the logical formula of a proposition It does 
not show that no proposition means more To warrant us m 
putting together two words with a copula between them, it is 
really enough that the thing or things denoted by one of the 
names should be capable, without violation of usage, of being 
called by the other name also If, then, this be all the mean¬ 
ing necessarily implied in the form of discourse called a Pro¬ 
position, why do I object to it as the scientific definition of 
what a proposition means ? Because, though the mere collo¬ 
cation which makes the proposition a proposition, conveys no 
more than this scanty amount *of meaning, that same collo- 



IMPORT OF PROPOSITIONS. 


101 


cation combined with other cncumstances, that foi i?i combined 
with othei mattei , does convey more, and much more. 

The only propositions of which Hobbes principle is a suffi¬ 
cient account, aie that limited and ummpoitant class m which 
both the piedicate and the subject aie proper names. For, as 
has already been lemarked, proper names have strictly no 
meaning, they are mere maiks for individual objects and 
when a piopei name is predicated of another proper name, all 
the signification conveyed is, that both the names are maiks 
for the same object But this is precisely what Hobbes pro¬ 
duces as a theoiy of piedication m geneial His doctune is a 
fall explanation of such predications as these Hyde was 
Claiendon, or, Tully is Cicero. It exhausts the meaning of 
those propositions. But it is a sadly inadequate theory of 
any otheis. That it should ever have been thought of as such, 
can be accounted for only by tlie fact, that Hobbes, in common 
with the other Nominalists, bestowed little or no attention 
upon the connotation of woids , and sought for then meaning 
exclusively in what they denote . as if all names had been 
(what none but pioper names really are) marks put upon indi¬ 
viduals ; and as if there were no difference between a proper 
and a general name, except that the first denotes only one 
individual, and the last a gieater number. 

It has been seen, however, that the meaning of all names, 
except pioper names and that portion of the class of abstract 
names which are not connotative, resides m the connotation. 
When, theiefore, we are analysing the meaning of any pro¬ 
position m which the piedicate and the subject, or either 
of them, aie connotative names, it is to the connotation of 
those terms that we must exclusively look, and not to what 
they denotei or m the language of Hobbes (language so far 
correct) are names of. 

In asseiting that the truth of a proposition depends on the 
conformity of import between its terms, as, for instance, that 
the proposition, Socrates is wise, is a true proposition, because 
Socrates and wise are names applicable to, or, as he expresses 
it, names of, the same person; it is very remarkable that 
so powerful a thinker should not have asked himself the ques- 



102 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


tion, But how came they to "be names of the same person ? 
Suiely not because such, was the intention of those who 
invented the words. When mankind fixed the meaning of the 
word wise, they were not thinking of Socrates, nor, when his 
paients gave him the name of Socrates, were they thinking 
of wisdom. The names happen to fit the same person because 
of a certain fact, which fact was not known, nor m being, 
when the names were invented. If we want to know what 
the fact is, we shall find the clue to it m the connotation of the 
names. 

A bird or a stone, a man, or a wise man, means simply, an 
object having such and such attributes. The real meaning of the 
word man, is those attributes, and not Smith, Brown, and the 
remainder of the individuals. The word mortal, m like manner 
connotes a certain attribute or attributes, and when we say, 
All men are mortal, the meaning of the proposition is, that all 
beings which possess the one set of attributes, possess also the 
other. If, m our experience, the attributes connoted by man 
are always accompanied by the attribute connoted by mortal, it 
will follow as a consequence, that the class man will be wholly 
included m the class mortal , and that mortal will be a name 
of all things of which man is a name * but why ? Those 
objects are brought under the name, by possessing the attri¬ 
butes connoted by it: but their possession of the attributes is 
the real condition on which the tiuth of the proposition 
depends, not their being called by the name. Connotative 
names do not precede, but follow, the attributes which they 
connote If one attribute happens to be always found m con¬ 
junction with another attribute, the concrete names which 
answer to those attributes will of course be predicable of the 
same subjects, and may be said, m Hobbes’ language, (m the 
propriety of which on this occasion I fully concur,) to be two 
names for the same things. But the possibility of a concur¬ 
rent application of the two names, is a mere consequence of 
the conjunction between the two attributes, and was, m most 
cases, never thought of when the names were introduced and 
their signification fixed. That the diamond is combustible, 
was a proposition certainly not dreamt of when the words 



IMPORT OF PROPOSITIONS. 


103 


Diamond and Combustible first received their meaning, and 
could not have been discovered by the most ingenious and 
refined analysis of the signification of those woids. It was 
found out by a very different process, namely, by exerting the 
senses, and learning from them, that the attribute of com¬ 
bustibility existed m the diamonds upon which the experi¬ 
ment was tiled, the number or character of the experiments 
being such, that what was true of those individuals might be 
concluded to be true of all substances “ called by the name/ 9 
that is, of all substances possessing the attributes which the 
name connotes. The asseition, therefore, when analysed, is, 
that wheiever we find certain attributes, there will be found a 
certain other attribute * which is not a question of the signifi¬ 
cation of names, but of laws of nature, the order existing 
among phenomena. 

§ 3 Although Hobbes’ theory of Predication has not, in 
the terms m which he stated it, met with a very favourable 
reception from subsequent thmkei s, a theory virtually iden¬ 
tical with it, and not by any means so perspicuously expressed, 
may almost be said to have taken the lank of an established 
opinion. The most generally received notion of Predication 
decidedly is that it consists in referring something to a class, 
i e , either placing an individual under a class, or placing one 
class under another class. Thus, the proposition, Man is 
mortal, asserts, according to this view of it, that the class 
man is included m the class mortal. “ Plato is a philosopher,” 
asseits that the individual Plato is one of those who compose 
the class philosopher. If the proposition is negative, then 
instead of placing something m a class, it is said to exclude 
something from a class. Thus, if the following be the propo¬ 
sition* The elephant is not carnivorous, what is asserted 
(according to this theory) is, that the elephant is excluded 
from the class carnivorous, or is not numbered among the 
things comprising that class. There is no real difference, 
except m language, between this theory of Predication and 
the theory of Hobbes. For a class is absolutely nothing but 
an indefinite number of individuals denoted by a general 



104 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS 


name. The name given to them m common, is what makes 
them a class To refer anything to a class, therefore, is to 
look upon it as one of the things which aie to be called by 
that common name. To exclude it fiom a class, is to say that 
the common name is not applicable to it. 

How widely these views of predication have prevailed, is 
evident from this, that they are the basis of the celebrated 
dictum de omm et nullo. When the syllogism is resolved, by 
all who treat of it, into an inference that what is true of a 
class is true of all things whatever that belong to the class, 
and when this is laid down by almost all piofessed logicians 
as the ultimate principle to which all reasoning owes its 
validity, it is clear that m the geneial estimation of logi¬ 
cians, the propositions of which reasonings are composed 
can be the expression of nothing but the process of dividing 
things into classes, and lefemng everything to its proper 
class 

This theory appears to me a signal example of a logical 
ei ror very often committed m logic, that of varepov irporepov, 
01 explaining a thing by something which presupposes it. 
When I say that snow is white, I may and ought to be think¬ 
ing of snow as a class, because I am asseitmg a pioposition 
as true of all snow but I am certainly not thinking of white 
objects as a class; I am thinking of no white object whatever 
except snow, but only of that, and of the sensation of white 
which it gives me When, indeed, I have judged, or assented 
to the propositions, that snow is white, and that several other 
things are also white, I gradually begin to think of white 
objects as a class, including snow and those other things. But 
this is a conception which followed, not pieceded, those judg¬ 
ments, and therefore cannot be given as an explanation of 
them. Instead of explaining the effect by the cause, this 
doctiine explains the cause by the effect, and is, I conceive, 
founded on a latent misconception of the nature of classifi¬ 
cation. 

There is a sort of language very generally prevalent m 
these discussions, which seems to suppose that classification 
is an arrangement and grouping of definite and known indi- 



14L 


V. 




K. '* 



\ 






* ^ 




IMPORT OF PROPOSITIONS ^ 105 

viduals. that when names were imposed, mankind took ipto 
consideration all the individual objects m the umveise, distri¬ 
buted them into parcels or lists, and gave to the objects of each 
list a common name, xepeating this operation toties quoties 
until they had invented all the general names of which lan¬ 
guage consists, which having been once done, if a question 
subsequently anses whether a certain general name can be 
truly predicated of a ceitam particular object, we have only 
(as it were) to read the roll of the objects upon which that 
name was conferied, and see whether the object about which 
the question arises is to be found among them. The framers 
of language (it would seem to be supposed) have predetermined 
all the objects that are to compose each class, and we have only 
to refer to the lecord of an antecedent decision. 

So absurd a doctrine will be owned by nobody when thus 
nakedly stated, but if the commonly received explanations of 
classification and naming do not imply this theory, it requires 
to be shown how they admit of being reconciled with any 
other. 

General names are not marks put upon definite objects, 
classes are not made by drawing a line round a given numbei 
of assignable individuals. The objects which compose any 
given class are perpetually fluctuating. We may fiame a class 
without knowing the individuals, or even any of the individuals, 
of which it may be composed, we may do so while believing 
that no such individuals exist. If by the meaning of a general 
name are to be understood the things which it is the name of, 
no general name, except by accident, has a fixed meaning at 
all, or ever long retains the same meaning The only mode 
m which any general name has a definite meaning, is by being 
a name of an indefinite variety of things, namely, of all 
things, known or unknown, past, present, or future, which 
possess certain definite attributes. When, by studying not 
the meaning of words, but the phenomena of nature, we dis¬ 
cover that these attributes are possessed by some object not 
previously known to possess them, (as when chemists found 
that the diamond was combustible), we include this new object 
m the class, but it did not already belong to the class. We 



10G 


>3AMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


place the individual m tlie class because the proposition is 
true, the proposition is not true because the object is placed 
in the class 

It will appear hereafter, in tieating of reasoning, how 
much the theory of that intellectual process has been vitiated 
by the influence of these enoneous notions, and by the habit 
which they exemplify of assimilating all the operations of the 
human understanding which have truth for then object, to pio- 
cesses of mere classification and naming Unfortunately, the 
minds which have been entangled m this net aie precisely those 
which have escaped the other cardinal error commented upon 
in the beginning of the present chapter. Since the revolution 
which dislodged Aristotle from the schools, logicians may 
almost be divided into those who have looked upon reasoning 
as essentially an affair of Ideas, and those who have looked 
upon it as essentially an affair of Names 

Although, however, Hobbes’ theory of Predication, accord¬ 
ing to the well-known lemark of Leibnitz, and the avowal of 
Hobbes himself,-* renders truth and falsity completely aibi- 
trary, with no standard hut the will of men, it must not be 
concluded that either Hobbes, or any of the other thinkers 
who have in the mam agreed with him, did m fact consider the 
distinction between truth and error as less real, or attached less 
importance to it, than other people To suppose that they did 
so would argue total unacquaintance with their othei specula¬ 
tions. But this shows how little hold their doctrine possessed 
over their own minds. No person, at bottom, ever imagined 
that there was nothing more m tiuth than propriety of expres¬ 
sion , than using language m conformity to a previous conven¬ 
tion When the inquiry was brought down from generals to a 
particular case, it has always been acknowledged that there is a 
distinction between verbal and real questions, that some false 
propositions are uttered from ignorance of the meaning of 


* ‘ * Prom hence also this may be deduced, that the first truths were arbi¬ 
trarily made by those that first of all imposed names upon things, or received 
them from the imposition of others. For it is true (for example) that man is a 
living creature , but it is for this reason, that it pleased men to impose both these 
names on the same thing .”—Computation or Logic, eh in sect 8. 



IMPORT OF PROPOSITIONS. 


107 


words, but that m others the source of the error is a misappre¬ 
hension of things, that a person who has not the use of lan¬ 
guage at all may form propositions mentally, and that they 
may be untrue, that is, he may believe as matteis of fact what 
are not really so This last admission cannot be made m 
stronger teims than it is by Hobbes himself,* though he will 
not allow such enoneous belief to be called falsity, but only 
eiror. And he has himself laid down, m other places, doctrines 
m which the true theory of predication is by implication con¬ 
tained He distinctly says that general names are given to 
things on account of their attributes, and that abstract names 
are the names of those attributes. “ Abstract is that which m 
any subject denotes the cause of the concrete name. . . . 
And these causes of names are the same with the causes of our 
conceptions, namely, some power of action, or affection, of the 
thing conceived, which some call the manner by which anything 
works upon our senses, but by most men they are called acci¬ 
dents.’^ It is strange that having gone so far, he should not 
have gone one step farther, and seen that what he calls the 
cause of the concrete name, is m reality the meaning of it; 
and that when we predicate of any subject a name which is 
given because of an attribute (or, as he calls it, an accident), 
our object is not to affirm the name, but, by means of the 
name, to affirm the attribute. 

§ 4. Let the predicate be, as we have said, a connotative 
term ; and to take the simplest case first, let the subject be a 
proper name “ The summit of Chimborazo is white.” The 


* “ Men are subject to err not only in affirming and denying, but also in 
perception, and }n silent cogitation . Tacit errors, 01 the eriors of sense and 
cogitation, aie made by passing from one imagination to the imagination of 
another different thing , or by feigning that to be past, or future, which never 
was, nor ever shall be ; as when by seeing the image of the sun m water, we 
imagine the sun itself to be there , or by seeing swords, that there has been, 
01 shall be, fighting, because it uses to be so for the most part, or when from 
promises we feign the mind of the promiser to be such and such , or, lastly, 
when from any sign we vainly imagine something to be signified which is not 
And errors of this sort are common to all things that have sense.”— Computa¬ 
tion or JjogiCj ch v sect 1 


t Ch. in. sect. 3. 



I OS NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS 

word white connotes an attubute which is possessed by tlie 
individual object designated by the woids “ summit of Chim¬ 
borazo which attubute consists m the physical fact, of its 
exciting m human bemgs the sensation which we call a sensa¬ 
tion of white. It will be admitted that, by asserting the pro¬ 
position, we wish to communicate mfoimation of that physical 
fact, and aie not thinking of the names, except as the neces¬ 
sary means of making that communication. The meaning of 
the proposition, theiefoie, is, that the individual thing denoted 
by the subject, has the attributes connoted by the predicate. 

If we now suppose the subject also to be a connotative 
name, the meaning expiessed by the proposition lias advanced 
a step farthei m complication. Let us fhst suppose the pro¬ 
position to be universal, as well as affirmative “ All men are 
mortal.” In this case, as m the last, what the pioposition 
asseits (or expresses a belief of) is, of course, that the objects 
denoted by the subject (man) possess the attributes connoted 
by the predicate (mortal) But the characteristic of this case 
is, that the objects are no longer individually designated They 
are pointed out only by some of their attributes : they aie the 
objects called men, that is, possessing the attributes connoted 
by the name man , and the only thing known of them may be 
those attnhutes indeed, as the proposition is geneial, and the 
objects denoted by the subject are therefore indefinite m 
number, most of them are not known individually at all. The 
assertion, therefore, is not, as before, that the attributes which 
the predicate connotes are possessed by any given individual, 
or by any numbei of individuals pieviously known as John, 
Thomas, &c., hut that those attributes are possessed by each 
and every individual possessing certain othei attnhutes , that 
whatever has the attnhutes connoted by the subject, has also 
those connoted by the predicate, that the latter set of attri¬ 
butes constantly accompany the former set. Whatever has the 
attributes of man has the attribute of mortality, mortality 
constantly accompanies the attributes of man * 


* To the preceding statement it has been objected, that <£ we naturally 
construe the subject of a proposition m its extension, and the predicate (which 
therefore may be an adjective) m its intension, (connotation) and that conse- 



IMPORT OF PROPOSITION'S. 


109 


If it be remembered that every attribute is grounded on 
some fact or phenomenon, either of outward sense or of inward 
consciousness, and that to possess an attribute is another 
phrase foi being the cause of, or forming part of, the fact or 
phenomenon upon which the attribute is grounded, we may 
add one more step to complete the analysis The pioposition 
which asseits that one attubute always accompanies another 
attribute, really asserts thereby no other thing than this, that 
one phenomenon always accompanies another phenomenon ; 
insomuch that where we find the one, we have assurance of 
the existence of the other Thus, m the proposition, All men 
are mortal, the word man connotes the attributes which we 
ascribe to a certain kind of living creatures, on the ground of 
ceitam phenomena which they exhibit, and which are partly 
physical phenomena, namely the impressions made on our 
senses by their bodily form and stiucture, and partly mental 
phenomena, namely the sentient and intellectual life which 
they have of their own All this is understood when we utter 
the word man, by any one to whom the meaning of the word 
is known. Now, when we say, Man is mortal, we mean that 
wherever these various physical and mental phenomena are all 
found, there we have assuiance that the othei physical and 
mental phenomenon, called death, will not fail to take place. 
The proposition does not affirm when; for the connotation of 
the word mortal goes no faither than to the occurrence of the 
phenomenon at some time or other, leaving the precise time 
undecided 


quently coexistence of attributes does not, any more than the opposite theory 
of equation of groups, correspond with the living processes of thought and 
language ” I acknowledge the distinction here drawn, which, indeed, I had 
myself laid down and exemplified a few pages back (p 104) But though it is 
true that we naturally “construe the subject of a pioposition m its extension,’* 
this extension, 01 m other words, the extent of the class denoted by the name, 
is not appi eh ended or indicated directly It is both apprehended and indi¬ 
cated solely thiough the attributes In the “ living processes of thought and 
language ” the extension, though m this case really thought of (which in the 
case of the piedicate it is not), is thought of only through the medium of what 
my acute and courteous critic terms the 4 "intension ” 

For fuither illustrations of this subject, see Examination of Sir William 
Hamilton's Philosophy, ch xxn 



no 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


§ 5 We have alieady proceeded far enough, not only to 
demonstrate the eiror of Hobbes, but to ascertain the leal 
import of by far the most numerous class of propositions 
The object of belief m a proposition, when it asseits an) thing 
more than the meaning of woids, is generally, as m the cases 
. which we have examined, either the co-existence or the 
sequence of two phenomena At the very commencement of our 
inquiry, we found that every act of belief implied two Things 
we have now asceitamed what, m the most frequent case, these 
two things are, namely two Phenomena, m other words, two 
states of consciousness, and what it is which the proposition 
affirms (or denies) to subsist between them, namely either suc¬ 
cession or co-existence. And this case includes innumerable 
instances which no one, previous to reflection, would think of 
referring to it Take the following example * A generous 
person is worthy of honour Who would expect to recognise 
heie a case of co-existence between phenomena 0 But so it is. 
The attribute which causes a person to be termed generous, is 
ascribed to lnm on the ground of states of his mind, and par¬ 
ticulars of his conduct both are phenomena the foimer are 
facts of internal consciousness, the latter, so far as distinct 
from the former, are physical facts, nr perceptions of the senses. 
Woithy of honour admits of a similar analysis. Honour, as 
here used, means a state of approving and admiring emotion, 
followed on occasion by corresponding outward acts “ Worthy 
of honour ” connotes all this, together with our approval of the 
act of showing honour. All these are phenomena, states of 
internal consciousness, accompanied or followed by physical 
facts When we say, A generous person is worthy of honour, 
we affirm co-existence between the two complicated pheno¬ 
mena connoted by the two terms respectively We affirm, 
that wherever and whenever the inward feelings and outward 
facts implied in the word generosity have place, then and 
there the existence and manifestation of an inward feeling 

D J 

honour, would he followed m our minds by another inward 
feeling, approval. 

After the analysis, m a former chapter, of the import of 
names, many examples aie not needed to illustrate the import 



IMPORT OF PROPOSITIONS. Ill 

of propositions. When there is any obscunty, or difficulty, 
it does not he m the meaning of the proposition, but m the 
meaning of the names which compose it, m the extiemely com¬ 
plicated connotation of many woids, the immense multitude 
and prolonged series of facts which often constitute the 
phenomenon connoted by a name. But where it is seen 
what the phenomenon is, there is seldom any difficulty m 
seeing that the asseition conveyed by the proposition is, the 
co-existence of one such phenomenon with another; or the 
succession of one such phenomenon to another their con¬ 
junction, in short, so that wheie the one is found, we may 
calculate on finding both. 

This, however, though the most common, is not the only 
meaning which piopositions are ever intended to convey. In 
the hist place, sequences and co-existences are not only 
asserted respecting Phenomena, we make propositions also 
respecting those hidden causes of phenomena, which are 
named substances and attributes A substance, however, 
being to us nothing but either that which causes, or that 
which is conscious of, phenomena, and the same being tme, 
mutatis mutandis, of attributes, no asseition can be made, at 
least with a meaning, concerning these unknown and un¬ 
knowable entities, except m virtue of the Phenomena by 
which alone they manifest themselves to our faculties When 
we say, Socrates was cotemporary with the Peloponnesian war, 
the foundation of this assertion, as of all assertions concern¬ 
ing substances, is an assertion concerning the phenomena 
which they exhibit,—namely, that the senes of facts by which 
Socrates manifested himself to mankind, and the senes of 
mental states which constituted his sentient existence, went 
on simultaneously with the series of facts known by the name 
of the Peloponnesian war. Still, the proposition does not 
assert that alone, it asserts that the Thing m itself, the 
| noumenon Socrates, was existing, and doing or experiencing 
those various facts during the same time. Co-existence and 
sequence, therefore, may be affirmed or denied not only be¬ 
tween phenomena, but between noumena, or between a noume¬ 
non and phenomena. And both of noumena and of phenomena 



m 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


we may affixm simple existence But what is a noumenon ? 
An unknown cause In affirming, therefore, the existence of a 
noumenon, we affiim causation Here, therefore, are two addi¬ 
tional kinds of fact, capable of being asseited m a proposition. 
Besides the propositions which assert Sequence 01 Coexistence, 
there are some which assert simple Existence, and others assert 
Causation, which, subject to the explanations which will follow 
in the Thud Book, must be considered provisionally as a dis¬ 
tinct and peculiai kind of assertion 

§ 6 To these four kinds of matter-of-fact or assertion, 
must be added a fifth, Eesemblance This was a species of 
attribute which we found it impossible to analyse; for which 
no fundamentum, distinct fiom the objects themselves, could 
be assigned. Besides propositions which asseit a sequence or 
co-existence between two phenomena, theie are therefore also 
propositions which assert resemblance between them as, This 
colour is like that colour,—The heat of to-day is equal to the 
heat of yesterday. It is true that such an assertion might 
with some plausibility be brought wuthm the description of 
an affirmation of sequence, by considering it as an assertion 
that the simultaneous contemplation of the two colours is 
followed by a specific feeling termed the feeling of resemblance. 
But there would be nothing gained by encumbering ourselves, 
especially in this place, with a generalization which may be 
looked upon as strained Logic does not undertake to analyse 
mental facts into their ultimate elements. Eesemblance be¬ 
tween two phenomena is more intelligible m itself than any 
explanation could make it, and under any classification must 
remain specifically distinct from the ordinary cases of sequence 
and co-existence 

It is sometimes said, that all propositions whatever, of which 
the predicate is a general name, do, m point of fact, affirm 01 
deny resemblance. All such propositions affirm that a thing 
belongs to a class, but things being classed together accord¬ 
ing to their resemblance, everything is of course classed with 
the things which it is supposed to resemble most, and thence, 
it may be said, when we affirm that Gold is a metal, or that 



IMPORT OF PROPOSITION’S. 


113 


Socrates is a man, the affirmation intended is, that gold re¬ 
sembles other metals, and Socrates other men, more nearly 
than they lesemble the objects contained in any other of the 
classes co-ordinate with these. 

There is some slight degree of foundation for this remark, 
but no more than a slight degree The arrangement of things 
into classes, such as the class metal, or the class man, is 
grounded indeed on a resemblance among the things which 
are placed m the same class, hut not on a meie general resem¬ 
blance the resemblance it is grounded on consists in the 
possession by all those things, of certain common peculiari¬ 
ties , and those peculiarities it is which the terms connote, and 
which the piopositions consequently assert, not the resem¬ 
blance : for though when I say, Gold is a metal, I say by im¬ 
plication that if theie be any other metals it must resemble 
them, yet if there were no other metals I might still assert the 
proposition with the same meaning as at present, namely, that 
gold has the various properties implied m the word metal, 
just as it might be said, Christians are men, even if there 
were no men who were not Christians. Propositions, there¬ 
fore, m which objects are referred to a class because they pos¬ 
sess the attributes constituting the class, are so far from assert¬ 
ing nothing but resemblance, that they do not, properly speak¬ 
ing, assert resemblance at all. 

But we remarked some time ago (and the reasons of the 
remark will be more fully entered into m a subsequent Book*) 
that there is sometimes a convenience in extending the 
boundaries of a class so as to include things which possess 
in a very inferior degree, if m any, some of the characteristic 
properties of the class,—provided they resemble that class 
moie than any other, insomuch that the general propositions 
which are true of the class, will be nearer to being true of 
those things than any other equally general propositions 
For instance, there are substances called metals which have 
very few of the properties by which metals are commonly 
recognised; and almost every great family of plants or animals 


VOL i. 


* Book iv ch. vu 
8 



114 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


bas a few anomalous genera or species on its borders, wbicb 
are admitted into it by a sort of courtesy, and concerning 
which it has been matter of discussion to what family they 
properly belonged. Now when the class-name is predicated 
of any object of this description, we do, by so predicating it, 
affirm resemblance and nothing more And m order to be 
scrupulously correct it ought to be said, that m every case m 
which we pie die ate a general name, we affirm, not absolutely 
that the object possesses the properties designated by the 
name, but that it either possesses those properties, or if it does 
not, at any rate resembles the things which do so, more than 
it resembles any other things. In most cases, however, it is 
unnecessary to suppose any such alternative, the latter of the 
two grounds being very seldom that on which the assertion is 
made and when it is, there is generally some slight differ¬ 
ence m the form of the expression, as, This species (or genus) 
is considered, or may he ranked , as belonging to such and such 
a family we should hardly say positively that it does belong 
to it, unless it possessed unequivocally the properties of which 
the class-name is scientifically significant. 

There is still another exceptional case, m which, though 
the predicate is the name of a class, yet m predicating it we 
affirm nothing but resemblance, the class being founded not 
on resemblance m any given particular, but on general unana¬ 
lysable resemblance. The classes m question are those into 
which our simple sensations, or other simple feelings, are 
divided. Sensations of white, for instance, are classed toge¬ 
ther, not because we can take them to pieces, and say they 
are alike m this, and not alike m that, but because we feel 
them to be alike altogether, though m different degrees. 
When, therefore, I say, The colour I saw yesterday was a 
white coloui, or, The sensation I feel is one of tightness, m 
both cases the attribute I affirm of the colour or of the other 
sensation is mere resemblance—simple likeness to sensations 
which I have had before, and which have had those names 
bestowed upon them. The names of feelings, like other con¬ 
crete general names, are connotative; but they connote a 
mere resemblance. When predicated of any individual feeling, 



TMPORT OF PROPOSITIONS 


115 


the information they convey is that of its likeness to the other 
feelings which we have been accustomed to call by the same 
name. Thus much may suffice m illustration of the kind of 
propositions m which the matter-of-fact asserted (or denied) is 
simple Eesemblance 

Existence, Coexistence, Sequence, Causation,Resemblance, 
one or other of these is asserted (or denied) m every proposi¬ 
tion which is not merely verbal This five-fold division is an 
exhaustive classification of matters-of-fact; of all things that 
can be believed, or tendered for belief, of all questions that 
can be propounded, and all answers that can be returned to 
them Instead of Coexistence and Sequence, we shall some¬ 
times say, for greater particularity. Order m Place, and Order 
m Time Order m Place being the specific mode of coex¬ 
istence, not necessary to be more particularly analysed here; 
while the mere fact of coexistence, or simultaneousness, may 
be classed, together with Sequence, under the head of Order 
m Time. 


§ 7 . In the foregoing inquiry into the import of Propo¬ 
sitions, we have thought it necessary to analyse directly those 
alone, m which the terms of the proposition (or the predicate 
at least) are concrete terms. Put, m doing so, we have indi¬ 
rectly analysed those m which the terms are abstract. The 
distinction between an abstract term and its corresponding 
conciete, does not turn upon any difference in what they aie 
appointed to signify, for the real signification of a concrete 
general name is, as we have so often said, its connotation, 
and what the concrete term connotes, forms the entue mean¬ 
ing of the abstract name. Since there is nothing in the 
import of an abstiact name which is not in the import of the 
corresponding concrete, it is natural to suppose that neithei 
can there he anything in the import of a proposition of which 
tne terms aie abstract, but what there is in some proposition 
which can be framed of concrete teims 

And this presumption a closer examination will confirm. 
An abstract name is the name of an attribute, or combination 
of attributes. The corresponding concrete is a name given to 

8—2 



116 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONSS. 


things, because of, and in order to express, their possessing 
that attribute, or that combination of attributes. When, 
therefoie, we piedicate of anything a conciete name, the 
attribute is what we m leality predicate of it. But it has 
now been shown that m all propositions of which the piedi¬ 
cate is a concrete name, what is really predicated is one of 
five things Existence, Coexistence, Causation, Sequence, or 
Resemblance. An attribute, therefore, is necessarily either 
an existence, a coexistence, a causation, a sequence, or a 
resemblance When a pioposition consists of a subject and 
predicate which are abstiact terms, it consists of terms which 
must necessanly signify one or other of these things. When 
we piedicate of anything an abstiact name, we affirm of the 
thing that it is one or other of these five things; that it is a 
case of Existence, or of Coexistence, or of Causation, or of 
Sequence, or of Resemblance. 

It is impossible to imagine any proposition expressed m 
abstract terms, which cannot he transformed into a precisely 
equivalent proposition m which the terms are conciete, 
namely, either the concrete names which connote the attri¬ 
butes themselves, 01 the names of the fundamenta of those 
attributes, the facts or phenomena on which they are 
grounded. To illustiate the latter case, let us take this 
proposition,, of which the subject only is an abstract name, 
“Thoughtlessness is dangerous.” Thoughtlessness is an 
attubute, grounded on the facts which we call thoughtless 
actions, and the proposition is equivalent to this. Thoughtless 
actions are dangerous In the next example the predicate as 
well as the subject are abstract names. C£ Whiteness is a 
colour,” or “ The colour of snow is a whiteness.” These 
attributes being grounded on sensations, the equivalent pro¬ 
positions m the concrete would be, The sensation of white is 
one of the sensations called those of colour,—The sensation of 
sight, caused by looking at snow, is one of the sensations 
called sensations of white. In these propositions, as we 
have before seen, the matter-of-fact asserted is a Resem¬ 
blance. In the following examples, the concrete terms are 
those which directly correspond to the abstract names, con- 



IMPORT OF PROPOSITIONS. 


117 


noting the attribute which these denote “ Prudence is a 
virtuethis may he rendered, “All prudent persons, m so 
far as prudent, are virtuous *” “ Courage is deserving of 
honour,” thus, “ All couiageous persons are deserving of 
honour m so far as they are courageous ” which is equiva¬ 
lent to this—“All courageous persons deserve an addition 
to the honour, or a diminution of the disgiace, which would 
attach to them on other grounds.” 

In order to throw still further light upon the import 
of propositions of which the terms are abstract, we will sub¬ 
ject one of the examples given above to a minuter analysis. 
The proposition we shall select is the following —“ Prudence 
is a vntue ” Let us substitute for the word virtue an equiva¬ 
lent but more definite expression, such as “ a mental quality 
beneficial to society,” or “ a mental quality pleasing to God,” 
or whatever else we adopt as the definition of virtue. What 
the proposition asserts is a sequence, accompanied with causa¬ 
tion , namely, that benefit to society, or that the approval of 
God, is consequent on, and caused by, piudence. Here is a 
sequence ; but between what ? We understand the consequent 
of the sequence, but we have yet to analyse the antecedent. 
Prudence is an attribute, and, m connexion with it, two 
things besides itself are to be considered, prudent persons, 
who are the subjects of the attribute, and prudential conduct, 
which may be called the foundation of it. Now is either of 
these the antecedent ? and, first, is it meant, that the approval 
of God, or benefit to society, is attendant upon all prudent per¬ 
sons 2 No , except in so far as they are prudent, for prudent 
persons who are scoundrels can seldom on the whole be bene¬ 
ficial to society, nor can they be acceptable to a good being Is 
it upon prudential conduct, then, that divine approbation and 
benefit to mankind are supposed to be invariably consequent ? 
Neither is this the assertion meant, when it is said that pru¬ 
dence is a vntue, except with the same reservation as before, 
and for the same reason, namely, that prudential conduct, 
although in so far as it is prudential it is beneficial to society, 
may yet, by reason of some other of its qualities, be productive 
of an injury outweighing the benefit, and deserve a displeasure 



118 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS 


exceeding the approbation which would be due to the pru¬ 
dence Neither the substance, therefore, (viz. the person,) nor 
the phenomenon, (the conduct,) is an antecedent on which the 
other term of the sequence is univeisally consequent. But the 
proposition, (< Prudence is a virtue,” is an universal proposi¬ 
tion What is it, then, upon which the proposition affirms the 
effects m question to be universally consequent 0 Upon that 
in the person, and m the conduct, which causes them to be 
called prudent, and which is equally in them when the action, 
though prudent, is wicked, namely, a correct foiesight of 
consequences, a just estimation of their importance to the 
object m view, and repression of any unreflecting impulse at 
variance with the deliberate purpose. These, which are states 
of the person’s mind, are the real antecedent m the sequence, 
the real cause m the causation, asserted by the proposition. 
But these are also the real ground, or foundation, of the attri¬ 
bute Prudence, since wherever these states of mind exist we 
may predicate prudence, even before we know whether any 
conduct has followed. And in this manner every assertion 
respecting an attribute, may he transformed into an assertion 
exactly equivalent respecting the fact 01 phenomenon which 
is the ground of the attubute. And no case can be assigned, 
where that which is predicated of the fact or phenomenon, does 
not belong to one or othei of the five species formerly enume¬ 
rated : it is either simple Existence, or it is some Sequence, 
Coexistence, Causation, or Resemblance. 

And as these five are the only things which can he affirmed, 
so are they the only things which can he denied, “ No horses 
are web-footed” denies that the attributes of a horse ever co¬ 
exist with web-feet. It is scarcely necessary to apply the same 
analysis to Particular affirmations and negations. “ Some 
birds are web-footed,” affirms that, with the attributes con¬ 
noted by bird, the phenomenon web-feet is sometimes co-exis- 
tent: “ Some birds are not web-footed,” asserts that there are 
other instances m which this coexistence does not have place. 
Any further explanation of a thing which, if the previous ex¬ 
position has been assented to, is so obvious, may here be spared. 



CHAPTER VI. 


OF PROPOSITIONS MERELY VERBAL. 

§ 1 As a prepaiation for the inquiry which is the proper 
object of Logic, namely, m what manner propositions are to 
be proved, we have found it necessary to mqune what they 
contain which requires, or is susceptible of, proof, or (which 
is the same thing) what they asseit. In the course of this 
preliminary investigation into the import of Propositions, we 
examined the opinion of the Conceptualists, that a proposition 
is the expression of a relation between two ideas, and the 
doctrine of the Nominalists, that it is the expression of an 
agreement or disagreement between the meanings of two 
names We decided that, as general theories, both of these 
are enoneous, and that, though propositions may be made 
both respecting names and respecting ideas, neither the one 
nor the other aie the subject-matter of Propositions considered 
generally We then examined the different kinds of Proposi¬ 
tions, and found that, with the exception of those which are 
merely verbal, they assert five different kinds of matters of fact, 
namely. Existence, Order m Place, Order m Time, Causation, 
and Resemblance, that m every proposition one of these five 
is either affirmed, or denied, of some fact or phenomenon, or of 
some obj'ect the unknown source of a fact or phenomenon. 

In distinguishing, however, the different kinds of matters 
of fact asserted m propositions, we reserved one class of pro¬ 
positions, which do not relate to any matter of fact, in the 
proper sense of the term, at all, but to the meaning of names. 
Since names and their signification are entirely arbitrary, such 
propositions are not, strictly speaking, susceptible of truth 
or falsity, but only of conformity or disconformity to usage or 
convention, and all the proof they are capable of, is proof of 
usage, proof that the words have been employed by others in 



120 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


the acceptation m which the speaker or writer desires to use 
them These propositions occupy, however, a conspicuous 
place m philosophy, and then nature and charactenstics 
are of as much importance m logic, as those of any of the 
other classes of propositions previously adverted to 

If all propositions respecting the signification of words 
were as simple and unimportant as those which served us 
for examples when examining Hobbes’ theory of piedication, 
viz. those of which the subject and predicate are proper names, 
and which assert only that those names have, or that they 
have not, been conventionally assigned to the same individual, 
there would be little to attract to such propositions the atten¬ 
tion* of philosophers. But the class of merely verbal proposi¬ 
tions embraces not only much more than these, but much moie 
than any piopositions which at first sight present themselves 
as veibal, comprehending a kind of assertions which have 
been regarded not only as relating to things, but as having 
actually a more intimate relation with them than any other 
propositions whatever. The student m philosophy will per¬ 
ceive that I allude to the distinction on which so much stress 
was laid by the schoolmen, and which has been retained either 
under the same or under other names by most metaphysicians 
to the piesent day, viz between what were called essential , 
and what were called accidental, propositions, and between 
essential and accidental properties or attributes 

§ 2 . Almost all metaphysicians prior to Locke, as well as 
many since his time, have made a great mystery of Essential 
Predication, and of predicates which are said to be of the 
essence of the subject The essence of a thing, they said, was 
that without which the thing could neither be, nor be con¬ 
ceived to be. Thus, rationality was of the essence of man, 
because without rationality, man could not be conceived to 
exist. The different attributes which made up the essence of 
the thing were called its essential properties ; and a proposition 
in which any of these were predicated of it was called an x 
Essential Proposition, and was considered to go deeper into the 
nature of the thing, and to convey more important information 



VERBAL AND REAL PROPOSITIONS. 


121 


respecting it, than any other proposition could do. All pro¬ 
perties, not of the essence of the thing, weie called its accidents ; 
were supposed to have nothing at all, or nothing comparatively, 
to do with its inmost nature , and tlie propositions m which 
any of these were predicated of it were called Accidental Pro¬ 
positions A connexion may he traced between this distinc¬ 
tion, which originated with the schoolmen, and the well-known 
dogmas of substantia secundce or general substances, and sub - 
stantial forms, doctnnes which under varieties of language per¬ 
vaded alike the Aristotelian and the Platonic schools, and of 
■which more of the spirit has come down to modern times than 
might be conjectured from the disuse of the phraseology. 
The false views of the nature of classification and generaliza¬ 
tion which prevailed among the schoolmen, and of which these 
dogmas were the technical expression, affoid the only explana¬ 
tion which can be given of their having misunderstood the real 
nature of those Essences which held so conspicuous a place m 
their philosophy They said, truly, that man cannot be con¬ 
ceived without rationality But though man cannot, a being 
may be conceived exactly like a man m all points except that 
one quality, and those others which are the conditions or con¬ 
sequences of it. All therefore which is really true m the asser¬ 
tion that man cannot be conceived without rationality, is only, 
that if he had not rationality, he would not be reputed a man 
There is no impossibility m conceiving the thing, nor, for 
aught we know, m its existing the impossibility is in the con¬ 
ventions of language, which will not allow the thing, even if 
it exist, to be called by the name which is reserved for rational 
beings Rationality, m short, is involved m the meaning of the 
woid man. is one of the attributes connoted by the name. The 
essence of man, simply means the whole of the attributes con¬ 
noted. by the word, and any one of those attubutes taken 
singly, is an essential property of man. 

But these reflections, so easy to us, would have been difficult 
to persons who thought, as most of the later Aristotelians did, 
that objects were made what they were called, that gold (for 
instance) was made gold, not by the possession of certain pro¬ 
perties to which mankind have chosen to attach that name, but 



122 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


by participation m the nature of a certain general substance, 
called gold m general, which substance, together with all the 
properties that belonged to it, inhered m every individual piece 
of gold * As they did not consider these universal substances 
to be attached to all general names, but only to some, they 
thought that an object borrowed only a part of its properties 
from an universal substance, and that the rest belonged to it 
individually the former they called its essence, and the latter 
its accidents. The scholastic doctnne of essences long survived 
the theory on which it rested, that of the existence of real 
entities corresponding to general terms , and it was reserved foi 
Locke at the end of the seventeenth century, to convince phi¬ 
losophers that the supposed essences of classes were merely the 
signification of their names, nor, among the signal services 
which his writings rendered to philosophy, was theie one more 
needful or more valuable. 

Now, as the most familiar of the general names by which 
an object is designated usually connotes not one only, but 
several attubutes of the object, each of which attributes sepa¬ 
rately forms also the bond of union of some class, and the 
meaning of some general name, we may predicate of a name 
which connotes a variety of attributes, another name which 
connotes only one of these attributes, or some smaller number 
of them than all In such cases, the universal affirmative pro¬ 
position will be true, since whatevei possesses the whole of 
any set of attributes, must possess any part of that same set 
A proposition of this sort, however, conveys no information 
to any one who previously understood the whole meaning of 
the terms. The propositions, Eveiv man is a corporeal being. 
Every man is a living creature, Every man is rational, convey 
no knowledge to any one who was already aware of the entire 
meaning of the word man, for the meaning of the word 


* The doctrines which prevented the real meaning of Essences from being 
understood, had not assumed so settled a shape m the time of Aristotle and 
his immediate followers, as was afterwards given to them by the Realists 
of the middle ages. Aristotle himself (in his Treatise on the Categories) ex¬ 
pressly denies that the devrepai ov<nai, or Substantise Secundse, inhere m a 
subject. They are only, he says, predicated of it 



VERBAL AND REAL PROPOSITIONS. 123 

includes all tins and that every man has the attributes con¬ 
noted by all these predicates, is already asserted when he is 
called a man. Now, of this nature are all the propositions 
which have been called essential They aie, m fact, identical 
propositions. 

It is true that a proposition which predicates any attribute, 
even though it be one implied in the name, is m most cases 
understood to involve a tacit assertion that there exists a thing 
corresponding to the name, and possessing the attributes con¬ 
noted by it; and this implied assertion may convey informa¬ 
tion, even to those who understood the meaning of the name. 
But all information of this sort, conveyed by all the essential 
propositions of which man can be made the subject, is included 
m the assertion, Men exist And this assumption of real ex¬ 
istence is, after all, the result of an imperfection of language. 
It arises from the ambiguity of the copula, which, m addition 
to its proper office of a maik to show that an assertion is made, 
is also, as formerly remarked, a concrete word connoting 
existence The actual existence of the subject of the proposi¬ 
tion is therefore only apparently, not really, implied in the 
predication, if an essential one we may say, A ghost is a dis¬ 
embodied spirit, without believing m ghosts But an accidental, 
or non-essential, affirmation, does imply the real existence of 
the suhj'ect, because m the case of a non-existent subj'ect 
there is nothing for the proposition to assert. Such a propo¬ 
sition as, The ghost of a murdered person haunts the couch of 
the murdeier, can only have a meaning if understood as im¬ 
plying a belief in ghosts, for since the signification of the 
word ghost imphes nothing of the kind, the speaker either 
means nothing, or means to assert a thing which he wishes to 
be believed to have really taken place. 

It will be hereafter seen that when any important conse¬ 
quences seem to follow, as m mathematics, from an essential 
proposition, or, m other words, from a proposition involved in 
the meaning of a name, what they really flow from is the tacit 
assumption of the real existence of the objects so named. 
Apart from this assumption of real existence, the class of pro¬ 
positions m which the predicate is of the essence of the subject 



124 * 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


(that is, in which the piedicate connotes the whole or part of 
what the subject connotes, but nothing besides) answer no 
purpose hut that of unfolding the whole or some part of the 
meaning of the name, to those who did not previously know it. 
Accordingly, the most useful, and m strictness the only useful 
kind of essential propositions, are Definitions. which, to be 
complete, should unfold the whole of what is involved m the 
meaning of the word defined ,* that is, (when it is a connotative 
word,) the whole of what it connotes In defining a name, 
however, it is not usual to specify its entire connotation, but 
so much only as is sufficient to mark out the objects usually 
denoted by it from all other known objects. And sometimes 
a merely accidental property, not involved m the meaning of 
the name, answers this purpose equally well. The various 
kinds of definition which these distinctions give rise to, and 
the purposes to which they aie respectively subservient, will be 
minutely considered m the proper place. 

§ 3. According to the above view of essential propositions, 
no proposition can be reckoned such which relates to an indi¬ 
vidual by name, that is, m which the subject is a proper name 
Individuals have no essences When the schoolmen talked of 
the essence of an individual, they did not mean the properties 
implied m its name, for the names of individuals imply no 
pioperties They regarded as of the essence of an individual, 
whatever was of the essence of the species m which they were 
accustomed to place that individual, i e of the class to which 
it was most familiarly referied, and to which, therefore, they 
conceived that it by nature belonged Thus, because the pro¬ 
position Man is a rational being, was an essential proposition, 
they affirmed the same thing of the proposition, Julius Caesar 
is a rational being This followed very naturally if genera and 
species were to be considered as entities, distinct from, hut 
inhering in, the individuals composing them If man was a 
substance inhering m each individual man, the essence of man 
(whatever that might mean) was naturally supposed to accom¬ 
pany it, to inhere m John Thompson, and to form the common 
essence of Thompson and Julius Csesar It might then be 



VERBAL AND REAL PROPOSITIONS. 125 

fairly said, that rationality, being of the essence of Man, was 
of the essence also of Thompson. But if Man altogether be 
only the individual men and a name bestowed upon them in 
consequence of certain common propeities, what becomes of 
John Thompson’s essence ? 

A fundamental eiror is seldom expelled from philosophy 
by a single victoiy. It retreats slowly, defends every inch 
of ground, and often, after it has been driven from the open 
countiy, retains a footing m some lemote fastness The 
essences of individuals were an unmeaning figment arising 
from a misapprehension of the essences of classes, yet even 
Locke, when he extirpated the parent error, could not shake 
himself free from that which was its fruit He distinguished 
two soi ts of essences, Beal and Nommal His nominal essences 
were the essences of classes, explained nearly as we have now 
explained them. Nor is anything wanting to render the third 
hook of Locke’s Essay a nearly unexceptionable treatise on 
the connotation of names, except to free its language fiom the 
assumption of what are called Abstract Ideas, which unfor¬ 
tunately is involved in the phraseology, though not necessarily 
connected with the thoughts contained in that immortal Thud 
Book.* But, besides nominal essences, he admitted real 
essences, or essences of individual objects, which he supposed 
to be the causes of the sensible properties of those objects. 
We know not (said he) what these are, (and this acknowledg¬ 
ment rendeied the fiction comparatively innocuous;) but if we 
did, we could, fiom them alone, demonstrate the sensible pro¬ 
peities of the object, as the properties of the triangle are 


* The always acute and often profound author of An Outline of Sematology 
(Mr B H Smait) justly says, “ Locke will be much more intelligible if, m 
the majority of places, we substitute * the knowledge of’ for what he calls ‘ the 
Idea of”’ (p 10) Among the many criticisms on Locke’s use of the word 
Idea, this is the one which, as it appears to me, most nearly hits the mark, 
and I quote it for the additional leason that it precisely expresses the point of 
diffeience respecting the import of Propositions, between my view and what I 
have spoken of as the Conceptuahst view of them Where a Conceptualist 
says that a name or a proposition expresses our Idea of a thing, I should 
generally say (instead of our Idea) our Knowledge, or Belief, concerning the 
thing itself 



126 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


demonstrated fiom the definition of the triangle I shall have 
occasion to revert to this theory m treating of Demonstration, 
and of the conditions under which one propeity of a thing 
admits of being demonstrated from another property It is 
enough here to remark that, aceoidmg to this definition, the 
real essence of an object has, m the progress of physics, come 
to he conceived as nearly equivalent, m the case of bodies, to 
their corpuscular structure what it is now supposed to mean 
m the case of any other entities, I would not take upon myself 
to define. 

§ 4. An essential proposition, then, is one which is purely 
veibal; which asserts of a thing under a particular name, only 
I what is asserted of it m the fact of calling it by that name , 

; and which therefore either gives no information, or gives it 
f lespectmg the name, not the thing. Non-essential, or acci¬ 
dental propositions, on the contrary, may be called Eeal Pro¬ 
positions, m opposition to Verbal They predicate of a thing 
some fact not involved m the signification of the name by 
which the proposition speaks of it, some attribute not com 
noted by that name. Such are all propositions concerning 
things individually designated, and all general or particular 
propositions m which the predicate connotes any attribute not 
connoted by the subject All these, if true, add to our know¬ 
ledge they convey information, not already involved m the 
names employed. When I am told that all, or even that some 
objects, which have ceitam qualities, or which stand m 
certain relations, have also certain other qualities, or stand 
in certain other relations, I learn fiom this proposition 
a new fact, a fact not included in my knowledge of the 
meaning of the words, nor even of the existence of Things 
answering to the signification of those words. It is this 
class of propositions only which are in themselves instructive, 
or from which any instructive propositions can he inferred * 

* This distinction corresponds to that which is drawn by Kant and other 
metaphysicians between what they teim analytic, and synthetic , judgments , the 
former being those which can be evolved from the meaning of the teims used 



VERBAL AND REAL PROPOSITIONS. 


127 


Nothing has probably contributed more to the opinion 
so long prevalent of the futility of the school logic, than the 
circumstance that almost all the examples used m the common 
school books to illustrate the doctrine of predication and that 
of the syllogism, consist of essential propositions They were 
usually taken either fiom the blanches or from the mam trunk 
of the Predicamental Tree, which included nothing but what 
was of the essence of the species . Omne corpus est substantia, 
Omne animal est coipus, Omnis homo est corpus, Omnis homo 
est animal, Omnis homo est rationalis, and so forth It is 
far from wonderful that the syllogistic art should have been 
thought to be of no use m assisting conect reasoning, when 
almost the only propositions which, m the hands of its pro¬ 
fessed teachers, it was employed to prove, were such as eveiy 
one assented to without proof the moment he comprehended 
the meaning of the words , and stood exactly on a level, m 
point of evidence, with the premises from which they were 
drawn. I have, therefore, throughout this work, avoided the 
employment of essential propositions as examples, except 
where the nature of the principle to be illustrated specifically 
required them. 

§ 5. With respect to propositions which do convey in¬ 
formation — which assert something of a Thing, under a 
name that does not alieady presuppose what is about to be 
asserted, there are two different aspects m which these, or 
rather such of them as are general propositions, may be con¬ 
sidered we may either look at them as portions of speculative 
truth, or as memoranda for practical use. According as we 
consider propositions in one or the other of these lights, their 
import may be conveniently expressed m one or m the other 
of two foimulas 

According to the formula which we have hitherto employed, 
and which is best adapted to express the import of the pro¬ 
position as a portion of our theoretical knowledge, All men 
are mortal, means that the attnbutes of man are always 
accompanied by the attribute mortality: No men are gods, 
means that the attiibutes of man are never accompanied by 



28 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


he attributes, or at least never by all the attributes, signified 
>y the word god. But when the proposition is considered as a 
aemorandum for practical use, we shall find a diffeient 
code of expressing the same meaning better adapted to in¬ 
dicate the office which the proposition performs. The prac- 
ical use of a proposition is, to appnse or remind us what 
> T e have to expect, m any individual case which comes within 
he assertion contained m the proposition. In reference to 
his purpose, the proposition, All men are moital, means 
hat the attributes of man are evidence of, are a mark of, 
lortalitv , an indication by which the piesence of that attn- 
ute is made manifest. No men are gods, means that the 
ttnbutes of man are a mark or evidence that some or all 
f the attributes understood to belong to a god are not there ; 
bat where the former are, we need not expect to find the 
itter 

These two forms of expression are at bottom equivalent, 
ut the one points the attention more directly to what a pro- 
osition means, the latter to the manner m which it is to be 
sed. 

Now it is to be observed that Reasoning (the subject to 
hich we are next to proceed) is a process into which propo- 
tions enter not as ultimate results, but as means to the 
jtablishment of other propositions. We may expect, there- 
ire, that the mode of exhibiting the import of a general pro- 
^sition which shows it m its application to practical use, will 
3St express the function which propositions perform in Rea¬ 
ming And accordingly, m the theory of Reasoning, the 
ode of viewing the subject which considers a Proposition 

> asserting that one fact or phenomenon is a mark or 
ndence of another fact or phenomenon, will be found almost 
dispensable For the purposes of that Theory, the best 
ode of defining the import of a proposition is not the mode 
hich shows most clearly what it is m itself, but that 
bich most distinctly suggests the manner m which it may 

> made available for advancing from it to other pro- 
isitions. 



CHAPTER VII. 


OF THE NATURE OF CLASSIFICATION, AND THE FIVE 
PREDICABLES. 

§ 1 In examining into the nature of general proposi¬ 
tions, we have adverted much less than is usual with logicians 
to the ideas of a Class, and Classification , ideas which, since 
the Realist doctnne of General Substances went out of vogue, 
have formed the basis of almost every attempt at a philoso¬ 
phical theory of general terms and general propositions. We 
have considered general names as having a meaning, quite in¬ 
dependently of their being the names of classes. That cir¬ 
cumstance is in truth accidental, it being wholly immaterial to 
the signification of the name whether there are many objects, 
or only one, to which it happens to be applicable, or whether 
there be any at all. God is as much a general term to the 
Christian or Jew as to the Polytheist, and dragon, hippogriff, 
chimera, mermaid, ghost, are as much so, as if real objects 
existed, corresponding to those names. Every name the sig¬ 
nification of which is constituted by attributes, is potentially a 
name of an indefinite number of objects ; but it needs not be 
actually the name of any, and if of any, it may be the name 
of only one. As soon as we employ a name to connote attri¬ 
butes, the things, be they more or fewer, which happen to 
possess those attributes, are constituted tpso facto a class. 
But m predicating the name we predicate only the attributes ; 
and the fact of belonging to a class does not, m many cases, 
come into view at all. 

Although, however. Predication does not presuppose Classi¬ 
fication, and though the theory of Names and of Propositions 
is not cleared up, but only encumbered, by intruding the idea 
of classification into it, there is nevertheless a close connexion 
between Classification and the employment of General Names 
VOL I. 9 



130 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


By every general name which, we introduce, we create a class, 
[f there be any things, real 01 imaginary, to compose it, that 
is, any Things conespondmg to the signification of the name 
Classes, therefore, mostly owe their existence to general lan¬ 
guage. But geneial language, also, though that is not the 
most common case, sometimes owes its existence to classes 
A geneial, which is as much as to say a significant, name, is 
indeed mostly mtioduced because we have a signification to 
sxpiess by it, because we need a word by means of which to 
predicate the attributes which it connotes But it is also true 
jhat a name is sometimes mtioduced because we have found it 
jonvement to create a class , because we have thought it useful 
for the regulation of our mental operations, that a certain 
gioup of objects should be thought of together A naturalist, 
or purposes connected with his particular science, sees reason 
,o distribute the animal or vegetable creation into certain 
gLoups rather than into any others, and he requires a name to 
und, as it were, each of his groups together It must not how- 
wei be supposed that such names, when introduced, differ m 
my lespect, as to their mode of signification, from other con- 
lotative names The classes which they denote are, as much 
„s any other classes,^constituted by certain common attributes, 
md their names are significant of those attributes* and of 
lothmg else. The names of Cuvier s classes and orders, 
Plantigrades, Digitigrades, &c., are as much the expression of 
^tributes as if those names had preceded, instead of grown 
>ut of, his classification of animals. The only peculiarity of 
he case is, that the convenience of classification was here the 
uimary motive for mtiaducmg the names, while in other 
tases the name is introduced as a means of predication, and 
he formation of a class denoted by it is only an indirect con¬ 
sequence. 

The principles which ought to regulate Classification as a 
ogical process subservient to the investigation of truth, cannot 
e discussed to any purpose until a much later stage of our 
aquiry. But, of Classification as resulting from, and implied 
i, the fact of employing general language, we cannot forbear 
o tieat here, without leaving the theory of general names^ 



CLASSIFICATION AND THE PRE DICABLES. 


131 


and of their employment m pi edication, mutilated and 
foimless. 


§ 2 This portion of the theory of geneial language is 
the subject of what is teimed the doctrine of the Predicables , 
a set of distinctions handed down from Anstotle, and his fol¬ 
lower Porphyiy, many of which have taken a firm root m 
scientific, and some of them even m popular, phraseology The 
predicables are a five-fold division of General Names, not 
grounded as usual on a difference m their meaning, that is, m 
the attribute which they connote, but on a difference in the 
kind of class which they denote We may predicate of a thing 
five different vaneties of class-name — 


A genus of the thing 
A species 
A differentia 
A propnum 
An accidens 


(yhos) 

{eldog). 

(Sia<popa) 

(iSiov) 


It is to be remarked of these distinctions, that they ex¬ 
press, not what the predicate is m its own meaning, but what 
relation it bears to the subject of which it happens on the 
particular occasion to be predicated There are not some 
names which are exclusively genera, and others which are 
exclusively species, or differentise , but the same name is re¬ 
fen ed to one or another predicable, according to the subject of 
which it is predicated on the particular occasion. Animal , for 
instance, is a genus with respect to man, or John, a species 
with respect to Substance, or Being Rectangular is one of 
the Differentiae of a geometrical square, it is merely one of 
the Accidentia of the table at which I am writing The words 
genus, species, &c are therefore relative terms; they are 
names applied to certain predicates, to express the relation 
between them and some given subject: a ielation grounded, 
as we shall see, not on what the predicate connotes, but on 
the class which it denotes, and on the place which, m some given 
classification, that class occupies relatively to the paiticulai 
subject, y* 


§ 3. Of these five names, two. Genus and Species, are 
9—2 



132 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS 


not only used by naturalists m a technical acceptation not 
pieciselv agreeing with their philosophical meaning, but have 
also acquired a popular acceptation, much more general than 
either In this popular sense any two classes, one of which 
includes the whole of the other and more, may be called a 
Genus and a Species. Such, for instance, are Animal and 
Man, Man and Mathematician Animal is a Genus, Man 
and Brute are its two species, or we may divide it into a 
gieatei number of species, as man, hoise, dog, &c Biped, or 
tivo-footed animal , may also be considered a genus, of which 
man and bird are two species Taste is a genus, of which sweet 
taste, sour taste, salt taste, &c are species. Virtue is a genus , 
justice, piudence, courage, fortitude, generosity, &c are its 
species 

The same class which is a genus with reference to the 
sub-classes or species included m it, may be itself a species 
vwith reference to a moie compiehensive, or, as it is often 
called, a superior genus. Man is a species with reference 
to animal, hut a genus with reference to the species Mathe¬ 
matician Animal is a genus, divided into two species, man 
and brute, but animal is also a species, which, with another 
species, vegetable, makes up the genus, organized being 
Biped is a genus with refetence to man and bird, hut a 
species with respect to the superior genus, animal. Taste is 
a genus divided into species, but also a species of the genus 
sensation Vntue, a genus with reference to justice, tem¬ 
perance, &c, is one of the species of the genus, mental 
quality. 

In this popular sense the words Genus and Species have 
passed into common discourse. And it should he observed 
that m 01 dinary parlance, not the name of the class, hut the 
class itself, is said to be the genus or species, not, of course, 
the class m the sense of each individual of the class, hut the 
individuals collectively, considered as an aggregate whole, the 
name by which the class is designated being then called not 
the genus or species, but the generic or specific name And 
this is an admissible form of expression; nor is it of any im¬ 
portance which of the two modes of speaking we adopt, pro- 




CLASSIFICATION AND THE PREDICABLES. 133 

Tided the rest of oui language is consistent with it, but, if we 
call the class itself the genus, we must not talk of piedicatmg 
the genus. We piedicate of man the name mortal, and by 
piedicatmg the name, we may be said, m an intelligible sense, 
to predicate what the name expresses, the attribute moitality, 
but m no allowable sense of the word piedication do we piedi¬ 
cate of man the class mortal We piedicate of him the fact 
of belonging to the class. 

By the Aristotelian logicians, the terms genus and species 
weie used m a more restricted sense They did not admit 
eieiy class which could be divided into other classes to be a 
genus, or every class which could be included m a laiger class 
to he a species Animal was by them considered a genus, man 
and biute co-ordmate species under that genus biped, however, 
would not have been admitted to be a genus with reference to 
man, but a propnum or accidens only. It was requisite, ac- 
c01 ding to their theoi y, that genus and species should be of 
the essence of the subject Animal was of the essence of man , 
biped was not And in eveiy classification they consideied 
some one class as the lowest or wfima species. Man, for in¬ 
stance, was a lowest species. Any further divisions into which 
the class might be capable of being broken down, as man into 
white, black, and led man, or into priest and layman, they did 
not admit to be species 

It has been seen, however, m the preceding chapter, that 
the distinction between the essence of a class, and the attri¬ 
butes or properties which are not of its essence—a distinction 
which has given occasion to so much abstruse speculation, 
and to which so mysterious a character was formerly, and by 
many wiiters is still, attached,—amounts to nothing more 
than the difference between those attributes of the class which 
are, and those which are not, involved m the signification of 
the class-name. As applied to individuals, the word Essence, 
we found, has no meaning, except in connexion with the ex¬ 
ploded tenets of the Realists; and what the schoolmen chose 
to call the essence of an individual, was simply the essence 
of the class to which that individual was most familiarly 
referred. 



134 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


Is there no diffeience, then, save this merely verbal one, 
between the classes which the schoolmen admitted to be genera 
or species, and those to which they refused the title ? Is it 
an enor to regard some of the differences which exist among 
objects as differences %n kind (genere or specie), and others only 
as differences m the accidents ? Weie the schoolmen right or 
wiong m giving to some of the classes into which things may 
be divided, the name of kinds, and consideimg others as 
secondary divisions, grounded on differences of a comparatively 
superficial nature ? Examination will show that the Aristo¬ 
telians did mean something by this distinction, and some¬ 
thing important, but which, being but indistinctly conceived, 
was inadequately expressed by the phraseology of essences, 
and the various other modes of speech to which they had 
recourse. 

§ 4 It is a fundamental principle m logic, that the 
power of framing classes is ’unlimited, as long as there is 
any (even the smallest) difference to found a distinction 
upon Take any attribute whatever, and if some things have 
it, and others have not, we may ground on the attribute a 
division of all things into two classes , and we actually do so, 
the moment we create a name which connotes the attribute. 
The number of possible classes, therefore, is boundless, and 
there are as many actual classes (either of leal or of imaginary 
things) as there are general names, positive and negative to- 
gether. 

But if we contemplate any one of the classes so formed, 
such as the class animal or plant, or the class sulphur or phos- 
phoius, or the class white or red, and consider m what parti¬ 
culars the individuals included in the class differ from those 
which do not come within it, we find a very remarkable diver¬ 
sity m this respect between some classes and others There 
are some classes, the things contained m which differ from 
other things only in certain particulars which may be num¬ 
bered, while others differ m more than can be numbered, more 
even than we need ever expect to know. Some classes have 
little or nothing m common to characterize them by, except 



CLASSIFICATION AND THE PREDICABLES. 135 

precisely what is connoted by the name white things, for ex¬ 
ample, are not distinguished by any common propeities, except 
whiteness , or if they are, it is only by such as are m some way 
dependent on, or connected with, whiteness But a hundred 
generations have not exhausted the common propeities of 
animals 01 of plants, of sulphur or of phosphorus, nor do we 
suppose them to he exhaustible, but proceed to new obser¬ 
vations and experiments, m the full confidence of discovering 
new properties which were by no means implied m those we 
previously knew While, if any one were to piopose for in¬ 
vestigation the common properties of all things which are of 
the same coloui, the same shape, or the same specific gravity, 
the absurdity would be palpable. We have no ground to be¬ 
lieve that any such common properties exist, except such as 
may be shown to be involved m the supposition itself, or to be 
denvable from it by some law of causation. It appeals, theie- 
foie, that the propeities, on which we ground our classes, some¬ 
times exhaust all that the class has m commbn, or contain it 
all by some mode of implication; but m othei instances we 
make a selection of a few properties from among not only a 
greater number, but a number inexhaustible by us, and to 
which as we know no bounds, they may, so far as we are con¬ 
cerned, be regarded as infinite, y 

There is no impropriety m saying that, of these two classi¬ 
fications, the one answers to a much more radical distinction 
m the things themselves, than the other does. And if any one 
even chooses to say that the one classification is made by 
nature, the other by us for our convenience, he will he right, 
provided he means no more than this. Where a certain 
apparent difference between things (though perhaps m itself of 
little moment) answers to we know not what number of other 
differences, pervading not only their known properties, but 
* properties yet undiscovered, it is not optional but imperative 
I to recognise this difference as the foundation of a specific dis 
tmction, while, on the contrary, differences that are merely 
finite and determinate, like those designated by the words 
white, black, or red, may be disregarded if the purpose for 
which the classification is made does not require attention 



136 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


_to tlin&e particular propeities The differences, however, aie 

made by nature, in both cases, while the recognition of those 
differences as grounds of classification and of naming, is, equally 
m both cases, the act of man only in the one case, the ends of 
language and of classification would be subverted if no notice 
•wei e taken of the difference, while m the other case, the neces¬ 
sity of taking notice of it depends on the importance 01 unim¬ 
portance of the particular qualities m which the difference 
happens to consist 

Now, these classes, distinguished by unknown multitudes 
of properties, and not solely by a few determinate ones—which 
are paited off from one another by an unfathomable chasm, 
instead of a meie ordinary ditch with a visible bottom—are 
the only classes which, by the Aristotelian logicians, were 
consideied as genera or species. Differences which extended 
^ only to a certain piopeity or piopeities, and there teiminated, 
they considered as differences only m the accidents of things , 
hut where any class differed from other things by an infinite 
series of differences, known and unknown, they considered the 
distinction as one of kind, and spoke of it as being an essential 
difference, which is also one of the current meanings of that 
vague expression at the present day 

Conceiving the schoolmen to have been justified m drawing 
a bioad line of separation between these two kinds of classes 
and of class-distmctions, I shall not only retain the division 
itself, but continue to express it m their language. According 
(o that language, the proximate (or lowest) Kind to which any 
individual is leferrible, is called its species. Confoimahly to 
this, Sir Isaac Newton would be said to he of the species 
man. There are indeed numerous sub-classes included m 
the class man, to which Newton also belongs, for example, 
Christian, and Englishman, and Mathematician. But these; 
though distinct classes, are not, m our sense of the teim, dis¬ 
tinct Kinds of men A Christian, for example, differs from 
other human beings; hut he differs only m the attribute 
which the word expresses, namely, belief m Christianity, and 
whatever else that implies, either as involved m the fact itself, 
or connected with it through some law of cause and effect. We 



CLASSIFICATION AND THE PREDICABLES 


137 


should nevei Jhmk of inquiring what properties, unconnected 
with Chustiamty either as cause or effect, are common to 
all Clnistians and peculiar to them, while m regaid to all 
Men, physiologists are perpetually carrying on such an 
mquiiy, nor is the answer ever likely to be completed. Man, 
theiefore, we may call a species , Christian, or Mathematician, 
we cannot 

Note heie, that it is by no means intended to imply that 
there may not be different Kinds, or logical species, of man 
The vanous laces and temperaments, the two sexes, and even 
the various ages, may be differences of kind, within our mean¬ 
ing of the teim I do not say that they are so For m the 
pjogiess of physiology it may almost be said to be made out, 
that the diffeiences which really exist between diffeient laces, 
sexes, &c., follow as consequences, under laws of nature, 
from a small number of primary differences which can be pre¬ 
cisely deteimined, and which, as the phrase is, account for all 
the rest If this be so, these are not distinctions m kind , no 
more than Christian, Jew, Mussulman, and Pagan, a difference 
which also carries many consequences along with it And in 
this way classes are often mistaken for real Kinds, which are 
afterwards pioved not to be so. But if it turned out that the 
diffeiences were not capable of being thus accounted for, then 
Caucasian, Mongolian, Negro, &c. would be really different 
Kinds of human beings, and entitled to be ranked as species by 
the logician; though not by the naturalist For (as already 
noticed) the word species is used m a different signification m 
. logic and m natural history. By the naturalist, organized 
beings are not usually said to be of different species, if it is sup¬ 
posed that they could possibly have descended from the same 
stock. That, however, is a sense artificially given to the 
word, for the technical purposes of a particular science. To the 
logician, if a negro and a white man differ m the same manner 
(however less m degree) as a horse and a camel do, that is, i£ 
their differences are inexhaustible, and not refernble *to any 
common cause, they are different species, whether they are 
descended from common ancestors or not But if their dif¬ 
ferences can all be traced to climate and habits, or to some 



138 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


one or a few special differences in structure, they are not, m the 
logician’s view, specially distinct. 

When the tnflpia species, 01 proximate Kind, to which an 
individual belongs, has been ascertained, the properties com¬ 
mon to that Kmd include necessarily the whole of the common 
properties of eveiy other real Kind to which the individual can 
be referable Let the individual, for example, be Socrates, and 
the proximate Kind, man. Animal, or living creature, is also 
a real Kind, and includes Socrates; but, since it likewise 
includes man, or in other words, since all men are animals, the 
properties common to animals form a portion of the common 
properties of the sub-class, man And if there be any class 
which includes Socrates without including man, that class is 
not a real Kmd. Let the class for example, be flat-nosed , 
that being a class which includes Socrates, without including 
all men. To determine whether it is a leal Kind, we must ask 
ourselves this question: Have all flat-nosed animals, m addi¬ 
tion to whatever is implied m their flat noses, any common 
properties, other than those which are common to all animals 
whatever ? If they had if a flat nose were a mark or index 
to an indefinite number of other peculiarities, not deducible 
fiom the former by an ascertarnable law, then out of the 
class man we might cut another class, flat-nosed man, which 
according to our definition, would be a Kind But if we could 
do this, man would not he, as it was assumed to be, the 
proximate Kind Therefore, the propeities of the proximate 
Kind do comprehend those (whether known or unknown) of 
all other Kinds to which the individual belongs, which was 
the point we undertook to prove. And hence, every other 
Kind which is predicable of the individual, will he to the 
proximate Kind m the relation of a genus, according to even 
the popular acceptation of the terms genus and species , that 
is, it will be a larger class, including it and more 
^ We are now able to fix the logical meaning of these terms, 
j E very class which is a ieal Kmd, that is, which is distin¬ 
guished from all other classes by an indeterminate multitude 
of properties not derivable from one another, is either a genus 
01 a species. A Kind which is not divisible into other Kinds, 



CLASSIFICATION AND THE PREDICABLES. 139 

cannot be a genus, because it has no species under it, but it 
is itself a species, both with refeience to the individuals below 
and to the genera above (Species Pisedicabilis and Species 
Subjicibilis ) But every Kind which admits of division into 
real Kinds (as animal into mammal, bird, fish, &c., or bird 
into various species of birds) is a genus to all below 
it, a species to all genera in which it is itself included. 
And here we may close this part of the discussion, and pass 
to the three lemainmg predicables, Differentia, Propnum, and 
Accidens 

§ 5 To begin with Differentia. This word is correlative 
with the woids genus and species, and as all admit, it signifies 
the attribute which distinguishes a given species fiom every 
other species of the same genus This is so far clear: hut we 
may still ask, which of the distinguishing attributes it signi¬ 
fies. For we have seen that every Kind (and a species must 
be a Kind) is distinguished fiom other Kinds not by any one 
attnbute, but by an indefinite number. Man, for instance, is 
a species of the genus animal. Rational (or rationality, for it 
is of no consequence here whether we use the concrete or the 
abstract form) is geneially assigned by logicians as the Diffe¬ 
rentia ; and doubtless this attribute serves the purpose of 
distinction but it has also been remarked of man, that he 
is a cooking animal, the only animal that dresses its food. 
This, therefore, is another of the attributes by which the 
species man is distinguished from other species of the same 
genus would this attribute serve equally well for a diffe¬ 
rentia ? The Aristotelians say No, having laid it down that 
the differentia must, like the genus and species, be of the 
essence of the subject. 

And here we lose even that vestige of a meaning grounded 
m the nature of the things themselves, which may be sup¬ 
posed to be attached to the word essence when it is said that 
genus and species must be of the essence of the thing. There 
can be no doubt that when the schoolmen talked of the 
essences of things as opposed to their accidents, they had 
confusedly m view the distinction between differences of kind. 



140 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


and tlie differences which aie not of kind, they meant to inti¬ 
mate that genera and species must he Kinds Their notion 
of the essence of a thing was a vague notion of a something 
which makes it what it is, i . e. which makes it the Kind of 
thing that it is—which causes it to have all that variety of 
pioperties which distinguish its Kind But when the matter 
came to be looked at more closely, nobody could discover what 
caused the thing to have all those pioperties, nor even that 
theie was anything which caused it to have them. Logicians, 
howevei, not liking to admit this, and being unable to detect 
what made the thing to be what it was, satisfied themselves 
with what made it to be what it was called. Of the mnu- t 
meiabie properties, known and unknown, that are common to 
the class man, a portion only, and of couise a very small 
portion, aie connoted by its name, these few T , however, will 
naturally have been thus distinguished from the rest either for 
their greater obviousness, or foi greater supposed importance. 
These pioperties, then, which were connoted by the name, 
logicians seized upon, and called them the essence of the 
species, and not stopping there, they affirmed them, m the 
case of the infima species, to be the essence of the individual 
too, for it was their maxim, that the species contained the 
“ whole essence” of the thing. Metaphysics, that fertile field 
of delusion propagated by language, does not afford a more 
signal instance of such delusion On this account it was that 
rationality, being connoted by the name man, was allowed to 
be a differentia of the class, hut the peculiarity of cooking 
their food, not being connoted, was lelegated to the class of 
accidental properties. 

The distinction, therefore, between Differentia, Propnum, 
and Accidens, is not grounded m the nature of things, but m 
the connotation of names, and we must seek it. there, if we 
wish to find what it is 

Trom the fact that the genus includes the species, m other 
words denotes more than the species, or is predicable of a 
gieater number of individuals, it follows that the species must 
connote moie than the genus. It must connote all the attri¬ 
butes which the genus connotes, or theie would be nothing 



CLASSIFICATION AND THE PREDICABLES 141 

to prevent it from denoting individuals not included m the 
genus And it must connote something besides, otherwise it 
would include the whole genus. Animal denotes all the indi¬ 
viduals denoted by man, and many more Man, theiefore, 
must connote all that animal connotes, otherwise there might 
he men who are not animals, and it must connote something 
more than animal connotes, otherwise all animals would he 
men This surplus of connotation—this which the species 
connotes over and above the connotation of the genus—is the \ 
Differentia, or specific difference, or, to state the same propo- s 
sition m other words, the Differentia is that which must he 
added to the connotation of the genus, to complete the conno¬ 
tation of the species. 

The word man, for instance, exclusively of what it con¬ 
notes m common with animal, also connotes rationality, and 
at least some approximation to that external form which we 
all know, hut which as we have no name for it considered m 
itself, we are content to call the human The Differentia, or | 
specific difference, therefore, of man, as referred to the genus f 
animal, is that outward form and the possession of reason. ^ 
The Aristotelians said, the possession of reason, without the 
outward form But if they adhered to this, they would have 
been obliged to call the Houyhnhnms men. The question 
never arose, and they were never called upon to decide how 
such a case would have affected their notion of essentiality. 
However this may he, they were satisfied with taking such a 
portion of the differentia as sufficed to distinguish the species 
from all other existing things, though by so doing they might 
not exhaust the connotation of the name. 

§ 6 . And here, to prevent the notion of differentia from 
being restricted within too narrow limits, it is necessary to 
remark, that a species, even as leferred to the same genus, 
will not always have the same differentia, hut a different one, 
according to the principle and purpose which preside over the 
particular classification For example, a naturalist surveys 
the various kinds of animals, and looks out for the classifica¬ 
tion of them most m accordance with the order in which, for 



Hi 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


zoological purposes, he considers it desirable that we should 
think of them With this view he finds it advisable that 
one of his fundamental divisions should be into waim-blooded 
and cold-blooded animals, or into animals which breathe 
with lungs and those which breathe with gills, or into car¬ 
nival ous, and frugivoious 01 giamimvorons, or into those 
which walk on the fiat part and those which walk on the 
extremity of the foot, a distinction on which two of Cuvier’s 
families are founded In doing this, the naturalist creates as 
many new classes , which are by no means those to which the 
individual animal is familiarly and spontaneously leferred , 
nor should we ever think of assigning to them so prominent 
a position m our arrangement of the animal kingdom, unless 
for a preconceived puipose of scientific convenience. And to 
the libeity of doing this there is no limit In the examples 
we have given, most of the classes aie real Kinds, since each 
of the peculiarities is an index to a multitude of propeities 
belonging to the class which it chaiactenzes . but even if the 
case were otherwise—if the other properties of those classes 
could all be denved, by any piocess known to us, from the 
one peculiarity on which the class is founded—even then, if 
these derivative properties were of primary importance for the 
purposes of the naturalist, he would be wan anted m founding 
his pnmaiy divisions on them. 

If, however, practical convenience is a sufficient wairant 
for making the mam demaications m oui arrangement of 
objects run m lines not coinciding with any distinction of 
Kmd, and so creating geneia and species m the popular 
sense which are not genera or species m the ngoious sense 
at all, a fortiori must we be wairanted, when our geneia 
and species are real geneia and species, m marking the dis¬ 
tinction between them by those of their properties which con- 
sideiations of practical convenience most strongly recommend 
If we cut a species out of a given genus—the species man, 
for instance, out of the genus animal—with an intention 
on our pait that the peculiarity by which we are to be 
guided m the application of the name man should be 
nationality, then rationality is the diffeientia of the species 



CLASSIFICATION AND THE PREDICABLES. 143 

man. Suppose, however, that being naturalists, we, for the 
puiposes of our particular study, cut out of the genus animal 
the same species man, but with an intention that the dis¬ 
tinction between man and all other species of animal should 
be, not rationality, but the possession of “ four incisors m 
each jaw, tusks solitary, and erect posture.” It is evident 
that the woid man, when used by us as naturalists, no longer 
connotes rationality, but connotes the three other properties 
specified , for that which we have expressly m view when 
we impose a name, assuredly forms part of the meaning of 
that name. We may, tliei efore, lay it down as a maxim, 
that wherever there is a Genus, and a Species marked out 
from that genus by an assignable differentia, the name of 
the species must be connotative, and must connote the diffe¬ 
rentia, but the connotation may be special—not involved m 
the signification of the term as ordinarily used, but given to 
it when employed as a term of art or science The word Man 
m common use, connotes rationality and a ceitam form, but 
does not connote the number or character of the teeth, m the 
Linnsean system it connotes the number of mcisoi and canine 
teeth, but does not connote rationality nor any particular 
form. The word man has, therefore, two different meanings , 
though not commonly considered as ambiguous, because it 
happens m both cases to denote the same individual objects 
But a case is conceivable m which the ambiguity would 
become evident we have only to imagine that some new 
kind of animal were discovered, having Linnaeus’s three cha¬ 
racteristics of humanity, but not rational, or not of the human 
form. In ordinary pailance, these animals would not be 
called men, but m natural history they must still be called 
so by those, if any there be, who adheie to the Lmnaean 
classification, and the question would arise, whether the word 
should continue to be used m two senses, or the classification 
be given up, and the technical sense of the term be abandoned 
along with it 

Words not otherwise connotative may, m the mode just 
adverted to, acquire a special or technical connotation. Thus 
the word whiteness, as we have so often remarked, connotes 



1U 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


nothing; it merely denotes the attribute corresponding to a 
certain sensation but if we are making a classification of 
colours, and desne to justify, 01 even meiely to point out, the 
particular place assigned to whiteness m oui arrangement we 
may define it “the colour produced by the mixtuie of all the 
simple rays /’ and this fact, though by no means implied m 
the meaning of the word whiteness as ordinarily used, but 
only known by subsequent scientific investigation, is part of 
its meaning m the paiticular essay or treatise, and becomes 
the differentia of the species * 

The diffeientia, theiefoie, of a species may be defined 
to be, that part of the connotation of the specific name, 
whether oidmaiy or special and technical, which distm-i 
guishes the species m question torn all other species of the' 
genus to which on the particular occasion we aie refer¬ 
ring it. 


§ 7 . Having disposed of Genus, Species, and Differentia, 
ve shall not find much difficulty m attaining a clear con¬ 
ception of the distinction between the other two predicables, 
as well as between them and the first three 

In the Anstotelian phraseology. Genus and Differentia 
are of the essence of the subject, by which, as we have seen, 
is really meant that the properties signified by the genus 
and those signified by the diffeientia, form part of the con¬ 
notation of the name denoting the species. Propnum and 
Accidens, on the other hand, foim no part of the essence, but 
are predicated of the species only accidentally . Both are 
Accidents, m the wider sense m which the accidents of a 
thing are opposed to its essence, though, m the doctrine of 
the Predicables, Accidens is used for one sort of accident 
only, Propnum being another sort. Pioprmm, continue the 
schoolmen, is predicated accidentally, indeed, but necessai ily, 


* If we allow a differentia to what is not really a species Eor the distinc¬ 
tion of Kinds, m the sense explained by us, not being m any way applicable to 
attributes, it of course follows that although attributes may be put into classes, 
those classes can be admitted to he genera or species only by courtesy. 



CLASSIFICATION AND THE PREDICABLES. 145 

or, as they furthei explain it, signifies an attribute which is 
not indeed part of the essence, but which flows from, or is a 
consequence of, the essence, and is, theiefoie, inseparably 
attached to the species, e g. the vanous properties of a 
tiiangle, which, though no part of its definition, must neces¬ 
sarily be possessed by whatevei comes under that definition. 
Accidens, on the conti aiy, has no connexion whatever with 
the essence, but may come and go, and the species still re¬ 
main what it was befoie If a species could exist without its 
Propna, it must be capable of existing without that on which 
its Propna are necessanly consequent, and therefore without 
its essence, without that which constitutes it a species. 
But an Accidens, whether sepaiable or inseparable fiom the 
species m actual experience, may be supposed separated, 
without the necessity of supposing any other alteration , or 
at least, without supposing any of the essential propeities oi 
the species to be alteied, since with them an Accidens has no 
connexion 

A Propnum, therefore, of the species, may be defined, any 
attribute which belongs to all the individuals included m the 
species, and which, though not connoted by the specific 
name, (either ordinarily if the classification we aie considering 
be for ordinaly purposes, or specially if it be for a special pur¬ 
pose,) yet follows fiom some attubute which the name either 
ordinarily or specially connotes. 

One attribute may follow from another m two ways, and 
theie are consequently two kinds of Propnum. It may 
follow as a conclusion follows premises, or it may follow as 
an effect follows a cause. Thus, the attribute of having the 
opposite sides equal, which is not one of those connoted by 
the word Parallelogram, nevertheless follows from those con¬ 
noted by it, namely, from having the opposite sides straight 
lines and parallel, and the number of sides four. The attri¬ 
bute, therefore, of having the opposite sides equal, is a Pro- 
prmm of the class parallelogram; and a Propnum of the 
first kind, which follows from the connoted attributes by way 
of demonstration. The attribute of being capable of under¬ 
standing language, is a Propnum of the species man, since 
VOL. i. 10 



146 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


without being connoted by the wold, it follows from an attri¬ 
bute which the woid does connote, viz fiom the attribute 
of rationality. But this is a Pioprmm of the second kind, 
which follows by way of causation How it is that one pro¬ 
perty of a thing follows, or can be inferred, from another, 
under what conditions this is possible, and what is the exact 
meaning of the phiase, are among the questions which will 
occupy us m the two succeeding Books At piesent it needs 
only be said, that whethei a Propnum follows by demonstra¬ 
tion or by causation, it follows neccssanly , that is to say, its 
not following would be inconsistent with some law wdnch we 
regard as a part of the constitution either of our thinking 
faculty or of the univeise 

§ 8 . Under the remaining predicable, Accidens, are in¬ 
cluded all attributes of a thing which are neither involved m 
the signification of the name (whether oidmanly or as a term 
of ait), noi have, so far as we know r , any necessary connexion 
with attributes which are so involved They aie commonly 
divided into Separable and Inseparable Accidents Inseparable 
accidents ai e those which—although w T e know of no connexion 
between them and the attnbutes constitutive of the species, 
and although, theiefore, so far as we are aware, they might be 
absent without making the name inapplicable and the species 
a different species—are yet never m fact known to he absent 
A concise mode of expressing the same meaning is, that in¬ 
separable accidents are properties which are universal to the 
species, hut not necessary to it Thus, blackness is an attri¬ 
bute of a crow, and, as far as we know, an universal one But 
if we were to discover a race of white birds, m other respects 
resembling ciows, we should not say, These are not crows, we 
should say, These are white ciows Crow, therefore, does not 
connote blackness, nor, flora any of the attributes which it 
does connote, whether as a word m popular use or as a term 
of art, could blackness he mfened Not only, therefore, can 
we conceive a white crow, hut we know of no reason why such 
an animal should not exist Since, however, none but black 
crows are known to exist, blackness, m the present state of our 



CLASSIFICATION AND THE PREDICABLES. 147 

knowledge, ranks as an accident, but an inseparable accident 
of the species crow. 

Sepai able Accidents are those which are found, m point of 
fact, to he sometimes absent from the species, which are not 
only not necessary, but not even universal They are such as 
do not belong to every individual of the species, but only to 
some individuals, or if to all, not at all times. Thus the 
colour of an European is one of the separable accidents of 
the species man, because it is not an attiibute of all human 
creatuies Being bom, is also (speaking m the logical sense) 
a separable accident of the species man, because, though an 
attribute of all human beings, it is so only at one paiticulai 
time A foition those attributes which are not constant even 
m the same individual, as, to be m one or m another place, to 
be hot or cold, sitting or walking, must be ranked as sepai able 
accidents 


10 -2 



CHAPTEE VIII. 


OF DEFINITION. 

§ 1. One necessary pait of the theory of Names and of 
Piopositions remains to be treated of in this place * the theory 
of Definitions As being the most important of the class of 
propositions which we have characterized as purely verbal, 
they have alieady received some notice m the chapter pre¬ 
ceding the last But their fuller treatment was at that time 
postponed, because definition is so closely connected with clas¬ 
sification, that, until the nature of the latter process is m some 
measure understood, the former cannot be discussed to much 
purpose. 

The simplest and most collect notion of a Definition is, a 
proposition declaiatorv of the meamng of a word, namely, 
either the meaning which it bears m common acceptation, or 
that which the speaker or writer, for the particulai purposes of 
his discourse, intends to annex to it 

The definition of a word being the proposition which 
enunciates its meaning, woids which have no meaning are 
unsusceptible of definition Proper names, therefore, cannot 
he defined. A proper name being a mere mark put upon an 
individual, and of which it is the characteristic property to be 
destitute of meamng, its meaning cannot of course be de¬ 
clared , though we may indicate by language, as we might 
indicate still more conveniently by pointing with the finger, 
upon what individual that particular maik has been, or is 
intended to be, put It is no definition of “ John Thomson ” 
to say he is “ the son of General Thomson,” for the name 
John Thomson does not express this Neither is it any 
definition of “ John Thomson ” to say he is “the man now 
crossing the street ” These propositions may serve to make 
known who is the particular man to whom the name belongs, 
but that may be done still more unambiguously by pointing to 



DEFINITION. 


149 


him, which, however, has not been esteemed one of the modes 
of definition. 

In the case of connotative names, the meaning, as has been 
so often obseived, is the connotation, and the definition of a 
connotative name, is the proposition which declaies its conno¬ 
tation. This might be done either directly or indirectly. The 
direct mode would be by a proposition m this form . “Man ” 
(or whatsoever the woid may be) “is a name connoting such 
and such attributes/’ or “ is a name which, when predicated of 
anything, signifies the possession of such and such attributes 
bv that thing ” Or thus . Man is everything which possesses 
such and such attnbutes Man is everything which possesses 
corporeity, organization, life, rationality, and certain pecu¬ 
liarities of external form. 

This torm of definition is the most pi ecise and least equi¬ 
vocal of any, but it is not brief enough, and is besides too 
technical for common discourse. The more usual mode of 
declaring the connotation of a name, is to predicate of it 
another name or names of known signification, which connote 
the same aggregation of attributes This may be done either 
bv predicating of the name intended to be defined, another 
connotative name exactly synonymous, as, “ Man is a human 
being,” which is not commonly accounted a definition at all, 
or by predicating two or more connotative names, which make 
up among them the whole connotation of the name to be 
defined. In this last case, again, we may either compose 
oui definition of as many connotative names as there are 
attributes, each attribute being connoted by one, as, Man is 
a corpoieal, organized, am mated, rational being, shaped so 
and so, or we may employ names which connote several of 
the attnbutes at once, as, Man is a rational animal, shaped 
so and so. 

The definition of a name, according to this view of it, is 
the sum total of all the essential propositions which can be 
framed with that name for their subject All propositions 
the truth of which is implied m the name, all those which we 
are made aware of by merely hearing the name, are included 
in the definition, if complete, and may be evolved from it 



150 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


without the aid of any othei premises ; whether the definition 
expresses them m two or thiee words, or m a larger number. 
It is, therefoie, not without reason that Condillac and other 
wnteis have affirmed a definition to he an analysis To lesolve 
any complex whole into the elements of which it is com¬ 
pounded, is the meaning of analysis : and this we do when we 
leplace one woid which connotes a set of attnbutes collectively, 
by two or moie which connote the same attributes singly, or 
m smaller gioups 

§ 2 . From this, however, the question naturally arises, m 
what manner are we to define a name which connotes only a 
single attnbute for instance, “white,” which connotes nothing 
but whiteness; “ rational,” which connotes nothing but the 
possession of reason. It might seem that the meaning of 
such names could only be declared m two ways , by a synony¬ 
mous term, if any such can be found, or m the direct way 
alieady alluded to . £C White is a name connoting the attnbute 
whiteness ” Let us see, however, whether the analysis of the 
meaning of the name, that is, the breaking down of that 
meaning into several parts, admits of being carried faither. 
Without at present deciding this question as to the word ivhite, 
it is obvious that m the case of rational some further explana¬ 
tion may be given of its meaning than is contained m the pro¬ 
position, “ Rational is that which possesses the attribute of 
leason,” since the attnbute reason itself admits of being de¬ 
fined. And heie we must turn our attention to the definitions 
of attributes, or lather of the names .of attnbutes, that is, of 
ab&ti act names. 

In regard to such names of attributes as are connotative, 
and express attributes of those attnbutes, theie is no diffi¬ 
culty like other connotative names they are defined by 
declaring their connotation Thus, the word fault may be 
defined, <e a quality productive of evil or inconvenience.” 
Sometimes, again, the attribute to be defined is not one 
attnbute, but an union of several: we have only, therefore, 
to put together the names of all the attributes taken sepa¬ 
rately, and we obtain the definition of the name which belongs 



DEFINITION. 


151 


to them all taken together; a definition which will correspond 
exactly to that of the corresponding concrete name. For, as 
we define a concrete name by enumerating the attributes which 
it connotes, and as the attributes connoted by a concrete name 
form the entire signification of the corresponding abstract name, 
the same enumeration will serve for the definition of both. 
Thus, if the definition of a human being be this, “ a being, 
corporeal, animated, i ational, shaped so and so/' the definition 
of humanity will be corporeity and animal life, combined 
with rationality, and with such and such a shape. 

When, on the othei hand, the abstiact name does not 
express a complication of attributes, but a single attribute, we 
must remember that every attribute is grounded on some fact 
or phenomenon, from which, and which alone, it derives its 
meaning To that fact or phenomenon, called m a former 
chapter the foundation of the attnbute, we must, therefore, 
have recourse for its definition Now, the foundation of the 
attribute may be a phenomenon of any degree of complexity, 
consisting of many different parts, either coexistent or in suc¬ 
cession To obtain a definition of the attribute, we must 
analyse the phenomenon into these parts Eloquence, for 
example, is the name of one attnbute only, but this attribute 
is grounded on external effects of a complicated nature, flowing 
from acts of the peison to whom we ascribed the attribute , and 
by resolving this phenomenon of causation into its two paits, 
the cause and the effect, we obtain a definition of eloquence, 
viz the powei of influencing the feelings by speech or wiitmg. 

A name, therefore, whether concrete or abstiact, admits of 
definition, provided w T e aie able to analyse, that is, to distinguish 
into parts, the attribute or set of attributes which constitute 
the meaning both of the concrete name and of the corresponding 
abstract * if a set of attributes, by enumerating them, if a 
single attribute, by dissecting the fact or phenomenon (whether 
of perception or of internal consciousness) which is the foun¬ 
dation of the attribute But, further, even when the fact is, 
one of our simple feelings or states of consciousness, and 
therefore unsusceptible of analysis, the names both of the 
object and of the attribute still admit of definition: or rather, 



152 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


would do so if all our simple feelings had names Whiteness 
may be defined, the property or power of exciting the sensa¬ 
tion of white A white object maybe defined, an object which 
excites the sensation of white The only names which aie un¬ 
susceptible of definition, because their meaning is unsusceptible 
of analysis, aie the names of the simple feelings themselves 
These are m the same condition as proper names. They are not 
indeed, like proper names, unmeaning , foi the words sensation 
of white signify, that the sensation which I so denominate re¬ 
sembles other sensations which I remember to have had before, 
and to have called by that name But as we have no woids 
by which to re cal those former sensations, except the very 
word which we seek to define, or some other which, being 
exactly synonymous with it, requires definition as much, words 
cannot unfold the signification of this class of names, and w T e 
aie obliged to make a direct appeal to the personal expenence 
of the individual whom we address 

§ % Having stated what seems to be the true idea of a 
Definition, we proceed to examine some opinions of philo¬ 
sophers, and some popular conceptions on the subject, which 
conflict more or less with that idea 

The only adequate definition of a name is, as already 
remaiked, one which declares the facts, and the whole of the 
facts, which the name involves m its signification. But with 
most persons the object of a definition' does not embrace so 
much; they look for nothing more, in a definition, than a 
guide to the correct use of the term—a protection against 
applying it m a manner inconsistent with custom and con¬ 
vention Anything, therefore, is to them a sufficient definition 
of a term, which will serve as a correct index to what the term 
denotes, though not embracing the whole, and sometimes, 
perhaps, not even any part, of what it connotes This gives 
nse to two sorts of imperfect, or unscientific definition, 
Essential but incomplete Definitions, and Accidental Defi¬ 
nitions, or Descriptions. In the former, a connotative name 
is defined by a part only of its connotation ; m the latter, by 
something which forms no part of the connotation at all. 



DEFINITION. 


153 


An example of the first kind of impeifect definitions is the 
following —Man is a lational animal It is impossible to 
consider this as a complete definition of the word Man, since 
(as befoie remarked) if we adhered to it we should be obliged 
to call the Houvhnhnms men, but as there happen to be no 
Houyhnhnms, this imperfect definition is sufficient to maik 
out and distinguish from all other things, the objects at piesent 
denoted by “ man all the beings actually known to exist, of 
whom the name is predicable. Though the word is defined by 
some only among the attributes which it connotes, not by all, 
it happens that all known objects which possess the enume¬ 
rated attributes, possess also those which aie omitted , so that 
the field of piedication which the word cowers, and the employ¬ 
ment of it which is conformable to usage, aie as well indicated 
by the inadequate definition as by an adequate one Such 
definitions, however, aie always liable to be overthrown by the 
discovery of new objects m nature. 

Definitions of this kind are what logicians have had in 
view, when they laid down the mle, that the definition of a 
species should be per genus et diffei entiam Differentia being 
seldom taken to mean the whole of the peculiarities constitu¬ 
tive of the species, but some one of those peculiarities only, 
a complete definition would be per genus et differentiae, rather 
than differentiam It would include, with the name of the 
superior genus, not merely some attribute which distinguishes 
the species intended to be defined from all other species of the 
same genus, but all the attributes implied m the name of the 
species, which the name of the superior genus has not already 
implied. The assertion, however, that a definition must of 
necessity consist of a genus and differentiae, is not tenable. It 
was early remarked by logicians, that the summum genus in 
any classification, having no genus superior to itself, could not 
b§ defined m this manner. Yet we have seen that all names, 
except those of our elementary feelings, are susceptible of 
definition m the strictest sense , by setting forth m words the 
constituent parts of the fact or phenomenon, of which the 
connotation of every word is ultimately composed. 



154 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


§ 4 . Although the first hind of imperfect definition, 
(which defines a connotative term by a pait only of what it 
connotes, hut a part sufficient to mark out coirectly the 
boundanes of its denotation,) has been considered by the 
ancients, and by logicians m geneial, as a complete defi¬ 
nition , it has always been deemed necessary that the, attu- 
butes employed should really foim pait of the connotation, for 
the rule was that the definition must be drawn fzom the essence 
of the class, and this would not have been the case if it had 
been in any degiee made up of attributes not connoted by the 
name. The second kind of imperfect definition, theiefoie, m 
which the name of a class is defined by any of its accidents,— 
that is, by attnbutes which are not included m its connota¬ 
tion,—has been rejected from the rank of genuine Definition 
by all logicians, and has been termed Description 

This kind of imperfect definition, howevei, takes its rise 
from the same cause as the other, namely, the willingness 
to accept as a definition anything which, vhethei it expounds 
the meaning of the name or not, enables us to disciimmate the 
things denoted by the name fiom all other things, and conse¬ 
quently to employ the term m predication without deviating 
from established usage. This purpose is duly answeied by 
stating any (no matter what) of the attributes which aie 
common to the whole of the class, and peculiar to it, or any 
combination of attnbutes which happens to be peculiar to it, 
though separately each of those attnbutes may be common to 
it with some other things. It is only necessary that the defi¬ 
nition (or description) thus formed, should be convertible with 
the name which it professes to define, that is, should he 
exactly co-extensive with it, being predicable of everything of 
which it is predicable, and of nothing of which it is not pre¬ 
dicable, though the attributes specified may have no con¬ 
nexion with those which mankind had in view when they 
formed 01 lecogmsed the class, and gave it a name The fol¬ 
lowing are correct definitions of Man, according to this test 
Man is a mammiferous animal, having (by nature) two hands 
(for the human species answers to this description, and no 



DEFINITION. 


155 


othei animal does) Man is an animal who cooks his food. 
Man is a featherless biped- 

What would" otherwise he a mere description, may be 
laised to the lank of a leal definition by the peculiar puipose 
which the speaker or wnter has in view As was seen m the 
piecedmg chapter, it may, for the ends of a particular art or 
science, or for the more convenient statement of an author’s 
paiticular doctunes, be advisable to give to some general name, 
without altering its denotation, a special connotation, different 
from its ordmaiy one. When this is done, a definition of the 
name by means of the attnbutes which make up the special 
connotation, though m general a mere accidental definition or 
descnption, becomes on the particular occasion and for the 
particular purpose a complete and genuine definition. This 
actually occuis with respect to one of the preceding examples, 
“Man is a mammiferous animal having two hands/" which is 
the scientific definition of man, considered as one of the species 
m Cuvier s distribution of the animal kingdom. 

In cases of this sort, though the definition is still a decla¬ 
ration of the meaning which m the particular instance the 
name is appointed to convey, it cannot be said that to state 
the meaning of the wor d is the purpose of the definition. The 
purpose is n^ to expoundTa name/Tiut a _ cSssiffcation. The 
special meaning which Cuvier assigned to the word Man, 
(quite foreign to its oidinary meaning, though involving 
no change m the denotation of the word,) was incidental to a 
plan of arranging animals into classes on a ceitam principle, 
that is, according to a ceitam set of distinctions And since 
the definition of Man according to the ordinary connotation of 
the word, though it would have answered every other purpose 
of a definition, would not have pointed out the place which the 
species ought to occupy m that particular classification, he 
gave the word a special connotation, that he might be able to 
define it by the kind of attnbutes on which, for reasons of 
scientific convenience, he had resolved to found his division of 
animated nature. 

Scientific definitions, whether they are definitions of scien¬ 
tific terms, or of common terms used in a scientific sense, are 



156 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS 


almost always of the kind last spoken of their roam purpose 
is to serve as the landmaiks of scientific classification And 
since the classifications m any science aie continually modified 
as scientific knowledge advances, the definitions m the sciences 
are also constantly varying. A striking instance is afforded 
by the woids Acid and Alkali, especially the former As 
experimental discovery advanced, the substances classed with 
acids have been constantly multiplying, and by a natural con¬ 
sequence the attributes connoted by the word have receded and 
become fewei. At first it connoted the attributes, of combin¬ 
ing with an alkali to form a neutral substance (called a salt), 
being compounded of a base and oxygen , causticity to the 
taste and touch, fluidity, &c The true analysis of muriatic 
acid, into chlorine and hydrogen, caused the second property, 
composition from a base and oxygen, to be excluded from 
the connotation. The same discovery fixed the attention of 
chemists upon hydrogen as an important element m acids , 
and more lecent discovenes having led to the recognition 
of its presence m sulphuric, nitric, and many other acids, 
where rts existence was not previously suspected, theie is now 
a tendency to include the presence of this element m the con¬ 
notation of the woid But carbonic acid, silica, sulphurous 
acid, have no hydrogen m their composition, that property 
cannot therefore be connoted by the term, unless those sub¬ 
stances are no longer to be considered acids. Causticity and 
fluidity have long since been excluded from the characteristics 
of the class, by the inclusion of silica and many other sub¬ 
stances m it, and the formation of neutral bodies by com¬ 
bination with alkalis, together with such electro-chemical 
peculiarities as this is supposed to imply, are now the only 
differ entice which form the fixed connotation of the word Acid, 
as a term of chemical science. 

What is true of the definition of any teim of science, is of 
course true of the definition of a science itself. and accord¬ 
ingly, (as observed m the Introductory Chapter of this work,) 
the definition of a science must necessarily be progressive and 
provisional. Any extension of knowledge or alteration m the 
current opinions respecting the subject matter, may lead to a 



DEFINITION. 


change more or less extensive m the particulars mcludei 
the science, and its composition being thus altered, it 
easily happen that a diffeient set of characteristics wil 
found better adapted as differentiae for defining its name 
In the same manner m which a special or technical de 
tion has foi its object to expound the artificial classifies 
out of which it grows, the Aristotelian logicians seen 
have imagined that it was also the business of ordinary de 
tion to expound the ordinary, and what they deemed 
natural, classification of things, namely, the division of t 
into Kinds; and to show the place which each Kind occu] 
as superior, collateral, or subordinate, among other Ki 
This notion would account for the rule that all defim 
must necessaniy be per genus et differential^ and would 
explain why a single differentia was deemed sufficient, 
to expound, or expiess m words, a distinction of Kind, 
already been shown to be an impossibility * the very mea, 
of a Kind is, that the propeities which distinguish it do 
grow out of one another, and cannot therefore be set fort 
words, even by implication, otherwise than by enumera 
them all * and all aie not known, noi are ever likely to b( 
It is idle, therefore, to look to this as one of the purposes 
definition : while, if it be only required that the definition 
Kind should indicate what Kinds include it or are mcludei 
it, any definitions which expound the connotation of the m 
will do this. for the name of each class must necessarily 
note enough of its properties to fix the boundaries of the c 
If the definition, therefore, be a full statement of the conn 
tion, it is all that a definition can be required to be. 

§ 5 . Of the two incomplete and popular modes of de 
tion, and m what they differ from the complete or phi] 
phical mode, enough has now been said. We shall next exai 
an ancient doctrine, once generally prevalent and still b 
means exploded, which I regard as the source of a great 
of the obscurity hanging over some of the most linpoi 
processes of the understanding in the pursuit of ti 
According to this, the definitions of which we have 



158 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


treated are only one of two sorts into winch definitions may 
he divided, \iz definitions of names, and definitions of things 
The former aie intended to explain the meaning of a term, 
the latter, the nature of a thing ; the last being mcompaiably 
the most important 

This opinion was held by the ancient philosophers, and by 
their followeis, with the exception of the Nominalists, but as 
the spnit of modern metaphysics, until a recent penod, has 
been on the whole a Nominalist spirit, the notion of defini¬ 
tions of things has been to a certain extent m abeyance, still 
continuing, however, to breed confusion m logic, by its conse¬ 
quences indeed rather than by itself Yet the doctime m its 
own pioper form now and then bleaks out, and has appeared 
(among other places) wheie it was scaicely to be expected, m 
a justly admired work, Archbishop Whately's Logic * In a 
review of that work published by me m the Westminster 


* In the fuller discussion which Archbishop Whately has given to this 
subject m his later editions, he almost ceases to regard the definitions of names 
and those of things as, m any important sense, distinct. He seems (9th ed 
p 145) to limit the notion of a Real Definition to one which explains any¬ 
thing moi e of the nature of the thing than is implied m the name(including 
under the word “ implied,” not only what the name connotes, bnt everything 
which can be deduced by reasoning from the attributes connoted) Even this, 
as he adds, is usually called, not a Definition, but a Description , and (as it 
seems to me) rightly so called. A Desenption, I conceive, can only be ranked 
among Definitions, when taken (as m the case of the zoological definition of 
man) to fulfil the true office of a Definition, by declaring the connotation given 
to a word m some special use, as a term of science or art which special conno¬ 
tation of course would not be expressed by the proper definition of the word m 
its ordinary employment 

Mr De Morgan, exactly reversing the doctrine of Archbishop Whately, un¬ 
derstands by a Real Definition one which contains less than the Nominal Defi¬ 
nition, provided only that what it contains is sufficient for distinction “ By 
real definition I mean such an explanation of the word, be it the whole of the 
meaning or only part, as will be sufficient to separate the things contained 
under that word from all others Thus the following, I believe, is a complete 
•definition of an elephant An animal which natuially drinks by drawing the 
water into its nose, and then spurting it into its mouth ”—Formal Logic , p. 36 
Mr. De Morgan’s general proposition and his example are at variance , for the 
peculiar mode of drinking of the elephant certainly forms no part of the mean¬ 
ing of the word elephant It could not be said, because a person happened to 
be ignorant of this property, that he did not know what an elephant means 



DEFINITION. 


159 


Renew for Januaiy 1828 , and containing some opinions winch 
I no longei entertain, I find the following observations on the 
question now before us, observations with which my present 
view of that question is still sufficiently m accordance 

“The distinction between nominal and real definitions, 
between definitions of word a and what are called definitions 
of things, though confoimable to the ideas of most of the 
Aristotelian logicians, cannot, as it appears to us, he main¬ 
tained We apprehend that no definition is ever intended to 
‘ explain and unfold the nature of a thing ’ It is some confii- 
mation of our opinion, that none of those wnteis who have 
thought that there were definitions of things, have ever suc¬ 
ceeded m discovenng any cuteiion by which the definition of 
a thing can be distinguished from any other proposition 
relating to the thing The definition, they say, unfolds the 
nature of the thing but no definition can unfold its whole 
nature, and eveiy proposrtion m which any quality whatever 
is predicated of the thing, unfolds some part of its natuie. 
The true state of the case we take to be this All definitions 
are of names, and of names only , but, m some definitions, it 
is cleaily apparent, that nothing is intended except to explain 
the meaning of the word, while m others, besides explaining 
the meaning of the word, it is intended to be implied that 
there exists a thing, corresponding to the word. Whether 
this be or be not implied in any given case, cannot be collected 
from the mere form of the expression. ‘A centaur is an 
animal with the upper parts of a man and the lower parts of a 
horse,’ and e A tnangle is a rectilineal figure with three sides, 
are, m form, expressions precisely similar; although m the 
former it is not implied that any thing , conformable to the 
term, really exists, while m the latter it is; as may be seen b} 
substituting, m both definitions, the word means for is. In 
the first expression, f A centaur means an animal/ &c., the 
sense would remain unchanged : m the second, ( A triangle 
means/ &c , the meaning would be altered, since it would be 
obviously impossible to deduce any of the truths of geometry 
from a proposition expressive only of the manner in which we 
intend to employ a particular sign. 



160 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


te There are,, therefore, expressions, commonly passing for 
definitions, which include in themselves moie than the mere 
explanation of the meaning of a term. But it is not correct 
to call an expression of this soit a peculiar kind of definition 
Its difference from the other kind consists m this, that it is 
not a definition, but a definition and something moie The 
definition above given of a triangle, obviously comprises not 
one, but two propositions, perfectly distinguishable. The one 
is, e There may exist a figure, bounded by three stiaight lines , 
the other, ‘ And this figure may be termed a triangle/ The 
former of these propositions is not a definition at all. the 
latter is a mere nominal definition, or explanation of the use 
and application of a term. The fiist is susceptible of truth 01 
falsehood, and may therefore be made the foundation of a 
tiam of reasoning. The latter can neither be true nor false ; 
the only character it is susceptible of is that of conformity or 
disconformitv to the ordinary usage of language.” 

There is a real distinction, then, between definitions of 
names, and what are erroneously called definitions of things , 
but it is, that the latter, along with the meaning of a name, 
covertly asserts a matter of fact. This covert asseition is not 
a definition, hut a postulate. The definition is a mere iden¬ 
tical proposition, which gives information only about the use 
of language, and from which no conclusions affecting matteis 
of fact can possibly be drawn. The accompanying postulate, 
on the other hand, affirms a fact, which may lead to conse¬ 
quences of every degree of importance. It affirms the actual 
or possible existence of Things possessing the combination of 
attributes set forth m the definition, and this, if true, may be 
foundation sufficient on which to build a whole fabric of 
scientific truth. 

We have already made, and shall often have to repeat, the 
remark, that the philosophers who overthrew Realism by no 
means got rid of the consequences of Realism, but retained 
long afterwards, in their own philosophy, numerous proposi¬ 
tions which could only have a rational meaning as part of a 
Realistic system. It had been handed down from Aristotle, 
and probably from earlier times, as an obvious truth, that the 



DEFINITION. 161 

science of Geometiy is deduced from definitions This, so 
long as a definition was considered to be a proposition “ un¬ 
folding the nature of the thing,” did well enough. But 
Hobbes followed, and 1 ejected utterly the notion that a defi¬ 
nition declares the natuie of the thing, or does anything but 
state the meaning of a name, yet he continued to affirm as 
broadly as any of his predecessors, that the ap^at, prmcipia, 
or original premises of mathematics, and even of all science, 
are definitions, producing the singular paradox, that systems 
of scientific truth, nay, all truths whatever at which we ainve 
by reasoning, are deduced from the arbitrary conventions of 
mankind concerning the signification of words 

To save the credit of the doctrine that definitions are the 
premises of scientific knowledge, the proviso is sometimes 
added, that they are so only under a certain condition, namely, 
that they be framed conformably to the phenomena of nature, 
that is, that they ascribe such meanings to terms as shall suit 
objects actually existing. But this is only an instance of the 
attempt so often made, to escape from the necessity of aban¬ 
doning old language after the ideas which it expresses have 
been exchanged for contrary ones. From the meaning of a 
name (we are told) it is possible to infer physical facts, pro¬ 
vided the name has corresponding to it an existing thing 
But if this proviso be necessary, from which of the two is 
the inference really drawn ? From the existence of a thing 
having the properties, or from the existence of a name meaning 
them 9 

Take, for instance, any of the definitions laid down as 
premises m Euclid’s Elements , the definition, let us say, of a 
drcle This, being analysed, consists of two propositions, 
the one an assumption with respect to a matter of fact, the 
other a genuine definition “A figure may exist, having all 
the points m the line which bounds it equally distant from a 
single point within it“Any figure possessing this property 
is called a circle Let us look at one of the demonstrations 
which are said to depend on this definition, and observe to 
which of the two propositions contained in it the demonstra¬ 
tion really appeals. “ About the centre A, describe the circle 
vol. i. 11 



162 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


B C D” Here is an assumption that a figure, such as the 
definition expresses, may be described, which is no othei than 
the postulate, or covert assumption, involved m the so-called 
definition. But whether that figure be called a circle or not 
is quite immaterial. The purpose would be as well answered, 
m all lespects except brevity, were we to say, “ Through the 
point B, draw a line returning into itself, of which every point 
shall he at an equal distance from the point A ” By this the 
definition of a circle would be got nd of, and rendered need* 
less; but not the postulate implied m it, without that the 
demonstration could not stand. The circle being now described, 
let us proceed to the consequence. “ Since B C D is a circle, 
the radius B A is equal to the radius G A.” B A is equal to 
0 A, not because B CDis a circle, but because B C D is a 
figure with the radii equal. Our warrant for assuming that 
such a figure about the centre A, with the ladius B A, may be 
made to exist, is the postulate Whether the admissibility of 
these postulates lests on intuition, or on proof, may be a 
matter of dispute , but in either case they are the piemises on 
which the theorems depend, and while these aie letamed it 
would make no difference m the certainty of geometrical 
truths, though every definition m Euclid, and every technical 
term therein defined, were laid aside. 

It is, perhaps, superfluous to dwell at so much length on 
what is so nearly self-evident; hut when a distinction, obvious 
as it may appear, has been confounded, and by powerful intel¬ 
lects, it is better to say too much than too little for the pur¬ 
pose of rendering such mistakes impossible m future. I will, 
therefore, detain the leader while I point out one of the absurd 
consequences flowing from the supposition that definitions, as 
such, are the premises m any of our reasonings, except such 
as relate to words only If this supposition were true, we 
might argue correctly from true premises, and arrive at a false 
conclusion. We should only have to assume as a premise the 
definition of a nonentity ; or rather of a name which has 
no entity corresponding to it. Let this, for instance, be our 
definition: 

A dragon is a serpent breathing flame. 



DEFINITION. 


16S 


This proposition, considered only as a definition, is indis¬ 
putably correct. A diagon is a serpent breathing flame the 
word means that The tacit assumption, indeed, (if there were 
any such understood asseition), of the existence of an object 
with properties corresponding to the definition, would, m the 
present instance, be false Out of this definition we may carve 
the premises of the following syllogism . 

A dragon is a thing which breathes flame: 

A dragon is a serpent: 

From which the conclusion is, 

Therefore some seipent or serpents breathe flame — 
an unexceptionable syllogism m the first mode of the third 
figure, m which both premises are true and yet the conclusion 
false, which every logician knows to be an absurdity. The 
conclusion being false and the syllogism correct, the premises 
cannot be true. But the premises, considered as parts of a 
definition, are true. Therefore, the premises considered as 
parts of a definition cannot be the real ones. The real pre 
mises must be— 

A dragon is a really existing thing which breathes flame 
A dragon is a really existing serpent: 
which implied premises being false, the falsity of the conclu¬ 
sion presents no absurdity. 

If we would determine what conclusion follows from the 
same ostensible premises when the tacit assumption of real 
existence is left out, let us, according to the recommendation 
in a previous page, substitute means for is We then have— 
Dragon is a woid meaning a thing which breathes flame 
Dragon is a word meaning a serpent 
From which the conclusion is, 

Some word or words which mean a serpent, also mean 
a thing which breathes flame * 

where the conclusion (as well as the premises) is true, and 
is the only kind of conclusion which can ever follow fiom a 
definition, namely, a proposition relating to the meaning of 
words. 

There is still another shape into which we may transform 
this syllogism. We may suppose the middle term to be the 

11—2 



164 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


designation neither of a thing nor of a name, hut of an idea. 
We then have— 

The idea of a dragon is an idea of a thing which breathes 
flame 

The idea of a dragon is an idea of a serpent. 

Therefore, there is an idea of a seipent, which is an idea of 
a thing breathing flame 

Here the conclusion is true, and also the premises, but the 
premises are not definitions They are propositions affirming 
that an idea existing m the mind, includes certain ideal ele¬ 
ments. The truth of the conclusion follows flora the existence 
of the psychological phenomenon called the idea of a dragon; 
and therefore still from the tacit assumption of a matter of 
fact % 

When, as m this last syllogism, the conclusion is a propo- 

* In tlie only attempt ’which, so far as I know, has been made to refute 
the preceding argumentation, it is maintained that m the fiist form of the 
syllogism, 

A dragon is a thing which breathes flame, 

A dragon is a serpent, 

Therefoie some serpent or serpents breathe flame, 

4 there is just as much truth in the conclusion as there is m the premises, or 
rather, no more in the lattei than m the former If the general name serpent 
includes both real and imaginary serpents, there is no falsity m the conclusion, 
if not, there is falsity in the minor premise ” 

Let us, then, try to set out the syllogism on the hypothesis that the name 
serpent includes imaginary serpents We shall find that it is now necessary to 
alter the predicates, for it cannot be asserted that an imaginary creature 
breathes flame m predicating of it such a fact, we assert by the most positive 
implication that it is real and not imaginary The conclusion must lun thus, 
“ Some serpent or serpents either do or are imagined to breathe flame ” And 
to prove this conclusion by the instance of diagons, the premises must he, A 
dragon is imagined as bi eathmg flame, A dragon is a (real or imaginary) ser¬ 
pent from which it undoubtedly follows, that there are serpents which are 
imagined to breathe flame , but tbe major premise is not a definition, nor part 
of a definition , which is all that I am concerned to prove 

Let us now examine the other assertion—that if the word serpent stands foi 
none but real serpents, the minor premise (a dragon is a serpent) is false This 
is exactly what I have myself said of the premise, consideied as a statement of 
fact but it is not false as part of the definition of a dragon , and smce the 
premises, or one of them, must be false, (the conclusion being so,) the real 
* emise cannot be the definition, which is true, but the statement of fact, 
which is false. 



DEFINITION. 


165 


sition respecting an idea, the assumption on which it depends 
may be merely that of the existence of an idea. But when 
the conclusion is a pioposition concerning a Thing, the postu¬ 
late involved m the definition which stands as the appaient 
piemise, is the existence of a thing conformable to the defini¬ 
tion, and not meiely of an idea conformable to it This as¬ 
sumption of real existence will always convey the impression 
that we intend to make, when we profess to define any name 
which is alieady known to be a name of really existing objects. 
On this account it is, that the assumption was not necessarily 
implied m the definition of a diagon, while there was no doubt 
of its being included m the definition of a circle. 

§ 6 . One of the cncuinstances which have contributed to 
keep up the notion, that demonstrative truths follow from 
definitions rather than fiom the postulates implied m those 
definitions, is, that the postulates, even m those sciences 
which aie considered to surpass all others m demonstrative 
certainty, are not always exactly true. It is not true that a 
circle exists, or can be described, which has all its radii exactly 
equal. Such accuracy is ideal only, it is not found m nature, 
still less can it be realized by art. People had a difficulty, 
therefore, m conceiving that the most certain of all con¬ 
clusions could rest on premises which, instead of being cer¬ 
tainly true, are certainly not true to the full extent asseited 
This apparent paradox will be examined when we come to 
treat of Demonstiation, where we shall be able to show that 
as much of the postulate is true, as is required to support as 
much as is true of the conclusion Philosophers, however, to 
whom this view had not occurred, or whom it did not satisfy, 
have thought it indispensable that there should be found in 
definitions something more certain, or at least more accu¬ 
rately true, than the implied postulate of the real existence of 
a corresponding object. And this something they flattered 
themselves they had found, when they laid it down that a 
definition is a statement and analysis not of the mere mean¬ 
ing of a word, nor yet of the nature of a thing, but of an idea. 
Thus, the proposition, <( A cirqle is a plane figure bounded 



166 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


by a line all the points of which are at an equal distance from 
a given point within it,” was considered by them, not as an 
assertion that any leal circle has that property, (which would 
not be exactly true,) but that we conceive a circle as having it, 
that our abstract idea of a circle is an idea of a figure with 
its radii exactly equal 

Conformably to this it is said, that the subject-matter of 
mathematics, and of every other demonstrative science, is not 
things as they really exist, but abstractions of the mind A 
geometrical line is a line without breadth, but no such line 
exists m nature; it is a notion merely suggested to the mind 
by its experience of natme. The definition (it is said) is a 
definition of this mental line, not of any actual line and it is 
only of the mental line, not of any line existing m nature, that 
the theorems of geometry are accurately true 

Allowing this doctrine respecting the nature of demonstra¬ 
tive truth to be correct (which, m a subsequent place, I 
shall endeavour to prove that it is not,) even on that suppo¬ 
sition, the conclusions which seem to follow from a definition, 
do not follow from the definition as such, but from an implied 
postulate. Even if it be true that there is no object m 
nature answering to the definition of a line, and that the 
geometrical properties of lines are not true of any lines in 
nature, but only of the idea of a line, the definition, at all 
events, postulates the real existence of such an idea it 
assumes that the mind can frame, or rather has framed, the 
notion of length without breadth, and without any other 
sensible property whatever. To me, indeed, it appears 
that the mind cannot form any such notion ; it cannot 
conceive length without breadth ; it can only, m con¬ 
templating objects, attend to their length, exclusively of 
their other sensible qualities, and so determine what pro¬ 
perties may be predicated of them in virtue of their length 
alone. If this be true, the postulate involved m the geome- 
tncal definition of a line, is the real existence, not of length 
without breadth, but merely of length, that is, of long objects. 
This is quite enough to support all the truths of geometry, 
smce every property of a geometrical line is really a property 



DEFINITION. 


167 


of all physical objects m so far as possessing length. But 
even what I hold to be the false doctrine on the subject, 
leaves the conclusion that our reasonings are grounded on the 
matters of fact postulated m definitions, and not on the de¬ 
finitions themselves, entirely unaffected, and accordingly this 
conclusion is one which I have m common with Dr. Whewell, 
m his Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences though, on the 
natuie of demolishative truth, Dr Whewell’s opinions are 
greatly at vanance with mine. And here, as m many other 
instances, I gladly acknowledge that his writings are emi¬ 
nently serviceable m clearing from confusion the initial steps 
m the analysis of the mental processes, even where his views 
respecting the ultimate analysis are such as (though with un¬ 
feigned respect) I cannot but regard as fundamentally erroneous 

§ 7. Although, according to the opinion here presented. 
Definitions are properly of names only, and not of things, it 
does not follow fiom this that definitions are arbitrary. How 
to define a name, may not only be an inquiry of considerable 
difficulty and intricacy, but may involve considerations going 
deep into the nature of the things which are denoted by the 
name. Such, for instance, are the inquiries which form the 
subjects of the most important of Plato’s Dialogues, as, 
c< What is rhetoric the topic of the Gorgias, or “ What is 
justice ? that of the Republic Such, also, is the question 
scornfully asked by Pilate, “ What is truth ?” and the fun 
damental question with speculative moralists in all ages, 
“ What is virtue ?” 

It would be a mistake to represent these difficult anu 
noble inquiries as having nothing m view beyond ascertaining 
the conventional meaning of a name. They are inquiries not 
so much to determine what is, as what should be, the meaning 
of a name, which, like other practical questions of terminology, 
requires for its solution that we should enter, and sometimes 
enter very deeply, into the properties not merely of names but 
of the things named. 

Although the meaning of every concrete general name 
resides m the attributes which it connotes, the objects were 



168 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


named before the attributes, as appeals fiom the fact that m 
all languages, abstiact names aie mostly compounds 01 othei 
derivatives of the conciete names which conespond to them. 
Connotative names, therefore, were, after proper names, the 
first which were used and m the simpler cases, no doubt, a 
distinct connotation was piesent to the minds of those who 
first used the name, and was distinctly intended by them to 
be convened by it The fhst person who used the word white, 
as applied to snow or to any other object, knew, no doubt, 
very well what quality he intended to predicate, and had a 
perfectly distinct conception m his mind of the attribute sig¬ 
nified by the name. 

But where the resemblances and differences on which 
our classifications are founded aie not of this palpable and 
easily determinable kind, especially where they consist not 
m any one quality but in a number of qualities, the effects 
of which being blended together are not very easily discu- 
rmnated, and referred each to its true souice, it often 
happens that names aie applied to nameable objects, with 
no distinct connotation present to the minds of those who 
apply them They are only influenced by a geneial lesem- 
blance between the new object and all or some of the old 
familiar objects which they have been accustomed to call by 
that name. This, as we have seen, is the law which even 
the mind of the philosopher must follow, m giving names to 
the simple elementary feelings of our nature * but, where the 
things to he named are complex wholes, a philosopher is not 
content with noticing a general resemblance, he examines 
what the lesemblance consists m: and he only gives the 
same name to things which resemble one another m the 
same definite particulars. The philosopher, therefore, habit¬ 
ually employs his general names with a definite connotation. 
But language was not made, and can only m some small 
degree he mended, by philosopheis. In the mmds of the 
real arbiters of language, general names, especially where 
the classes they denote cannot be brought before the tri¬ 
bunal of the outward senses to be identified and discrimi¬ 
nated, connote little more than a vague gross resemblance 



DEFINITION. 


169 


to the things which they were eailiest, 01 have been most, 
accustomed to call by those names When, for instance, 
ordinary peisons predicate the words just or unjust of any 
action, nolle or mean of any sentiment, expression, or 
demeanour, statesman 01 charlatan of any peisonage figuring 
m politics, do they mean to affirm of those various subjects 
any detemnnate attributes, of whatever kind ? No they 
merely recognise, as they think, some likeness, more or less 
vague and loose, between these and some other things which 
they have been accustomed to denominate or to hear deno¬ 
minated by those appellations 

Language, as Sir James Mackintosh used to say of govern¬ 
ments, “ is not made, but grows ” A name is not imposed at 
once and by previous purpose upon a class of objects, but is 
first applied to one thing, and then extended by a series of 
transitions to another and another By this process (as has 
been remarked by several writers, and illustrated with great 
force and clearness by Dugald Stewart m his Philosophical 
Essays) a name not unfrequently passes by successive links of 
resemblance fiom one object to another, until it becomes ap¬ 
plied to things having nothing m common with the first things 
to which the name was given , which, however, do not, for 
that reason, drop the name, so that it at last denotes a con¬ 
fused huddle of objects, having nothing whatever m common, 
and connotes nothing, not even a vague and general resem¬ 
blance ( When a name has fallen into this state, m which by 
predicating it of any object we assert literally nothing about 
the object, it has become unfit for the purposes either of 
thought or of the communication of thought, and can only 
be made serviceable by stripping it of some part of its multi- 
fanous denotation, and confining it to objects possessed of 
some attributes m common, which it may be made to connote. 
Such are the inconveniences of a language which “ is not made, 
but grows ” Like the governments which are m a similar 
case, it may be compared to a road which is not made but has 
made itself: it requires continual mending m order to be 
passable. 

Erom this it is already evident, why the question respect- 



170 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


mg the definition of an abstract name is often one of so much 
difficulty. The question, What is justice ? is, in other woids. 
What is the attribute which mankind mean to predicate when 
they call an action just ? To which the fiist answer is, that 
having come to no precise agreement on the point, they do 
not mean to predicate distinctly any attribute at all. Never¬ 
theless, all believe that theie is some common attribute be¬ 
longing to all the actions which they are m the habit of calling 
just. The question then must be, whether there is any such 
common attribute ? and, m the first place, whether mankind 
agree sufficiently with one another as to the particular actions 
which they do or do not call just, to render the inquiry, what 
quality those actions have m common, a possible one * if so, 
whether the actions really have any quality m common , and 
if they have, what it is. Of these three, the first alone is an 
inquiry into usage and convention, the other two are inquiries 
into matters of fact And if the second question (whether the 
actions form a class at all) has been answered negatively, there 
remains a fourth, often more arduous than all the rest, namely, 
how best to form a class artificially, which the name may 
denote. 

And here it is fitting to remark, that the study of the 
spontaneous growth of languages is of the utmost importance 
to those who would logically remodel them. The classifica¬ 
tions rudely made by established language, when retouched, as 
they almost all require to be, by the hands of the logician, are 
often in themselves excellently suited to his purposes. As 
compared with the classifications of a philosopher, they are 
like the customary law of a country, which has grown up as 
it were spontaneously, compared with laws methodized and 
digested into a code the former are a far less perfect instru¬ 
ment than the latter; but being the result of a long, though 
unscientific, course of experience, they contain a mass of mate¬ 
rials which may be made very usefully available m the forma¬ 
tion of the systematic body of written law. In like mannei, 
the established grouping of obj’ects under a common name, 
even when founded only on a gross and general resem¬ 
blance, is evidence, in the first place, that the resemblance is 




DEFINITION. 


171 


obvious, and tberefoie considerable; and, m the next place, 
that it is a lesemblance which has struck great numbeis of 
persons during a series of years and ages. Even when a name, 
by successive extensions, has come to be apphed to things 
among which theie does not exist this gross resemblance com¬ 
mon to them all, still at every step m its progress we shall 
find such a resemblance And these transitions of the mean¬ 
ing of words are often an index to real connexions between 
the things denoted by them, which might otherwise escape 
the notice of thinkers, of those at least who, from using a 
diffeient language, or from any difference m their habitual 
associations, have fixed their attention m preference on some 
other aspect of the things The history of philosophy abounds 
in examples of such oversights, committed for want of per¬ 
ceiving the hidden link that connected together the seemingly 
disparate meanings of some ambiguous word * 

Whenever the inquiry into the definition of the name of 
any real object consists of anything else than a mere comparison 
of authorities, we tacitly assume that a meaning must be found 
foi the name, compatible with its continuing to denote, if pos¬ 
sible all, but at any rate the greater or the more important 
part, of the things of which it is commonly predicated. The 
inquiry, therefore, into the definition, is an inquiry into the 
resemblances and differences among those things whether 
there be any resemblance running through them all, if not, 
through what portion of them such a general resemblance can 

* “Few people n (I have said m another place) “have reflected how great 
a knowledge of Things is required to enable a man to affirm that any given 
argument turns wholly upon words There is, perhaps, not one of the leadmg 
terms of philosophy which is not used m almost innumerable shades of meaning, 
to express ideas more or less widely different from one another Between two 
of these Ideas a sagacious and penetrating mmd will discern, as it were intui¬ 
tively, an unobvious link of connexion, upon which, though perhaps unable to 
give a logical account of it, he will found a perfectly valid argument, which his 
cntic, not having so keen an insight into the Things, will mistake for a fallacy 
turning on the double meaning of a term. And the greater the genius of him 
who thus safely leaps over the chasm, the greater will probably be the crowing 
and vain-glory of the mere logician, who, hobbling after him, evinces his own 
superior wisdom by pausing on its brmk, and giving up as desperate his proper 
business of bridging it over/* 



172 


NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. 


be traced and finally, what are the common attributes, tbe 
possession of which gives to them all, or to that portion of 
them, the character of resemblance which has led to their being 
classed togethei. When these common attributes have been 
ascertained and specified, the name which belongs m common 
to the resembling objects acquires a distinct instead of a vague 
connotation , and by possessing this distinct connotation, be¬ 
comes susceptible of definition 

In giving a distinct connotation to the general name, the 
philosopher will endeavour to fix upon such attributes as, 
while they aie common to all the things usually denoted by 
the name, are also of greatest importance m themselves , either 
directly, or from the number, the conspicuousness, 01 the 
interesting character, of the consequences to which they lead. 
He will select, as far as possible, such differentia as lead to the 
greatest number of interesting propria . For these, rather than 
the more obscure and recondite qualities on which they often 
depend, give that general character and aspect to a set of 
objects, which deteimme the groups into which they naturally 
fall. But to penetrate to the moi e hidden agieement on which 
these obvious and superficial agreements depend, is often one 
of the most difficult of scientific problems As it is among the 
most difficult, so it seldom fails to be among the most im¬ 
portant. And since upon the result of this inquiry respecting 
the causes of the propeities of a class of thmgs, theie inci¬ 
dentally depends the question what shall he the meaning of a 
word, some of the most profound and most valuable investi¬ 
gations which philosophy presents to us, have been introduced 
by, and have offered themselves under tbe guise of, lnqumes 
into the definition of a name. 



BOOK II. 


OP REASONING. 



AtO)pt(TfLEV(i)V $E TOVTOJV XiyMjUEV TjSrjj Sia TlVOJVj mt 7 rOTSj 
/cat 7TU>Q yivzrat 7 rag ovXXoyujpog' vcrrepov Ss Xekteov irspi 
a7ro$d%E(i)Q JlpOTZpov yap irepl avXXoyiapov Xekteov, rj Trepl 
ctTroSsl^Ewg, Sia to KaOoXov jxaXXov elvai rov arvXXoyiapov. 
H [lev yap a? roSsi^ig y avXXoyicrpog Tig * 6 ovXXoyicrpog Se ov 
7 rag, UTroSsi^ig. 


Aeist. Analyt Prior 1. i cap. 4 



CHAPTER I. 


OF INFERENCE, OR REASONING, IN GENERAL. 

§ 1. In the preceding Book, we have been occupied not 
with the nature of Proof, but with the nature of Assertion: 
the import conveyed by a Pioposition, whether that Proposi¬ 
tion be true or false; not the means by which to discriminate 
true from false Propositions The proper subject, however, of 
Logic is Proof. Before we could understand what Proof is, it 
was necessary to understand what that is to which proof is 
applicable; what that is which can be a subject of belief or 
disbelief, of affirmation or denial, what, m short, the different 
kinds of Propositions assert 

This preliminary inquiry we have prosecuted to a definite 
result Assertion, m the first place, relates either to the 
meaning of words, or to some property of the things which 
words signify Assertions respecting the meaning of words, 
among which definitions are the most important, hold a place, 
and an indispensable one, m philosophy, but as the meaning 
of words is essentially arbitrary, this class of assertions are 
not susceptible of truth or falsity, nor therefore of proof or 
| disproof. Assertions respecting Things, or what may be called 
v |Real Propositions, m contradistinction to verbal ones, are of 
various sorts. We have analysed the import of each sort, and 
have ascertained the nature of the things they relate to, and 
the nature of what they severally assert respecting those 
things. We found that whatever be the form of the propo¬ 
sition, and whatever its nominal subject or predicate, the real 
subject of every proposition is some one or more facts or phe¬ 
nomena qf consciousness, or some one or more of the hidden 
causes or powers to which we ascribe those facts, and‘that 
what is predicated or asserted, either in the affirmative or 



176 


REASONING. 


negative, of those phenomena or those powers, is always 
either Existence, Orclei m Place, Order in Time, Causation, 
01 Eesemblance This, then, is the theory of the Impoit of 
Propositions, reduced to its ultimate elements. but there is 
another and a less abstiuse expression for it, which, though 
stopping short m an earlier stage of the analysis, is suffi¬ 
ciently scientific foi many of the purposes for which such a 
geneial expression is required. This expression recognises 
the commonly received distinction between Subject and Attri¬ 
bute, and gives the following as the analysis of the meaning 
of propositions —Every Proposition asserts, that some given 
subject does or does not possess some attribute, or that some 
attribute is or is not (either m all or m some portion of the 
subjects m which it is met with) conjoined with some other 
attribute. 

We shall now for the piesent take our leave of this portion 
of our inquiry, and proceed to the peculiar pioblem of the 
Science of Logic, namely, how the assertions, of which we 
have analysed the import, are proved oi disproved, such of 
them, at least, as, not being amenable to direct consciousness 
or intuition, are appropriate subjects of proof 

We say of a fact or statement, that it is pioved, when we 
believe its truth by reason of some other fact or statement 
from which it is said to follow Most of the propositions, 
whether affirmative or negative, umveisal, particular, or 
singular, which we believe, are not believed on their own 
evidence, hut on the ground of something previously assented 
to, from which they are said to he inferred . To infer a 
proposition from a previous proposition 01 propositions, to 
| give ciedence to it, or claim credence for it, as a conclusion 
(from something else, is to reason , m the most extensive sense 
of the term. There is a narrower sense, m which the name 
reasoning is confined to the form of inference which is termed 
ratiocination, and of which the syllogism is the general type 
The reasons for not conforming to this restricted use of the 
term were stated m an earlier stage of our inquiry, and addi¬ 
tional motives will he suggested by the considerations on 
which we are now about to enter. 



INFERENCE IN GENERAL 


177 


§ 2 In proceeding to take into consideration the cases 
xn which inferences can legitimately be drawn, we shall first 
mention some cases m which the inference is apparent, not 
real, and which lequne .notice chiefly that they may not he 
confounded with cases of inference pioperly so called. This 
occurs when the proposition ostensibly inferred from another, 
appears on analysis to be merely a repetition of the same, or 
part of the same, assertion, which was contained m the first. 
All the cases mentioned m books of Logic as examples of 
aequipollency or equivalence of propositions, are of this nature 
Thus, if we were to argue. No man is incapable of reason, 
for every man is rational, or, All men are moital, for no 
man is exempt from death, it would be plain that we were 
not pioving the proposition, but only appealing to another 
mode of wording it, which may or may not be more readily 
comprehensible by the hearer, or better adapted to suggest 
the leal proof, but which contains m itself no shadow of 
proof. 

Another case is where, from an universal proposition, we 
affect to mfei anothei which differs from it only m being par¬ 
ticular as All A is 33 , therefoie Some A is 33 No A is 33 , 
therefoie Some A is not 33 This, too, is not to conclude one 
proposition from another, but to repeat a second time some¬ 
thing which had been asserted at first, with the difference, 
that we do not heie repeat the whole of the previous assertion, 
but only an indefinite part of it 

A third case is where, the antecedent having affirmed a 
predicate of a given subject, the consequent affirms of the 
same subject something already connoted by the formei pre¬ 
dicate as, So dates is a man, therefore Socrates is a living 
creature, where all that is connoted by living creature was 
affirmed of Socrates when he was asserted to be a man 
If the propositions are negative, we must invert their order, 
thus Socrates is not a living creature, therefoie he is not a 
man, for if we deny the less, the greater, which includes it, 
is already denied by implication These, therefore, are not 
really cases of inference, and yet the trivial examples by 
which, in manuals of Logic, the rules of the syllogism are 
vol. I. 12 



178 


REASONING. 


illustrated, are often of this ill-chosen kind, foimal demon¬ 
strations of conclusions to which whoever understands the 
terms used in the statement of the data, has already, and 
consciously, assented. 

^ The most complex case of this sort of apparent mfeience 
' is what is called the Conversion of piopositions, which 
consists m turning the predicate into a subject, and the 
subject into a predicate, and flaming out of the same terms 
thus reversed, another proposition, which must he true if the 
former is true Thus, from the particular afhimative proposi¬ 
tion, Some A is B, we may infer that Some B is A. Thom 
the universal negative, No A is B, we may conclude that 
No B is A From the universal affirmative proposition, 
All A is B, it cannot he inferred that all B is A, though 
all water is liquid, it is not implied that all liquid is water, 
but it is implied that some liquid is so , and hence the pro¬ 
position, All A is B, is legitimately convertible into Some 
B is A. This process, which conveits an umveisal propo¬ 
sition mto a paiticular, is termed conveision pel acculens 
From the proposition, Some A is not B, we cannot even infer 
that some B is not A, though some men aie not Englishmen, 
i it does not follow that some Englishmen are not men The 
* only mode usually recognised of converting a particular nega¬ 
tive proposition, is m the form, Some A is not B, theiefoie, 
something which is not B is A; and this is termed conver¬ 
sion by contiaposition. In this case, however, the predicate 
and subject are not mei ely leversed, hut one of them is 
changed. Instead of [A] and [B], the terms of the new 
proposition aie [a thing which is not B], and [A] The 
original proposition, Some A is not B, is first changed into 
a proposition eequipollent with it, Some A is “ a thing which 
is not B, ’ and the proposition, being now no longer a 
particular negative, but a paiticular affirmative, admits of 
conversion in the first mode, or as it is called, simple con¬ 
version.** 


* As Sir William Hamilton has pointed out, “ Some A is not B ” may also 
be converted in the following form “No B is some A ” Some men are not 
negroes, therefore, No negroes are some men (e, g. Emopeans), 



INFERENCE IN GENERAL. 


179 


In all these cases theie is not leally any mfeienoe, theie is 
in the conclusion no new tiuth, nothing but what was already 
asserted in the premises, and obvious to whoever apprehends 
them. The fact asserted m the conclusion is either the very 
same fact, or part of the fact asserted m the original proposi¬ 
tion. This follows from our previous analysis of the Impoit 
of Propositions When we say, for example, that some lawful 
sovereigns are tyrants, what is the meaning of the assertion ? 
That the attubutes connoted hy the term “lawful sovereign," 
and the attributes connoted by the term “ tyrant,” sometimes 
coexist m the same individual. Now this is also precisely 
what we mean, when we say that some tyrants are lawful 
soveieigns, which, therefoie, is not a second pioposition 
inferred from the first, any more than the English translation 
of Euclid’s Elements is a collection of theorems different from, 
and consequences of, those contained m the Greek original. 
Again, if we assert that no great geneial is a rash man, 
we mean that the attributes connoted by “ great general,” 
and those connoted hy “rash,” never coexist m the same sub¬ 
ject, which is also the exact meaning which would be ex¬ 
pressed by saying, that no rash man is a great general. When 
we say that all quadrupeds are warm-blooded, we assert, not 
only that the attributes connoted by “ quadruped” and those 
connoted by “warm-blooded” sometimes coexist, but that the 
former never exist without the latter. now the proposition, 
Some warm-blooded creatuies are quadrupeds, expiesses the 
first half of this meaning, dropping the latter half, and 
therefore has been aheady affirmed m the antecedent proposi¬ 
tion, All quadiupeds are warm-blooded But that all warm¬ 
blooded creatures are quadrupeds, or, m other woids, that the 
attributes connoted hy “ warm-blooded” never exist without 
those connoted by “ quadruped,” has not been asserted, and 
cannot be inferred In order to reassert, m an mveited form, 
the whole of what was affirmed m the proposition, All quad¬ 
rupeds are warm-blooded, w T e must convert it by contra¬ 
position, thus, Nothing which is not warm-blooded is a quad¬ 
ruped. This proposition, and the one from which it is derived, 
are exactly equivalent, and either of them may he substituted 

12—2 



ISO 


REASONING. 


for the other, foi, to say that when the attubutes of a quad- 
mped aie piesent, those of a warm-blooded creature aie pre¬ 
sent, is to say* that when the lattei aie absent the foimer are 
absent. 

In a manual for young students, it -would be proper to 
dwell at gi eater length on the convexsxon and sequipollency of 
propositions For, though that cannot be called leasonmg 
or mfeience which is a mere reasseition m diffeient words 
of what had been asserted before, there is no more important 
intellectual habit, nor any the cultivation of which falls more 
stnctly within the piovmce of the ait of logic, than that 
of discerning lapidly and surely the identity of an assertion 
when disguised under diveisity of language That important 
chapter m logical treatises which lelates to the Opposition 
of Piopositions, and the excellent technical language which 
logic pi ovules for distinguishing the diffeient kinds or modes 
of opposition, aie of use chiefly foi this puipose. Such con¬ 
siderations as these, that contiaiy propositions may both he 
false, but cannot both be true, that sub contrary pi opositions 
may both he true, hut cannot both be false, that of two con- 
tiadictoiy propositions one must be true and the othei false, 
that of two subaltemate pi opositions the tiuth of the uni¬ 
versal pioves the ti nth of the paiticular, and the falsity of the 
particulai pioves the falsity of the univeisal, hut not vice 
tend aie apt to appear, at fust sight, very technical and 
mysterious, but when explained, seem almost too obvious 
to require so foimal a statement, since the same amount 
of explanation which is necessary to make the principles intel¬ 
ligible, would enable the tiuths which they convey to he 


conti aries 


■* All A is B ^ 

No A is B j 
Some A is B 
Some A is not B 
All A is B 
Some A is not B 

No A is B \ a j gQ contj adictories 
Some A is B / 

All A is B | and No A is B 
Some A is B) Some A is not B 


| subcontranes. 

| contradictories, 


) 


respectively subaltemate. 



inference in general 


181 


apprehended in any particular case which can occur. In this 
respect, howevei, these axioms of logic are on a level with 
those of mathematics. That things which aie equal to the 
same thing aie equal to one anothei, is as obvious m any pai- 
ticular case as it is in the general statement. and if no such 
general maxim had ever been laid down, the demonstrations m 
Euclid would nevei have halted for any difficulty in stepping 
acioss the gap which this axiom at piesent serves to budge 
over. Yet no one has ever censured wiiters on geometry, for 
placing a list of these elementary generalizations at the head 
of then treatises, as a first exercise to the learner of the faculty 
which will he requued in him at every step, that of appre¬ 
hending a general ti uth And the student of logic, m the dis¬ 
cussion even of such truths as we have cited above, acquires 
habits of cncumspect intei pretation of words, and of exactly 
measunng the length and breadth of his asseitions, which are 
among the most indispensable conditions of any considerable 
mental attainment, and which it is one of the primary objects 
of logical discipline to cultivate. 

§ 3 . Having noticed, m Older to exclude frofn the pro¬ 
vince of Seasoning or Infeience properly so called, the cases 
in which the progression from one truth to another is only ap¬ 
parent, the logical consequent being a mere repetition of the 
logical antecedent; we now pass to those which are cases of 
inference m the pi oper acceptation of the term, those m which 
we set out from known truths, to arrive at others leally dis¬ 
tinct from them. 

Eeasoning, m the extended sense m which I use the term, 
and in which it is synonymous with Inference, is popularly 
said to he of two kinds reasoning from particulars to generals, | 
and reasoning from generals to particulais , the former beingf 
called Induction, the latter Eatiocmation or Syllogism. It 
will presently be shown that there is a third species of rea¬ 
soning, which falls under neither of these descriptions, and 
which, nevertheless, is not only vahd, but is the foundation of 
both the others. 

It is necessary to observe, that the expressions, reasoning 



182 


REASONING. 


fiom paiticulars to generals, and reasoning from generals to 
paiticulars, are recommended by brevity rather than by pre¬ 
cision, and do not adequately mark, without the aid of a 
commentary, the distinction between Induction (m the sense 
now adverted to) and Ratiocination The meaning intended 
! by these expressions is, that Induction is inferring a propo¬ 
sition from propositions less geneial than itself, and Ratioci¬ 
nation is mfeiiing a proposition from propositions equally or 
moie general. When, from the observation of a number of 
individual instances, we ascend to a general proposition, or 
when, by combining a number of general propositions, we 
conclude fiom them another proposition still more general, 
the process, which is substantially the same m both instances, 
is called Induction. When from a general proposition, not 
alone (for fiom a single proposition nothing can be concluded 
which is not involved m the terms), but by combining it with 
other propositions, we infer a proposition of the same degree 
of generality with itself, or a less general proposition, or a 
pioposition merely individual, the process is Ratiocination. 
When, m short, the conclusion is more genei al than the 
r largest of the premises, the argument is commonly called 
Induction; when less general, or equally general, it is Ratio¬ 
cination 

As all experience begins with individual cases, and pro¬ 
ceeds from them to generals, it might seem most conformable 
to the natural order of thought that Induction should be 
treated of before we touch upon Ratiocination. It will, how¬ 
ever, be advantageous, m a science which aims at tracing our 
acquired knowledge to its sources, that the inquirer should 
commence with the latter rather than with the earlier stages of 
the process of constructing our knowledge, and should trace 
derivative truths backward to the truths from which they are 
deduced, and on which they depend for their evidence, before 
attempting to point oiit the original spring from which both 
ultimately take their nse. The advantages of this order of 
proceeding m the present instance will manifest themselves as 
we advance, in a manner superseding the necessity of any 
further justification or explanation. 



INFERENCE IN GENERAL. 


183 


Of Induction, therefore, we shall say no more at present, 
than that it at least is, without doubt, a process of real infer' 
ence The conclusion m an induction embraces more than is 
contained m the premises The principle or law collected 
from particular instances, the general proposition m which we 
embody the result of our experience, covers a much larger 
extent of ground than the individual experiments which form 
its basis. A principle ascertained by experience, is more than 
a mere summing up of what has been specifically observed m 
the individual cases which have been examined, it is a gene¬ 
ralization giouuded on those cases, and expressive of our belief, 
that what we there found true is true m an indefinite number 
of cases which we have not examined, and are never likely to 
examine. The nature and grounds of this inference, and the 
conditions necessary to make it legitimate, will be the subject 
of discussion m the Third Book but that such inference 
really takes place is not susceptible of question. In every in¬ 
duction we proceed from truths which we knew, to truths which 
we did not know , from facts certified by observation, to facts 
which we have not observed, and even to facts not capable of 
being now observed , future facts, for example, but which we 
do not hesitate to believe on the sole evidence of the induction 
itself 

Induction, then, is a real process of Reasoning or Inference. 
Whether, and m what sense, as much can be said of the Syl¬ 
logism, remains to be determined by the examination into which 
we are about to enter. 



CHAPTEE II 


OF BATIOCINATION, OB SYLLOGISM. 

§ 1. The analysis of the Syllogism has been so accurately 
and fully performed m the common manuals of Logic, that in 
the piesent work, which is not designed as a manual, it is suf¬ 
ficient to recapitulate, memories causa, the leading results of 
that analysis, as a foundation for the remarks to be afterwards 
made on the functions of the syllogism, and the place which it 
holds in science. 

To a legitimate syllogism it is essential that there should be 
three, and no more than three, propositions, namely, the con¬ 
clusion, or proposition to be proved, and two other propositions 
which together prove it, and which are called the piemises It 
is essential that there should be three, and no more than three, 
terms, namely, the subject and predicate of the conclusion, and 
another called the middleterm, which must be found in both 
premises, since it is by means of it that the other two terms are 
to be connected togethei. The piedicate of the conclusion is 
called the major term of the syllogism ; the subject of the con¬ 
clusion is called the minor term. As there can be but three 
terms, the major and minor terms must each be found m one, 
and only one, of the premises, together with the middleterm 
which is m them both. The premise which contains the mid¬ 
dleterm and the major term is called the maj’or premise , that 
which contains the middleterm and the minor term is called 
the minor premise. 

Syllogisms are divided by some logicians into three figures, 
by others into four, according to the position of the middle- 
term, which may either be the subject m both premises, the 
predicate m both, or the subject m one and the predicate m 
the other. The most common case is that m which the middle- 
term is the subject of the major premise and the predicate of 



RATIOCINATION, OR SYLLOGISM. 


185 


the minor This is reckoned as the first figure. When the 
middleteim is the piedicate in both premises, the syllogism 
belongs to the second figure, when it is the subject in both, to 
the third In the fourth figuie the middleterm is the subject 
of the minor premise and the piedicate of the major. Those 
writers who reckon no moie than three figures, include this case 
m the first. 

Each figure is divided into moods, according to what are 
called the quantity and quality of the piopositions, that is, ac- 
coidmg as they are universal or particular, affirmative or nega¬ 
tive. The following aie examples of all the legitimate moods, 
that is, all those in which the conclusion conectly follows from 
the premises. A is the minor term, C the major, B the middle- 
term 

First Figure 

All B is C No B is 0 All B is C No B is C 
All A is B All A is B Some A is B Some A is B 
therefore thei efore theiefore therefore 

All A is 0 No A is 0 Some A is C Some A is not C 

Second Figure. 

No C is B All C is B No C is B All C is B 

All A is B No A is B Some A is B Some A is not B 

therefoie therefore therefore therefore 

No A is 0 No A is C Some A is not C Some A is not C 

Third Figure 

All B is C No B is C Some B is C All B is C Some B is not C No B is C 
All B is A All B is A All B is A Some B is A All B is A Some B is A 

therefore therefore therefore theiefore therefore therefore 

Some A is C Some A is not C Some A is C Some A is C Some A is not C Some A is not C 

Fourth Iigure. * 

All C is B All 0 is B Some 0 is B No C is B No C is B 

All B is A No Bis A All Bis A All B is A Some Bis A 

therefore therefore theiefore therefore therefore 
Some A is C Some A is not C Some A is C Some A is not C SomeAisnotC 

In these exemplars, or blank forms for making syllogisms, 
no place is assigned to singular propositions, not, of course, 
because such propositions are not used in ratiocination, but 
because, their predicate being affirmed or denied of the 
whole of the subject, they are ranked, for the purposes of the 
syllogism, with universal propositions. Thus, these two syllo¬ 
gisms— 



186 


REASONING. 


All men are mortal, All men are mortal, 

All kings are men, Socrates is a man, 

therefore therefoie 

All kings are mortal, Socrates is mortal, 
are arguments piecisely similar, and are both ranked in the first 
mood of the first figure. 

The reasons why syllogisms in any of the above forms are 
legitimate, that is, why, if the piemises are true, the conclu¬ 
sion must inevitably be so, and why this is not the case m 
any other possible mood, (that is, m any other combination of 
universal and paiticular, affirmative and negative propositions,) 
any person taking interest m these inquiries may be presumed 
to have either learned from the common school books of the 
syllogistic logic, 01 to be capable of discovering for himself. 
The reader may, however, be refei red, for every needful expla¬ 
nation, to Archbishop Whately’s Elements of Logic, where he 
will find stated with philosophical precision, and explained with 
remarkable perspicuity, the whole of the common doctrine of 
the syllogism. 

All valid ratiocination; all reasoning by which, from gene¬ 
ral propositions previously admitted, other propositions equally 
or less general are inferred, may be exhibited m some of the 
above forms. The whole of Euclid, for example, might be 
thrown without difficulty into a series of syllogisms, regular m 
mood and figure 

Though a syllogism framed according to any of these for¬ 
mulae is a valid argument, all correct ratiocination admits of 
being stated m syllogisms of the first figure alone. The rules 
for throwing an argument m any of the other figures into the 
first figure, are called rules for the reduction of syllogisms 
It is done by the conversion of one or other, or both, of the 
premises. Thus an argument m the first mood of the second 
figure, as— 

No C is B 
All A is B 
therefore 
No A is C, 

may be reduced as follows. The proposition, No C is B, 



RATIOCINATION, OR SYLLOGISM 


187 


being an universal negative, admits of simple conversion, and 
may be changed into No B is 0, which, as we showed, is the 
very same assertion m other words—the same fact differently 
expressed This tiansformation having been effected, the 
argument assumes the following form — 

No B is 0 
All A is B 
therefore 
No A is 0, 

which is a good syllogism m the second mood of the first 
figure Again, an argument m the first mood of the third 
figure must resemble the following — 

All B is 0 
All B is A 
therefoie 
Some A is C, 

where the minor premise. All B is A, confoimably to what 
was laid down in the last chapter respecting umversal affirma¬ 
tives, does not admit of simple conversion, but may be 
converted per accidens, thus, Some A is B, which, though it 
does not express the whole of what is asserted m the propo¬ 
sition All B is A, expresses, as was formerly shown, part 
of it, and must therefore be true if the whole is true We 
have, then, as the result of the reduction, the following syllo¬ 
gism m the third mood of the first figure — 

All B is C 
Some A is B, 

from which it obviously follows, that 

Some A is 0. 

In the same manner, oi m a manner on which after these 
examples it is not necessary to enlarge, every mood of the 
second, third, and fourth figures may be reduced to some one 
of the four moods of the first. In other words, every conclu¬ 
sion which can be proved m any of the last three figures, 
may be proved m the first figure from the same premises, 
with a slight alteration in the mere manner of expressing 



188 


REASONING. 


them. Every valid ratiocination, therefore, may he stated m 
the first figure, that is, m one of the following forms — 


Every B is 0 


All A J 

Some A ) 
theiefore 
All A ) 

Some A j 


is B, 


is C 


is B, 


No B is C 
All A 
Some A 

therefore 
No A is | 
Some A is not j 


Or if more significant symbols are preferred — 

To piove an affirmative, the aigument must admit of being 
stated m this foim — 


All animals are mortal, 
All men 


Some men 
Socrates 


are animals, 


therefore 


All men 
Some men 
Socrates 


aie moital 


To prove a negative, the argument must be capable of being 
expressed m this form — 

No one who is capable of self-contiol is necessanly 
vicious, 


All negroes 
Some negroes 
Mr. A’s negro 


are capable of self-control, 


therefore 


No negroes are 
Some negroes are not 
Mr A’s negio is not 


necessanly vicious 


Though all ratiocination admits of being thrown into one 
or the other of these forms, and sometimes gams consider¬ 
ably by the transformation, both m clearness and m the 
obviousness of its consequence, there are, no doubt, cases 
m which the argument falls more natuially into one of the 
other three figures, and m which its conclusiveness is moie 



RATIOCINATION, OR SYLLOGISM. 


1S9 


appaient at the fiist glance in those figures, than when reduced 
to the fiist Thus, if the proposition were that pagans may be 
virtuous, and the evidence to piove it were the example of 
Aristides , a syllogism m the thud figure, 

Aristides was virtuous, 

Anstides was a pagan, 
therefore 

Some pagan was vntuous, 

would be a more natural mode of stating the argument, and 
would cany conviction more instantly home, than the same 
ratiocination strained into the fiist figure, thus—- 
Aristides was vntuous, 

Some pagan was Anstides, 
therefoie 

Some pagan was virtuous 

A Geiman philosopher, Lambert, whose Neues Organon 
(published m the year 17G4) contains among other things 
one of the most elaborate and complete expositions which, had 
ever been made of the syllogistic doctnne, has expressly ex¬ 
amined what sort of arguments fall most natuially and suitably 
into each of the four figures, and his investigation is charac-l 
tenzed by great ingenuity and clearness of thought.* The * 
argument, however, is one and the same, m whichever figure 
it is expressed, since, as we have already seen, the premises 
of a syllogism m the second, third, or fourth figure, and those 
of the syllogism m the first figure to which it may he reduced, 
are the same premises m everything except language, or, at 
least, as much of them as contributes to the pioof of the con- 

* * His conclusions aie, “The first figure is suited to the discovery or proof 

of the propeities of a thing, the second to the discovery or proof of the dis¬ 
tinctions between things, the third to the discovery 01 proof of instances and 
exceptions , the fourth to the discoveiy, or exclusion, of the diffeient species of 
a genus ” The reference of syllogisms m the last three figures to the dictum* 
de omni et nullo is, m Lambert’s opinion, strained and unnatural to each of 
the three belongs, according to him, a separate axiom, co-ordmate and of equal 
authority with that dictum , and to which he gives the names of dictum de 
diverso for the second figuie, dictum de exemplo for the third, and dictum de 
reciproco for the fourth See part 1 or Dianoiologie, chap iv § 229 et seqq 
Mr Bailey, {Theory of Reasoning, 2nd ed pp. 70-74) takes a similar view of the 
subject 



190 


REASONING. 


elusion is the same. We are theiefore at liberty, m con¬ 
formity with the general opinion of logicians, to consider 
the two elementary forms of the first figure as the universal 
types of all correct ratiocination; the one, when the conclusion 
to be proved is affirmative, the other, when it is negative, 
even though cei tain arguments may have a tendency to clothe 
themselves in the foims of the second, third, and fourth 
figuies , which, however, cannot possibly happen with the 
only class of arguments which are of fiist-iate scientific im¬ 
portance, those m which the conclusion is an universal affirm a- 
tive, such conclusions being susceptible of proof m the first 
figure alone ■* 


* Since this chapter was written, two treatises have appeared (or rather a 
tieatise and a fragment of a treatise), which aim at a further improvement m 
the theory of the forms of ratiocination Mr De Morgan’s “ Formal Logic , 
or, the Calculus of Inference, Necessary and Probable,” and the “New 
Analytic of Logical Forms,” attached as an Appendix to Sir William Hamil¬ 
ton s Discussions on Philosophy, and at greater length, to his posthumous Lee- 
tui es on Logic 

In Mr He Morgan s volume—abounding, in its more populai parts, with 
valuable observations felicitously expressed—the pnncipal feature of ongmahty 
is an attempt to bring within strict technical rules the cases m which a conclusion 
can be drawn from premises of a foim usually classed as particular Mr De 
Morgan observes, very justly, that from the premises Most Bs are Cs, most 
Bs are As, it may be concluded with certainty that some As are Cs, since two 
portions of tlie class B, each of them comprising more than half, must neces¬ 
sarily m part Qonsist of the same individuals. Following out this line of 
thought, it is equally evident that if we knew exactly what proportion the 
c most m each of the premises bear to the entire class B, we could mciease m 
a corresponding degree the definiteness of the conclusion. Thus if 60 per cent 
of B are included m C, and 70 per cent m A, 30 per cent at least must be 
common to both , m other words, the number of As which are Cs, and of Cs 
winch are As, must be at least equal to 30 pei cent of the class B Pioceedmg 
ou this conception of “ numerically definite propositions,” and extending it to 
such forms as these —“45 Xs (or more) are each of them one of 70 Ys,” or 
** 45 Xs (or more) are no one of them to be found among 70 Ys,” and examin¬ 
ing what inferences admit of being drawn from the various combinations which 
may be made of premises of this description, Mr De Morgan establishes um- 
veisal formulae for such inferences , creating for that purpose not only a new 
technical language, hut a formidable airay of symbols analogous to those of 
algebra. 

Since it is undeniable that inferences, m the cases examined by Mr. De 
Moigan, can legitimately be drawn, and that the ordinary theory takes no 



RATIOCINATION, OR SYLLOGISM. 


191 


§ 2 On examining, then, these two general formulae, we 
find that m both of them, one piemise, the major, is an uni¬ 
versal proposition, and accoiding as this is affiimative or 
negative* the' conclusion is so too. Ail ratiocination, therefoi e, 
starts from a qeneial proposition, principle, or assumption a 


account of them, I wdl not say that it was not worth while to show m detail 
how these also could be reduced to formulas as rigorous as those of Aristotle 
What Mr De Morgan has done was worth doing once (peihaps more than once, 
as a school exeicise) , but I question if its lesults are worth studying and mas¬ 
tering for any practical purpose The practical use of technical forms of rea¬ 
soning is to bar out fallacies but the fallacies which require to be guarded 
against m ratiocination propeily so called, arise from the incautious use of the 
common fonns of language , and the logician must track the fallacy into that 
terntoiy, instead of waiting for it on a territory of his own While he lemams 
among propositions which have acquired the numerical precision of the Calculus 
of Probabilities, the enemy is left m possession of the only ground on which he 
can be formidable And since the propositions (short of universal) on which 
a thinker has to depend, either foi purposes of speculation or of practice, do 
not, except m a few peculiar cases, admit of any numerical precision , common 
reasoning cannot be translated mto Mr. De Moigan’s forms, which theiefore 
cannot seive any puipose as a test of it 

Sir William Hamilton’s theory of the {C quantification of the predicate” (con¬ 
cerning the originality of which m his case theie can be no doubt, however Mr. 
De Morgan may have also, and independently, originated an equivalent doc¬ 
trine) may be buefly described as follows — 

“ Logically” (I quote his own words) a we ought to take into account the 
quantity, always understood m thought, but usually, for manifest reasons, 
elided m its expression, not only of the subject, but also of the predicate of a 
judgment ” All A is B, is equivalent to all A is some B No A is B, to No 
A is any B Some A is B, is tantamount to some A is some B Some A is 
not B, to Some A is not any B. As m these forms of asseition the predicate 
is exactly coextensive with the subject, they all admit of simple conversion , 
and by this we obtain two additional forms—Some B is all A, and No B is 
some A We may also make the assertion All A is all B, which will be true 
if the classes A and B aie exactly coextensive The last three forms, though 
conveying real assertions, have no place m the ordinaly classification of Pro 
positions. All piopositions, then, being supposed to be translated into this 
language, and written each in that one of the preceding forms which answers 
to its signification, there emerges a new set of syllogistic rules, materially dif¬ 
ferent fiom the common ones A geneial view of the points of difference may 
be given m the words of Sir W Hamilton ( Discussions , 2nd ed p 651) — 

44 The revocation of the two terms of a Proposition to tlieir true 1 elation , a 
proposition being always an equation of its subject and its piedicate. 

“ The consequent reduction of the Conversion of Piopositions from three 
species to one—that of Simple Conversion. 



192 


REASONING. 


proposition m winch a predicate is affirmed or denied of an 
entile class , that is, m which some attnbute, or the negation 
of some attribute, is asseited of an indefinite number of objects 
distinguished by a common charactenstic, and designated m 
consequence, by a common name. 

The other premise is always affiimative, and asseits that 
something (which may be eithei an individual, a class, or pait 

“ The reduction of all the Genei al Laws of Categorical Syllogisms to a single 
Canon 

“ The evolution from that one canon of all the Species and varieties of Syl¬ 
logisms 

“ The abrogation of all the Special Laws of Sy ilogism 

“ A demonstiation of the exclusive possibility of Three syllogistic Figures, 
and (on new grounds) the scientific and final abolition of the Fourth 

<<r A manifestation that Figure is an unessential variation in syllogistic form, 
and the consequent absurdity of Reducing the syllogisms of the other figures to 
the first 

t£ An enouncement of one Organic Principle for each Figure 

“ A determination of the true number of the Legitimate Moods , with 

“ Their amplification m numbei (thirty -six), 

“Their numerical equality under all the figures , and 

“ Their relative equivalence, or vntual identity, throughout every schematic 
diffeience 

“ That, m the second and third figuies, the extremes holding both the same 
relation to the middle teim, there is not, as m the fiist, an opposition and sub- 
oidmation between a teim majoi and a term minor, mutually containing and 
contained, m the counter wholes of Extension and Compiehension 

“ Consequently, m the second and third figures, there is no determinate 
major and minor premise, and there are two indifferent conclusions whereas 
m the first the premises are determinate, and there is a single proximate con¬ 
clusion ” 

This doctrine, like that of Mr Re Morgan previously noticed, is a real 
addition to the syllogistic theory , and has moreover this advantage over Mr 
Re Morgan’s “ numerically definite Syllogism,” that the forms it supplies aie 
really available as a test of the correctness of ratiocination , since propositions 
m the common form may always have their predicates quantified, and so be 
made amenable to Sn W Hamilton’s mles Considered however as a con¬ 
tribution to the Science of Logic, that is, to the analysis of the mental pro¬ 
cesses concerned m leasomng, the new doctrine appears to me, I confess, not 
merely superfluous, but erroneous , since the form in which it clothes pi ©posi¬ 
tions does not, like the ordinary foim, express what is m the mind of the 
speaker when he enunciates the proposition I cannot think Sir William 
Hamilton right m maintaining that the quantity of the predicate is “ always 
understood m thought ” It is implied, but is not present to the mind of the 
person who asseits the proposition. The quantification of the predicate, mstead 



RATIOCINATION, OR SYLLOGISM. 


193 


of a class) belongs to., or is included in, the class respecting 
which something was affirmed or denied m the major premise. 
It follows that the attnbute affirmed or denied of the entire 
class may (if that affirmation 01 denial was correct) he 
affiimed or denied of the object or objects alleged to be in¬ 
cluded m the class and this is precisely the assertion made m 
the conclusion 

Whethei or not the foregoing is an adequate account of the 
constituent paits of the syllogism, will be presently considei ed, 
but as fai as it goes it is a true account. It has accordingly 
been geneialized, and erected into a logical maxim, on which 
all ratiocination is said to be founded, insomuch that to reason, 
and to apply the maxim, are supposed to be one and the same 
thing The maxim is. That whatevei can be affirmed (or denied) 
of a class, may be affirmed (or denied) of everything included 
m the class This axiom, supposed to be the basis of the 
syllogistic theory, is termed by logicians the dictum de omm et 
nulio 

This maxim, however, when considered as a principle of 
reasoning, appears suited to a system of metaphysics once 
indeed genei ally received, but which for the last two centuries 
has been considered as finally abandoned, though there have 
not been wanting m our own day attempts at its revival. 
So long as what are termed Universals were regarded as a 
peculiar kind of substances, having an objective existence 
distinct from the individual objects classed under them, the 
dictum de omm conveyed an important meaning, because it 
expiessed the intercommunity of nature, which it was neces- 


°f bemg a means of bringing out more clearly the meaning of tbe proposition, 
actually leads the mind out of tbe proposition, lfito another order of ideas For 
when we say, All men aie mortal, we simply mean to affirm tbe attribute moi- 
tality of all men , without thinking at all of the class mortal m tbe concrete, or 
troubling ourselves about whether it contains any other beings or not It is 
only for some artificial purpose that we ever look at the proposition m the aspect 
m which the predicate also is thought of as a class-name, either including the 
subject only, or the subject and something more. (See above, p 104 ) 

For a fuller discussion of this subject, see the twenty-second chapter of a 
work already refeired to, “An Examination of Sir William Hamilton’s Philo¬ 
sophy. ” 

VOL. I. 


13 



194 


REASONING. 


saiy on tLat theory that we should suppose to exist between 
those general substances and the particular substances which 
were subordinated to them. That everything piedicable of 
the universal was piedicable of the various individuals con¬ 
tained under it, was then no identical proposition, but a 
statement of what was conceived as a fundamental law of the 
universe The assertion that the entire nature and properties 
of the substantia secunda foimed pait of the nature and pro¬ 
perties of each of the individual substances called by the same 
name, that the pioperiies of Man, for example, were propei- 
ties of all men, was a proposition of leal significance when 
man did not mean all men, but something mheient m men, 
and vastly supenor to them in dignity Now, however, when 
it is known that a class, an umveisal, a genus or species, is 
not an entity pei se } but neither more nor less than the indi¬ 
vidual substances themselves which are placed m the class, 
and that theie is nothing real m the matter except those 
objects, a common name given to them, and common attri¬ 
butes indicated by the name, what, I should he glad to know, 
do we learn by being told, that whatever can he affiimed of a 
class, may he affirmed of eveiy object contained m the class 9 
The class is nothing but the objects contained m it and the 
dictum de omm nreiely amounts to the identical proposition, 
that whatevei is true of certain objects, is tine of each of those 
objects If all ratiocination were no more than the applica¬ 
tion of this maxim to particular cases, the syllogism would 
indeed he, what it has so often been declared to be, solemn 
trifling The dictum de omm is on a par with another truth, 
which in its time was also reckoned of great importance, 
“ Whatever is, is ” To give any real meaning to the dictum 
de omm, we must consider it not as an axiom, hut as a defi¬ 
nition, we must look upon it as intended to explain, in a 
circuitous and paraphrastic manner, the meaning of the word 
<lass 

An error which seemed finally refuted and dislodged from 
thought, often needs only put on a new' suit of phrases, to he 
welcomed hack to its old quarters, and allowed to repose 
unquestioned for another cycle of ages Modem philosophers 



RATIOCINATION, OR SYLLOGISM. 195 

have not been spanng m their contempt for the scholastic 
dogma that geneia and species are a peculiar kind of sub¬ 
stances, which general substances being the only permanent 
things, while the individual substances comprehended under 
them are m a perpetual flux, knowledge, which necessarily 
imports stability, can only have relation to those^ general sub¬ 
stances or umversals, and not to the facts or particulars in¬ 
cluded under them Yet, though nominally rejected, this 
very doctrine, whether disguised under the Abstract Ideas of 
Locke (whose speculations, however, it has less vitiated than 
those of peihaps any other writer who has been infected with 
it), under the ultra-nominalism of Hobbes and Condillac, or 
the ontology of the later Kantians, has never ceased to poison 
philosophy Once accustomed to consider scientific investiga¬ 
tion as essentially consisting m the study of umversals, men 
did not drop this habit of thought when they ceased to regard 
univeisals as possessing an independent existence and even 
those who went the length of considenng them as mere names, 
could not free themselves from the notion that the investiga¬ 
tion of tiuth consisted entirely or partly in some kind of con¬ 
juration or juggle with those names. When a philosopher 
adopted fully the Nominalist view of the signification of 
general language, retaining along with it the dictum de omm 
as the foundation of all reasoning, two such premises fairlv 
put together were likely, if he was a consistent thinker, to 
land him m rather startlm^conclusions Accordingly it has 
been seuously held, by wnters^of deserved celebuty, that the 
process of arriving at new truths by reasoning consists m the 
meie substitution of one, set of aibitrary signs for another, 
a doctrine which they suppose to deixve irresistible confirma¬ 
tion from the example of algebra. If there were any process 
lin sorcery or necromancy more preternatural than this, I 
^should he much surprised. The culminating point of this 
philosophy is the noted aphorism of Condillac, that a science 
is nothing, or scarcely anything, hut une langne hen faite , 
in other words, that the one sufficient rule for discovering the 
nature and properties of objects is to name them properly * as 
if the reverse were not the truth, that it is impossible to name 

13—2 



196 


REASONING. 


them propeily except m proportion as we aie already acquainted 
with their nature and properties Can it he necessaiy to say, 
that none, not even the most tuvial knowledge with respect 
to Things, ever was or could he ongmally got at hy any con¬ 
ceivable manipulation of mere names, as such; and that what 
can he learned from names, is only what somebody who used 
the names knew before ^ Philosophical analysis confirms the 
indication of common sense, that the function of names is hut 
that of enabling us to remember and to communicate our 
thoughts That they also strengthen, even to an incalculable 
extent, the power of thought itself, is most txue * but they do 
this by no mtunsic and peculiar virtue, they do it by the 
powei mheient in an artificial memory, an instrument of which 
few have adequately considered the immense potency. As an 
artificial memory, language truly is, what it has so often been 
called, an instrument of thought, but it is one thing to be the 
instrument, and another to be the exclusive subject upon which 
the instrument is exercised We think, indeed, to a consider¬ 
able extent, by means of names, but what we think of, are the 
things called by those names, and there cannot be a greater 
error than to imagine that thought can be earned on with 
nothing m our mind but names, or that we can make the 
names think for us. 

§ 3. Those who considered the dictum de omm as the 
foundation of the syllogism, looked upon arguments m a 
manner corresponding to the erroneous view which Hobbes 
took of propositions. Because theie are some propositions 
which are merely verbal, Hobbes, m order apparently that his 
definition might be ngoiously universal, defined a proposition 
as if no piopositions declaied anything except the meaning of 
words. If Hobbes was right, if no further account than this 
could be given of the import of piopositions, no theoiy could 
be given but the commonly received one, of the combination of 
propositions m a syllogism If the minor premise asserted 
nothing more than that something belongs to a class, and if 
the major premise asserted nothing of that class except that it 
is included m another class, the conclusion would only be 



RATIOCINATION; OR SYLLOGISM. 


197 


that what was included m the lower class is included m the 
higher, and the result, therefoie, nothing except that the classi¬ 
fication is consistent with itself. But we have seen that it 
is no sufficient account of the meaning of a pi ©position, to say 
that it i efers something to, 01 excludes something from, a class 
Every proposition which conveys real information asserts a 
matter of fact, dependent on the laws of nature, and not 
on classification It asserts that a given object does or 
does not possess a given attribute, or it asserts that two 
attributes, or sets of attributes, do or do not (constantly 
or occasionally) coexist Since such is the purport of all 
propositions which convey any real knowledge, and since 
ratiocination is a mode of acquiring real knowledge, any 
theory of ratiocination which does not recognise this 
import of propositions, cannot, we may be sure, be the true 
one. 

Applying this view of propositions to the two premises of 
a syllogism, we obtain the following results The major pre¬ 
mise, which, as already remarked, is always universal, asserts, 
that all things which have a certain attribute (or attributes) ? 
have or have not along with it, a certain other attribute 
(or attributes) The minor premise asserts that the thing 
or set of things which are the subject of that premise, have 
the first-mentioned attribute, and the conclusion is, that they 
have (or that they have not) the second. Thus m our former 
example. 

All men are mortal, 

Socrates is a man, 
therefore 

Socrates is mortal, 

the subject and predicate of the major premise are connotative 
terms, denoting objects and connoting attributes. The asser¬ 
tion m the major premise is, that along with one of the two 
sets of attributes, we always find the other that the attri¬ 
butes connoted by “man” never exist unless conjoined with 
the attribute called mortality The assertion m the minor 
premise is that the individual named Socrates possesses the 
former attributes, and it is concluded that he possesses also the 



198 


REASONING. 


attribute mortality. Or if both the premises are general pro¬ 
positions, as 

All men are mortal, 

All kings are men, 
therefore 

All kings are mortal, 

the minor piemise asseits that the attributes denoted by king- 
ship only exist m conjunction with those signified by the word 
man. The major asserts as before, that the last-mentioned 
attubutes are never found without the attnbute of mortality. 
The conclusion is, that wherever the attubutes ot kingship are 
found, that of moitality is found also 

If the majoi piemise weie negative, as, No men are omni¬ 
potent, it would asseit, not that the attubutes connoted by 
“man” nevei exist without, but that they never exist with, 
those connoted by “ omnipotent ” fiom which, together with 
the minor piemise, it is concluded, that the same incompati¬ 
bility exists between the attnbute omnipotence and those con¬ 
stituting a king. In a similar manner we might analyse 
any othei example of the syllogism 

If we geneialize this process, and look out for the prin¬ 
ciple or law involved m eveiy such inference, and piesupposed 
in every syllogism, the propositions of which aie anything more 
than merely verbal, we find, not the unmeaning dictum 
de omni et nullo, hut a fundamental principle, or lather two 
principles, stnkmgly resembling the axioms of mathematics. 
The first, which is the principle of affiunative syllogisms, 
is, that things which coexist with the same thing, coexist 
with one another. The second is the principle of negative 
syllogisms, and is to this effect. that a thing which coexists 
with another thing, with which other a thud thing does not 
coexist, is not coexistent with that third thing. These axioms 
manifestly ielate to facts, and not to conventions, and one or 
othei of them is the ground of the legitimacy of every argu¬ 
ment m which facts and not conventions are the matter 
treated of.* 

* Mr. Herbert Spencer [Pnncvples of Psychology, pp 125-7), though his 
theory of the syllogism coincides with all that is essential of mine, trunks it a 



RATIOCINATION, OR SYLLOGISM. 199 

§ 4 It remains to tian&late this exposition of the syllo¬ 
gism from the one into the other of the two languages in 


logical fallacy to present the two axioms m the text, as the regulating principles 
of syllogism He charges me with falling into the error pointed out by Arch¬ 
bishop Whately and myself, of confounding exact likeness with literal identity , 
and maintains, that we ought not to say that Sociates possesses the same attri¬ 
butes which are connoted by the word Man, but only that he possesses attri¬ 
butes exactly Uhe them according to which phraseology, Socrates, and the at¬ 
tribute mortality, are not two things coexisting with the same thing, as the 
axiom asseits, but two things coexisting with two different things 

The question between Mr Spencer and me is merely one of language, for 
neither of us (if I understand Mr Spencer’s opinions rightly) believes an attri¬ 
bute to be a real thing, possessed of objective existence, we believe it to be a 
particular mode of naming oui sensations, or our expectations of sensation, 
when looked at in their relation to an external object which excites them The 
question raised by Mr Spencer does not, therefore, concern the piopeities of 
any really existing thing, but the comparative appropriateness, for philosophical 
purposes, of two different modes of using a name Considered in this point of 
view, the phraseology I have employed, which is that commonly used by philo¬ 
sophers, seems to me to be the best Mi Spencer is of opinion that because 
Socrates and Alcibiades are not the same man, the attribute which constitutes 
them men should not be called the same attribute , that because the humanity 
of one man and that of another express themselves to our senses not by the 
same individual sensations but by sensations exactly alike, humanity ought to 
be regarded as a different attnbute m every diffeient man But on this 
showing, the humanity even of any one man should be considered as different 
attributes now and half-an-hour hence , foi the sensations by which it will then 
manifest itself to my organs will not be a continuation of my present sensations, 
but a lepetuion of them , fresh sensations, not identical with, but only exactly 
like the present If every geneial conception, instead of being “the One m the 
Many, 5 ’ were considered to be as many different conceptions as there are things 
to which it is applicable, tbeie would be no such thing as general language 
A name would have no general meaning if man connoted one thing when pre¬ 
dicated of John, and another, though closely resembling, thing when predicated 
of William. Accoidmgly a recent pamphlet asserts the impossibility of general 
knowledge on this precise ground. 

The meaning of any general name is some outward 01 inward phenomenon, 
consisting, m the lastresoit, of feelings , and these feelings, if their continuity 
is for an instant bioken, are no longer the same feelings, m the sense of indi¬ 
vidual identity. What, then, is the common something which gives a meaning 
to the general name ? Mr Spencer can only say, it is the similanty of the 
feelings , and I rejoin, the attnbute is precisely that similanty The names of 
attributes are m their ultimate analysis names for the lesemblances of out sen¬ 
sations (or other feelings) Every general name, whether abstract or conciete, 
denotes or-connotes one or more of those resemblances. It will not, probably, 



200 


REASONING. 


which we formerly remaiked 4 " that all propositions, and of 
course therefore all combinations of propositions, might be 
expressed We obsened that a proposition might be con¬ 
sidered m two different lights, as a portion of our knowledge 
of nature, or as a memorandum for our guidance Under the 
former, or speculative aspect, an affirmative general proposi¬ 
tion is an assertion of a speculative truth, viz that whatever 
has a certain attribute has a certain other attribute. Under 
the other aspect, it is to be regarded not as a part of our know¬ 
ledge, but as an aid for our practical exigencies, by enabling 
us, when we see or learn that an object possesses one of the 
two attnbutes, to infer that it possesses the other, thus em- 
plo}ung the fust attribute as a mark 01 evidence of the second 
Thus regarded, every syllogism comes within the following 
general formula — 

Attribute A is a mark of attribute B, 

The given object has the mark A, 
therefore 

The given object has the attribute B 
Referred to this type, the arguments which we have lately 


lie denied, that if a handled sensations aie undistmguishably alike, their resem¬ 
blance ought to be spoken of as one resemblance, and not a hundred resem¬ 
blances which merely resemble one another The things compared are many, 
but the somethmg common to all of them must be conceived as one, just as the 
name is conceived as one, though corresponding to numerically diffeient sensa¬ 
tions of sound each time it is pronounced The general term man does not 
connote the sensations derived once from one man, which, once gone, can no 
more occur again than the same flash of lightning It connotes the general type 
of the sensations derived always from all men, and the powei (always thought 
of as one) of pioducmg sensations of that type And the axiom might be thus 
worded Two types of sensation each of which coexists with a third type, 
coexist with another , or Two powers each of which coexists with a third power 
coexist with one another 

M r. Spencer has misunderstood me m anothei particular He supposes that 
the coexistence spoken of m the axiom, of two things with the same third 
thing, means simultaneousness m time The coexistence meant is that of being 
jointly attributes of the same subject The attribute of being bom without 
teeth, and the attribute of having thirty-two teeth m mature age, are m this 
sens** coexistent, both being attributes of man, though ex m tei mini never of 
the same man at the same time. 


* Supra, p. 128. 



RATIOCINATION., OR SYLLOGISM. 201 

cited as specimens of the syllogism, will express themselves m 
the following manner — 

The attributes of man are a maik of the attribute mortality, 
Sociates has the attubutes of man, 
therefore 

Socrates has the attubute moitality 
And again, 

The attubutes of man are a mark of the attribute mortality, 
The attubutes of a king are a mark of the attributes of man, 

therefore 

The attributes of a king are a mark of the attribute mortality 
And, lastly, 

The attubutes of man are a mark of the absence of the 
attribute omnipotence, 

The attubutes of a king aie a maik of the attubutes of man, 

therefore 

The attributes of a king aie a mark of the absence of the 
attribute signified by the word omnipotent 
(or, aie evidence of the absence of that attubute) 

To correspond with this alteration m the form of the 
syllogisms, the axioms on which the syllogistic process is 
founded must undergo a corresponding transformation In 
this altered phraseology, both those axioms may be brought 
under one general expression, namely, that whatever has any 
mark, has that which it is a mark of. Or, when the minor 
I premise as well as the major is universal, we may state it 
thus* Whatever is a mark of any mark, is a mark of that 
which this last is a mark of. To trace the identity of these 
axioms with those previously laid down, may be left to the 
intelligent reader We shall find, as we proceed, the great 
convenience of the phraseology into which we have last thrown 
them, and which is better adapted than any I am acquainted 
with, to express with precision and force what is aimed at, and 
actually accomplished, m every case of the ascertainment of 
a truth by ratiocination. 



CHAPTER III 


OF THE FUNCTIONS AND LOGICAL VALUE OF THE 
SYLLOGISM. 

§ I. We have shown what is the real nature of the truths 
with which the Syllogism is conversant, m contradistinction 
to the more superficial manner m which their impoit is con¬ 
ceived in the common theory, and what are the fundamental 
axioms on which its probative force or conclusiveness depends. 
We have now to inquire, whether the svllogistic process, that 
of reasoning from generals to particulars,, is, or is not, a pro¬ 
cess of inference, a progress fioin the known to the unknown . 
a means of coming to a knowledge of something which we did 
not know befoie. 

Logicians have been lemaikably unanimous m their mode 
of answering this question It is universally allowed that a 
syllogism is vicious if there be anything more m the conclu¬ 
sion than was assumed m the premises. But this is, m fact, 
to say, that nothing ever was, or can he, proved by syllogism, 
which was not known, or assumed to be known, before. Is 
ratiocination, then, not a process of inference 9 And is the 
syllogism, to which the word reasoning has so often been 
repiesented to be exclusively appropriate, not really entitled 
to be called reasoning at all 9 This seems an inevitable con¬ 
sequence of the doctrine, admitted by all writers on the 
subject, that a syllogism can prove no more than is involved 
m the premises. Yet the acknowledgment so explicitly made, 
has not prevented one set of writers fiom continuing to repre¬ 
sent the syllogism as the correct analysis of what the mmd 
actually performs m discovering and proving the larger half 
of the truths, whether of science or of daily life, which we 
believe, while those who have avoided this inconsistency, and 
followed out the general theoiem respecting the logical value 



FUNCTIONS AND VALUE OF THE SYLLOGISM. 203 

of the syllogism to its legitimate corollary, have been led to 
impute uselessness and fiivohty to the syllogistic tlieoiy itself, 
on the ground of the petitio pnncipn winch they allege to be 
inherent m every syllogism. As I believe both these opinions 
to be fundamentally erroneous, I must request the attention 
of the readei to certain considerations, without which any just 
appreciation of the true character of the syllogism, and the 
functions it peifoims m philosophy, appears to me impossible , 
hut which seem to have been either overlooked, or insufficiently 
adverted to, both by the defenders of the syllogistic theory and 
by its assailants. 

§ 2. It must be gi anted that m every syllogism, con¬ 
sidered as an argument to prove the conclusion, there is a 
petitio pnncipn, When we say. 

All men are mortal, 

Socrates is a man, 
therefore 

Socrates is mortal, 

it is unanswerably urged by the adversaries of the syllogistic 
theoiy, that the proposition, Socrates is mortal, is presupposed 
m the more general assumption, All men are mortal that we 
cannot be assured of the mortality of all men, unless we are 
already ceitam of the mortality of every individual man * that 
if it be still doubtful whether Sociates, or any other individual 
w*e choose to name, be mortal or not, the same degree of un¬ 
certainty must hang over the assertion, All men are mortal: 
that the general pnnciple, instead of being given as evidence 
of the particular case, cannot itself be taken foi tiue without 
exception, until every shadow of doubt which could affect any 
case comprised with it, is dispelled by evidence ahundS , and 
then what remains for the syllogism to prove ? That, m 
short, no reasoning from generals to particulars can, as such, 
prove anything. since from a general principle we cannot 
infer any particulars, but those which the principle itself 
assumes as known. 

This doctrine appears to me irrefragable, and if logicians, 



204 


REASONING. 


though unable to dispute it, have usually exhibited a strong 
disposition to explain it away, this was not because they could 
discover any flaw m the argument itself, but because the 
contrary opinion seemed to rest on arguments equally indis¬ 
putable In the syllogism last referred to, for example, or 
m any of those which we previously constructed, is it not 
evident that the conclusion may, to the person to whom the 
syllogism is presented, be actually and bond fide a new truth ? 
Is it not matter of daily experience that truths previously 
unthought of, facts which have not been, and cannot be, 
directly observed, are arrived at by way of general reason¬ 
ing? We believe that the Duke of Wellington is mortal. 
We do not know this by dnect observation, so long as he is 
not yet dead If we weie asked how, this being the case, we 
know the duke to be mortal, we should probably answer, 
Because all men are so Here, therefore, we arrive at the 
knowledge of a truth not (as yet) susceptible of observation, by 
a reasoning which admits of bemg exhibited m the following 
syllogism 

All men are mortal, 

The Duke of Wellington is a man, 
therefore 

The Duke of Wellington is mortal 

And since a large portion of our knowledge is thus acquired, 
logicians have persisted m representing the syllogism as a 
process of inference or proof; though none of them has cleared 
up the difficulty which arises from the inconsistency between 
that assertion, and the principle, that if there be anything m 
the conclusion which was not already asserted m the pre¬ 
mises, the argument is vicious For it is impossible to attach 
any serious scientific value to such a mere salvo, as the dis¬ 
tinction drawn between being involved by implication in the 
premises, and being directly asserted m them. When Arch¬ 
bishop Whately says* that the object of reasoning is <e merely 
to expand and unfold the assertions wrapt up, as it were, and 
implied m those with which we set out, and to bring a person 


Logic , p 239 (9th ed ) 



FUNCTIONS AND VALUE OF THE SYLLOGISM. 205 

6 

to perceive and acknowledge tlie full force of that wi&ph. he 
has admitted/’ he does not, I think, meet the real difficulty^ 
qunmg to be explained, namely, how it happens that a science, ^ 
like geometry, can he all “ wrapt up” m a few definitions and 
axioms. Nor does this defence of the syllogism differ much 
from what its assailants urge against it as an accusation, 
when they chaige it with being of no use except to those who 
seek to press the consequences of an admission into which a 
person has been entrapped without having considered and 
understood its full force When you admitted the major 
premise, you asseited the conclusion, but, says Aichbishop 
Whately, you asserted it by implication merely this, how¬ 
ever, can heie only mean that you asseited it unconsciously, 
that you did not know you were asserting it, but, if so, the 
difficulty revives m this shape —Ought you not to have 
known ? Were you wan anted m asserting the general pro¬ 
position without having satisfied yourself of the truth of 
everything which it fairly includes ? And if not, is not the 
syllogistic art jprima facie what its assailants affirm it to be, 
a contrivance for catching you m a trap, and holding you 
fast m it 

§ 3. From this difficulty there appears to be but one 
issue. The proposition that the Duke of Wellington is 
mortal, is evidently an inference, it is got at as a conclusion 


* It is hardly necessary to say, that I am not contending for any such 
absurdity as that we actually “ought to have known” and considered the case 
of every individual man, past, present, and future, before affirming that all men 
are mortal although this interpretation has been, strangely enough, put upon 
the preceding observations There is no diffei ence between me and Archbishop 
"Whately, 01 any other defender of the syllogism, on the practical part of the 
matter , I am only pointing out an inconsistency m the logical theory of it, as 
conceived by almost all writers I do not say that a person who affirmed, be¬ 
fore the Duke of Wellington was born, that all men are mortal, Tenm that the 
Duke of Wellington was mortal, but I do say that he asserted it, and I ask 
for an explanation of the apparent logical fallacy, of adducing m proof of the 
Duke of Wellington’s moitality, a general statement which piesupposes it. 
Finding no sufficient resolution of this difficulty m any of the writers on Logic, 
I have attempted to supply one 



206 


REASONING. 


from something else; but do we, m reality, conclude it from 
the proposition, All men are moital ? I answer, no 

The eiror committed is, I conceive, that of overlooking 
the distinction between two paits of the process of philo¬ 
sophizing, the infen mg part, and the legistermg part ^ and 
ascribing to the latter the functions of the former. The 
mistake is that of referring a peison to his own notes for 
the origin of his knowledge. If a person is asked a question, 
and is at the moment unable to answer it, he may refresh 
his memory by turning to a memorandum which he carries 
about with him But if he were asked, how the fact came 
to his knowledge, he would scarcely answer, because it was 
set down m his note-hook unless the hook was written, 
like the Koran, with a quill from the wing of the angel 
Gabriel 

Assuming that the proposition, The Duke of Wellington 
is mortal, is immediately an inference from the proposition, 
All men are mortal; whence do we derive our knowledge of 
that general truth ? Of course fiom observation Now, all 
which man can observe are individual cases From these all 
general truths must he drawn, and into these they may he 
again resolved , for a general truth is but an aggregate of 
particular truths, a comprehensive expiession, by which an 
indefinite number of individual facts are affirmed or denied 
at once But a general proposition is not merely a com¬ 
pendious form for recording and preseivmg m the memory 
a number of paiticular facts, all of which have been observed. 
Generalization is not a process of mere naming, it is also a 
process of inference. From instances which we have ob¬ 
served, we feel warranted m concluding, that what we found 
true m those instances, holds m all similar ones, past, 
present, and fatuie, however numerous they may he We 
then, hv that valuable contrivance of language which enables 
us to speak of many as if they were one, record all that we 
have observed, together with all that we infer from out 
observations, in one concise expression, and have thus only 
one proposition, instead of an endless number, to remember 
or to communicate. The results of many observations and 



FUNCTIONS AND VALUE OF THE SYLLOGISM 207 

inferences, and mstiuctions for making innumerable infe¬ 
rences m unforeseen cases, are compressed into one short 
sentence. 

When, therefore, we conclude from the death of John and 
Thomas, and eveiy other person we ever heard of m whose 
case the experiment had been fairly tried, that the Duke of 
Wellington is mortal like the rest, we may, indeed, pass 
through the geneialization, All men are mortal, as an inter¬ 
mediate stage , but it is not in the latter half of the process, 
the descent from all men to the Duke of Wellington, that 
the inference lesides. The inference ls finished when we 
have asserted that all men are mortal. What remains to 
be performed afterwards is merely decyphenng our own 
notes 

Aichbishop Whately has contended that syllogizing, or 
reasoning fiom geneials to particulars, is not, agreeably to 
the vulgar idea, a peculiar mode of reasoning, but the philo¬ 
sophical anal} sis of the mode m which all men reason, and 
must do so if they reason at all With the deference due 
to so high an authority, I cannot help thinking that the 
vulgar notion is, m this case, the more coirect If, from our 
experience of John, Thomas, &c, who once were living, but 
are now dead, we aie entitled to conclude that all human 
hemgs are mortal, we might surely without any logical incon¬ 
sequence have concluded at once from those instances, 
that the Duke of Wellington is mortal The mortality of 
John, Thomas, and company is, after all, the whole evidence 
we have for the mortality of the Duke of Wellington Not 
one iota is added to the pioof by interpolating a general pro¬ 
position. Since the individual cases are all the evidence we 
can possess, evidence which no logical form into which we 
choose to throw it can make greater than it is , and since 
that evidence is either sufficient in itself, or, if insufficient 
for the one purpose, cannot he sufficient for the other, I am 
unable to see why we should be forbidden to take the shortest 
cut from these sufficient premises to the conclusion, and con¬ 
strained to travel the “ high pnoii road," by the arbitrary 
fiat of logicians I cannot peiceive why it should be impos- 



208 


REASONING. 


sible to journey from "one place to another unless we tfc maich 
up a hill, and then maich down again ” It may be the safest 
road, and theie may he a lestmg-place at the top of the lull, 
affording a commanding view of the surioundmg countiy , 
hut foi the meie purpose of arriving at our journey’s end, oui 
taking that road is perfectly optional, it is a question of time, 
tiouble, and danger 

Not only may we reason from paiticulars to paiticulars 
without passing thiough generals, but we perpetually do so 
reason. All our eailiest mfeiences are of this nature Fiona 
the first dawn of intelligence we diaw inferences, but yeais 
elapse befoie we learn the use of geneial language. The 
child, who, having burnt his fingers, avoids to thiust them 
again into the fire, has reasoned 01 inlWied, though he has 
nevei thought of the general maxim. Fire bums He knows 
from memory that he has been burnt, and on this evidence 
believes, when he sees a candle, that if he puts his finger into 
the flame of it, he will be burnt again He believes this m 
every case which happens to arise, but without looking, m 
each instance, beyond the present case. He is not geneializmg, 
he is infemng a particular from paiticulars In the same 
way, also, brutes reason There is no ground for attiibutmg 
to any of the lower animals the use of signs, of such a nature 
as to render geneial propositions possible But those animals 
profit by expenence, and avoid what they have found to cause 
them pam, m the same manner, though not always with the 
same skill, as a human creatuie Not only the burnt child, 
but the burnt dog, dreads the fire. 

I believe that, m point of fact, when drawing inferences 
from our personal expenence, and not from maxims handed 
down to us by books or tradition, we much oftener conclude 
from particular to particulars directly, than thiough the 
intermediate agency of any geneial proposition. We are 
constantly reasoning from oui selves to other people, or from 
one person to another, without giving ouiselves the trouble 
to erect our observations into general maxims of human or 
external nature When we conclude that some person will, 
on some given occasion, feel or act so and so, we sometimes 



FUNCTIONS AND VALUE OF THE SYLLOGISM. £09 

judge from an enlarged consideration of the manner m which 
human beings m geneial, or peisons of some particular cha¬ 
racter, are accustomed to feel and act hut much oftener from 
merely recollecting the feelings and conduct of the same 
person m some pievious instance, or fiom considering how we 
should feel or act ourselves It is not only the village 
matron, who, when called to a consultation upon the case of 
a neighbour’s child, pronounces on the evil and its remedy 
simply on the recollection and authority of vhat she accounts 
the similar case of her Lucy. We all, where we have no 
definite maxims to steer by, guide ourselves m the same 
way and if we have an extensive experience, and retain its 
impressions strongly, we may acquire m tins manner a very 
considerable power of accurate judgment, which we may he 
utterly incapable of justifying or of communicating to others 
Among the higher order of practical intellects there have 
been many of whom it was remarked how admirably they 
suited then means to their ends, without being able to give 
any sufficient reasons for what they did, and applied, or 
seemed to apply, recondite pnnciples which they were 
wholly ucable to state. This is a natural consequence of 
having a mind stored with appropriate particulars, and 
having been long accustomed to reason at once from these 
to fresh particulars, without practising the habit of stating to 
oneself or to others the corresponding general propositions 
An old wamor, on a rapid glance at the outlines of the 
ground, is able at once to give the necessary orders for a 
skilful arrangement of his troops, though if he has received 
little theoretical msti action, and has seldom been called 
upon to answei to other people for his conduct, he may 
never have had m his mind a single general theorem 
respecting the relation between ground and array. But his 
experience of encampments, m cncumstances more or less 
similar, has left a number of vivid, unexpressed, ungeneral- 
ized analogies m his mind, the most appropriate of which, 
instantly suggesting itself, determines him to a judicious 
arrangement 

The skill of an uneducated person m the use of weapons, 
VOL. i. H 



£10 


REASONING. 


or of tools, is of a precisely similar nature. The savage who 
executes unerringly the exact throw which brings down his 
game, or his enemy, m the manner most suited to his purpose, 
under the operation of all the conditions necessarily involved, 
the weight and foim of the weapon, the direction and distance 
of the object, the action of the wind, &c, owes this power 
to a long series of previous experiments, the results of which 
he certainly never framed into any veibal theorems 01 rules. 
The same thing may generally he said of any other extraor¬ 
dinary manual dexterity. Not long ago a Scotch manufacturer 
piocuied from England, at a high rate of wages, a working 
dyer, famous for producing very fine colouis, with the view 
of teaching to his other workmen the same skill The work¬ 
man came , but his mode of piopoitionmg the ingredients, 
in which lay the secret of the effects he produced, was by 
taking them up m handfuls, while the common method was to 
weigh them. The manufactuier sought to make him turn his 
handling system into an equivalent weighing system, that the 
general pnnciple of his peculiar mode of pioceedmg might 
he ascertained This, howevei, the man found himself quite 
unable to do, and therefore could impart his skill to nobody. 
He had, from the individual cases of his own expenence, 
established a connexion m his mind between fine effects of 
colour, and tactual perceptions m handling his dyeing 
materials, and from these peiceptions he could, m any par¬ 
ticular case, infer the means to be employed, and the effects 
which would be produced, hut could not put others m pos¬ 
session of the grounds on which he proceeded, from having 
never generalized them m his own mind, 01 expressed them 
m language. 

Almost every one knows Lord Mansfield’s advice to a 
man of practical good sense, who, being appointed governor 
of a colony, had to preside m its court of justice, without 
previous judicial practice or legal education The advice 
was to give his decision boldly, for it would probably be 
right, but never to venture on assigning reasons, for they 
would almost infallibly he wrong In cases like this, which 
are of no uncommon occurrence, it would be absurd to sup- 



FUNCTIONS AND VALUE OF THE SYLLOGISM. 211 

pose that the had reason was the souice of the good decision. 
Lord Mansfield knew that if any reason were assigned it 
would he necessarily an afterthought, the judge being m fact 
guided hy impressions from past experience, without the 
circuitous piocess of framing general principles from them, 
and that if he attempted to fiame any such he would 
assuredly fail Loid Mansfield, however, would not have 
doubted that a man of equal expeiience who had also a 
mind stoied with general piopositions derived hy legitimate 
induction from that experience, would have been gieatly pre¬ 
ferable as a judge, to one, howevei sagacious, who could not 
be trusted with the explanation and justification of his own 
judgments The cases of men of talent peiformmg wonderful 
things they know not how, aie examples of the rudest and 
most spontaneous form of the operations of supenor minds. 

It is a defect m them, and often a source of errors, not to 
have generalized as they went on , but generalization, though 
a help, the most important indeed of all helps, is not an 
essential 

Even the scientifically instructed, who possess, m the form 
of general propositions, a systematic record of the results of the 
experience of mankind, need not always 1 evert to those general 
propositions m order to apply that experience to a new case. 

It is justly remarked by Dugald Stewart, that though the 
reasonings m mathematics depend entirely on the axioms, it is 
by no means necessary to our seeing the conclusiveness of the 
proof, that the axioms should be expressly adverted to When , 
it is inferred that AB is equal to CD because each of them is * 
equal to EF, the most uncultivated understanding, as soon as j 
the propositions were understood, would assent to the in¬ 
ference, without having ever heard of the general truth that 
“ things which are equal to the same thing are equal to one 
another.” This remark of Stewart, consistently followed out, 
goes to the root, as I conceive, of the philosophy of ratiocina¬ 
tion , and it is to be regretted that he himself stopt short 
at a much more limited application of it He saw that the 
general propositions on which a reasoning is said to depend, 
may, m certain cases, be altogether omitted, without impairing 

14—2 



REASONING. 


2B 

its probative force. But be imagined tbis to be a peculiarity 
belonging to axioms ; and aigued from it, that axioms are not 
the foundations 01 first principles of geometry, from which all 
the other truths of the science are synthetically deduced (as 
the laws of motion and of the composition of foices m dyna¬ 
mics, the equal mobility of fluids m hydrostatics, the laws of 
reflection and refraction m optics, are the first principles of 
those sciences) , hut aie merely necessary assumptions, self- 
evident indeed, and the denial of which would annihilate all 
demonstration, but from which, as premises, nothing can be 
demonsti ated. In the present, as m many other instances, 
this thoughtful and elegant writer has perceived an important 
truth, but only by halves. Finding, m the case of geometrical 
axioms, that general names have not any talismamc virtue forf 
conjuring new tiuths out of the well where they lie hid, and not I 
seeing that this is equally true m every other case of generali¬ 
sation, he contended that axioms aie in their natuie bairen of 
consequences, and that the really fruitful truths, the real first 
principles of geometry, aie the definitions , that the definition, 
for example, of the circle is to the properties of the circle, what 
the laws of equilibrium and of the pressure of the atmosphere 
are to the rise of the mercury in the Torricellian tube Yet 
all that he had asserted respecting the function to wdnch the 
axioms are confined m the demonstrations of geometry, holds 
equally tiue of the definitions. Every demonstration m Euclid 
might be carried on without them This is apparent from the 
ordinary piocess of proving a proposition of geometry by means 
of a diagram What assumption, m fact, do we set out from, 
to demonstrate by a dragram any of the properties of the 
circle ? Not that in all circles the radii are equal, hut only 
that they aie so m the circle ABC. As our warrant for 
assuming this, we appeal, it is true, to the definition of a circle 
in. general, but it is only necessary that the assumption be 
granted m the case of the particular circle supposed From 
this, which is not a general hut a singular proposition, com¬ 
bined with other propositions of a similar kind, some of which 
when generalized are called definitions, and others axioms, we 
pro\e that a certain conclusion is true, not of all circles, but 



FUNCTIONS AND VALUE OF THE SYLLOGISM. 213 


of the particular cncle ABC , or at least would he so, if the 
facts precisely accoided with our assumptions. The enuncia¬ 
tion, as it is called, that is, the general theoiem which stands 
at the head of the demonsti ation, is not the proposition 
actually demonstrated. One instance only is demonstrated. 
hut the process by which this is done, is a process which, 
when we consider its natuie, we perceive might he exactly 
copied m an indefinite number of other instances ; in every 
instance which conforms to certain conditions The con¬ 
trivance of general language furnishing us with terms which 
connote these conditions, we are able to assert this indefinite 
multitude of tiuths m a single expression, and this expression 
is the general theoiem By dropping the use of diagrams, and 
substituting, m the demonstrations, general phiases for the 
letters of the alphabet, we might prove the general theorem 
directly, that is, we might demonstrate all the cases at once, 
and to do this we must, of couise, employ as out piemises, the 
axioms and definitions m their general form But this only 
means, that if we can prove an individual conclusion by assum¬ 
ing an individual fact, then m whatever case we are warranted 
m making an exactly similar assumption, we may draw an 
exactly similar conclusion. The definition is a sort of notice 
to ourselves and others, what assumptions we think ourselves 
entitled to make. And so m all cases, the genei al propositions, 
whether called definitions, axioms, or laws of nature, which we 
lay down at the beginning of our reasonings, are merely 
abridged statements, m a kind of short-hand, of the parti¬ 
cular facts, which, as occasion arises, we either think we may 
proceed on as proved, or intend to assume In any one de¬ 
monstration it is enough if we assume for a particular case 
suitably selected, what by the statement of the definition or 
principle we announce that we intend to assume m all cases 
which may arise The definition of the circle, therefore, is to 
one of Euclid's demonstrations, exactly what, according to 
Stewart, the axioms are, that is, the demonstration does not 
depend on it, but yet if we deny it the demonstration fails. The 
proof does not rest on the general assumption, hut on a similar 
assumption confined to the particular case : that case, however* 



214 


REASONING. 


being- chosen as a specimen or paradigm of the whole class of 
cases included m the theoiem, there can be no giound foi 
making the assumption m that case which does not exist 
m every other, and to deny the assumption as a general 
truth, is to deny the right of making it m the particulai 
instance 

Theie are, undoubtedly, the most ample reasons for stating 
both the principles and the theorems m their general form, 
and these will be explained presently, so far as explanation is 
requisite. But, that unpractised learners, even m making use 
of one theoiem to demonstiate another, reason rather from 
particular to particular than from the general proposition, is 
manifest from the difficulty they find m applying a theorem 
to a case m which the configuration of the diagram is 
extremely unlike that of the diagram by which the original 
theorem was demonstrated. A difficulty which, except m 
cases of unusual mental power, long piactice can alone 
lemove, and lemoves chiefly by rendenng us familiar with all 
the configurations consistent with the general conditions of the 
theorem 

§ 4 Biom the considerations now adduced, the following 
conclusions seem to he established. All inference is from par- 
^ ticulars to particulars General propositions are merely regis¬ 
ters of such inferences already made, and short formulae for 
making more The major premise of a syllogism, conse¬ 
quently, is a formula of this description and the conclusion 
is not an inference diawn fiom the formula, but an inference 
drawn according to the formula the real logical antecedent, 
f or premise, being the paiticular facts from which the geneial 
| proposition was collected by induction. Those facts, and the 
individual instances which supplied them, may have been for¬ 
gotten , but a record remains, not indeed descriptive of the 
facts themselves, hut showing how those cases may be distin¬ 
guished, respecting which the facts, when known, were consi¬ 
dered to warrant a given inference. According to the indica¬ 
tions of this record we draw our conclusion , which is, to all 
intents and purposes, a conclusion from the forgotten facts. 



FUNCTIONS AND VALUE OF THE SYLLOGISM. £15 


For tins it is essential that we should read the record conectly 
and the rules of the syllogism are a set of piecautions to ensure 
our doing so 

This view of the functions of the syllogism is confirmed 
by the consideration of precisely those cases which might be 
expected to be least favourable to it, namely, those m which 
ratiocination is independent of any previous induction We 
have already obseived that the syllogism, m the ordinary 
course of oui leasonmg, is only the lattei half of the process 
of travelling from premises to a conclusion There are, how¬ 
ever, some peculiar cases m which it is the whole piocess 
Particulars alone are capable of being subjected to observation , 
and all knowledge which is derived from observation, begins, 
therefore, of necessity, in particulars , but oui knowledge may, 
m cases of certain descuptions, be conceived as coming to us 
from other sources than observation It may present itself as 
coming from testimony, which, on the occasion and for the 
purpose m hand, is accepted as of an authoritative character. 
and the information thus communicated, may be conceived to 
comprise not only particular facts but general propositions, as 
when a scientific doctrine is accepted without examination on 
the authority of writers, or a theological doctrine on that of 
Scripture. Or the generalization may not be, m the ordinary 
sense, an assertion at all, but a command, a law, not m the 
philosophical, but m the moral and political sense of the term - 
an expression of the desire of a superior, that we, or any 
number of othei persons, shall conform our conduct to certain 
general mstiuctions. So far as this asserts a fact, namely, a 
volition of the legislator, that fact is an individual fact, and the 
proposition, therefore, is not a general proposition But the 
description therein contained of the conduct which it is the 
will of the legislator that his subjects should observe, is general. 
The proposition asserts, not that all men are anything, but 
that all men shall do something. 

In both these cases the generalities are the original data, 
and the particulars are elicited from them by a process which 
correctly resolves itself into a senes of syllogisms. The real 
nature, however, of the supposed deductive process, is evident 



216 


REASONING 


enough. The only point to he deteimmecl is, whether the 
authority which declared the general proposition, intended 
to Include this case m it, and whethei the legislator intended 
his command to apply to the piesent case among others, or 
not This is ascertained hy examining whethei the case pos¬ 
sesses the marks hy which, as those authorities have signified, 
the cases which they meant to certify or to influence may he 
known. The object of the inquiry is to make out the wit¬ 
ness’s or the legislator’s intention, thiough the indication 
given by their words. This is a question, as the Germans 
express it, of hermeneutics The operation is not a process 
of inference, but a process of interpretation 

In tWs last piua&c tfe have oh tamed an expression which 
j-ppears to me to chaiactenze, more aptly than any other, the 
functions of the syllogism in all cases When the premises 
are given by authority, the function of Reasoning is to ascer¬ 
tain the testimony of a witness, or the will of a legislator, hy 
interpreting the signs m which the one has intimated his 
assertion and the other his command In like manner, when 
the premises are derived from observation, the function of 
Reasoning is to ascertain what we (or our predecessors) 
formerly thought might be inferred from the observed facts, 
and to do this by interpreting a memorandum of ouis, or of 
theirs The memorandum reminds us, that from evidence, 
more or less carefully weighed, it formerly appeared that a 
certain attribute might be inferred wbeiever we perceive a 
certain mark The proposition, All men are moital (for 
instance) shows that we have had experience from which we 
thought it followed that the attributes connoted by the term 
man, are a mark of mortality But when we conclude that 
the Duke of Wellington is mortal, we do not infer this from 
the memorandum, but from the former experience All that 
we infer from the memorandum is our own pievious belief, 
(or that of those who transmitted to us the pioposition), con¬ 
cerning the inferences which that former experience would 
warrant 

This view of the nature of the syllogism renders con¬ 
sistent and intelligible what otherwise remains obscure and 



FUNCTIONS AND VALUE OF THE SYLLOGISM. 217 

confused in the theory of Archbishop Whately and other 
enlightened defenders of the syllogistic doctrine, respecting 
the limits to -which its functions are confined They affirm m 
as explicit teims as can be used, that the sole office of general 
reasoning is to pi event inconsistency m our opinions, to pre¬ 
vent us fiom assenting to anything, the truth of which would 
contiadict something to which we had pre\iously on good 
grounds given ~our assent And they tell us, that the sole 
ground which a syllogism affords for assenting to the conclu¬ 
sion, is that the supposition of its being false, combined with 
the supposition that the piemises are true, would lead to a 
contradiction m terms Now this would be but a lame 
account of the real giounds which we have for believing the 
facts which we learn fiom reasoning, m contradistinction to 
observation The true reason why we believe that the Duke 
of Wellington will die, is that his fathers, and our fathers, 
and all other peisons who were cotemporaiy with them, have 
died Those facts are the leal piemises of the reasoning But 
we are not led to infer the conclusion from those piemises, 
by the necessity of avoiding any verbal inconsistency There 
is no contradiction m supposing that all those persons have 
died, and that the Duke of Wellington may, notwithstand¬ 
ing, live for ever But there would be a contradiction if we 
first, on the ground of those same premises, made a general 
assertion including and covering the case of the Duke of 
Wellington, and then refused to stand to it m the individual 
case There is an inconsistency to be avoided between the 
memorandum we make of the inferences which may be justly 
drawn m future cases, and the inferences we actually draw m 
those cases when they arise With this view we interpret our 
own formula, precisely as a judge interprets a law m order 
that we may avoid diawing any inferences not conformable to 
our former intention, as a judge avoids giving any decision 
not conformable to the legislator s intention. The rules for 
this interpretation are the rules of the syllogism . and its 
sole purpose is to maintain consistency between the conclu¬ 
sions we draw m eveiy particular case, and the previous 
general duections for drawing them, whether those general 



218 


REASONING. 


directions were framed by ourselves as the result of induction, 
or were received by us from an authority competent to give 
them. 

§ 5 In the above observations it has, I think, been 
shown, that, though there is always a process of reasoning or 
inference where a syllogism is used, the syllogism is not a 
correct analysis of that process of reasoning or mfeience, which 
is, on the contrary, (when not a mere inference from testi¬ 
mony) an inference from particulars to paiticulais, autho- 
nzed by a previous mfeience fiom particulars to generals, 
and substantially the same with it, of the nature, therefore, 
of Induction. But while these conclusions appear to me un¬ 
deniable, I must yet enter a protest, as strong as that of 
Archbishop Whately himself, against the doctune that the 
.syllogistic art is useless for the purposes of reasoning. The 
reasoning lies m the act of generalization, not m mteipretmg 
the recoid of that act, but the syllogistic foim is an indis¬ 
pensable collateral security for the correctness of the gene¬ 
ralization itself 

It has already been seen, that if we have a collection of 
particulars sufficient for grounding an induction, we need not 
frame a general proposition, we may reason at once from 
those particulars to other particular But it is to he re¬ 
marked withal, that whenever, from a set of particular cases, 
we can legitimately diaw any inference, we may legitimately 
make oui inference a general one. If, from observation and 
experiment, we can conclude to one new case, so may we to 
an indefinite number If that which has held true m our past 
experience will therefoi e hold m time to come, it will hold not 
merely m some individual case, hut m all cases of some given 
description Every induction, therefore, which suffices to 
prove one fact, proves an indefinite multitude of facts the 
experience which justifies a single prediction must he such as 
will suffice to bear out a general theorem. This theorem it is 
extremely important to ascertain and declare, m its broadest 
form of generality , and thus to place before our mmds, in its 



FUNCTIONS AND VALUE OF THE SYLLOGISM. 219 

full extent, the whole of what our evidence must prove if it 
proves anything 

This throwing of the whole body of possible inferences 
from a given set of particulars, into one general expression* 
operates as a security for then being just inferences, m more 
ways than one Bust, the general principle presents a larger 
object to the imagination than any of the singular proposi¬ 
tions which it contains. A process of thought which leads to 
a comprehensive generality, is felt as of greater importance 
than one which terminates m an insulated fact, and the mind 
is, even unconsciously, led to bestow greater attention upon 
the process, and to weigh more carefully the sufficiency of the 
experience appealed to, for supporting the inference grounded 
upon it. There is another, and a moie important, advantage. 
In reasoning from a course of individual observations to some 
new and unobserved case, which we are but imperfectly 
acquainted with (or we should not be inquiring into it), and 
m which, since we aie inquiring into it* we probably feel a 
peculiar interest, there is very little to prevent us from giving 
way to negligence, or to any bias which may affect our wishes 
or our imagination, and, under that influence, accepting in¬ 
sufficient evidence as sufficient. But if, instead of concluding 
straight to tlie particular case* we place before ourselves an 
entire class of facts—the whole contents of a general proposi¬ 
tion, every tittle of which is legitimately inferrible from our 
premises, if that one particular conclusion is so , theie is then 
a considerable likelihood that if the premises are insufficient, 
and the general inference, therefore, groundless, it will com¬ 
prise within it some fact or facts the reverse of which we 
already know to be true , and we shall thus discover the error 
m our generahzation by a reductio acl impossibile. 

Thus if* during the reign of Marcus Aurelius, a subject of 
the Roman empire, under the bias natui ally given to the 
imagination and expectations by the lives and characters of 
the Antomnes, had been disposed to expect that Commodus 
would be a just ruler, supposing him to stop there* he might 
only have been undeceived by sad experience. But if he 



220 


REASONING. 


reflected that this expectation could not he justifiable unless 
from the same evidence he was warranted m concluding 
some general proposition, as, for instance, that all Roman 
emperors are just rulers , he would immediately have thought 
of Nero, Domitian, and other instances, which, showing the 
falsity of the geneial conclusion, and therefore the insufficiency 
of the piemises, would have warned him that those premises 
could not prove in the instance of Commodus, what they were 
inadequate to prove in any collection of cases m which his was 
included. 

The advantage, m judging whethei any controverted in¬ 
ference is legitimate, of referring to a parallel case, is univer¬ 
sally acknowledged. But by ascending to the general propo¬ 
sition, we bung under our view not one parallel case only, but 
all possible parallel cases at once, all cases to which the same 
set of eudentiaiv considerations are applicable. 

When, therefore, we argue from a number of known cases 
to another case supposed to be analogous, it is always possible, 
and generally advantageous, to diveit oui argument into the 
circuitous channel of an induction from those known cases to 
a general proposition, and a subsequent application of that 
general pioposition to the unknown case This second part of 
the opeiation, which, as before observed, is essentially a pro¬ 
cess of interpretation, will be resolvable into a syllogism or a 
series of syllogisms, the majois of which will be general pro¬ 
positions embracing whole classes of cases, every one of which 
propositions must be true m all its extent, if the argument is 
maintainable If, therefore, any fact fairly coming within the 
range of one of these general propositions, and consequently 
t asserted by it, is known 01 suspected to be other than the 
proposition asserts it to be, this mode of stating the argument 
causes us to know or to suspect that the original observations, 
which are the real grounds of our conclusion, are not sufficient 
to suppoit it And m proportion to the gi eater chance of oui 
detecting the mconclusiveness of our evidence, will he the 
increased reliance we aie entitled to place m it if no such 
evidence of defect shall appear 

The value, therefore, of the syllogistic form, and of the 



FUNCTIONS AND VALUE OF THE SYLLOGISM. 221 


rales for using it correctly, does not consist m their being 
the form and the rules according to which our reasonings 
are necessarily, or even usually, made, hut m their furnishing 
us with a mode m which those reasonings may always be 
represented, and which is admuably calculated, if they are 
inconclusive, to bring their mconclusiveness to light. An 
induction from particulars to generals, followed by a syllo¬ 
gistic process from those generals to other particular, is a 
form m which we may always state our reasonings if we 
please It is not a form m which we must leason, hut it is 
a form m which we may reason, and into which it is indis¬ 
pensable to thiow our reasoning, when theie is any doubt of 
its validity though when the case is familial and little com¬ 
plicated, and theie is no suspicion of error, we may, and do, 
reason at once from the known particular cases to unknown 
ones * 

These are the uses of syllogism, as a mode of verifying 
any given argument Its ulterior uses, as respects the general 
course of our intellectual opeiations, hardly require illustra¬ 
tion, being m fact the acknowledged uses of general language. 
They amount substantially to this, that the inductions may 
he made once for all a single careful interrogation of expe¬ 
rience may suffice, and the result may be registered in-the 
form of a general proposition, which is committed to memory 
or to writing, and fiom which afterwards we have only to 
syllogize The paiticulais of our expenments may then be 
dismissed fiom the memoiy, in which it would be impossible 
to retain so gieat a multitude of details, while the knowledge 
which those details afforded for future use, and which would 
otherwise he lost as soon as the observations were foigotten, 

* The language of 1 atiocmation would, I think, he brought into closer agree¬ 
ment with the real nature of the piocess, if the general propositions employed 
m reasoning, instead of being in the form All men are mortal, or Every man is 
mortal, were e\pi esse i m the form Any man is moi tal This mode of expression, 
exhibiting as the type of all reasoning fiom experience “The men A, B, G, &c. 
are so and so, therefore any man is so and s*>,” would much better manifest the 
true idea—that inductive reasoning is always, at bottom, mfeience from pai- 
ticulars to particulars, and that the whole function of geneial propositions ra 
reasoning, is to vouch foi the legitimacy of such inferences 



222 


REASONING. 


or as their record became too bulky for reference, is retained 
m a commodious and immediately available shape by means 
of general language. 

Against this advantage is to be set the countervailing 
inconvenience, that mfeiences originally made on insufficient 
evidence, become consecrated, and, as it were, hardened into 
general maxims , and the mind cleaves to them from habit, 
after it has outgrown any liability to be misled by similar 
fallacious appealances if they were now for the first time pre¬ 
sented , but having forgotten the paiticulars, it does not 
think of revising its own former decision An inevitable 
drawback, which, however considerable m itself, forms evi¬ 
dently but a small set-off against the immense benefits of 
general language 

The use of the syllogism is m truth no other than the use 
of general propositions m reasoning. We can reason with¬ 
out them , m simple and obvious cases we habitually do so; 
minds of great sagacity can do it m cases not simple and 
obvious, provided their experience supplies them with in¬ 
stances essentially similar to every combination of circum¬ 
stances likely to arise But other mmds, and the same minds 
where they have not the same pie-emment advantages of per¬ 
sonal experience, are quite helpless without the aid of general 
propositions, wherever the case presents the smallest complica¬ 
tion ; and if we made no general propositions, few persons 
would get much beyond those simple inferences which are 
drawn by the more intelligent of the brutes Though not 
necessary to reasoning, general propositions are necessary to 
any considerable progress m reasoning It is, therefore, 
natural and indispensable to sepaiate the process of investiga¬ 
tion into two parts, and obtain general formulae for determin¬ 
ing what inferences may he diawn, befoie the occasion arises 
for drawing the inferences The work of diawing them is 
then that of applying the formulae, and the rules of syllo¬ 
gism are a system of securities for the correctness of the 
application. 

§ 6 To complete the series of considerations connected 



FUNCTIONS AND VALUE OF THE SYLLOGISM. 223 

with the philosophical character of the syllogism, it is requi¬ 
site to consider, since the syllogism is not the universal type 
of the reasoning process, what is the real type This resolves 
itself into the question, what is the nature of„ the minor pie- 
raise, and m what manner it contributes to establish the con¬ 
clusion * for as to the major, we now fully understand, that 
j, the place which it nominally occupies m our reasonings, 

4 properly belongs to the individual facts or observations of 
which it expresses the general result, the major itself being 
no real part of the argument, but an intermediate halting- 
place for the mind, interposed by an artifice of language 
between the real premises and the conclusion, by way of a 
security, which it is m a most material degiee for the cor¬ 
rectness of the process. The minor, however, being an indis¬ 
pensable part of the syllogistic expression of an argument, 
without doubt either is, or corresponds to, an equally indis¬ 
pensable part of the argument itself, and we have only to 
inquire what part. 

It is perhaps worth while to notice here a speculation 
of a philosopher to whom mental science is much indebted, 
but who, though a very penetrating, was a very hasty 
thinker, and whose want of due circumspection lendered him 
fully as remarkable for what he did not see, as for what he 
saw I allude to Dr Thomas Brown, whose theory of ratio¬ 
cination is peculiar. He saw the petitio prmcipn which is 
inherent m every syllogism, if we consider the major to be 
itself the evidence by which the conclusion is proved, instead of 
being, what m fact it is, an assertion of the existence of 
evidence sufficient to prove any conclusion of a given descrip¬ 
tion. Seeing this, Dr. Brown not only failed to see the 
immense advantage, m point of security for correctness, which 
is gained by interposing this step between the real evidence 
and the conclusion, but he thought it incumbent on him to 
strike out the major altogether from the reasoning process, 
without substituting anything else, and maintained that our 
reasonings consist only of the minor premise and the conclu¬ 
sion, Socrates is a man, therefore Socrates is mortal. thus 
actually suppressing, as an unnecessary step m the argument, 



224 


REASONING. 


the appeal to former experience. The absurdity of this was 
disguised from him by the opinion he adopted, that reasoning 
is merely analysing our own genual notions, or abstract ideas, 
and that the proposition, Socrates is mortal, is evolved from 
the proposition, Socrates is a man, simply by recognising the 
notion of mortality as already contained m the notion we form 
of a man 

After the explanations so fully entered into on the subject 
of propositions, much further discussion cannot be necessary 
to make the ladical error of this view of ratiocination apparent 
If the word man connoted moitality, if the meaning of 
“ mortal” were involved m the meaning of “ man /’ we might, 
undoubtedly, evolve the conclusion from the minor alone, 
because the minor would have already asserted it. But if, 
as is m fact the case, the woid man does not connote mortality, 
how does it appear that in the mind of every peison who 
admits Socrates to he a man, the idea of man must include 
the idea of mortality ? Dr Brown could not help seeing this 
difficulty, and m order to avoid it, was led, contrary to his 
intention, to re-establish, under another name, that step m 
the aigument which coiresponds to the major, by affirming 
the necessity of previously pei ceivmg the relation between the 
idea of man and the idea of mortal. If the ieasoner has 
not previously perceived this relation, he will not, says Dr. 
Brown, infer because Socrates is a man, that Socrates is 
mortal. But even this admission, though amounting to a 
surrender of the doctrine that an argument consists of the 
minor and the conclusion alone, will not save the remainder of 
Dr. Brown s theory The failuie of assent to the argument 
does not take place merely because the ieasoner, for want of 
due analysis, does not perceive that his idea of man includes 
the idea of mortality, it takes place, much more commonly, 
because m his mind that relation between the two ideas has 
never existed. And m truth it never does exist, except as the 
result of experience. Consenting, for the sake of the argu¬ 
ment, to discuss the question on a supposition of which we 
have recognised the radical mcoirectness, namely, that the 
meaning of a proposition relates to the ideas of the things 



FUNCTIONS AND VALUE OF THE SYLLOGISM. 225 

spoken of, and not to the things themselves; I must yet 
observe, that the idea of man, as an umveisal idea, the 
common piopeity of all rational cieatures, cannot involve 
anything but what is strictly implied m the name. If any one 
includes m his own pnvate idea of man, as no doubt is always 
the case, some othei attributes, such for instance as mortality, 
he does so only as the consequence of experience, after having 
satisfied himself that all men possess that attribute. so that 
whatever the idea contains, m any person’s mind, beyond what 
is included m the conventional signification of the word, has 
been added to it as the result of assent to a proposition, 
while Di Brown’s theory requnes us to suppose, on the con- 
tiaiv, that assent to the proposition is produced by evolving, 
through an analytic piocess, this very element out of the 
idea This theory, therefoie, may be considered as sufficiently 
lefuted, and the minor premise must be regarded as totally 
insufficient to piove the conclusion, except with the assistance 
of the major, 01 of that which the major represents, namely, 

! the vanous singular propositions expressive of the series of 
observations, of which the generalization called the majoi 
"premise is the result 

In the argument, then, which proves that Socrates is 
mortal, one indispensable pait of the premises will be as 
follows “My father, and my fathei’s father, A, B, C, and 
an indefinite number of other persons, were mortalwhich 
is only an expression in different words of the observed fact 
that they have died This is the major piermse divested of 
the petitio pmncipii, and cut down to as much as is really 
known by direct evidence. 

In order to connect this proposition with the conclusion 
Socrates is mortal, the additional link necessary is such a pro¬ 
position as the following “ Socrates resembles my father, and 
my father’s father, and the otliei individuals specified ” This 
proposition we assert when we say that Socrates is a man 
By saying so we likewise assert m what respect he resembles 
them, namely, m the attributes connoted by the word man 
And we conclude that he fiutlier resembles them m the attn- 
bute mortality 

VOL. i. 


15 



226 


REASONING. 


§ 7 . We have thus obtained what we were seeking, an 
universal type of the leasomng process We find it lesolv- 
able m all cases into the following elements Certain indi¬ 
viduals have a given attubute , an individual or individuals 
resemble the foimer m certain other attributes, therefore 
they lesemble them also m the given attribute This type of 
ratiocination does not claim, like the syllogism, to be con¬ 
clusive, fiom the mere form of the expression, noi can it 
possibly be so That one proposition does or does not 
assert the very fact which was already asserted m another, 
may appear from the form of the expression, that is, fiom a 
comparison of the language, but when the two propositions 
assert facts which are bond fide different, whether the one 
fact proves the other or not can never appear from the lan- 
guage, but must depend on other considerations Whether, 
from the attributes m which Socrates lesembles those men 
who have heretofoie died, it is allowable to infer that he 
resembles them also m being moital, is a question of Induc¬ 
tion , and is to be decided by the principles or canons which 
we shall hereaftei recognise as tests of the correct peiformance 
of that great mental operation 

Meanwhile, however, it is certain, as befoie remaiked, 
that if this mfeience can be drawn as to Socrates, it can be 
diawn as to all others who resemble the observed individuals 
m the same attributes m which he resembles them, that is 
(to express the thing concisely) of all mankind If, therefore, 
the argument be admissible m the case of Socrates, we 
are at liberty, once for all, to treat the possession of the 
attributes of man as a maik, or satisfactoiy evidence, of the 
attubute of mortality This we do by laying down the uni¬ 
versal proposition, All men are mortal, and interpreting this, 
as occasion arises, m its application to Socrates and others 
By this means we establish a very convenient division of the 
entire logical operation into two steps, first, that of ascer¬ 
taining what attributes are marks of mortality , and, secondly, 
whether any given individuals possess those marks And 
it will generally be advisable, m our speculations on the 
reasoning process, to consider this double operation as m 



FUNCTIONS AND VALUE OF THE SYLLOGISM. 227 

fact taking place, and all reasoning as earned on in the form 
mto which it must necessarily he thiown to enable us to apply 
to it any test of its correct performance. 

Although, theiefore, all processes of thought m which the 
ultimate premises are particulars, whether we conclude from 
particulars to a general formula, or fiom particulars to other 
particulars according to that formula, are equally Induction , 
we shall yet, conformably to usage, consider the name Induc¬ 
tion as more peculiarly belonging to the process of establish¬ 
ing the general proposition, and the remaining operation, 
which is substantially that of interpreting the general propo¬ 
sition, we shall call by its usual name, Deduction And we 
shall consider every piocess by which anything is inferred 
respecting an unobserved case, as consisting of an Induction 
followed by a Deduction, because, although the process needs 
not necessarily be carried on m this form, it is always susceptible 
of the form, and must be thiown into it when assurance ot 
scientific accuracy is needed and desired 

§ 8 . The theory of the syllogism, laid down m the pre¬ 
ceding pages, has obtained, among other important adhesions, 
three of peculiar value, those of Sir John Herschel,* * * § Dr 
Whewell,f and Mr. Bailey, J Sir John Herschel consider¬ 
ing the doctrine, though not strictly “ a discoveiy,” § to 
be u one of the greatest steps which have yet been made m 
the philosophy of Logic.” “When we consider” (to quote 
the further words of the same authority) “ the inveteracy of 
the habits and prejudices which it has cast to the winds,” there 
is no cause for misgiving m the fact that other thinkers, no 
less entitled to consideration, have formed a very different esti- 


* Review of Quetelet on Probabilities, Essay s, p 367 

t Philosophy of Discovery > p 289 

+ Theory of Reasoning , ch iv to which I may refer for an able statement 
and enforcement of the grounds of the doctrine 

§ It is very probable that the doctune is not new, and that it was, as Sir 
John Herschel thinks, substantially anticipated by Berkeley But 1 certainly 
am not aware that it is (as has been affirmed by one of my ablest and most 
candid critics) “among the standing marks of what is called the empirical phi¬ 
losophy ” 


15—2 



228 


REASONING. 


mate of it. Their principal objection cannot be better or more' 
succinctly stated than by borrowing a sentence fiom Arch¬ 
bishop Whately + “ In eveiy case where an inference is diawn 
from Induction (unless that name is to be given to a mere 
landom guess without any grounds at all) we must foim _a 
judgment that the instance 01 instances adduced are sufficient 
to authorize the conclusion, that it is allowable to take these 
instances as a sample wan anting an mfeience respecting the 
whole class and the expression of this judgment m words 
(it has been said by seveial of my critics) i$ the major 
piemise 

I quite admit that the major is an afihmation of the suffi¬ 
ciency of the evidence on which the conclusion rests That it 
is so, is the very essence of my own theory And whoever 
admits that the major premise is only this, adopts the theory 
m its essentials. 

But I cannot concede that this recognition of the suffi¬ 
ciency of the evidence—that is, of the coirectness of the induc¬ 
tion—is a pait of the induction itself, unless we ought to say 
that it is a part of everything we do, to satisfy ourselves that 
it has been done rightly We conclude from known instances 
to unknown by the impulse of the generalizing propensity , 
and (until after a considerable amount of practice and mental 
discipline) the question of the sufficiency of the evidence is 
only raised by a retrospective act, tinning back upon our own 
footsteps, and examining whethei we were wananted m doing 
what we have already done To speak of this reflex opera¬ 
tion as part of the original one, requiring to be expressed m 
words m oidei that the verbal formula may correctly represent 
the psychological process, appears to me false psychology + 
We review our syllogistic as well as our inductive pro¬ 
cesses, and recognise that they have been coirectly per- 
fondled, but logicians do not add a third premise to the 
syllogism, to express this act of recognition. A careful copyistf 
verifies his transcript by collating it with the original, and| 

* ZogiCy book iv ch 1 . sect 1 

f See tbe important chapter on Belief, m Professor Bain’s gi eat tieatise, 
The Emotions and the Will, pp 581-4 



FUNCTIONS AND VALUE OF THE SYLLOGISM. 229 

if no error appears, he recognises that the transcript has been 
conectlv made But we do not call the examination of the 
copy a part of the act of copying 

The conclusion m an induction is mfened 'from the 
evidence' itself, and not fiom a lecognition of the sufficiency 
of the * deuce , as I infer that my fuend is walking towards 
me because 1 see him, and not because I recognise that my 
eyes are open, and that eyesight is a means of knowledge In 
all operations which require care, it is good to assure ourselves 
that the process has been performed accurately; but the test' 
mg of the process is not the process itself, and, besides, may 
have been omitted altogether, and yet the process be correct 
It is precisely because that operation is omitted m oidmary 
unscientific reasoning, that there is anything gamed m cer¬ 
tainty by throwing reasoning into the syllogistic form To 
make sure, as far as possible, that it shall not be omitted, we 
make the testing operation a part of the leasonmg process 
itself We insist that the inference from particulars to par¬ 
ticulars shall pass through a general proposition But this is a 
security foi good reasoning, not a condition of all reasoning , 
and m some cases not even a security Our most familiar 
inferences are all made before we learn the use of general pro¬ 
positions ; and a person of untutored sagacity will skilfully 
apply his acquired experience to adjacent cases, though he 
would bungle grievously m fixing the limits of the appropriate 
general theorem But though he may conclude rightly, he 
never, properly speaking, knows whether lie has done so or 
not, he has not tested his reasoning. Now, this is precisely 
what forms of reasoning do for us We do not need them to 
enable us to reason, but to enable us to know whether we 
reason correctly. 

In still further answer to the objection, it may be added 
that, even when the test has been applied, and the sufficiency 
of the evidence recognised,—if it is sufficient to support the 
general proposition, it is sufficient also to support an inference 
from particulars to particulars without passing through the 
general proposition. The inquirer who has logically satisfied 
himself that the conditions of legitimate induction were 



£80 


REASONING. 


lealized in the cases A, E, 0 , would be as much justified in 
concluding dnectl} to the Duke of Wellington as m conclud¬ 
ing to all men The general conclusion is never legitimate, 
unless the particular one would he so too , and m no sense, 
intelligible to me, can the particular conclusion he said to be 
drawn from the general one Whenever there is ground for 
di awing any conclusion at all from particular instances, there 
is ground for a general conclusion, hut that this general con¬ 
clusion should be actually drawn, however useful, cannot be 
an indispensable condition of the validity of the inference m 
the particular case A man gives away sixpence by the same 
power by which he disposes of his whole fortune , but it is not 
necessaiy to the legality of the smaller act, that he should 
make a formal assertion of his right to the greater one. 

Some additional remaiks, m reply to minor objections, are 
appended 4 


* A water iq the ‘British Quarterly Review” (August 1846), m a review 
of this treatise, endeavours to show that there is no petitzo pi mcipn m the 
syllogism, by denying that the proposition, All men are mortal, asserts oi 
assumes that Soci ates is mortal In support of this denial, he argues that we 
may, and m fact do, admit the general proposition that all men are mortal, with¬ 
out having particularly examined the case of Socrates, and even without knowing 
whether the individual so named is a man or something else But this of course 
was never denied That we can and do diaw conclusions concerning cases 
specifically unknown to us, is the datum from which all who discuss this subject 
must set out The question is, m what terms the evidence, or ground, on which 
we draw these conclusions, may best be designated—whether it is most correct 
to say, that the unknown case is pioved by known cases, or that it is proved by 
a general proposition including both sets of cases, the unknown and the known * 
I contend for the foimer mode of expression I hold it an abuse of language to 
say, that the proof that Socrates is mortal, is that all men are mortal Turn it 
in what way we will, this seems to me to be asserting that a thing is the proof 
of itself Whoever pronounces the words, All men are mortal, has affirmed 
that Socrates is mortal, though he may never have heard of Socrates , for since 
Socrates, whether known to be so or not, leally is a man, he is included m the 
words, All men and in every asseition of which they are the subject If the 
reviewer does not see that there is a difficulty here, I can only advise him to 
leconsider the subject until he does after which he will be a bettei judge of 
the success or failure of an attempt to remove the difficulty. That he had re¬ 
flected very little on the point when he wrote his remarks, is shown by his over¬ 
sight respecting the dictum de omni et nullo . He acknowledges that this maxim 
as commonly expressed,—“ Whatever is true of a class, is true of everything id- 



FUNCTION’S AND VALUE OF THE SYLLOGISM. 231 


§ 9. The preceding considerations enable us to undei- 
stand the true nature of what is termed, by recent writers, 
Formal Logic, and the relation between it and Logic m the 
widest sense Logic, as I conceive it, is the entire theory of 

eluded m the class, ” is a mere identical proposition, since the class is nothing 
but the things included in it But he thinks this defect would be cured by 
woidmg the maxim thus,—“ Whatever is true of a class, is true of eveiythmg 
which can he shown to be a member of the class ” as if a thing could “be 
shown ” to be a member of the class without being one If a class means the 
sum of all the things included in the class, the things which can “be shown ” 
to be included m it are part of the sum, and the dictum is as much an identical 
proposition with respect to them as to the rest One would almost imagine that, 
m the reviewer’s opinion, things are not members of a class until they are called 
up publicly to take their place m it—that so long, m fact, as Socrates is not 
known to be a man, he is not a man, and any asseition which can be made con¬ 
cerning men does not at all regard him, nor is affected as to its truth or falsity 
by anything m which he is concerned 

The difference between the reviewer’s theory and mine may be thus stated 
Both admit that when we say, All men are mortal, we make an asseition leach, 
mg beyond the sphere of our knowledge of individual cases , and that when a 
new individual, Socrates, is brought within the field of our knowledge by 
means of the minor premise, we learn that we have already made an assertion 
respecting Socrates without knowing it our own general formula being, to that 
extent, for the first time interpreted to us But accoidmg to the reviewer’s 
theory, the smaller assertion is proved by the laiger while I contend, that both 
assertions are pioved together, by the same evidence, namely, the grounds of 
experience on which the general assertion was made, and by winch it must be 
j ustified 

The reviewer says, that if the major premise included the conclusion, “ we 
should be able to affirm the conclusion without the intervention of the minoi 
piemise, but every one sees that that is impossible” A similai argument is 
uiged by Mi De Morgan (Foimal Logic , p 259) “The whole objection 
tacitly assumes the superfluity of the minor , that is, tacitly assumes we know 
Socrates* to be a man as soon as we know him to be Socrates ” The objection 
would be well grounded if the assertion that the major premise includes the 
conclusion, meant that it individually specifies all it includes As however the 
only indication it gives is a description by marks, we have still to compare any 
new individual with the marks, and to show that this comparison has been 
made, is the office of the minor. But since, by supposition, the new individual 
has the maiks, whether we have ascertained him to have them or not, if we 
have affirmed the major premise, we have asserted him to be mortal Now my 
position is that this assertion cannot he a necessary part of the argument It 
cannot be a necessary condition of reasoning that we should begin by making 

* Mr De Morgan says u Plato,” but to prevent confusion I have kept to my 
own exemplum 



£32 


REASONING. 


the asceitainment of leasoned or mfeiiecl truth Formal 
Logic, therefoie, which Sn William Hamilton from his own 
point of view, and Aichbishop Whately fiom his, have re¬ 
presented as the whole of Logie propeily so called, is really a 
veiy suhoidmate pait of it, not being directly concerned with 
the process of Seasoning or Inference m the sense m which 
that piocess is a part of the Investigation of Truth What, 
then, is Foimal Logic ? The name seems to be properly 
applied to all that portion of doctrine which relates to the 
equivalence of different modes of expiession , the rules for 
determining when assertions m a given foim imply or suppose 
the tiuth or falsity of otliei asseitions This includes the 
theoiy of the Import of Piopositions, and of their Conver- 


an asseition, which is afterwards to be employed in proving a part of itself. 
X can conceive only one way out of this difficulty, viz that what really foims 
the pi oof is the othei part of the assertion , the portion of it, the tiuth of which 
has been ascertained previously and that the unproved part is bound upm one 
formula with the proved part in mere anticipation, and as a memoiandum of 
the nature of the conclusions which we are prepared to prove 

With respect to the minor premise in its foimal shape, the minor as it 
stands m the syllogism, piedicatmg of Socrates a definite class name, I readily 
admit that it is no more a necessary part of reasoning than the major When 
there is a major, doing its work by means of a class name, mmois are needed 
to interpret it but reisonmg can be earned on without eithei the one or the 
othei They are not the conditions of leasomng, but a precaution against 
erroneous reasoning The only minor piemise necessary to reasoning m the 
example under consideration, is, Socrates is hie A, B, 0, and"the other indi¬ 
viduals who are known to have died And this is the only umveisal type of 
that step in the reasoning process which is represented by the minor Expe¬ 
rience, however*- of the uncertainty of this loose mode of inference, teaches the 
expediency of detei mining beforehand what ktnd of likeness to the cases 
observed, is necessary to bring an unobserved case within the same predicate , 
and the answei to this question is the major. Thus the syllogistic major and the 
syllogistic minor start into existence together, and are called forth by the same 
exigency. When we conclude from personal experience without refeinng to 
any record—to any general theorems, either written, or traditional, or mentally 
registered by ouiselves as conclusions of our own drawing, we do not use, m 
our thoughts, eithei a major or a mmoi, such as the syllogism puts into words 
When, however, we revise this rough inference from particuiais to particulars, 
and substitute a careful one, the 1 ©vision consists m selecting two syllogistic 
premises But this neither alteis nor adds to the evidence we had before , 
it only puts us m a better position for judging whether our inference from 
particulars to particulars is well grounded 



FUNCTIONS AND VALUE OF THE SYLLOGISM. 233 

sion, iEquipollence, and Opposition, of those falsely called 
Inductions (to he here aft ei spoken of*), m -which the apparent 
generalization is a mere ahudged statement of cases known 
individually, and finally, of the syllogism while the theoiy 
of Naming, and of (what is inseparably connected with it) 
Definition, though belonging still moie to the othei and larger 
kind of logic than to this, is a necessary preliminary to this. 
The end aimed at by Foimal Logic, and attained by the ob¬ 
servance of its precepts, is not truth, but consistency. It has 
been seen that this is the only direct puipose of the rules of 
the syllogism , the intention and effect of which is simply to 
keep our inferences or conclusions m complete consistency 
with our general formulae or dnections for drawing them The 
Logic of Consistency is a necessary auxiliary to the logic of 
tiuth, not only because what is inconsistent with itself or with 
othei truths cannot be tiue, but also because truth can only 
be successfully pursued by drawing inferences from experience, 
which, if warrantable at all, admit of being generalized, and, 
to test their wanantableness, require to be exhibited in a gene¬ 
ralized form , after which the correctness of their application 
to particular cases is a question which specially concerns the 
Logic of Consistency. This Logic^ not requiring,any pre¬ 
liminary knowledge of the processes or conclusions of the 
various sciences, may be studied with benefit m a much earlier 
stage of education than the Logic of Truth * and the practice 
which has empirically obtained of teaching it apart, through 
elementary treatises which do not attempt to include anything 
else, though the reasons assigned for the practice are m 
general very far from philosophical, admits of a philosophical 
justification 


X- 


\ 


Infra, book m eh n 



CHAPTER IV 


OF TRAINS OF REASONING, AND DEDUCTIVE SCIENCES. 

§ 1. In oui analysis of the syllogism, it appeared that the 
minor premise always affirms a resemblance between a new 
case and some cases previously known, while the major 
premise asserts something which, having been found true of 
those known cases, we consider ourselves warranted m holding 
true of anv other case resembling the former m ceitain given 
particulars 

If all ratiocinations resembled, as to the minor premise, 
the examples which were exclusively employed m the preceding 
chaptei , if the resemblance, which that premise asserts, were 
obvious to the senses, as m the proposition <e Socrates is a 
man,” or were at once asceitamable by direct observation; 
theie would be no necessity for tiams of reasoning, and De¬ 
ductive or Ratiocmative Sciences would not exist Trains of 
reasoning exist only for the sake of extending an induction 
founded, as all inductions must be, on observed cases, to other 
cases m which we not only cannot directly observe what is to 
be proved, but cannot directly observe even the mark which is 
to prove it. 

§ 2 Suppose the syllogism to be, All cows luminate, 
the animal which is before me is a cow, therefore it ruminates 
The minor, if tiue at all, is obviously so the only premise 
the establishment of which requires any anterior process of 
inquiry, is the major, and provided the induction of which 
that premise is the expression was correctly performed, the 
conclusion respecting the animal now present will be in¬ 
stantly drawn, because, as soon as she is compared with the 
fommla, she will be identified as being included m it But 
suppose the syllogism to he the following —All arsenic is 



TRAINS OF REASONING. 


235 


poisonous, the substance which is before me is arsenic, 
therefore it is poisonous. The truth of the minor may not 
here be obvious at first sight, it may not be intuitively evi¬ 
dent, hut may itself be known only by inference. It may be 
the conclusion of another argument, which, thrown into the 
syllogistic foim, would stand thus.—Whatevei when lighted 
pioduces a dark spot on a piece of white porcelain held m the 
flame, which spot is soluble m hypochlorite of calcium, is 
arsenic, the substance before me conforms to this condition , 
theiefore it is arsenic To establish, therefore, the ultimate 
conclusion, The substance before me is poisonous, requires a 
process, which, m order to be syllogistically expressed, stands 
in need of two syllogisms, and we have a Tram of Reasoning 
When, however, we thus add syllogism to syllogism, we 
are really adding induction to induction Two separate 
inductions must have taken place to render this chain of 
inference possible, inductions founded, probably, on different 
sets of individual instances, but which converge m their 
results, so that the instance which is the subject of inquiry 
comes within the range of them both The lecoid of these 
inductions is contained m the majors of the two syllogisms 
Tirst, we, or others for us, have examined various objects 
which yielded under the given circumstances a dark spot with 
the given property, and found that they possessed the proper¬ 
ties connoted by the word arsenic, they were metallic, volatile, 
their vapour had a smell of garlic, and so forth Next, we, 01 
others for us, have examined various specimens which pos¬ 
sessed this metallic and volatile character, whose vapour had 
this smell, &c, and have invariably found that they were 
poisonous The first observation we judge that we may ex¬ 
tend to all substances whatever which yield that particular 
kind of dark spot, the second, to all metallic and volatile sub¬ 
stances resembling those we examined, and consequently, not 
to those only which are seen to be such, but to those which 
are concluded to be such by the prior induction. The sub¬ 
stance before us is only seen to come within one of these 
inductions, but by means of this one, it is brought within the 
other We are still, as before, concluding from particulars to 



236 


REASONING. 


particulars; but we aie now concluding from paiticulars ob¬ 
served, to other paiticulars which aie not, as m the simple 
case, seen to lesemble them m the material points, but inferred 
to do so, because resembling them m something else, which 
we have been led by quite a different set of instances to con¬ 
sider as a maik of the former resemblance 

This first example of a tram of reasoning is still extiemely 
simple, the series consisting of only two syllogisms. The fol¬ 
lowing is somewhat more complicated —No government, 
which earnestly seeks the good of its subjects, is likely to 
be overthrown, some particular government earnestly seeks 
the good of its subjects, therefore it is not likely to be over¬ 
thrown The major premise m this argument we shall suppose 
not to be derived from considerations a prion, but to be a 
generalization from histoiy, which, whether collect or errone¬ 
ous, must have been founded on observation of governments 
concerning whose desire of the good of their subjects there 
was no doubt It hns been found, or thought to be found, 
that these were not easily overthrown, and it has been 
deemed that those instances wan anted an extension of the 
same predicate to any and every government which resembles 
them m the attribute of desiring earnestly the good of its 
subjects But does the government m question thus resemble 
them ? This may be debated pro and con by many argu-| 
ments, and must, m any case, be proved by another induc¬ 
tion , for we cannot directly observe the sentiments and 
desires of the persons who carry on the government To 
prove the minor, therefore, we require an aigument in this 
form * Every government which acts in a ceitam manner, 
desires the good of its subjects; the supposed government 
acts in that particular manner, therefore it desires the good 
of its subjects But is it true that the government acts in 
the manner supposed ? This minor also may require proof, 
still another induction, as thus:—What is asserted by intel¬ 
ligent and disinterested witnesses, may be believed to be 
tiue, that the government acts in this manner, is asseited by 
such witnesses, therefore it may be believed to be true The 
aigument hence consists of three steps Having the evidence 



TRAINS OF REASONING. 


237 


of our senses that the case of the government under consi¬ 
deration resembles a number of former cases, m the circum¬ 
stance of having something asserted respecting it by intelli¬ 
gent and disinterested witnesses, we infer, fust, that, as m 
those former instances, so in this instance, the assertion is 
tiue ^Secondly, what was asserted of the government being 
that it acts m a paiticulai manner, and other governments 
01 persons having been obseived to act m the same mannei, 
the government m question is brought into known resem¬ 
blance with those other governments or persons, and since 
they weie known to desire the good of the people, it is there- 
upon, by a second induction, infened that the particular 
government spoken of, desires the good of the people. This 
brings that government into known resemblance with the 
other governments which were thought likely to escape revo¬ 
lution, and thence, by a third induction, it is concluded that 
this particular government is also likely to escape This is 
still leasomng from particular to particulars, but we now 
reason to the new instance fiom three distinct sets of former 
instances to one only of those sets of instances do we directly 
perceive the new one to be similar, but from that similarity 
we inductively infer that it has the attribute by which it 
is assimilated to the next set, and brought within the 
corresponding induction, after which by a repetition of the 
same operation we infer it to be similar to the thud set, 
and hence a third induction conducts us to the ultimate 
conclusion. 

§ 3 . Notwithstanding the superior complication of these 
examples, compared with those by which m the preceding 
chaptei we illustrated the general theory of leasomng, every 
doctrine which we then laid down holds equally true m these 
more intricate cases. The successive general propositions are 
not steps m the reasoning, are not intermediate links m the 
chain of inference, between the particulars observed and those 
to which we apply the observation. If we had sufficiently 
capacious memories, and a sufficient power of maintaining 
order among a huge mass of details, the reasoning could go 



238 


REASONING. 


on without any general propositions, they are mere formulae 
for inferring particulars from particulars The principle of 
general reasoning is (as befoie explained), that if from obser¬ 
vation of certain known particulars, what was seen to be true 
of them can be inferred to be true of any others, it may be 
inferred of all others which are of a certain descuption And 
m order that we may never fail to draw this conclusion m a 
new case when it can be drawn correctly, and may avoid 
diawing it when it cannot, we determine once for all what aie 
the distinguishing marks by which such cases may be recog¬ 
nised. The subsequent process is meiely that of identifying 
an object, and ascertaining it to have those marks, whether 
we identify it by the very marks themselves, or by others 
which we have ascertained (through another and a similar 
process) to be marks of those marks The real inference is 
always from particulars to particulars, from the observed 
instances to an unobserved one * but m drawing this infe¬ 
rence, we conform to a formula which we have adopted for our 
guidance m such operations, and which is a lecoid of the 
criteria by which we thought we had ascertained that we 
might distinguish when the inference could, and when it 
could not, he drawn. The real premises are the individual 
observations, even though they may have been forgotten, 01, 
being the observations of others and not of ourselves, may, to 
us, never have been known but we have before us proof that 
we or others once thought them sufficient for an induction, 
and we have maiks to show whether any new case is one of 
those to which, if then known, the induction would have been 
deemed to extend. These marks we either recognise at once, 
or by the aid of other marks, which by another previous 
induction we collected to be maiks of the first Even these 
marks of marks may only be recognised through a third set 
of marks, and we may have a tram of reasoning, of any length, 
to bung a new case within the scope of an induction grounded 
on particulars its similarity to which is only asceitamed m 
this indirect manner. 

Thus, m the preceding example, the ultimate inductive m- 



TRAINS OF REASONING 


239 


ference was, that a certain government was not likely to be 
overthrown, this inference was drawn according to a formula 
m which desire of the public good was set down as a mark of 
not being likely to be oveithrown , a mark of this mark was, 
acting m a particular manner, and a mark of acting m that 
manner was, being asserted to do so by intelligent and dis¬ 
interested witnesses this mark, the government under discus¬ 
sion was recognised by the senses as possessing. Hence that 
government fell within the last induction, and by it was brought 
within all the others The perceived resemblance of the case 
to one set of observed particular cases, brought it into known 
lesemblance with another set, and that with a third 

In the more complex branches of knowledge, the deduc¬ 
tions seldom consist, as m the examples hitheito exhibited, ol 
a single chain, a a mark of 6 , b of c, c of d, therefore a a mark 
of d They consist (to carry on the same metaphor) of several 
chains united at the extremity, as thus * a a mark of d, b of e, 
c of/, d ef of n, therefore ab c a maik of n. Suppose, foi 
example, the following combination of circumstances, 1 st, 
lays of light impinging on a reflecting surface, 2 nd, that sur¬ 
face parabolic, 3 rd, those rays parallel to each other and to the 
axis of the surface. It is to be proved that the concomse ot 
these three circumstances is a mark that the reflected rays 
will pass through the focus of the parabolic surface. Now, 
each of the three circumstances is singly a maik of something 
material to the case. Rays of light impinging on a leflectmg 
surface, are a mark that those rays will be reflected at an 
angle equal to the angle of incidence. The parabolic foim of 
the surface is a mark that, from any point of it, a line drawn 
to the focus and a line parallel to the axis will make equal 
angles with the surface. And finally, the parallelism of the 
lays to the axis is a mark that their angle of incidence coin¬ 
cides with one of these equal angles. The three marks taken 
together aie therefore a mark of all these thiee things united. 
But the three united are evidently a maik that the angle of 
reflection must coincide with the other of the two equal angles, 
that formed by a line drawn to the focus , and this again, by 



240 


REASONING 


the fundamental axiom concerning straight lines, is a mark 
that the reflected rays pass thiough the focus Most chains of 
physical deduction aie of this more complicated t)pe, and even 
m mathematics such are abundant, as m all propositions where 
the hypothesis includes numeious conditions “ If a circle be 
taken, and if within that cncle a point he taken, not the 
centre, and if straight lines be drawn from that point to the 
circumference, then,” &c. 

§ 4 The considerations now stated lemove a serious diffi¬ 
culty from the view we have taken of reasoning, which view 
might otherwise have seemed not easily reconcilable with the 
fact that there aie Deductive or Katiocmative Sciences It 
might seem to follow, if all reasoning be induction, that the 
difficulties of philosophical investigation must lie m the induc¬ 
tions exclusively, and that when these were easy, and suscep¬ 
tible of no doubt 01 hesitation, there could be no science, or, at 
least, no difficulties m science The existence, for example, of 
an extensive Science of Mathematics, requiring the highest 
scientific genius m those who contributed to its creation, and 
calling for a most continued and vigorous exertion of intellect 
m order to appropriate it when created, may seem haid to be 
accounted for on the foregoing theory. But the considera¬ 
tions more recently adduced lemove the mystery, by showing, 
that even when the inductions themselves are obvious, there 
may be much difficulty in finding whether the particular case 
which is the subject of inquiry comes within them, and ample 
room for scientific ingenuity m so combining various inductions, 
as, by means of one within which the case evidently falls, to 
bring it within others m which it cannot be directly seen to be 
included 

When the more obvious of the inductions which can be 
made in any science fiom dnect observations, have been 
made, and general formulas have been framed, determining 
the limits withm which these inductions are applicable, as 
often as a new case can he at once seen to come withm one 
of the formulas, the induction is applied to the new case, and 
the business is ended But new cases are continually arising, 



trains of reasoning. 


241 


which do not obviously come withm any formula whereby the 
question we want solved m respect of them could be answered 
Let us take an instance from geometry and as it is taken 
only for illustration, let the reader concede to us for the pre¬ 
sent, what we shall endeavour to prove m the next chapter, 
that the first pnnciples of geometiy are results of induction 
Our example shall be the fifth pioposition of the first book of 
Euclid The inquiry is, Are the angles at the base of an 
isosceles triangle equal or unequal 9 The first thing to be 
considered is, what inductions we have, fiom which we can 
infer equality or inequality For inferring equality we have 
the following formulae —Things winch being applied to each 
other coincide, are equals. Things which are equal to the 
same thing are equals. A whole and the sum of its parts aie 
equals The sums of equal things are equals. The differences 
of equal things are equals. There are no other original for¬ 
mulae to prove equality. For inferring inequality we have the 
following —A whole and its parts are unequals. The sums of 
equal things and unequal things are unequals The differ¬ 
ences of equal things and unequal things aie unequals In 
all, eight formulae. The angles at the base of an isosceles 
triangle do not obviously come within any of these The 
formulae specify certain maiks of equality and of inequality, 
but the angles cannot be peiceived intuitively to have any of 
those marks On examination it appears that they have , and 
we ultimately succeed in bunging them within the formula, 
“The differences of equal things are equal.” Whence comes 
the difficulty of recognising these angles as the differences of 
equal things 9 Because each of them is the difference not of 
one pair only, but of innumerable pairs of angles , and out of 
these we had to imagine and select two, which could either be 
intuitively perceived to be equals, or possessed some of the 
marks of equality set down m the various formulae By an ex¬ 
ercise of ingenuity, which, on the part of the first inventor, 
deserves to be regarded as considerable, two pairs of angles 
were hit upon, which united these requisites. Fust, it could be 
perceived intuitively that their differences were the angles at 
the base, and, secondly, they possessed one of the marks of 
VOL. I. 16 



242 


REASONING. 


equality, namely, coincidence when applied to one another. 
This coincidence, however, was not perceived intuitively, but 
inferred, m confoimity to another formula. 

Eor greater clearness, I subjoin an analysis of the de¬ 
monstration. Euclid, it will be remembered, demonstiates 
his fifth pioposition by means of the fourth. This it is not 
allowable foi us to do, because we are undertaking to trace 
deductive truths not to prior deductions, but to their original 
inductive foundation. We must therefore use the premises 
of the fourth pioposition instead 
of its conclusion, and prove the 
fifth directly from first principles. 

To do so requires six formulas. 

(We must begin, as m Euclid, 
by prolonging the equal sides 
AB, AC, to equal distances, and 
joining the extremities BE, 

DO) 

First Formula. The sums of equals are equal. 

AD and AE are sums of equals by the supposition Hav¬ 
ing that mark of equality, they are concluded hy this formula 
to be equal 

Second Formula. Equal straight lines being applied 
to one another coincide . 

AO, AB, are within this formula hy supposition, AD, 
AE, have been brought within it hy the preceding step. 
Both these pans of straight lines have the property of equality, 
which, according to the second formula, is a mark that, if ap¬ 
plied to each other, they will coincide. Coinciding altogether 
means coinciding m every part, and of course at their extremi¬ 
ties, D, E, and B, C 

Third Formula. Straight lines, having their extremities 
coincident, coincide. 

B E and C D have been brought within this formula hy 
the preceding induction, they will, theiefore, coincide. 




TRAINS OB REASONING 


243 


Fourth Formula Angles, having their sides coincident, 
coincide 

The third induction having shown that BE and CD co¬ 
incide, and the second that AB, AC, coincide, the angles 
ABE and ACD are thereby brought within the fouith for¬ 
mula, and accordingly coincide. 

Fifth Formula. Things which coincide are equal. 

The angles ABE and ACD are brought within this 
formula by the induction immediately preceding. This tram 
of reasoning being also applicable, mutatis mutandis, to the 
angles EBC, DCB, these also are brought withm the fifth 
formula. And, finally, 

Sixth Formula. The differences of equals are equal 

The angle ABC being the difference of ABE, CBE, 
and the angle ACB being the difference of ACD, DCB, 
which have been proved to be equals, ABC and ACB are 
brought withm the last formula by the whole of the previous 
process 

The difficulty here encountered is chiefly that of figuring 
to ourselves the two angles at the base of the triangle ABC 
as remainders made by cutting one pair of angles out of 
another, while each pair shall be corresponding angles of 
triangles which have two sides and the intervening angle 
equal It is by this happy contrivance that so many different 
inductions are brought to bear upon the same particular case 
And this not being at all an obvious thought, it may be seen 
from an example so near the threshold of mathematics, how 
much scope there may well be for scientific dexterity in tile 
higher branches of that and other sciences, m order so to com¬ 
bine a few simple inductions, as to bring withm each of them 
mnumeiable cases which are not obviously included m it, and 
how long, and numerous, and complicated may be the processes 
necessary for bringing the inductions together, even when eaAh 
induction may itself be very easy and simple. All the induc¬ 
tions involved m all geometry are comprised m those simple 
ones, the formula of which are the Axioms, and a few of the 

16—2 



244 


REASONING. 


so-called Definitions The remainder of the science is made 
up of the processes employed for bringing unforeseen cases 
within these inductions, or (m syllogistic language) for piov- 
mg the minors necessary to complete the syllogisms, the 
majois being the definitions and axioms In those definitions 
and axioms aie laid down the whole of the marks, by an artful 
combination of which it has been found possible to discover 
and prove all that is proved m geometry The marks being 
so few, and the inductions which furnish them being so obvious 
and familiar, the connecting of several of them together, 
which constitutes Deductions, 01 Trams of Seasoning, forms 
the whole difficulty of the science, and with a trifling excep¬ 
tion, its whole bulk, and hence Geometry is a Deductive 
Science 


§ 5 . It will be seen hereafter* that there are weighty 
scientific reasons for giving to every science as much of the 
chai acter of a Deductive Science as possible , for endeavouring 
to construct the science from the fewest and the simplest 
possible inductions, and to make these, by any combinations 
however complicated, suffice for proving even such truths, 
relating to complex cases, as could be proved, if we chose, by 
inductions from specific experience Eveiy branch of natural 
philosophy was originally expenmental, each generalization 
rested on a special induction, and was derived from its own 
distinct set of observations and experiments From being 
sciences of pure experiment, as the phrase is, or, to speak 
more correctly, sciences m which the reasonings mostly con¬ 
sist of no more than one step, and are expressed by single 
syllogisms, all these sciences have become to some extent, and 
some of them m nearly the whole of their extent, sciences of 
pure reasoning, whereby multitudes of truths, already known 
by induction from as many different sets of experiments, have 
come to be exhibited as deductions or corollaries from induc¬ 
tive propositions of a simpler and more universal character. 
Thus mechanics, hydrostatics, optics, acoustics, thermo- 


* Infra, book in ch iv. § 3, and elsewhere 



TRAINS OF REASONING. 


245 


logy, have successively been rendered mathematical, and 
astronomy was brought by Newton within the laws of general 
mechanics. Why it is that the substitution of this circuitous 
mode of pioceedmg for a process apparently much easier and 
more natural, is held, and justly, to be the greatest tnumph 
of the investigation of nature, we are not, m this stage of our 
inquiry, prepaied to examine. But it is necessary to remaik, 
that although, by this progressive transformation, all sciences 
tend to become more and more Deductive, they are not, there¬ 
fore, the less Inductive, every step m the Deduction is still 
an Induction. The opposition is not between the terms 
Deductive and Inductive, but between Deductive and Experi¬ 
mental A science is experimental, m proportion as every 
new case, which presents any peculiar features, stands m need 
of a new set of observations and experiments—a fiesli induc¬ 
tion It is deductive, m proportion as it can draw conclusions, 
respecting cases of a new kind, by processes winch bring those 
cases under old inductions, by ascertaining that cases which 
cannot be observed to have the requisite marks, have, however, 
marks of those marks. 

We can now, therefore, perceive what is the generic dis¬ 
tinction between sciences which can be made Deductive, and 
those which must as yet remain Experimental. The differ¬ 
ence consists m our having been able, or not yet able, to dis¬ 
cover maiks of marks If by our various inductions we have 
been able to pioceed no further than to such propositions as 
these, a a maik of b } or a and b marks of one another, c a 
mark of d, or c and d marks of one another, without anything 
to connect a or b with c or d , we have a science of detached 
and mutually independent generalizations, such as these, that 
acids redden vegetable blues, and that alkalies colour them 
green, fiom neither of which propositions could we, directly 
or indirectly, infer the other: and a science, so far as it is 
composed of such propositions, is purely experimental. 
Chemistry, m the present state of our knowledge, has not yet 
thrown off this character There are other sciences, however, 
of which the propositions are of this kind a a mark of b, b a 
mark of c, c of d 9 d of e, &c In these sciences we can mount 



246 


REASONING. 


the ladder from a to e by a process of ratiocination; we can 
conclude that a is a mark of e, and that every object which 
has the mark a has the property e, although, perhaps, we 
never were able to observe a and e together, and although 
even cl, our only dnect maik of e 9 may not be perceptible m 
those objects, but only infemble Or, varying the first meta¬ 
phor, we may be said to get from a to e underground: the 
marks 6, c, d, which indicate the route, must all be possessed 
somewheie by the objects concerning which we are inquiring, 
but they are below the suiface. a is the only mark that is 
visible, and by it we are able to trace m succession all the 
rest, 

§ 6 We can now understand how an experimental may 
transform itself into a deductive science by the mere progress 
of experiment In an experimental science, the inductions, 
as we have said, lie detached, as, a a mark of 6, e a mark of 
d 3 e a mark of/, and so on now, a new set of instances, and 
a consequent new induction, may at any time bridge over 
the interval between two of these unconnected arches, h , for 
example, may be ascertained to be a mark of c, which enables 
us thenceforth to prove deductively that a is a mark of c 
Or, as sometimes happens, some comprehensive induction 
may raise an arch high m the air, which bridges over hosts 
of them at once b 3 d, f 3 and all the rest, turning out to be 
marks of some one thing, or of things between which a con¬ 
nexion has already been traced. As when Newton discovered 
that the motions, whether regular or apparently anomalous, 
of all the bodies of the solar system, (each of which motions 
had been inferred by a separate logical operation, from 
separate marks,) were all marks of moving round a common 
centre, with a centripetal force varying directly as the mass, 
and inversely as the square of the distance from that centre. 
This is the greatest example winch has yet occurred of the 
transformation, at one stroke, of a science which was still 
to a great degree merely experimental, into a deductive 
science. 

Transformations of the same nature, but on a smaller scale. 



TRAINS OF REASONING. 


247 


continually take place m the less advanced branches of physical 
knowledge, without enabling them to throw off the character of 
experimental sciences Thus with regard to the two uncon¬ 
nected pi opositions before cited, namely, Acids redden vege¬ 
table blues, Alkalies make them green, it is remarked by 
Liebig, that all blue colouring matters which are reddened by 
acids (as well as, reciprocally, all red colouring matters which 
are rendered blue by alkalies) contain nitrogen and it is quite 
possible that this circumstance may one day furnish a bond of 
connexion between the two propositions m question, by show¬ 
ing that the antagonistic action of acids and alkalies m pro¬ 
ducing or destroying the colour blue, is the result of some 
one, more general, law. Although this connecting of detached 
generalizations is so much gam, it tends but little to give a 
deductive character to any science as a whole, because the new 
courses of observation and experiment, which thus enable us 
to connect together a few general truths, usually make known 
to us a still greater number of unconnected new ones Hence 
chemistry, though similar extensions and simplifications of its 
generalizations are continually taking place, is still in the mam 
an experimental science, and is likely so to continue unless 
some comprehensive induction should be hereafter arrived at, 
which, like Newton's, shall connect a vast number of the 
smaller known inductions together, and change the whole 
method of the science at once. Chemistry has already one 
great generalization, which, though relating to one of the sub¬ 
ordinate aspects of chemical phenomena, possesses withm its 
limited sphere this comprehensive character, the principle of 
Dalton, called the atomic theory, or the doctrine of chemical 
equivalents which by enabling us to a certain extent to fore¬ 
see the proportions in which two substances will combine, 
before the experiment has been tried, constitutes undoubtedly 
a source of new chemical truths obtainable by deduction, as 
well as a connecting principle for all truths of the same de¬ 
scription previously obtained by experiment. 

§ 7. The discoveries which change the method of a 
science from experimental to deductive, mostly consist in 



248 


REASONING. 


establishing, either by deduction or by dnect experiment, that 
the varieties of a paiticular phenomenon umfoimly accompany 
the vaneties of some other phenomenon bettei known. Thus 
the science of sound, which previously stood m the lowest 
rank of merely experimental science, became deductive when 
it was proved by experiment that every variety of sound was 
consequent on, and therefore a maik of, a distinct and de¬ 
finable variety of oscillatoiy motion among the particles of the 
transmitting medium. When this was ascertained, it followed 
that every relation of succession or coexistence which ob¬ 
tained between phenomena of the more known class, obtained 
also between the phenomena which coriesponded to them 
m the other class. Every sound, being a maik of a parti- 
culai oscillatory motion, became a mark of everything which, 
by the laws of dynamics, was known to be mfernble from 
that motion; and everything which by those same laws was 
a mark of any oscillatory motion among the paitieles of an 
elastic medium, became a mark of the corresponding sound. 
And thus many truths, not before suspected, concerning 
sound, become deducible fiom the known laws of the propa¬ 
gation of motion through an elastic medium; while facts 
already empirically known respecting sound, become an indi¬ 
cation of corresponding properties of vibiatmg bodies, pre¬ 
viously undiscovered. 

But the giand agent for transforming experimental into de¬ 
ductive sciences, is the science of number. The properties of 
numbers, alone among all known phenomena, are, m the most 
ngorous sense, properties of all things whatever All things 
are not coloured, or ponderable, or even extended, but all 
things are numerable. And if we consider this science m its 
whole extent, from common arithmetic up to the calculus of 
variations, the truths already ascertained seem all but infinite, 
and admit of indefinite extension 

These truths, though affirm able of all things whatever, of 
course apply to them only m respect of their quantity But 
if it comes to be discovered that variations of quality m any 
class of phenomena, correspond regularly to variations of 
quantity either m those same or m some other phenomena, 



TRAINS OF REASONING. 


249 


every foimula of mathematics applicable to quantities winch 
vary m that particular manner, becomes a mark of a corre¬ 
sponding geneial truth respecting the vanations in quality 
which accompany them and the science of quantity being (as 
far as any science can be) altogether deductive, the theory of 
that particular land of qualities becomes, to this extent, de¬ 
ductive likewise. 

The most striking instance m point which history affords 
(though not an example of an experimental science rendered 
deductive, but of an unparalleled extension given to the de¬ 
ductive process m a science which was deductive aheady), is 
the revolution m geometry which originated with Descartes, 
and was completed by Clairaut. These great mathematicians 
pointed out the importance of the fact, that to eveiy variety 
of position m points, direction m lines, or form m curves or 
surfaces (all of which are Qualities), there corresponds a pecu¬ 
liar 1 elation of quantity between either two or three rectilineal 
co-ordinates, insomuch that if the law weie known according 
to which those co-ordinates vary relatively to one another, 
eveiy other geometrical property of the line or surface m 
question, whether relating to quantity or quality, would be 
capable of being mfeiied. Hence it followed that every 
geometrical question could be solved, if the coiresponding 
algebraical one could ; and geometry received an accession 
(actual 01 potential) of new truths, corresponding to every 
property of numbers which the progress of the calculus had 
biought, or might m futuie bring, to light In the same 
general manner, mechanics, astronomy, and m a less degree, 
every branch of natuial philosophy commonly so called, have 
been made algebiaical. The varieties of physical phenomena 
with which those sciences are conversant, have been found to 
answer to determinable varieties in the quantity of some 
circumstance or other, or at least to varieties of form or 
position, for which corresponding equations of quantity had 
already been, or were susceptible of being, discovered by 
geometers 

In these various transformations, the propositions of the 
science of number do but fulfil the function proper to all pro- 



250 


REASONING, 


positions forming a train of reasoning, viz that of enabling 
ns to airive m an indirect method, by marks of marks, at such 
of the pioperties of objects as we cannot directly ascertain (or 
not so conveniently) by experiment We travel from a given 
visible or tangible fact, through the truths of numbers, to the 
facts sought. The given fact is a mark that a certain relation 
subsists between the quantities of some of the elements con¬ 
cerned , while the fact sought presupposes a certain relation 
between the quantities of some other elements: now, if these 
last quantities are dependent m some known manner upon the 
former, or vice versa, we can argue from the numerical relation 
between the one set of quantities, to determine that which 
subsists between the other set, the theorems of the calculus 
affording the intermediate links. And thus one of the two 
physical facts becomes a mark of the other, by being a mark 
of a mark of a mark of it 



CHAPTER V 


OF DEMONSTRATION, AND NECESSARY TRUTHS. 

§ 1 If, as laid down in the two preceding chapters, the 
foundation of all sciences, even deductive or demonstrative 
sciences, is Induction, if every step m the ratiocinations even 
of geometry is an act of induction , and if a tram of reasoning 
is but bringing many inductions to bear upon the same subject 
of inquiry, and drawing a case within one induction by means 
of another, wherein lies the peculiar ceitamty always ascribed 
to the sciences which are entirely, or almost entirely, deduc¬ 
tive ? Why are they called the Exact Sciences 9 Why are 
mathematical certainty, and the evidence of demonstration, 
common phrases to express the very highest degree of assur¬ 
ance attainable by reason ? Why are mathematics by almost 
all philosophers, and (by some) even those branches of natural 
philosophy which, through the medium of mathematics, have 
been converted into deductive sciences, considered to be inde¬ 
pendent of the evidence of experience and observation, and 
characterized as systems of Necessary Truth ? 

The answer I conceive to be, that this character of neces¬ 
sity, ascribed to the truths of mathematics, and even (with 
some reservations to be hereafter made) the peculiar certainty 
attributed to them, is an illusion, m order to sustain which, 
it is necessary to suppose that those truths relate to, and ex¬ 
press the properties of, purely imaginary objects. It is 
acknowledged that the conclusions of geometry are deduced, 
partly at least, from the so-called Definitions, and that those 
definitions are assumed to be correct representations, as far as 
they go, of the objects with which geometry is conversant. 
Now we have pointed out that, from a definition as such, no 
proposition, unless it be one concerning the meaning of a 
word, can ever follow; and that what apparently follows 



252 


REASONING. 


from a definition, follows in reality from an implied assump¬ 
tion that theie exists a leal thing confoimable thereto This 
assumption, m the case of the definitions of geometry, is false 
theie exist no leal things exactly conformable to the defini¬ 
tions Theie exist no points without magnitude, no lines 
without breadth, nor perfectly stiaight, no circles with all 
then radii exactly equal, noi squares with all their angles 
perfectly light It will perhaps be said that the assumption 
does not extend to the actual, but only to the possible, ex¬ 
istence of such things. I answer that, according to any test 
we have of possibility, they are not even possible Then 
existence, so fai as we can form any judgment, would seem to 
be inconsistent with the physical constitution of our planet at 
least, if not of the universe To get nd of this difficulty, 
and at the same time to save the ciedit of the supposed system 
of necessary truth, it is customary to say that the points, hues, 
cncles, and squares which aie the subject of geometry, exist 
in our conceptions merely, and are part of our minds, which 
minds, by working on then own materials, construct an a pi ion 
science, the evidence of which is purely mental, and has nothing 
whatever to do with outward experience. By howsoever high 
authorities this doctrine may have been sanctioned, it appears 
to me psychologically incorrect The points, lines, cncles, 
and squares, which any one has m his mind, are (I appiehend) 
simply copies of the points, lines, cncles, and squaies which 
he has known m his experience Our idea of a point, I 
apprehend to be simply our idea of the minimum visibile, the 
smallest portion of surface which we can see. A line, as 
defined by geometeis, is wholly inconceivable. We can reason 
about a line as if it had no breadth, because we have a power, 
which is the foundation of all the control we can exeicise over 
the operations of our minds; the power, when a perception is 
present to our senses, or a conception to out intellects, of 
attending to a part only of that perception or conception, 
instead of the whole But we cannot conceive a line without 
breadth, we can form no mental picture of such a line: all 
the lines which we have m our minds are lines possessing 
breadth. If any one doubts this, we may refer him to his own 



DEMONSTRATION, AND NECESSARY TRUTHS 253 

expeuence. I much question if any one who fancies that he 
can conceive what is called a mathematical line, thinks so 
from the evidence of his consciousness I suspect it is rather 
because he supposes that unless such a conception were possi¬ 
ble, mathematics could not exist as a science a supposition 
which there will be no difficulty m showing to be entirely 
groundless 

Since, then, neither m nature, nor m the human mind, do 
there exist any objects exactly corresponding to the definitions 
of geometiy, while yet that science cannot be supposed to be 
conversant about non-entities, nothing remains but to consider 
geometiy as conversant with such lines, angles, and figures, as 
really exist, and the definitions, as they are called, must be 
regarded as some of our first and most obvious generalizations 
concerning those natural objects The correctness of those 
generalizations, as generalizations, is without a flaw * the 
equality of all the radii of a cncle is tiue of all circles, so far 
as it is true of any one. but it is not exactly true of any 
circle, it is only nearly true, so nearly that no error of any 
importance m practice will be incurred by feigning it to be 
exactly true When we have occasion to extend these in¬ 
ductions, or their consequences, to cases m which the error 
would be appreciable—to lines of perceptible breadth or 
thickness, parallels which deviate sensibly from equidistance, 
and the like—we correct our conclusions, by combining 
with them a fiesh set of propositions relating to the aberra¬ 
tion, just as we also take m propositions relating to the 
physical 01 chemical properties of the matenal, if those 
properties happen to introduce any modification into the 
result, which they easily may, even with respect to figure and 
magnitude, as m the case, for instance, of expansion by heat 
So long, however, as there exists no practical necessity for 
attending to any of the properties of the object except its 
geometrical properties, or to any of the natural irregularities 
m those, it is convenient to neglect the consideration of the 
other properties and of the irregularities, and to reason as if 
these did not exist accordingly, we formally announce m the 
definitions, that we intend to proceed on this plan. But it is 



254 


REASONING. 


an error to suppose, because we resolve to confine our atten¬ 
tion to a certain number of the properties of an object, that 
we therefore conceive, or have an idea of, the object, denuded 
of its other properties. We are thinking, all the time, of 
precisely such objects as we have seen and touched, and with 
all the properties which naturally belong to them; but, for 
scientific convenience, we feign them to be divested of all pro¬ 
perties, except those which aie material to our purpose, and m 
regaid to which we design to consider them. 

The peculiar accuracy, supposed to be charactenstic of the 
first principles of geometry, thus appears to be fictitious The 
assertions on which the reasonings of the science are founded, 
do not, any more than m other sciences, exactly correspond 
with the fact, but we suppose that they do so, for the sake 
of tracing the consequences which follow from the supposition. 
The opinion of Dugald Stewart respecting the foundations of 
geometry, is, I conceive, substantially correct; that it is 
built on hypotheses, that it owes to this alone the peculiar 
certainty supposed to distinguish it; and that in any science 
whatever, by reasoning from a set of hypotheses, we may 
obtain a body of conclusions as certain as those of geometry, 
that is, as strictly in accordance with the hypotheses, and as 
irresistibly compelling assent, on condition that those hypotheses 
are true. 

When, therefore, it is affirmed that the conclusions of 
geometry are neoessaiy truths, the necessity consists m reality 
only m this, that fhey coneetly follow from the suppositions 
from which they are deduced. Those suppositions are so far x 
from being necessary, that they are not even true , they pur¬ 
posely depart, more or less widely, from the truth The only 
sense m which necessity can be ascribed to the conclusions of 
any scientific investigation, is that of legitimately following 
from some assumption, which, by the conditions of the inquiry, 
is not to be questioned. In this relation, of course, the deri¬ 
vative truths of every deductive science must stand to the 
inductions, or assumptions, on which the science is founded, 
and which, whether true or untrue, certain or doubtful in 
themselves, are always supposed certain for the purposes of the 



DEMONSTRATION^ AND NECESSARY TRUTHS. 255 

particular science. And therefore the conclusions of all deduc¬ 
tive sciences were said by the ancients to he necessary propo¬ 
sitions. We have observed already that to he predicated 
necessarily was characteristic of the predicable Pioprmm, and 
that a propnum was any property of a thing which could he 
deduced from its essence, that is, from the piopcrties included 
m its definition. 

§ 2 The important doctrine of Dugald Stewart, which 
I have endeavouied to enfoice, has been contested by Dr. 
Whewell, both m the dissertation appended to his excellent 
Mechanical Euclid, and m his elaborate woik on the Philosophy 
of the Inductive Sciences , m which last he also replies to an 
article m the Edinburgh Eeview, (ascribed to a wiiter of great 
scientific eminence), m which Stewait’s opinion was defended 
against his former strictures The supposed lefutation of 
Stewart consists m proving against him (as has also been done 
m this work) that the premises of geometry are not definitions, 
but assumptions of the real existence of things corresponding 
to those definitions. This, however, is doing little for Dr.. 
Whewell’s puipose, for it is these very assumptions which are 
asserted to be hypotheses, and which he,' if he denies that 
geometry is founded on hypotheses, must show to be absolute 
tiuths. All he does, however, is to observe, that they at any 
late, are not arbitrary hypotheses; that we should not be at 
liberty to substitute other hypotheses for them , that not only 
“ a definition, to he admissible, must necessarily refer to and 
agree with some conception which we can distinctly frame in 
our thoughts,” but that the straight lines, for- instance, which 
we define, must be “ those by which angles are contained, those 
by which triangles are bounded, those of which parallelism may 
be predicated, and the like ”* And this is true ; but this has 
never been contradicted. Those who say that the premises of 
geometry aie hypotheses, are not bound to maintain them to be 
hypotheses which have no relation whatever to fact. Since an 
hypothesis framed for the purpose of scientific inquiry must 


K Meckamcal Euclid, pp. 149 et seqq* 



256 


REASONING. 


relate to something which has real existence, (for there can be 
no science lespectmg non-entities,) it follows that any hypo¬ 
thesis we make lespectmg an object, to facilitate our study of 
it, must not involve anything which is distinctly false, and re¬ 
pugnant to its leal nature we must not ascribe to the thing 
any propeity which it has not, our hbeity extends only to 
slightly exaggeiating some of those which it has, (by assuming 
it to be completely what it really is very neaily,) and sup¬ 
pressing others, under the indispensable obligation of restoring 
them whenever, and m as far as, their presence or absence 
would make anv material difference m the truth 6f our con¬ 
clusions Of this nature, accordingly, are the first principles 
involved m the definitions of geometiy. That the hypotheses 
should be of this particular character, is however no further 
necessaiy, than inasmuch as no others could enable us to deduce 
conclusions which, with due collections, would be true of real 
objects and in fact, when our aim is only to illustrate truths, 
and not to investigate them, we are not under any such lestnction 
We might suppose an imaginary animal, and woik out by de¬ 
duction, from the known laws of physiology, its natural history , 
or an imaginary commonwealth, and from the elements com¬ 
posing it, might argue what would be its fate And the con¬ 
clusions which we might thus draw from purely arbitrary hypo¬ 
theses, might form a highly useful intellectual exercise * but as 
they could only teach us what ivould be the properties of objects 
which do not really exist, they would not constitute any addi¬ 
tion to our knowledge of nature while on the contrary, if the 
hypothesis merely divests a real object of some portion of its 
properties, without clothing it in false ones, the conclusions 
will always express, under known liability to correction, actual 
truth. 

§ 3. But though Dr Whewell has not shaken Stewarts 
doctnne as to the hypothetical character of that portion of 
the first principles of geometiy which are involved m the so- 
called definitions, he has, I conceive, greatly the advantage of 
Stewart on another important point m the theory of geome¬ 
trical reasoning, the necessity of admitting, among those first 



DEMONSTRATION; AND NECESSARY TRUTHS 257 


principles, axioms as well as definitions. Some of the axioms 
of Euclid might, no doubt, be exhibited m the form of defini¬ 
tions, or might be deduced, by reasoning, from propositions 
similar to what are so called. Thus, if instead of the axiom, 
Magnitudes which can be made to coincide are equal, we in¬ 
ti oduce a definition, “Equal magnitudes are those which may 
be so applied to one another as to coincidethe three axioms 
which follow (Magnitudes which are equal to the same are 
equal to one another—If equals are added to equals the sums 
are equal—If equals are taken from equals the remamdeis 
are equal,) may be proved by an imaginary superposition, re¬ 
sembling that by which the fourth proposition of the first 
book of Euclid is demonstrated. But though these and 
several others may be struck out of the list of first principles, 
because, though not requiring demonstration, they are suscep¬ 
tible of it, there will be found m the list of axioms two or 
three fundamental truths, not capable of being demonstrated 
among which must be reckoned the proposition that two 
straight lines cannot inclose a space, (or its equivalent. Straight 
lines which coincide m two points coincide altogether,) and 
some property of parallel lines, other than that which con¬ 
stitutes their definition : one of the most suitable for the pui- 
pose being that selected by Professor Playfair * “ Two straight 
lines which intersect each other cannot both of them be parallel 
to a third straight line 

The axioms, as well those which are indemonstrable as those 
which admit of being demonstrated, differ from that other 
class of fundamental principles which are involved m the 


* We might, it is true, insert this property mto the definition of parallel 
lines, framing the definition so as to require, both that when produced indefi¬ 
nitely they shall never meet, and also that any straight line which intersects 
one of them shall, if prolonged, meet the other, But by doing this we by no 
means get rid of the assumption , we are still obliged to take foi granted the 
geometncal truth, that all straight lines in the same plane, which have the 
former of these pioperties, have also the latter. For if it weie possible that 
they should not, that is, if any straight lines other than those which are parallel 
according to the definition, had the property of never meeting although indefi¬ 
nitely produced, the demonstrations of the subsequent portions of the theory of 
parallels could not be maintained 
VOL. I. 


17 



258 


REASONING. 


definitions, m this, that they aie true without any mixture of 
hypothesis. That things which, are equal to the same thing 
are equal to one anothei, is as true of the lines and figures m 
nature, as it would be of the imaginary ones assumed m the 
definitions In this respect, howevei, mathematics aie only 
on a par with most other sciences. In almost all sciences 
there are some general piopositions which aie exactly true, 
while the greater part are only more or less distant approxi¬ 
mations to the truth. Thus in mechanics, the first law of 
motion (the continuance of a movement once impiessed, until 
stopped or slackened by some resisting force) is true without 
qualification or enor. The rotation of the earth m twenty- 
four hours, of the same length as m our time, has gone on since 
the first accurate observations, without the increase or diminu¬ 
tion of one second m all that period. These are inductions 
which require no fiction to make them be received as accurately 
tiue. but along with them there are others, as for instance 
the propositions i espectmg the figure of the eaith, which are 
but appioximations to the truth, and m older to use them for 
the fuither advancement of our knowledge, we must feign 
that they are exactly true, though they really want something 
of being so. 

§ 4. It lemams to inquire, what is the ground of our 
belief m axioms—what is the evidence on which they rest ? I 
» ? answer, they are experimental truths, generalizations fiom ob- 
* serration The proposition, Two straight lines cannot inclose 
a space—or m other words. Two straight lines which have 
once met, do not meet again, but continue to diverge—is an 
induction from the evidence of our senses. 

This opinion runs counter to_a scientific prejudice of long 
standing and gieat strength, and there is probably no pro¬ 
position enunciated m this work for which a more unfavourable 
reception is to be expected. It is, however, no new opinion; 
and even if it were so, would be entitled to be judged, not by 
its novelty, but by the strength of the arguments by which it 
can be supported. I consider it very fortunate that so emi¬ 
nent a champion of the contrary opinion as Dr. Wkewell, has 



DEMONSTRATION, AND NECESSARY TRUTHS. 259 

found occasion for a most elaborate treatment of the whole 
theory of axioms, m attempting to construct the philosophy 
of the mathematical and physical sciences on the basis of the 
doctrine against which I now contend Whoever is anxious 
that a discussion should go to the bottom of the subject, must 
rejoice to see the opposite side of the question worthily re¬ 
presented If what is said by Dr Whewell, m suppoit of an 
opinion which he has made the foundation of a systematic 
work, can be shown not to be conclusive, enough will have 
been done, without going fuither m quest of stronger argu¬ 
ments and a more powerful adversary. 

It is not necessary to show that the truths which we call 
axioms are originally suggested by observation, and that we 
should never have known that two straight lines cannot inclose 
a space if we had never seen a straight lme: thus much being 
admitted by Dr Whewell, and by all, m recent times, who 
have taken his view of the subject But they contend, that it 
is not experience which proves the axiom , but that its truth 
is pei ceived a priori, by the constitution of the mind itself, 
from the first moment when the meaning of the proposition is 
apprehended; and without any necessity for verifying it by 
repeated trials, as is requisite m the case of truths really 
ascertained by observation. 

They cannot, however, but allow that the truth of the 
axiom, Two straight lines cannot inclose a space, even if 
evident independently of experience, is also evident from 
experience Whether the axiom needs confirmation or not, 
it receives continuation m almost every instant of our lives; 
since we cannot look at any two straight lines which intersect 
one another, without seeing that from that point they con¬ 
tinue to diverge more and more. Experimental proof crowds 
m upon us m such endless profusion, and without one instance 
in which there can be even a suspicion of an exception to the 
rule, that we should soon have stronger ground for believing 
the axiom, even as an expenmental truth, than we have for 
almost any of the general truths which we confessedly learn 
from the evidence of our senses. Independently of d priori 
evidence, we should certainly believe it with an intensity of 

17—2 



£60 


REASONING. 


conviction far gi eater than we accord to any ordinary physical 
truth: and this too at a time of life much earlier than that 
from which we date almost any part of our acquired know¬ 
ledge, and much too early to admit of our retaining any 
lecollection of the history of our intellectual operations at 
that period. Where then is the necessity for assuming that 
our recognition of these truths has a different ongin from the 
rest of our knowledge, when its existence is perfectly accounted 
for by supposing its ongin to he the same? when the causes 
which produce belief in all other instances, exist m this 
instance, and m a degree of strength as much superior to 
what exists m other cases, as the intensity of the belief itself 
is supenor ? The buiden of proof lies on the advocates of 
the contrary opinion: it is for them to point out some fact, 
inconsistent with the supposition that this part of our know¬ 
ledge of nature is derived from the same souices as eveiy other 
part * 

This, for instance, they would be able to do, if they could 
prove chronologically that we had the conviction (at least 
practically) so early m infancy as to be anterior to those im¬ 
pressions on the senses, upon which, on the other theory, the 
conviction is founded. This, however, cannot be proved the 
point being too far back to be within the reach of memory, and 
too obscure for external observation. The advocates of the 
cL priori theory are obliged to have recourse to other arguments 


* Some persons find themselves prevented from believing that the axiom, 
Two straight lines cannot inclose a space, could ever become known to us 
through experience, by a difficulty which may be stated as follows If the 
straight lines spoken of are those contemplated m the definition—lines abso¬ 
lutely without breadth and absolutely straight,—that such are incapable of 
inclosing a space is not proved by experience, for lines such as these do not pre¬ 
sent themselves m our experience If, on the other hand, the lines meant are 
such straight lines as we do meet with in experience, lines straight enough for 
practical purposes, but m reality slightly zigzag, and with some, however 
trifling, breadth, as applied to these lines the axiom is not true, for two of 
them may, and sometimes do, inclose a small portion of space. In neither case, 
therefore, does experience prove the axiom. 

Those who employ this argument to show that geometrical axioms cannot be 
proved by induction, show themselves unfamiliar with a common and perfectly 



DEMONSTRATION, AND NECESSARY TRUTHS. 261 

These are reducible to two, which I shall endeavour to state as 
clearly and as forcibly as possible. 

§ 5 In the fhst place it is said that if our assent to the 
proposition that two straight lines cannot inclose a space, 
were derived from the senses, we could only he convinced of 
its truth by actual tual, that is, by seeing or feeling the 
straight lines; whereas m fact it is seen to he true by merely 
thinking of them. That a stone thrown into water goes to the 
bottom, may be perceived by our senses, but mere thinking 
of a stone thrown into the water would never have led us to 
that conclusion not so, however, with the axioms relating to 
straight lines if I could be made to conceive what a straight 
line is, without having seen one, I should at once recognise 
that two such lines cannot inclose a space. Intuition is “ ima¬ 
ginary looking but experience must be real looking: if we 
see a property of straight lines to be true by merely fancying 
ourselves to be looking at them, the ground of our belief cannot 
be the senses, or experience, it must be something mental. 

To this argument it might be added m the case of this 
particular axiom, (for the assertion would not be true of all 
axioms,) that the evidence of it from actual ocular inspection 
is not only unnecessary, but unattainable. What says the 
axiom ? That two straight lines cannot inclose a space , that 
after having once intersected, if they are prolonged to infinity 
they do not meet, but continue to diverge from one another. 

valid mode of inductive proof, proof by approximation Though experience 
furnishes us with no lines so unimpeachably straight that two of them are inca¬ 
pable of inclosing the smallest space, it presents us with gradations of lines 
possessing less and less either of breadth or of flexure, of which senes the 
straight line of the definition is the ideal limit And observation shows that 
just as much, and as nearly, as the straight lines of experience approximate to 
having no breadth or flexure, so much and so nearly does the space-mclosmg 
power of any two of them approach to zero The inference that if they had 
no breadth or flexure at all, they would inclose no space at all, is a correct in¬ 
ductive inference from these facts, conformable to one of the four Inductive 
Methods hereinafter chaiactenzed, the Method of Concomitant Variations; of 
which the mathematical Doctrine of Limits presents the extreme case. 

*-Whewell’s History of Scientific Ideas, 1 140 . 



2 62 


REASONING. 


How can this, in any single case, be proved by actual obser¬ 
vation 9 We may follow the lines to any distance we please, 
but we cannot follow them to infinity for aught our senses 
can testify, they may, immediately beyond the farthest point 
to which we have traced them, begin to approach, and at last 
meet. Unless, therefore, we had some other proof of the im¬ 
possibility than observation affords us, we should have no 
ground for believing the axiom at all. 

To these aiguments, which I trust I cannot be accused of 
understating, a satisfactory answer will, I conceive, be found, 
if we advert to one of the characteristic properties of geome¬ 
trical forms—their capacity of being painted m the imagina¬ 
tion with a distinctness equal to .reality: m other words, the 
exact resemblance of our ideas of form to the sensations which 
suggest them. This, m the first place, enables us to make 
(at least with a little practice) mental pictures of all possible 
combinations of lines and angles, which resemble the realities 
quite as well as any which we could make on paper, and m 
the next place, make those pictures just as fit subjects of 
geometrical experimentation as the realities themselves, inas¬ 
much as pictures, if sufficiently accurate, exhibit of course all 
the properties which would be manifested by the realities at 
one given inslant, and on simple inspection and m geometry 
we are concerned only with such properties, and not with that 
which pictures could not exhibit, the mutual action of bodies 
one upon another The foundations of geometry would there¬ 
fore be laid m direct experience, even if the experiments (which 
m this case consist merely m attentive contemplation) were 
practised solely upon what we call our ideas, that is, upon the 
diagrams in our minds, and not upon outward objects. Tor 
m all systems of experimentation we take some objects to 
serve as t representatives of all which resemble them, and in 
the present case the conditions which qualify a real object to 
be the representative of its class, are completely fulfilled by an 
object existing only m our fancy. Without denying, therefore, 
the possibility of satisfying ourselves that two straight lines 
cannot inclose a space, by merely thinking of straight lines 
without actually looking at them; I contend, that we do not 



DEMONSTRATION, AND NECESSARY TRUTHS. 263 

believe this truth on the ground of the imaginary mtuitipn 
simply, but because we know that the imaginary lines exactly 
resemble real ones, and that we may conclude from them to 
real ones with quite as much certainty as we could conclude 
from one real line to another The conclusion, therefore, is 
still an induction from observation. And we should not be 
authoiized to substitute observation of the image m our mind, 
for obseivation of the reality, if we had not learnt by long- 
continued experience that the properties of the reality are faith¬ 
fully represented m the image, just as we should be scienti¬ 
fically warranted m describing an animal which we have never 
seen, from a picture made of it with a daguerreotype; but not 
until we had learnt by ample experience, that observation of 
such a picture is precisely equivalent to observation of the 
original. 

These considerations also remove the obj'ection arising from 
the impossibility of ocularly following the lines m their pro¬ 
longation to infinity. Tor though, m order actually to see 
that two given lines never meet, it would be necessary to 
follow them to infinity, yet without doing so we may know 
that if they ever do meet, or if, after diverging from one 
another, they begin again to approach, this must take place 
not at an infinite, but at a finite distance. Supposing, there¬ 
fore, such to be the case, we can transport ourselves thither m 
imagination, and can frame a mental image of the appearance 
which one or both of the lines must present at that point, 
which we may rely on as being precisely similar to the reality. 
Now, whether we fix our contemplation upon this imaginary 
picture, or call to mind the generalizations we have had occa¬ 
sion to make from former ocular observation, we learn by the 
evidence of experience, that a line which, after diverging from 
another straight line, begins to approach to it, produces 
the impression on our senses which we 'describe by the ex¬ 
pression, “ a bent line,” not by the expression, u a straight 
line.”* 

* Dr. Whewell {Philosophy of Discovery, p. 289) thinks it unreasonable 
to contend that we know by experience, that our idea of a line exactly resembles 
a real line, “ It does not appear,” he says, “ how we can compare our ideas 



264 


REASONING. 


§ 6. The first of the two arguments m support of the 
theory that axioms are apiiori truths, having, I think, been 
sufficiently answered, I proceed to the second, which is usually 
the most relied on Axioms (it is asserted) are conceived by 
us not only as true, but as universally and necessarily true. 
Now, experience cannot possibly give to any proposition this 


■with the realities, since we know the reahties only by our ideas ” We know 
the realities (I conceive) by oui senses Dr Whewell surely does not hold the 
“ doctrine of perception by means of ideas,” which Reid gave himself so much 
trouble to refute. 

If Dr Whewell doubts whether we compare our ideas with the corresponding 
sensations, and assume that they resemble, let me ask on what evidence do we 
judge that a poi trait of a person not present is like the original Surely because 
it is like our idea, or mental image of the person, and because our idea is like 
the man himself 

Dr Whewell also says, that it does not appear why this resemblance of 
ideas to the sensations of which they are copies, should be spoken of as if it 
were a peculiarity of one class of ideas, those of space My reply is, that I do 
not so speak of it. The peculiarity I contend for is only one of degree All our 
ideas of sensation of course resemble the corresponding sensations, but they do so 
with very different degrees of exactness and of reliability No one, I presume, 
can recal m imagination a colour or an odour with the same distinctness and 
accuracy with which almost every one can mentally reproduce an image of a 
straight line or a triangle To the extent, howevei, of their capabilities of 
accuracy, our recollections of colours or of odours may serve as subjects of 
experimentation, as well as those of lines and spaces, and may yield conclusions 
which will be true of their external prototypes A person m whom, either from 
natural gift or from cultivation, the impressions of coloui were peculiarly vivid 
and distinct, if asked which of two blue flowers was of the darkest tmge, though 
he might never have compared the two, or even looked at them together, might 
be able to give a confident answer on the faith of his distinct recollection of the 
colours, that is, he might examine his mental pictuies, and find there a pro¬ 
perty of the outward objects. But m hardly any case except that of simple 
geometrical forms, could this be done by mankind generally, with a degree of 
assurance equal to that which is given by a contemplation of the objects them¬ 
selves Persons differ most widely m the precision of their recollection, even of 
loims • one peison, when he has looked any one m the face for half a minute, can 
draw an accurate likeness of him from memory , another may have seen him every 
day for six months, and hardly know whether his nose is long or short. But every¬ 
body has a perfectly distinct mental image of a straight line, a cncle, or a rec¬ 
tangle And every one concludes confidently from these mental images to the 
corresponding outward things The tiuth is, that we may, and continually do, 
study nature m our recollections, when the objects themselves are absent, and 
in the case of geometrical forms we can perfectly, but in most other cases only 
imperfectly, trust our recollections. 



DEMONSTRATION, AND NECESSARY TRUTHS. 265 

character. I may have seen snow a hundred times, and may 
have seen that it was white, hut this cannot give me entire 
assurance even that all snow is white, much less that snow 
must he white. “ However many instances we may have ob¬ 
served of the truth of a pioposition, there is nothing to assure 
us that the next case shall not he an exception to the lule 
If it be strictly true that every ruminant animal yet known 
has cloven hoofs, we still cannot be sure that some creature 
will not hereafter be discovered which has the first of these, 
attributes, without having the other. . . . Experience must 
always consist of a limited number of observations , and, how- 
evei numerous these may be, they can show nothing with re¬ 
gard to the infinite number of cases m which the experiment 
has not been made.” Besides, Axioms are not only universal, 
they are also necessary. Now “experience cannot offer the 
smallest ground for the necessity of a proposition. She can 
observe and record what has happened, but she cannot find, 
m any case, or m any accumulation of cases, any reason for t 
what must happen. She may see objects side by side, but she , 
cannot see a reason why they must ever be side by side. She i 
finds certain events to occur m succession, but the succession 
supplies, m its occurrence, no reason for its recurrence. She 
contemplates external objects, but she cannot detect any in¬ 
ternal bond, which indissolubly connects the future with the 
past, the possible with the real. To learn a proposition by ex¬ 
perience, and to see it to be necessarily true, are two altogether 
different processes of thought.”* And Dr. Whewell adds, “ If 
any one does not clearly comprehend this distinction of neces¬ 
sary and contingent truths, he will not be able to go along 
with us m our researches into the foundations of human know¬ 
ledge , nor, indeed, to pursue with success any speculation on 
the subject.”+ 

In the following passage, we are told what the distinction 
is, the non-recognition of which incurs this denunciation 
“ Necessary truths are those in which we not only learn that 
the proposition is true, but see that it must he true, m which 


History of Scientific Ideas, 1 . 65-67. 


f Ibid. 60. 



266 


REASONING. 


the negation of the truth is not only false, but impossible, m 
which we cannot, even by an effort of imagination, or m a sup¬ 
position, conceive the reverse of that which is asserted. That 
there are such truths cannot be doubted. We may take, for 
example, all relations of number Three and Two added to¬ 
gether make FiveT We cannot conceive it to be otherwise. 
We cannot, by any freak of thought, imagine Three and Two 
to make Seven.”* 

, Although Dr Whewell has naturally and properly employed 
a vanety of phrases to bring his meaning more forcibly home, 
he would, I presume, allow that they are all equivalent, and 
that wh$t he means by a necessary truth, would be sufficiently 
defined, a proposition the negation of which is not only false 
hut inconceivable I am unable to find m any of his expres¬ 
sions, turn them what way you will, a meaning beyond this, 
and I do not believe he would contend that they mean any¬ 
thing more. 

This, therefore, is the principle asserted : that propositions, 
the negation of which is inconceivable, or m othei woids, which 
we cannot figure to ourselves ets being false, must rest on evi¬ 
dence of a higher and more cogent description than any which 
experience can afford. 

Now I cannot but wonder that so much stress should be 
laid on the circumstance of inconceivableness, when there is 
such ample experience to show, that our capacity or incapacity 
of conceiving a thing has very little to do with the possibility 
of the thing m itself, but is m truth very much an affair 
of accident, and depends on the past history and habits of our 
own minds. There is no more generally acknowledged fact 
in human nature, than the extreme difficulty at first felt m 
conceiving anything as possible, which is m contradiction to 
long established and familiar experience, or even to old 
familiar habits of thought. And this difficulty is a necessary 
result of the fundamental laws of the human mind. When 
we have often seen and thought of two things together, and 
have never in any one instance either seen or thought of them 


History of Scientific Ideas , i. 58, 59. 



DEMONSTRATION, AND NECESSARY TRUTHS. 267 

separately, there is by the primary law of association an in¬ 
creasing difficulty, which may m the end become msupeiable, 
of conceiving the two things apart This is most of all con¬ 
spicuous in uneducated persons, who are m general utterly 
unable to separate any two ideas which have once become 
firmly associated in their minds, and if persons of cultivated 
intellect have any advantage on the point, it is only because, 
having seen and heard and read more, and being more accus¬ 
tomed to exercise their imagination, they have experienced 
their sensations and thoughts m more varied combinations, and 
have been prevented from forming many of these inseparable 
associations But this advantage has necessarily its limits. 
The most practised intellect is not exempt from the universal 
laws of our ccfnceptive faculty. If daily habit presents to 
any one for a long period two facts m combination, and if he 
, is not led during that period either by accident or by his 
voluntary mental operations to think of them apart, he will 
probably m time become incapable of doing so even by the 
strongest effort, and the supposition that the two facts can be 
separated m nature, will at last present itself to his mind 
with all the characters of an inconceivable phenomenon * 
There are remarkable instances of this m the history of science : 
instances m which the most instructed men rejected as impos¬ 
sible, because inconceivable, things which their posterity, by 
earlier practice and longer perseverance m the attempt, found 
it quite easy to conceive, and which everybody now knows to 
be tiue. There was a time when men of the most cultivated 
intellects, and the most emancipated from the dominion of 
early prejudice, could not credit the existence of antipodes ; 
were unable to conceive, m opposition to old association, the 
force of gravity acting upwards instead of downwards. The 
Cartesians long rejected the Newtonian doctrine of the gravi- 


* “ If all mankind had spoken one language, we cannot doubt that there 
would have been a powerful, perhaps a universal, school of philosopheis, who 
would have believed m the inherent connexion between names and things, who 
would have taken the sound man to be the mode of agitating the air which is 
essentially communicative of the ideas of reason, cookery, bipedality, &c —De 
Morgan, Formal Logic , p. 246. 


268 


REASONING. 


tation of all bodies towards one another, on the faith of a 
geneial proposition, the reverse of which seemed to them to 
he inconceivable—the proposition that a body cannot act where 
it is not. All the cumbrous machinery of imaginary vortices, 
assumed without the smallest particle of evidence, appeared to 
these philosophers a more rational mode of explaining the 
heavenly motions, than one which involved what seemed to 
them so great an absuidity.* And they no douht found it as 
impossible to conceive that a body should act upon the earth 
at the distance of the sun or moon, as we find it to conceive 
an end to space or time, or two straight lines inclosing a space 
Newton himself had not been able to realize the conception, 
or we should not have had his hypothesis of a subtle ether, the 
occult cause of gravitation, and his writings prove, that 
though he deemed the particular nature of the intermediate 
agency a matter of conjecture, the necessity of some such 
agency appeared to him indubitable. It would seem that even 
now the majority of scientific men have not completely got 
over this very difficulty, for though they have at last learnt 
to conceive the sun attracting the earth without any intervening 
fluid, they cannot yet conceive the sun illuminating the eaith 
without some such medium. 

If, then, it be so natural to the human mind, even in a 
high state of culture, to he incapable of conceiving, and on 
that ground to believe impossible, what is afterwards not only 
found to be conceivable but proved to be true; what wonder 


* It would be difficult to name a man more remarkable at once for the great¬ 
ness and the wide range of his mental accomplishments, than Leibnitz. Yet this 
eminent man gave as a reason for rejecting Newton’s scheme of the solar system, 
that God could not make a body revolve lound a distant centie, unless either by 
some impelling mechanism, or by miracle —“ Toutce qui n’est pas explicable” 
says he in a letter to the Abbd Conti, “ par la nature des creatures, est mira- 
culeux. II ne suffit pas de dire Dieu a fait une telle loi de nature, done la 
chose est naturelle II faut que la loi soit executable par les natures des 
creatures Si Dieu donnait cette loi, par exemple, h un corps libre, de tourner 
d l’entour d’un certain centre, il faudrait ou guhl y joignit d'autres corps qui 
par leur impulsion Vobligeassent de Tester toujours dans son orbite circular e i ou 
qu\l mit un ange & ses trousses , ou enfin il faudrait quhl y concourilt extraordi- 
nairement , car naturellement il s’ecartera par la tangente.”— Works of Leibnitz, 
ed. Dutens, in 446. 



DEMONSTRATION, AND NECESSARY TRUTHS. 269 

if m cases where the association is still older, more confirmed, 
and more familiar, and m which nothing ever occurs to shake 
our conviction, or even suggest to us any conception at vari¬ 
ance with the association, the acquired incapacity should con¬ 
tinue, and he mistaken for a natural incapacity ? It is true, 
our experience of the varieties m nature enables us, within 
certain limits, to conceive other varieties analogous to them. 
We can conceive the sun or moon falling, foi though we 
never saw them fall, nor ever perhaps imagined them falling, 
we have seen so many other things fall, that we have innu¬ 
merable familiar analogies to assist the conception , which, 
after all, we should probably have some difficulty m framing, 
were we not well accustomed to see the sun and moon move 
(or appear to move,) so that we are only called upon to con¬ 
ceive a slight change m the direction of motion, a circum¬ 
stance familiar to our experience But when experience affords 
no model on which to shape the new conception, how is it 
possible for us to form it? How, for example, can we imagine 
an end to space or time ? We never saw any object without 
something beyond it, nor experienced any feeling without 
something following it When, therefore, we attempt to con¬ 
ceive the last point of space, we have the idea irresistibly 
raised of other points beyond it. When we try to imagine 
the last instant of time, we cannot help conceiving another 
instant after it Nor is there any necessity to assume, as is 
done by a modem school of metaphysicians, a peculiar funda¬ 
mental law of the mind to account for the feeling of infinity 
inherent in our conceptions of space and time, that apparent 
infinity is sufficiently accounted for by simpler and universally 
acknowledged laws. 

Now, in the case of a geometrical axiom, such, for example, 
as that two straight lines cannot inclose a space,—a truth 
which is testified to us by our very earliest impressions of the 
external woild,—how is it possible (whether those external 
impressions be or be not the giound of our belief) that the 
reverse of the proposition could be otherwise than inconceiv¬ 
able to ns ? What analogy have we, what similar order of 
facts in any other branch of our expenence, to facilitate to us 



270 


REASONING. 


the conception of two straight lines inclosing a space ? Nor 
is even this all. I have already called attention to the pecu¬ 
liar property of our impressions of form, that the ideas oi 
mental images exactly resemble their prototypes, and ade¬ 
quately represent them for the purposes of scientific obseiva- 
tion. From this, and from the intuitive character of the 
observation, which m this case reduces itself to simple inspec¬ 
tion, we cannot so much as call up m our imagination two 
straight lines, in order to attempt to conceive them inclosing 
a space, without by that very act repeating the scientific 
experiment which establishes the contraiy. Will it really be 
contended that the inconceivableness of the thing, m such cir¬ 
cumstances, proves anything against the experimental origin 
of the conviction ? Is it not clear that m whichever mode our 
belief m the proposition may have originated, the impossibility 
of our conceiving the negative of it must, on either hypothesis, 
be the same ? As, then, Dr Whewell exhorts those who have 
any difficulty m recognising the distinction held by him between 
necessary and contingent truths, to study geometry,—a condi¬ 
tion which I can assure him I have conscientiously fulfilled,— 
I, m leturn, with equal confidence, exhort those who agi;ee 
with him, to study the geneial laws of association, being con¬ 
vinced that nothing more is requisite than a moderate familiarity 
with those laws, to'dispel the illusion which ascnbes a peculiar 
necessity to our earliest inductions from experience, and mea¬ 
sures the possibility of things m themselves, by the human 
capacity of conceiving them. 

I hope to be pardoned for adding, that Dr. Whewell him¬ 
self has both confirmed by his testimony the effect of habitual 
association m giving to an experimental truth the appearance 
of a necessary one, and afforded a striking instance of that 
remarkable law m his own person In his Philosophy of the 
Inductive Sciences he continually asseits, that propositions 
which not only are not self-evident, but which we know to 
have been discovered gradually, and by great efforts of genius 
and patience, have, when once established, appeared so self- 
evident that, but for historical proof, it would have been impos¬ 
sible to conceive that they had not been recognised from the 



DEMONSTRATION* AND NECESSARY TRUTHS. 271 

first by all persons in a sound state of their faculties. “ We 
now despise those who, m the Copermcan controversy, could 
not conceive the apparent motion of the sun on the heliocentric 
hypothesis, or those who, m opposition to Galileo, thought 
that a uniform force might be that which generated a velocity 
proportional to the space, or those who held there was some¬ 
thing absurd m Newtons doctune of the different refrangi- 
bility of differently coloured rays, or those who imagined that 
when elements combine, their sensible qualities must be mani¬ 
fest m the compound, or those who were reluctant to give up 
the distinction of vegetables into herbs, shrubs, and trees. 
We cannot help thinking that men must have been smgulaily 
dull of comprehension, to find a difficulty m admitting what 
is to us so plain and simple We have a latent persuasion 
that we m their place should have been wiser and more clear¬ 
sighted , that we should have taken the right side, and given 
our assent at once to the truth. Yet m reality such a per¬ 
suasion is a mere delusion. The persons who, m such instances 
the above, were on the losing side, were very far, *m most 
cases, from being persons more prejudiced, or stupid, or narrow¬ 
minded, than the greater part of mankind now are, and the 
cause^ for which they fought was far from being a manifestly 
bad one, till it had been so decided by the result of the war. 

. . . So complete has been the victory of truth m most of 

these instances, that at present we can hardly imagine the 
struggle to have been necessary. The very essence of these 
triumphs is, that they lead us to regard the views we reject as 
not only false but inconceivable”* 

This last proposition is precisely what I contend for, and 
I ask no more, m order to overthrow the whole theory of its 
author on the nature of the evidence of axioms. Tor what is 
that theory ? That the truth of axioms cannot have been 
learnt from experience, because their,, falsity is inconceivable. 
But Dr. Whewell himself says, that we are continually led, 
by the natural progress of thought, to regard as inconceivable^ 
what our forefathers not only conceived but believed, nay even 


Novum Organum J2 enovatum, pp 32, 33. 



272 


REASONING. 


(he might have added) weie unable to conceive the reveise of. 
He cannot intend to justify this mode of thought he cannot 
mean to say, that we can he light in regarding as inconceivable 
what others have conceived, and as self-evident what to others 
did not appear evident at all After so complete an admission 
that inconceivableness is an accidental thing, not mheient m 
the phenomenon itself, but dependent on the mental history of 
the person who tues to conceive it, how can he ever call upon 
us to reject a proposition as impossible on no other ground 
than its inconceivableness ? Yet he not only does so, but has 
unintentionally afforded some of the most remarkable examples 
which can be cited of the very illusion which he has himself 
so cleaily pointed out I select as specimens, his remarks on the 
evidence of the three laws of motion, and of the atomic theory. 

With respect to the ]aws of motion, Dr Whew ell says: 
“No one can doubt that, m historical fact, these laws were 
collected from experience. That such is the case, is no 
matter of conjecture. We know the time, the peisons, the 
circumstances, belonging to each step of each discovery ”* 
After this testimony, to adduce evidence of the fact would be 
superfluous. And not only weie these laws by no means 
intuitively evident, but some of them were originally para¬ 
doxes The fust law was especially so That a body, once 
m motion, would continue for ever to move m the same dnec- 
tion with undimimshed velocity unless acted upon by some 
new force, was a proposition which mankind found for a long 
time the greatest difficulty m crediting. It stood opposed to 
apparent experience of the most familiar kind, which taught 
that it was the nature of motion to abate gradually, and at last 
terminate of itself. Yet when once the contrary doctrine was 
firmly established, mathematicians, as Dr Whewell observes, 
speedily began to believe that laws, thus contradictory to first 
appearances, and which, even after full proof had been ob¬ 
tained, it had required generations to render familiar to the 
minds of the scientific world, were under cc a demonstrable 
necessity, compelling them to be such as they are and no 


History of Scientific Ideas, x. 264. 



DEMONSTRATION, AND NECESSARY TRUTHS. 27S 

otherand he himself, though not venturing <c absolutely 
to pronounce 5 ’ that all these laws can be ngoiously traced 
to an absolute necessity m the nature of things,”* does actually 
so think of the law just mentioned, of which he says 
c< Though the discoveiy of the fust law of motion was made, 
histoncally speaking, by means of experiment, we have now 
attained a point of view m which we see that it might have 
been certainly known to be true, independently of experi¬ 
ence.’^ Can there be a more striking exemplification than is 
here affoided, of the effect of association which we have 
described ? Philosophers, for geneiations, have the most 
extraoi dinary difficulty m putting certain ideas together; 
they at last succeed m doing so, and after a sufficient repeti¬ 
tion of the process, they first fancy a natural bond between 
the ideas, then experience a giowing difficulty, which at last, 
by the continuation of the same progress, becomes an impos¬ 
sibility, of severing them from one another If such be the 
progress of an expenmental conviction of which the date is 
of yesterday, and which is in opposition to first appearances, 
how must it fare with those which are conformable to appear¬ 
ances familiar fiom the first dawn of intelligence, and of the 
conclusiveness of which, from the eaihest lecords of human 
thought, no sceptic has suggested even a momentaiy doubt ? 

The other instance which I shall quote is a truly asto¬ 
nishing one, and may be called the reductio ad absurdum of 
the theory of inconceivableness. Speaking of the laws of 
chemical composition. Dr. Whewell says J ff That they could 
never have been cleaily understood, and theiefore never firmly 
established, without labonous and exact experiments, is 
certain, but yet we may venture to say, that being once 
known, they possess an evidence beyond that of mere experi¬ 
ment For how m fact can we conceive combinations, other¬ 
wise than as definite in kind and quality 2 If we were to 
suppose each element ready to combine with any other indif¬ 
ferently, and mdiffeiently m any quantity, we should have a 


* Mist. JSc Id y i 263 f Ibid 240 

t Hist. Sc. Id.y il 25, 26. 

18 


VOL. I. 



274 


REASONING. 


world m winch all would be confusion and indefiniteness 
There would be no fixed kinds of bodies. Salts, and stones, 
and ores, would approach to and graduate into each other by 
insensible degrees Instead of this, we know that the world 
consists of bodies distinguishable from each other by definite 
differences, capable of being classified and named, and of 
having general propositions asserted concerning them And 
as we cannot conceive a world m which this should not be the 
case, it would appear that we cannot conceive a state of things 
m which the laws of the combination of elements should not 
be of that definite and measured kind which we have above 
asserted.” 

That a philosopher of Dr. Whew ell’s eminence should 
gravely assert that we cannot conceive a world m which the 
simple elements should combine m other than definite pro¬ 
portions ; that by dint of meditating on a scientific truth, the 
original discoverer of which was still living, he should have 
rendered the association in his own mind between the idea 
of combination and that of constant proportions so familiar 
and intimate as to be unable to conceive the one fact without 
the other, is so signal an instance of the mental law for which 
I am contending, that one word more m illustration must be 
superfluous. 

In the latest and most complete elaboration of his meta¬ 
physical system (the Philosophy of Discovery), as well as m 
the earlier discouise on the Fundamental Antithesis of Philo¬ 
sophy, reprinted as an appendix to that woik, Dr Whewell, 
while very candidly admitting that his language was open to 
misconception, disclaims having intended to say that mankind 
m general can now perceive the law of definite proportions m 
chemical combination to be a necessary truth. All he meant 
was that philosophical chemists m a future generation may 
possibly see this. “ Some truths may be seen by intuition, 
but yet the intuition of them may be a rare and a difficult at¬ 
tainment ”■* And he explains that the mconoeivableness 


PTiiL of Disc , p. 339. 



DEMONSTRATION^ AND NECESSARY TRUTHS. 


275 


which, according to his theory, is the test of axioms, “ de¬ 
pends entiiely upon the clearness of the Ideas which the 
axioms involve. So long as those Ideas aie vague and indis¬ 
tinct, the contrary of an Axiom may be assented to, though 
it cannot be distinctly conceived It may be assented to, not 
because it is possible, but because we do not see clearly what 
is possible To a person who is only beginning to think 
geometrically, there may appear nothing absuid m the asser¬ 
tion, that two straight lines may inclose a space And m the 
same manner, to a person who is only beginning to think of 
mechanical truths, it may not appear to be absurd, that m 
mechanical piocesses, Eeaction should be greater or less than 
Action, and so, again, to a person who has not thought 
steadily about Substance, it may not appear inconceivable, 
that by chemical operations, we should generate new mattei, 
or destroy matter which already exists ”* Necessary truths, J 
therefore, are not those of which we cannot conceive, but 
“those of which we cannot distinctly conceive, the contiaiyAt 
So long as our ideas are indistinct altogether, we do not know 
what is or is not capable of being distinctly conceived; but, 
by the ever increasing distinctness with which scientific men 
apprehend the general conceptions of science, they m time 
come to perceive that theie are certain laws of nature, which, 
though historically and as a matter of fact they were learnt 
from experience, we cannot, now that we know them, distinctly 
conceive to he other than they are. 

The account which I should give of this progress of the 
scientific mind is somewhat different. After a general law of 
nature has been ascertained, mens minds do not at first acquit e 
a complete facility of familiarly representing to themselves the 
phenomena of nature m the character which that law assigns 
to them. The habit which constitutes the scientific cast of 
mind, that of conceiving facts of all descriptions conformably 
to the laws which regulate them—phenomena of all descrip¬ 
tions according to the relations which have been ascertained 
really to exist between them, this habit, in the case of newly 


* PTiil of Disc , p 338 

18—2 


f Xb. p. 463 



276 


REASONING. 


discovered relations, comes only by degrees. So long as it is 
not thoioughly formed, no necessaiy chaiacter is ascubed to 
the new truth. But m time, the philosopher attains a state of 
mind m which his mental picture of nature spontaneously re¬ 
presents to him all the phenomena with which the new theory 
is concerned, m the exact light m which the theory regards 
them: all images or conceptions derived from any other theory, 
or flora the confused view of the facts which is anterior to any 
theory, having entirely disappeared from his mind. The mode 
of repiesentmg facts which 1 esults from the theory, has now 
become, to his faculties, the only natural mode of conceiving 
them. It is a known truth, that a prolonged habit of arrang¬ 
ing phenomena m certain groups, and explaining them by 
means of certain principles, makes any other arrangement or 
explanation of these facts be felt as unnatural and it may at 
last become as difficult to him to represent the facts to himself 
m any other mode, as it often was, originally, to represent 
them in that mode 

But, further, if the theory is true, as we are supposing it to 
be, any other mode m which he tues, or m which he was for¬ 
merly accustomed, to represent the phenomena, will be seen 
by him to be inconsistent with the facts that suggested the new 
theory—facts which now form a part of his mental picture of 
natuie. And since a contradiction is always inconceivable, his 
imagination rejects these false theories, and declares itself in¬ 
capable of conceiving them Their inconceivableness to him 
does not, however, result from anything m the theones them¬ 
selves, intrinsically and a prion repugnant to the human 
faculties, it results from the repugnance between them and a 
poition of the facts , which facts as long as he did not know, 
or did not distinctly realize m his mental representations, the 
false theory did not appear other than conceivable, it becomes 
inconceivable, merely from the fact that contradictory elements 
cannot be combined m the same conception. Although, then, 
his real reason for rejecting theones at variance with the true 
one, is no other than that they clash with his experience, he 
easily falls into the belief, that he rejects them because they 
are inconceivable, and that he adopts the true theory because 



DEMONSTRATION, AND NECESSARY TRUTHS*. 277 

it is self-evident, and does not need the evidence of expenence 
at all. 

This I take to be the real and sufficient explanation of the 
paradoxical tiuth, on which so much stress is laid by Dr 
Whewell, that a scientifically cultivated mind is actually, m 
virtue of that cultivation, unable to conceive suppositions 
which a common man conceives without the smallest diffi¬ 
culty. For theie is nothing inconceivable m the suppositions 
themselves, the impossibility is m combining them with facts 
inconsistent with them, as part of the same mental pictuie, 
an obstacle of course only felt by those who know the tacts, 
and are able to perceive the inconsistency. As far as the sup¬ 
positions themselves are concerned, m the case of many of 
Dr Whewell’s necessary truths the negative of the axiom is, 
and probably will be as long as the human race lasts, as easily 
conceivable as the affixmative There is no axiom (for ex¬ 
ample) to which Dr Whewell ascribes a more thorough cha- 
xacter of necessity and self-evidence, than that of the indestruc¬ 
tibility of matter That this is a true law of nature I fully 
admit; but I imagine there is no human being to whom the 
opposite supposition is inconceivable—who has any difficulty m 
imagining a portion of matter annihilated. inasmuch as its 
apparent annihilation, m no respect distinguishable from real 
by our unassisted senses, takes place every time that water 
dries up, or fuel is consumed. Again, the law that bodies 
combine chemically m definite proportions is undeniably true , 
but few besides Dr. Whewell have reached the point which he 
seems personally to have arrived at, (though he only dares 
prophesy similar success to the multitude after the lapse of 
generations,) that of being unable to conceive a world m which 
the elements are ready to combine with one another “ indiffe¬ 
rently m any quantitynor is it likely that we shall ever nse 
to this sublime height of inability, so long as all the mechanical 
mixtures m our planet, whether solid, liquid, or aeriform, ex¬ 
hibit to our daily observation the very phenomenon declared to 
be inconceivable. 

According to Dr. Whewell, these and similar laws of nature 
cannot be drawn from experience, inasmuch as they are, on 



278 


REASONING. 


the contrary, assumed m the interpretation of experience. Our 
inability to “ add to or dimmish the quantity of matter in the 
world,” is a truth which “neither is nor can he derived from 
experience, for the experiments which we make to verify it 
presuppose its truth. . . . When men began to use the 

balance m chemical analysis, they did not prove by trial, but 
took for granted, as self-evident, that the weight of the whole 
must be found m the aggregate weight of the elements.”* 
True, it is assumed, but, I apprehend, no otherwise than as 
all experimental mquny assumes provisionally some theory or 
hypothesis, which is to be finally held true or not, according as 
the experiments decide. The hypothesis chosen for this pur¬ 
pose will natui ally be one which groups together some consi- 
deiable number of facts already known. The proposition that 
the material of the world, as estimated by weight, is neither 
increased nor diminished by any of the processes of nature or 
ait, had many appearances m its favour to begin with. It 
expressed tiuly a gieat number of familiar facts There were 
other facts which it had the appearance of conflicting with, 
and which made its truth, as an universal law of nature, at first 
doubtful Because it was doubtful, experiments were devised 
to verify it Men assumed its truth hypothetically, and pro¬ 
ceeded to try whether, on more careful examination, the pheno¬ 
mena which apparently pointed to a different conclusion, would 
not be found to be consistent with it. This turned out to be 
the case, and from that time the doctrine took its place as an 
universal truth, but as one proved to be such by experience. 
That the theory itself preceded the proof of its truth—that it 
had to be conceived before it could be proved, and m order 
that it might be proved—does not imply that it was self-evi¬ 
dent, and did not need proof Otherwise all the true theories 
in the sciences are necessary and self-evident, for no one 
knows better than Dr. Whewell that they all began by being 
assumed, for the purpose of connecting them by deductions 
with those facts of experience on which, as evidence, they now 
confessedly rest t 


* Phil, of Disc a pp 472, 473 

f The Quarterly Review for June 1841, contained an article of great ability 



DEMONSTRATION, AND NECESSARY TRUTHS, 279 


on Dr. Whewell’s two great works (since acknowledged and repunted in Sir 
John Herschel’s Essays) which maintains, on the subject of axioms, the doctrine 
advanced m the text, that they are generalizations from experience, and sup¬ 
ports that opinion by a line of argument strikingly coinciding with mine 
When I state that the whole of the present chapter (except the last foui 
pages, added m the fifth edition) was written before I had seen the article, 
(the greater part, indeed, before it was published,) it is not my object to 
occupy the reader’s attention with a matter so unimportant as the degree 
of originality which may or may not belong to any portion of my own 
speculations, but to obtain foi an opinion which is opposed to reigning doc¬ 
trines, the recommendation derived from a striking concunence of sentiment 
between two inquirers entirely independent of one another I embrace the 
opportunity of citing fiom a writer of the extensive acquirements m physical 
and metaphysical knowledge and the capacity of systematic thought which the 
article evinces, passages so remarkably in unison with my own views as the 
following — 

“ The truths of geometry are summed up and embodied m its definitions 
and axioms . Let us turn to the axioms, and what do we find 2 A string 
of propositions concerning magnitude in the abstract, which are equally true of 
space, time, force, number, and eveiy other magnitude susceptible of aggrega¬ 
tion and subdivision Such propositions, where they are not meie definitions, 
as some of them are, cany their inductive origin on the face of their enuncia¬ 
tion Those which declare that two straight lines cannot inclose a space, 

and that two straight lines which cut one another cannot both be parallel to a 
third, arem reality the only ones which expiess chai act eristic properties of space, 
and these it will be worth while to consider more nearly. Now the only clear 
notion we can foim of straightness is uniformity of diiection, for space m its 
ultimate analysis is nothing but an assemblage of distances and directions And 
(not to dwell on the notion of continued contemplation, i e , mental expenence, 
as included m the very idea of uniformity , nor on that of transfer of the contem¬ 
plating being from point to point, and of experience, during such tiansfer, of 
the homogeneity of the intei val passed over) we cannot even piopose the propo¬ 
sition in an intelligible form to any one whose experience ever since he was born 
has not assured him of the fact. The unity of direction, or that we cannot march 
from a given point by more than one path dnect to the same object, is matter of 
practical expenence long before it can by possibility become matter of abstiact 
thought We cannot attempt mentally to exemplify the conditions of the assertion 
m an tmagmai y case opposed to it, without violating our habitual recollection of 
this experience, and defacing our menial picture of space as grounded on it 
What but expenence, we may ask, can possibly assure us of the homogeneity of 
the parts of distance, tune, force, and measurable aggregates in general, on 
which the truth of the other axioms depends ? As regards the lattei axiom, after 
what has been said it must be clear that the very same course of iemarks equally 
applies to its case, and that its truth is quite as much forced on the mind as that 
of the former by daily and hourly experience, . including always , be it 
observed , m our notion of experience , that which is gained by contemplation of 
the inward picture which the mind forms to itself m any proposed case , or which 
it arbitrarily selects as an example—such picture , m virtue of the extreme sim- 



280 


REASONING. 


phcity of these primary relations , being called up by the imagination with as much 
vividness and clearness as could be done by any external impression , which is the 
only meaning we can attach to the word intuition , as applied to such relations ” 
And again, of the axioms of mechanics —“As we admit no such propo¬ 
sitions, other than as truths inductively collected from observation, even m 
geometry itself, it can hardly be expected that, m a science of obviously contin¬ 
gent relations, we should acquiesce in a contrary view Let us take one of these 
axioms and examine its evidence for instance, that equal forces perpendicularly 
applied at the opposite ends of equal arms of a straight lever will balance each 
other What but experience, we may ask, in thefhst place, can possibly inform 
us that a force so applied will have any tendency to turn the lever on its centre 
at all 2 or that force can be so transmitted along a rigid line perpendicular to its 
direction, as to act elsewhere m space than along its own line of action 2 Surely 
this is so far from being self-evident that it has even a paradoxical appearance, 
which is only to he removed by giving our lever thickness, material composition* 
and molecular powers Again, we conclude, that the two forces, being equal 
and applied under precisely similar circumstances, must, if they exert any effort 
at all to turn the lever, exeit equal and opposite efforts but what & prion 
reasoning can possibly assure us that they do act under precisely similar circum¬ 
stances 2 that points which differ in place are similarly circumstanced as regards 
the exertion of force 2 that universal space may not have relations to universal 
foice—or, at all events, that the organization of the material universe may not 
be such as to place that portion of space occupied by it m such relations to the 
forces exerted m it, as may invalidate the absolute similarity of circumstances 
assumed 2 Oi we may argue, what have we to do with the notion of angular 
movement m the lever at all 2 The case is one of rest, and of quiescent de¬ 
struction of force by force. Now how is this destruction effected 2 Assuredly 
by the counter-pressure which supports the fulcrum But would not this de¬ 
struction equally arise, and by the same amount of counter-acting force, if 
each force simply pressed its own half of the lever against the fulcrum 2 And 
what can assure us that it is not so, except removal of one or other force, and 
consequent tilting of the lever * The other fundamental axiom of statics, that 
the pressure on the point of support is the sum of the weights . is merely 
a scientific transformation and more refined mode of stating a coarse and 
obvious result of universal experience, viz that the weight of a rigid body is 
the same, handle it or suspend it m what position or by what point we will, 
and that whatever sustains it sustains its total weight Assuredly, as Mr. 
Whewell justly remarks, ‘ No one probably ever made a trial for the purpose 
of showing that the pressure on the support is equal to the sum of the weights.’ 
. . . But it is precisely because m every action of his life from eaikest infancy 
he has been continually making the trial, and seeing it made by every other 
living being about him, that he never di earns of staking its result on one addi¬ 
tional attempt made with scientific accuracy. This would be as if a man 
shouldiesol veto decide by experiment whether his eyes were useful forthe purpose 
of seemg, by hermetically sealing himself up for half an hour in a metal case.’ 5 

On the “ paiadox of universal propositions obtained by experience,” the same 
writer says * 1 If there be necessary and universal truths expressible m proposi¬ 
tions of axiomatic simplicity and obviousness a and having for their subject- 



DEMONSTRATION, AND NECESSARY TRUTHS. 281 


matter the elements of all our experience and all our knowledge, surely these are 
the tiuths which, if experience suggest to us any truths at all, it ought to suggest 
most readily, cleaily, and unceasingly. If it were a truth, universal and neces¬ 
sary, that a net is spread over the whole surface of eveiy planetary globe, we 
should not travel far on our own without getting entangled m its meshes, and 
making the necessity of some means of extrication an axiom of locomotion , . 

There is, therefore, nothing paradoxical, but the reverse, m our being led by 
obsei vation to a recognition of such truths, as general propositions, coextensive 
at least with all human experience That they pervade all the objects of expe¬ 
rience, must ensuie their continual suggestion by experience, that they are 
true, must ensure that consistency of suggestion, that iteration of uncontra¬ 
dicted assertion, which commands implicit assent, and removes all occasion of 
exception, that they are simple, and admit of no misunderstanding, must 
secure their admission by every mind ** 

“ A truth, necessary and umveisal, relative to any object of our knowledge, 
must verify itself m every instance where that object is before our contemplation, 
and if at the same time it be simple and intelligible, its verification must be 
obvious The sentiment of such a truth cannot , tJw efore , but be present to our 
minds whenever that object is contemplated, and must therefoi e make a part of the 
mental picture o? idea of that object which we may on any occasion summon before 
our imagination . All propositions , therefore , become not only untrue but 
inconceivable , if . . axioms be violated m their enunciation/* 

Another eminent mathematician had previously sanctioned by his authority 
the doctrine of the origin of geometrical axioms in experience. ‘ ‘ Geometry 
is thus founded likewise on observation , but of a kind so familiar and obvious, 
that the primary notions which it furnishes might seem intuitive.”— Sir John 
Leslie, quoted by Sir William Hamilton, Discourses , &c. p, 272, 



CHAPTER VI. 


THE SAME SUBJECT CONTINUED. 

§ 1. In the examination which formed the subject of 
the last chapter, into the nature of the evidence of those 
deductive sciences which are commonly represented to be 
systems of necessary truth, we have been led to the following 
conclusions. The results of those sciences are indeed neces- 
saiy, m the sense of necessarily following fiom certain Hist 
principles, commonly called axioms and definitions, that is, 
of being certainly true if those axioms and definitions are so, 
for the word necessity, even m this acceptation of it, means 
no more than certainty. But their claim to the character of 
necessity m any sense beyond this, as implying an evidence 
independent of and superior to observation and experience, 
must depend on the previous establishment of such a claim m 
favour of the definitions and axioms themselves With regard 
to axioms, we found that, considered as experimental truths, 
they rest on superabundant and obvious evidence. We in¬ 
quired, whether, since this is the case, it be imperative to 
suppose any other evidence of those truths than experimental 
evidence, any other origin foi our belief of them than an expe¬ 
rimental origin. We decided, that the burden of proof lies 
with those who maintain the affirmative, and we examined, at 
considerable length, such arguments as they have produced. 
The examination having led to the rejection of those argu¬ 
ments, we have thought ourselves warranted m concluding 
that axioms are but a class, the most universal class, of in¬ 
ductions from experience, the simplest and easiest cases of 
generalization from the facts furnished to us by our senses or 
by our internal consciousness. 

While the axioms of demonstrative sciences thus ap- 



DEMONSTRATION, AND NECESSARY TRUTHS. £83 

peared to be experimental truths, the definitions, as they are 
mconectly called, m those sciences, were found by us to be 
generalizations from expeiience which jire not even, accurately 
speaking, tiuths, being propositions m which, while we asseit 
of some kind of object, some property or properties which 
observation shows to belong to it, we at the same time deny 
that it possesses any other propeities, though m truth other 
properties do m every individual instance accompany, and m 
almost all instances modify, the property thus exclusively 
predicated. The denial, therefoie, is a mere fiction, or suppo¬ 
sition, made for the purpose of excluding the consideration of 
those modifying cncumstances, when their influence is of too 
trifling amount to be worth consideung, or adjourning it, when 
important, to a more convenient moment. 

From these considerations it would appear that Deductive 
or Demonstrative Sciences are all, without exception, Induc¬ 
tive Sciences, that their evidence is that of experience, but 
that they are also, m virtue of the peculiar character of one 
indispensable portion of the general formulae according to 
which their inductions are made, Hypothetical Sciences Then 
conclusions are only true on ceitam suppositions, which are, 
or ought to be, approximations to the truth, but are seldom, 
if ever, exactly true ,* and to this hypothetical character is to 
be ascribed the peculiar certainty, which is supposed to be 
inherent m demonstration 

What we have now asserted, however, cannot be received 
as universally true of Deductive or Demonstrative Sciences, 
until venfied by being applied to the most remarkable of all 
those sciences, that of Numbers, the theory of the Calculus, 
Arithmetic and Algebra It is harder to believe of the doc¬ 
trines of this science than of any other, either that they are 
not truths a priori, but experimental truths, or that their 
peculiar certainty is owing to their being not absolute but only 
conditional truths. This, therefore, is a case which merits 
examination apart; and the more so, because on this subject 
we have a double set of doctrines to contend with; that of the 
a py ion philosophers on one side , and on the other, a theory 
the most opposite to theirs, which was at one time very gene- 



284 


REASONING. 


rally received, and is still far from being altogether exploded, 
among metaphysicians. 

§ 2. This theoiy attempts to solve the difficulty appa¬ 
rently mhei ent m the case, by lepresentmg the propositions 
of the science of numbers as merely veibal, and its piocesses 
as simple tiansformations of language, substitutions of one 
expiession foi another. The proposition, Two and one are 
equal to thiee, according to these writers, is not a truth, is 
not the assertion of a really existing fact, but a definition of 
the word three, a statement that mankind have agreed to use 
the name thiee as a sign exactly equivalent to two and one, 
to call by the former name whatever is called by the other 
more clumsy phrase. According to this doc tune, the longest 
process m algebra is but a succession of changes in termi¬ 
nology, by which equivalent expressions are substituted one 
for another, a senes of translations of the same fact, fiom 
one into another language, though how, after such a senes 
of translations, the fact itself comes out changed (as when 
we demonstrate a new geometrical theorem by algebra,) they 
have not explained; and it is a difficulty which is fatal to 
their theory. 

It must be acknowledged that there are peculiarities m the 
processes of arithmetic and algebra which render the theoiy 
m question very plausible, and have not unnaturally made 
those sciences the stronghold of Nominalism. The doctrine 
that we can discover facts, detect the hidden processes of 
nature, by an artful manipulation of language, is so contrary 
to common sense, that a person must have made some ad¬ 
vances m philosophy to believe it. men fly to so paradoxical 
a belief to avoid, as they think, some even greater difficulty, 
which the vulgar do not see. What has led many to believe 
that reasoning is a mere verbal process, is, that no other 
theory seemed reconcileable with the nature of the Science of 
Numbers. For we do not carry any ideas along with us when 
we use the symbols of arithmetic or of algebra. In a geome- 
tncal demonstration we have a mental diagram, if not one on 
paper, AB, AC, aie present to our imagination as lines, m- 



DEMONSTRATION^ AND NECESSARY TRUTHS. 285 

teisectmg other lines, forming an angle with one another, and 
the like , but not so a and b. These may represent lines or 
any other magnitudes, but those magnitudes are never thought 
of, nothing is lealized m our imagination but a and b . The 
ideas which, on the particular occasion, they happen to repre¬ 
sent, are banished from the mind during every intermediate 
part of thepiocess, between the beginning, when the premises 
are translated from things into signs, and the end, when the 
conclusion is translated back from signs into things. Nothing, 
then, being m the reasoner’s mind but the symbols, what can 
seem moie inadmissible than to contend that the reasoning pro¬ 
cess has to do with anything more? We seem to have come 
to one of Bacons Prerogative Instances , an expemmentum 
crucis on the natuie of reasoning itself 

Nevertheless, it will appear on consideration, that this 
apparently so decisive instance is no instance at all, that there 
is m every step of an arithmetical or algebraical calculation a 
real induction, a real inference of facts fiom facts , and that 
what disguises the induction is simply its comprehensive nature, 
and the consequent extreme generality of the language. All 
numbers must be numbers of something there are no such 
things as numbers m the abstract. Ten must mean ten bodies, 
or ten sounds, or ten beatings of the pulse But though numbers 
must be numbers of something, they may be numbers of any¬ 
thing. Propositions, therefore, concerning numbers, have the 
remarkable peculiarity that they are propositions concerning 
all things whatever; all objects, all existences of every kind, 
known to our expenence. All things possess quantity , con¬ 
sist of parts which can be numbered, and m that character 
possess all the properties which are called properties of numbers. 
That half of four is two, must be true whatever the word four 
represents, whether four hours, four miles, or four pounds 
weight. We need only conceive a thing divided into four equal 
parts, (and all things may be conceived as so divided,) to be 
able to predicate of it every property of the number four, that 
is, every arithmetical proposition in which the number four 
stands on one side of the equation. Algebra extends the 
generalization still farther . every number represents that pai- 



286 


REASONING. 


ticular number of all things without distinction, but every 
algebraical symbol does more, it represents all numbers with¬ 
out distinction As soon as we conceive a thing divided into 
equal parts, without knowing into what number of paits, we 
may call it a or x, and apply to it, without danger of error, 
every algebraical formula m the books The proposition, 
2(a+b) = 2a + 2b, is a truth co-extensive with all nature. 
Since then algebraical truths are tiue of all things whatever, 
and not, like those of geometry, true of lines only or angles 
only, it is no wonder that the symbols should not excite m 
our minds ideas of any things m particular. When we de¬ 
monstrate the forty-seventh proposition of Euclid, it is not 
necessary that the words should raise m us an image of all 
right-angled tnangles, but only of some one right-angled 
triangle so m algebra we need not, under the symbol a, 
picture to ourselves all things whatever, but only some one 
thing; why not, then, the letter itself? The mere wntten 
characters, a, b, x } y, z, serve as well for representatives of 
Things m general, as any more complex and apparently 
more concrete conception That we are conscious of them 
however in their character of things, and not of mere signs, 
is evident from the fact that our whole process of reason¬ 
ing is earned on by predicating of them the properties of 
things. In resolving an algebraic equation, by what rules do 
we pr6eeed ? By applying at each step to a 3 b, and x, the 
proposition that equals added to equals make equals, that 
equals taken from equals leave equals , and other propositions 
founded on these two. These are not properties of language, 
or of signs as such, but of magnitudes, which is as much as 
to say, of all things. The inferences, therefore, which are suc¬ 
cessively drawn, are inferences concerning things, not sym¬ 
bols , though as any Things whatever will serve the turn, 
there is no necessity for keeping the idea of the Thing at all 
distinct, and consequently the process of thought may, m this 
case, be allowed without danger to do what all processes of 
thought, when they have been perfoimed often, will do if per¬ 
mitted, namely, to become entirely mechanical Hence the 
general language of algebra comes to be used familiarly with- 



DEMONSTRATION, AND NECESSARY TRUTHS. 287 

out exciting ideas, as all other general language is prone to 
do from meie habit, though m no other case than this can it 
be done with complete safety. But when we look hack to see 
from whence the piobative force of the process is derived, we 
find that at every single step, unless we suppose ourselves to 
he thinking and talking of the things, and not the mere sym¬ 
bols, the evidence fails. 

Theie is another circumstance, which, still more than that 
which we have now mentioned, gives plausibility to the notion 
that the propositions of arithmetic and algebra are merely 
verbal That is, that when considered as propositions respect¬ 
ing Things, they all have the appearance of being identical 
piopositions. The assertion, Two and one are equal to three, 
considered as an assertion respecting objects, as for instance 
“Two pebbles and one pebble are equal to three pebbles/’ 
does not affirm equality between two collections of pebbles, 
but absolute identity. It affirms that if we put one pebble to 
two pebbles, those very pebbles are three. The objects, there¬ 
fore, being the very same, and the mere assertion that “ ob¬ 
jects are themselves” being insignificant, it seems but natural 
to consider the proposition, Two and one are equal-to three, 
as asserting mere identity of signification between the two 
names 

This, however, though it looks so plausible, will not hear 
examination The expression “ two pebbles and one pebble,” 
and the expression, “ three pebbles/’ stand indeed for the 
same aggregation of objects, but they by no means stand foi 
the same physical fact They are names of the same objects, 
but of those objects m two different states % though they de¬ 
note the same things, their -connotation is different. Three 
pebbles m two separate parcels, and three pebbles m one 
parcel, do not make the same impression on our senses, and 
the assertion that the very same pebbles may by an alteration 
of place and arrangement be made to produce either the one 
set of sensations or the other, though a very familiar proposi¬ 
tion, is not an identical one. It is a truth known to us by 
early and constant experience. an inductive truth, and such 
truths are the foundation of the science of Number. The 



2S8 


REASONING. 


fundamental truths of that science all rest on the evidence of 
sense , they are proved by showing to our eyes and our fingers 
that any given number of objects, ten balls for example, may 
by separation and re-ariangement exhibit to our senses all the 
different sets of numbers the sum of which is equal to ten 
All the improved methods of teaching arithmetic to children 
proceed on a knowledge of this fact. All who wish to carry 
the child’s mind along with them in learning arithmetic , all 
who wish to teach numbers, and not mere ciphers—now teach 
it thiough the evidence of the senses, m the manner we have 
described. 

We may, if we please, call the proposition, “ Three is two 
and one,” a definition of the number three, and assert that 
anthmetic, as it has been asserted that geometiy, is a science 
founded on definitions. But they are definitions m the 
geometrical sense, not the logical, asserting not the meaning 
of a term only, but along with it an observed matter of fact. 
The proposition, “ A circle is a figure bounded by aline which 
has all its points equally distant from a point within it,” 
is called the definition of a circle, but the proposition from 
which so many consequences follow, and which is really a 
first principle m geometiy, is, that figures answering to this 
description exist. And thus we may call “ Three is two 
and one” a definition of three, but the calculations which 
depend on that proposition do not follow from the definition 
itself, but from an arithmetical theorem presupposed m it, 
namely, that collections of objects exist, which while they 
impress the senses thus, °°, may be separated into two paits, 
thus, oo o. This pioposition being granted, we term all 
such parcels Threes, after which the enunciation of the above 
mentioned physical fact will serve also for a definition of the 
word Three. 

The Science of Number is thus no exception to the conclu¬ 
sion we previously arrived at, that the piocesses even of de¬ 
ductive sciences are altogether inductive, and that their first 
principles are generalizations from experience It remains 
to be examined whether this science resembles geometry m 
the further circumstance, that some of its inductions are not 



DEMONSTRATION, AND NECESSARY TRUTHS. 289 


exactly tine, and that the peculiar certainty ascribed to it, 
on account of which its propositions are called Necessary 
Truths, is fictitious and hypothetical, being true m no other 
sense than that those propositions legitimately follow from the 
hypothesis of the truth of piemises which are avowedly mere 
approximations to truth 

§ 3. The inductions of arithmetic are of two sorts fiist, 
those which we have just expounded, such as One and one aie 
two, Two and one are three, &c, which may he called the 
definitions of the vanous numbers, m the improper or geome- 
tncal sense of the word Definition, and secondly, the two fol¬ 
lowing axioms The sums of equals are equal, The differences 
of equals are equal These two are sufficient, for the corre¬ 
sponding propositions respecting unequals may be proved from 
these, by a reductio ad ahsurdum. 

These axioms, and likewise the so-called definitions, are, 
as has already been said, results of induction, true of all ob¬ 
jects whatever, and, as it may seem, exactly true, without the 
hypothetical assumption of unqualified truth where an approxi¬ 
mation to it is all that exists The conclusions, therefore, it 
will naturally he inferred, are exactly true, and the science of 
number is an exception to other demonstrative sciences m this, 
that the categorical certainty which is predicable of its demon¬ 
strations is independent of all hypothesis. 

On more accurate investigation, however, it will he found 
that, even m this case, there is one hypothetical element in the 
latiocmation In all propositions concerning numbers, a con¬ 
dition is implied, without which none of them would be true, 
and that condition is an assumption which maybe false. The 
condition, is that 1 = 1, that all the numbers are numbers of 
the same or of equal units Let this be doubtful, and not one 
of the propositions of arithmetic will hold true How can we 
know that one pound and one pound make two pounds, if one 
of the pounds may he troy, and the other avoirdupois ? They 
may not make two pounds of either, or of any weight. How 
can we know that a forty-horse power is always equal to itself, 
unless we assume that all horses are of equal strength ? It is 
VOL. i. 19 



290 


REASONING. 


certain that 1 is always equal m number to 1, and where the 
mere number of objects, or of the parts of an object, without 
supposing them to be equivalent m any other respect, is all 
that is material, the conclusions of arithmetic, so far as thev 
go to that alone, are true without mixture of hypothesis Theie 
are a few such cases, as, for instance, an inquiry into the 
amount of the population of any country It is indifferent to 
that inquiry whether they are grown people or children, strong 
or weak, tall or short, the only thing we want to ascertain is 
then number But whenever, from equality or inequality of 
numbei, equality or inequality m any other respect is to be 
inferred, arithmetic earned into such inquiries becomes as hy¬ 
pothetical a science as geometry. All units must be assumed 
to be equal in that other respect; and this is never accurately 
true, for one actual pound weight is not exactly equal to 
another, nor one measured mile's length to another; a nicer 
balance, or more accurate measuring msti uments, would always 
, detect some diffeience. 

What is commonly called mathematical certainty, therefore, 
which comprises the twofold conception of unconditional truth 
and perfect accuracy, is not an attribute of all mathematical 
truths, but of those only which relate to pure Number, as dis- 
, tmguished from Quantity m the more enlarged sense, and 
only so long as we abstain from supposing that the numbers 
are a precise index to actual quantities. The certainty usually 
ascribed to the conclusions of geometry, and even to those of 
mechanics, is nothing whatever but certainty of inference. We 
can have full assurance of particular results under particular 
suppositions, but we cannot have the same assurance that these 
suppositions are accurately true, nor that they include all the 
data which may exercise an influence over the result in any 
given instance 

§ 4. It appears, therefore, that the method of all Deduc¬ 
tive Sciences is hypothetical. They proceed by tracing the 
consequences of certain assumptions , leaving for separate con¬ 
sideration^ whether the assumptions are true or not, and if not 



t DEMONSTRATION, AND NECESSARY TRUTHS. 291 

exactly true, whether they are a sufficiently near approxima¬ 
tion to the truth. The reason is obvious Since it is only m 
questions of pure number that the assumptions are exactly 
true, and even there, only so long as no conclusions except 
purely numerical ones are to be founded on them, it must, m 
all other cases of deductive investigation, form a part of the 
inquiry, to determine how much the assumptions want of being 
exactly true m the case in hand This is generally a matter 
of observation, to be repeated in every fresh case, or if it has 
to be settled by argument instead of observation, may require 
m every different case different evidence, and piesent every 
degree of difficulty from the lowest to the highest But the 
other part of the process—namely, to determine what else may 
he concluded if we find, and m proportion as we find, the as¬ 
sumptions to be true—may be performed once for all, and the 
results held ready to be employed as the occasions turn up for 
use We thus do all beforehand that can be so done, and leave 
the least possible work to be performed when cases arise and 
press for a decision This inquiry into the inferences which 
can be drawn from assumptions, is what properly constitutes 
Demonstrative Science 

It is of course quite as practicable to arrive at new conclu¬ 
sions from facts assumed, as from facts observed, from fic¬ 
titious, as from real, inductions. Deduction, as we have seeh, 
consists of a series of inferences in this form —a is a mark of b, 
b of c, c of d, therefore a is a mark of d, which last may be a 
truth inaccessible to direct observation In like manner it is 
allowable to say, suppose that a were a mark of b } b of c, and 
c of d, a would be a mark of d, which last conclusion was not 
thought of by those who laid down the premises A system of 
propositions as complicated as geometry might be deduced 
from assumptions which are false; as was done by Ptolemy, 
Descartes, and others, m their attempts to explain syntheti¬ 
cally the phenomena of the solar system on the supposition 
that the apparent motions of the heavenly bodies were the real 
motions, or were produced m some way more or less different 
from the true one. Sometimes the same thing is knowingly 

19—2 



292 


REASONING. 


done, for the purpose of showing the falsity of the assumption , 
which is called a redudio ad absurdum. In such cases, the 
reasoning is as follows .a is a mark of b, and b of c; now if c 
were also a maik of d, a would be a mark of d 3 but d is known 
to be a mark of the absence of a , consequently a would be a 
mark of its own absence, which is a contradiction, therefore c 
is not a mark of d 

§ 5 It has even been held by some ^writers, that all 
jatiocmation rests in the last resort on a reductio ad absur¬ 
dum , since the way to enforce assent to it, in case of ob¬ 
scurity, would be to show that if the conclusion be denied 
we must deny some one at least of the premises, which, as 
they are all supposed true, would be a contradiction And 
m accordance with this, many have thought that the peculiar 
nature of the evidence of ratiocination consisted m the impos¬ 
sibility of admitting the premises and rejecting the conclusion 
without a contradiction m terms This theory, however, is 
inadmissible as an explanation of the grounds on which ratio¬ 
cination itself lests. If any one denies the conclusion not¬ 
withstanding his admission of the premises, he is not involved 
m any direct and express contradiction until he is compelled 
to deny some premise, and he can only be forced to do this 
by a reductio ad absurdum , that is, by another ratiocination * 
now, if he denies the validity of the reasoning process itself, 
he can no more be forced to assent to the second syllogism 
than to the first In truth, therefore, no one is ever forced 
to a contradiction m terms he can only be forced to a con¬ 
tradiction (or rather an infringement) of the fundamental 
maxim of ratiocination, namely, that whatever has a maik, has 
what it is a mark of, or, (in the case of universal propositions,) 
that whatever is a mark of anything, is a mark of whatever 
else that thing is a mark of. For m the case of every correct 
argument, as soon as thrown into the syllogistic form, it is 
evident without the aid of any other syllogism, that he who, 
admitting the premises, fails to draw the conclusion, does not 
conform to the above axiom. 



DEMONSTRATION^ AND NECESSARY TRUTHS. 293 

We have now proceeded as far m the theory of Deduction 
as we can advance m the present stage of our inquiry. Any 
further insight into the subject requires that the foundation 
shall have been laid of the philosophic theory of Induction 
itself, m which theory that of deduction, as a mode of 
induction, which we have now shown it to be, will assume 
spontaneously the place which belongs to it, and will receive 
its share of whatever light may be thrown upon the great 
intellectual operation of which it forms so important a part. 



CHAPTER VII 


EXAMINATION OF SOME OPINIONS OPPOSED TO THE 
PRECEDING DOCTRINES. 

§ 1. Polemical discussion is foreign to the plan of this 
work. But an opinion which stands m need of much illus¬ 
tration, can often receive it most effectually, and least tedi- 
ously, m the form of a defence against objections. And on 
subjects concerning which speculative minds are still divided, 
a writer does but half his duty by stating his own doctrine, if 
he does not also examine, and to the best of his ability judge, 
those of other thinkers. 

In the dissertation which Mr. Herbert Spencer has prefixed 
to his, m many respects, highly philosophical treatise on the 
Mind,* he criticises some of the doctnnes of the two preceding 
chapters, and propounds a theory of his own on the subject of 
first principles. Mr. Spencer agrees with me m considering 
axioms to be “ simply our earliest inductions from experience. 1 ’ 
But he differs from me “ widely as to the worth of the test of 
inconceivableness.” He thinks that it is the ultimate test of 
all beliefs He arrives at this conclusion by two steps First, 
we never can have any stronger ground for believing anything, 
than that the belief of it “ invariably exists.” Whenever any 
fact or proposition is invariably believed, that is, if I under¬ 
stand Mr. Spencer rightly, believed by all persons, and by one¬ 
self at all times; it is entitled to be received as one of the 
primitive truths, or original premises of our knowledge. 
Secondly, the criterion by which we decide whether anything 
is invariably believed to be true, is our inability to conceive it 
as false. “ The inconceivability of its negation is the test by 
which we ascertain whether a given belief invariably exists 


Principles of Psychology 




THEORIES CONCERNING AXIOMS. 


295 


or not.” “ For our primary beliefs, the fact of mvanable 
existence, tested by an abortive effort to cause their non¬ 
existence, is the only reason assignable.” He thinks this the 
sole ground of our belief in our own sensations If I believe 
that I feel cold, I only receive this as true because I cannot 
conceive that I am not feeling cold. “ While the proposition 
remains true, the negation of it remains inconceivable. 5 
Theie are numerous other beliefs which Mr Spencer considers 
to rest on the same basis, being chiefly those, or a part of 
those, which the metaphysicians of the Reid and Stewart 
school considei as truths of immediate intuition. That there 
exists a material world, that this is the very world which we 
directly and immediately perceive, and not merely the hidden 
cause of our perceptions , that Space, Time, Force, Extension, 
Figure, are not modes of our consciousness, but objective 
realities, are regarded by Mr. Spencer as tmths known by 
the mconceivableness of their negatives We cannot, he says, 
by any effort, conceive these objects of thought as mere states 
of our mmd, as not having an existence external to us. Then 
real existence is, therefore, as certain as our sensations them¬ 
selves The truths which are the subject of direct knowledge, 
being, according to this doctrine, known to be truths only 
by the inconceivability of their negation, and the truths 
which are not the object of direct knowledge, being known 
as mfeiences from those which are, and those inferences 
being believed to follow from the premises, only because we 
cannot conceive them not to follow, inconceivability is thus 
the ultimate ground of all assured beliefs. 

Thus fai, there is no very wide difference between Mr. 
Spencer’s doctrine and the ordinary one of philosophers of the 
intuitive school, from Descartes to Dr. Whewell, but at this 
point Mr Spencer diverges from them For he does not, like 
them, set up the test of inconceivability as infallible On the 
contrary, he holds that it may be fallacious, not from any fault 
m the test itself, but because “ men have mistaken for incon¬ 
ceivable things, some things which were not inconceivable 
And he himself, m this very book, denies not a few proposi¬ 
tions usually regarded as among the most marked examples 



296 


REASONING. 


of truths whose negations are inconceivable. But occasional 
failure, he says, is incident to all tests If such failure viti¬ 
ates “ the test of mconceivableness,” it “ must similarly viti¬ 
ate all tests whatever We consider an inference logically 
drawn from established premises to be true Yet m millions of 
cases men have been wrong in the inferences they have thought 
thus diawn. Do we therefore argue that it is absurd to con¬ 
sider an inference tiue on no other ground than that it is 
logically drawn from established premises ? No . we say that 
though men may have taken for logical inferences, inferences 
that were not logical, there nevertheless are logical inferences, 
and that we are justified m assuming the truth of what seem 
to us such, until better instructed Similarly, though men 
may have thought some things inconceivable which were not 
so, there may still be inconceivable things, and the inability 
to conceive the negation of a thing, may still be our best 
warrant for believing it . . . Though occasionally it 

may prove an imperfect test, yet, as our most certain beliefs 
are capable of no better, to doubt any one belief because we 
have no higher guarantee for it, is really to doubt all beliefs ” 
Mr. Spencer s doctrine, therefore, does not erect the curable, 
but only the incurable limitations of the human conceptive 
faculty, into laws of the outward universe. 

§ 2 The doctrine, that “ a belief which is proved by the 
mconceivableness of its negation to invariably exist, is true,” 
Mr Spencer enforces by two arguments, one of which may be 
distinguished as positive, and the other as negative. 

The positive argument is, that every such belief represents 
the aggregate of all past experience. “ Conceding the entire 
truth of” the “ position, that during any phase of human pro¬ 
gress, the ability or inability to form a specific conception 
wholly depends on the experiences men have had; and that, 
by a widening of their experiences, they may, by and by, be 
enabled to conceive things before inconceivable to them, it 
may still be argued that as, at any time, the best warrant 
men can have for a, belief is the perfect agreement of all pre¬ 
existing experience in support of it, it follows that, at any 



THEORIES CONCERNING AXIOMS. 


297 


time, the mconceivableness of its negation is the deepest test 
any belief admits of. . . . Objective facts are ever im¬ 

pressing themselves upon us, our experience is a register of 
these objective facts, and the inconceivableness of a thing 
implies that it is wholly at variance with the register Even 
weie this all, it is not clear how, if every truth is primarily 
inductive, any better test of truth could exist. But it must 
he remembered that whilst many of these facts, impressing 
themselves upon us, are occasional, whilst others again are 
very general, some are universal and unchanging. These 
universal and unchanging facts are, by the hypothesis, certain 
to establish beliefs of which the negations are inconceivable; 
whilst the others are not certain to do this, and if they do, 
subsequent facts will reverse their action Hence if, after an 
immense accumulation of experiences, there remain beliefs of 
which the negations are still inconceivable, most, if not all of 
them, must correspond to universal objective facts. If there 
be . certain absolute uniformities m nature , if these 

uniformities produce, as they must, absolute uniformities m 
our experience, and if . . . these absolute uniformities 

in our experience disable us from conceiving the negations of 
them, then answering to each absolute uniformity in nature 
which we can cognize, there must exist m us a belief of which 
the negation is inconceivable, and which is absolutely true. 
In this wide range of cases subjective mconceivableness must 
correspond to objective impossibility. Further experience will 
produce correspondence where it may not yet exist, and we 
may expect the correspondence to become ultimately com¬ 
plete. In nearly all cases this test of mconceivableness must 
be valid now,” (I wish I could think we were so nearly arrived 
at omniscience) “ and where it is not, it still expresses the net 
result of our experience up to the present time, which is the 
most that any test can do.” 

To this I answer ‘ Even if it were true that mconceivableness 
represents “ the net result” of all past experience, why should we 
stop at the representative when we can get at the thing repre¬ 
sented ? If our incapacity to conceive the negation of a given 
supposition is proof of its truth, because proving that our expe- 



298 


REASONING. 


nence has hitherto been uniform in its favour, the real evidence 
for the supposition is not the inconceivableness, but the uni¬ 
formity of experience. t Now this, which is the substantial and 
only proof, is dnectly accessible. We aie not obliged to presume 
it from an incidental consequence. If all past experience is 
m favour of a belief, let this be stated, and the belief openly 
rested on that giound after which the question arises, what 
that fact may be worth as evidence of its truth ? For uni¬ 
formity of experience is evidence in very different degiees m 
some cases it is strong evidence, m others weak, m otheis it 
scarcely amounts to evidence at all. That all metals sink m 
water, was an uniform experience, from the origin of the 
human lace to the discovery of potassium m the present cen¬ 
tury by Sir Humphry Davy. That all swans are white, was 
an uniform expeuence down to the discovery of Austialia In 
the few cases m which uniformity of experience does amount 
to the strongest possible proof, as with such propositions as 
these. Two straight lines cannot inclose a space, Every event 
has a cause, it is not because their negations are inconceivable, 
which is not always the fact; but because the experience, 
which has been thus umfoim, pervades all nature. It will be 
shown m the following Book that none of the conclusions 
either of induction or of deduction can be considered certain, 
except as far as their truth is shown to be inseparably bound 
up with truths of this class, 

I maintain then, first, that uniformity of past experience is 
very far from being universally a criterion of truth. But 
secondly, mconceivableness is still farther fiom being a test 
even of that test. Uniformity of contrary expeuence is only 
one'of many causes of inconceivability Tiadition handed 
down from a period of more limited knowledge, is one of the 
commonest. The mere familiarity of one mode of production 
of a phenomenon, often suffices to make every other mode 
appear inconceivable. Whatever connects two ideas by a 
strong association may, and continually does, render their 
separation m thought impossible, as Mr Spencer, m other 
parts of his speculations, frequently recognises. It was not 
for want of experience that the Cartesians weie unable to con- 



THEORIES CONCERNING AXIOMS. 299 

eeive that one body could produce motion m another without 
contact They had as much experience of other modes of pro¬ 
ducing motion, as they had of that mode The planets had 
yevolved, and heavy bodies had fallen, every hour of their lives. 
But they fancied these phenomena to be produced by a hidden 
machmeiy which they did not see, because without it they 
were unable to conceive what they did see. The mconceiv-" 
ableness, instead of repiesentmg their experience, dominated 
and overrode their experience. It is needless to dwell farther 
on what I have termed the positive argument of Mr. Spencer 
in support of his cnterion of truth I pass to his negative 
argument, on which he lays more stress. 

§ 3. The negative argument is, that, whether inconceiv¬ 
ability be good evidence or bad, no stionger evidence is to be 
obtained. That what is inconceivable cannot be true, is pos¬ 
tulated m every act of thought. It is the foundation of all our 
original premises. Still more it is assumed m all conclusions 
fiom those premises The invariability of belief, tested by the 
mconceivableness of its negation, “is our sole warrant for 
every demonstration. Logic is simply a systematization of 
the process by which we indirectly obtain this wanant for 
beliefs that do not directly possess it. To gam the strongest 
conviction possible respecting any complex fact, we either 
analytically descend from it by successive steps, each of which 
we unconsciously test by the mconceivableness of its negation, 
until we reach some axiom or truth which we have similarly 
tested, or we synthetically ascend from such axiom or truth 
by such steps In either case we connect some isolated belief, 
with a belief which invariably exists, by a series of interme¬ 
diate beliefs which invariably exist ” The following passage 
sums up the whole theory , “ When we perceive that the 
negation of the belief is inconceivable, we have all possible 
warrant for asserting the mvanability of its existence : and m 
asserting this, we express alike our logical justification of it, 
and the inexorable necessity we are under of holding it . . . 
We have seen that this is the assumption on which every con¬ 
clusion whatever ultimately rests. We have no other guaran- 



300 


REASONING. 


tee for the reality of consciousness, of sensations, of personal 
existence, we have no other guarantee for any axiom; we 
have no other guarantee for any step m a demonstration. 
Hence, as being taken for granted m every act of the under¬ 
standing, it must be regarded as the Universal Postulate.” 
But as this postulate which we are under an “ inexorable 
necessity” of holding true, is sometimes false, as “ beliefs 
that once were shown by the inconceivableness of their nega¬ 
tions to invariably exist, have since been found untrue,” and 
as “ beliefs that now possess this character may some day share 
the same fatethe canon of belief laid down by Mr Spencer 
is, that “ the most certain conclusion” is that “ which involves 
the postulate the fewest times.” Reasoning, therefore, never 
ought to prevail against one of the immediate beliefs (the 
belief m Matter, m the outward reality of Extension, Space, 
and the like), because each of these involves the postulate only 
once ; while an argument, besides involving it m the premises, 
involves it again in every step of the ratiocination, no one of 
the successive acts of inference being recognised as valid ex¬ 
cept because we cannot conceive the conclusion not to follow 
from the premises. 

It will be convenient to take the last part of this argu¬ 
ment first In every reasoning, according to Mr. Spencer, 
the assumption of the postulate is renewed at every step. At 
each inference we judge that the conclusion follows from the 
premises, our sole warrant for that judgment being that we 
cannot conceive it not to follow. Consequently if the postu¬ 
late is fallible, the conclusions of reasoning are more vitiated 
by that uncertainty than direct intuitions; and the dispro¬ 
portion is greater, the more numerous the steps of the 
argument. 

To test this doctrine, let us first suppose an argument 
consisting only of a single step, which would be represented 
by one syllogism. This argument does rest on an assumption, 
and we have seen m the preceding chapters what the assump¬ 
tion is. It is, that whatever has a mark, has what it is a 
mark of. The evidence of this axiom I shall not consider at 



THEORIES CONCERNING AXIOMS. 301 

present / let us suppose it (with Mr Spencer) to be the m- 
conceivableness of its reverse. 

Let us now add a second step to the argument: we require, 
what 9 Another assumption 9 No: the same assumption a 
second time, and so on to a third, and a fourth I confess I 
do not see how, on Mi Spencers own principles, the repeti¬ 
tion of the assumption at all weakens the force of the argu¬ 
ment. If it were necessary the second time to assume some 
other axiom, the argument would no doubt be weakened, 
since it would be necessary to its validity that both axioms 
should be true, and it might happen that one was true and 
not the other. making two chances of error instead of one. 
But since it is the same axiom, if it is true once it is true 
eveiy time, and if the argument, being of a hundred links, 
assumed the axiom a hundred times, these hundred assump¬ 
tions would make but one chance of error among them all 
It is satisfactory that we are not obliged to suppose the 
deductions of pure mathematics to be among the most uncer-^ 
tain of argumentative processes, which on Mr. Spencer’s 
theory they could haidly fail to be, since they are the longest. 
But the number of steps m an argument does not subtract 
from its reliableness, if no new 'premises, of an uncertain cha¬ 
racter, are taken up by the way 

To speak next of the premises Our assurance of their 
truth, whether they be generalities or individual facts, is 
grounded, m Mr. Spencei’s opinion, on the mconceivableness 
of their being false It is necessary to advert to a double 
meaning of the word inconceivable, which Mr. Spencer is 
aware of, and would sincerely disclaim founding an argument 
upon, but fiom which his case derives no little advantage 
notwithstanding. By inconceivableness is sometimes meant, 
inability to form or get rid of an idea , sometimes, inability to 
form or get rid of a belief The former meaning is the most 
conformable to the analogy of language, for a conception 

* Mr Spencer is mistaken m supposing me to claim, any peculiar “neces¬ 
sity” for tins axiom as compaied with otheis I have corrected the expressions 
which led him into that misappiehension of my meaning 



302 


REASONING. 


always means an idea, and never a "belief The wrong meaning 
of “inconceivable” is, however, fully as frequent in philosophical 
discussion as the right meaning, and the intuitive school of 
metaphysicians could not well do without either. To illustrate 
the difference, we will take two contrasted examples The early 
physical speculators consideied antipodes incredible, because 
inconceivable But antipodes were not inconceivable in the 
primitive sense of the word An idea of them could be formed 
without difficulty they could be completely pictured to the 
mental eye What was difficult, and as it then seemed, impos¬ 
sible, was to apprehend them as believable. The idea could be 
put together, of men sticking on by their feet to the under side 
of the earth, but the belief icould follow, that they must fall off 
Antipodes were not unimaginable, but they were unbelievable. 

On the other hand, when I endeavour to conceive an end 
to extension, the two ideas refuse to come together. When I 
attempt to form a conception of the last point of space, I can¬ 
not help figuring to myself a vast space beyond that last point 
The combination is, under the conditions of our experience, 
unimaginable. This double meaning of inconceivable it is 
very important to bear m mind, for the argument from mcon- 
ceivableness almost always turns on the alternate substitution 
of each of those meanings for the other 

In which of these two senses does Mr Spencer employ the 
term, when he makes it a test of the truth of a proposition 
that its negation is inconceivable ? Until Mr. Spencer ex¬ 
pressly stated the contrary, I inferred from the course of his 
argument, that he meant unbelievable He has, however, in 
a paper published m the fifth number of the Fortnightly 
Remew, disclaimed this meaning, and declared that by an in¬ 
conceivable proposition he means, now and always, “ one of 
which the terms cannot, by any effort, be brought before con¬ 
sciousness m that relation which the proposition asserts 
between them—a pioposition of which the subject and predi¬ 
cate offer an insurmountable resistance to union in thought.” 
We now, therefore, know positively that Mr. Spencer always 
endeavours to use the word inconceivable m this, its proper, 
sense: but it may yet be questioned whether his endeavour is 



THEORIES CONCERNING AXIOMS. 


303 


always successful, whether the other, and popular use of the 
word does not sometimes creep m with its associations, and 
prevent him fiom maintaining a clear sepaiation between the 
two. When, for example, he says, that when I feel cold, I 
cannot conceive that I am not feeling cold, this expression 
cannot be translated into, et I cannot conceive myself not feel¬ 
ing cold,” for it is evident that I can . the word conceive, there¬ 
fore, is here used to express the recognition of a matter of fact 
—the perception of truth or falsehood , which I apprehend to 
be exactly the meaning of an act of belief, as distinguished 
from simple conception. Again, Mr Spencer calls the attempt 
to conceive something which is inconceivable, “ an abortive 
effort to cause the non-existence” not of a conception or mental 
representation, but of a belief. There is need, therefore, to 
revise a considerable part of Mr Spencer s language, if it is to 
be kept always consistent with his definition of inconceivability. 
But m truth the point is of little importance, since inconceiva¬ 
bility, m Mr. Spencer s theory, is only a test of truth, inasmuch 
as it is a test of believability. The inconceivableness of a 
supposition is the extreme case of its unbelievability. This is 
the very foundation of Mr. Spencer's doctrine. The invaria¬ 
bility of the belief is with him the real guarantee The 
attempt to conceive the negative, is made in order to test the 
inevitableness of the belief It should be called, an attempt 
to believe the negative When Mr. Spencer says that while 
looking at the sun a man cannot conceive that he is looking 
into darkness, he should have said that a man cannot believe 
that he is doing so. For it is surely possible, m broad daylight, 
to imagine oneself looking into darkness * As Mr Spencer 
himself says, speaking of the belief of our own existence. 
“ That he might not exist, he can conceive well enough , but 
that he does not exist, he finds it impossible to conceive,” i e. 


* Mr. Spencer makes a distinction between conceiving myself looking into 
darkness, and conceiving that I am then and there looking into darkness To 
me it seems that this change of the expiession to the form I am , just marks 
the transition from conception to belief, and that the phrase “ to conceive that 
I am or u that anything is,” is not consistent with using the word conceive in 
its rigorous sense 



304 


REASONING. 


to "believe So that the statement resolves itself into this That 
I exist, and that I have sensations, I believe, because I cannot 
believe otbeiwise And m this case every one will admit that 
the necessity is leal. Any one’s present sensations, or other 
states of subjective consciousness, that one person inevitably 
believes They aie facts known per se it is impossible to 
ascend beyond them Their negative is really unbelievable, 
and therefore theie is never any question about believing it. 
Mr Spencei’s theory is not needed for these truths. 

But according to Mr. Spencer there are other beliefs, 
relating to other things than our own subjective feelings, for 
which we have the same guarantee—which are, m a similar 
manner, invariable and necessaiy With regaid to these other 
beliefs, they cannot be necessary, since they do not always 
exist. There have been, and are, many persons who do not 
believe the reality of an external world, still less the reality of 
extension and figure as the forms of that external world, who 
do not believe that space and time have an existence indepen¬ 
dent of the mind—nor any other of Mr Spencers objective 
intuitions The negations of these alleged invariable beliefs 
are not unbelievable, for they aie believed It may be main¬ 
tained, without obvious eiror, that we cannot imagine tangible 
objects as mere states of our own and other people’s con¬ 
sciousness , that the perception of them irresistibly suggests to 
us the idea of something external to ourselves * and I am not 
m a condition to say that this is not the fact (though I do not 
think any one is entitled to affirm it of any person besides 
himself) But many thinkers have believed, whether they could 
conceive it or not, that what we represent to ourselves as ma¬ 
terial objects, are mere modifications of consciousness, com¬ 
plex feelings of touch and of muscular action. Mr. Spencer 
may think the inference correct from the unimaginable to the 
unbelievable, because he holds that belief itself is but the per¬ 
sistence of an idea, and that what we can succeed m imagining, 
we cannot at the moment help apprehending as believable 
But of what consequence is it what we apprehend at the 
moment, if the moment is m contradiction to the permanent 
state of our mind ? A person who has been frightened when 



THEORIES CONCERNING AXIOMS. 


305 


an infant by stones of ghosts, though he disbelieves them in 
after years (and perhaps disbelieved them at first), may be 
unable all his life to be m a dark place, m circumstances stimu¬ 
lating to the imagination, without mental discomposure The 
idea of ghosts, 'with all its attendant terrors, is irresistibly 
called up in his mind by the outward circumstances 
Mr Spencer may say, that while he is under the influence of 
this terror he does not disbelieve m ghosts, but has a tem¬ 
porary and uncontrollable belief m them. Be it so ; but 
allowing it to be so, which would it be truest to say of this 
man on the whole—that he believes m ghosts, or that he does 
not believe m them ? Assuredly that he does not believe m 
them The case is similar with those who disbelieve a material 
world. Though they cannot get nd of the idea, though while 
looking at a solid object they cannot help having the concep¬ 
tion, and therefore, according to Mr. Spencer’s metaphysics, 
the momentary belief, of its externality, even at that moment 
they would sincerely deny holding that belief and it would 
be incorrect to call them other than disbelievers of the doc¬ 
trine. The belief therefore is not invariable , and the test of 
inconceivableness fails m the only cases to which there could 
ever be any occasion to apply it 

That a thing may be perfectly believable, and yet may 
not have become conceivable, and that we may habitually 
believe one side of an alternative, and conceive only m the 
other, is familiarly exemplified m the state of mind of educated 
peisons respecting sunrise and sunset. All educated persons 
either know by investigation, or believe on the authority of 
science, that it is the earth and not the sun which moves 
but there are probably few who habitually conceive the pheno¬ 
menon otherwise than as the ascent or descent of the sun 
Assuredly no one can do so without a prolonged trial, and it 
is probably not easier now than in the first generation after 
Copernicus. Mr Spencer does not say, “ In looking at sun¬ 
rise it is impossible not to conceive that it is the sun which 
moves, therefore this is what everybody believes, and we have 
all the evidence for it that we can have for any truth.” Yet 
YOL. i. 20 



306 


REASONING 


this would be an exact parallel to his doqfcrme about the belief 
in matter. 

The existence of matter, and other Noumena, as dis¬ 
tinguished from the phenomenal world, remains a question 
of argument, as it was before; and the very general, but 
neither necessary nor universal, belief m them, stands as a 
psychological phenomenon to be explained, either on the 
hypothesis of its tiuth, or on some other. The belief is not a 
conclusive proof of its own truth, unless there aie no such 
things as idola tiibus ,* but, bemg’a fact, it calls on antagonists 
to show, from what except the real existence of the thing be¬ 
lieved, so general and apparently spontaneous a belief can have 
originated. And its opponents have never hesitated to accept 
this challenge.* The amount of their success m meeting it 
will probably determine the ultimate verdict of philosophers on 
the question. 

§ 4. Sir William Hamilton holds as I do, that incon¬ 
ceivability is no criterion of impossibility. “ Theie is no ground 
for infeinng a certain fact to be impossible, merely from our 
inability to conceive its possibility " “ Things there are which 

may, nay must, be true, of which the understanding is wholly 
unable to construe to itself the possibility ”+ Sir William 
Hamilton is however a firm believer in the a pi ion character 
of many axioms, and of the sciences deduced from them, and 
is so far from considering those axioms to rest on the evidence 
of experience, that he declares ceitam of them to he true even 
of Noumena—of the Unconditioned—of which it is one of the 
principal aims of his philosophy to prove that the nature of our 
faculties dehais us from having any knowledge. The axioms 
to which he attributes this exceptional emancipation from the 
limits which confine all our other possibilities of knowledge , 
the chinks through which, as he represents, one ray of light 
finds its way to as from behind the curtain which veils from 


* I have myself accepted the contest, and fought it out on this battle¬ 
ground, in the eleventh chapter of An Examination of Sir William Hamilton's 
Philosophy 

+ Discussions , &c , 2nd ed p 624 



THEORIES CONCERNING AXIOMS. 


S07 


us the mysterious world of Things m themselves,—are the two 
principles, which he teims, after the schoolmen, the Principle 
of Contradiction, and the Principle of Excluded Middle the 
first, that tvo contiadictoiy propositions cannot both be true , 
the second, that they cannot both be false. Armed with these 
logical weapons, we may boldly face Things m themselves, and 
tendei to them the double alternative, sure that they must 
absolutely elect one or the other side, though we may be for 
ever precluded from discovering which. To take his favourite 
example, we cannot conceive the infinite divisibility of matter, 
and we cannot conceive a minimum, or end to divisibility yet 
one 01 the other must be true. 

As I have hitherto said nothing of the two axioms m ques¬ 
tion, those of Contradiction and of Excluded Middle, it is not 
unseasonable to consider them here. The former asserts that 
an affirmative proposition and the corresponding negative pro¬ 
position cannot both be true ; which has generally been held 
to be intuitively evident. Sir William Hamilton and the 
Germans consider it to be the statement m woids of a form 
or law of our thinking faculty. Other philosophers, not less 
deserving of consideration, deem it to be an identical proposi¬ 
tion , an assertion involved m the meaning of terms , a modd 
of defining Negation, and the word Not 

I am able to go one step with these last. An affirmative 
assertion and its negative are not two independent assertions, 
connected with each other only as mutually incompatible. 
That if the negative be true, the affirmative must be false, 
really is a mere identical proposition, for the negative pro¬ 
position asserts nothing but the falsity of the affirmative, and 
has no other sense or meaning whateyer. The Pnncipium 
Contradictioms should therefore put off the ambitious phrase¬ 
ology which gives it the air of a fundamental antithesis per¬ 
vading nature, and should be enunciated m the simpler form, 
that the same proposition cannot at the same time be false 
and true. But I can go no farther with the Nominalists; for 
I cannot look upon this last as a merely verbal proposition 
I consider it to be, like other axioms, one of our first and most 
familiar generalizations from experience. The original foun- 

20—2 



308 


REASONING. 


dation of it I take to be, that Belief and Disbelief are two dif¬ 
ferent mental states, excluding one another This we know by 
the simplest observation of oui own minds. And if we carry 
our obseivation outwards, we also find that light and daikness, 
sound and silence, motion and quiescence, equality and in¬ 
equality, preceding and following, succession and simultane¬ 
ousness, any positive phenomenon whatever and its negative, 
are distinct phenomena, pointedly contrasted, and the one 
always absent wheie the other is piesent I consider the 
maxim m question to be a generalization fiom all these facts. 

In like manner as the Principle of Contradiction (that one 
of two contradictones must be false) means that an assertion 
cannot be both true and false, so the Principle of Excluded 
Middle, or that one of two contradictories must be true, means 
that an assertion must be either true or false either the affir¬ 
mative is true, or otherwise the negative is tiue, which means 
that the affirmative is false I cannot help thinking' this 
principle a surprising specimen of a so-called necessity of 
Thought, since it is not even true, unless with a large qualifi¬ 
cation A proposition must be either true or false, provided 
that the predicate be one which can m any intelligible sense 
be attnbuted to the subject, (and as this is always assumed 
to be the case m tieatises on logic, the axiom is always laid 
down there as of absolute truth). “Abracadabra is a second 
intention” is neither true nor false Between the true and the 
false there is a third possibility, the Unmeaning and this 
alternative is fatal to Sir William Hamilton s extension of the 
maxim to Noumena That Matter must either have a minimum 
of divisibility or be infinitely divisible, is more than we can 
ever know. Por m the first place, Matter, m any other than 
the phenomenal sense of the term, may not exist and it will 
scarcely be said that a non-entity must be either infinitely or 
finitely divisible * In the second place, though matter, con¬ 
sidered as the occult cause of our sensations, do really exist, 

* If it be said that the existence of matter is among the things proved by 
the principle of Excluded Middle, that principle must prove also the existence 
of diagons and hippogriffs, because they must be either scaly or not scaly, 
creeping or not creeping, and so foith. 



THEORIES CONCERNING AXIOMS. 


309 


yet what we call divisibility may be an attribute only of our 
sensations of sight and touch, and not of their uncogmzable 
cause Divisibility may not be predicable at all, m any intel¬ 
ligible sense, of Things in themselves, nor therefore of Matter 
in itself, and the assumed necessity of being either infinitely 
or finitely divisible, may be an inapplicable alternative 

On this question I am happy to have the full concurrence 
of Mr. Herbert Spencer, from whose paper m the Fortnightly 
Review I extract the following passage. The germ of an idea 
identical with that of Mr Spencer may be found m the present 
chapter, about a page back, but in Mr. Spencer it is not an 
undeveloped thought, but a philosophical theory 

a When remembering a ceitam thing as in a certain place, 
the place and the thing are mentally represented together, 
while to think of the non-existence of the thing m that place, 
implies a consciousness m which the place is represented, but 
not the thing. Similarly, if instead of thinking of an object 
as colourless, we think of its having colour, the change con¬ 
sists m the addition to the concept of an element that was 
before absent from it—the object cannot be thought of first as 
red and then as not red, without one component of the thought 
being totally expelled from the mind by another. The law of 
the Excluded Middle, then, is simply a generalization of the 
universal experience that some mental states are directly de¬ 
structive of other states. It formulates a certain absolutely 
constant law, that the appearance of any positive mode of con¬ 
sciousness cannot occur without excluding a correlative negative 
mode, and that the negative mode cannot occur without ex¬ 
cluding fhe correlative positive mode. the antithesis of positive 
and negative being, indeed, merely an expression of this ex¬ 
perience. Hence it follows that if consciousness is not m one 
of the two modes it must be m the other.”* 

I must here close this supplementary chapter, and with it 
the Second Book. The theory of Induction, m the most com¬ 
prehensive sense of the term, will form the subject of the Third. 

* Eor further considerations respecting the axioms of Contradiction and 
Excluded Middle, see the twenty-first chapter of An Examination of Sv Wil¬ 
liam Hamilton's Philosophy. 




BOOK III. 


OF INDUCTION. 



“According to the doctrine now stated, the highest, or rather the only 
proper object of physics, is to ascertain those established conjunctions of suc¬ 
cessive events, which constitute the*order of the universe, to record the 
phenomena which it exhibits to our observations, or which it discloses to 
our experiments, and to refer these phenomena to their general laws”— 
D Stewart, Elements of the Philosophy of the Human Mind , vol. u. chap iv. 
sect 1. 



CHAPTER L 


PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIONS ON INDUCTION IN 
GENERAL. 

§ 1. The portion of the present inquiry upon which we 
are now about to enter, may be considered as the principal, 
both fiom its surpassing m intricacy all the other branches, 
and because it relates to a process which has been shown in 
the preceding Book to be that in which the investigation of 
nature essentially consists. We have found that all Inference, 
consequently all Proof, and all discovery of truths not self- 
evident, consists of inductions, and the interpretation of induc¬ 
tions . that all our knowledge, not intuitive, comes to us ex¬ 
clusively from that source. What Induction is, therefore, and 
what conditions render it legitimate, cannot but be deemed the 
main question of the science of logic—the question which in¬ 
cludes all others. It is, however, one which professed writers 
on logic have almost entirely passed over. The generalities of 
the subject have not been altogether neglected by metaphysi¬ 
cians , but, for want of sufficient acquaintance with the processes 
by which science has actually succeeded in establishing general 
truths, their analysis of the inductive operation, even when un¬ 
exceptionable as to correctness, has not been specific enough 
to be made the foundation of practical rules, which might be 
for induction itself what the rules of the syllogism are for the 
interpretation of induction: while those by whom physical 
science has been carried to its present state of improvement— 
and who, to arrive at a complete theory of the process, needed 
only to generalize, and adapt to all varieties of problems, the 
methods which they themselves employed in their habitual 
pursuits—never until very lately made any serious attempt to 
philosophize on the subject, nor regarded the mode m which 



814 


INDUCTION. 


they arrived at their conclusions as deserving of study, inde¬ 
pendently of the conclusions themselves 

§ 2 For the puiposes of the present inquiry, Induction 
maybe defined, the operation of discovering and proving general 
propositions. It is true that (as already shown) the process of 
xndiiectly ascertaining individual facts, is as truly inductive as 
that by which we establish geneial truths But it is not a different 
kind of induction, it is afoim of the very same process since, 
on the one hand, generals aie but collections of particulars, de¬ 
finite m kind but indefinite m number, and on the other hand, 
whenever the evidence which we derive from observation of 
known cases justifies us m drawing an inference respecting 
even one unknown case, we should on the same evidence be 
justified m drawing a similar inference with lespect to a whole 
class of cases. The inference either does not hold at all, or 
it holds m all cases of a certain description; in all cases 
which, m ceitam definable respects, resemble those we have 
obseived 

If these remarks are just, if the principles and rules of in¬ 
ference are the same whether we infer general propositions or 
individual facts , it follows that a complete logic of the sciences 
would be also a complete logic of practical business and com¬ 
mon life. Since there is no case of legitimate inference from 
experience, in which the conclusion may not legitimately be a 
general proposition, an analysis of the process by which 
general truths are arrived at, is virtually an analysis of all in¬ 
duction whatever Whether we are lnquning into a scientific 
principle or into an individual fact, and whether we proceed by 
experiment or by ratiocination, every step m the tram of in¬ 
ferences is essentially inductive, and the legitimacy of the in¬ 
duction depends m both cases on the same conditions. 

True it is that m the case of the practical inquirer, who is 
endeavouring to ascertain facts not for the purposes of science 
but for those of business, such for instance as the advocate or 
the j udge, the chief difficulty is one m which the principles of 
induction will afford him no assistance. It lies not m making 
his inductions, but m the selection of them; m choosing from 



INDUCTION IN GENERAL. 


315 


among all general propositions ascertained to be true, those 
■which furnish marks by which he may trace whether the given 
subject possesses or not the predicate m question In arguing a 
doubtful question of fact before a jury, the general propositions 
or principles to which the advocate appeals are mostly, m them¬ 
selves, sufficiently tnte, and assented to as soon as stated his 
skill lies m bunging his case under those propositions or prin¬ 
ciples , m calling to mind such of the known or received maxims 
of probability as admit of application to the case m hand, and 
selecting from among them those best adapted to his object 
Success is heie dependent on natural or acquired sagacity, aided 
by knowledge of the particular subject, and of subjects allied 
with it Invention, though it can be cultivated, cannot be re¬ 
duced to rule, there is no science which will enable a man to 
bethink himself of that which will suit his purpose. 

But when he has thought of something, science can tell him 
whether that which he has thought of will suit his purpose or 
not. The inquirer or arguer must be guided by his own know¬ 
ledge and sagacity m the choice of the inductions out of which 
he will construct his argument But the validity of the argu¬ 
ment when constructed, depends on piinciples and must be tried 
by tests which are the same for all descriptions of inquiries, 
whether the result be to give A an estate, or to ennch science 
with a new general tiuth. In the one case and in the other, 
the senses, or testimony, must decide on the individual facts; 
the rules of the syllogism will determine whether, those facts 
being supposed correct, the case really falls withm the formulae 
of the different inductions under which it has been successively 
brought, and finally, the legitimacy of the inductions them¬ 
selves must be decided by other rules, and these it is now our 
purpose to investigate If this third part of the operation be, m 
many of the questions of practical life, not the most, but the least 
arduous portion of it, we have seen that this is also the case m 
some great departments of the field of science, m all those 
which are principally deductive, and most of all m mathematics; 
where the inductions themselves are few m number, and so 
obvious and elementary that they seem to stand m no need of 
the evidence of experience, while to combine them so as to 



316 


INDUCTION. 


prove a given theorem or solve a problem, may call for the 
utmost powers of invention and contrivance with which our 
species is gifted. 

If the identity of the logical processes which prove parti¬ 
cular facts and those which establish general scientific truths, 
required any additional confirmation, it would be sufficient to 
consider that m many branches of science, single facts have to 
be pioved, as well as principles, facts as completely individual 
as any that are debated m a court of justice, but which are 
proved m the same manner as the other truths of the science, 
and without disturbing m any degree the homogeneity of its 
method. A remarkable example of this is afforded by astronomy. 
The individual facts on which that science grounds its most im¬ 
portant deductions, such facts as the magnitudes of the bodies 
of the solar system, their distances from one another, the figure 
of the earth, and its rotation, are scarcely any of them accessible 
to our means of direct observation - they are pioved indirectly, 
by the aid of inductions founded on other facts which we 
I can more easily reach Tor example, the distance of the 
I moon from the earth was determined by a very circuitous 
process. The share which direct observation had in the 
work consisted m ascertaining, at one and the same instant, 
the zenith distances of the moon, as seen from two points 
very remote from one another on the earth’s surface The as¬ 
certainment of these angular distances ascertained their supple¬ 
ments ; and since the angle at the earth’s centre subtended by 
the distance between the two places of observation was dedu- 
cible by spherical trigonometry from the latitude and longitude 
of those places, the angle at the moon subtended by the same 
line became the fourth angle of a quadrilateral of which the 
other three angles were known. The four angles being thus 
ascertained, and two sides of the quadrilateral being radii of the 
earth; the two remaining sides and the diagonal, or m other 
words, the moons distance fiom the two places of observation 
and from the centre of the earth, could be ascertained, at least 
in terms of the earth’s radius, from elementary theorems of 
geometry At each step m this demonstration we take m a 



INDUCTION IN GENERAL. 317 

new induction, represented, m the aggregate of its results, by 
a general proposition 

Not only is the process by which an individual astrono¬ 
mical fact was thus ascertained, exactly similar to those by 
which the same science establishes its general truths, but also 
(as we have shown to be the case m all legitimate reasoning) 
a general proposition might have been concluded instead of a 
single fact In strictness, indeed, the result of the reasoning, 
is a general proposition; a theorem respecting the distance,* 
not of the moon m particular, but of any inaccessible object, 
showing m what relation that distance stands to certain other 
quantities And although the moon is almost the only heavenly 
body the distance of which from the eaith can really be thus 
ascei tamed, this is merely owing to the accidental circum¬ 
stances of the other heavenly bodies, which render them inca¬ 
pable of affording such data as the application of the theorem 
lequires, for the theorem itself is as true of them as it is of the 
moon * 

* Di Whewell thinks it improper to apply the term Induction to any 
operation not terminating m the establishment of a geneial truth. Induction, 
he says (Philosophy of Discovery, p 245), 4 ‘is not the same thing as experience 
and observation Induction is experience or obseivation consciously looked at 
in a general form This consciousness and generality are necessary parts of 
that knowledge which is science ” And he objects (p 241) to the mode m 
which the word Induction is employed m this work, as an imdue extension of 
that term f 4 not only to the cases in which the general induction is consciously 
applied to a particular instance, but to the cases m which the particular instance 
is dealt with by means of experience in that rude sense m which experience can 
be asserted of brutes, and m which of course we can m no way imagine that the 
law is possessed or understood as a general proposition ** This use of the term 
he deems a 44 confusion of knowledge with practical tendencies ” 

I disclaim, as strongly as Di Whewell can do, the application of such terms 
as induction, inference, or leasonmg, to operations pel formed by mere instinct, 
that is, from an animal impulse, without the exertion of any intelligence. But 
I perceive no ground foi confining the use of those terms to cases in which the 
inference is drawn m the forms and with the precautions required by scientific 
propriety. To the idea of Science, an express recognition and distinct appre¬ 
hension of general laws as such, is essential but nine-tenths of the conclusions 
drawn from experience in the course of piactical life, are drawn without any 
such recognition they aie direct inferences from known cases, to a case sup¬ 
posed to be similar, I have endeavoured to show that this is not only as legi- 




318 


INDUCTION. 


We shall fall into no eiror, then, if m tieating of Induction, 
we limit our attention to the establishment of general proposi¬ 
tions. The principles and rules of Induction as dnected to this 
end., are the principles and rules of all Induction, and the logic 
of Science is the universal Logic, applicable to all inquiries m 
which man can engage. 

timate an operation, but substantially the same operation, as that of ascending 
from known cases to a general proposition , except that the latter process has 
one great security for correctness which the former does not possess In Science, 
the inference must necessarily pass through the intermediate stage of a general 
proposition, because Science wants its conclusions for record, and not for in¬ 
stantaneous use But the inferences drawn for the guidance of practical affairs, 
by peisons who would often be quite incapable of expressing m unexceptionable 
terms the corresponding generalizations, may and fi equently do exhibit intel¬ 
lectual powers quite equal to any which have ever been displayed m Science 
and if these inferences are not inductive, what are they 2 The limitation im¬ 
posed on the term by Dr Whewell seems perfectly arbitrary , neither justified 
by any fundamental distinction between what he includes and what he desires 
to exclude, nor sanctioned by usage, at least from the time of Beid and Stewart, 
the principal legislatoi s (as far as the English language is concerned) of modern 
metaphysical terminology. 



CHAPTER II. 


OF INDUCTIONS IMPROPERLY SO CALLED. 

§ 1. Induction, then, is that opeiation of the mmd, by 
which we infer that what we know to be true m a particular 
case 01 cases, will be true m all cases which resemble the former 
m ceitam assignable respects. In other words, Induction is 
the piocess by which we conclude that what is true of certain 
individuals of a class is true of the whole class, or that what 
is tiue at certain times will be true m similar cncumstances at 
all times. 

This definition excludes from the meaning of the term In¬ 
duction, various logical operations, to which it is not unusual 
to^apply that name. 

Induction, as above defined, is a process of inference, it 
proceeds fiom the known to the unknown, and any operation 
involving no inference, any process m which what seems the 
conclusion is no wider than the premises from which it is 
\ drawn, does not fall within the meaning of the term. Yet m 
the common books of Logic we find this laid down as the 
most perfect, indeed the only quite perfect, form of induction. 
In those books, every process which sets out fiom a less general 
and terminates m a more general expression,—which admits 
of being stated in the form, “ This and that A are B, there¬ 
fore every A is B,”—is called an induction, whether any¬ 
thing be really concluded or not: and the induction is as¬ 
serted not to be perfect, unless every single individual of 
the class A is included m the antecedent, or premise. that is, 
unless what we affirm of the class has already been ascer¬ 
tained to be true of every individual m it, so that the 
nominal conclusion is not really a conclusion, but a mere 
reassertion of the premises. If we were to say. All the 
planets shine by the suns light, from observation of each 



320 


INDUCTION. 


separate planet, or All the Apostles were Jews, because 
this is true of Peter, Paul, John, and every other apostle,— 
these, and such as these, would, in the phraseology in ques¬ 
tion, he called perfect, and the only perfect, Inductions. 
This, however, is a totally different kind of induction from 
ours; it is not an inference from facts known to facts un¬ 
known, but a mere short-hand registration of facts known. 
The two simulated arguments which we have quoted, are not 
generalizations, the propositions purporting to he conclusions 
fiom them, are not really general propositions. A general 
proposition is one m which the predicate is affirmed or denied 
of an unlimited number of individuals; namely, all, whether 
few or many, existing or capable of existing, which possess 
the propeities connoted by the subject of the proposition 
“All men are mortal” does not mean all now living, hut all 
men past, present, and to come When the signification of 
the term is limited so as to render it a name not for any 
and every individual falling under a certain general descrip¬ 
tion, hut only for each of a number of individuals designated 
as such, and as it were counted off individually, the proposi¬ 
tion, though it may he general m its language, is no general 
proposition, hut merely that number of singular propositions, 
written m an abridged character The operation may be very 
useful, as most forms of abridged notation are, but it is no 
part of the investigation of truth, though often bearing an 
important part m the preparation of the materials for that 
investigation. 

As we may sum up a definite number of singular proposi¬ 
tions m one proposition, which will be apparently, but not 
really, general, so we may sum up a definite number of general 
propositions m one proposition, which will be apparently, but 
not really, more general. If by a separate induction applied 
to every distinct species of animals, it has been established 
that each possesses a nervous system, and we affirm thereupon 
that all animals have a nervous system, this looks like a 
generalization, though as the conclusion merely affirms of all 
what has already been affirmed of each, it seems to tell us 
nothing but what we knew before A distinction however 



INDUCTIONS IMPROPERLY SO CALLED. 


821 


must be made. If m concluding that all animals have a 
nervous system, we mean the same thing and no more as if 
we had said “ all known animals/’ the pioposition is not 
general, and the piocess by which it is ailived at is not in¬ 
duction But if oui meaning is that the obseivations made 
of the various species of animals have discoveied to us a law 
of animal natuie, and that we are m a condition to say that a 
nervous system will be found even m animals yet undiscovered, 
this indeed is an induction, but m this case the geneial pro¬ 
position contains moie than the sum of the special proposi¬ 
tions from which it is mfened The distinction is still more 
forcibly brought out when we consider, that if this real gene¬ 
ralization be legitimate at all, its legitimacy piobably does not 
require that w r e should have examined without exception every 
known species It is the number and natuie of the instances, 
and not their being the whole of those which happen to be 
known, that makes them sufficient evidence to piove a general 
law. while the moie limited assertion, which stops at all 
known animals, cannot be made unless we have ngoiou&ly 
verified it m every species. In like manner to (return to a 
former example) we might have inferred, not that all the 
planets, but that all planets, shine by reflected light the 
former is no induction; the latter is an induction, and a bad 
one, being dispioved by the case of double stais—self-luminous 
bodies which aie properly planets, since they 1 evolve round a 
centi e 


§ 2 . There are several processes used m mathematics 
which requne to be distinguished fiom Induction, being not 
unfiequently called by that name, and being so far similar to 
Induction propeily so called, that the propositions they lead 
to are really general propositions For example, when we 
have proved with respect to the circle, that a straight line 
cannot meet it m more than two points, and when the same 
thing has been successively proved of the ellipse, the parabola, 
and the hyperbola, it may be laid down as an universal pro¬ 
perty of the sections of the cone. The distinction diawn m 
the two previous examples can have no place here, there being 
VOL I. 21 



322 


INDUCTION 


no difference between all known sections of the cone and all 
sections, since a cone demonstrably cannot be intersected by 
a plane except m one*of these four lines It would be diffi¬ 
cult, therefore, to iefuse*to the proposition arrived at, the name 
of a generalization, since there is no room for any geneializa- 
tion beyond it But there is no induction, because there is no 
inference the conclusion is a mere summing up of what was 
asseited m the various piopositions from which it is di awn. 
A case somewhat, though not altogether, similar, is the proof 
of a geometrical theoiem by means of a diagram. Whether 
the diagiam he on paper or only m the imagination, the de- 
monstiation (as formerly observed*) does not prove directly the 
general theorem, it proves only that the conclusion, which the 
theorem asseits generally, is true of the particular triangle or 
circle exhibited m the diagram , but since we perceive that m 
the same way m which we have pioved it of that cncle, it 
might also be proved of any other circle, we gather up into 
one general expiession all the singular propositions susceptible 
of being thus proved, and embody them m an umveisal pro¬ 
position Having shown that the thiee angles of the tnangle 
ABC are together equal to two right angles, we conclude that 
this is tiue of every other triangle, not because it is tiue of 
ABC, but foi the same reason which proved it to be true 
of ABC. If this were to be called Induction, an appropriate 
name for it would be, induction by parity of reasoning But 
the term cannot propeily belong to it; the characteristic 
quality of Induction is wanting, since the truth obtained, 
though really general, is not believed on the evidence of par¬ 
ticular instances We do not conclude that all triangles have 
the property because some triangles have, but from the ulterior 
demonstiative evidence which was the giound of our convic¬ 
tion m the particular instances 

There are nevertheless, m mathematics, some examples of 
so-called Induction, m which the conclusion does bear the 
appearance of a generalization grounded on some of the par¬ 
ticular cases included m it, A mathematician, when he has 


Supra, p 214. 



INDUCTIONS IMPROPERLY SO CALLEt). 


328 


calculated a sufficient number of the terms of an algehiaical 
or arithmetical senes to have ascertained what is called the law 
of the series, does not hesitate to fill up any number of the 
succeeding teims without lepeatmg the calculations But I 
apprehend he only does so when it is apparent from a 'priori 
considerations (which might be exhibited m the foim of 
demonstration) that the mode of formation of the subsequent 
terms, each from that which pieceded it, must be similar to 
the formation of the terms which have been already calculated. 
And when the attempt has been hazarded without the sanction 
of such geneial considerations, there are instances on recoid m 
which it has led to false results. 

It is said that Newton discovered the binomial theorem 
by induction, by raising a binomial successively to a certain 
number of p*owers, and compaung those powers with one 
another until he detected the 1 elation m which the algebraic 
formula of each power stands to the exponent of that power, 
and to the two terms of the binomial. The fact is not im¬ 
probable but a mathematician like Newton, who seemed to 
amve per saltam at principles and conclusions that ordinary 
mathematicians only reached by a succession of steps, certainly 
could not have peiformed the comparison in question without 
being led by it to the a priori giound of the law , since any 
one who understands sufficiently the nature of multiplication 
to venture upon multiplying several lines of symbols at one 
operation, cannot but perceive that m raising a binomial to a 
power, the coefficients must depend orf the laws of permuta¬ 
tion and combination * and as soon as this is recognised, the 
theorem is demonstrated. Indeed, when once it was seen that 
the law prevailed m a few of the lower powers, its identity 
with the law of permutation would at once suggest the con¬ 
siderations which prove it to obtain universally. Even, 
therefore, such cases as these, are but examples of what I 
have called Induction by panty of reasoning, that is, not 
really Induction, because not involving inference of a geneial 
proposition from particular instances 

§ 3. There remains a third improper use of the term 
£ 1—2 



324 


INDUCTION. 


Induction, which it is of leal importance to clear up, because 
the theory of Induction has been, m no oidinary degiee, con¬ 
fused by it, and because the confusion is exemplified m the 
most recent and elaborate tieatise on the inductive philosophy 
which exists m our language The eiroi m question is that 
of confounding a meie descuption, by general teims, of a set 
of observed phenomena, with an induction fiom them. 

Suppose that a phenomenon consists of paits, and that 
these paits aie only capable of being obseived separately, and 
as it were piecemeal When the obseivations have been made, 
there is a convenience (amounting for many purposes to a 
necessity) m obtaining a representation of the phenomenon as 
a whole, by combining, or as we may say, piecing these 
detached fragments together. A navigator sailing m the 
midst of the ocean discovers land he cannot at first, or 
by any one observation, determine whether it is a continent 
or an island , but he coasts along it, and after a few days finds 
himself to have sailed completely lound it he then pionounces 
it an island Now there was no paiticulai time 01 place of 
observation at which he could perceive that this land was 
entirely surrounded by watei he ascertained the fact by a 
succession of partial observations, and then selected a general 
expression which summed up m two or three woids the 
whole of what he so observed. But is there anything of the 
nature of an induction m this piocess ? Bid he infer anything 
that had not been observed, from something else which had ? 
Certainly not. He had observed the whole of what the pro¬ 
position asserts. That the land m question is an island, is 
not an inference fiom the paitial facts which the navigator saw 
m the couise of his circumnavigation, it is the facts them¬ 
selves, it is a summary of those facts, the description of a 
complex fact, to which those simpler ones are as the parts of 
a whole 

Now there is, I conceive, no difference inland between this 
simple operation, and that by which Kepler ascertained the 
nature of the planetary orbits and Keplers operation, all 
at least that was charactenstic m it, was not more an inductive 
act than that of our supposed navigator. 



INDUCTIONS IMPROPERLY SO CALLED 


325 


The object of Kepler was to determine the real path de¬ 
scribed by each of the planets, or let ns say by the planet 
Mars (since it was of that body that he hist established the 
two of his three laws which did not require a comparison of 
planets) To do this there was no other mode than that of 
direct observation and all which obseivation could do was to 
ascertain a gieat number of the successive places of the planet, 
or rather, of its apparent places That the planet occupied 
successively all these positions, or at all events, positions which 
produced the same impressions on the eye, and that it passed 
fiom one of these to another insensibly, and without any 
apparent breach of continuity, thus much the senses, with the 
aid of the proper instruments, could ascertain. What Kepler 
did more than this, was to find what soit of a curve these dif¬ 
ferent points would make, supposing them to be all joined 
togethei. He expressed the whole senes of the obseived 
places of Mars by what Dr Whewell calls the general concep¬ 
tion of an ellipse. This opeiation was far from being as easy 
as that of the navigator who expressed the series of his obser¬ 
vations on successive points of the coast by the general con¬ 
ception of an island But it is the veiy same sort of operation, 
and if the one is not an induction but a description, this must 
also be true of the other. 

The only real induction concerned in the case, consisted in 
infeirmg that because the observed places of Mars were cor¬ 
rectly represented by points m an imaginary ellipse, therefore 
Mars would continue to revolve m that same ellipse, and m 
concluding (before the gap had been filled up by further obser¬ 
vations) that the positions of the planet duiing the time which 
intervened between two observations, must have coincided 
with the intermediate points of the curve. For these were 
facts which had not been directly observed. They were 
inferences from the observations, facts inferred, as distin¬ 
guished from facts seen. But these inferences were so far 
from being a part of Keplei's philosophical operation, that 
they had been drawn long before he was born. Astronomers 
had long known that the planets periodically returned to the 
same places. When this had been ascertained, theie was no 



326 


INDUCTION. 


induction left for Kepler to make, nor did be make any further 
induction. He merely applied his new conception to the facts 
inferred, as he did to the facts observed Knowing already 
that the planets continued to move rn the same paths, when 
he found that an ellipse correctly represented the past path, 
he knew that it would represent the futuie path. In finding 
a compendious expression for the one set of facts, he found 
one foi the other but he found the expression only, not the 
inference, nor did he (which is the true test of a general 
truth) add anything to the power of prediction already pos¬ 
sessed. 


■§ 4 . The descriptive operation which enables a number 
of details to be summed up m a single proposition, Dr. 
Whew ell, by an aptly chosen expression, has termed the 
Colligation of Facts. - In most of his observations concerning 
that mental piocess I fully agree, and would gladly transfer 
all that portion of his book into my own pages I only think 
him mistaken m setting up this kind of operation, which 
according to the old and received meaning of the term, is not 
induction at all, as the type of induction generally, and laying 
down, throughout his woik, as principles of induction, the 
principles of mere colligation. 

Dr. Whewell maintains that the general proposition which 
binds together the particular facts, and makes them, as it 
weie, one fact, is not the mere sum of those facts, but some¬ 
thing more, since there is introduced a conception of the 
mind, which did not exist m the facts themselves. “The 
particular facts, says he,* “ are not merely brought together, 
but there is a new element added to the combination by the 
very act of thought by which they are combined. . . When 
the Greeks, after long observing the motions of the planets, 
saw that these motions might be rightly considered as pro¬ 
duced by the motion of one wheel revolving m the inside of 
another wheel, these wheels were creations of their mmds, 
added to the facts which they perceived by sense And even 


Novum Organum Renoiatum, pp. 72, 73, 



INDUCTIONS IMPROPERLY SO CALLED. 


327 


if the wheels were no longer supposed to he matenal, hut 
were reduced to mere geometrical spheies 01 circles, they 
were not the less products of the mind alone,—something 
additional to the facts oh served. The same is the case m 
all other discovenes The facts are known, hut they are 
insulated and unconnected, till the discoverer supplies from 
his own store a principle of connexion. The peails are 
there, hut they will not hang together till some one provides 
the string.” 

Let me first remark that Dr Whewell, m this passage, 
blends together, indiscriminately, examples of both the pro¬ 
cesses which I am endeavouring to distinguish from one 
another. When the Greeks abandoned the supposition that 
the planetai y motions were produced by the revolution of 
material wheels, and fell back upon the idea of “ mere geo¬ 
metrical spheres or circles,” theie was more m this change of 
opinion than the mere substitution o± an ideal curve for a 
physical one. There was the abandonment of a theory, and 
the replacement of it by a mere description No one would 
think of calling the doctrine of matenal wheels a mere de¬ 
scription. That doctrine was an attempt to point out the 
force by which the planets were acted upon, and compelled to 
move m their orbits. But when, by a great step in philosophy, 
the materiality of the wheels was discarded, and the geome¬ 
trical forms alone retained, the attempt to account for the 
motions was given up, and what was left of the theory was a 
mere description of the orbits The assertion that the planets 
were earned round by wheels revolving m the inside of other 
wheels, gave place to the proposition, that they moved m the 
same lines which would be traced by bodies so carried - which 
was a mere mod^ of representing the sum of the observed 
facts, as Keplers was another and a better mode of repre¬ 
senting the same observations. 

It is true that for these simply descriptive operations, as well 
as for the erroneous inductive one, a conception of the mmd was 
required. The conception of an ellipse must have presented 
itself to Kepler’s mind, before he could identify the planetary 
orbits with it. According to Dr. Whewell, the conception 



328 


INDUCTION. 


was something added to the facts. He expiesses himself as 
if Kepler had put something into the facts by his mode of 
conceiving them But Kepler did no such thing The ellipse 
was m the facts before Keplei lecogmsed it, just as the island 
was an island befoie it had been sailed round Kepler did not 
put what he had conceived into the facts, but saw it m them. 
A conception implies, and corresponds to, something conceived* 
and though the conception itself is not in the facts, but m our 
mind, yet if it is to convey any knowledge relating to them, 
it must be a conception of something which really is m the 
facts, some property which they actually possess, and which 
they would manifest to our senses, if our senses were able to 
take cognizance of it. If, for instance, the planet left behind 
it m space a visible track, and if the observer were m a fixed 
position at such a distance from the plane of the orbit as 
would enable him to see the whole of it at once, he would see 
it to be an ellipse, and if gifted with appropriate instruments 
and powers of locomotion, he could prove it to be such by 
measuring its different dimensions Nay, further if the 
track were visible, and he were so placed that he could see all 
parts of it m succession, but not all of them at once, he might 
be able, by piecing together his successive observations, to 
discover both that it was an ellipse and that the planet moved 
m it The case would then exactly resemble that of the navi¬ 
gator who discovers the land to be an island by sailing round 
it If the path was visible, no one I think would dispute that 
to identify it with an ellipse is to describe it. and I cannot see 
why any difference should be made by its not being directly 
an object of sense, when every point m it is as exactly ascer¬ 
tained as if it were so. 

Subject to the indispensable condition which has just 
been stated, I cannot conceive that the part which concep¬ 
tions have m the operation of studying facts, has ever been 
overlooked or undervalued No one ever disputed that m 
order to reason about anything we must have a conception 
of it, or that when we include a multitude of things under a 
general expression, there is implied m the expression a 
conception of something common to those things But it 



INDUCTIONS IMPROPERLY SO CALLED. 


329 


by no means follows tliat the conception is necessarily pre¬ 
existent, or constiucted by the mind out of its own matenals 
If the facts are rightly classed under the conception, it is 
because there is m the facts themselves something of which 
the conception is itself a copy, and which if we cannot 
dnectlv peiceive, it is because of the limited power of our 
organs, and not because the thing itself is not there The 
conception itself is often obtained by abstraction from the 
very facts which, m Dr WhewelTs language, it is afterwards 
called m to connect. This he himself admits, when he ob¬ 
serves, (which he does on several occasions,) how great a 
service would he rendered to the science of physiology by the 
philosopher “ who should establish a precise, tenable, and con¬ 
sistent conception of life Such a conception can only be 
abstracted fiom the phenomena of life itself, from the very 
facts which it is put m requisition to connect In other cases, 
no doubt, instead of collecting the conception from the very 
phenomena which we are attempting to colligate, we select it 
from among those which have been previously collected 
by abstraction fiom other facts In the instance of Kepler s 
laws, the lattei was the case The facts being out of the 
reach of being observed, in any such manner as would 
have enabled the senses to identify directly the path of 
the planet, the conception lequisite for framing a general 
description of that path could not be collected by abstrac¬ 
tion from the observations themselves, the mind had to 
supply hypothetically, from among the conceptions it had 
obtained fiom other portions of its experience, some one 
which would correctly represent the series of the observed 
facts It had to frame a supposition respecting the general 
course of the phenomenon, and ask itself. If this be the 
general description, what will the details be? and then com¬ 
pare these with the details actually observed. If they agreed, 
the hypothesis would serve for a description of the pheno¬ 
menon if not, it was necessarily abandoned, and another tried. 
It is such a case as this which gives rise to the doctrine that 


Novum Organum Renovatwm, p. 32. 



330 


INDUCTION. 


the mind, m fiammg the descriptions, adds something of its 
own which it does not find m the facts 

Yet it is a fact suiely, that the planet does describe 
an ellipse , and a fact w r hich we could see, if we had adequate 
visual organs and a suitable position Not having these 
advantages, but possessing the conception of an ellipse, or 
(to expiess the meaning m less technical language) knowing 
what an ellipse was, Kepler tried whether the obseived places 
of the planet were consistent *with such a path. He found 
they were so, and he, consequently, asserted as a fact that the 
planet moved in an ellipse But this fact, which Kepler did 
not add to, but found in, the motions of the planet, namely, 
that it occupied m succession the various points m the circum¬ 
ference of a given ellipse, was the very fact, the sepaiate parts 
of which had been separately obseived, it was the sum of the 
different observations 

Having stated this fundamental diffeience between my 
opimon and that of Hr Whewell, I must add that his account 
of the manner m which a conception is selected, suitable to 
express the facts, appears to me peifectly just. The expenence 
of all thinkers will, I believe, testify that the piocess is 
tentative, that it consists of a succession of guesses, many 
being rejected, until one at last occurs fit to he chosen We 
know fiom Kepler himself that before hitting upon the “ con¬ 
ception ” of an ellipse, he tried nineteen other imaginary paths, 
which, finding them inconsistent with the observations, he was 
obliged to ieject. But as Hi. Whewell truly says, the suc¬ 
cessful hypothesis, though a guess, ought generally to he 
called, not a lucky, but a skilful guess The guesses which 
serve to give mental unity and wholeness to a chaos of 
scattered particulais, aie accidents which laiely occui to any 
minds hut those abounding m knowledge and disciplined m 
intellectual combinations. 

How far this tentative method, so indispensable as a means 
to the colligation of facts for purposes of description, admits 
of application to Induction itself, and what functions belong 
to it m that department, will be considered m the chapter of 
the present Book which relates to Hypotheses. On the pie- 



INDUCTIONS IMPROPERLY SO CALLED. 


331 


sent occasion we have chiefly to distinguish this process of 
Colligation from Induction pioperly so called, and that the 
distinction may he made clearer, it is well to advert to a 
curious and interesting remaik, which is as strikingly true of 
the foimer operation, as it appears to me unequivocally false of 
the latter 

In different stages of the piogiess of knowledge, philoso¬ 
pher have employed, for the colligation of the same order of 
facts, different conceptions The early rude observations of 
the heavenly bodies, m which minute precision was neither 
attained nor sought, presented nothing inconsistent with the 
representation of the path of a planet as an exact circle, having 
the earth for its centre. As observations increased m accuracy, 
and facts were disclosed which were not reconcileable with this 
simple supposition, for the colligation of those additional 
facts, the supposition was varied, and varied again and again 
as facts became more numerous and precise. The earth was 
removed from the centre to some other point within the circle, 
the planet was supposed to revolve m a smaller circle called 
an epicycle, round an imaginary point which revolved m a circle 
round the earth m proportion as obsei vation elicited fresh 
facts contradictory to these representations, other epicycles and 
other excentncs were added, producing additional complica¬ 
tion, until at last Kepler swept all these cncles away, and 
substituted the conception of an exact ellipse. Even this is 
found not to represent with complete correctness the accurate 
observations of the present day, which disclose many slight 
deviations fiom an oibit exactly elliptical. Now Dr. Whewell 
has remaiked that these successive general expressions, though 
apparently so conflicting, were all correct they all answered 
the purpose of colligation, they all enabled the mind to repie- 
sent to itself with facility, and by a simultaneous glance, the 
whole body of facts at the time ascertained. each m its turn 
served as a correct description of the phenomena, so far as the 
senses had up to that time taken cognizance of them. If a 
necessity afterwards arose for discarding one of these general 
descriptions of the planet’s orbit, and framing a different 
imaginary line, by which to express the series of observed posi- 



332 


INDUCTION. 


tions, it was because a number of new facts had now been 
added, which it was necessaiy to combine with the old facts 
into one general descuption. But this did not affect the cor¬ 
rectness of the foimei expression, considered as a general state¬ 
ment of the only facts which it was intended to lepiesent And 
so true is this, that, as is well remarked by M. Comte, these 
ancient generalizations, even the rudest and most impeifect of 
them, that of unifoim movement m a cncle, aie so far fiom 
being entnely false, that they are even now habitually em¬ 
ployed by astronomers when only a lough approximation to 
con ectness is required Cf L’astronomie moderne, en de- 
trmsant sans retour les hypotheses primitives, envisagees 
comme lois reelles du monde, a soigneusement mamtenu leur 
„valeur positive et permanente, la piopriete de representer com- 
modement les phenomenes quand il sagit d’une piemiere 
ebauche Nos ressources a cet egard sont meme bien plus 
etendues, piecisement a cause que nous ne nous faisons aucune 
illusion sur la lealite des hypotheses, ce qui nous permet 
d employe! sans scrupule, en chaque cas, celle que nous jugeons 
la plus avantageuse 

Dr. Whewell’s remark, therefore, is philosophically correct 
Successive expressions for the colligation of observed facts, or 
m other word^, successive descriptions of a phenomenon as a 
whole, which has been observed only m paits, may, though 
conflicting, be all conect as far as they go But it would 
surely be absuid to assert this of conflicting inductions 

The scientific study of facts may be undertaken for three 
different purposes the simple 'descuption of the facts, their 
explanation, or their prediction. meaning by prediction, 
the determination of the conditions under which similar facts 
may be expected again to occur. To the first of these three 
operations the name of Induction does not propelly belong. 
to the other two it does. Now, Dr. Whewell’s observation is 
true of the first alone Considered as a mere descuption, the 
circular theory of the heavenly motions represents perfectly 
well their general features. and by adding epicycles without 


Couvs de Philosophic Positive, vol n p 202 



INDUCTIONS IMPROPERLY SO CALLED. 


383 


limit, those motions, even as now known to us, might he ex¬ 
pressed with any degree of accuracy that might be required. 
The elliptical theory, as a mere description, would have a gieat 
advantage m point of simplicity, and m the consequent facility 
of conceiving it and reasoning about it, hut it would not 
really he more tine than the other. Different descriptions, t 
therefore, may he all true: hut not, surely, different explana- , 
tions The doctrine that the heavenly bodies moved by a 
virtue inherent m their celestial nature; the doctnne that 
they were moved by impact, (which led to the hypothesis of 
vortices as the only impelling force capable of whirling bodies 
m circles,) and the Newtonian doctrine, that they are moved 
by the composition of a centupetal with an original piojectile 
force, all these aie explanations, collected by leal induction 
from supposed parallel cases, and they were all successively 
received by philosophers, as scientific truths on the subject 
of the heavenly bodies Can it be said of these, as was said 
of the different descriptions, that they are all true as far as 
they go ? Is it not clear that only one can be tiue in any 
degree, and the other two must be altogether false ? So much 
for explanations. let us now compare different predictions 
the first, that eclipses will occur when one planet or satellite 
is so situated as to cast its shadow upon another, the second, 
that they will occur when some great calamity is impending 
over mankind. Do these two doctrines only differ m the 
degree of their truth, as expressing real facts with unequal 
degiees of accuracy 9 Assuredly the one is true, and the other 
absolutely false * , 


* Dr Whew ell, in his reply, contests the distinction here drawn, and main¬ 
tains, that not only different descriptions, but different explanations of a 
phenomenon, may all be true Of the three theones respecting the motions 
of the heavenly bodies, he says (Philosophy of Discovery , p 2dl) “Un¬ 
doubtedly all these explanations may be true and consistent with each other, 
and would be so if each had been followed out so as to show m what manner it 
could be made consistent with the facts And this was, m reality, m a great 
measure done The doctrine that the heavenly bodies were moved by vortices 
was successfully modified, so that it came to coincide m its results with the 
doctrine of an inverse-quadratic centripetal force , When this point was 

reached, the vortex was merely a machinery, well or ill devised, for producing 



334 


INDUCTION. 


In every way, therefore, it is evident that to explain in¬ 
duction as the colligation of facts by means of appropriate 
conceptions, that is, conceptions which will really express 

such a centripetal force, and therefore did not contradict the doctrine of a cen¬ 
tripetal force Nekton himself does not appear to have been averse to explaining 
gravity by impulse So little is it true that if one theory be true the other must 
be false The attempt to explain gravity by the impulse of streams of particles 
flowing through the umveise m all directions, which I have mentioned m the 
Philosophy, is so far from being inconsistent with the Newtonian theory, that it 
is founded entirely upon it And even with regaid to the doctrine, that the 
heavenly bodies move by an inherent virtue, if this doctrine had been main¬ 
tained in any such way that it was brought to agiee with the facts, the inherent 
virtue must have had its laws determined, and then it would have been found 
that the virtue had a reference to the central body, and so, the * inherent 
virtue’ must have coincided m its effect with the Newtonian force , and then, 
the two explanations would agree, except so far as the word 'inherent 5 was 
concerned And if such a part of an earlier theory as this word inherent indi¬ 
cates, is found to be untenable, it is of course rejected m the transition to later 
and more exact theories, m Inductions of this kind, as well as m what Mi Mill 
calls Descriptions There is, therefore, still no validity discoverable in the dis¬ 
tinction which Mr Mill attempts to draw between descriptions like Kepler’s 
law of elliptical orbits, and other examples of induction ” 

If the doctrine of vortices had meant, not that vortices existed, but only 
that the planets moved m the same manner as if they had been whirled by 
vortices, if the hypothesis had been merely a mode of 1 epresentmg the facts, 
not an attempt to account for them, if, m shoit, it had been only a Descnp- 
tion , it would, no doubt, have been reconcileable with the Newtonian theory 
The vortices, however, were not a mere aid to conceiving the motions of the 
planets, hut a supposed physical agent, actively impelling them , a material fact, 
which might be true or not true, but could not be both true and not true Ac¬ 
cording to Descartes 5 theory it was true, according to Newton's it was not true. 
Du Whewell probably means that since the phrases, centripetal and projectile 
force, do not declare the nature but only the direction of the forces, the New¬ 
tonian theory does not absolutely contradict any hypothesis which may be framed 
respecting the mode of their production The Newtonian theory, legarded as a 
mere description of the planetary motions, does not, but the Newtonian 
theory as an explanation of them does Eor m what does the explanation con¬ 
sist « In ascribing those motions to a general law which obtains between all 
particles of matter, and in identifying this with the law by which bodies fall to 
the ground. If the planets are kept in their orbits by a force which draws 
the particles composing them towards every other particle of mattei m 
the solar system, they are not kept m those orbits by the impulsive force 
of certain streams of matter which whirl them round The one explanation 
absolutely excludes the other Either the planets are not moved by vortices, 
or they do not move by a law common to all matter It is impossible that both 
opinions can be true As well might it be said that there is no contradiction 



INDUCTIONS IMPROPERLY SO CALLED. 335 

them, is to confound meie description of the observed facts 
with inference from those facts, and ascube to the latter what 
is a charactenstic propeity of the former 


between the assertions, that a man died because somebody killed him, and that 
he died a natural death. 

So, again, the theoiy that the planets move by a virtue inherent m their 
celestial nature, is incompatible with eithei of the two others either that of 
their being moved by vortices, or that which legards them as moving by a 
pioperty which they have in common with the earth and all terrestnal bodies 
Dr Whewell says that the theory of an inherent virtue agrees with Newton’s 
when the word inherent is left out, which of course it would be (he says) if 
“ found to be untenable ** But leave that out, and where is the theory 2 The 
word inherent is the theory When that is omitted, there remains nothing ex¬ 
cept that the heavenly bodies move by “ a virtue,” 1 e by a power of some sort, 
or by virtue of then celestial nature, which directly contradicts the doctrine that 
terrestrial bodies fall by the same law 

If Dr Whewell is not yet satisfied, any other subject will serve equally well 
to test his doctrine He will hardly say that there is no conti adiction between 
the emission theory and the undulatory theoiy of light, or that there can be 
both one and two electricities, or that the hypothesis of the production of 
the higher organic forms by development from the lowei, and the supposition 
of separate and successive acts of creation, are quite recoDcileable , or that the 
theory that volcanoes are fed from a central fire, and the doctrines which 
ascribe them to chemical action at a comparatively small depth below the earth’s 
surface, are consistent with one another, and all ti ue as far as they go 

If different explanations of the same fact cannot both be true, still less, 
surely, can diffeient predictions Dr Whewell quarrels (on what ground it is 
not necessary here to consider) with the example I had chosen on this point, 
and thinks an objection to an illustration a sufficient answer to a theory 
Examples not liable to his objection are easily found, if the proposition that 
conflicting predictions cannot both be true, can be made clearer by any examples 
Suppose the phenomenon to be a newly-discovered comet, and that one astro¬ 
nomer predicts its return once in every 300 years—anothei once in every 400 
can they both be light ? When Columbus predicted that by sailing constantly 
westwaid he should m time return to the point from which he set out, while 
otheis asserted that he could never do so except by turning back, were both he 
and his opponents true prophets ? Were the predictions which foretold the 
wonders of railways and steamships, and those which averred that the Atlantic 
could never be crossed by steam navigation, nor a railway tram propelled ten 
miles an hour, both (m Dr. Whewell*s words) “tiue, and consistent with one 
another” 2 

Dr Whewell sees no distinction between holding contradictory opinions on 
a question of fact, and meiely employing different analogies to facilitate the 
conception of the same fact The case of different Inductions belongs to the 
former class, that of different Descriptions to the latter. 



336 


INDUCTION. 


There is, however, between Colligation and Induction, a 
real correlation, which it is important to conceive correctly 
| Colligation is not always induction , hut induction is always 
| colligation The assertion that the planets move m ellipses, 
was hut a mode of representing observed facts, it was but a 
colligation, while the asseition that they are diawn, or tend, 
towards the sun, was the statement of a new fact, inferred 
by induction. But the induction, once made, accomplishes 
‘ the purposes of colligation likewise. It brings the same 
facts, which Kepler had connected by his conception of an 
ellipse, under the additional conception of bodies acted upon 
by a central force, and serves therefore as a new bond of 
connexion for those facts, a new pimciple for their classifi¬ 
cation. 

Further, the descriptions which aie improperly confounded 
with induction, are nevertheless a necessary pieparation for 
induction, no less necessary than collect observation of the 
facts themselves. Without the previous colligation of detached 
observations by means of one general conception, we could 
never have obtained any basis for an induction, except m the 
case of phenomena of very limited compass We should not 
be able to affirm any predicates at all, of a subject incapable 
of being observed otherwise than piecemeal much less could 
we extend those predicates by induction to other similar sub¬ 
jects. Induction, therefore, always presupposes, not only that 
the necessary observations are made with the necessary accu¬ 
racy, but also that the results of these observations are, so far 
as practicable, connected togethei by general descriptions, 
enabling the mind to represent to itself as wholes whatever 
phenomena are capable of being so repiesented. 

§ 5. Dr Whewell has replied at some length to the pre¬ 
ceding observations, re-stating his opinions, but without (as 
far as I can perceive) adding anything material to his former 
aiguments. Since, however, mine have not had the good 
fortune to make any impression upon him, I will subjoin a 
few remarks, tending to show more cleaily m what our diffe- 



INDUCTIONS IMPROPERLY SO CALLED. 337 

rence of opinion consists, as well as, m some measure, to 
account for it 

Nearly all the definitions of induction, by wnteis of autho¬ 
rity, make it consist m diawmg inferences fiom known cases 
to unknown, affiimmg of a class, a predicate which has been 
found tiue of some cases belonging to the class, concluding, 
because some things have a ceitam property, that other things 
which resemble them have the same property—or because a 
thing has manifested a property at a certain time, that it has 
and will have that piopeity at other times. 

It will scarcely be contended that Kepler s operation was 
an Induction m this sense of the term The statement, that 
Mais moves m an elliptical oibit, was no generalization from 
individual cases to a class of cases Neither was it an exten¬ 
sion to all time, of what had been found true at some pai- 
ticular time. The whole amount of generalization which the 
case admitted of, was ah eady completed, 01 might have been 
so Long before the elliptic theory was thought of, it had 
been asceitamed that the planets returned periodically to the 
same apparent places, the series of these places was, or might 
have been, completely determined, and the apparent course of 
each planet marked out on the celestial globe m an uninter¬ 
rupted line. Kepler did not extend an observed truth to 
other cases than those m which it had been observed: he did 
not widen the subject of the proposition which expressed the 
observed facts The alteration he made was m the predicate. 
Instead of saying, the successive places of Mars are so and so, 
he summed them up m the statement, that the successive 
places of Mais are points m an ellipse. It is true, this state¬ 
ment, as Dr Whewell says, was not the sum of the observa¬ 
tions merely; it was the sum of the observations seen under a 
new point of view * But it was not the sum of more than the 
observations, as a real induction is It took m no cases but 
those which had been actually observed, or which could have 
been inferred from the observations before the new point of 
view presented itself. Theie was not that transition fiom 


VOL. I. 


* Phil . of Discov p 256 

2S 



338 


INDUCTION 


known cases to unknown, which constitutes Induction in the 
original and acknowledged meaning of the term 

Old definitions, it is true, cannot prevail against new 
knowledge and if the Keplerian opeiation, as a logical pio- 
cess, he really identical with what takes place m acknow¬ 
ledged induction* the definition of induction ought to be so 
widened as to take it m, since scientific language ought to 
adapt itself to the true relations which subsist between the 
things it is employed to designate Here then it is that I 
am at issue with Dr Whewell He does think the operations 
identical. He allows of no logical process m any case of in¬ 
duction, other than what there was m Kepler’s case, namely, 
guessing until a guess is found which tallies with the facts ; 
and accordingly, as we shall see hereafter, he rejects all canons' 
of induction, because it is not by means of them that we guess 
Dr Whewell’s theory of the logic of science would be very 
perfect if it did not pass over altogether the question of 
Pi oof. But in my apprehension there is such a thing as proof, 
and inductions differ altogether from descriptions m their 
relation to that element Induction is pioof, it is inferring 
something unobseived from something observed it lequnes, 
therefore, an appiopnate test of proof, and to provide that 
test, is the special puipose of inductive logic. When, on the 
conti ary, we merely collate known observations, and, m Dr. 
Whewell s phraseology, connect them by means of a new con¬ 
ception , if the conception does serve to connect the observa¬ 
tions, we have all we want As the proposition m which it 
is embodied pretends to no other truth than what it may 
share with many other modes of representing the same facts, 
to be consistent with the facts is all it requires. it neither 
needs nor admits of proof, though it may serve to prove other 
things, inasmuch as, by placing the facts m mental connexion 
with other facts, not previously seen to resemble them, it assi¬ 
milates the case to another class of phenomena, concerning 
which real Inductions have already been made Thus Kep¬ 
ler’s so-called law brought the orbit of Mars mto the class 
ellipse, and by doing so, proved all the properties of an ellipse 



INDUCTIONS IMPROPERLY SO CALLED. 


339 


to be true of tlie oibit but m this proof Keplei s law supplied 
the minor piemise, and not (as is the case with leal Induc¬ 
tions) the major. 

Dr. Whew ell calls nothing Induction where there is not a 
new mental conception introduced, and everything induction 
wheie there is But this is to confound two very different 
things, Invention and Proof The introduction of a new con¬ 
ception belongs to Invention and invention may be required 
m any opei ation, but is the essence of none A new concep¬ 
tion may be mtioduced for descnptive purposes, and so it may 
for inductive puiposes But it is so far from constituting 
induction, that induction does not necessanly stand m need 
of it Most inductions require no conception but what was 
present m every one of the particular instances on which the 
induction is grounded That all men are moital is suiely an 
inductive conclusion, yet no new conception is mtioduced by 
it. Whoevei knows that any man has died, has all the con¬ 
ceptions involved m the inductive geneialization But Dr. 
Whewell considers the piocess of invention which consists m 
framing a new conception consistent with the facts, to be not 
meiely a necessary part of all induction, but the whole of it 

The mental operation which extracts from a number of 
detached observations ceitam general characters m which the 
observed phenomena resemble one another, or resemble other 
known facts, is what Bacon, Locke, and most subsequent, 
metaphysicians, have understood by the word Abstiaction A 
geneial expression obtained by abstraction, connecting known 
facts by means of common characteis, but without concluding 
from them to unknown, may, I think, with strict logical cor¬ 
rectness, be termed a Description , nor do I know in what 
other way things can ever be described. My position, how¬ 
ever, does not depend on the employment of that particular 
word, I am quite content to use Dr Whewell’s term Colli¬ 
gation, 01 the more general phrases, “ mode of repiesentmg, 
or of expressing, phenomena ” provided it be clearly seen 
that the process is not Induction, but something radically 
different. 


22—2 



840 


INDUCTION. 


What more may usefully be said on the subject of Colliga¬ 
tion, or of the correlative expression invented by Dr. Whewell, 
the Explication of Conceptions, and generally on the subject 
of ideas and mental representations as connected with the study 
of facts, will find a more appropriate place m the Fourth Book, 
on the Opeiations Subsidiary to Induction: to which I must 
refer the reader for the removal of any difficulty which the 
present discussion may have left. 



OHAPTEK III. 


OF THE GROUND OF INDUCTION. 

§ 1. Induction propeily so called, as distinguished from 
those mental operations, sometimes though impropeily desig¬ 
nated by the name, which I have attempted in the preceding 
chapter to characterize, may, then, he summarily defined as 
Generalization from Expenence. It consists m mfeinng from 
some individual instances m which a phenomenon is observed 
to occur, that it occurs m all instances of a certain class; 
namely, m all which resemble the foimer, m what are regarded 
as the matenal circumstances. 

In what way the material circumstances are to be distin¬ 
guished from those which are immaterial, or why some of the 
circumstances are material and others not so, we aie not yet 
ready to point out. We must first observe, that there is a 
pimciple implied m the very statement of what Induction is, 
an assumption with regard to the course of nature and the 
older of the universe, namely, that there are such things m 
nature as parallel cases; that what happens once, will, under 
a sufficient degree of similarity of ciicumstances, happen again, 
and not only again, but as often as the same ciicumstances 
recur. This, I say, is an assumption, involved m every case of 
induction And, if we consult the actual course of nature, we 
find that the assumption is warranted. The universe, so far 
as known to us, is so constituted, that whatever is true m any 
one case, is true m all cases of a certain description; the only 
difficulty is, to find what description. 

This universal fact, which is our warrant for all inferences 
from experience, has been described by different philosophers 
m different forms of language: that the coursp of nature is 
uniform ; that the universe is governed by general laws; and 



342 


INDUCTION. 


the like. One of the most usual of these modes of expiession, 
"but also one of the most inadequate, is that which has been 
- brought into familial use by the metaphysicians of the school 
of Reid and Stewart. The disposition of the human mind to 
genei alize fiom expeuence,—a propensity considered by these 
philosopheis as an instinct of our nature,—they usually de¬ 
scribe undei some such name as “ our intuitive conviction that 
the futuie will lesemble the past ” Now it has been well 
pointed out by Mr. Bailey,* that (whethei the tendency be or 
not an ougmal and ultimate element of our natuie), Time, m 
its modifications of past, present, and futuie, has no concern 
either with the belief itself* or with the grounds of it We 
believe that hie will bum to-morrow, because it burned to-day 
and yesteiday, but we believe, on precisely the same grounds* 
that it burned before we weie bom, and that it burns this veiy 
day m Cochin-China. It is not from thespast to the future, as 
past and futuie, that we infer, but fiom the known to the un¬ 
known , from facts observed to facts unobserved, fiom what 
we have peiceived, or been directly conscious of, to what has 
not come within our experience. In this last piedicament is 
the whole legion of the futuie, but also the vastly gieater 
portion of the present and of the past 

Whatever be the most proper mode of expressing it, the 
proposition that the course of natuie is umfoim, is the funda¬ 
mental punciple, or general axiom, of Induction. It would yet 
be a great error to offer this large generalization as any expla¬ 
nation of the inductive process. On the contrary, I hold it to 
be itself an instance of induction, and induction by no means 
of the most obvious kind. Ear from being the fust induction 
we make, it is one of the last, or at all events one of those 
which are latest m attaining strict philosophical accuracy As 
a general maxim, indeed, it has scarcely entered into the minds 
of any hut philosophers; nor even by them, as we shall have 
many oppoitumties of remarking, have its extent and limits 
been always very justly conceived. The truth is, that this 
great generalization is itself founded on prior generalizations 


Essays on the Pursuit of Truth. 



GROUND OF INDUCTION. 


343 


The obscurei laws of natuie weie discovered by means of it, 
but the more obvious ones must have been undeistood and as¬ 
sented to as general tiuths before it was evei'heard of *We 
should never have thought of affirming that all phenomena 
take place accoidmg to geneial laws, if we had not hist ailived, 
m the case of a gieat multitude of phenomena, at some know¬ 
ledge of the laws themselves, which could be done no other¬ 
wise than by induction. In what sense, then, can a pnnciple, 
which is so fai fiom being our earliest induction, be regarded 
as our wan ant for all the otheis ? In the only sense, m which 
(as we have already seen) the geneial piopositions which we 
place at the head of oui reasonings when we thiow them into 
syllogisms, ever leally contnbute to their validity. As Arch¬ 
bishop Whately remarks, every induction is a syllogism with 
the major premise suppressed, or (as I prefer expressing it) 
eveiy induction may be thiown into the form of a syllogism, 
by supplying a major premise If this be actually done, the 
principle which w r e are now considering, that of the uniformity 
of the couise of nature, will appear as the ultimate majoi pre¬ 
mise of all inductions, and will, theiefoie, stand to all indue-' 
tions m the relation m which, as has been shown at so much 
length, the major proposition of a syllogism always stands to 
the conclusion, not contributing at all to prove it, but being 
a necessary condition of its being proved, since no conclu¬ 
sion is proved, for which there cannot be found a true major 
premise.* 


* In the first edition a note was appended at this place, containing some 
criticism on Ar-chbishop Whately’s mode of conceiving the relation between 
Syllogism and Induction. In a subsequent issue of his Logic , the Aichbishop 
made a reply to the criticism, which induced me to cancel part of the note, 
incorporating the remainder m the text In a still later edition, the Archbishop 
observes in a tone of something like disapprobation, that the objections, “ doubt¬ 
less fiom their being fully answered and found untenable, were silently sup¬ 
pressed,” and that hence he might appear to some of his leaders to be combating 
a shadow On this latter point, the Archbishop need give himself no uneasi¬ 
ness His readers, I make bold to say, will fully credit his mere affirmation 
that the objections have actually been made 

But as he seems to think that what he terms the suppression of the objec¬ 
tions ought not to have been made ‘ c silently,” I now break that silence, and 
state exactly what it is that I suppi eased, and why I suppiessed that alone 



344 


INDUCTION. 


The statement, that the uniformity of the course of nature 
is the ultimate major premise m all cases of induction, may be 
thought to requne some explanation The immediate major 
premise m eveiy inductive argument, it certainly is not Of 
that. Archbishop Whately’s must be held to be the correct 
account. The induction, “ John, Peter, &c aie mortal, there¬ 
fore all mankind aie mortal,” may, as he justly says, bethiown 
into a syllogism by prefixing as a major piemise (what is 
at any late a necessary condition of the validity of the aigu- 
ment) namely, that what is tine of John, Peter, &c is tiue of 
all mankind Put how came we by this major premise ? It is 
not self-evident, nay, m all cases of unwananted generaliza¬ 
tion, it is not true. How, then, is it arnved at? Necessarily 
either by induction or latiocmation, and if by induction, the 
process, like all other inductive arguments, may be thiown mto 
the form of a syllogism. This previous syllogism it is, there¬ 
fore, necessary to consti uct. Theie is, in the long run, only 
one possible construction The real proof that what is true of 
John, Peter, &c is true of all mankind, ean only be, that 
a different supposition would be inconsistent with the uni- 
foimity which we know to exist m the course of nature. 

which might be regarded as personal criticism on the Archbishop. I had im¬ 
puted to him the having omitted to ask himself a particular question I found 
that he had asked himself the question, and could give it an answer consistent 
with his own theory I had also, within the compass of -a parenthesis, hazarded 
some lemarks on certain geneial characteristics of Archbishop Whately as a 
philosopher These remaiks, though their tone, I hope, was neither disrespect¬ 
ful nor arrogant, I felt, on reconsideration, that I was hardly entitled to make , 
least of all, when the instance which I had regarded as an illustration of them, 
failed, as I now saw, to bear them out The real matter at the bottom of the 
whole dispute, the different view we take of the function of the major premise, 
remains exactly where it was, and so far was I from thinking that my opinion 
had been “ fully answered” and was “ untenable,” that m the same edition in 
which I cancelled the note, I not only enforced the opinion by further aigu- 
ments, hut answeied (though without naming him) those of the Aichbishop 
For not having made this statement before, I do not think it needful to 
apologize It would be attaching very great importance to one’s smallest say¬ 
ings, to think a formal retractation requisite every time that one commits an 
error Nor is Archbishop Whately’s well-earned fame of so tender a quality as 
to require, that m withdrawing a slight criticism on him I should have been 
bound to offer a public amende foi having made it 



GROUND OF INDUCTION. 


345 


Whether there would he this inconsistency or not, may he 
a matter of long and delicate inquiry, hut unless there would, 
we have no sufficient ground for the major of the inductive 
syllogism. It hence appeals, that if we throw the whole 
course of any inductive argument into a series of syllogisms, 
we shall arrive hy more or fewer steps at an ultimate syllogism, 
which will have for its major premise the principle, 01 axiom, 
of the uniformity of the couise of natuie * 

It was not to he expected that m the case of this axiom, 
any moie than of other axioms, theie should he unanimity 
among thinkers with lespect to the giounds on which it is to 
he received as true I have alieady stated that I legard it as 
itself a generalization from experience Others hold it to be a 
principle which, antecedently to any veiideation hy expenence, 
we aie compelled by the constitution of our thinking faculty to 
assume as true. Having so recently, and at so much length, 
combated a similar doctrine as applied to the axioms of mathe¬ 
matics, by arguments which are m a great measure applicable 
to the piesent case, I shall defer the more particular discussion 
of this controverted point m regard to the fundamental axiom 
of induction, until a more advanced penod of our inquiry + 


* But though, it is a condition of the validity of every induction that there 
be uniformity m the course of nature, it is not a necessary condition that the 
uniformity should pervade all nature It is enough that it pervades the par¬ 
ticular class of phenomena to which the induction relates An induction con¬ 
cerning the motions of the planets, or the properties of the magnet, would not 
he vitiated though we were to suppose that wind and weather are the sport oi 
chance, provided it be assumed that astronomical and magnetic phenomena are 
under the dominion of general laws Otherwise the eaily experience of mankind 
would have rested on a veiy weak foundation , for in the infancy of science it 
could not be known that all phenomena are regular m their course 

Neither would it be coriect to say that every induction by which we mfei 
any truth, implies the general fact of uniformity as foreknown , even m reference 
to the kind of phenomena concerned It implies, either that this general fact 
is already known, or that we may now know it, as the conclusion, the Duke ol 
Wellington is mortal, drawn from the instances A, B, and C, implies either 
that we have already concluded all men to be mortal, or that we are now entitled 
to do so from the same evidence A vast amount of confusion and paralogism 
respecting the grounds of Induction would be dispelled by keeping m view these 
simple considerations. 


f Infra, chap xxi 



846 


INDUCTION. 


At piesent it is of more importance to understand thoroughly 
the lmpoit of the axiom itself. For the proposition, that the 
course of nature is uniform, possesses ratliei the bievity suit¬ 
able to popular, than the precision requisite in philosophical 
language its terms require to he explained, and a stricter 
than their 01 dinary signification given to them, before the truth 
of the assertion can be admitted. 

§ 2 Every persons consciousness assures him that he 
does not always expect uniformity m the course of events, he 
does not always believe that the unknown will be similar to 
the known, that the future will resemble the past. Nobody 
believes that the succession of ram and fine weather will be 
the same m every future year as m the piesent Nobody ex¬ 
pects to have the same dieams repeated every night On the 
contrary, eveiybody mentions it as something extraordinary, 
if the course of nature is constant, and resembles itself, m these 
particular To look for constancy where constancy is not to 
be expected, as for instance that a day which has once brought 
good fortune will always be a fortunate day, is justly accounted 
superstition 

The couise of nature, m truth, is not only umfoim, it is 
also infinitely various Some phenomena aie always seen to 
recur in the very same combinations m which we met with 
them at first, others seem altogether capricious, while some, 
which we had been accustomed to regard as bound down ex¬ 
clusively to a particular set of combinations, we unexpectedly 
find detached from some of the elements with which we had 
hitherto found them conjoined, and united to otheis of quite 
a contrary description. To an inhabitant of Cential Afnca, 
fifty years ago, no fact probably appeared to lest on more 
umfoim experience than this, that all human beings are 
black. To Europeans, not many years ago, the proposition, 
All swans are white, appeared an equally unequivocal instance 
of uniformity m the couise of nature. Fuitber expenence has 
proved to both that they were mistaken, but they had to wait 
fifty centuries for this expenence. During that long time, 



GROUND OF INDUCTION. 


347 


mankind believed m an uniformity of the course of nature 
where no such uniformity really existed. 

According to the notion which the ancients enteitamed of 
induction, the foiegoing were cases of as legitimate inference 
as any inductions whatever. In these two instances, m 
which, the conclusion being false, the ground of inference 
must have been insufficient, there was, nevertheless, as much 
giound for it as this conception of induction admitted of. 
The induction of the ancients has been well described by 
Bacon, under the name of “ Inductio per enumerationem sim- 
phcem, ubi non lepentur mstantia conti adictoria.” It con¬ 
sists m ascribing the character of general truths to all pro¬ 
positions which are true m every instance that we happen 
to know of. This is the kind of induction which is natural 
to the mind when unaccustomed to scientific methods The 
tendency, which some call an instinct, and which others 
account for by association, to infer the future fiom the past, 
the known from the unknown, is simply a habit of expecting 
that what has been found true once or several times, and 
never yet found false, will be found true again. Whether 
the instances are few or many, conclusive or inconclusive, 
does not much affect the matter: these are considerations 
which occur only on reflection; the unprompted tendency of 
the mind is to generalize its experience, provided this points 
all m one direction, provided no other expenence of a con¬ 
flicting character comes unsought The notion of seeking it, 
of experimenting for it, of inter? ogatmg nature (to use Bacon’s 
expression) is of much later growth. The observation of 
nature, by uncultivated intellects, is purely passive. they 
accept the facts which piesent themselves, without taking 
the trouble of searching for more it is a superior mind only 
which asks itself what facts are needed to enable it to come to 
a safe conclusion, and then looks out for these. 

But though we have always a propensity to generalize 
from unvarying expenence, we are not always warranted m 
doing so Before we can be at liberty to conclude that some¬ 
thing is universally true because we have never known an 



348 


INDUCTION. 


instance to the contrary, we must have reason to believe that 
if there were m nature any instances to the contrary, we 
should have known of them This assuianee, m the great 
majority of cases, we cannot have, or can have only m a very 
moderate degree The possibility of having it, is the founda¬ 
tion on which we shall see hereafter that induction by simple 
enumeiation may m some lemarkable cases amount practically 
to proof * No such assurance, however, can be had, on any of 
the ordinary subjects of scientific inquiry. Popular notions 
are usually founded on induction by simple enumeration, m 
science it carries us but a little way We are forced to begin 
with it, we must often lely on it piovisionally, m the absence 
of means of more searching investigation But, for the accu¬ 
rate study of nature, we requue a surer and a more potent 
instrument. 

It was, above all, by pointing out the insufficiency of this 
rude and loose conception of Induction, that Bacon merited 
the title so generally awarded to him, of Founder of the In¬ 
ductive Philosophy The value of his own contributions to 
a more philosophical theory of the subject has certainly been 
exaggerated. Although (along with some fundamental errors) 
his writings contain, more or less fully developed, several 
of the most important principles of the Inductive Method, 
physical investigation has now far outgrown the Baconian 
conception of Induction Moral and political inquiry, indeed, 
are as yet far behind that conception The current and 
approved modes of reasoning on these subj ects are still of 
the same vicious description against which Bacon piotested; 
the method almost exclusively employed by those professing 
to treat such matters inductively, is the very inductio per 
enumerationem simphcem which he condemns , and the expe¬ 
rience which we hear so confidently appealed to by all sects, 
parties, and interests, is still, m his own emphatic words, mera 
palpatio 

§ 3 . In order to a better understanding of the problem 


Xnfia, chap, xxi xxxi. 



GROUND OF INDUCTION. 


349 


which the logician must solve if he would establish a scientific 
theory of Induction, let us compare a few cases of mcoirect 
inductions with others which are acknowledged to be legiti¬ 
mate Some, we know, which were believed for centuries to 
be correct, were nevertheless mcoirect That all swans are 
white, cannot have been a good induction, since the conclu¬ 
sion has turned out erroneous. The experience, however, on 
which the conclusion rested, was genuine From the earliest 
records, the testimony of the inhabitants of the known woild 
was unammous on the point The uniform experience* there¬ 
fore, of the inhabitants of the known world, agreeing m a 
common result, without one known instance of deviation from 
that result, is not always sufficient to establish a general 
conclusion 

But let us now turn to an instance apparently not very 
dissimilar to this. Mankind were wrong, it seems, m con¬ 
cluding that all swans weie white are we also wrong, when 
we conclude that all men's heads glow above their shoulders, 
and never below, m spite of the conflicting testimony of the 
natuialist Pliny ? As there weie black swans, though civi¬ 
lized people had existed for three thousand years on the earth 
without meeting with them, may there not also be “ men 
whose heads do grow beneath their shoulders," notwith¬ 
standing a rather less perfect unanimity of negative testimony 
from observers ? Most persons would answer No, it was 
more credible that a bud should vary m its colour, than that 
men should vary m the relative position of their principal 
organs And there is no doubt that m so saying they would 
be right but to say why they are right, would be impossible, 
without entering more deeply than is usually done, into the 
true theory of Induction. 

Again, there are cases m which we reckon with the most 
unfailing confidence upon uniformity, and other cases m which 
we do not count upon it at all In some we feel complete 
assurance that the future will resemble the past, the unknown 
be precisely similar to the known In others, however 
invariable may be the result obtained from the instances 
which have been obseived, we draw from them no more than 



350 


INDUCTION 


a very feeble presumption tliat the like result will hold in all 
other cases. That a straight line is the shortest distance 
between two points, we do not doubt to be true even m the 
region of the fixed stars When a chemist announces the 
existence and properties of a newly-discovered substance, if 
we confide m his accuracy, we feel assured that the conclu¬ 
sions he has arrived at will hold universally, though the 
induction be founded but on a single instance We do not 
withhold our assent, waiting for a repetition of the experi¬ 
ment, 01 if we do, it is from a doubt whether the one expen- 
ment was pioperly made, not whether if properly made it 
would be conclusive. Here, then, is a general law of nature, 
inferred without hesitation from a single instance, an universal 
proposition from a singular one Now mark another case, and 
contiast it with this Not all the instances which have been 
observed since the beginning of the woild, m support of the 
general proposition that all crows are black, would be deemed 
a sufficient presumption of the tiuth of the pioposition, to 
outweigh the testimony of one unexceptionable witness who 
should affirm that m some region of the eaith not fully ex¬ 
plored, he had caught and examined a crow, and had found it 
to be grey. 

Why is a single instance, m some cases, sufficient for a 
complete induction, while m otheis, myriads of concurring 
instances, without a single exception known or presumed, go 
such a very little way towards establishing an univeisal pro¬ 
position ? Whoever can answer this question knows more of 
the philosophy of logic than the wisest of the ancients, and has 
solved the problem of induction. 



CHAPTEE IY 


OF LAWS OF NATURE. 

§ 1 In the contemplation of that uniformity in the course 
of nature, which is assumed m every mfeience from experi¬ 
ence, one of the first obseivations that present themselves 
is, that the uniformity in question is not piopeily uniformity, 
but umfoimities The general legulanty results from the 
coexistence of partial regularities The course of nature m 
geneial is constant, because the couise of each of the various 
phenomena that compose it is so A certain fact invariably 
occuis whenever certain circumstances are present, and does 
not occur when they are absent, the like is true of another 
fact, and so on From these separate threads of connexion 
between parts of the great whole which we teim nature, a 
general tissue of connexion unavoidably weaves itself, by which 
the whole is held together. If A is always accompanied by 
E, B by E, and C by F, it follows that A B is accompanied 
by D E, A C by D F, B C by E F, and finally A B 0 by 
DEF, and thus the general character of regularity is pro- 
'duced, which, along with and m the midst of infinite diversity, 
peivades all nature 

The fiist point, therefore, to be noted m regard to what is 
called the uniformity of the course of nature, is, that it is itself 
a complex fact, compounded of all the separate uniformities 
which exist m respect to single phenomena These various 
uniformities, when ascertained by what is regaided as a suffi¬ 
cient induction, we call m common parlance, Laws of Nature 
Scientifically speaking, that title is employed in a more re¬ 
stricted sense, to designate the uniformities when reduced to 
their most simple expression Thus m the illustration already 
employed, there were seven uniformities, all of which, if con¬ 
sidered sufficiently certain, would in the more lax application 



852 


INDUCTION. 


of the term, be called laws of nature But of the seven, three 
alone are properly distinct and independent, these being pie- 
supposed, the others follow of couise. The three fust, there¬ 
fore, accoidmg to the stricter acceptation, are called laws of 
nature, the remainder not, because they are m tiuth mere 
cases of the three first, vutually included m them , said, there¬ 
fore, to result from them* whoever affirms those three has 
already affirmed all the rest. 

To substitute real examples for symbolical ones, the follow¬ 
ing aie three uniformities, or call them laws of nature, the 
law that air has weight, the law that pressure on a fluid is 
propagated equally m all directions, and the law that pressure 
m one direction, not opposed by equal pressure m the contrary 
direction, produces motion, which does not cease until equili- 
bnum is restored. From these three uniformities we should 
be able to predict another uniformity, namely, the nse of the 
mercury m the Tomcelhan tube This, m the stnctei use of 
the phiase, is not a law of nature It is the result of laws of 
nature. It is a case of each and every one of the three laws; 
and is the only occurrence by which they could all he fulfilled. 
If the mercury were not sustained m the barometer, and sus¬ 
tained at such a height that the column of mercuiy were equal 
m weight to a column of the atmosphere of the same diameter, 
here would be a case, either of the air not pressing upon the 
surface of the mercury with the foice which is called its weight, 
or of the downward pressure on the mercury not being pro¬ 
pagated equally m an upward direction, or of a body pressed 
in one direction and not m the direction opposite, either not 
moving m the direction m which it is pressed, or stopping 
before it had attained equilibrium If we knew, therefore, the 
three simple laws, but had never tried the Torricellian expen- 
ment, we might deduce its result from those laws. The known 
weight of the air, combined with the position of the appa¬ 
ratus, would bring the mercury within the first of the three 
inductions, the first induction would bring it within the 
second, and the second within the third, m the mannei which 
we characterized m treating of Ratiocination. We should 
thus come to know the more complex uniformity, indepen- 



LAWS OF NATURE. 


853 


dently of specific experience, through our knowledge of the 
simpler ones from which it results , though, for reasons which 
will appear hereafter, verification by specific experience would 
still he desnable, and might possibly be indispensable 

Complex uniformities which, like this, are mere cases of 
simpler ones, and have, therefore, been virtually affirmed m 
affirming those, may with propriety be called laws, but can 
scarcely, m the strictness of scientific speech, be termed Laws 
of Nature It is the custom in science, wherever regularity of 
any kind can be traced, to call the general proposition which 
expresses the nature of that regularity, a law ,* as when, in 
mathematics, we speak of the law of decrease of the successive 
terms of a converging series But the expression law of 
nature has generally been employed with a sort of tacit refei- 
ence to the original sense of the word law, namely, the ex¬ 
pression of the will of a superior When, therefore, it appeared 
that any of the uniformities which were observed m nature, 
would result spontaneously from certain other uniformities, no 
separate act of creative will being supposed necessary for the 
production of the derivative uniformities, these have not usu¬ 
ally been spoken of as laws of nature According to one 
mode of expression, the question, What are the laws of nature ? 
may be stated thus:—What are the fewest and simplest as¬ 
sumptions, which being granted, the whole existing order of 
nature would result ? Another mode of stating it would be 
thus What aie the fewest general propositions from which 
all the uniformities which exist m the universe might be de¬ 
ductively inferred ? 

Every great advance which marks an epoch in the progress 
of science, has consisted m a step made towards the solution 
of this problem. Even a simple colligation of inductions 
already made, without any fresh extension of the inductive 
inference, is already an advance in that direction When 
Kepler expressed the regularity which exists m the observed 
motions of the heavenly bodies, by the three general proposi¬ 
tions called his laws, he, m so doing, pointed out three simple 
suppositions which, instead of a much greater number, would 
suffice to construct the whole scheme of the heavenly motions, 
vol. i. 23 



354 


INDUCTION. 


so far as it was known up to that time. A similar and still 
greater step was made when these laws, which at first did not 
seem to he included m any more general truths, weie dis¬ 
covered to be cases of the three laws of motion, as obtaining 
among bodies which mutually tend towards one another with 
a certain force, and have had a certain instantaneous impulse 
originally impressed upon them After this great discovery, 
Kepler’s three propositions, though still called laws, would 
hardly, by any person accustomed to use language with pre¬ 
cision, be termed laws of nature. that phrase would be reseived 
for the simpler and more general laws into which Newton is 
said to have resolved them. 

According to this language, every well-grounded inductive 
generalization is either a law of nature, or a result of laws of 
nature, capable, if those laws aie known, of being predicted 
from them. And the problem of Inductive Logic may be 
summed up m two questions : how to asceitam the laws of 
nature , and how, after having ascertained them, to follow 
them into their results. On the other hand, we must not 
suffer ourselves to imagine that this mode of statement amounts 
to a real analysis, or to anything but a mere verbal trans¬ 
formation of the pioblem, for the expression, Laws of Nature, 
v pxeans nothing but the uniformities which exist among natural 
‘ phenomena (or, m other words, the results of induction), when 
reduced to their simplest expression. It is, however, some¬ 
thing to have advanced so far, as to see that the study of 
nature is the study of laws, not a law, of uniformities, m the 
plural number that the different natural phenomena have 
their separate rules or modes of taking place, which, though 
much intermixed and entangled with one another, may, to a 
eeitain extent, be studied apart: that (to resume our former 
metaphor) the regularity which exists m nature is a web com¬ 
posed of distinct thieads, and only to be understood by tracing 
each of the threads separately , for which purpose it is often 
necessary to unravel some portion of the web, and exhibit the 
fibies apart. The rules of experimental inquiry are the con¬ 
trivances for unravelling the web. 



LAWS OF NATURE. 


355 


§ 2 . In thus attempting to ascertain the geneial older of 
natuie by ascertaining the paiticular order of the occunence 
of each one of the phenomena of nature, the most scientific 
proceeding can be no moie than an impioved form of that 
which was primitively pursued by the human undeistanding, 
while undirected by science When mankind hist formed the 
idea of studying phenomena according to a stnctei and surer 
method than that which they had m the first instance spon¬ 
taneously adopted, they did not, confoimably to the well- 
meant but impracticable piecept of Descartes, set out from 
the supposition that nothing had been alieady ascertained. 
Many of the uniformities existing among phenomena are so 
constant, and so open to observation, as to force themselves 
upon mvoluntaiy recognition Some facts aie so peipetually 
and familiaily accompanied by ceitam others, that mankind 
learnt, as children learn, to expect the one where they found 
the othei, long before they knew how to put their expectation 
into woids by asseitmg, m a proposition, the existence of a 
connexion between those phenomena No science was needed 
to teach that food nounshes, that water diowns, or quenches 
tlinst, that the sun gives light and heat, that bodies fall to 
the ground The first scientific inquirers assumed these and 
the like as known tiuths, and set out from them to discovei 
otheis which were unknown nor were they wrong m so doing, 
subject, however, as they afterwards began to see, to an ulte- 
noi levision of these spontaneous generalizations themselves, 
when the progiess of knowledge pointed out limits to them, 
or showed their truth to be contingent on some circumstance 
not ongmally attended to. It will appear, I think, fiotn 
the subsequent pait of our inquiry, that there is no logical 
fallacy m this mode of proceeding, but we may see already 
that any other mode is rigorously impiacticable. since it is 
impossible to frame any scientific method of induction, or 
test of the coirectness of inductions, unless on the hypothesis 
that some inductions deserving of reliance have been alieady 
made. 

Let us revert, for instance, to one of our former illustra* 
23—3 



356 


INDUCTION. 


tions, and consider why it is that, with exactly the same 
amount of evidence, both negative and positive, we did not 
reject the assertion that there are black swans, while we 
should refuse credence to any testimony which asserted that 
tbeie were men wearing their heads underneath their shoulders. 
The first assertion was more credible than the latter But 
why moie credible ? So long as neither phenomenon had 
been actually witnessed, what reason was there for finding the 
one haider to be believed than the other ? Appaiently because 
there is less constancy m the colours of animals, than m the 
geneial structme of their anatomy But how do we know 
this ? Doubtless, from experience. It appears, then, that we 
need experience to inform us, m what degree, and m what 
cases, or sort of cases, experience is to be relied on Expe¬ 
rience must be consulted m order to learn from it under what 
circumstances arguments from it will he valid We have no 
ulterior test to which we subject experience m general, but 
we make experience its own test. Experience testifies, that 
among the uniformities which it exhibits or seems to exhibit, 

<some are more to he relied on than others, and uniformity, 
theiefore, may he piesumed, from any given number of in¬ 
stances, with a greater degree of assurance, m proportion as 
the case belongs to a class m which the uniformities h§Lve 
hitherto been found more uniform^ 

This mode of correcting one generalization by means of 
another, a narrower generalization by a wider, which common 
sense suggests and adopts m practice, is the real type 
of scientific Induction All that art can do is hut to give 
accuracy and precision to this process, and adapt it to all 
varieties of cases, without any essential alteration m its 
principle 

There are of course no means of applying such a test as 
that above described, unless we already possess a general 
knowledge of the prevalent character of the uniformities 
existing throughout nature. The indispensable foundation, 
therefore, of a scientific formula of induction, must he a 
suivey of the inductions to which mankind have been con¬ 
ducted in unscientific piactice, with the special purpose of 



LAWS OF NATURE. 


35 ? 


ascertaining what kinds of uniformities have been found pei- 
fectly invariable, pervading all nature, and what are those 
which have been found to vary with difference of time, place, 
or other changeable circumstances. 

§ 3 The necessity of such a survey is confirmed by the 
consideration, that the stronger inductions are the touchstone 
to which we always endeavour to bring the weaker. If we 
find any means of deducing one of the less strong inductions 
from stronger ones, it acquires, at once, all the strength of 
those fiom which it is deduced, and even adds to that 
strength, since the independent experience on which the 
weaker induction previously rested, becomes additional evi¬ 
dence of the tiuth of the better established law m which it is 
now found to be included. We may have inferred, fiom his¬ 
torical evidence, that the uncontrolled power of a monaich, 
of an aristocracy, or of the majority, will often be abused 
but we are entitled to lely on this generalization with much 
greater assurance when it is shown to be a corollary from still 
better established facts, the very low degree of elevation of 
character ever yet attained by the average of mankind, and 
the little efficacy, for the most part, of the modes of education 
hitheito practised, m maintaining the predominance of reason 
and conscience over the selfish propensities It is at the same 
time obvious that even these more general facts derive an acces¬ 
sion of evidence from the testimony which history bears to the 
effects of despotism The stiong induction becomes still 
stronger when a weaker one has been bound up with it. 

On the other hand, if an induction conflicts with stronger 
inductions, or with conclusions capable of being conectly 
deduced from them, then, unless on reconsideration it should 
appear that some of the stronger inductions have been 
expressed with greater universality than their evidence war¬ 
rants, the weaker one mus-t give way. The opinion so long 
prevalent that* a comet, or any other unusual appearance m 
the heavenly legions, was the precursor of calamities to 
mankind, or to those at least who witnessed it, the belief m 
the veracity of the oracles of Delphi or Dodona; the rehance 



358 


INDUCTION. 


on astrology, or on the weather-prophecies m almanacs, were 
doubtless inductions supposed to be grounded on experience * 
and faith m such delusions seems quite capabl3 of holding out 
against a great multitude of failures, provided it be nourished 
by a leasonable number of casual coincidences between the 
pie diction and the event What has really put an end to 
these insufficient inductions, is their inconsistency with the 
strongei inductions subsequently obtained by scientific mquny, 
respecting the causes on which terrestrial events leally depend , 
and wheie those scientific tuiths have not yet penetrated, the 
same or similar delusions still prevail. 

It may be affirmed as a general pnnciple, that all induc¬ 
tions, whether strong or weak, which can be connected by 
ratiocination, aie confirmatory of one another, while any 
which lead deductively to consequences that aie incompatible, 


* Dr Wliewell [Phil of Discov p 246) will not allow these and similar 
erroneous judgments to be called inductions , inasmuch as such superstitious 
fancies “were not collected from the facts by seeking a law of their occurrence, 
but were suggested by au imagination of the angei of superior powers, shown 
by such deviations from the ordinary course of nature ” I conceive the ques¬ 
tion to be, not m what manner these notions weie at first suggested, hut by 
what evidence they have, from time to time, been supposed to be substantiated 
If the believeis m these erroneous opinions had been put on their defence, they 
would have referred to experience to the comet which preceded the assassina¬ 
tion of Julius Gsesai, or to oracles and other piophecies known to have been 
fulfilled It is by such appeals to facts that all analogous superstitions, even m 
our day, attempt to justify themselves, the supposed evidence of experience 
is necessaiy to their hold on the mind I quite admit that the influence 
of such coincidences would not be what it is, if strength were not lent to it by 
an antecedent presumption , but this is not pecuhai to such cases, preconceived 
notions of probability form pai t of the explanation of many other cases of belief 
on insufficient evidence. The a pi ion prejudice does not prevent the enoneous 
opinion from being sincerely regarded as a legitimate conclusion from experience, 
though it impropeily piedisposes the mmd to that interpretation of experience 
Thus much m defence of the sort of examples objected to. But it would 
be easy to produce mstances, equally adapted to the purpose, and m which no 
antecedent prejudice is at all concerned “ For many ages,” says Archbishop 
Whately, u all farmers and gaideners were firmly convinced—and convinced 
of their knowing it by experience—that the crops would never turn out good 
unless the seed weie sown during the increase of the moon.” Tms was 
induction, but bad induction just as a vicious syllogism is reasoning, but bad 
reasoning 



LAWS OF NATURE. 


359 


become mutually each other’s test, showing that one or other 
must be given up, or at least more guardedly expressed. In 
the case of inductions which confirm each other, the one which 
becomes a conclusion from ratiocination rises to at least the 
level of certainty of the weakest of those from which it is 
deduced, while m general all are more or less increased m 
certainty. Thus the Torricellian experiment, though a mere 
case of three more general laws, not only strengthened greatly 
the evidence on which those laws rested, but converted one of 
them (the weight of the atmosphere) from a doubtful gene¬ 
ralization into a completely established doctrine. 

If, then, a survey of the uniformities which have been 
ascertained to exist m nature, should point out some which, 
as fax as any human purpose requires certainty, may be con¬ 
sidered quite certain and quite universal; then by means of 
these uniformities we may be able to raise multitudes of other 
inductions to the same point m the scale. For if we can show, 
with respect to any inductive inference, that either it must be 
true, or one of these certain and universal inductions must admit 
of an exception , the former generalization will attain the same 
certainty, and indefeasibleness within the bounds assigned to it, 
which are the attributes of the latter It will be proved to be 
a law-, and if not a result of other and simpler laws, it will be 
a law of nature. 

There are such certain and universal inductions , and it is 
because there are such, that a Logic of Induction is possible. 



CHAPTER V. 


OF THE LAW OF UNIVERSAL CAUSATION. 

§ 1. The phenomena of natuie exist m two distinct re¬ 
lations to one another, that of simultaneity, and that of suc¬ 
cession. Every phenomenon is related, in an uniform manner, 
to some phenomena that coexist with it, and to some that have 
preceded and will follow it. 

Of the uniformities which exist among synchronous pheno¬ 
mena, the most important, on every account, are the laws of 
number, and next to them those of space, or, m other words, 
of extension and figure. The laws of number are common to 
synchronous and successive phenomena That two and two 
make foui, is equally tme whether the second two follow the 
first two or accompany them. It is as tme of days and years 
as of feet and inches. The laws of extension and figure (m 
other words, the theorems of geometiy, ftom its lowest fo its 
highest branches) are, on the contrary, laws of simultaneous 
phenomena only. The various parts of space, and of the 
objects which are said to fill space, coexist ; and the unvarying 
laws which are the subject of the science of geometry, are an 
expression of the mode of their coexistence 

This is a class of laws, or m other words, of uniformities, 
for the comprehension and proof of which it is not necessary 
to suppose any lapse of time, any variety of facts or events suc¬ 
ceeding one another. If all the objects m the universe were 
unchangeably fixed, and had remained m that condition from 
eternity, the propositions of geometry would still be true of 
those objects All things which possess extension, or, m other 
words, which fill space, are subject to geometrical laws. Pos¬ 
sessing extension, they possess figure, possessing figure, they 
must possess some figure m particular, and have all the pro¬ 
perties which geometry assigns to that figure. If one body be 



LAW OF CAUSATION. 


361 


a sphere and another a cylinder, of equal height and diameter, 
the one will he exactly two-thirds of the other, let the nature 
and quality of the material he what it will. Again, each body, 
and each point of a body, must occupy some place or position 
among other bodies; and the position of two bodies lelatively 
to each other, of whatever nature the bodies be, may be un~ 
einngly inferred from the position of each of them relatively 
to any third body. 

In the laws of number, then, and in those of space, we re¬ 
cognise m the most unqualified manner, the rigorous univer¬ 
sality of which we are m quest. Those laws have been m all 
ages the type of certainty, the standard of comparison for all 
mfenoi degrees of evidence. Their mvailability is so perfect, 
that it lenders us unable even to conceive any exception to 
them, and philosophers have been led, though (as I have en¬ 
deavoured to show) erroneously, to consider their evidence as 
lying not m experience, but m the original constitution of the 
intellect. If therefore, from the laws of space and number, we 
were able to deduce uniformities of any other description, this 
would be conclusive evidence to us that those other uniformi¬ 
ties possessed the same rigorous certainty But this we cannot 
do. Prom laws of space and number alone, nothing can be 
deduced but laws of space and number. 

Of all truths relating to phenomena, the most valuable to 
us are those which relate to the order of their succession. On 
a knowledge of these is founded every reasonable anticipation 
of future facts, and whatever power we possess of influencing 
those facts to our advantage. Even the laws of geometry are 
chiefly of practical importance to us as being a portion of the 
premises from which the Older of the succession of phenomena 
may be mfened. Inasmuch as the motion of bodies, the action 
of forces, and the propagation of influences of all sorts, take 
place m ceitam lines and over definite spaces, the properties 
of those lines and spaces are an important part of the laws 
to which those phenomena are themselves subject Again, 
motions, forces or other influences, and times, are numerable 
quantities, and the properties of number are applicable to 
them as to all other things. But though the laws of number 



362 


INDUCTION. 


and space are important elements m the ascertainment of 
uniformities of succession, they can do nothing towards it 
when taken by them selves. They can only he made instru¬ 
mental to that purpose when we combine with them additional 
premises, expressive of uniformities of succession already known 
By taking, for instance, as piemises these propositions, that 
bodies acted upon by an instantaneous force move with uniform 
velocity m straight lines, that bodies acted upon by a con¬ 
tinuous force move with accelerated velocity m straight lines ; 
and that bodies acted upon by two forces m different directions 
move m the diagonal of a parallelogram, whose sides represent 
the dnection and quantity of those forces, we may by com¬ 
bining these truths with propositions relating to the properties 
of straight lines and of parallelograms, (as that a triangle is 
half a parallelogram of the same base and altitude,) deduce 
another important uniformity of succession, viz , that a body 
moving round a centre of force describes areas propoitional to 
the times. But unless there had been laws of succession m 
our premises, there could have been no truths of succession m 
our conclusions A simrlar remaik might be extended to every 
other class of phenomena leally peculiar, and, had it been 
attended to, would have prevented many chimerical attempts 
at demonstrations of the indemonstrable, and explanations 
which do not explain. 

It is not, therefore, enough for us that the laws of space, 
which are only laws of simultaneous phenomena, and the laws 
of number, which though true of successive phenomena do not 
relate to their succession, possess the ngoious certainty and 
universality of which we are m search We must endeavour 
to find some law of succession wdiich has those same attributes, 
and is therefore fit to be made the foundation of processes for 
discovering, and of a test for verifying, all other uniformities 
of succession This fundamental law must resemble the truths 
of geometry m their most remarkable peculiarity, that'of never 
being, in any instance whatever, defeated or suspended by any 
change of circumstances. 

Now among all those uniformities m the succession of 
phenomena, which common observation is sufficient to bring 



LAW OF CAUSATION. 


363 


to light, there are very few which have any, even apparent, 
pretension to this ngoious mdefeasibility. and of those few, 
one only has been found capable of completely sustaining it. 
In that one, however, we recognise a law which is umveisal 
also m another sense, it is coextensive with the entne field of 
successive phenomena, all instances whatever of succession 
being examples of it This law is the Law of Causation 
The truth that every fact which has a beginning has a cause, 
is coextensive with human experience 

This generalization may appear to some minds not to 
amount to much, since after all it asserts only this. “ it is a 
law, that eveiy event depends on some law.” cc it is a law, 
that there is a law for everything” We must not, however, 
conclude that the geneiahty of the principle is merely veibal, 
it will be found on inspection to be no vague 01 unmeaning 
assertion, but a most important and really fundamental tiuth 

§ 2 . The notion of Cause being the loot of the whole 
theory of Induction, it is indispensable that this idea should, 
at the very outset of our inquiry, be, with the utmost prac¬ 
ticable degree of precision, fixed and determined. If, indeed, 
it were necessary for the purpose of inductive logic that the 
strife should be quelled, which has so long raged among the 
different schools of metaphysicians, respecting the ongm and 
analysis of our idea of causation ; the promulgation, or at least 
the general reception, of a true theory of induction, might be 
considered desperate for a long time to come But the 
science of the Investigation of Truth by means of Evidence 
is happily independent of many of the controversies whict 
perplex the science of the ultimate constitution of the humar 
mind, and is under no necessity of pushing the analysis o 
mental phenomena to that extreme limit which alone ought t< 
satisfy a metaphysician 

I premise, then, that when in the course of this inquiry 
speak of the cause of any phenomenon, I do not mean a causi 
which is not itself a phenomenon, I make no research into th 
ultimate or ontological cause of anything. To adopt a dis 
tmction familiar m the writings ,of the Scotch metaphysicians 



364 


INDUCTION. 


and especially of Keid, the causes with which I concern myself 
are not efficient, hut physical causes. They are causes m 
that sense alone, m which one physical fact is said to he the 
cause of another. Of the efficient causes of phenomena, or 
whether any such causes exist at all, I am not called upon 
to give an opinion The notion of causation is deemed, by 
the schools of metaphysics most m vogue at the piesent 
moment, to imply a mysteuous and most powerful tie, such 
as cannot, or at least does not, exist between any physical 
fact and that other physical fact on which it is invariably 
consequent, and which is popularly termed its cause. and 
thence is deduced the supposed necessity of ascending higher, 
into the essences and inherent constitution of things, to find 
the true cause, the cause which is not only followed by, but 
actually produces, the effect. No such necessity exists for 
the purposes of the present inquiry, nor will any such doctrine 
be found m the following pages The only notion of a cause, 
which the theory of induction requires, is such a notion as 
can be gained from expenence. The Law of Causation, the 
recognition of which is the mam pillar of inductive science, is 
but the familiar tiuth, that invariability of succession is found 
by observation to obtain between eveiy fact m nature and 
some other fact which has pieceded it, independently of all 
consideration respecting the ultimate mode of production of 
phenomena, and of every other question regarding the natuie 
of “ Things m themselves/’ 

Between the phenomena, then, which exist at any instant, 
and the phenomena which exist at the succeeding instant, 
these is an invariable order of succession, and, as we said 
m spiking of the general uniformity of the couise of nature, 
this vfeb is composed of sepaiate fibres, this collective order 
is made up of particular sequences, obtaining invariably 
among the separate parts To certain facts, certain facts 
always do, and, as we believe, will continue to, succeed The 
invariable antecedent is termed the cause; the invariable con¬ 
sequent, the effect. And the universality of the law of causa¬ 
tion consists m this, that every consequent is connected m 
this manner with some particular antecedent, or set of ante- 



1 


LAW OF CAUSATION. 365 

cedents. Let the fact be what it may, if it has begun to exist, 
it was preceded by some fact or facts, with which it is in¬ 
variably connected For every event there exists some com¬ 
bination of objects or events, some given concurrence of cir¬ 
cumstances, positive and negative, the occurrence of which 
is always followed by that phenomenon. We may not have 
found out what this concurrence of circumstances may be, but 
we never doubt that theie is such a one, and that it never 
occms without having the phenomenon m question as its effect 
or consequence On the universality of this truth depends 
the possibility of reducing the inductive process to rules The 
undoubted assurance we have that theie is a law to be found 
if we only knew how to find it, will be seen presently to be 
the source from which the canons of the Inductive Logic 
derive their validity. 

§ 3 It is seldom, if ever, between a consequent and a 
single antecedent, that this invariable sequence subsists. It 
is usually between a consequent and the sum of several ante¬ 
cedents , the concurrence of all of them being requisite to 
produce, that is, to be certain of being followed by, the con¬ 
sequent In such cases it is very common to single out one 
only of the antecedents under the denomination of Cause, 
calling the others merely Conditions. Thus, if a person eats 
of a paiticular dish, and dies m consequence, that is, would 
not have died if he had not eaten of it, people would be apt 
to say that eating of that dish was the cause of his death 
There needs not, however, be any invariable connexion between 
eating of the dish and death, but there certainly is, among 
the circumstances which took place, some combination or other 
on which death is invariably consequent * as, for instance, the 
act of eating of the dish, combined with a particular bodily 
constitution, a paiticular state of present health, and perhaps 
even a certain state of the atmosphere, the whole of which 
circumstances perhaps constituted m this particular case the 
conditions of the phenomenon, or, in other words, the set of 
antecedents which determined it, and but for which it would 
not have happened. The real Cause, is the whole o'f these 



i66 


INDUCTION. 


atecedents; and we have, philosophically speaking, no right 
o give the name of cause to one of them, exclusively of the 
ithers. What, in the case we have supposed, disguises the 
ncoirectness of the expression, is this that the various coa¬ 
litions, except the single one of eating the food, were not 
'vents (that is, instantaneous changes, or successions of mstan- 
,aneous changes) hut states, possessing more or less of per- 
nanency; and might therefore have preceded the effect by 
tn id definite length of duration, for want of the event which 
vas requisite to complete the required concurrence of con- 
htions while as soon as that event, eating the food, occurs, 
10 other cause is waited for, but the effect begins imme- 
liately to take place and hence the appearance is piesented 
>f a more immediate and close connexion between the effect 
md that one antecedent, than between the effect and the 
emainmg conditions. But though we may think proper to 
jive the name of cause to that one condition, the fulfilment 
)f which completes the tale, and brings about the effect with* 
mt further delay, this condition has really no closer 1 elation 
,o the effect than any of the other conditions has. The pio- 
luction of the consequent required that they should all exist 
mmediately previous, though not that they should all begin 
,o exist immediately previous The statement of the cause is 
ncomplete, unless m some shape or other we introduce all the 
jonditions A man takes meicury, goes out of doors, and 
latches cold We say, perhaps, that the cause of his taking 
3 old was exposure to the air. It is clear, however, that his 
laving taken meicury may have been a necessary condition of 
matching cold, and though it might consist with usage to say 
that the cause of his attack was exposure to the air, to be 
accurate we ought to say that the cause was exposure to the 
air while under the effect of mercury 

If we do not, when aiming at accuracy, enumerate all the 
conditions, it is only because some of them will m most cases 
be understood without being expressed, or because for the 
puipose m view they may without detument be overlooked. 
For example, when we say, the cause of a mans death was 



LAW OF CAUSATION. 


367 


that his foot slipped m climbing a ladder, we omit as a thing 
unnecessary to he stated the circumstance of his weight, 
though quite as indispensable a condition of the effect which 
took place. When we say that the assent of the crown to a 
hill makes it law, we mean that the assent, being never given 
until all the othei conditions are fulfilled, makes up the sum 
of the conditions, though no one now regards it as the prin¬ 
cipal one When the decision of a legislative assembly has 
been determined by the casting vote of the chairman, we 
sometimes say that this one person was the cause of all the 
effects which resulted from the enactment Yet we do not 
really suppose that his single vote contributed more to the 
result than that of any other person who voted m the affirma¬ 
tive , but, foi the purpose we have m view, which is to insist 
on his individual responsibility, the part which any other 
person had m the transaction is not material 

In all these instances the fact which was dignified with the 
name of cause, was the one condition which came last into 
existence. But it must not be supposed that m the employ¬ 
ment of the term this or any other rule is always adhered to. 
Nothing can better show the absence of any scientific ground 
for the distinction between the cause of a phenomenon and 
its conditions, than the capricious manner m which we select 
from among the conditions that which we choose to deno¬ 
minate the cause. Howevei numerous the conditions maybe, 
there is hardly any of them which may not, according to 
the purpose of oui immediate discourse, obtain that nominal 
pre-eminence This will be seen by analysing the conditions 
of some one familiar phenomenon Bor example, a stone 
thrown into water falls to the bottom. What are the condi¬ 
tions of this event ? In the first place there must be a stone, 
and water, and the stone must be thrown into the water, but 
these suppositions forming part of the enunciation of the 
phenomenon itself, to include them also among the conditions 
would be a vicious tautology, and this class of conditions, 
therefore, have never received the name of cause fiom any but 
the Aiistotelians, by whom they were called the material cause. 



368 


INDUCTION. 


causa matenalis. The next condition is, there must be an 
earth.; and accordingly it is often said, that the fall of a stone 
is caused by the earth, or by a power or property of the 
earth, or a force exerted by the earth, all of which are merely 
roundabout ways of saying that it is caused by the earth, 
or, lastly, the earth’s attraction ; which also is only a technical 
mode of saying that the earth causes the motion, with the 
additional particulanty that the motion is towards the earth, 
which is not a character of the cause, but of the effect. Let 
us now pass to another condition It is not enough that the 
earth should exist; the body must be within that distance 
from it, m which the earth's attraction preponderates over 
that of any other body. Accordingly we may say, and the 
expression would be confessedly correct, that the cause of the 
stone’s falling is its being within the sphere of the earth’s 
attraction We proceed to a further condition. The stone is 
immersed m water it is therefore a condition of its reaching 
the ground, that its specific gravity exceed that of the sur¬ 
rounding fluid, or m other words that it surpass m weight 
an equal volume of water Accordingly any one would be 
acknowledged to speak correctly who said, that the cause of 
the stone’s going to the bottom is its exceeding m specific 
gravity the fluid m which it is immersed. 

Thus we see that each and every condition of the pheno¬ 
menon may be taken m its turn, and, with equal propriety m 
common parlance, but with equal impropriety m scientific dis¬ 
course, may be spoken of as if it were the entire cause And 
in practice, that particular condition is usually styled the cause, 
whose share m the matter is superficially the most conspi¬ 
cuous, or whose requisiteness to the production of the effect 
we happen to be insisting on at the moment So great is the 
force of this last consideration, that it sometimes induces us 
to give the name of cause even to one of the negative condi¬ 
tions. We say, for example. The army was surprised because 
the sentinel was off his post. But since the sentinel’s absence 
was not what created the enemy, or put the soldiers asleep, 
how did it cause them to be surprised ? All that is really 
meant is, that the event would not have happened if he had 



LAW OF CAUSATION. 


869 


been at his duty. His being off his post was no producing 
cause, but the mere absence of a preventing cause it was 
simply equivalent to his non-existence From nothing, from 
a mere negation, no consequences can proceed. All effects are 
connected, by the law of causation, with some set of positive 
conditions, negative ones, it is tiue, being almost always 
requned m addition In other words, every fact or phenome¬ 
non which has a beginning, mvanably arises when some ceitam 
combination of positive facts exists, provided certain other 
positive facts do not exist. 

There is, no doubt, a tendency (which our first example, 
that of death fiom taking a particular food, sufficiently illus¬ 
trates) to associate the idea of causation with the pioximate 
antecedent eient, rather than with any of the antecedent states , 
01 permanent facts, which may happen also to be conditions 
of the phenomenon, the reason being that the event not only 
exists, but begins to exist immediately previous, while the 
other conditions may have pre-existed for an indefinite time. 
And this tendency shows itself very visibly m the diffeient 
logical fictions which are lesorted to, even by men of science, 
to avoid the necessity of giving the name of cause to anything 
which had existed for an indeterminate length of time before 
the effect Thus, rather than say that the eaith causes the fall 
of bodies, they ascnbe it to a force exeited by the earth, or an 
attraction by the earth, abstractions which they can represent 
to themselves as exhausted by each effoit, and theiefoie con¬ 
stituting at each successive instant a fresh fact, simultaneous 
with, or only immediately preceding, the effect Inasmuch as 
the coming of the circumstance which completes the assemblage 
of conditions, is a change or event, it thence happens that an 
event is always the antecedent m closest apparent proximity 
to the consequent and this may account foi the illusion which 
disposes us to look upon the proximate event as standing more 
peouhaily m the position of a cause than any of the antecedent 
states. But even this peculiarity, of being in closei proximity 
to the effect than any other of its conditions, is, as we have 
already seen, far from being necessary to the common notion 
of a cause; with which notion, on the contrary, any one of the 
vol. i. 24 



370 


INDUCTION. 


conditions, either positive or negative, is found, on occasion, 
completely to accord * 

, The cause, then, .philosophically speaking, is the sum total 
of the conditions, 'positive and negative taken together, the 
whole of the contingencies of every description, which being 
realized, the consequent invariably follows. The negative 


* The assertion, that any and every one of the conditions of a phenomenon 
may b§ and is, on some occasions and for some purposes, spoken of as the 
cause, has been disputed by an intelligent reviewer of this work; m the Prospec¬ 
tive Review (the predecessor of the justly esteemed National Review), who main¬ 
tains that “we always apply the word cause rather to that element in the ante¬ 
cedents which exercises force, and which would tend at all times to produce the 
same or a similar effect to that which, under certain conditions, it would actually 
produce ” And he says, that ff every one would feel” the expression, that the 
cause of a surpnse was the sentinel’s being off his post, to be incorrect, but 
that the “ allurement or foice which drew him off his post, might be so called, 
because in doing so it removed a resisting power which would have prevented 
the surprise ” I cannot think that it would be wrong to say, that the event 
took place because the sentinel -was absent, and yet right to say that it took 
place because he was bribed to be absent Since the only direct effect of the 
bnbe was his absence, the bribe could be called the 1 emote cause of the surprise, 
only on the supposition that the absence was the proximate cause, Dor does it 
seem to me that any one (who had not a theory to support) would use the one 
expression and ieject the other 

The reviewer observes, that when a person dies of poison, his possession of 
bodily organs is a necessaiy condition, but that no one would ever speak of it 
as the cause I admit the fact, but I believe the reason to be, that the occa¬ 
sion could never arise for so speaking of it, for when in the inaccuracy of com¬ 
mon discourse weaie led to speak of some one condition of a phenomenon as its 
cause, the condition so spoken of is always one which it is at least possible that 
the hearer may requite to be informed of The possession of bodily organs is a 
known condition, and to give that as the answer, when asked the cause of a per¬ 
son’s death, would not supply the information sought Once conceive that a 
doubt could exist as to his having bodily organs, or that he were to be compared 
with some being who had them not, and cases may be imagined m which it might 
be said that his possession of them was the cause of his death If Faust and 
Mephistopbeles together took poison, it might be said that Faust died because 
he was a human being, and had a body, while Mephistopheles survived because 
he was a spmt 

It is for the same reason that no one (as the reviewer remarks) “ calls the 
cause of a leap, the muscles or sinews of the body, though they are necessary 
conditions , nor the cause of a self-sacilfice, the knowledge which was necessary 
for it, nor the cause of writing a book, that a man has time foi it, which is a 
necessary condition.” These conditions (besides that they are antecedent states, 
and not proximate antecedent events, and are therefore nevei the conditions m 



LAW OF CAUSATION. 


Ml 


conditions, however, of any phenomenon, a special enumeration 
of which would generally be very prolix, may be all summed 
up under one head, namely, the absence of preventing 01 coun¬ 
teracting causes. The convenience of this mode of expression 
is mainly grounded on the fact, that the effects of any cause m 
counteracting another cause may m most cases be, with strict 
scientific exactness, regarded as a mere extension of its own 
proper and separate effects If gravity retards the upward 
motion of a piojectile, and deflects it into a parabolic trajectory, 
it produces, m so doing, the very same kind of effect, and even 


closest apparent proximity to the effect) are all of them so obviously implied, 
that it is haidly possible there should exist that necessity for insisting on them, 
which alone gives occasion [for speaking of a single condition as if it were the 
cause Wherever this necessity exists in regard to some one condition, and does 
not exist in regard to any othei, I conceive that it is consistent with usage, when 
scientific accuracy is not aimed at, to apply the name cause to that one condi¬ 
tion If the only condition which can be supposed to be unknown is a nega¬ 
tive condition, the negative condition may be spoken of as the cause It might 
be said that a person died for want of medical advice though this would not 
be likely to be said, unless the peison was already understood to be ill, and 
m oidei to indicate that this negative circumstance was what made the illness 
fatal, and not the weakness of his constitution, or the original vnulence of the 
disease It might be said that a person was drowned because he could not 
swim , the positive condition, namely, that he fell into the water, being already 
implied m the word drowned And here let me remark, that his falling into the 
water is m this case the only positive condition all the conditions not expressly 
or virtually included m this (as that he could not swim, that nobody helped 
him, and so forth) are negative Yet, if it were simply said that the cause 
of a man’s death was falling into the water, there would be quite as gieat a 
sense of impropiiety m the expression, as there would be if it were said that the 
cause was his inability to swim , because, though the one condition is positive 
and the other negative, it would he felt thatneithei of them was sufficient, with¬ 
out the other, to produce death. 

With regard to the assertion that nothing is termed the cause, except the 
element which exerts active force; I wave the question as to the meaning of 
active force, and accepting the phrase m its populai sense, 1 1 evert to a former 
example, and I ask, would it be more agreeable to custom to say that a man 
fell because his foot slipped m climbing a ladder, or that he fell because of his 
weight * for his weight, and not the motion of his foot, was the active force 
which determined his fall If a person walking out m a frosty day, stumbled 
and fell, it might be said that he stumbled because the ground was slippery, or 
because he was not sufficiently careful, but few people, I suppose, would say, 
that he stumbled because he walked Y et the only active force concerned was 
that which he exeited m walking the others were mere negative conditions , 

24 —2 



m 


INDUCTION". 


(as mathematicians know) the same quantity of effect, as it 
does m its oidmary operation of causing the fall of bodies 
when simply deprived of their support. If an alkaline solution 
mixed with an acid destioys its sourness, and prevents it from 
reddening vegetable blues, it is because the specific effect of 
the alkali is to combine with the acid, and form a compound 
with totally diffeient qualities. Thispioperty, which causes of 
all descuptions possess, of preventing the effects of other 
causes by vntue (for the most part) of the same laws according 
to which they produce their own,* enables us, by establishing 

but they happened to be the only ones which theie could be any necessity to 
state , foi he walked, most likely, m exactly his usual manner, and the negative 
conditions made all the difference Again, if a person were asked why the army 
of Xerxes defeated that of Leonidas, he would piobably say, because they were 
a thousand times the number , but I do not think he would say, it was because 
they fought, though that was the element of active force To borrow another 
example, used by Mr Grove and by Mr Baden Powell, the opening of floodgates 
is said to be the cause of the flow of water , yet the active force is exerted 
by the water itself, and opening the floodgates merely supplies a negative 
condition The reviewer adds, “theie are some conditions absolutely passive, 
and yet absolutely necessary to physical phenomena, viz the xelations of space 
and time, and to these no one ever applies the word cause without being 
immediately anested by those who heai him ” Even fiom this statement I 
am compelled to dissent Few persons would feel it incongruous to say (for 
example) that a secret became known because it was spoken of when A B was 
within hearing, which is a condition of space or that the cause why one of 
two particular trees is taller than the other, is that it haB been longer planted, 
which is a condition of time 

* There aie a few exceptions , for there aie some properties of objects which 
seem to be puiely preventive , as the property of opaque bodies, by which 
they intercept the passage of light This, as far as we aie able to understand 
it, appears an instant e not of one cause counteracting another by the same law 
wheieby it pioduces its own effects, but of an agency which manifests itself m 
no other way than m defeating the effects of another agency If we knew on 
what other relations to light, or on what peculianties of structuie, opacity de¬ 
pends, we might find that this is only an apparent, not a real, exception to the 
geneial pioposition in the text In any case it needs not affect the piactical 
application The formula which includes all the negative conditions of an 
effect in the single one of the absence of counteiacting causes, is not violated 
by such cases as this, though, if all counteracting agencies were of this descrip¬ 
tion, there would be no puipose served by employing the formula, since we 
should still have to enumerate specially the negative conditions of each pheno¬ 
menon, instead of regarding them as implicitly contained in the positive laws of 
the vanous other agencies m nature. 



hAW OF CAUSATION. 


373 


the general axiom that all causes aie liable to he counteracted 
m their effects by one another, to dispense with the consideration 
of negative conditions entirely, and limit the notion of cause 
to the assemblage of the positive conditions of the phenomenon . 
one negative condition invariably undeistood, and the same m 
all instances (namely, the absence of counteracting causes) 
being sufficient, along with the sum of the positive conditions, 
to make up the whole set of cncumstances on which the phe¬ 
nomenon is dependent. 

§ 4 . Among the positive conditions, as we have seen that 
there are some to which, m common pailance, the term cause 
is more readily and frequently awarded, so there are others to 
which it is, m ordinary cncumstances, refused In most cases 
of causation a distinction is commonly di awn between some¬ 
thing which acts, and some other thing which is acted upon, 
between an agent and a patient Both of these, it would be 
universally allowed, are conditions of the phenomenon, but it 
would be thought absuid to call the latter the cause, that title 
being reserved for the former The distinction, howevei, 
vanishes on examination, or rather is found to he only verbal, 
arising from an incident of mere expression, namely, that the 
object said to be acted upon, and which is considered as the scene 
m which the effect takes place, is commonly included m the 
phrase by which the effect is spoken of, so that if it were also 
reckoned as part of the cause, the seeming mcongiuity would 
arise of its being supposed to cause itself. In the instance 
which we have already had, of falling bodies, the question was 
thus put What is the cause which makes a stone fall 0 and 
if the answer had been “the stone itself/' the expression 
would have been m apparent contiadiction to the meaning of 
the word cause. The stone, therefore, is conceived as the 
patient, and the eaith (or, according to the common and 
most unphilosophical practice, some occult quality of the 
earth) is represented as the agent or cause. But that there is 
nothing fundamental m the distinction may he seen from this, 
that it is quite possible to conceive the stone as causing its 
own fall, provided the language employed be such as to save 



374 


INDUCTION. 


the mere verbal incongruity. We might say that the stone 
moves towards the earth by the properties of the matter com¬ 
posing it, and according to this mode of presenting the 
phenomenon, the stone itself might without impropriety be 
called the agent, though, to save the established doctrine 
of the inactivity of matter, men usually piefer heie also to 
ascribe the effect to an occult quality, and say that the cause 
is not the stone itself, but the weight or gravitation of the 
stone 

Those who have contended for a radical distinction be¬ 
tween agent and patient, have generally conceived the agent 
as that which causes some state of, 01 some change m the 
state of, another object which is called the patient. But 
a little reflection will show that the licence we assume of 
speaking of phenomena as states of the various objects which 
take part m them, (an artifice of which so much use has been 
made by some philosophers, Brown m particular, for the appa¬ 
rent explanation of phenomena,) is simply a soit of logical 
fiction, useful sometimes as one among several modes of 
expression, but which should never be supposed to be the 
enunciation of a scientific truth Even those attributes of 
an object which might seem with greatest propriety to be 
called states of the object itself, its sensible qualities, its 
colour, hardness, shape, and the like, are m .reality (as no 
one has pointed out more cleailv than Brown himself) 
phenomena of causation, m which the substance is distinctly 
the agent, or producing cause, the patient being our own 
oigans, and those of other sentient beings. What we _eall 
states of objects, are always sequences into which the 
objects enter, generally as antecedents or causes, and things 
are never more active than m the production of those phe¬ 
nomena m which they are said to be acted upon Thus, 
m the example of a stone falling to the earth, according to 
the theory of gravitation the stone is as much an agent as 
the earth, which not only attracts, but is itself atti acted by, 
the stone In the case of a sensation produced m our organs, 
the laws of our organization, and even those of our minds, are 
as directly operative m determining the effect produced, as the 



LAW OF CAUSATION. 


875 


laws of the outward object. Though we call prussic acid the 
agent of a person’s death, the whole of the vital and organic 
properties of the patient are as actively instrumental as the 
,poison, m the chain of effects which so rapidly terminates his 
sentient existence. In the process of education, we may 
call the teacher the agent, and the scholar only the material 
acted upon , yet m truth all the facts which pre-existed m ' 
the scholar’s mind exert either co-operating or counteracting 
agencies m relation to the teacher’s efforts. It is not light 
alone which is the agent in vision, but light coupled with the 
active properties of the eye and bi am, and with those of the 
visible object The distinction between agept and patient" is 
merely verbal': patients aie always agents, in a great pro¬ 
portion, indeed, of all natural phenomena, they are so to 
such a degree as to react forcibly on the causes which acted 
upon them and even when this is not the case, they con¬ 
tribute, m the same manner as any of the other conditions, to 
the production of the effect of winch they aie vulgarly tieated s 
as the mere theatre All the positive conditions of a phe¬ 
nomenon are alike agents, alike active , and m any expression 
of the cause which professes to be complete, none of them can 
with reason be excluded, except such as have already been 
implied m the words used for describing the effect, nor by 
including even these would there be incurred any but a merely 
verbal impropriety. 

§ 5 . It now remains to advert to a distinction which is of 
first-rate importance both for clearing up the notion of cause, 
and for obviating a very specious objection often made against 
the view which we have taken of the subject. 

When we define the cause of anything (m the only sense 
in which the present inquiry has any concern with causes) to 
be the antecedent which it invariably follows,” we do not use 
this phrase as exactly synonymous with “ the antecedent which 
it invariably has followed in our past experience ” Such a 
mode of conceiving causation would be liable to the objection 
very plausibly urged by Dr. Reid, namely, that according to 
this doctrine night must be the cause of day, and day the 



876 


INDUCTION. 


cause of night; since these phenomena have invariably 
succeeded one another from the beginning of the world 
But it is necessary to our using the word cause, that we 
should believe not only that the antecedent always has 
been followed by the consequent, but that, as long as the 
present constitution of things* enduies, it always will be so. 
And this would not he true of day and night. We do not 
believe that night will be followed by day under all imagi¬ 
nable circumstances, but only that it will be so provided the 
sun rises above the horizon If the sun ceased to rise, which, 
for aught we know, may be perfectly compatible with the 
general laws of matter, night would be, 01 might be, eternal. 
On the other hand, if the sun is above the horizon, his light 
not extinct, and no opaque body between us and him, we 
believe firmly that unless a change takes place m the pro¬ 
pel ties of matter, this combination of antecedents will be 
followed by the consequent, day, that if the combination of 
antecedents could be indefinitely prolonged, it would be 
always day , and that if the same combination had always 
existed, it would always have been day, quite independently 
of night as a previous condition. Therefoie is it that we do 
not call night the cause, nor even a condition, of day. The 
existence of the sun (or some such luminous body), and there 
being no opaque medium m a straight lmef between that 
body and the part of the earth where we are situated, are the 
sole conditions, and the union of these, without the addition 
of any superfluous circumstance, constitutes the cause. This 
is what writers mean when they say that the notion of cause 


* I mean by this expression, the ultimate laws of nature (whatever they 
may be) as distinguished from the derivative laws and from the collocations. 
The diurnal 1 evolution of the earth (for example) is not a part of the constitu¬ 
tion of things, because nothing can be so called which might possibly be termi¬ 
nated or altered by natural causes. 

t I use the woids “ straight line*’ for brevity and simplicity In reality 
the line in question is not exactly straight, for, from the effect of refraction, 
we actually see the sun for a short interval during which the opaque mass of 
the earth is interposed m a direct line between the sun and our eyes, thus 
realizing, though but to a limited extent, the coveted desideratum of seeing 
lound a comei. 



LAW OF CAUSATION. 


377 


involves the idea of necessity. If there he any meaning 
■which confessedly belongs to the term necessity, it is uncon- 
ditionalness That which is necessary, that which must be, 
means that which will be, whatever supposition we may make 
m regard to all other things. The succession of day and night 
evidently is not necessary m this sense. It is conditional on 
the occuirence of other antecedents That which will be 
followed by a given consequent when, and only when, some 
third circumstance also exists, is not the cause, even though 
no case should ever have occurred m which the phenomenon 
took place without it. 

Invanable sequence, therefore, is not synonymous with 
causation, unless the sequence, besides being invariable, is 
unconditional. There are sequences, as uniform m past 
expenence as any others whatever, which yet we do not re¬ 
gard as cases of causation, but as conjunctions m some sort 
accidental. Such, to an accurate thinker, is that of day and 
night. The one might have existed for any length of time, 
and the other not have followed the sooner for its existence, 
it follows only if certain other antecedents exist, and where 
those antecedents existed, it would follow m any case, No 
one, probably, ever called night the cause of day, mankind 
must so soon have arrived at the very obvious generalization, 
that the state of general illumination which we call day would 
follow from the presence of a sufficiently luminous body, 
whethei darkness had preceded or not 

We may define, therefore, the cause of a phenomenon, to 
be the antecedent, or the concurrence of antecedents, on 
which it is .invariably and unconditionally consequent. Or if 
we adopt the convenient modification of the meaning of the 
word cause, which confines it to the assemblage of positive 
conditions without the negative, then instead of “ uncon¬ 
ditionally, n we must say, “ subject to no other than negative 
conditions.” 

To some it may appear, that the sequence between night 
and day being invariable m our experience, we have as much 
ground m this case as experience can give m any case, for 
recognising the two phenomena as cause and effect, and that 



378 


INDUCTION. 


to say that more is necessary—to require a belief that the 
succession is unconditional, or m other words that it would 
be invariable under all changes of circumstances, is to acknow¬ 
ledge m causation an element of belief not denved from 
experience. The answer to this is, that it is experience itself 
which teaches us that one uniformity of sequence is con¬ 
ditional and another unconditional. When we judge that the 
succession of night and day is a derivative sequence, depending 
on something else, we proceed on grounds of experience. It 
is the evidence of experience which convinces us that day 
could equally exist without being followed by night, and that 
night could equally exist without being followed by day To 
say that these beliefs are “ not generated by our meie obser¬ 
vation of sequence/’* is to forget that twice m every twenty- 
four hours, when the sky is clear, we have an expenmen- 
twm crucis that the cause of day is the sun. We have an 
experimental knowledge of the sun which justifies us on 
experimental grounds m concluding, that if the sun were 
always above the horizon there would be day, though there 
had been no night, and that if the sun were always below the 
horizon there would be night, though there had been no day. 
We thus know from experience that the succession of night 
and day is not unconditional Let me add, that the antece¬ 
dent which is only conditionally invariable, is not the inva¬ 
riable antecedent. Though a fact may, m experience, have 
always been followed by another fact, yet if the remainder of 
our experience teaches us that it might not always be so 
followed, or if the experience itself is such as leaves room for 
a possibility that the known cases may not correctly represent 
all possible cases, the hitherto invariable antecedent is not 
accounted the cause; but why ? Because we are not sure that 
it is the invariable antecedent 

Such cases of sequence as that of day and night not only 
do not contradict the doctrine which resolves causation into 
invariable sequence, but are necessarily implied m that 
doetime. It is evident, that from a limited number of uncon- 


Second Burnett Pnze Essay, by Principal Tullocb, p 25 



LAW OF CAUSATION. 


37S 


ditional sequences, there will result a much greater number oj 
conditional ones. Certain causes being given, that is, certain 
antecedents which are unconditionally followed by certain 
consequents, the mere coexistence of these causes will give 
rise to an unlimited number of additional uniformities It 
two causes exist together, the effects of both will exist toge¬ 
ther; and if many causes coexist, these causes (by what we 
shall teim hereafter the intermixture of their laws) will give 
rise to new effects, accompanying or succeeding one another m 
some particular order, which order will be invariable while 
the causes continue to coexist, but no longer The motion of 
the earth m a given oibit round the sun, is a senes of 
changes which follow one another as antecedents and conse¬ 
quents, and will continue to do so while the sun’s attraction, 
and the force with which the eaith tends to advance m a 
direct line through space, continue to coexist m the same 
quantities as at piesent But vary either of these causes, 
and this particular succession of motions would cease to take 
place. The senes of the earth’s motions, therefore, though 
a case of sequence invariable within the limits of human 
experience, is not a case of causation It is not uncon¬ 
ditional 

This distinction between the relations of succession which 
so far as we know are unconditional, and those relations, 
whether of succession or of coexistence, which, like the earth’s 
motions, or the succession of day and night, depend on the 
existence or on the coexistence of other antecedent facts— 
corresponds to the great division which Dr. Whewell and 
other wnteis have made of the field of science, into the in¬ 
vestigation of what they term the Laws of Phenomena, and 
the investigation of causes , a phraseology, as I conceive, not 
philosophically sustainable, inasmuch as the ascertainment of 
causes, such causes as the human faculties can ascertain, 
namely, causes which are themselves phenomena, is, therefore, 
merely the ascertainment of other and more universal Laws of 
Phenomena And let me here observe, that Dr Whewell, 
and m some degree even Sir John Herschel, seem to have 
misunderstood the meaning of those writers who, like 



380 


INDUCTION. 


M. Comte, limit the sphere of scientific investigation to Laws 
of Phenomena, and speak of the mquiiy into causes as vam 
and futile. The causes which M. Comte designates as inac¬ 
cessible, are efficient causes. The investigation of physical, 
as opposed to efficient, causes (including the study of all the 
active forces in Nature, considered as facts of observation) is 
as important a part of M. Comtes conception of science as of 
Dr. Whewell’s. His objection to the word cause is a mere 
matter of nomenclature, m which, as a matter of nomenclature, 
I consider him to be entirely wrong “ Those,” it is justly 
lemarked by Mr. Bailey,* “who, like M. Comte, object to 
designate events as causes, are objecting without any real 
ground to a mere but extremely convenient generalization, to 
a very useful common name, the employment of which in¬ 
volves, or needs involve, no particular theory.” To which it 
may be added, that by 1 ejecting this form of expression, 
M. Comte leaves himself without any term for maikmg a 
distinction which, however incorrectly expressed, is not only 
real, but is one of the fundamental distinctions m science, 
indeed it is on this alone, as we shall hereafter find, that the 
possibility rests of framing a rigorous Canon of Induction. 
And as things left without a name are apt to be forgotten, a 
Canon of that description is not one of the many benefits 
which the philosophy of Induction has received from M. 
Comte’s great powers. 

§ 6 . Does a cause always stand with its effect m the 
relation of antecedent and consequent ? Do we not often say 
of two simultaneous facts that they are cause and effect—as 
when we say that fire is the cause of warmth, the sun and 
moisture the cause of vegetation, and the like ? Since a cause 
does not necessarily perish because its effect has been pro¬ 
duced, the two things do very generally coexist, and there 
are some appearances, and some common expressions, seeming 
to imply not only that causes may, but that they must, be 
contemporaneous with their effects. Cessante causa cessat et 


Letters on the Philosophy of the Human Mind , First Series, p 219, 



LAW OF CAUSATION. 


381 


etfectus, has been a dogma of the schools: the necessity for 
the continued existence of the cause m older to the continu¬ 
ance of the effect, seems to have been once a generally received 
doctrine Keplers numeious attempts to account for the 
motions of the heavenly bodies on mechanical principles, were 
rendeied abortive by his always supposing that the agency 
which set those bodies m motion must continue to operate m 
order to keep up the motion which it at first produced. Yet 
there were at all times many familiar instances of the continu¬ 
ance of effects, long after their causes had ceased. A coup de 
soleil gives a peison a brain fever will the fever go off as soon 
as he is moved out of the sunshine ? A sword is run thiough 
his body must the swoid remain m his body m order that he 
may continue dead ? A ploughshare once made, remains a 
ploughshare, without any continuance of heating and ham¬ 
mering, and even after the man who heated and hammered it 
has been gathered to his fathers On the other hand, the 
piessure which forces up the meicury in an exhausted tube 
must be continued in order to sustain it m the tube This 
(it may be replied) is because another foice is acting without 
intermission, the force of giavity, which would restore it to 
its level, unless counterpoised by a foice equally constant. 
But again , a tight bandage causes pam, which pam will some¬ 
times go off as soon as the bandage is removed The illumina¬ 
tion which the sun diffuses over the earth ceases when the sun 
goes down 

There is, therefore, a distinction to be drawn. The con¬ 
ditions which aie necessary for the first production of a phe¬ 
nomenon, are occasionally also necessary for its continuance, 
though more commonly its continuance requires no condition 
except negative ones Most things, once produced, continue 
as they aie, until something changes or destroys them, but 
some require the peimanent piesence of the agencies which 
produced them at fiist These may, if we please, he considered 
as instantaneous phenomena, requiring to he renewed at each 
instant by the cause by which they weie at first generated. 
Accoidingly, the illumination of any given point of space 
has always been looked upon as an instantaneous fact, which 



382 


INDUCTION. 


pensbes and is perpetually renewed as long as the necessary 
conditions subsist. If we adopt this language we a\oid the 
necessity of admitting that the continuance of the cause is 
ever required to maintain the effect. We may say, it is not 
required to maintain, hut to reproduce, the effect, or else to 
counteract some force tending to destioy it. And this may be 
a convenient phiaseology But it is only a phraseology The 
fact remains, that m some cases (though these axe a minority) 
the continuance of the conditions which produced an effect is 
necessary to the continuance of the effect. 

As to the ulterior question, whether it is strictly necessary 
that the cause, or assemblage of conditions, should precede, 
by ever so short an instant, the production of the effect, (a 
question raised and argued with much ingenuity by Sir John 
Herschel m an Essay already quoted, # ) the inquiry is of no 
consequence for our piesent purpose. There certainly are 
cases m which the effect follows without any interval per¬ 
ceptible by our faculties. and when there is an interval, we 
cannot tell by how many intermediate links impelceptible to 
us that interval may really be filled up But even gianting 
that an effect may commence simultaneously with its cause, 
the view I have taken of causation is m no way practically 
affected. Whether the cause and its effect he necessanly suc¬ 
cessive or not, the beginning of a phenomenon is what implies 
a cause, and causation is the law of the succession of phe¬ 
nomena. If these axioms be granted, we can afford, though 
I see no necessity for doing so, to drop the words antecedent 
and consequent as applied to cause and effect I have no 
objection to define a cause, the assemblage of phenomena, 
which occurring, some other phenomenon invariably com¬ 
mences, or has its origin Whether the effect coincides m 
point of time with, or immediately follows, the hindmost of its 
conditions, is immaterial. At all events it does not precede 
it, and when we are m doubt, between two coexistent phe¬ 
nomena, which is cause and which effect, we rightly deem the 
question solved if we can ascertain which of them preceded 
the other. 

* Essays, pp. 206-208. 



LAW OF CAUSATION. 


88. 


§ 7 . It continually happens that several different phe 
nomena, which are not in the slightest degree dependent o 
conditional on one another, are found all to depend, as th 
phrase is, on one and the same agent, m other words, om 
and the same phenomenon is seen to he followed by severa 
sorts of effects quite heterogeneous, hut which go on simul 
taneouslyone with another, provided, of course, that all othe 
conditions requisite for each of them also exist Thus, the sui 
produces the celestial motions, it ptoduces daylight, and i 1 
produces heat The earth causes the fall of heavy bodies, anc 
it also, m its capacity of a gLeat magnet, causes the pheno 
mena of the magnetic needle. A crystal of galena causes 
the sensations of hardness, ot weight, of cubical form, of gre) 
colour, and many others between which we can trace no inter¬ 
dependence. The purpose to which the phraseology of Pro¬ 
perties and Powers is specially adapted, is the expression oi 
this sort of cases When the same phenomenon is followed 
(either subject or not to the presence of other conditions) by 
effects of different and dissimilar orders, it is usual to say that 
each different sort of effect is produced by a different property 
of the cause. Thus we distinguish the attractive or gravita- 
live property of the earth, and its magnetic property* the 
giavitative, luminiferous, and calorific properties of the sun * 
the colour, shape, weight, and hardness of a crystal These 
are mere phrases, which explain nothing, and add nothing to 
our knowledge of the subject, but, considered as abstract 
names denoting the connexion between the different effects 
produced and the object which produces them, they are a very 
powerful instrument of abridgment, and of that acceleration of 
the process of thought which abridgment accomplishes. 

This class of considerations leads to a conception which we 
shall find to be of great importance, that of a Permanent 
Cause, or original natural agent. There exist m nature a 
number of permanent causes, which have subsisted ever since 
the human race has been m existence, and for an indefinite 
and piobably an enormous length of time previous The sun, 
the earth, and planets, with their various constituents, air, 
water, and other distinguishable substances, whether simple or 



384 


INDUCTION. 


compound, of which nature is made up, are such Permanent 
Causes These have existed, and the effects or consequences 
which they were fitted to produce have taken place (as often 
as the other conditions of the production met,) from the very 
beginning of our experience But we can give no account of 
the oiigm of the Permanent Causes themselves Why these 
particular natural agents existed ongmally and no others, or 
why they are commingled m such and such proportions, and 
distributed m such and such a manner throughout space, is a 
question we cannot answer Moie than this we can discover 
nothing regular m the distnbution itself, we can ieduce it to 
no uniformity, to no law There are no means by which, from 
the distribution of these causes or agents in one part of space, 
we could conjecture whether a similai distribution prevails m 
another The coexistence, therefore, of Primeval Causes, 
lanks, to us, among meiely casual concurrences and all those 
sequences or coexistences among the effects of seveial such 
causes, which, though invariable while those causes coexist, 
would, if the coexistence terminated, terminate along with it, 
we do not class as cases of causation, or laws of natuie. we 
can only calculate on finding these sequences or coexistences 
where we know by direct evidence, that the natural agents on 
the piopeities of which they ultimately depend, aie distributed 
m the requisite manner These Permanent Causes are not 
always objects, they are sometimes events, that is to say, 
periodical cycles of events, that being the only mode in which 
events can possess the property of permanence. Not only, for 
instance, is the earth itself a peimanent cause, or primitive 
natural agent, hut the earth’s rotation is so too * it is a cause 
which has produced, fiom the eaihest penod, (by the aid of 
other necessary conditions,) the succession of day and night, 
the ebb and flow of the sea, and many other effects, while, as 
we can assign no cause (except conjecturally) for the rotation 
itself, it is entitled to he ranked as a primeval cause It is, 
however, only the origin of the rotation which is mystenous to 
us once begun, its continuance is accounted for by the first 
law of motion (that of the permanence of rectilineal motion 



LAW OF CAUSATION. 385 

once impiessed) combined with the gravitation of the parts of 
the eaith towaids one another. 

All phenomena without exception which begin to exist, 
that is, all except the primeval causes, are effects either im¬ 
mediate or lemote of those primitive facts, or of some combi¬ 
nation of them There is no Thing produced, no event 
happening, m the known univeise, which is not connected 
by an uniformity, or mvanable sequence, with some one or 
moie of the phenomena which preceded it, insomuch that it 
will happen again as often as those phenomena occur again, 
and as no other phenomenon having the character of a coun¬ 
teracting cause shall coexist. These antecedent phenomena, 
again, weie connected m a similar manner with some that 
preceded them, and so on, until we reach, as the ultimate 
step attainable by us, either the properties of some one 
primeval cause, or the conjunction of several. The whole of 
the phenomena of nature weie therefore the necessary, or m 
other words, the unconditional, consequences of some former 
collocation of the Permanent Causes. 

The state of the whole universe at any instant, we believe 
to be the consequence of its state at the previous instant, 
insomuch that one who knew all the agents which exist at the 
present moment, their collocation in space, and all their pio- 
peities, m other words, the laws of their agency, could predict 
the whole subsequent history of the universe, at least unless 
some new volition of a power capable of controlling the 
univeise should supervene * And if any particular state of the 


* To the universality which mankind are agieed m ascribing to the Law of 
Causation, there is one claim of exception, one disputed case, that of the Human 
Will , the determinations of which, a large class of metaphysicians are not 
willing to regard as following the causes called motives, according to as strict 
laws as those which they suppose to exist in the woild of mere matter This 
contioverted point will undergo a special examination when we come to treat 
particularly of the Logic of the Moial Sciences (Book vi ch 2). In the mean 
time I may remaik that these metaphysicians, who, it must be obseived, ground 
the mam part of their objection on the supposed repugnance of the doctrine m 
question to our consciousness, seem to me to mistake the fact which conscious¬ 
ness testifies against What is really m contradiction to consciousness, they 
VOL I. 25 



386 


INDUCTION. 


entire nniveise could ever recur a second time, all subsequent 
states would return too, and history would, like a circulating 
decimal of many figmes, penodically repeat itself 

Jam redit et virgo, redeunt Saturma regna . . . 

Alter exit turn Tiphys, et altera quae vehat Argo 

Delectos heroas , erunt quoque altera bella, 

Atque iterum ad Trojam magnus mittetur Achilles 

And though things do not really revolve m this eternal round, 
the whole series of events m the history of the umveise, past 
and future, is not the less capable, m its own nature, of being 
constiucted a by any one whom we can suppose 

acquainted with the ongmal distribution of all natural agents, 
and with the whole of their properties, that is, the laws of 
succession existing between them and their effects. saving the 
far moie than human powers of combination and calculation 
which would be required, even m one possessing the data, for 
the actual performance of the task 

§ 8. Since everything which occurs is determined by 
laws of causation and collocations of the ongmal causes, it 
follows that the coexistences which are obseivable among 
effects cannot be themselves the subject of any similai set of 
laws, distinct from laws of causation Uniformities there are, 
as well of coexistence as of succession, among effects, but 
these must m all cases be a meie result either of the identity 
or of the coexistence of their causes if the causes did not 
coexist, neither could the effects. And these causes being also 
effects of pnor causes, and these of others, until we reach the 
primeval causes, it follows that (except m the case of effects 
which can be traced immediately or remotely to one and the 

would, I thmk, on strict self-examination, find to be, the application to human 
actions and volitions of the ideas involved m the common use of the term 
Necessity, which I agree with them in objecting to But if they would 
consider that by saying that a person’s actions necessarily follow fiom his 
character, all that is really meant (for no more is meant m any case whatever 
of causation) is that he invariably does act m conformity to his character, and 
that any one who thoroughly knew his chaiacter would certainly predict how 
he would act m any supposable case , they probably would not find this doctrine 
either contrary to their experience or revolting to their feelings And no more 
than this is contended for by any one but an Asiatic fatalist. 



LAW OF CAUSATION. 


387 


same cause) the coexistences of phenomena can m no case be 
universal, unless the coexistences of the pnmeval causes to 
which the effects are ultimately traceable, can be reduced to 
an universal law but we have seen that they cannot Theie 
are, accoidmgly, no oiigmal and independent, in othei words 
no unconditional, uniformities of coexistence, between effects 
of different causes, if they coexist, it is only because the 
causes have casually coexisted The only independent and 
unconditional coexistences which are sufficiently invariable to 
have any claim to the character of laws, aie between different 
and mutuallv independent effects of the same cause, m other 
words, between different properties of the same natural agent. 
This portion of the Laws of Nature will be treated of m the 
latter part of the present Book, under the name of the Specific 
Properties of Kinds 

§ 9 It is piopei m this place to advert to a rather 
ancient doctnne respecting causation, which has been revived 
during the last few }eais in many quarters, and at piesent 
gives more signs of life than any other theory of causation at 
vanance with that set foith m the preceding pages 

According to the theory m question, Mind, 01 , to speak 
more precisely. Will, is the only cause of phenomena. The 
type of Causation, as well as the exclusive source from which 
we derive the idea, is our own voluntary agency. Here, and 
heie only (it is said) we have direct evidence of causation. 
We know that we can move our bodies Respecting the 
phenomena of inanimate nature, we have no other direct 
knowledge than that of antecedence and sequence But in 
the case of our voluntary actions, it is affirmed that we are 
conscious of power, before we have experience of results. An 
act of volition, whether followed by an effect or not, is accom¬ 
panied by a consciousness of effort, “ of force exerted, of power 
m action, which is necessarily causal, or causative ” This 
feeling of energy or foice, inherent in an act of will, is know¬ 
ledge a priori , assurance, prior to expenence, that we have 
the power of causing effects. Volition, therefore, it is 
asserted, is something more than an unconditional antecedent, 

25—2 



388 


INDUCTION'. 


it is a cause, m a different sense from that m winch physical 
phenomena are said to cause one another it is an Efficient 
Cause. Fiom this the transition is easy to the fuither doc- 
tune, that Volition is the sole Efficient Cause of all pheno¬ 
mena “ It is inconceivable that dead force could continue 
unsupported for a moment beyond its creation. We cannot 
even conceive of change 01 phenomena without the eneigy of 
a mind.” “ The word acnon itself, says anothei wntei of 
the same school, “ has no leal significance except when applied 
to the doings of an intelligent agent Let any one conceive, 
if he can, of any powei, eneigy, or force, mheient m a lump 
of matter.” Phenomena may have the semblance of being 
produced by physical causes, but they aie m leality produced, 
say these wnteis, by tbe immediate agency of mind All 
things which do not pioceed fiom a human (01, I suppose, an 
animal) will, pioceed, they say, duectly from divine will 
The earth is not moved by the combination of a centripetal 
and a projectile foice , this is but a mode of speaking, which 
serves to facilitate our conceptions. It is moved by the dnect 
volition of an omnipotent Being, m a path coinciding with 
that which we deduce fiom the hypothesis of these two foices 
As I have so often observed, the geneial question of the 
existence of Efficient Causes does not fall within the limits of 
our subject but a theory which represents them as capable of 
being subjects of human knowledge, and which passes off as 
efficient causes what are only physical or phenomenal causes, 
belongs as much to Logic as to Metaphysics, and is a fit 
subject for discussion here. 

To my appiehension, a volition is not an efficient, but 
simply a physical, cause Oui will causes our bodily actions 
m the same sense, and m no other, m which cold causes ice, 
or a spaik causes an explosion of gunpowdei. The volition, 
a state of our mind, is the antecedent, the motion of our 
limbs m conformity to the volition, is the consequent This 
sequence I conceive to be not a subject of dnect consciousness, 
in the sense intended by the theory. The antecedent, indeed, 
and the consequent, are subjects of consciousness But the 
connexion between them is a subject of expenence. I cannot 



LAW OF CAUSATION 


389 


admit that oui consciousness of the volition contains m itself 
any a pnon knowledge that the muscular motion will follow 
If oui nerves of motion were paralyzed, or our muscles stiff 
and inflexible, and had been so all our lives, I do not see the 
slightest giound for supposing that we should ever (unless by 
information from other people) have known anything of voli¬ 
tion as a physical power, or been conscious of any tendency 
m feelings of our mind to produce motions of our body, or of 
other bodies I will not undeitake to say whether we should 
m that case have had the physical feeling which I suppose is 
meant when these writers speak of “ consciousness of effort 
I see no reason why we should not, since that physical feeling 
is probably a state of nervous sensation beginning and ending 
m the brain, without involving the motory apparatus. but we 
certainly should not have designated it by any term equivalent 
to effort, since effort implies consciously aiming at an end, 
which we should not only m that case have had no reason to 
do, but could not even have had the idea of doing. If conscious 
at all of this peculiai sensation, we should have been conscious 
of it, I conceive, only as a kind of uneasiness, accompanying 
our feelings of desire 

It is well aigued by Sir William Hamilton against the 
theoiy m question, that it “ is iefuted by the consider ation, 
that between the overt fact of corporeal movement of which 
we are cognisant, and the internal act of mental determination 
of which we are also cognisant, there intervenes a numerous 
senes of intermediate agencies of which we have no know¬ 
ledge , and, consequently, that we can have no consciousness 
of any causal connexion between the extreme links of this 
chain, the volition to move and the limb moving, as this 
hypothesis asserts. No one is immediately conscious, for 
example, of moving his arm through his volition Previously 
to this ultimate movement, muscles, nerves, a multitude of 
solid and fluid parts, must be set m motion by the will, but of 
this motion we know, from consciousness, absolutely nothing. 
A person struck with paralysis is conscious of no inability m 
his limb to fulfil the determinations of his will, and it is only 
after having willed, and finding that his limbs do not obey his 



390 


INDUCTION. 


volition, tliat he learns by this experience, that the external 
movement does not follow the internal act. But as the para¬ 
lytic learns after the volition that his limbs do not obey his 
mind , so it is only after volition that the man m health learns, 
that his limbs do obey the mandates of his will!”' 1 * 

Those against whom I am contending have never pro¬ 
duced, and do not pretend to pioduce, any positive evidencef 
that the power of our will to move om bodies would be known 
to us independently of expenence What they have to say 
on the subject is, that the production of physical events by a 
will seems to carry its own explanation with it, while the 
action of matter upon matter seems to require something else 
to explain it, and is even, according to them, “ inconceivable” 


* Lectures on Metaphysics, vol 11 Lect xxxix pp 391-2 
I regret that I cannot invoke the authority of Sir William Hamilton m 
favour of my own opinions on Causation, as I can against the paiticular 
theory which I am now combating But that acute thinker has a theory of 
Causation peculiar to himself, which has never yet, as far as I know, been 
analytically examined, but which, I venture to think, admits of as complete 
refutation as any one of the false or insufficient psychological theories which 
strew the ground m such numbeis under his potent metaphysical scythe 
(Since examined and controverted m the sixteenth chapter of An Examination 
of Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy) 

f 1 Unless we are to consider as such the following statement, by one of the 
writers quoted m the text “ In the case of mental exertion, the result to be 
accomplished is preconsidered or meditated, and is therefoie known d pi ion, 
or before experience ”—(Bowen’s Lowell Lectures on the Application of Meta¬ 
physical and Ethical Science to the Evidence of Religion, Boston, 1849.) This is 
merely saying that when we will a thing we have an idea of it But to have an 
idea of what we wish to happen, does not imply a piophetic knowledge that it 
will happen Perhaps it will be said that the first time we exerted our will, 
when we had of course no experience of any of the powers residing m us, we 
nevertheless must aheady have known that we possessed them, since we cannot 
will that which we do not believe to be m oui power. But the impossibility is 
perhaps m the words only, and not m the facts , for we may desiie what we do 
not know to be m our power , and finding by experience that om bodies move 
according to our desire , we may then, and only then, pass into the more com¬ 
plicated mental state which is termed will. 

After all, even if we had an instinctive knowledge that our actions would 
follow our will, this, as Blown remarks, would prove nothing as to the nature 
of Causation. Our knowing, previous to expenence, that an antecedent will be 
followed by a certain consequent, would not prove the relation between them to 
be anything more than antecedence and consequence. 



LAW OF CAUSATION# 


391 


on any other supposition than that some will intervenes 
between the apparent cause and uts apparent effect They 
thus rest their case on an appeal to the inherent laws of 
our conceptive faculty , mistaking, as I apprehend, for the 
laws of that faculty its acquired habits, grounded on the spon¬ 
taneous tendencies of its uncultured state The succession 
between the will to move a limb and the actual motion, is one 
of the most direct and instantaneous of all sequences which 
come under our observation, and is familiar to every moment's 
experience from our earliest infancy, more familiar than any 
succession of events extenor to our bodies, and especially 
more so than any other case of the apparent origination (as 
distinguished from the mere communication) of motion. Now, 
it is the natural tendency of the mind to be always attempting 
to facilitate its conception of unfamiliar facts by assimilating 
them to others which are familiar Accordingly, our volun¬ 
tary acts, being the most familiar to us of all cases of causa¬ 
tion, are, in the infancy and early youth of the human race, 
spontaneously taken as the type of causation m general, and 
all phenomena are supposed to be directly produced by the 
will of some sentient being This original Fetichism I shall 
not chaiactenze m the words of Hume, or of any follower of 
Hume, but m those of a religious metaphysician, Dr Reid, m 
order more effectually to show the unanimity which exists on 
the subject among all competent thinkers. 

“ When we turn our attention to external objects, and 
begin to exercise our rational faculties about them, we find 
that there are some motions and changes m them which we 
have power to produce, and that there are many which must 
have some other cause. Either the objects must have life and 
active power, as we have, or they must be moved or changed 
by something that has life and active power, as external objects 
are moved by us. 

“ Our first thoughts seem to be, that the objects in which 
we perceive such motion have understanding and active power 
as we have ‘ Savages,’ says the Abbe Raynal, c wherever they 
see motion which they cannot account for, there they suppose 
a soul.’ All men may be considered as savages m this respect, 



89 a 


INDUCTION. 


until they are capable of Distinction, and of using their facul¬ 
ties m a moie perfect manner than savages do. 

“ The Abbe Eaynal’s observation is sufficiently confirmed, 
both from fact, and fiom the structure of all languages 

“ Kude nations do really believe sun, moon, and stars, 
earth, sea, and air, fountains, and lakes, to have understanding 
and active power To pay homage to them, and implore their 
favour, is a kind of ldolatiy natuial to savages 

“ All languages carry m their structuie the marks of their 
being formed when this belief prevailed The distinction of 
verbs and participles into active and passive, which is found m 
all languages, must have been originally intended to distin¬ 
guish what is really active from what is merely passive, and 
m all languages, we find active verbs applied to those objects, 
m which, according to the Abbe EaynaFs observation, savages 
suppose a soul. 

“ Thus we say the sun rises and sets, and comes to the 
meridian, the moon changes, the sea ebbs and flows, the winds 
blow Languages weie formed by men who believed these 
objects to have life and active power m themselves It was 
therefore proper and natuial to express their motions and 
changes by active verbs. 

“Theie is no surer way of tracing the sentiments of nations 
before they have records, than by the structure of their lan¬ 
guage, which, notwithstanding the changes produced m it by 
time, will always retain some signatures of the thoughts of 
those by whom it was invented. When we find the same 
sentiments indicated m the structure of all languages, those 
sentiments must have been common to the human species 
when languages were invented. 

“ When a few, of supenor intellectual abilities, find leisure 
for speculation, they begin to philosophize, and soon discover, 
that many of those objects which at first they believed to be 
intelligent and active are really lifeless and passive. This is 
a very important discovery It elevates the nnnd, emancipates 
from many vulgar superstitions, and invites to further disco¬ 
veries of the same kind 

“ As philosophy advances, life and activity m natural 



LAW OF CAUSATION. 


393 


objects retires, and leaves them dead and inactive Instead of 
moving voluntarily, we find them to be moved necessarily , 
instead of acting, we find them to be acted upon, and Nature 
appears as one great machine, wheie one wheel is turned by 
another, that by a thud, and how far this necessary succes¬ 
sion may reach, the philosopher does not know/’* 

There is, then, a spontaneous tendency of the intellect to 
account to itself for all cases of causation by assimilating them 
to the intentional acts of voluntaiy agents like itself. This is 
the instinctive philosophy of the human mind m its earliest 
stage, befoie it has become familiar with any other invariable 
sequences than those between its own volitions or those of other 
human beings and their voluntaiy acts. As the notion of fixed 
laws of succession among external phenomena gradually 
establishes itself, the propensity to refer all phenomena to volun¬ 
taiy agency slowly gives way befoie it The suggestions, how¬ 
ever, of daily life continuing to be more poweiful than those of 
scientific thought, the original instinctive philosophy maintains 
its ground m the mind, underneath the growths obtained by 
cultivation, and keeps up a constant resistance to their throw- 
mg then loots deep into the soil. The theory against which 
I am contending denves its nourishment from that substratum. 
Its strength does not lie m argument, but m its affinity to an 
obstinate tendency of the infancy of the human mind. 

That this tendency, however, is not the result of an in¬ 
herent mental law, is proved by superabundant evidence 
The history of science, from its eailiest dawn, shows that 
mankind have not been unanimous m thinking either that the 
action of matter upon matter was not conceivable, or that the 
action of mind upon matter was. To some thinkers, and 
some schools of thinkers, both m ancient and m modern times, 
this last has appeared much more inconceivable than the 
former Sequences entirely physical and material, as soon as 
they had become sufficiently familiar to the human mind, came 
to be thought perfectly natural, and were regaided not only as 
needing no explanation themselves, but as being capable of 


* Reid’s Essays on the Active Powei s, Essay iv. ch 3 



394 


INDUCTION. 


affording it to others, and even of seivmg as the ultimate ex¬ 
planation of things m geneial. 

One of the ablest lecent suppoiters of the Volitional 
theory has furnished an explanation, at once histoneally tine 
and philosophically acute, of the failuie of the Gieek philo¬ 
sopher m physical inquiry, m which, as I conceive, he un¬ 
consciously depicts his own state of mind. “ Their stumbling- 
block was one as to the nature of the evidence they had 
to expect for then conviction. . , . They had not seized the 
idea that they must not expect to undeistand the processes 
of outward causes, but only their results and consequently, 
the whole physical philosophy of the Gieeks was an attempt 
to identify mentally the effect with its cause, to feel after 
some not only necessary but natuial connexion, wheie they 
meant by natural that which would per se cairy some pre¬ 
sumption to their own mind . . They wanted to see some 
reason why the physical antecedent should produce this par¬ 
ticular consequent, and then only attempts weie m duections 
where they could find such leasons.”* In other woids, they 
weie not content merely to know that one phenomenon was 
always followed by another, they thought that they had not 
attained the true aim of science, unless they could perceive 
something m the nature of the one phenomenon from which 
it might have been known or piesumed previous to trial that 
it would be followed by the other . just what the writer, who 
has so clearly pointed out then eiror, thinks that he per¬ 
ceives m the nature of the phenomenon Volition And to 
complete the statement of the case, he should have added 
that these eaily speculatois not only made this their aim, 
but were quite satisfied with their success m it, not only 
sought for causes which should carry m their mere statement 
evidence of their efficiency, but fully believed that they had 
found such causes. The reviewei can see plainly that this 
was an eiror, because he does not believe that theie exist 
any lelations between material phenomena which can account 
for their producing one another. but the veiy fact of the per- 


Prospeciive Renew for February 1850. 



LAW OF CAUSATION. 


895 


sistency of the Greeks m this error, shows that their mmds 
were m a very different state : they were able to deuve from 
the assimilation of physical facts to other physical facts, the 
kind of mental satisfaction which we connect with the woid 
explanation, and which the reviewer would have us think can 
only be found m refemng phenomena to a will. When Thales 
and Hippo held that moisture was the universal cause, and 
external element, of which all other things were but the infi¬ 
nitely various sensible manifestations, when Anaximenes 
predicated the same thing of air, Pythagoras of numbers, and 
the like, they all thought that they had found a real expla¬ 
nation , and were content to rest m this explanation as 
ultimate The ordinary sequences of the external universe 
appeared to them, no less than to their critic, to be incon¬ 
ceivable without the supposition of some universal agency to 
connect the antecedents with the consequents , but they did 
not think that Volition, exerted by minds, was the only agency 
which fulfilled this requirement Moisture, or air, or numbers, 
carried to their minds a precisely similar impiession of making 
intelligible what was otherwise inconceivable, and gave the 
same full satisfaction to the demands of their conceptive 
faculty 

It was not the Greeks alone, who ec wanted to see some 
reason why the physical antecedent should pioduce this par¬ 
ticular consequent,” some connexion “ which would per se 
carry some piesumption to their own mind.” Among modem 
philosophers, Leibnitz laid it down as a self-evident principle 
that all physical causes without exception must contain m 
their own nature something which makes it intelligible that 
they should be able to produce the effects which they do 
produce. Far from admitting Volition as the only kind of 
cause which carried internal evidence of its own power, and as 
the real bond of connexion between physical antecedents and 
their consequents, he demanded some naturally and per se 
efficient physical antecedent as the bond of connexion between 
Vohtion itself and its effects He distinctly refused to admit 
the will of God as a sufficient explanation of anything except 
miracles; and insisted upon finding something that would 



396 


INDUCTION”. 


account better foi the phenomena of nature than a mere refe¬ 
rence to divine volition.* 

Again, and conveisely, the action of mind upon matter 
(which, we aie now told, not only needs no explanation itself, 
but is the explanation of all other effects), has appealed to 
some thmkeis to be itself the grand inconceivability It was 
to get over this veiv difficulty that the Cartesians invented the 
system of Occasional Causes They could not conceive that 
thoughts m a mind could produce movements m a body, or 
that bodily movements could produce thoughts They could 
see no necessary connexion, no relation a prion, between a 
motion and a thought And as the Cartesians, moie than any 
other school of philosophical speculation before or since, made 
their own minds the measure of all things, and refused, on 
principle, to believe that Nature had done what they were 
unable to see any leason why she must do, they affirmed it to 
be impossible that a material and a mental fact could be causes 
one of another. They regarded them as meie Occasions on 
which the real agent, God, thought fit to exert his power as a 
Cause. When a man walls to move his foot, it is not his will 
that moves it, but God (they said) moves it on the occasion of 
his will. God, according to this system, is the only efficient 
cause, not qua mind, or qua endowed with volition, but qua 
omnipotent This hypothesis was, as I said, originally sug¬ 
gested by the supposed inconceivability of any real mutual 
action between Mind and Matter. * but it was afterwards 
extended to the action of Mattel upon Matter, for on a nicer 
examination they found this inconceivable too, and therefore, 
according to their logic, impossible The deus ex maehmd 
was ultimately called m to produce a spaik on the occasion of 
a flint and steel coming together, or to break an egg on the 
occasion of its falling on the ground 

All this, undoubtedly, shows that it is the disposition of 
mankind m geneial, not to be satisfied with knowing that one 
fact is invariably antecedent and another consequent, but to look 
out for something which may seem to explain their being so. 
Eut we also see that this demand may be completely satisfied 


* Tide supra, p. 270, note 



LAW OF CAUSATION. 


397 


by an agency puiely physical, piovided it be much more familiar 
than that which it is invoked to explain To Thales and 
Anaximenes, it appeared inconceivable that the antecedents 
which we see m nature, should produce the consequents, but 
peifectly natural that water, or an, should produce them The 
wnters whom I oppose declaie this inconceivable, but can con¬ 
ceive that mmd, 01 volition, is per se an efficient cause while 
the Cartesians could not conceive even that, but peremptonly 
declaied that no mode of production of any fact whatever was 
conceivable, except the direct agency of an omnipotent being. 
Thus giving additional pi oof of what finds new confirmation 
m eveiy stage of the history of science * that both what 
persons can, and what they cannot, conceive, is very much an 
afian of accident, and depends altogether on their experience, 
and their habits of thought, that by cultivating the requisite 
associations of ideas, people may make themselves unable to 
conceive any given thing, and may make themselves able to 
conceive most things, however inconceivable these may at first 
appear and the same facts in each person’s mental history 
which determine what is or is not conceivable to him, deter - 
mine also which among the various sequences m nature will 
appear to him so natural and plausible, as to need no other 
proof of their existence, to be evident by their own light, 
independent equally of expenence and of explanation. 

By what lule is any one to decide between one theory of 
this description and another ? The theorists do not direct us 
to any external evidence, they appeal each to his own sub¬ 
jective feelings. One says, the succession C, B, appears to me 
more natural, conceivable, and ciedible per se, than the succes¬ 
sion A, B , you aie therefore mistaken m thinking that B 
depends upon A, I am ceitam, though I can give no other 
evidence of it, that C comes m between A and B, and is the 
real and only cause of B. The othei answers—the successions 
0 , B, and A, B, appear to me equally natural and conceivable, 
or the latter moie so than the former. A is quite capable of 
producing B without any other intervention. A third agrees 
with the first m being unable to conceive that A can produce B, 
but finds the sequence D, B, still more natural than 0 , B, or 
of nearer km to the subject matter, and prefers his D theory 



398 


INDUCTION. 


to the C theory. It is plain that theie is no universal law 
operating here, except the law that each persons conceptions 
are governed and limited "by his individual expenence and 
habits of thought We are wan anted m saying of all three, 
what each of them alieady believes of the other two, namely, 
that they exalt into an ongmal law of the human intellect 
and of outward nature, one particular sequence of phenomena, 
which appears to them more natural 'and more conceivable 
than othei sequences, only because it is more familiar. And 
from this judgment I am unable to except the theory, that 
Volition is an Efficient Cause. 

I am unwilling to leave the subject without adverting to 
the additional fallacy contained m the coiollaiy fiom this 
theory, m the mfeience that because Volition is an efficient 
cause, therefore it is the only cause, and the direct agent m 
producing even what is apparently produced by something 
else. Volitions are not known to pioduce anything directly 
except nervous action, for the will influences even the muscles 
only through the nerves. Though it were granted, then, that 
every phenomenon has an efficient, and not meiely a pheno¬ 
menal cause, and that volition, m the case of the peculiar 
phenomena which are known to be produced by it, is that 
efficient cause, are we therefore to say, with these writers, 
that since we know of no other efficient cause, and ought not 
to assume one without evidence, there is no other, and volition 
is the direct cause of all phenomena ? A moie outrageous 
stretch of inference could hardly be made Because among 
the infinite variety of the phenomena of nature there is one, 
namely, a particular mode of action of certain nerves, which 
has for its cause, and as we are now supposing for its efficient 
cause, a state of our mind, and because this is the only effi¬ 
cient cause of which we are conscious, being the only one of 
which in the nature of the case we can be conscious, since it is 
the only one which exists within ourselves, does this justify 
us m concluding that all other phenomena must have the 
same kind of efficient cause with that one eminently special, 
narrow, and peculiarly human or animal, phenomenon ? The 
nearest parallel to this specimen of generalization is suggested 



LAW OF CAUSATION. 


399 


by the recently revived contioversy on the old subject of 
Plurality of Worlds, m which the contending parties have 
been so conspicuously successful m overthrowing one another. 
Here also we have experience only of a single case, that of the 
world m which we live, but that this is inhabited we know 
absolutely, and without possibility of doubt. Now if on this 
evidence any one were to infer that every heavenly body 
without exception, sun, planet, satellite, comet, fixed star or 
nebula, is inhabited, and must be so from the inherent consti¬ 
tution of things, his inference would exactly resemble that of 
the wiiters who conclude that because volition is the efficient 
cause of our own bodily motions, it must be the efficient cause 
of everything else m the universe. It is true theie are cases 
m which, with acknowledged propriety, we generalize from a 
single instance to a multitude of instances But they must be 
instances which resemble the one known instance, and not 
such as have no circumstance m common with it except that 
of being instances I have, for example, no direct evidence 
that any creature is alive except myself, yet I attribute, with 
full assurance, life and sensation to other human beings and 
animals. But I do not conclude that all other things are 
alive merely because I am I ascribe to certain other 
creatures a life like my own, because they manifest it by the 
same sort of indications by which mine is manifested. I find 
that their phenomena and mine conform to the same laws, 
and it is for this reason that I believe both to arise from 
a similar cause. Accordingly I do not extend the conclusion 
beyond the grounds for it Earth, fire, mountains, trees, 
are remarkable agencies, but their phenomena do not conform 
to the same laws as my actions do, and I therefore do not 
believe earth or fire, mountains or trees, to possess animal 
life. But the supporters of the Volition Theory ask us to 
infer that volition causes everything, for no reason except that 
it causes one particular thing, although that one pheno¬ 
menon, far from being a type of all natural phenomena, is 
eminently peculiar; its laws bearing scarcely any resemblance 
to those of any other phenomenon, whether of inoiganic or of 
organic nature. 



m 


INDUCTION. 


NOTE SUPPLEMENTARY TO THE PRECEDING- CHAPTER 

The author of the Second Burnett Prize Essay (Dr Tulloch), who has em¬ 
ployed a considerable number of pages m controverting the doctunes of the pre¬ 
ceding chapter, has somewhat surprised me by denying a fact, which I imagined 
too well known to require proof—that there have been philosophers who found 
in physical explanations of phenomena the same complete mental satisfaction 
which we are told is only given by volitional explanation, and others who de¬ 
nied the Volitional Theory on the same ground of inconceivability on which it 
is defended The asseition of the Essayist is countersigned still more positively 
by an able reviewer of the Essay * “ Two illustrations, ” says the reviewer, 
aie advanced by Mr Mill the case of Thales and Anaximenes, stated by him 
to have maintained, the one Moisture and the other An to be the origin of all 
things , and that of Descartes and Leibnitz, whom he assei ts to have found the 
action of Mmd upon Matter the grand inconceivability In counterstatement 
as to the first of these cases the author shows—what we believe now hardly 
admits of doubt—that the Greek philosophers distinctly recognised as beyond 
and above their primal material source, the vovg, or Divine Intelligence, as 
the efficient and originating Source of all and as to the second, by proof that 
it was the mode, not th e fact, of that action on matter, which was repiesented 
as inconceivable ,y 

A greater quantity of histoiical error has seldom been comprised m a single 
sentence With regard to Thales, the assertion that he consideied water as a 
mere material m the hands of voug lests on a passage of Ciceio de Naturd 
JDeoi icm and whoever will refer to any of the accurate historians of philo¬ 
sophy, will find that they tieat this as a mere fancy of Cicero, lestmg on no 
authority, opposed to all the evidence, and make surmises as to the manner 
m which Cicero may have been led into the enor (See Ritter, vol i p 211, 
2nd ed , Brandis, vol i pp 118-9, 1st ed , Preller, Histona Philosophies 
Gi ceco-Romance, p 10 '* Schiefe Ansicht, duichaus zu verwerfen £< augen- 

schemlich folgernd statt zu berichten “ quibus vera sententia Thaletis plane 
detorquetur /* are the expressions of these writers ) As foi Anaximenes, he, 
even according to Cicero, maintained, not that an was the matenal out of 
which God made the world, but that the air was a god “ Anaximenes a era 
deum statuit ” or according to St Augustine, that it was the material out of 
which the gods were made, 41 non tamen ah ipsis [Dus] aeiem factum, sed 
ipsos ex aere ortos credidit ” Those who aie not familial with the metaphy¬ 
sical terminology of antiquity, must not he misled by finding it stated that 
Anaximenes attnbuted (translated soul , or life) to his universal element, 
the air. The Gieek philosophers acknowledged several kinds of Tp v XV> the 
nutritive, the sensitive, and the intellective f Even the moderns with ad¬ 
mitted correctness attribute life to plants As far as we can make out the 
meaning of Anaximenes, lie made choice of Air as the universal agent, on the 
ground that it is perpetually in motion, without any apparent cause external 
to itself so that he conceived it as exercising spontaneous force, and as the 

* Westminster Review foi Octobei 1855 

+ See the whole doctrine in Aristotle de Ammd where the 0 pair tiki) 
is treated as exactly equivalent to Bps?mm) dvvapig 



LAW OF CAUSATION. 


401 


principle of life and activity m all things, men and gods inclusive If 
this be not representing it as the Efficient Cause, the dispute altogethei has 
no meaning 


If eithei Anaximenes, or Thales, or any of their cotemporanes, had held the 
doctrine that vovg was the Efficient Cause, that doctrine could not have been 
reputed, as it was throughout antiquity, to have originated With Anaxagoias 
The testimony of Aristotle, m the fiist book of his Metaphysics, is perfectly 
decisive with respect to these early speculations After enumerating foui kinds 
of causes, or rather four diffeient meanings of the word Cause, viz the 
Essence of a thing, the Matter of it, the Oiigm of Motion (Efficient Cause), 
and the End or Final Cause, he proceeds to say, that most of the eaily philo¬ 
sopher recognised only the second kind of Cause, the Matter of a thing, rag Iv 
vhqq eldei povag <pi]9r}(yav apxdg zivcu TravTwv As his first example he 
specifies Thales, whom he descubes as taking the lead m this view of the sub¬ 
ject, 6 rjjg roiavTTjg dpxvyog (f>i\oao<piag : and goes on to Hippon, Anaximenes, 
Diogenes (of Apolloma), Hippasus of Metapontum, Heraclitus, and Empe 
docles Anaxagoras, however, (he proceeds to say,) taught a different doctrine, 
as we Inow, and it is alleged that Heimotimus of Clazomenae taught it before 
him Anaxagoras represented, that even if these various theories of the uni¬ 
versal material were true, there would he need of some othei cause to account 
for the transformations of the matenal, since the matenal cannot originate its own 


changes ov yap dg to ye viroKEipEVov avro ttoiel fxera/3 oXXelv iavro Xsyuj 
^ olov OVTE TO £vXov ovTs o x^XKog alriog rov lAETafiaXXEiv iicarspov avru>v , 
ovce ttoieT to plv £uXov kXlvtjv o ds x^icog avdpLavra, aXX’ ETEpov tl Trig 
ptrafioXrjg aitiov, viz, the other kind of cause, o6ev rj apxv rijt , KivrjcrEwg —an 
Efficient Cause Anstotle expresses great appiobation of this doctrine (which 
he says made its author appear the only sober man among persons raving, 
olov vrifpuv tyavq Trap elk XkyovTag revg TrpoTspov), but while describing the 
influence which it exercised over subsequent speculation, he remaiks that the 
philosophers against whom this, as he thinks, ihsupeiable difficulty was urged, 
had not felt it to be any difficulty oudkv idvcrxspdvav iv iavToXg It is suiely 
unnecessary to say more m proof of the matter of fact which Di Tulloch and 
his reviewer deny 


Having pointed out what he thinks the error of these early speculator m 
not recognising the need of an efficient cause, Anstotle goes on to mention two 
other efficient causes to which they might have had lecomse, instead of intel¬ 
ligence rv X v, chance, and rb abropdrov, spontaneity He indeed puts these 
aside as not sufficiently woithy causes for the order m the universe, obS" at rip 
abropar V Ka i ry rb X y roaovrov Inrptycu rrpdypa Ka \u, e d X iv hut he does 
not reject them as incapable of pioducing any effect, but only as incapable of 
producing that effect He himself recognises rb xv and rb abropdrov as co¬ 
ordinate agents with Mind m pioducing the phenomena of the umve.se , the de¬ 
partment allotted to them being composed of all the classes of phenomena which 
are not supposed to follow any umfoim law By thus including Chance amone 
efficient causes, Aristotle fell into an error which philosophy has now outgrown 
but which is by no means so alien to the spirit even of modem speculation u 
it may at fiist sight appear Up to quite a recent period philosophers went on 
asc.ib.ng, and many of them have not yet ceased to ascribe, a real existence to 

vol. i. 26 



402 


INDUCTION. 


the results of abstraction. Chance could make out as good a title to that dig¬ 
nity as many other of the mind’s abstract creations . it had had a name given to 
it, and why should it not be a reality ? As for rb avrofiarov, it is recognised 
even yet as one of the modes of origination of phenomena, by all those thinkers 
who maintain what is called the Freedom of the Will. The same self-deter¬ 
mining powei which that doctrine attubutes to volitions, was supposed by the 
ancients to be possessed also by some other natural phenomena a circumstance 
which throws considerable light on more than one of the supposed invincible 
necessities of belief I have introduced it here, because this belief of Aristotle, 
or rather of the Greek philosophers generally, is as fatal as the doctrines of 
Thales and the Ionic school, to the theory that the human mind is compelled by 
its constitution to conceive volition as the origin of all force, and the efficient 
cause of all phenomena.* 

With regard to the modem philosophers (Leibnitz and the Cartesians) whom 
I had cited as having maintained that the action of mind upon matter, so far from 


* It deseives notice that the parts of nature, which Aristotle regards as pie- 
sen ting evidence of design, are the Uniformities the phenomena in so far as re¬ 
ducible to law Tiixv and to avrojiarov satisfy him as explanations of the vai lable 
element m phenomena, but their occurring according to a fixed rule can only, 
to his conceptions, be accounted for by an Intelligent Will The common, or 
what may be called the instinctive, religious interpretation of nature, is the re¬ 
verse of this The events m which men spontaneously see the hand of a super¬ 
natural being, are those which cannot, as they think, be reduced to a physical 
law What they can distinctly connect with physical causes, and especially what 
they can predict, though of course ascnbed to an Author of Nature if they 
already lecogmse such an author, might be conceived, they think, to ansefrom 
a blind fatality, and in any case do not appear to them to bear so obviously the 
mark of a divine will And this distinction has been countenanced by eminent 
writers on Natuial Theology, m particular by Dr Chalmers who thinks that 
though design is present everywhere, the irresistible evidence of it is to be found 
not m the laws of nature but m the collocations, % e m the part of nature 
m which it is impossible to tiace any law A few properties of dead matter 
might, he thinks, conceivably account for the regular and invariable succession 
of effects and causes , but that the diffeient kinds of matter have been so placed 
as to promote beneficent ends, is what he regards as the proof of a Divine Pro¬ 
vidence Mr Baden Powell, m his Essay entitled “ Philosophy of Creation,” 
has returned to the point of view of Aristotle and the ancients, and vigorously 
leasserts the doctrine that the indication of design m the universe is not 
special adaptations, but Uniformity and Law, these being the evidences of mind, 
and not what appears to us to be a provision for our uses While I decline to 
express any opinion here on this •uexata qucestio, I ought not to mention 
Mr Powell’s volume without the acknowledgment due to the philosophic spirit 
winch pervades generally the three Essays composing it, forming m the case 
of one of them (the a Unity of Woilds”) an honourable contrast with the other 
dissertations, so far as they have come under my notice, which have appeared 
on either side of that controversy. 



LAW OF CAUSATION. 


403 


being the only conceivable origin of material phenomena, is itself inconceivable, 
the attempt to rebut this argument by asserting that the mode, not the fact, of 
the action of mind on matter was represented as inconceivable, is an abuse of 
the privilege of writing confidently about authors without reading them foi 
any knowledge whatever of Leibnitz would have taught those who thus speak 
of him, that the inconceivability of the mode, and the impossibility of the thing, 
were m his mind convertible expressions What was his famous Pnnciple of 
the Sufficient Reason, the very corner stone of his philosophy, fi ora which the 
Preestablished Harmony, the doctrine of Monads, and all the opinions most 
characteristic of Leibnitz, were corollaries? It was, that nothing exists, the 
existence of which is not capable of being proved and explained & prion , the 
proof and explanation m the case of contingent facts being derived from the 
nature of their causes, whicn could not be the causes unless there was some- 
tkrng m their nature showing them to be capable of producing those particular 
effects And this “something” which accounts for the production of physical 
effects, he was able to find m many physical causes, but could not find it m any 
finite minds, which theiefore he unhesitatingly asserted to be incapable of pro¬ 
ducing any physical effects whatever “On ne saurait coneevoir,” he says, 
“une action r6cipioque de la matibre et de ^intelligence l’une sur l’autre,” and 
there is therefore (he contends) no choice but between the Occasional Causes 
of the Caitesians, and his own Preestablished Haimony, according to which 
there is no moie connexion between our volitions and our muscular actions 
than there is between two clocks which are wound up to strike at the same 
instant. But he felt no sinulai difficulty as to physical causes and throughout 
his speculations, as m the passage I have already cited respecting gravitation, 
he distinctly refuses to consider as part of the order of natuie any fact which is 
not explicable from the nature of its physical cause 

With regard to the Caitesians (not Descartes, 1 did not make that mistake, 
though the reviewer of Dr Tulloch’s Essay attnbutes it to me) I take a passage 
almost at landom fiom Malebianche, who is the best known of the Caitesians, 
and, though not the inventor of the system of Occasional Causes, is its principal 
expositor In Part 2, chap 3, of his Sixth Book, having first said that matter 
cannot have the power of moving itself, he proceeds to argue that neither can 
mmd have the powei of moving it “ Quand on examine 1’id^e que Ton a de 
tous les espnts finis, on ne voit point de liaison n^cessaire entre leui volont<5 et 
le mouvement de quelque corps que ce soit, on voit au contraire qu’il n’y en a 
point, et qu’il n’y en peut avoir(there is nothing m the idea of finite mmd 
which can account for its causing the motion of a body ,) “ on doit aussi con- 
clure, si on veut raisonner selon ses lumibies, qu’il n’y a aucun esprit ci 66 qui 
puisse remuer quelque corps que ce soit comme cause veritable ou principal, de 
mSme que 1’on a dit qu’aucun corps ne se pouvait lemuer soi-meme ” thus the 
idea of Mmd is according to him as incompatible as the idea of Matter with the 
exercise of active force But when, he continues, we consider not a created but 
a Divme Mmd, the case is aiteied , for the idea of a Divine Mmd includes omni¬ 
potence , and the idea of omnipotence does contain the idea of being able to 
move bodies Thus it is the nature of omnipotence which lenders the motion 
of bodies even by the divine mmd ci edible oi conceivable, while, so fai as 
depended on the mere nature of mmd, it would have been inconceivable and 

26 —2 



404 - 


induction. 


incredible If Malebrancbe had not believed m an omnipotent being, be would 
have held all action of mind on body to be a demonstrated impossibility.* 

A doctrine more precisely the reverse of the Volitional theory of causation 
cannot well be imagined The volitional theory is, that we know by intuition 
or by direct experience the action of our own mental volitions on matter, that 
we may hence infer all other action upon matter to be that of volition, and 
might thus know, without any other evidence, that matter is under the govern¬ 
ment of a divine mind Leibnitz and the Cartesians, on the contrary, maintain 
that our volitions do not and cannot act upon matter, and that it is only the 
existence of an all-governing Being, and that Being omnipotent, which can 
account for the sequence between our volitions and our bodily actions. When 
we consider that each of these two theories, which, as theories of causation, 
stand at the opposite extremes of possible divergence from one another, invokes 
not only as its evidence, but as its sole evidence, the absolute inconceivability 
of any theory but itself, we are enabled to measure the worth of this kind of 
evidence and when we find the Volitional theoiy entirely built upon the asser¬ 
tion that by our mental constitution we are compelled to recognise our volitions 
as efficient causes, and then find other thinkers maintaining that we know that 
they are not, and cannot be such causes, and cannot conceive them to be so, 
I think we have a right to say, that this supposed law of our mental constitu¬ 
tion does not exist 

Dr Tulloeh (pp 45-7) thinks it a sufficient answer to this, that Leibnitz 
and the Cartesians weie Theists, and believed the will of God to be an efficient 
cause Doubtless they did, and the Cartesians even believed (though Leibnitz 
did not) that it is the only such cause Dr, Tulloeh mistakes the nature of the 
question I was not writing on Theism, as Dr Tulloeh is, but against a par¬ 
ticular theory of causation, which if it be unfounded, can give no effective sup¬ 
port to Theism or to anything else I found it asserted that volition is the 
only efficient cause, on the ground that no other efficient cause is conceivable. 
To this assertion I oppose the instances of Leibnitz and of the Cartesians, who 
affirmed with equal positiveness that volition as an efficient cause is itself not 
conceivable, and that omnipotence, which renders all things conceivable, can 
alone take away the impossibility This I thought, and think, a conclusive 
answer to the argument on which this theory of causation avowedly depends 
But I certainly did not imagine that Theism was bound up with that theory ; 
nor expected to be charged with denying Leibnitz and the Cartesians to be 
Theists because I denied that they held the theory 


* In the words of Fontenelle, another celebrated Cartesian, “ les philosophes 
aussi bien que le peuple avaient cru que 1’a.rne et le corps agissaient rdellement 
et physiquement 1’un sur Tauti e Descartes vint, qui prouva que leur nature 
ne permettait point cette sorte de communication veritable, et qu’ils n’en pou- 
vaient avoir qu’une apparente, dont Dieu dtait le MSdiateur .”—CEmres de 
Fontenelle , ed 1767, tom v p. 534. 



CHAPTEE VL 


ON THE COMPOSITION OF CAUSES. 

§ 1 . To complete the general notion of causation on 
which the lules of experimental mqiiiiy into the laws of 
nature must he founded, one distinction still remains to he 
pointed out a distinction so radical, and of so much impor¬ 
tance, as to requne a chapter to itself. 

The preceding discussions have rendered us familiar with 
the case m which several agents, or causes, concur as condi¬ 
tions to the production of an effect, a case, m tmth, almost 
umversal, there hemg very few effects to the pioduction of 
which no more than one agent contributes Suppose, then, 
that two diffeient agents, operating jointly, are followed, 
under a certain set of collateial conditions, by a given effect 
If either of these agents, instead of being joined with the 
other, had operated alone, under the same set of conditions 
m all other respects, some effect would probably have fol¬ 
lowed , which would have been diffeient from the joint effect 
of the two, and more or less dissimilar to it. Now, if we 
happen to know what would be the effect of each cause 
when acting sepaiately from the other, we are often able to 
arrive deductively, or d pi ioi i y at a correct prediction of what 
will arise from their conjunct agency. To enable us to do 
this, it is only necessary that the same law which expresses 
the effect of each cause acting by itself, shall also correctly 
express the part due to that cause, of the effect which follows 
from the two together. This condition is realized m the 
extensive and important class of phenomena commonly 
called mechanical, namely the phenomena of the communi¬ 
cation of motion (or of pressure, which is tendency to motion) 
from one body to another. In this important class of cases 
of causation, one cause never, properly speaking, defeats or 



406 


INDUCTION. 


frustrates another, both have their full effect If a body is 
propelled in two directions by two forces, one tending to 
drive it to the north and the other to the east, it is caused 
to move in a given time exactly as far m both directions as 
the two forces would separately have carried it; and is left 
precisely wheie it would have arrived if it had been acted upon 
hist by one of the two forces, and afterwards by the other 
This law of nature is called, m dynamics, the principle of the 
Composition of Forces * and m imitation of that well-chosen 
expression, I shall give the name of the Composition of Causes 
to the principle which is exemplified m all cases m which the 
joint effect of several causes is identical with the sum of their 
separate effects 

This principle, however, by no means prevails in all 
departments of the field of nature The chemical combina¬ 
tion of two substances produces, as is well known, a third 
substance with properties entirely different from those of 
either of the two substances separately, or both of them 
taken together Not a trace of the propeities of hydrogen 
or of oxygen is observable m those of their compound, 
water The taste of sugar of lead is not the sum of the 
tastes of its component elements, acetic acid and lead or its 
oxide, nor is the colour of blue vitriol a mixture of the 
colours of sulphuric acid and copper. This explains why 
mechanics is a deductive or demonstrative science, and 
chemistry not. In the one, we can compute the effects of 
all combinations of causes, whether real or hypothetical, 
from the laws which we know to govern those causes when 
acting separately, because they continue to observe the 
same laws when in combination which they observed when 
separate whatever would have happened m consequence of 
each cause taken by itself, happens when they are together, 
and we have only to cast up the results Not so m the 
phenomena which are the peculiar subject of the science of 
chemistry. There, most of the uniformities to which the 
causes conformed when separate, oease altogether when they 
are conjoined, and we are not, at least m the present state 
of our knowledge, able to foresee what result will follow 



COMPOSITION OF CAUSES. 


407 


from any new combination, until we have tried the specific 
experiment 

If this he true of chemical combinations, it is still more 
true of those far more complex combinations of elements 
which constitute organized bodies, and m which those extia- 
ordmary new unifoimities anse, which are called the laws 
of life All organized bodies are composed of parts similar to 
those composing inorganic nature, and which have even them¬ 
selves existed m an inorganic state, but the phenomena of 
life, which result fiom the juxtaposition of those parts m a 
certain manner, bear no analogy to any of the effects which 
would be produced by the action of the component substances 
considered as mere physical agents To whatever degree we 
might imagine our knowledge of the properties of the several 
ingredients of a living body to be extended and perfected, it 
is certain that no mere summing up of the separate actions of 
those elements will ever amount to the action of the living 
body itself. The tongue, for instance, is, like all other parts 
of the animal frame, composed of gelatine, fibrin, and other 
products of the chemistry of digestion, but from no knowledge 
of the properties of those substances could we ever predict 
that it could taste, unless gelatine or fibrin could themselves 
taste, for no elementary fact can be in the conclusion, which 
was not in the premises 

There are thus two different modes of the conjunct action 
of causes, from which arise two modes of conflict, or mutual 
interference, between laws of nature Suppose, at a given 
point of time and space, two or more causes, which, if they 
acted separately, would produce effects contrary, or at least 
conflicting with each other; one of them tending to undo, 
wholly or partially, what the other tends to do. Thus, the 
expansive force of the gases generated by the ignition of gun¬ 
powder tends to project a bullet towards the sky, while its 
gravity tends to make it fall to the ground. A stream running 
into a reservoir at one end tends to fill it higher and higher, 
while a dram at the other extremity tends to empty it Now, 
m such cases as these, even if the two causes which are m 
joint action exactly annul one another, still the laws of both 



408 


INDUCTION. 


are fulfilled, the effect is the same as if the drain had been 
open for half an hour first,* and the stream had flowed m for 
as long afterwards. Each agent produced the same amount 
of effect as if it had acted separately, though the contrary 
effect which was taking place during the same time obliterated 
it as fast as it was produced Heie then are two causes, 
pioducmg by their joint operation an effect which at fust 
seems quite dissimilar to those which they produce separately, 
but which on examination proves to be really the sum of those 
separate effects. It will be noticed that we here enlarge the 
idea of the sum of two effects, so as to include what is com¬ 
monly called their difference, but which is m reality the result 
of the addition of opposites, a conception to which mankind 
are indebted for that admuable extension of the algebraical 
calculus, which has so vastly increased its powers as an instru¬ 
ment of discovery, by introducing into its reasonings (with 
the sign of subtraction piefixed, and under the name of 
Negative Quantities) every description whatever of positive 
phenomena, pi ovided they are of such a quality m refeience to 
those previously introduced, that to add the one is equivalent 
to subtracting an equal quantity of the other 

There is, then, one mode of the mutual interference of laws 
of nature, m which, even when the concurrent causes annr- 
hiJate each other's effects, each exerts its full efficacy according 
to its own law, its law as a separate agent. But m the other 
description of cases, the agencies which are brought together 
cease entirely, and a totally different set of phenomena arise. 
as m the experiment of two liquids which, when mixed m cer¬ 
tain proportions, instantly become, not a larger amount of 
liquid, but a solid mass. 

§ 2. This difference between the case m which the joint 
effect of causes is the sum of their separate effects, and the 


* I omit, for simplicity, to take into account the effect, m this latter case, 
of the diminution of pressure, m diminishing the flow of water through the 
dram, which evidently m no way affects the truth or applicability of the 
principle, since when the two causes act simultaneously the conditions of that 
diminution of pressure do not arise. 



COMPOSITION OF CAUSES. 


409 


case m which it is heteiogeneons to them , between laws which 
work together without alteration, and laws which, when called 
upon to woik together, cease and give place to others, is one 
of the fundamental distinctions m nature. The former case, 
that of the Composition of Causes, is the general one, the 
other is always special and exceptional. There aie no objects 
which do not, as to some of their phenomena, obey the prin¬ 
ciple of the Composition of Causes, none that have not some 
laws which are ligidly fulfilled m eveiy combination into 
which the objects enter. The weight of a body, for instance, 
is a property which it retains m all the combinations m which 
it is placed. The weight of a chemical compound, or of an 
organized body, is equal to the sum of the weights of the 
elements which compose it The weight either of the ele¬ 
ments or of the compound will vaiy, if they be Gained farther 
from their centre of attraction, or biought nearer to it, but 
whatever affects the one affects the other. They always 
lemam precisely equal. So again, the component parts of a 
vegetable or animal substance do not lose their mechanical 
and chemical properties as separate agents, when, by a peculiar 
mode of juxtaposition, they, as an aggregate whole, acquire 
physiological or vital properties m addition. Those bodies 
continue, as before, to obey mechanical and chemical laws, m 
so far as the operation of those laws is not counteracted by 
the new laws which govern them as organized beings. When, 
m shoit, a concurrence of causes takes place which calls into 
action new laws bearing no analogy to any that we can trace 
m the separate operation of the causes, the new laws, while 
they supersede one portion of the previous laws, may coexist 
with another portion, and may even compound the effect of 
those previous laws with their own. 

Again, laws which were themselves generated in the second 
mode, may generate others m the first Though there are 
laws which, like those of chemistry and physiology, owe their 
existence to a breach of the principle of Composition of Causes, 
it does not follow that these peculiar, or as they might be 
termed, heteropathic laws, are not capable of composition with 
one another. The causes which by one combination have 



410 


INDUCTION. 


had their laws altered, may carry their new laws with them 
unaltered mto their ulterior combinations And hence there 
is no reason to despair of ultimately raising chemistry and 
physiology to the condition of deductive sciences ; for though 
it is impossible to deduce all chemical and physiological truths 
from the laws or propeities of simple substances or elementary 
agents, they may possibly be deducible from laws which com¬ 
mence when these elementary agents are brought together 
into some model ate number of not very complex combina¬ 
tions. The Laws of Life will never be deducible from the 
mere laws of the ingredients, but the prodigiously complex 
Tacts of Life may all be deducible from comparatively simple 
laws of life , which laws (depending indeed on combinations, 
but on comparatively simple combinations, of antecedents) 
may, in more complex cneumstances, be stnctly compounded 
with one another, and with the physical and chemical laws of 
the ingredients The details of the vital phenomena, even 
now, afford innumerable exemplifications of the Composition 
of Causes; and in propoition as these phenomena are more 
accurately studied, theie appears more reason to believe that 
the same laws which operate m the simpler combinations of 
circumstances do, m fact, continue to be observed m the more 
complex This will be found equally true m the phenomena 
of mind, and even m social and political phenomena, the 
results of the laws of mind. It is m the case of chemical 
phenomena that the least progress has yet been made m 
bringing the special laws under general ones from which they 
may be deduced, but there aie even m chemistry many cir¬ 
cumstances to encourage the hope that such general laws will 
hereafter be discovered The different actions of a chemical 
compound will never, undoubtedly, be found to be the sums 
of the actions of its separate elements , but there may exist, 
between the properties of the compound and those of its 
elements, some constant relation, which, if discoverable by a 
sufficient induction, would enable us to foresee the sort of 
compound which will result from a new combination before 
we have actually tried it, and to judge of what sort of elements 
some new substance is compounded before we have analysed 



COMPOSITION OP CAUSES. 


411 


it The law of definite proportions, first discovered m its full 
generality by Dalton, is a complete solution of this problem 
m one, though but a secondary aspect, that of quantity and 
m respect to quality, we have already some partial generaliza¬ 
tions sufficient to indicate the possibility of ultimately pio- 
ceedmg farther We can predicate some common properties 
of the kind of compounds which result from the combination, 
m each of the small number of possible proportions, of any 
acid whatever with any base. We have also the curious law, 
discovered by Beithollet, that two soluble salts mutually 
decompose one another whenever the new combinations which 
result produce an insoluble compound, or one less soluble than 
the two former. Another uniformity is that called the law 
of isomorphism; the identity of the crystalline forms of sub¬ 
stances which possess m common certain peculiarities of 
chemical composition. Thus it appears that even heteropathie 
laws, such laws of combined agency as are not compounded 
of the laws of the separate agencies, are yet, at least m some 
cases, derived from them according to a fixed principle There 
may, theiefore, be laws of the generation of laws from others 
dissimilar to them; and m chemistry, these undiscovered 
laws of the dependence of the pioperties of the compound 
on the properties of its elements, may, together with the 
laws of the elements themselves, furnish the premises by 
which the science is perhaps destined one day to be rendered 
deductive. 

It would seem, therefore, that there is no class of pheno¬ 
mena m which the Composition of Causes does not obtain 
that as a general rule, causes m combination produce exactly 
the same effects as when acting singly but that this rule, 
though general, is not universal. that m some instances, at 
some particular points m the transition from separate to 
united action, the laws change, and an entirely new set of 
effects are either added to, or take the place of, those which 
arise from the separate agency of the same causes the 
laws of these new effects being again susceptible of com¬ 
position, to an indefinite extent, like the laws which they 
superseded. 



412 


INDUCTION. 


§ 3. That effects are proportional to their causes is laid 
down by some wnteis as an axiom m the theory of causation, 
and gieat use is sometimes made of this principle m reason¬ 
ings respecting the laws of nature* though it is incumbered 
with many difficulties and apparent exceptions, which much 
ingenuity has been expended m showing not to be real ones. 
This pioposition, m so far as it is true, enters as a particular 
case into the general principle of the Composition of Causes , 
the causes compounded being, m this instance, homogeneous, 
in which case, if m any, their joint effect might be expected 
to be identical with the sum of their separate effects If a 
foice equal to one hundred weight will raise a certain body 
along an inclined plane, a force equal to two hundred weight 
will raise two bodies exactly similar, and thus the effect is 
proportional to the cause. But does not a force equal to two 
hundred weight actually contain m itself two forces each 
equal to one hundred weight, which, if employed apart, 
would separately raise the two bodies in question ? The fact, 
therefore, that when excited jointly they raise both bodies at 
once, lesults from the Composition of Causes, and is a mere 
instance of the general fact that mechanical forces are subject 
to the law of Composition. And so m every other case which 
can be supposed Tor the doctrine of the proportionality of 
effects to their causes cannot of course be applicable to cases 
m which the augmentation of the cause alters the kind of 
effect, that is, m which the surplus quantity superadded to 
the cause does not become compounded with it, but the two 
together generate an altogether new phenomenon. Suppose 
that the application of a certain quantity of heat to a body 
merely increases its bulk, that a double quantity melts it, and 
a tuple quantity decomposes it: these three effects being 
heterogeneous, no ratio, whether corresponding or not to that 
of the quantities of heat applied, can be established between 
them. Thus the supposed axiom of the proportionality of 
effects to their causes fails at the precise point where the prin¬ 
ciple of the Composition of Causes also fails , viz., where the 
concurrence of causes is such as to determine a change m the 
properties of the body generally, and render it subject to new 



COMPOSITION OF CAUSES. 


413 


laws, more or less dissimilar to those to which it conformed in 
its previous state. The recognition, therefore, of any such 
law of proportionality, is superseded by the more comprehen¬ 
sive principle, m which as much of it as is true is implicitly 
asserted 

The geneial remarks on causation, which seemed necessary 
as an mtioduction to the theory of the inductive process, may 
here terminate That piocess is essentially an inquiry into 
cases of causation All the uniformities which exist in the 
succession of phenomena, and most of the uniformities m their 
coexistence, aie either, as we have seen, themselves laws of 
causation, or consequences resulting from, and corollaries 
capable of being deduced from, such laws If we could deter¬ 
mine what causes aie correctly assigned to what effects, and 
what effects to what causes, we should be virtually acquainted 
with the whole course of nature All those uniformities 
which are mere results of causation, might then be explained 
and accounted for, and every individual fact or event might 
be predicted, provided we had the requisite data, that is, the 
requisite knowledge of the circumstances which, m the parti¬ 
cular instance, preceded it 

To ascertain, therefore, what are the laws of causation 
which exist m nature, to determine the effect of every 
cause, and the causes of all effects,—is the mam business of 
Induction, and to point out how this is done is the chief 
object of Inductive Logic. 



CHAPTEB VII. 


OF OBSERVATION AND EXPERIMENT. 

§ 1. It results from the preceding exposition, that the 
process of ascertaining what consequents, m nature, are inva¬ 
riably connected with what antecedents, or m other woids 
what phenomena aie related to each other as causes and 
effects, is in some sort a process of analysis That every 
fact which begins to exist has a cause, and that this cause 
must be found somewhere among the facts which imme¬ 
diately preceded the occunence, may be taken for ceitam. 
The whole of the piesent facts are the infallible lesult of all 
past facts, and more immediately of all the facts which 
existed at the moment previous Here, then, is a great 
sequence, which we know to be unifoim. If the whole prior 
state of the entire universe could again recur, it would again 
be followed by the present state. The question is, how to 
i esolve this complex unifoimity into the simpler uniformities 
which compose it, and assign to each portion of the vast 
antecedent the portion of the consequent which is attendant 
on it. 

This opeiation, which we have called analytical, inasmuch 
as it is the resolution of a complex whole into the component 
elements, is more than a meiely mental analysis. No mere 
contemplation of the phenomena, and paitition of them by 
the intellect alone, will of itself accomplish the end we have 
now m view. Nevertheless, such a mental partition is an 
indispensable fiist step The older of nature, as perceived at 
a first glance, presents at every instant a chaos followed by 
another chaos We must decompose each chaos into single 
facts. We must learn to see m the chaotic antecedent a mul¬ 
titude of distinct antecedents, m the chaotic consequent a 
multitude of distinct consequents. This, supposing it done, 



OBSERVATION AND EXPERIMENT. 


415 


will not of itself tell us on which of the antecedents each conse¬ 
quent is mvaiiably attendant. To determine that point, we 
must endeavour to effect a separation of the facts from one an¬ 
other, not in our minds only, but m nature. The mental ana¬ 
lysis, however, must take place fiist. And every one knows that 
m the mode of performing it, one intellect differs immensely 
from another It is the essence of the act of observing, for 
the observer is not he who merely sees the thing which is before 
his eyes, but he who sees what paits that thing is composed of. 
To do this well is a rare talent One peison, from inattention, 
or attending only m the wiong place, overlooks half of what 
he sees . another sets down much more than he sees, confound¬ 
ing it with what he imagines, or with what he infers, another 
takes note of the kind of all the circumstances, but being inex¬ 
pert m estimating their degree, leaves the quantity of each 
vague and unceitam, another sees indeed the whole, but 
makes such an awkward division of it into parts, throwing 
things into one mass which require to be separated, and sepa¬ 
rating others which might more conveniently be considered as 
one, that the lesult is much the same, sometimes even worse, 
than if no analysis had been attempted at all It would be 
possible to point out what qualities of mind, and modes of 
mental culture, fit a person for being a good observer that, 
however, is a question not of Logic, hut of the Theory of Edu¬ 
cation, m the most enlarged sense of the term There is not 
piopeily an Ait of Observing. There may be rules for ob- 
seivmg. But these, like lules for inventing, are properly 
msti uctions for the preparation of one’s own mind, for putting 
it into the state m which it will be most fitted to observe, or 
most likely t6 invent They are, therefore, essentially rules of 
self education, which is a different thing from Logic They 
do not teach how to do the thing, but how to make ourselves 
capable of doing it They are an art of strengthening the 
limbs, not an art of using them. 

The extent and minuteness of observation which may be 
requisite, and the degree of decomposition to which it may be 
necessary to carry the mental analysis, depend on the parti¬ 
cular purpose m view. To ascertain the state of the whole 



416 


INDUCTION. 


universe at any particular moment is impossible, but would 
also be useless In making chemical experiments, we do not 
think it necessaiy to note the position of the planets , because 
experience has shown, as a very superficial expenence is suffi¬ 
cient to show, that m such cases that cncumstance is not 
material to the lesult and, accordingly, m the ages when 
men believed m the occult influences of the heavenly bodies, 
it might have been unphilosophical to omit asceitaming the 
piecise condition of those bodies at the moment of the expen- 
ment As to the degree of minuteness of the mental sub¬ 
division , if we weie obliged to bieak down what we observe 
into its veiy simplest elements, that is, liter ally into single 
facts, it would be difficult to say wheie we should find them 
we can hardly evei affirm that our divisions of any kind have 
leached the ultimate unit But this too is foitunately un¬ 
necessary The only object of the mental sepaiation is to 
suggest the requisite physical sepaiation, so that we may 
either accomplish it ourselves, or seek for it m nature, and 
we have done enough when we have earned the subdivision as 
far as the point at which we aie able to see what observations 
or expenments we requne It is only .essential, at whatever 
point our mental decomposition of facts may for the present 
have stopped, that we should hold ourselves leady and able to 
carry it faithei as occasion requnes, and should not allow the 
freedom of our discriminating faculty to be imprisoned by the 
swathes and hands of ordinaly classification , as was the case 
with all early speculative lnquners, not excepting the Greeks, 
to whom it seldom occurred that what was called by one 
abstract name might, in reality, he several phenomena, or that 
there was a possibility of decomposing the facts of the universe 
into any elements but those which ordinary language already 
recognised. 

§ 2. The different antecedents and consequents, being, 
then, supposed to be, so far as the case requnes, ascertained 
and discriminated from one another, we are to inquire which 
is connected with which In every instance which comes 
under our observation, there are many antecedents and many 



OBSERVATION AND EXPERIMENT. 


417 


consequents. If those antecedents could not he severed from 
one another except in thought, or if those consequents never 
were found apart, it would be impossible for us to distinguish 
{d 'posteno'n at least) the real laws, or to assign to any cause 
its effect, or to any effect its cause. To do so, we must be 
able to meet with some of the antecedents apart from the rest, 
and observe what follows from them, 01 some of the conse¬ 
quents, and observe by what they aie pieceded We must, 
m short, follow the Baconian rule of varying the circumstances. 
This is, indeed, only the first rule of physical inquiry, and not, 
as some have thought, the sole rule , but it is the foundation 
of all the rest. 

Tor the purpose of varying the circumstances, we may 
have recourse (according to a distinction commonly made) 
eithei to observation 01 to experiment, we may either find an 
instance m nature, suited to our purposes, or, by an artificial 
arrangement of circumstances, male one The value of the 
instance depends on what it is m itself, not on the mode m 
which it is obtained its employment for the purposes of in¬ 
duction depends on the same principles m the one case and m 
the other, as the uses of money are the same whether it is 
inherited or acquired There is, m short, no difference m 
kind, no real logical distinction, between the two processes of 
investigation There are, however, practical distinctions to 
which it is of considerable importance to advert 

§ 3. The first and most obvious distinction between 
Observation and Experiment is, that the latter is an immense 
extension of the former It not only enables us to produce 
a much greater number of variations m the circumstances than 
nature spontaneously offers, but also, m thousands of cases, to 
pioduce the precise sort of variation which we are m want of 
for discovering the law of the phenomenon, a service which 
nature, being constructed on a quite different scheme from 
that of facilitating our studies, is seldom so friendly as to 
bestow upon us. Tor example, m order to ascertain what 
principle m the atmosphere enables it to sustain life, the 
variation we requn e is that a living animal should be immersed 
von i. 27 



418 


INDUCTION. 


m eacli component element of the atmosphere separately. But 
nature does not supply either oxygen or azote m a separate 
state. We are indebted to artificial experiment for our know¬ 
ledge that it is the former, and not the lattei, which supports 
respiration , and for our knowledge of the veiy existence of the 
tw T o ingredients 

Thus fai the advantage of experimentation over simple ob¬ 
servation is universally recognised all ai e aware that it enables 
us to obtain mnumei able combinations of circumstances which 
are not to be found m nature, and so add to nature’s experi¬ 
ments a multitude of experiments of our own. But there is 
another supenonty (or, as Bacon would have expressed it, 
another prerogative) of instances aitificially obtained over 
spontaneous instances,—of our own experiments over even the 
same experiments when made by nature,—which is not of less 
importance, and which is far from being felt and acknowledged 
in the same degree. 

When we can produce a phenomenon artificially, we can 
take it, as it were, home with us, and ohseive it m the midst 
of circumstances with which m all other lespects we are accu¬ 
rately acquainted If we desne to know what are the effects 
of the cause A, and are able to pioduce A by means at our 
disposal, we can generally determine at our own discretion, so 
far as is compatible with the natuie of the phenomenon A, the 
whole of the cucumstances which shall be present along with 
it and thus, knowing exactly the simultaneous state of every¬ 
thing else which is within the reach of As influence, we have 
only to observe what alteration is made m that state by the pre¬ 
sence of A. 

For example, by the electric machine we can produce 
in the midst of known cucumstances, the phenomena which 
nature exhibits on a grander scale m the form of lightning 
and thunder. Now let any one consider what amount of 
knowledge of the effects and laws of electric agency mankind 
could have obtained from the mere observation of thunder¬ 
storms, and compare it with that which they have gained, 
and may expect to gam, from electncal and galvanic experi¬ 
ments. This example is the moie stiikmg, now that we have 



OBSERVATION AND EXPERIMENT. 


419 


reason to believe that electnc action is of all natural pheno¬ 
mena (except heat) the most pervading and univeisal, which, 
tlierefoie, it might antecedently have been supposed could 
stand least in need of aitificial means of production to enable 
it to be studied, while the fact is so much the contraiy, that 
without the electnc machine, the Leyden jar, and the voltaic 
battery, we probably should never have suspected the existence 
of electricity as one of the great agents in natuie, the few 
electnc phenomena we should have known of would have con¬ 
tinued to be regarded eithei as supernatural, 01 as a sort of 
anomalies and eccentricities in the older of the universe 

When we have succeeded m insulating*the phenomenon 
which is the subject of mquny, by placing it among known 
circumstances, we may pioduce fuither variations of circum¬ 
stances to any extent, and of such kinds as we think best 
calculated to bring the laws of the phenomenon into a clear 
light By introducing one well-defined circumstance after 
another into the experiment, we obtain assuiance of the 
mannei m which the phenomenon behaves under an indefinite 
variety of possible circumstances. Thus, chemists, after 
having obtained some newly-discovered substance m a pure 
state, (that is, having made sure that there is nothing present 
which can interfere with and modify its agency,) introduce 
various other substances, one by one, to ascertain whether it 
will combine with them, or decompose them, and with what 
result, and also apply heat, or electricity, or pressuie, to dis¬ 
cover what will happen to the substance under each of these 
circumstances. 

But if, on the other hand, it is out of our power to pro¬ 
duce the phenomenon, and we have to seek for instances m 
which nature produces it, the task before us is veiy diffeient. 
Instead of being able to choose what the concomitant cn- 
cumstances shall be, we now have to discovei what they are , 
which, when we go beyond the simplest and most accessible 
cases, it is next to impossible to do, with any precision and 
completeness. Let us take, as an exemplification of a phe¬ 
nomenon which we have no means of fabricating artificially, 
a human mind. Nature produces many, hut the consequence 

27—2 



m 


INDUCTION. 


of our not being able to produce them by ait is, that m every 
instance m which we see a human mind developing itself, or 
acting upon other things, we see it sunounded and obscured 
by an indefinite multitude of unascei tamable cn cum stances, 
rendering the use of the common experimental methods almost 
delusive We may conceive to what extent this is true, if we 
consider, among other things, that whenever nature produces 
a human mmd, she produces, in close connexion with it, a 
body; that is, a vast complication of physical facts, m no two 
cases peihaps exactly similar, and most of which (except the 
mere structure, which we can examine m a sort of coarse 
way after it has ceased to act), are radically out of the reach 
of our means of exploration. If, instead of a human mind, 
we suppose the subject of investigation to be a human society 
or State, all the same difficulties recur m a greatly augmented 
degree 

We have thus already come within sight of a conclusion, 
hich the piogress of the inquiry will, I think, bring before 
us with the clearest evidence namely, that m the sciences 
w hich deal with phenomena m which artificial expenments 
are impossible (as m the case of astronomy), or m which they 
have a very limited range (as in mental philosophy, social science, 
and even physiology), induction from direct experience is prac¬ 
tised at a disadvantage m most cases equivalent to impractica¬ 
bility . fiom which it follows that the methods of those sciences, 
m order to accomphsh anything worthy of attainment, must be 
to a great extent, if not pnncipally, deductive. This is already 
known to be the case with the first of the sciences we have 
mentioned, astronomy, that it is not generally lecogmsed as 
true of th p others, is probably one of the reasons why they are 
not in a moie advanced state 

§ 4 If what is called pure observation is at so great a 
disadvantage, compared with artificial experimentation, m one 
department of the direct exploration of phenomena, there is 
another branch m which the advantage is all on the side of 
the former. 

Inductive inquiry having for its object to ascertain what 



OBSERVATION AND EXPERIMENT. 


421 


causes are connected with what effects, we may begin this 
search at either end of the road which leads from the one 
point to the other we may eithei inquire into the effects of a 
given cause, or into the causes of a given effect The fact that 
light blackens chloride of silvei might have been discovered 
either by experiments on light, trying what effect it would 
produce on vanous substances, or by obseivmg that portions 
of the chloride had repeatedly become black, and inquiring 
into the circumstances. The effect of the urali poison might 
have become known eithei by administering it to animals, or 
by examining how it happened that the wounds which the 
Indians of G-uiana inflict with their arrows prove so uniformly 
mortal Now it is manifest fiom the mere statement of 
the examples, without any theoretical discussion, that arti¬ 
ficial experimentation is applicable only to the former of these 
modes of investigation. We can take a cause, and try what it 
will produce but we cannot take an effect, and try what it 
will be produced by We can only watch till we see it pro¬ 
duced, or aie enabled to pioduce it by accident 

This would be of little importance, if it always depended 
on our choice from which of the two ends of the sequence we 
would undeitake our inquiries But we have seldom any 
option. As we can only travel from the known to the un¬ 
known, we are obliged to commence at whichever end we are 
best acquainted with. If the agent is more familiar to us than 
its effects, we watch for, or contrive, instances of the agent, 
under such varieties of circumstances as are open to us, and 
obseive the result If, on the contrary, the conditions on 
which a phenomenon depends are obscure, but the phenomenon 
itself familiar, we must commence our inquiry from the effect 
If we are struck with the fact that chloride of silver has been 
blackened, and have no suspicion of the cause, we have no 
resource but to compare instances m which the fact has 
chanced to occur, until by that comparison we discover that m 
all those instances the substances had been exposed to light 
If we knew nothing of the Indian arrows but their fatal effect, 
accident alone could turn our attention to experiments on the 
urali, m the regular course of investigation, we could only 



INDUCTION. 


422 

inquire, or try to observe, what had been done to the arrows in 
particular instances. 

Wherevei, having nothing to guide us to the cause, we 
are obliged to set out from the effect, and to apply the rule of 
varying the cncumstances to the consequents, not the antece¬ 
dents, we are necessanly destitute of the resource of artificial 
experimentation We cannot, at our choice, obtain conse¬ 
quents, as we can antecedents, under any set of circumstances 
compatible with then natuie There are no means of pro¬ 
ducing effects but through their causes, and by the supposi¬ 
tion the causes of the effect m question aie not known to us. 
We have therefoie no expedient but to study it where it 
offers itself spontaneously If natuie happens to present us 
with instances sufficiently varied m then circumstances, and if 
we are able to discover, either among the proximate ante¬ 
cedents or among some other older of antecedents, something 
which is always found when the effect is found, however 
vauous the circumstances, and never found when it is not, 
we may discovei, by meie observation without expenment, a 
real uniformity m nature 

But though this is certainly the most favourable case for 
sciences of pure obseivation, as contiasted with those m which 
artificial expenments aie possible, there is m reality no case 
wdneh more stiikmgly illustrates the mheient impeifection of 
direct induction when not founded on experimentation. Sup¬ 
pose that, by a companson of cases of the effect, we have 
lound an antecedent which appears to he, and perhaps is, 
invariably connected with it. we have not yet proved that 
antecedent to he the cause, until we have reversed the piocess, 
and produced the effect by means of that antecedent If we 
can produce the antecedent aitificially, and if, when we do so, 
the effect follows, the induction is complete, that antecedent 
is the cause of that consequent * But we have then added 

* Unless, indeed, the consequent was generated not by the antecedent, but 
by tbe means employed to produce the antecedent As, however, these 
means are under our power, there is so far a probability that they are also 
sufficiently within our knowledge, to enable us to judge whether that could be 
the case or not. 



OBSERVATION AND EXPERIMENT. 423 

the evidence of experiment to that of simple observation 
Until we had done so, we had only pioved imcnictble ante¬ 
cedence within the limits of experience, but not unconditioned 
antecedence, or causation Until it had been shown by the 
actual production of the antecedent under known circum¬ 
stances, and the occurrence thereupon of the consequent, that 
the antecedent was really the condition on which it depended, 
the uniformity of succession which was proved to exist between 
them might, for aught we knew, be (like the succession of day 
and night) not a case of causation at all, both antecedent and 
consequent might he successive stages of the effect of an ulte¬ 
rior cause Observation, m short, without experiment (sup¬ 
posing no aid from deduction) can ascertain sequences and 
coexistences, hut cannot prove causation 

In order to see these remarks verified by the actual state 
of the sciences, we have only to think of the condition of 
natuial history In zoology, for example, there is an immense 
number of uniformities ascertained, some of coexistence, others 
of succession, to many of which, notwithstanding considerable 
variations of the attendant cncumstances, we know not any 
exception * but the antecedents, for the most part, are such as 
we cannot artificially pioduce, or if we can, it is only by set¬ 
ting m motion the exact process by which nature produces 
them, and this being to us a mysterious process, of which 
the mam cncumstances are not only unknown but unobserv¬ 
able, we do not succeed in obtaining the antecedents under 
known circumstances What is the result ? That on this 
vast subject, which affords so much and such varied scope for 
observation, we have made most scanty progress m ascertaining 
any laws of causation. We know not with certainty, m the 
case of most of the phenomena that we find conjoined, which 
is the condition of the other, which is cause, and which effect, 
or whether either of them is so, or they are not rather conjunct 
effects of causes yet to be discovered, complex results of laws 
hitherto unknown. 

Although some of the foregoing observations may be, m 
technical strictness of arrangement, prematuie m this place, it 
seemed that a few general remarks on the difference between 



424 


INDUCTION. 


sciences of mere observation and sciences of experimentation, 
and the extreme disadvantage under which directly inductive 
inquiry is necessanly earned on m the former, were the best 
preparation for discussing the methods of direct induction, a 
preparation rendering superfluous much that must otherwise 
have been mtioduced, with some inconvenience, into the heart 
of that discussion. To the consideration of these methods we 
now proceed. 



CHAPTER VIII. 


OF THE FOUR METHODS OF EXPERIMENTAL INQUIRY. 

§ 1. The simplest and most obvious modes of singling 
out from among the circumstances which precede or follow a 
phenomenon, those with which it is really connected by an 
invariable law, are two m number One is, by comparing ^ 
togethei different instances m which the phenomenon occurs * 
The other is, by comparing instances in which the phenomenon 
does occur, with instances m other respects similar m which 
it does not. These two methods may be respectively deno¬ 
minated, the Method of Agreement, and the Method of Dif¬ 
ference 

In illustrating these methods, it will be necessary to bear 
m mind the twofold character of inquiries into the laws of 
phenomena, which may be either inquiries into the cause of 
a given effect, or into the effects or properties of a given cause. 
We shall consider the methods m their application to either 
order of investigation, and shall draw our examples equally 
from both., 

We shall denote antecedents by the large letters of the 
alphabet, and the consequents corresponding to them by the 
small. Let A, then, be an agent or cause, and let the object 
of our inquiry be to ascertain what are the effects of this cause. 
If we can either find, or pioduce, the agent A m such varieties 
of circumstances, that the different cases have no circumstance 
m common except A, then whatever effect we find to be pro¬ 
duced m all our trials, is indicated as the effect of A. Sup¬ 
pose, for example, that A is tried along with B and 0, and 
that the effect is a b c , and suppose that A is next tried with 
D and E, but without B and C, and that the effect is a d e. 
Then we may reason thus. b and c are not effects of A, for 
they were not produced by it m the second experiment; nor 



426 


INDUCTION. 


aie d and e, for they weie not produced m the first Whatever 
is really the effect of A must have been produced in both 
instances , now this condition is fulfilled by no cncumstance 
except a The phenomenon a cannot have been the effect of 
B or C, since it was pioduced where they were not, nor of L 
or E, since it was produced where they weie not Theiefore it 
is the effect of A. 

Foi example, let the antecedent A be the contact of an 
alkaline substance and an oil This combination being tiled 
under several varieties of circumstances, resembling each other 
m nothing else, the results agree m the production of a gieasy 
and detersive or saponaceous substance it is theiefoie con 
eluded that the combination of an oil and an alkali causes the 
production of a soap. It is thus we inquire, by the Method of 
Agreement, into the effect of a given cause. 

In a similar manner we may inquire into the cause of a 
given effect Let a be the effect. Here, as shown in the 
last chapter, we have only the lesouree of observation without 
expenment. we cannot take a phenomenon of which we know 
not the origin, and try to find its mode of production by pro¬ 
ducing it if we succeeded m such a random tual it could only 
he by accident But if we can observe a m two different com¬ 
binations, a b c } and a d e , and if we know, or can discover, 
that the antecedent circumstances m these cases respectively 
were ABC and ALE, we may conclude by a reasoning 
similar to that m the preceding example, that A is the ante¬ 
cedent connected with the consequent a by a law of causation 
B and C, we may say, cannot be causes of a, since on its 
second occurrence they were not present, nor are D and E, 
for they were not present on its fiist occurrence A, alone of 
the five circumstances, was found among the antecedents of a 
m both instances. 

For example, let the effect a be crystallization. We com¬ 
pare instances in which bodies are known to assume crystalline 
structure, but which have no other point of agreement; and we 
find them to have one, and as far as we can observe, only one, 
antecedent m common . the deposition of a solid matter from 
a liquid state, either a state of fusion or of solution We con- 



THE FOUR EXPERIMENTAL METHODS. 


427 


elude, therefore, that the solidification of a substance from a 
liquid state is an mv ail able antecedent of its crystallization 

In this example we may go farther, and say, it is not only 
the mvanable antecedent but the cause, 01 at least the proxi¬ 
mate event which completes the cause. For m this case we 
are able, after detecting the antecedent A, to produce it aiti- 
ficially, and by finding that a follows it, verify the result of 
our induction The impoitance of thus leversing the pi oof 
was stnkmgly manifested when by keeping a phial of water 
charged with siliceous pai tides undisturbed for years, a 
chemist (I believe Dr. Wollaston) succeeded m obtaining 
ciystals of quartz , and m the equally intei estmg experiment 
m which Sn James Hall produced artificial marble, by the 
cooling of its matenals fiom fusion under immense piessure 
two admnable examples of the light which may be thiown 
upon the most seciet piocesses of nature by well-contrived 
mteirogation of her. 

But if we cannot aitificially produce the phenomenon A, 
the conclusion that it is the cause of a remains subject to 
very considerable doubt. Though an mvanable, it may not 
be the unconditional antecedent of a } but may piecede it as 
day precedes night or night day This uncertainty arises 
from the impossibility of assuring ourselves that A is the only 
immediate antecedent common to both the instances. If we 
could be certain of having asceitamed all the mvanable ante¬ 
cedents, we might be sure that the unconditional invariable 
antecedent, 01 cause, must be found somewhere among them. 
Unfortunately it is hardly ever possible to ascertain all the 
antecedents, unless the phenomenon is one which we can 
produce artificially. Even then, the difficulty is merely 
lightened, not removed. men knew how to raise water m 
pumps long before they adverted to what was really the 
operating cncumstance in the means they employed, namely, 
the pressure of the atmosphere on the open surface of the 
water. It is, however, much easier to analyse completely 
a set of arrangements made by ourselves, than the whole 
complex mass of the agencies which nature happens to be 
exerting at the moment of the production of a given phe- 



428 


INDUCTION. 


nomenon We may overlook some of the material circum¬ 
stances m an experiment with an electrical machine, but we 
shall, at the worst, he better acquainted with them than with 
those of a thunder-stoim. 

The mode of discovering and piovmg laws of nature, which 
we have now examined, proceeds on the following axiom 
Whatever circumstances can be excluded, without prejudice to 
the phenomenon, or can be absent notwithstanding its 
presence, is not connected with it m the way of causation 
The casual circumstances being thus eliminated, if only one 
remains, that one is the cause which we aie m search of if 
more than one, they either are, or contain among them, the 
cause, and so, mutatis mutandis , of the effect. As this method 
proceeds by comparing different instances to ascertain in 
what they agree, I have termed it the Method of Agreement 
and we may adopt as its regulating principle the following 
canon — 

First Canon. 

If two or more instances of the phenomenon under investiga¬ 
tion have only one circumstance m common, the circumstance m 
which alone all the instances ag? ee , is the cause (or effect) of the 
given phenomenon 

Quitting for the present the Method of Agreement, to 
which we shall almost immediately return, we pioceed to a 
still more potent instrument of the investigation of nature, the 
Method of Difference. 

§ 2. In the Method of Agreement, we endeavoured to 
obtain instances which agreed m the given circumstance but 
differed m every other m the present method we requne, 
on the contrary, two instances resembling one another m 
every other respect, but differing in the presence or absence 
of the phenomenon we wish to study If our object be to 
discover the effects of an agent A, we must procure A m 
some set of ascertained circumstances, as A B 0, and having 
noted the effects produced, compare them with the effect 
of the remaining cncumstances B C, when A is absent. If 
the effect of A B C is a b c 7 and the effect of B 0, & c, it is 



THE FOUR EXPERIMENTAL METHODS. 


429 


evident that the effect of A is a. So again, if we begin at 
the other end, and desire to investigate the cause of an effect 
a, we must select an instance, as a b c, m which the effect 
occurs, and m which the antecedents were ABC, and we 
must look out for another instance m which the lemaimng 
circumstances, b c, occur without a If the antecedents, m 
that instance, are B 0, we know that the cause of a must he 
A either A alone, or A m conjunction with some of the other 
circumstances present 

It is scaicely necessary to give examples of a logical 
process to which we owe almost all the inductive conclusions 
we draw m daily life. When a man is shot through the 
heart, it is by this method we know that it was the gun-shot 
which killed him for he was m the fulness of life imme¬ 
diately before, all cncumstances being the same, except the 
wound. 

The axioms implied m this method are evidently the 
following. Whatever antecedent cannot be excluded without 
preventing the phenomenon, is the cause, or a condition, of 
that phenomenon Whatever consequent can be excluded, 
with no other difference m the antecedents than the absence 
of a particular one, is the effect of that one. Instead of 
comparing different instances of a phenomenon, to discovei 
m what they agree, this method compares an instance of its 
occurrence with an instance of its non-occurrence, to discover 
m what they differ. The canon which is the regulating 
principle of the Method of Difference may be expressed as 
follows 

Second Canon. 

If an instance m which the phenomenon under investigation 
occurs, and an instance in which it does not occur, have every 
circumstance in common save one, that one occurring only m 
the former , the circumstance m which alone the two instances 
differ, is the effect, or the cause, or an indispensable part of 
the cause, of the phenomenon . 

§ 3. The two methods which we have now stated have 
many features of resemblance, but there are also many dis- 



430 


INDUCTION. 


tmctions "between them Both aie methods of elimination 
This term (employed m the theoiy of equations to denote the 
process by which one after another of the elements of a question 
is excluded, and the solution made to depend on the relation 
between the remaining elements only) is well suited to express 
the operation,.analogous to this, which has been understood 
since the time of Bacon to he the foundation of expeiimental 
mquny namely, the successive exclusion of the various cir¬ 
cumstances which aie found to accompany a phenomenon m a 
given instance, m order to ascertain what are those among 
them which can be absent consistently with the existence of 
the phenomenon The Method of Agreement stands on the 
ground that whatever can be eliminated, is not connected with 
[the phenomenon by any law The Method of Difference has 
for its foundation, that whatever cannot be eliminated, is con¬ 
nected with the phenomenon by a law. 

Of these methods, that of Diffeience is moie paiticularly 
a method of aitificial experiment, while that of Agreement is 
more especially the resource employed where experimentation 
is impossible A few reflections will prove the fact, and point 
out the reason of it 

It is inherent m the peculiar character of the Method of 
Difference, that the natuie of the combinations which it 
requires is much more strictly defined than m the Method of 
Agreement. The two instances which are to be compared 
with one another must be exactly similar, m all circumstances 
except the one which we aie attempting to investigate . they 
must be m the relation of A B C and B C, or of a b c and b c. 
It is true that this similarity of circumstances needs not 
extend to such as are already known to be immaterial to the 
iesult And m the case of most phenomena we learn at once, 
from the commonest experience, that most of the coexistent 
phenomena of the universe may be either present or absent 
without affecting the given phenomenon, or, if present, are 
present indifferently when the phenomenon does not happen 
and when it does Still, even limiting the identity which is 
required between the two instances, ABO and B C, to such 
circumstances as are not already known to be indifferent, it is 



THE FOUR EXPERIMENTAL METHODS. 


431 


-very seldom that nature affords two instances, of which we 
can be assuied that they stand in this precise relation to one 
another. In the spontaneous operations of natuie there is 
generally such complication and such obscurity, they are 
mostly either on so overwhelmingly large or on so inaccessibly 
minute a scale, we are so ignorant of a great part of the facts 
which really take place, and even those of which we are not 
ignorant aie so multitudinous, and theiefore so seldom ex¬ 
actly alike m any two cases, that a spontaneous experiment, of 
the kind required by the Method of Difference, is commonly 
not to be found When, on the contiary, we obtain a pheno¬ 
menon by an artificial experiment, a pair of instances such as 
the method requnes is obtained almost as a matter of course, 
provided the piocess does not last a long time A certain 
state of surrounding circumstances existed before we com¬ 
menced the experiment, this is B 0 We then introduce A, 
say, for instance, by merely bringing an object from another 
pait of the room, before theie has been time for any change 
m the other elements It is, m short (as M Comte observes), 
the very nature of an experiment, to introduce into the pre¬ 
existing state of circumstances a change peifectly definite 
We choose a previous state of things with which we aie well 
acquainted, so that no unfoieseen alteration m that state is 
likely to pass unobserved, and into this we introduce, as 
rapidly as possible, the phenomenon which we wish to study, 
so that m general we are entitled to feel complete assurance 
that the pre-existing state, and the state which we have pro¬ 
duced, differ m nothing except the presence or absence of that 
phenomenon If a bud is taken from a cage, and instantly 
plunged into carbonic acid gas, the experimentalist may be 
fully assured (at all events after one or two repetitions) that 
no cncumstance capable of causing suffocation had supervened 
m the interim, except the change from immersion m the 
atmosphere to immersion m carbonic acid gas There is one 
doubt, indeed, which may remain m some cases of this descrip¬ 
tion, the effect may have been produced not by the change, 
but by the means employed to pioduce the change. The pos¬ 
sibility, however, of this last supposition generally admits of 



432 


INDUCTION, 


being conclusively tested by otbei experiments. It thus 
appears that m the study of the various kinds of phenomena 
which we can, by oui voluntary agency, modify or contiol, we 
can m general satisfy the requisitions of the Method of Dif¬ 
ference , but that by the spontaneous operations of nature 
those requisitions are seldom fulfilled 

The reverse of this is the case with the Method of Agree¬ 
ment. We do not here require instances of so special and deter¬ 
minate a kind Any instances whatever, m which nature 
presents us with a phenomenon, may be examined for the 
purposes of this method, and if all such instances agree m 
anything, a conclusion of considerable value is already attained. 
We can seldom, indeed, be sure that the one point of agree¬ 
ment is the only one, but this ignorance does not, as m the 
Method of Difference, vitiate the conclusion ; the certainty 
of the result, as far as it goes, is not affected We have 
ascertained one invariable antecedent or consequent, however 
many other invariable antecedents or consequents may still 
remain unascertained If A B C, A D E, A F G, are all equally 
followed by a, then a is an invariable consequent of A If 
ab c, a d e, afg> all number A among tlieir antecedents, then 
A is connected as an antecedent, by some mvanable law, 
with a . But to determine whether this mvanable antecedent 
is a cause, or this invariable consequent an effect, we must be 
able, m addition, to pioduce the one by means of the other, 
or, at least, to obtain that which alone constitutes our assur¬ 
ance of having pioduced anything, namely, an instance m 
which the effect, a, has come into existence, with no other 
change m the pre-existing cncumstances than the addition of 
A And this, if we can do it, is an application of the Method 
of Difference, not of the Method of Agreement. 

It thus appears to be by the Method of Difference alone 
that we can ever, m the way of direct experience, arrive with 
certainty at causes. The Method of Agreement leads only 
to laws of phenomena (as some writers call them, but im¬ 
properly, since laws of causation are also laws of phenomena) 
that is, to uniformities, which either are not laws of causation, 
or m which the question of causation must for the present 



THE FOUR EXPERIMENTAL METHODS. 


438 


remain undecided The Method of Agieement is chiefly to 
be resoited to, as a means of suggesting applications of the 
Method of Difference (as m the last example the companson 
of A B C, AD E, A F G, suggested that A was the antece¬ 
dent on which to tiy the expenment whether it could produce 
a) , or as an mfeiioi resource, m case the Method of Difference 
is impiacticahle, which, as we before showed, generally arises 
from the impossibility of artificially producing the phenomena 
And hence it is that the Method of Agieement, though appli¬ 
cable m principle to either case, is more emphatically the 
method of investigation on those subjects where artificial ex¬ 
perimentation is impossible because on those it is, generally, 
our only resource of a directly inductive nature , while, m the 
phenomena which we can produce at pleasure, the Method of 
Difference generally affords a more efficacious process, which 
will ascertain causes as well as mere laws 

§ 4. There are, however, many cases m which, though 
our power of producing the phenomenon is complete, the 
Method of Difference either cannot be made available at all, 
or not without a previous employment of the Method of 
Agreement. This occurs when the agency by which we can 
produce the phenomenon is not that of one single antecedent, 
but a combination of antecedents, which we have no power of 
sepaiatmg fiom each othei, and exhibiting apait For instance, 
suppose the subject of inquiry to be the cause of the double 
refraction of light. We can produce this phenomenon at 
pleasure, by employing any one of the many substances which 
are known to lefract light m that peculiar manner But if, 
taking one of those substances, as Iceland spar for example, 
we wish to determine on which of the properties of Iceland 
spar this remarkable phenomenon depends, we can make no 
use, for that purpose, of the Method of Diffeience, for we 
cannot find another substance precisely resembling Iceland 
spar except m some one property. The only mode, therefore, 
of prosecuting this inquiry is that afforded by the Method of 
Agreement, by which, m fact, through a comparison of all 
the known substances which have the property of doubly 
vol. i. 28 



434 


INDUCTION. 


refracting light, it was asceitamed that they agree m the 
circumstance of being crystalline substances ; and though the 
converse does not hold, though all crystalline substances have 
not the property of double refraction, it was concluded, with 
reason, that there is a real connexion between these two pro¬ 
perties , that either crystalline structure, or the cause which 
gives rise to that structure, is one of the conditions of double 
refraction 

Out of this employment of the Method of Agreement arises 
a peculiar modification of that method, which is sometimes of 
great avail m the investigation of nature. In cases similar to 
the above, m which it is not possible to obtain the precise pair 
of instances which our second canon requires—instances agree¬ 
ing in every antecedent except A, or m every consequent except 
a , we may yet be able, by a double employment of the Method 
of Agreement, to discover m what the instances which contain 
A or a, differ from those which do not 

If we compare various instances m which a occurs, and 
find that they all have m common the cn cum stance A, and 
(as far as can be observed) no other circumstance, the Method 
of Agreement, so far, bears testimony to a connexion between 
A and a. In order to convert this evidence of connexion into 
proof of causation by the direct Method of Difference, we 
ought to be able, m some one of these instances, as for example 
A B C, to leave out A, and observe whether by doing so, a 
is prevented Now supposing (what is often the case) that we 
are not able to tiy this decisive experiment, yet, provided we 
can by any means discovei what would be its result if we 
could try it, the advantage will be the same Suppose, then, 
that as we previously examined a variety of instances m which 
a occuned, and found them to agree m containing A, so we now 
observe a variety of instances m which a does not occur, and 
find them agree m not containing A, which establishes, by 
the Method of Agreement, the same connexion between the 
absence of A and the absence of a, which was before esta¬ 
blished between their presence As, then, it had been shown 
that whenever A is present a is present, so it being now shown 
that when A is taken away a is removed along with it, we 



THE FOUR EXPERIMENTAL METHODS. 


435 


have by the one proposition A B C, a b c, by the other E C, 
b c, the positive and negative instances which the Method of 
Difference requnes. 

This method may be .called the Indirect Method of Dif¬ 
ference, 01 the Joint Method of Agieement and Diffeience, 
and consists m a double employment of the Method of Agree¬ 
ment, each pi oof being independent of the other, and cono- 
boratmg it But it is not equivalent to a pioof by the direct 
Method of Diffeience. Bor the lequisitions of the Method of 
Difference are not satisfied, unless we can be quite sure either 
that the instances affiimative of a agree m no antecedent 
whatever but A, or that the instances negative of a agiee m 
nothing but the negation of A. Now if it were possible, 
which it never is, to have this assuiance, we should not need 
the joint method, for either of the two sets of instances 
separately would then be sufficient to prove causation. This 
indirect method, therefore, can only be regarded as a great 
extension and impiovement of the Method of Agreement, but 
not as participating m the more cogent nature of the Method 
of Difference. The following may be stated as its canon.— 

Third Canon. 

If tivo or moie instances m which the phenomenon occurs 
have only one circumstance in common, while two or more m- 
stances m which it does not occur have nothing m common 
save the absence of that circumstance, the circumstance m 
which alone the two sets of instances differ, is the effect, or the 
cause, or an indispensable part of the cause, of the phenomenon 

We shall presently see that the Joint Method of Agree¬ 
ment and Difference constitutes, m another respect not yet 
adverted to, an impiovement upon the common Method of 
Agreement, namely, m being unaffected by a characteristic 
imperfection of that method, the natuie of which still remains 
to be pointed out But as we cannot entei into this exposi¬ 
tion without introducing a new element of complexity into 
this long and intricate discussion, I shall postpone it to a sub¬ 
sequent chapter, and shall at once proceed to a statement of 
two other methods, which will complete the enumeration of 

28—2 



436 


INDUCTION, 


the means which mankind possess for exploring the laws of 
nature by specific observation and expenence. 

§ 5 . The first of these has been aptly denominated the 
Method of Eesidues Its principle is very simple. Subduct¬ 
ing fioin any given phenomenon all the poitions which, by 
virtue of preceding inductions, can be assigned to known 
causes, the remainder will be the effect of the antecedents 
which had been overlooked, or of which the effect was as yet 
an unknown quantity 

Suppose, as before, that we have the antecedents ABC, 
followed by the consequents a b c, and that by pievious induc¬ 
tions (founded, we will suppose, on the Method of Difference) 
we have ascertained the causes of some of these effects, or the 
effects of some of these causes, and are thence appnsed that 
the effect of A is a, and that the effect of B is b. Subtracting 
the sum of these effects from the total phenomenon, there 
remains c, which now, without any fresh experiments, we may 
know to be the effect of C This Method of Eesidues is m 
truth a peculiar modification of the Method of Difference If 
the instance A B C, a b c, could have been compared with a 
single instance A B, a b, we should have proved C to he the 
cause of c } by the common process of the Method of Differ¬ 
ence. In the present case, however, instead of a single 
instance A B, we have had to study separately the causes 
A and B, and to infer from the effects which they pro¬ 
duce separately, what effect they must pioduce m the case 
ABC where they act together Of the two instances, there¬ 
fore, which the Method of Difference requires,—the one posi¬ 
tive, the other negative,—the negative one, or that m which 
the given phenomenon is absent, is not the direct result of 
observation and experiment, but has been arrived at by deduc¬ 
tion. As one of the forms of the Method of Difference, the 
Method of Eesidues partakes of its rigorous certainty, pro¬ 
vided the previous inductions, those which gave the effects of 
A and B, were obtained by the same infallible method, and 
provided we are certain that C is the onhj antecedent to which 
the residual phenomenon c can be referred, the only agent of 



THE FOUR EXPERIMENTAL METHODS. 437 

winch we had not already calculated and subducted the effect. 
But as we can nevei he quite ceitam of tins, the evidence de- 
uved fiom the Method of Eesidues is not complete unless we 
can obtain 0 artificially and tiy it separately, or unless its 
agency, when once suggested, can he accounted for, and proved 
deductively fiom known laws 

Even with these reseivations, the Method of Residues is 
one of the most important among our msti uments of dis¬ 
covery. Of all the methods of investigating laws of nature, 
this is the most fertile m unexpected results , often informing 
us of sequences m which neither the cause nor the effect were 
sufficiently conspicuous to attract of themselves the attention 
of observeis The agent C may be an obscuie circumstance, 
not likely to have been perceived unless sought for, nor likely 
to have been sought for until attention had been awakened by 
the insufficiency of the obvious causes to account for the whole 
of the effect And c may be so disguised by its intermixture 
with a and b, that it would scaicely have presented itself 
spontaneously as a subject of sepaiate study. Of these uses of 
the method, we shall presently cite some remaikable examples. 
The canon of the Method of Eesidues is as follows .— 

Fourth Canon. 

Subduct from any phenomenon such part as is known bypre- 
i ious inductions to be the effect of certain antecedents, and the 
residue of the phenomenon is the effect of the remaining ante¬ 
cedents. 

§ 6. There remains a class of laws which it is imprac¬ 
ticable to ascertain by any of the three methods which I have 
attempted to charactenze, namely, the laws of those Permanent 
Causes, or indestructible natural agents, which it is impossible 
either to exclude or to isolate, which we can neither hinder 
from being present, nor contrive that they shall be present 
alone. It would appear at first sight that we could by no means 
separate the effects of these agents fiom the effects of those 
other phenomena with which they cannot be prevented from 
coexisting In respect, indeed, to most of the permanent 
causes, no such difficulty exists, since though we cannot 



488 


INDUCTION. 


eliminate them as coexisting facts, we can eliminate them as 
influencing agents, by simply trying oui expeximent m a local 
situation beyond the limits of their influence The pendulum, 
for example, has its oscillations disturbed by the vicinity of a 
mountain we remove the pendulum to a sufficient distance 
from the mountain, and the disturbance ceases iiom these 
data we can deteimme by the Method of Difference, the amount 
of effect due to the mountain , and beyond a ceitain distance 
everything goes on piecisely as it would do if the mountain 
exeicised no influence whatever, which, accordingly, we, with 
sufficient reason, conclude to be the fact. 

The difficulty, therefore, m applying the methods already 
treated of to deteimme the effects of Permanent Causes, is 
confined to the cases in which it is impossible foi us to get 
out of the local limits of their influence. The pendulum can 
be removed from the influence of the mountain, but it cannot 
be removed from the influence of the earth we cannot take 
away the earth from the pendulum, nor the pendulum fionx 
the earth, to asceitain whether it would continue to vibrate 
if the action which the earth exerts upon it were withdrawn. 
On what evidence, then, do we ascribe its vibiations to the 
earth’s influence ? Not on any sanctioned by the Method of 
Difference, for one of the two instances, the negative in¬ 
stance, is wanting Nor by the Method of Agreement, for 
though all pendulums agree m this, that during their oscil¬ 
lations the earth is always present, why may we not as well 
ascribe the phenomenon to the sun, which is equally a co¬ 
existent fact m all the experiments ? It is evident that to 
establish even so simple a fact of causation as this, there was 
required some method over and above those which we have 
yet examined. 

As another example, let us take the phenomenon Heat. 
Independently of all hypothesis as to the real nature of the 
agency so called, this fact is certain, that we are unable to 
exhaust any body of the whole of its heat. It is equally cer¬ 
tain, that no one ever perceived heat not emanating from a 
body Being unable, then, to separate Body and Heat, we 
cannot effect such a variation of circumstances as the fore- 



THE FOUR EXPERIMENTAL METHODS. 


439 


going three methods requhe , we cannot ascertain, by those 
methods, what portion of the phenomena exhibited by any 
body is due to the heat contained m it. If we could observe 
a body with its heat, and the same body entirely divested of 
heat, the Method of Difference would show the effect due to 
the heat, apart from that due to the body. If we could observe 
heat under circumstances agreeing in nothing but heat, and 
therefore not characterized also by the presence of a body, we 
could ascertain the effects of heat, from an instance of heat 
with a body and an instance of heat without a body, by the 
Method of Agreement, or we could determine by the Method 
of Difference what effect was due to the body, when the 
remainder which was due to the heat would he given hv the 
Method of Eesidues. But we can do none of these things ; 
and without them the application of any of the three methods 
to the solution of this problem would be illusory. It would 
be idle, for instance, to attempt to ascertain the effect of heat 
by subtracting from the phenomena exhibited by a body, all 
that is due to its other properties, for as we have never been 
able to observe any bodies without a portion of heat m them, 
effects due to that heat might form a part of the very results, 
which we were affecting to subtract m order that the effect of 
heat might be shown by the residue. 

If, therefoie, there were no other methods of experimental 
investigation than these three, we should be unable to deter¬ 
mine the effects due to heat as a cause. But we have still a 
resource Though we cannot exclude an antecedent altogether, 
we may be able to produce, or nature may produce for us, 
some modification m it. By a modification is here meant, a 
change m it, not amounting to its total removal. If some 
modification m the antecedent A is always followed by a 
change in the consequent a, the other consequents b and c 
remaining the same; or vice versa, if every change m a is 
found to have been preceded by some modification m A, none 
being observable m any of the other antecedents, we may 
safely conclude that a is, wholly or m part, an effect traceable 
to A, or at least m some way connected with it through 
causation. For example, m the case of heat, though we can- 



440 


INDUCTION. 


not expel it altogether from any body, we can modify it m 
quantity, we can mciease ol dimmish it; and doing so, we 
find by the vanous methods of expeumentation or observation 
alieady tieated of, that such mciease or diminution of heat is 
followed by expansion or contraction of the body In this 
xnannei we amve at the conclusion, otheiwise unattainable by 
us, that one of the effects of heat is to enlaige the dimensions 
of bodies, 01 what is the same thing m othei woids, to widen 
the distances between their particles. 

A change m a thing, not amounting to its total removal, 
that is, a change which leaves it still the same thing it was, 
must be a change either in its quantity, 01 m some of its 
vanable relations to other things, of which variable lelations 
the principal is its position m space. In the previous example, 
the modification which was produced m the antecedent was an 
alteration m its quantity. Let us now suppose the question to 
be, what influence the moon exerts on the surface of the earth. 
We cannot try an expenment m the absence of the moon, 
so as to observe what teirestnal phenomena her annihilation 
would put an end to, but when we find that all the variations 
m the position of the moon aie followed by coiresponding 
variations m the time and place of high water, the place being 
always either the part of the earth which is neaiest to, or that 
which is most remote from, the moon, we have ample evidence 
that the moon is, wholly or partially, the cause which deter¬ 
mines the tides. It very commonly happens, as it does m this 
instance, that the variations of an effect are correspondent, or 
analogous, to those of its cause , as the moon moves faither 
towards the east, the high water point does the same but this 
is not an indispensable condition , as may be seen m the same 
example, for along with that high water point there is at the 
same instant another high water point diametrically opposite 
to it, and which, therefore, of necessity, moves towards the 
west, as the moon, followed by the nearer of the tide waves, 
advances towards the east: and yet both these motions are 
equally effects of the moons motion 

That the oscillations of the pendulum are caused by the 
earth, is proved by similar evidence. Those oscillations take 



THE FOUR EXPERIMENTAL METHODS. 441 

place between equidistant points on the two sides of a line, 
which, being perpendiculai to the eaith, varies with every 
variation m the earth s position, eithei m space or relatively to 
the object Speaking accurately, we only know by the method 
now chaiactenzed, that all terrestnal bodies tend to the earth, 
and not to some unknown fixed point lying m the same direc¬ 
tion In every twenty-four hours, by the earths rotation, the 
line diawn from the body at right angles to the earth coincides 
successively with all the ladn of a circle, and m the course of 
six months the place of that circle varies by nearlv two 
hundred millions of miles, yet m all these changes of the 
earths position, the line m which bodies tend to fall continues 
to be dnected towards it which pioves that teirestnal gravity 
is dnected to the earth, and not, as was once fancied by some, 
to a fixed point of space. 

The method by which these results weie obtained, may be 
termed the Method of Concomitant Variations. it is regulated 
by the following canon — 

Fifth Canon. 

Whatever phenomenon vanes in any manner whenever 
another phenomenon vanes in some particular manner , is 
either a cause or an effect of that phenomenon , or is connected 
with it through some fact of causation. 

The last clause is subjoined, because it by no means follows 
when two phenomena accompany each other m their vanations, 
that the one is cause and the other effect. The same thing 
may, and indeed must happen, supposing them to be two dif¬ 
ferent effects of a common cause: and by this method alone it 
would never be possible to ascertain which of the suppositions 
is the true one. The only way to solve the doubt would be 
that which we have so often adverted to, viz. by endeavouiing 
to ascertain whether we can produce the one set of variations 
by means of the other. In the case of heat, for example, by 
increasing the temperature of a body we increase its bulk, but 
by increasing its bulk we do not increase its temperature, on 
the contrary, (as m the rarefaction of air under the receiver of 
an air-pump,) we generally dimmish it. therefore heat is not 



442 


INDUCTION. 


an effect, but a cause, of mciease of bulk If we cannot our¬ 
selves produce the vanations, we must endeavour, though it is 
an attempt which is seldom successful, to find them pioduced 
by natuie m some case m which the pie-existing circumstances 
are perfectly known to us 

It is scarcely necessary to say, that m order to ascertain 
the uniform concomitance of vanations m the effect with varia¬ 
tions in the cause, the same precautions must be used as m 
any other case of the determination of an mvanable sequence. 
We must endeavour to retain all the other antecedents un¬ 
changed, while that particular one is subjected to the requisite 
series of variations, 01 m other words, that we may be war¬ 
ranted m inferring causation from concomitance of variations, 
the concomitance itself must be pioved by th£ Method of 
Difference 

It might at first appear that the Method of Concomitant 
Yanations assumes a new axiom, or law of causation m 
general, namely, that every modification of the cause is fol¬ 
lowed b} a change m the effect And it does usually happen 
that when a phenomenon A causes a phenomenon a, any 
variation m the quantity or m the various relations of A, is 
uniformly followed by a variation m the quantity or relations 
of a To take a familiar instance, that of gravitation. The 
sun causes a certain tendency to motion m the earth; here 
we have cause and effect, but that tendency is towards the 
sun, and therefore varies in direction as the sun varies m the 
relation of position, and moreover the tendency vanes m 
intensity, m a certain numerical coirespondence to the suns 
distance from the earth, that is, according to another relation 
of the sun. Thus we see that there is not only an invariable 
connexion between the sun and the earth’s gravitation, but 
that two of the relations of the sun, its position with respect 
to the earth and its distance from the earth, are invariably 
connected as antecedents with the quantity and direction of 
the earth’s gravitation. The cause of the earth’s gravitating 
at all, is simply the sun, but the cause of its gravitating with 
a given intensity and in a given direction, is the existence of 
the sun in a given direction and at a given distance. It is not 



THE FOUR EXPERIMENTAL METHODS. 


443 


strange that a modified cause, which is m truth a different 
cause, should produce a different effect 

Although it is for the most part tiue that a modification of 
the cause is followed by a modification of the effect, the 
Method of Concomitant Variations does not, however, pie- 
suppose this as an axiom. It only requires the convexse 
proposition, that anything on whose modifications, modifi¬ 
cations of an effect are invariably consequent, must he the 
cause (or connected with the cause) of that effect, a propo¬ 
sition, the truth of which is evident, for if the thing itself 
had no influence on the effect, neither could the modifications 
of the thing have any influence If the stars have no power 
over the foitunes of mankind, it is implied in the very terms, 
that the conjunctions or oppositions of different stais can have 
no such power. 

Although the most striking applications of the Method of 
Concomitant Vanations take place m the cases m which the 
Method of Difference, strictly so called, is impossible, its use 
is not confined to those cases, it may often usefully follow 
after the Method of Difference, to give additional piecision to 
a solution which that has found When by the Method of 
Difference it has first been ascertained that a ceitain object 
produces a ceitam effect, the Method of Concomitant Varia¬ 
tions may be usefully called in, to determine according to what 
law the quantity or the different relations of the effect follow 
those of the cause. 

§ 7 The case m which this method admits of the most 
extensive employment, is that m which the variations of the 
cause are variations of quantity. Of such vanations we may 
m general affirm with safety, that they will be attended not 
only with vanations, but with similar variations, of the effect: 
the proposition, that more of the cause is followed by more of 
the effect, being a corollary from the principle of the Compo¬ 
sition of Causes, which, as we have seen, is the general rule of 
causation, cases of the opposite description, m which causes 
change their properties on being conjoined with one another, 
being, on the contrary, special and exceptional. Suppose, 



444 


INDUCTION. 


then, that ■when A changes m quantity, a also changes m 
quantity, and in such a mannei that we can tiace the numerical 
relation which the changes of the one beai to such changes of 
the other as take place within our limits of observation. We 
may then, with certain pi ecautions, safely conclude that the 
same numerical 1 elation will hold beyond those limits If, for 
instance, we find that when A is double, a is double, that 
when A is treble or quadruple, a rs treble or quadiuple, we 
may conclude that if A were a half or a thud, a would be a 
half or a thud, and finally, that if A were annihilated, a 
would be annihilated, and that a is wholly the effect of A, or 
wholly the effect of the same cause with A And so with any 
other numencal relation according to which A and a would 
vanish simultaneously, as for instance, if a weie proportional 
to the square of A If, on the other hand, a is not wholly 
the effect of A, but yet vanes when A varies, it is pi obably a 
mathematical function not of A alone, but of A and something 
else. its changes, for example, may be such as would occur if 
part of it lemamed constant, or varied on some othei prin¬ 
ciple, and the iemamder varied m some numencal relation to 
the variations of A In that case, when A diminishes, a will 
be seen to appioach not towards zero, but towards some other 
limit. and when the senes of variations is such as to indicate 
what that limit is, if constant, or the law of its variation if 
variable, the limit will exactly measuie how much of a is the 
effect of some other and independent cause, and the iemamder 
will be the effect of A (or of the cause of A). 

These conclusions, however, must not be diawn without 
certain precautions. In the first place, the possibility of 
drawing them at all, manifestly supposes that we aie ac¬ 
quainted not only with the variations, but with the absolute 
quantities both of A and a. If we do not know the total 
quantities, we cannot, of course, determine the real numencal 
relation according to which those quantities vary It is there¬ 
fore an error to conclude, as some have concluded, that because 
increase of heat expands bodies, that is, increases the dis¬ 
tance between their particles, therefore the distance is wholly 
the effect of heat, and that if we could entirely exhaust the 



THE FOUR EXPERIMENTAL METHODS. 


445 


body of its heat, the paitides would be m complete contact. 
This is no more than a guess, and of the most hazardous sort, 
not a legitimate induction . for since we neither know how 
much heat there is m any body, nor what is the real distance 
between any two of its particles, wc cannot judge whether the 
contraction of the distance does 01 does not follow the diminu¬ 
tion of the quantity of heat accoidmg to such a numerical le- 
lation that the two quantities would vanish simultaneously. 

In contiast with this, let us consider a case m which the 
absolute quantities are known, the case contemplated m the 
first law of motion, viz that all bodies m motion continue to 
move m a stiaight line with umfoim velocity until acted upon 
by some new foice. This asseition is m open opposition to 
fiist appealances, all terrestnal objects, when m motion, 
gradually abate then velocity and at last stop, w T hich accoid- 
mgly the ancients, with then mductio per enumerationem svm- 
phcem, imagined to be the law. Every moving body, however, 
encounteis various obstacles, as friction, the resistance of the 
atmospheie, &e, which we know by daily experience to be 
causes capable of destroying motion It was suggested that 
the whole of the retaidation might be owing to these causes 
How was this mquned into ? If the obstacles could have 
been entnelv removed, the case would have been amenable to 
the Method of Difference They could not be removed, they 
could only be diminished, and the case, therefore, admitted 
only of the Method of Concomitant Variations This accord¬ 
ingly being employed, it was found that every diminution of 
the obstacles diminished the retardation of the motion. and 
inasmuch as in this case (unlike the case of heat) the total 
quantities both of the antecedent and of the consequent -were 
known , it was practicable to estimate, with an approach to 
accuiacv, both the amount of the retardation and the amount 
of the retarding causes, or resistances, and to judge how near 
they both weie to being exhausted ; and it appeared that the 
effect dwindled as rapidly, and at each step was as far on the 
road towards annihilation, as the cause was The simple 
oscillation of a weight suspended from a fixed point, and moved 
a little out of the perpendicular, which m ordinary circum- 



446 


INDUCTION. 


stances lasts but a few minutes, was prolonged m Bordas ex¬ 
periments to more than thirty houis, by diminishing as much 
as possible the friction at the point of suspension, and by 
making the body oscillate m a space exhausted as nearly as 
possible of its air. Theie could therefore be no hesitation m 
assigning the whole of the retardation of motion to the influence 
of the obstacles , and since, after subducting this retardation 
from the total phenomenon, the remainder was an uniform velo¬ 
city, the result was the proposition known as the fiist law of 
motion. 

There is also another characteristic uncertainty affecting 
the inference that the law of variation which the quantities 
observe within our limits of observation, will hold beyond 
those limits There is of course, m the first instance, the 
possibility that beyond the limits, and m cncum stances there¬ 
fore of which we have no direct experience, some counteract¬ 
ing cause might develop itself, either a new agent, or a new 
property of the agents concerned, which lies doimant m the 
circumstances we are able to observe. This is an element of 
uncertainty which enters laigely into all our predictions of 
effects , but it is not peculiarly applicable to the Method of 
Concomitant Variations. The uncertainty, however, of which 
I am about to speak, is characteristic of that method, espe¬ 
cially m the cases m which the extreme limits of our observa¬ 
tion are very narrow, m comparison with the possible variations 
in the quantities of the phenomena. Any one who has the 
slightest acquaintance with mathematics, is aware that very 
different laws of variation may produce numerical results 
which differ hut slightly from one another within narrow 
limits, and it is often only when the absolute amounts of 
variation are considerable, that the difference between the 
results given by one law and by another becomes appreciable. 
When, therefore, such variations m the quantity of the ante¬ 
cedents as we have the means of observing, are small m com¬ 
parison with the total quantities, there is much danger lest 
we should mistake the numerical law, and he led to miscalcu¬ 
late the variations which would take place beyond the limits; a 
miscalculation which would vitiate any conclusion respecting 



THE FOUR EXPERIMENTAL METHODS. 


447 


the dependence of the effect upon the cause, that could he 
founded on those variations. Examples are not wanting of 
such mistakes. “ The formulae,” says Sir John Herschel,* 
“ which have been empirically deduced for the elasticity of 
steam, (till veiy recently,) and those for the resistance of 
fluids, and other similar subjects,” when relied on beyond the 
limits of the obseivations from which they were deduced, “ have 
almost invariably failed to support the theoretical structures 
which have been erected on them.” 

In this uncertainty, the conclusion we may draw from the 
concomitant vanations of a and A, to the existence of an 
invariable and exclusive connexion between them, or to the 
permanency of the same numeiical relation between their 
variations when the quantities are much greatei or smaller 
than those which we have had the means of observing, cannot 
he considered to rest on a complete induction All that m 
such a case can be regaided as proved on the subject of causa¬ 
tion is, that there is some connexion between the two pheno¬ 
mena , that A, or something which can influence A, must be 
one of the causes which collectively determine a. We may, 
however, feel assured that the relation which we have observed 
to exist between the variations of A and a, will hold true m all 
cases which fall between the same extreme limits, that is, 
wherever the utmost increase or diminution m which the result 
has been found by observation to coincide with the law, is not 
exceeded. 

The four methods which it has now been attempted to de¬ 
scribe, are the only possible modes of experimental inquiry— 
of dnect induction a postenon, as distinguished from deduc¬ 
tion at least, I know not, nor am able to imagine, any 
otheis And even of these, the Method of Residues, as we 
have seen, is not independent of deduction, though, as it 
also requnes specific experience, it may, without impro¬ 
priety, be included among methods of direct observation and 
experiment 

These, then, with such assistance as can be obtained fiom 


Discourse on the Study of Natural Philosophy, p. 179 



448 


INDUCTION, 


Deduction, compose the available resources of the human mind 
for ascertaining the laws of the succession of phenomena 
Before proceeding to point out certain circumstances, by which 
the employment of these methods is subjected to an immense 
increase of complication and of difficulty, it is expedient to 
illustrate the use of the methods, by suitable examples drawn 
from actual physical investigations These, accordingly, will 
form the subject of the succeeding chapter 



CHAPTER IX. 


MISCELLANEOUS EXAMPLES OF THE FOUR METHODS. 

§ 1. I shall select, as a first example, an interesting 
speculation of one of the most eminent of theoretical chemists, 
Baron Liebig. The object in view, is to ascertain the imme¬ 
diate cause of the death produced by metallic poisons 

Arsemous acid, and the salts of lead, bismuth, coppei, 
and meicuiy, if introduced into the animal organism, except 
m the smallest doses, destroy life These facts have long 
been known, as insulated truths of the lowest order of 
generalization, but it was reserved for Liebig, by an apt em¬ 
ployment of the first two of our methods of experimental 
inquiry, to connect these truths together by a higher induc¬ 
tion, pointing out what property, common to all these dele¬ 
terious substances, is the really operating cause of their fatal 
effect 

When solutions of these substances are placed m suffi¬ 
ciently close contact with many animal products, albumen, 
milk, muscular fibre, and animal membranes, the acid or salt 
leaves the water m which it was dissolved, and enters into com¬ 
bination with the animal substance. which substance, after 
being thus acted upon, is found to have lost its tendency to 
spontaneous decomposition, or putrefaction 

Observation also shows, in cases where death has been 
produced by these poisons, that the parts of the body with 
which the poisonous substances have been brought into con¬ 
tact, do not afterwards putrefy. 

And, finally, when the poison has been supplied m too 
small a quantity to destroy life, eschars are produced, that is, 
certain superficial portions of the tissues are destroyed, which 
are afterwards thrown off by the reparative process taking 
place m the healthy parts. 

VOL. i. 


29 



450 


INDUCTION. 


These three sets of instances admit of being treated accord¬ 
ing to the Method of Agreement. In all of them the metallic 
compounds are brought into contact with the substances which 
compose the human or animal body ; and the instances do not 
seem to agiee m any other circumstance. The remaining 
antecedents are as different, and even opposite, as they could 
possibly be made ; for m some the animal substances exposed 
to the action of the poisons are m a state of life, m others 
only m a state of organization, m others not even m that. 
And what is the result which follows m all the cases 9 
The conversion of the animal substance (by combination 
with the poison) into a chemical compound, held together 
by so powerful a force as to resist the subsequent action 
of the ordinary causes of decomposition. Now, organic life 
(the necessary condition of sensitive life) consisting m a 
continual state of decomposition and recomposition of the 
different organs and tissues, whatever incapacitates them for 
this decomposition destroys life And thus the pioximate 
cause of the death produced by tins description of poisons, 
is ascertained, as far as tbe Method of Agreement can 
ascertain it. 

Let us now bring our conclusion to tbe test of tbe Method 
of Difference. Setting out from the cases already mentioned, 
m which the antecedent is the piesence of substances forming 
with the tissues a compound incapable of putrefaction, 
(and a fortiori incapable of the chemical actions which con¬ 
stitute life,) and the consequent is death, either of the whole 
oiganism, or of some portion of it, let us compare with these 
cases other cases, as much resembling them as possible, 
but m which that effect is not produced And, first, “ many 
insoluble basic salts of arsemous acid are known not to 
be poisonous. Tbe substance called alkargen, discovered 
by Bunsen, which contains a very large quantity of arsenic, 
and approaches very closely m composition to the organic 
arsemous compounds found m the body, has not the slightest 
injurious action upon the organism/’ Now when these 
substances are brought into contact with the tissues m 
any way, they do not combine with them, they do not arrest 



EXAMPLES OF THE FOUR METHODS. 


451 


their progiess to decomposition. As far, therefore, as these 
instances go, it appears that when the effect is absent, 
it is by reason of the absence of that antecedent which 
we had already good ground for considering as the proximate 
cause. 

But the rigorous conditions of the Method of Difference 
are not yet satisfied, for we cannot be sure that these un- 
poisonous bodies agree with the poisonous substances m every 
property, except the particular one, of entering into a difficultly 
decomposable compound with the animal tissues. To render 
the method strictly applicable, we need an instance, not of a 
different substance, but of one of the very same substances, m 
circumstances which would prevent it from foimmg, with the 
tissues, the sort of compound in question, and then, if death 
does not follow, our case is made out Now such instances 
are afforded by the antidotes to these poisons For example, 
m case of poisoning by arsemous acid, if hydrated peroxide of 
iron is administered, the destructive agency is instantly checked. 
Now this peroxide is known to combine with the acid, and 
form a compound, which, being insoluble, cannot act at all on 
animal tissues. So, again, sugar is a well-known antidote to 
poisoning by salts of copper, and sugar reduces those salts 
either into metallic copper, 01 into the red sub oxide, neither 
of which enters into combination with animal matter. The 
disease called painters colic, so common in manufactones of 
white lead, is unknown where the workmen are accustomed to 
take, as a preservative, sulphuric acid lemonade (a solution of 
sugar rendered acid by sulphuric acid) Now diluted sul¬ 
phuric acid has the property of decomposing all compounds of 
lead with organic matter, or of preventing them from being 
formed. 

There is another class of instances, of the nature required 
by the Method of Difference, which seem at fiist sight to con¬ 
flict with the theory. Soluble salts of silver, such for instance 
as the nitrate, have the same stiffening antiseptic effect on 
decomposing animal substances as corrosive sublimate and 
the most deadly metallic poisons, and when applied to 
the external parts of the body, the nitrate is a powerful 

£ 9—2 



452 


INDUCTION. 


caustic, depriving those parts of all active vitality, and 
causing them to he thiovm off by the neighbouring living 
structures, m the form of an eschar. The nitrate and the 
other salts of silver ought, then, it would seem, if the theory 
be correct, to be poisonous, yet they may be administered 
internally with perfect impunity. From this apparent excep¬ 
tion arises the strongest confirmation which the theory has yet 
received. Nitrate of silver, m spite of its chemical pro¬ 
pel ties, does not poison when introduced into the stomach , 
but in the stomach, as m all animal liquids, there is common 
salt, and m the stomach there is also free muriatic acid 
These substances opeiate as natural antidotes, combining with 
the nitrate, and if its quantity is not too great, immediately 
converting it into chloride of silver, a substance very slightly 
soluble, and therefore incapable of combining with the tissues, 
although to the extent of its solubility it has a medicinal 
influence, though an entnely different class of organic 
actions. 

The preceding instances have afforded an induction of a 
high order of conclusiveness, illustrative of the two simplest of 
our four methods, though not rising to the maximum of cer¬ 
tainty which the Method of Difference, m its most perfect 
exemplification, is capable of affording. For (let us not 
forget) the positive instance and the negative one which the 
rigour of that method requires, ought to differ only m the 
presence or absence of one single circumstance. Now, m the 
preceding argument, they differ m the presence or absence not 
of a single circumstance , but of a single substance' and as 
every substance has innumerable properties, theie is no know¬ 
ing what number of real differences are involved m what is 
nominally and apparently only one difference. It is conceiv¬ 
able that the antidote, the peroxide of iron for example, may 
counteract the poison through some other of its properties than 
that of forming an insoluble compound with it; and if so, the 
theory would fall to the ground, so far as it is supported by 
that instance This source of uncertainty, which is a serious 
hindrance to all extensive generalizations m chemistry, is how¬ 
ever reduced m the present case to almost the lowest degree 



EXAMPLES OF THE FOUR METHODS. 


453 


possible, when we find that not only one substance, but many 
substances, possess the capacity of acting as antidotes to 
metallic poisons, and that all these agiee m the pioperty of 
forming insoluble compounds with the poisons, while they 
cannot be asceitamed to agiee m any other propeity what¬ 
soever. We have thus, m favour of the theoiv, all the evidence 
which can be obtained by what we termed the Indirect Method 
of Difference, or the Joint Method of Agreement and Differ¬ 
ence , the evidence of which, though it never can amount to 
that of the Method of Difference piopeily so called, may ap¬ 
proach indefinitely neai to it 

§ 2 . Let the object be # to ascertain the law of what is 
termed induced electricity, to find undei what conditions any 
electrified body, whether positively or negatively electrified, 
gives rise to a contiaiy electnc state in some other body adja¬ 
cent to it. 

The most familiar exemplification of the phenomenon to he 
investigated is the following. Aiound the prime conductors of 
an electrical machine, the atmosphere to some distance, or any 
conducting surface suspended m that atmosphere, is found to 
he m an electnc condition opposite to that of the pnme con¬ 
ductor itself. Near and around the positive prime conductor 
there is negative electncity, and near and around the negative 
pnme conductor there is positive electricity When pith halls 
aie brought near to either of the conductors, they become elec- 
tnfied with the opposite electncity to it, either receiving a 
share from the already electrified atmosphere by conduction 
or acted upon by the direct inductive influence of the conductor 
itself they aie then attracted by the conductor to which they 
are m opposition, or, if withdrawn m their electnfied state, 

* Por tills speculation, as for many other of my scientific illustrations, 
I am indebted to Professor Bam, of Aberdeen, who has since, m his profound 
treatises entitled “The Senses and the Intellect,” and “The Emotions and the 
Will,” earned the analytic investigation of the mental phenomena according 
to the methods of physical science, to the most advanced point which it has yet 
reached, and has worthily inscribed his name among the successive constructors 
of an edifice to which Hartley, Brown, and James Mill had each contributed 
their part 



454 


INDUCTION. 


they will be attracted by any othei oppositely charged body. 
In like manner the band, if biougkt near enough to the con¬ 
ductor, receives or gives an electric discharge, now we have 
no evidence that a chaiged conductor can be suddenly dis- 
ohaiged unless by the approach of a body oppositely electri¬ 
fied. In the case, therefore, of the electric machine, it appears 
that the accumulation of electricity m an insulated conductor 
is always accompanied by the excitement of the contrary elec¬ 
tricity m the sunoundmg atmospbeie, and m every conductor 
placed near the foimer conductor It does not seem possible, 
nr this case, to produce one electncity by itself. 

Let us now examine all the other instances which we can 
obtain, resembling this instance m the given consequent, 
namely, the evolution of an opposite electricity m the neigh - 
bouihood of an electrified body. As one remaikable instance 
we have the Leyden jar, and aftei the splendid experiments 
of Earadav m complete and final establishment of the substan¬ 
tial identity of magnetism and electricity, we may cite the 
magnet, both the natural and the electro-magnet, in neither of 
winch it is possible to produce one kind of electncity by itself, 
01 to charge one pole without charging an opposite pole with 
the contrary electricity at the same time We cannot have a 
magnet with one pole if we break a natural loadstone into a 
thousand pieces, each piece will have its two oppositely elec¬ 
trified poles complete within itself In the voltaic circuit, 
again, we cannot have one current without its opposite In 
the ordinary electnc machine, the glass cylinder or plate, and 
the rubber, acquire opposite electricities 

From all these instances, treated by the Method of Agree¬ 
ment, a general law appears to result The instances embrace 
all the known modes m which a body can become charged with 
electricity, and m all of them there is found, as a concomitant 
or consequent, the excitement of the opposite electric state m 
some other body or bodies It seems to follow that the two 
facts aie invariably connected, and that the excitement of elec¬ 
tricity m any body has for one of its necessary conditions the 
possibility of a simultaneous excitement of the opposite elec¬ 
tricity m some neighbouring body 



EXAMPLES OF THE FOUR METHODS. 


455 


As the two contrary electricities can only he produced 
together, &o they can only cease together This may be shown 
by an application of the Method of Difference to the example 
of the Leyden jar. It needs scarcely be here remarked that m 
the Leyden jar, electricity can be accumulated and*retained m 
considerable quantity, by the contrivance of having two con¬ 
ducting surfaces of equal extent, and parallel to each other 
through the whole of that extent, with a non-conducting sub¬ 
stance such as glass between them When one side of the jar 
is charged positively, the other is charged negatively, and it 
was by vntue of this fact that the Leyden jar served just now 
as an instance m our employment of the Method of Agree¬ 
ment Now it is impossible to discharge one of the coatings 
unless the other can be dischaiged at the same time. A con¬ 
ductor held to the positive side cannot convey away any elec¬ 
tricity unless an equal quantity be allowed to pass from the 
negative side if one coating be perfectly insulated, the charge 
is safe. The dissipation of one must proceed pan passu with 
that of the other. 

The law thus strongly indicated admits of corroboration 
by the Method of Concomitant Variations. The Leyden jar 
is capable of receiving a much higher charge than can ordi¬ 
narily be given to the conductor of an electrical machine. 
Now in the case of the Leyden jar, the metallic surface which 
receives the induced electricity is a conductor exactly similar 
to that which receives the primary charge, and is therefore as 
susceptible of receiving and letammg the one electricity, as 
the opposite surface of receiving and retaining the other, but 
m the machine, the neighbouring body which is to be op¬ 
positely electrified is the surrounding atmospheie, or any body 
casually brought neai to the conductor, and as these are gene¬ 
rally much inferior m their capacity of becoming electrified, to 
the conductor itself, their limited power imposes a correspond¬ 
ing limit to the capacity of the conductor for being charged 
As the capacity of the neighbouring body for supporting the 
opposition increases, a higher charge becomes possible. and 
to this appears to be owing the great superiority of the Leyden 
jar. 



456 


INDUCTION. 


A further and most decisive confirmation by the Method 
of Difference, is to he found m one of Faraday’s experiments 
m the course of his researches on the subject of induced 
electricity 

Since common or machine electricity, and voltaic electn- 
citv, may be considered for the present puipose to be identical, 
Faraday wished to know whether, as the pume conductor de- 
v el opes opposite electricity upon a conductor m its vicinity, so 
a voltaic cunent lunmng along a wire would induce an oppo¬ 
site cuirent upon another wne laid parallel to it at a short 
distance Now this case is similar to the cases previously ex¬ 
amined, m every encumstance except the one to which we 
have ascribed the effect. We found m the former instances 
that whenever electncity of one kind was excited m one body, 
electricity of the opposite kind must be excited m a neigh¬ 
bouring body. Eut m Faraday’s experiment this indispensable 
opposition exists within the wire itself From the nature of a 
voltaic chaige, the two opposite cunents necessaiy to the ex¬ 
istence of each other are both accommodated m one wire, and 
there is no need of another wne placed beside it to contain one 
of them, m the same way as the Leyden jar must have a posi¬ 
tive and a negative surface The exciting cause can and does 
produce all the effect which its laws require, independently of 
any electric excitement of a neighbouring body. Now the 
result of the experiment with the second wire was, that no op¬ 
posite cuirent was produced. There was an instantaneous 
effect at the closing and breaking of the voltaic circuit, electric 
inductions appeared when the two wires were moved to and 
fiom one another, but these are phenomena of a different class. 
Theie was no induced electricity m the sense m which this is 
predicated of the Leyden jar, there was no sustained current 
running up the one wire while an opposite current ran down 
the neighbouring wire; and this alone would have been a true 
parallel case to the other. 

It thus appears by the combined evidence of the Method of 
Agreement, the Method of Concomitant Variations, and the 
most rigorous form of the Method of Difference, that neither 
of the two kinds of electncity can be excited without an equal 



EXAMPLES OF THE FOUR METHODS. 


457 


excitement of the other and opposite kind . that both are effects 
of the same cause, that the possibility of the one is a condition 
of the possibility of the othei, and the quantity of the one an 
impassable limit to the quantity of the other A scientific 
lesult of consideiable interest m itself, and lllustiatmg those 
three methods m a manner both characteristic and easily 
intelligible.* 

§ 3 Our thud example shall be extracted from Sir John 
Herschel’s Discourse on the Study of Natural Philosophy, a 
woik replete -with happily-selected exemplifications of induc¬ 
tive processes fiom almost every department of physical science, 
and m which alone, of all books which I have met with, the 
four methods of induction are distinctly recognised, though 
not so clearly characterized and defined, nor their coir elation 
so fully shown, as has appeared to me desirable. The present 
example is descnbed by Sir John Herschel as “ one of the 
most beautiful specimens” which can be cited ce of inductive 
experimental inquiry lying within a moderate compass, ’ the 
theory of dew, fiist promulgated by the late Dr. Wells, and 
now universally adopted by screntifie authorities. The pas¬ 
sages m inverted commas are extracted verbatim from the 
Discoursed 

“ Suppose dew were the phenomenon proposed, whose cause 
we would know. In the first place” we must determine pre¬ 
cisely what we mean by dew what the fact really is, whose 


* This view of the necessary coexistence of opposite excitements involves 
a great extension of the original doctrine of two electricities The early 
theonsts assumed that, when amber was rubbed, the amber was made positive 
and the rubber negative to the same degiee, but it never occurred to them 
to suppose that the existence of the amber charge was dependent on an opposite 
chaige m the bodies with which the amber was contiguous, while the existence 
of the negative charge on the lubber was equally dependent on a contrary state 
of the surfaces that might accidentally be confronted with it, that, in fact, m 
a case of electrical excitement by fuction, four charges were the minimum that 
could exist But this double electrical action is essentially implied m the 
explanation now universally adopted m legard to the pnenomena of the common 
electric machine. 

+ Pp 159—162.. 



458 


INDUCTION. 


cause we desire to investigate “We must separate dew from 
rain, and tlie moisture of fogs, and limit the application of the 
teim to what is really meant, which is the spontaneous appear¬ 
ance of moisture on substances exposed m the open an when 
no ram or visible wet is falling ” This answers to a prelimi¬ 
nary operation which will be charaetenzed mtlie ensuing book, 
treating of operations subsidiary to induction * 

“ Now, here we have analogous phenomena m the mois¬ 
ture which bedews a cold metal or stone when we breathe 
upon it, that which appears on a glass of water fresh from 
the well m hot weather, that which appears on the inside of 
windows when sudden 1am or hail chills the external air; 
that which runs down our walls when, after a long fiost, a 
warm moist thaw comes on.” Compaimg these cases, we find 
that they all contain the phenomenon which was proposed as 
the subject of investigation. Now “ all these instances agiee 
m one point, the coldness of the object dewed, m companson 
with the air m contact with it ” But there still remains the 
most important case of all, that of nocturnal dew does the 
same circumstance exist m this case ? “ Is it a fact that the 

object clewed 'is colder than the air ? Ceitamly not, one 
would at fiist be inclined to say , for what is to make it so ? 
But .... the expenment is easy * we have only to lay 
a thermometer m contact with the dewed substance, and hang 
one at a little distance above it, out of reach of its influence 
The experiment has been therefore made, the question has 
been asked, and the answer has been invariably m the affir¬ 
mative Whenever an object contracts dew, it is colder than 
the air.” 

Here then is a complete application of the Method of 
Agreement, establishing the fact of an invariable connexion 
between the deposition of dew on a surface, and the coldness 
of that surface compared with the external air. But which of 
these is cause, and which effect ? 01 are they both effects of 
something else ? On this subject the Method of Agreement 
can afford us no light. we must call m a more potent method. 


* Infra, book iv ch. li. On Abstraction. 



EXAMPLES OP THE FOUR METHODS. 459 

“We must collect more facts, or, which comes to the same 
thing, vary the circumstances, since every instance m which 
the circumstances differ is a fiesh fact and especially, we 
must note the contrary or negative cases, i e. where no clew 
is produced ” a companson between instances of dew and in¬ 
stances of no dew, being the condition necessary to bung the 
Method of Difference into play 

“ Now, first, no dew is produced on the surface of polished 
metals, but it is very copiously on glass, both exposed with 
their faces upwards, and m some cases the under side of a 
horizontal plate of glass is also dewed ” Here is an instance 
m which the effect is produced, and another instance m which 
it is not pioduced; but we cannot yet pronounce, as the 
canon of the Method of Diffei ence requires, that the latter 
instance agrees with the former m all its circumstances except 
one , for the differences between glass and polished metals are 
manifold, and the only thing we can as yet be sure of is, that 
the cause of dew will be found among the circumstances by 
which the foimer substance is distinguished from the latter. 
But if we could be suie that glass, and the various other sub¬ 
stances on which dew is deposited, have only one quality m 
common, and that polished metals and the other substances 
on which dew is not deposited have also nothing m common 
but the one circumstance, of not having the one quality which 
the others have , the requisitions of the Method of Difference 
would be completely satisfied, and we should recognise, m that 
quality of the substances, the cause of dew This, accordingly, 
is the path of inquiry which is next to be pursued 

“In the cases of polished metal and polished glass, the 
contrast shows evidently that the substance has much to do 
with the phenomenon, therefore let the substance alone be 
diversified as much as possible, by exposing polished surfaces 
of various kinds This done, a scale of intensity becomes 
obvious. Those polished substances are found to be most 
strongly dewed which conduct heat worst; while those which 
conduct well, resist dew most effectually ” The complication 
increases; here is the Method of Concomitant Variations 
called to our assistance ; and no other method was practicable 



460 


INDUCTION. 


on tins occasion , foi the quality of conducting heat could not 
be excluded, since all substances conduct heat m some degree. 
The conclusion obtained is, that ccetens 'paribus the deposition 
of dew is m some piopoition to the power which the body pos¬ 
sesses of resisting the passage of heat, and that this, there - 
foie, (01 something connected with this,) must be at least one 
of the causes which assist m producing the deposition of dew 
on the surface. 

“ But if we expose rough surfaces instead of polished, we 
sometimes find this law interfered with Thus, loughened 
iron, especially if painted over or blackened, becomes dewed 
soonei than varnished paper, the kind of surface , therefore, 
has a great influence. Expose, then, the same material m very 
diversified states as to surface/’ (that is, employ the Method 
of Diffeience to ascertain concomitance of variations,) “ and 
another scale of intensity becomes at once appaient, those 
surfaces which pait with their heat most readily by ladiation, 
are found to contract dew most copiously ” Heie, therefore, 
are the requisites foi a second employment of the Method of 
Concomitant Variations , which m this case also is the only 
method available, since all substances radiate heat m some 
degree or other. The conclusion obtained by this new appli¬ 
cation of the method is, that ccetens payibus the deposition of 
dew is also m some proportion to the power of radiating heat, 
and that the quality of doing this abundantly (or some cause 
on which that quality depends) is another of the causes which 
promote the deposition of dew on the substance. 

“ Again, the influence ascertained to exist of substance and 
surface leads us to consider that of textme and here, again, 
we are presented on trial with remarkable differences, and with 
a third scale of intensity, pointing out substances of a close 
firm texture, such as stones, metals, &c, as unfavourable, but 
those of a loose one, as cloth, velvet, wool, eider-down, cotton, 
&c., as eminently favourable to the contraction of dew ” The 
Method of Concomitant Variations is here, for the third time, 
had recourse to, and, as before, fiom necessity, since the tex¬ 
ture of no substance is absolutely firm or absolutely loose. 
Looseness of texture, theiefore, or something which is the cause 



EXAMPLES OF THE FOUR METHODS 


461 


of tliat quality, is another circumstance which promotes the 
deposition of dew , but this thud cause resolves itself into the 
first, viz. the quality of resisting the passage of heat * for sub¬ 
stances of loose texture “ are precisely those which are best 
adapted for clothing, or for impeding the free passage of heat 
from the skm into the air, so as to allow their outer surfaces 
to be very cold, while they remain warm withinand this last 
is, therefore, an induction (from fresh instances) simply corro¬ 
borative of a formei induction. 

It thus appears that the instances m which much dew is 
deposited, which aie very various, agiee m this, and, so far as 
we aie able to observe, m this only, that they either radiate 
heat rapidly or conduct it slowly qualities between which 
there is no other cucumstance of agreement, than that by 
virtue of either, the body tends to lose heat from the surface 
more rapidly than it can be restored from within The in¬ 
stances, on the contrary, m which no dew, or but a small 
quantity of it, is formed, and which are also extremely 
various, agree (as far as we can observe) m nothing except 
m not having this same property. We seem, therefore, to 
have detected the characteristic difference between the sub¬ 
stances on which dew is produced, and those on which it is not 
produced And thus have been realized the requisitions of 
what we have termed the Indirect Method of Difference, or 
the Joint Method of Agreement and Difference The example 
afforded of this indirect method, and of the manner m which 
the data are prepared for it by the Methods of Agreement 
and of Concomitant Variations, is the most important of all 
the illustrations of induction afforded by this interesting 
speculation 

We might now consider the question, on what the depo¬ 
sition of dew depends, to be completely solved, if we could be 
quite sure that the substances on which dew is produced differ 
from those on which it is not, m nothing but m the property 
of losing heat from the surface faster than the loss can be 
repaired from within. And though we never can have that 
complete certainty, this is not of so much importance as might 
at first be supposed, for we have, at all events, ascertained 



m 


INDUCTION. 


tliat even if there be any other quality hitherto unobserved 
which is piesent m all the substances which contract dew, and 
absent m those which do not, this other property must be 
one which, in all that great number of substances, is present 
or absent exactly wheie the property of being a better radiator 
than conductoi is present or absent, an extent of coincidence 
which affords a stiong piesumption of a community of cause, 
and a consequent invariable coexistence between the two pro¬ 
pel ties, so that the propeity of being a hettei ladiator than 
conductoi, if not itself the cause, almost certainly always 
accompanies the cause, and, for purposes of prediction, no 
erroi is likely to be committed by treating it as if it were 
really such 

Reverting now to an eailier stage of the inquiry, let us 
remember that we had asceitamed that, m every instance 
where dew is formed, there is actual coldness of the surface 
below the temperature of the surrounding air, but we were 
not sure whether this coldness was the cause of dew, or its 
effect. This doubt we are now able to resolve We have 
found that, m eveiy such instance, the substance is one which, 
by its own pioperties or laws, would, if exposed m the night, 
become colder than the surrounding air. The coldness there¬ 
fore being accounted for independently of the dew, while it 
is proved that there is a connexion between the two, it must 
be the dew which depends on the coldness, or m other words, 
the coldness is the cause of the dew. 

This law of causation, already so amply established, admits, 
however, of efficient additional corroboration m no less than 
thiee ways. First, by deduction fiom the known laws of 
aqueous vapoui when diffused through air or any other gas , 
and though we have not yet come to the Deductive Method, 
we will not omit what is necessary to render this speculation 
complete. It is known by direct expenment that only a 
limited quantity of water can remain suspended in the state 
of vapour at each degree of temperature, and that this maxi¬ 
mum grows less and less as the temperature diminishes. From 
this it follows, deductively, that if there is already as much 
vapour suspended as the air will contain at its existing tern- 



EXAMPLES OF THE FOUR METHODS. 


463 


perature, any lowering of that temperature will cause a portion 
of the vapour to he condensed, and become water. But, again, 
we know deductively, from the laws of heat, that the contact 
of the air with a body colder than itself, will necessarily lower 
the temperature of the stratum of air immediately applied to 
its surface , and will therefore cause it to part with a portion 
of its water, which accordingly will, by the ordinary laws of 
gravitation or cohesion, attach itself to the surface of the 
body, thereby constituting dew. This deductive proof, it will 
have been seen, has the advantage of at once pioving causa¬ 
tion as well as coexistence , and it has the additional advan¬ 
tage that it also accounts for the exceptions to the occurrence 
of the phenomenon, the cases m which, although the body is 
colder than the air, yet no dew is deposited, by showing that 
this will necessauly be the case when the air is so under-sup¬ 
plied with aqueous vapour, comparatively to its temperature, 
that even when somewhat cooled by the contact of the colder 
body, it can still continue to hold m suspension all the vapour 
which was previously suspended m it thus m a very dry 
summer there aie no dews, m a very dry winter no hoar frost. 
Here, therefore, is an additional condition of the production 
of dew, which the methods we previously made use of failed 
to detect, and which might have remained still undetected, if 
recourse had not been had to the plan of deducing the effect 
from the ascertained properties of the agents known to be 
present. 

The second conoboration of the theory is by direct experi¬ 
ment, according to the canon of the Method of Difference. We 
can, by cooling the surface of any body, find m all cases some 
temperature, (more or less inferior to that of the surrounding 
an*, according to its hygrometnc condition,) at which dew will 
begin to be deposited. Here, too, therefore, the causation is 
directly proved. We can, it is true, accomplish this only on 
a small scale , but we have ample reason to conclude that the 
same operation, if conducted m Natures great laboratory, 
would equally pioduce the effect. 

And, finally, even on that great scale we are able to verify 
the result. The case is one of those rare cases, as we have 



464 


INDUCTION. 


shown them to he, in which nature woiks the experiment for 
us m the same manner m which we ourselves perform it, in¬ 
troducing into the previous state of things a single and per¬ 
fectly definite new circumstance, and manifesting the effect so 
rapidly that there is not time for any other material change 
m the pie-existing circumstances “ It is observed that dew 
is never copiously deposited m situations much screened from 
the open sky, and not at all m a cloudy night, but if the 
clouds withdraw even for a few minutes, and leave a clear 
opening, a deposition of dew presently begins, and goes on in¬ 
creasing. . . Dew formed m clear intervals will often even 
evapoiate again when the sky becomes thickly overcast ” The 
proof, therefoie, is complete, that the presence or absence of 
an uninterrupted communication with the sky causes the de¬ 
position or non-deposition of dew. Now, since a clear sky is 
nothing but the absence of clouds, and it is a known property 
of clouds, as of all other bodies between which and any given 
object nothing intervenes but an elastic fluid, that they tend 
to raise or keep up the superficial temperature of the object 
by radiating heat to it, we see at once that the disappearance 
of clouds will cause the surface to cool, so that Nature, m 
this case, produces a change m the antecedent by definite and 
known means, and the consequent follows accordingly a 
natural experiment which satisfies the requisitions of the 
Method of Difference * 


* I must, however, remark, that this example, which seems to militate 
against the assertion we made of the comparative inapplicability of the Method 
of Difference to cases of pure observation, is really one of those exceptions 
which, according to a proverbial expression, prove the general rule. Form 
this case, m which Nature, m her experiment, seems to have imitated the type 
of the expeliments made by man, she has only succeeded m producing the like¬ 
ness of man’s most imperfect experiments , namely, those in which, though he 
succeeds m producing the phenomenon, he does so by employing complex 
means, which he is unable perfectly to analyse, and can form therefore no 
sufficient judgment what portion of the effects may be due, not to the supposed 
cause, but to some unknown agency of the means by which that cause was 
produced. In the natural experiment which we are speaking of, the means 
used was the clearing off a canopy of clouds , and we ceitainly do not know 
sufficiently m what this process consists, or on what it depends, to be ceitam 
ci prion that it might not operate upon the deposition of dew independently of 



EXAMPLES OF THE FOUR METHODS. 


465 


The accumulated pi oof of which the Theory of Dew has 
been found susceptible, is a striking instance of the fulness of 
assurance which the inductive evidence of laws of causation 
may attain, in cases m which the invariable sequence is by no 
means obvious to a superficial view. 

§ 4. The admirable physiological investigations of Dr. 
Brown-Sequaid affoid brilliant examples of the application 
of the Inductive Methods to a class of inquiries m which, for 
leasons which will piesentlv be given, direct induction takes 
place under peculiai difficulties and disadvantages As one of 
the most apt instances I select his speculation (m the Pro¬ 
ceedings of the Royal Society for May 16, 1861) on the rela¬ 
tions between muscular nritability, cadaveric ngidity, and 
putrefaction 

The law which Dr. Brown-Sequaid’s investigation tends 
to establish, is the following —“ The greater the degiee of 
muscular lintability at the time of death, the later the cada- 
venc ngidity sets m, and the longer it lasts, and the later also 
putrefaction appears, and the slower it pi ogresses.” One 
would say at first sight that the method here requned must 
be that of Concomitant Variations. But this is a delusive ap¬ 
pearance, ansing from the circumstance that the conclusion to 
be tested is itself a fact of concomitant variation Por the 
establishment of that fact any of the Methods may be put in 
requisition, and it will be found that the foui th Method, though 
really employed, has only a subordinate place m this paiticular 
investigation. 

The evidences by which Dr. Brown-Sequard establishes the 
law may be enumerated as follows:— 

1st Paralysed muscles have greater irritability than 
healthy muscles. Now, paralysed muscles are later in as¬ 
suming the cadaveric rigidity than healthy muscles, the rigidity 


i 


any thermometric effect at the earth’s surface. Even, therefoie, m a case so 
favourable as this to Nature’s experimental talents, her experiment is of little 
value except in corroboration of a conclusion already attained through other 
means. 


VOL. I. 


30 



466 


INDUCTION. 


lasts longer, and putrefaction sets m later and proceeds more 
slowly. 

Both these propositions had to he proved by experiment, 
and for the expenments which prove them, science is also in¬ 
debted to Dr. Biown-Seguard. The foimer of the two—that 
paiaiysed muscles have greater irritability than healthy 
muscles—he asceitamed in various ways, but most decisively 
by “ comparing the duration of mitability m a paralysed 
muscle and in the conespondmg healthy one of the opposite 
side, while they are both submitted to the same excitation. 55 
He “ often found m experimenting m that way, that the paia¬ 
iysed muscle lemamed lrntable twice, three times, or even four 
times as long as the healthy one 55 This is a case of induction 
by the Method of Difference. The two limbs, being those of 
the same animal, were presumed to differ m no circumstance 
material to the case except the paralysis, to the presence and 
absence of which, therefore, the difference m the muscular 
irritability was to be attributed This assumption of complete 
resemblance m all material cncumstances save one, evidently 
could not be safely made m any one pair of experiments, be¬ 
cause the two legs of any given animal might be accidentally 
m very different pathological conditions , but if, besides taking 
pams to avoid any such difference, the experiment was re¬ 
peated sufficiently often m different animals to exclude the 
supposition that any abnormal circumstance could be present 
m them all, the conditrons of the Method of Difference were 
adequately secured. 

In the same manner rn which Dr Brown-Sequard proved 
that paralysed muscles have greater irritability, he also proved 
the correlative proposition respecting cadaveric rigidity and 
putrefaction. Having, by section of the roots of the sciatic 
neive, and again of a lateral half of the spinal cord, produced 
paralysis m one hind leg of an animal while the other re¬ 
mained healthy, he found that not only did museulai irritability 
last much longer m the paralysed limb, hut rigidity set m 
later and ended later, and putrefaction began later and was 
less rapid than on the healthy side. This is a common case 



EXAMPLES OP THE FOUR METHODS 


467 


of the Method of Difference, requiring no comment A further 
and veiy important corroboiation was obtained by the same 
method When the animal was killed, not shortly after the 
section of the nerve, but a month later, the effect was reversed , 
ligidity set m sooner, and lasted a shorter tune, than m the 
healthy muscles. But after this lapse of time, the paralysed 
muscles, having been kept by the paralysis m a state of rest, 
had lost a gieat part of then irritability, and instead of more, 
had become less 1111 table than those on the healthy side This 
gives the A B C, a b c, and B C, b c, of the Method of Dif¬ 
ference One antecedent, increased irritability, being changed, 
and the other circumstances being the same, the consequence 
did not follow, and moreover, when a new antecedent, con¬ 
trary to the first, was supplied, it was followed by a contrary 
consequent This instance is attended with the special advan¬ 
tage, of proving that the retardation and prolongation of the 
rigidity do not depend directly on the paralysis, since that was 
the same m both the instances, but specifically on one effect 
of the paralysis, namely, the increased irritability, since they 
ceased when it ceased, and were reversed when it was reversed. 

2ndly Diminution of the temperature of muscles before 
death increases their irritability But diminution of their tem¬ 
perature also retards cadaveric rigidity and putrefaction. 

Both these truths were first made known by Dr. Brown- 
Sequard himself, through experiments which conclude accord¬ 
ing to the Method of Difference. There is nothing m the 
nature of the process requiring specific analysis. 

3rdly Muscular exercise, prolonged to exhaustion, dimi¬ 
nishes the muscular irritability. This is a well-known truth, 
dependent on the most general laws of muscular action, and 
pioved by experiments under the Method of Difference, con¬ 
stantly repeated Now it has been shown by observation that 
oveidriven cattle, if killed before recovery from their fatigue, 
become rigid and putrefy m a surprisingly short time A 
similar fact has been observed m the case of animals hunted to 
death, cocks killed during or shortly after a fight, and 
soldiers slam m the field of battle These various cases agree 

30—2 



68 


INDUCTION. 


2 no circumstance, directly connected with the muscles, except 
hat these have just been subjected to exhausting exeicise 
Jndei the canon, theiefoie, of the Method of Agieement, it 
nay be mfened that there is a connexion between the two 
acts The Method of Agieement, indeed, as has been shown, 
s not competent to prove causation The present case, how- 
ivei, is alieady known to be a case of causation, it being cer¬ 
tain that the state of the body after death must somehow 
lepend upon its state at the time of death We are therefore 
wan anted m concluding that the single circumstance m which 
all the instances agiee, is the part of the antecedent which is 
the cause of that particular consequent 

4thly. In proportion as the nutrition of muscles is m a 
good state, their in it ability is high. This fact also rests on 
the geneial evidence of the laws of physiology, giounded on 
many familiar applications of the Method of Difference Now, 
m the case of those who die from accident 01 violence, with 
their muscles m a good state of nutntion, the muscular muta¬ 
bility continues long after death, rigidity sets m late, and 
peisists long without the putiefactive change On the contraiy, 
in cases of disease m which nutrition has been diminished for 
a long time before death, all these effects are leversed. These 
are the conditions of the Joint Method of Agreement and 
Difference. The cases of retarded and long continued ngidity 
heie m question, agree only m being preceded by a high state 
of nutrition of the muscles, the cases of rapid and brief 
rigidity agree only m being preceded by a low state of mus¬ 
cular nutntion, a connexion is therefore inductively proved 
between the degree of the nutntion, and the slowness and pro¬ 
longation of the rigidity. 

5thly Convulsions, like exhausting exercise, hut m a 
still gieater degree, dimmish the muscular irritability Now, 
when death follows violent and prolonged convulsions, as m 
tetanus, hydrophobia, some cases of cholera, and ceitam 
poisons, rigidity sets m very rapidly, and after a very brief 
duration, gives place to putrefaction. This is another ex¬ 
ample of the Method of Agieement, of the same character 
with No. 3, 



EXAMPLES OF THE FOUR METHODS. 


469 


Othly. The senes of instances which we shall take last, is 
of a more complex character, and regimes a more minute 
analysis. 

It has long been observed that m some cases of death by 
lightning, cadaveric ngidity either does not take place at all, 
01 is of such extremely brief duration as to escape notice, and 
that in these cases putrefaction is very rapid. In other cases, 
howevei, the usual cadavenc ngidity appears. There must be 
some difference m the cause, to account for this difference m 
the effect. Now “ death by lightning maybe the result of, 
1st, a syncope by flight, 01 m consequence of a direct or reflex 
influence of lightning on the par vagum, 2ndly, hemorrhage 
m or around the biam, or m the lungs, the pencaidium, &c., 
Sidly, concussion, or some other alteration m the brain ,” none 
of which phenomena have any known property capable of 
accounting for the suppression, or almost suppression, of the 
cadaveric rigidity. But the cause of death may also be that 
the lightning produces “ a violent convulsion of every muscle 
m the body,” of which, if of sufficient intensity, the known 
effect would be that “ muscular irritability ceases almost at 
once ” If Dr Biown-Sequard’s generalization is a true law, 
these will be the very cases m which rigidity is so much 
abridged as to escape notice, and the cases m which, on the 
contrary, ngidity takes place as usual, will be those in which 
the stroke of lightning operates in some of the other modes 
which have been enumerated. How, then, is this brought to 
the test? By experiments not on lightning, which cannot be 
commanded at pleasure, but on the same natural agency m a 
manageable form, that of aitificial galvanism. Dr Brown- 
Scquaid galvanized the entire bodies of animals immediately 
after death Galvanism cannot operate m any of the modes m 
which the stroke of lightning may have opeiated, except the 
single one of producing muscular convulsions. If, therefore, 
after the bodies have been galvanized, the duration of rigidity 
is much shortened and putrefaction much accelerated, it is 
reasonable to ascribe the same effects when produced by light¬ 
ning, to the property which galvanism shares with lightning, 
and not to those which it does not. Now this Dr. Brown- 



470 


INDUCTION 


Sequard found to be the fact The galvanic expeiiment was 
tiled with charges of very vanous degrees of stiength , and the 
more powerful the charge, the shortei was found to be the dura¬ 
tion of ngidity, and the moie speedy and rapid the putrefaction 
In the expeiiment m which the charge was stiongest, and the 
muscular lintability most promptly destroyed, the rigidity only 
lasted fifteen minutes On the principle, therefore, of the 
Method of Concomitant Variations, it may be inferred that the 
duration of the rigidity depends on the degree of the n ina¬ 
bility ; and that if the charge had been as much stronger than 
Dr Biown-Sequard’s strongest, as a stroke of lightning must 
be stronger than any electric shock which we can pioduce 
artificially, the rigidity would have been shortened m a coire- 
spondmg ratio, and might have disappeaied altogether This 
conclusion having been arrived at, the case of an electric shock, 
whether natural or artificial, becomes an instance m addition 
to all those already ascertained, of correspondence between the 
mitability of the muscle and the duiation of rigidity 

All these instances are summed up in the following state¬ 
ment :— cc That when the degree of muscular mutability at the 
time of death is considerable, either in consequence of a good 
state of nutntion, as m persons who die m full health from 
an accidental cause, or m consequence of rest, as m cases of 
paialysis, or on account of the influence of cold, cadaveric 
rigidity m all these cases sets m late and lasts long, and putre¬ 
faction appears late, and progresses slowly ” but “ that when 
the degree of muscular lintability at the time of death is slight, 
either in consequence of a bad state of nutrition, 01 of exhaus¬ 
tion from ovei-exeition, or from convulsions caused by disease 
01 poison, cadaveric rigidity sets m and ceases soon, and 
putrefaction appeals and pi ogresses quickly ” These facts 
piesent, m all then completeness, the conditions of the Joint 
Method of Agreement and Difference. Early and brief rigidity 
takes place m cases which agree only m the circumstance of a 
low state of muscular irritability Kigidity begins late and 
lasts long m cases which agree only m the contrary circum¬ 
stance, of a muscular irritability high and unusually prolonged 
It follows that there is a connexion through causation between 
the degree of muscular irritability after death, and the taidiness 



EXAMPLES OF THE FOUR METHODS. 471 

and prolongation of the cadaveric rigidity. This investigation 
places in a stiong light the value and efficacy of the Joint 
Method. For, as we have alieady seen, the defect of that 
Method is, that like the Method of Agreement, of which it is 
only an improved form, it cannot piove causation. But m the 
present case (as m one of the steps m the argument which led 
up to it) causation is already proved , since there could nevei 
he any doubt that the rigidity altogether and the putrefaction 
which follows it, are caused by the fact of death the obser¬ 
vations and experiments on which this rests are too familiar to 
need analysis, and fall under the Method of Difference It 
being, therefore, beyond doubt that the aggregate antecedent, 
the death, is the actual cause of the whole tram of con¬ 
sequents, whatever of the circumstances attending the death 
can he shown to be followed in all its variations by variations 
m the effect under investigation, must be the paiticular feature 
of the fact of death on which that effect depends The degree 
of muscular lrntability at the time of death fulfils this con¬ 
dition The only point that could be brought into question, 
would be whether the effect depended on the irritability itself, 
or on something which always accompanied the irritability 
and this doubt is set at rest by establishing, as the instances 
do, that by whatever cause the high or low irritability is pro¬ 
duced, the effect equally follows, and cannot, therefoie, depend 
upon the causes of irritability, nor upon the other effects of 
those causes, which are as various as the causes themselves ; 
hut upon the irritability, solely. 

§ 5. The last two examples will have conveyed to any 
one by whom they have been duly followed, so clear a concep 
tion of the use and practical management of three of the foui 
methods of experimental inquiry, as to supersede the necessity 
of any further exemplification of them. The remaining method, 
that of Residues, not having found a place in any of the pie- 
cedmg investigations, I shall quote from Sir John Herschel 
some examples of that method, with the remarks by which they 
are introduced. 

“ It is by this process, m fact, that science, m its present 
advanced state, is chiefly promoted. Most of the phenomena 



hn 


INDUCTION. 


which Nature piesents are very complicated , and when the 
effects of all known causes are estimated with exactness, and 
subducted, the residual facts aie constantly appearing m the 
form of phenomena altogether new, and leading to the most 
important conclusions. 

“Foi example the return of the comet predicted w by Pro¬ 
fessor Encke, a great many times m succession, and the 
general good agreement of its calculated with its observed 
place dm mg any one of its periods of visibility, would lead us 
to say that its giavitation towaids the sun and planets is the 
sole and sufficient cause of all the phenomena of its orbitual 
motion , but when the effect of this cause is stnetly calculated 
and subducted from the observed motion, theie is found to 
remain behind a i esidual ‘phenomenon, which would never have 
been otherwise asceitamed to exist, which is a small anticipa¬ 
tion of the time of its reappeaiance, 01 a diminution of its 
periodic time, which cannot be accounted for by gravity, and 
whose cause is theiefore to be inquired into. Such an antici¬ 
pation would be caused by the resistance of a medium dis¬ 
seminated thiough the celestial legions , and as there are other 
good leasons foi believing this to be a vera causa,” (an actually 
existing antecedent,) “ it has theiefore been ascubed to such a 
resistance * 

“ M Arago, having suspended a magnetic needle by a silk 
thread, and set it m vibration, observed, that it came much 
sooner to a state of rest when suspended over a plate of copper, 
than when no such plate was beneath it Now, m both 
cases there were two verce caused ” (antecedents known to 
exist) “why it should come at length to rest, viz. the resist¬ 
ance of the air, which opposes, and at length destroys, all 
motions performed m it, and the want of peifect mobility m 
the silk thiead. But the effect of these causes being exactly 
known by the observation made m the absence of the copper, 
and being thus allowed for and subducted, a residual pheno¬ 
menon appeared, m the fact that a retarding influence was 


* In his subsequent work, Outlines of Astronomy (§ 570), Sir John 
Herschel suggests another possible explanation of the acceleration of the revolu¬ 
tion of a comet. 



EXAMPLES OF THE FOUR METHODS. 


473 


exeited by the copper itself, and tins fact, once asceitamed, 
speedily led to the knowledge of an entirely new and unex¬ 
pected class of relations.” This example belongs, however, 
not to the Method of Eesidues hut to the Method of Differ¬ 
ence, the law being asceitamed by a direct companson of 
the lesults of two experiments, which diffeied in nothing but 
the presence or absence of the plate of copper. To have made 
it exemplify the Method of Residues, the effect of the resistance 
of the air and that of the rigidity of the silk should have been 
calculated a pi 1071, fiom the laws obtained by sepaiate and 
foiegone experiments 

ce Unexpected and pecuhaily stiiking confiimations of 
inductive laws frequently occur m the form of le si dual phe¬ 
nomena, in the course of investigations of a widely different 
nature fiom those which gave rise to the inductions them¬ 
selves. A very elegant example may be cited m the unex¬ 
pected confhmation of the law of the development of heat m 
elastic fluids by compression, which is afforded by the phe¬ 
nomena of sound. The inquiry into the cause of sound had 
led to conclusions respecting its mode of propagation, from 
which its velocity m the air could be precisely calculated. 
The calculations were performed, but, when compared with 
fact, though the agieement was quite sufficient to show the 
general correctness of the cause and mode of propagation 
assigned, yet the whole velocity could not be shown to anse 
from this theory There was still a residual velocity to be 
accounted for, which placed dynamical philosophers for a 
long time m great dilemma. At length Laplace struck on 
the happy idea, that this might arise from the heat developed 
m the act of that condensation which necessarily takes place 
at every vibration by which sound is conveyed. The matter 
was subjected to exact calculation, and the result was at once 
the complete explanation of the residual phenomenon, and a 
strking confirmation of the general law of the development 
of heat by compression, under circumstances beyond artificial 
imitation ” 

“ Many of the new elements of chemistry have been 
detected m the investigation of residual phenomena Thus 
Arfwedson discovered lithia by perceiving an excess of weight 



474 


INDUCTION. 


m the sulphate produced from a small portion of what he 
considered as magnesia piesent m a mineral he had analysed 
It is on this principle, too, that the small concentrated 
residues of great opeiations m the aits are almost sure to be 
the lurking places of new chemical ingredients witness 
iodine, brome, selenium, and the new metals accompanying 
platma m the experiments of Wollaston and Tennant It was 
a happy thought of Glauber to examine what everybody else 
threw away,”* 

“ Almost all the greatest discoveries m Astronomy,” says 
the same author,f “ have resulted from the consideration of 
residual phenomena of a quantitative or numerical kind . . . 
It was thus that the grand discoveiv of the precession of 
the equinoxes resulted as a residual phenomenon, from the 
imperfect explanation of the return of the seasons by the 
return of the sun to the same apparent place among the 
fixed stars. Thus, also, abeiration and nutation resulted as 
residual phenomena fiom that poition of the changes of the 
apparent places of the fixed stars which was left unac¬ 
counted foi by precession And thus again the appaient 
proper motions of the stais are the observed residues of 
their appaient movements outstanding and unaccounted for 
by strict calculation of the effects of piecession, nutation, and 
abenation. The nearest approach which human theories 
can make to peifection is to dimmish this residue, this caput 
moitmcm of observation, as it may be considered, as much as 
practicable, and, if possible, to reduce it to nothing, either by 
showing that something has been neglected m our estimation 
of known causes, or by reasoning upon it as a new fact, and 
on the principle of the inductive philosophy ascending horn 
the effect to its cause or causes.” 

The disturbing effects mutually pioduced by the earth 
and planets upon each other’s motions were first brought to 
light as residual phenomena, by the difference which appeared 
between the observed places of those bodies, and the places 
calculated on a consideration solely of their gravitation 


Discouise, pp. 156-8, and 171. f Outlines of Asti onomy, § 856. 



EXAMPLES OF THE FOUR METHODS. 


475 


towards the sun It was this which determined astronomers 
to consider the law of gravitation as obtaining between 
all bodies whatever, and therefore between all particles of 
matter, their first tendency having been to regard it as a 
foice acting only between each planet or satellite and the 
cential body to whose system it belonged Again, the 
catastrophists, m geology, be their opinion right 01 wiong, 
suppoit it on the plea, that after the effect of all causes 
now m operation has been allowed for, theie remains m the 
existing constitution of the earth a large lesidue of facts, 
proving the existence at former periods either of other forces, 
or of the same foices m a much greater degree of intensity. 
To add one more example those who asseit, what no one 
has shown any real giound for believing, that theie is m 
one human individual, one sex, 01 one lace of mankind 
over another, an mheient and inexplicable superiority m 
mental faculties, could only substantiate their proposition by 
subtracting from the differences of intellect which we m fact 
see, all that can be traced by known laws either to the ascer¬ 
tained differences of physical oigamzation, or to the dif¬ 
ferences which have existed m the outward cncumstances m 
which the subjects of the comparison have hitherto been 
placed. What these causes might fail to account for, would 
constitute a residual phenomenon, which and which alone 
would be evidence of an ulterior original distinction, and 
the measure of its amount But the assertors of such sup¬ 
posed differences have not provided themselves with these 
necessary logical conditions of the establishment of their 
doctime. 

The spirit of the Method of Residues being, it is hoped, 
sufficiently intelligible from these examples, and the other 
three methods having already been so fully exemplified, we 
may heie close our exposition of the four methods, considered 
as employed m the investigation of the simpler and more 
elementary order of the combinations of phenomena. 

§ 6 . Dr. Whewell has expressed a very unfavourable 
opinion of the utility of the Four Methods, as well as of the 



476 


INDUCTION. 


aptness of the examples by which I have attempted to illus- 
tiate them. His woids are these —+ 

“ Upon these methods, the obvious thing to lemaik is, 
that they take for gianted the \ery thing which is most 
difficult to discovei, the reduction of the phenomena to 
foimulae such as are heie piesented to us. When we have 
any set of complex facts offered to us, for instance, those 
which weie offeied m the cases of discoveiy which I have 
mentioned,—the facts of the planetary paths, of falling 
bodies, of lefiacted lays, of cosmical motions, of chemical 
analysis, and when, m any of these cases, we would disco\er 
the law of natuie which governs them, 01, if any one chooses 
so to term it, the featuie m which all the cases agree, where 
aie we to look for our A, B, 0 , and a, b, c 2 Natuie does 
not piesent to us the cases m this form, and how aie we to 
reduce them to this form ? You say, when we find the com¬ 
bination of A B C with a be and A B D with a b cl , then 
w T e may diaw our inference. Gianted, but when and wheie 
aie we to find such combinations ? Even now that the dis¬ 
covers aie made, who will point out to us wffiat are the 
A, B, C, and a, b, c elements of the cases which have just 
been enumerated 9 Who will tell us which of the methods 
of inquiry those histoncally real and successful inqumes 
exemplify? Who will cairy these formulae thiough the 
history of the sciences, as they have really grown up, and 
show us that these four methods have been operative m their 
formation, or that any light is thrown upon the steps of 
their piogress by reference to these formulae ?” 

He adds that, m this woik, the methods have not been 
applied “ to a large body of conspicuous and undoubted ex¬ 
amples of discovery, extending along the whole history of 
science,” which ought to have been done m older that the 
methods might be shown to possess the “ advantage” (which 
he claims as belonging to his own) of being those “by which 
all gieat discoveries m science have really been made.”— 
(p. 277 .) 


Philosophy of Discovery , pp 263, 264 



EXAMPLES OF THE FOUR METHODS. 


4?r 


There is a sinking similarity between the objections here 
made against Canons of Induction, and what was alleged, m 
the last century, by as able men as Dr Whewell, against the 
acknowledged Canon of Ratiocination. Those who protested 
against the Aristotelian Logic said of the Syllogism, what 
Dr. Whewell says of the Inductive Methods, that it “ takes 
foi gi anted the very thing which is most difficult to discover, 
the ieduction of the ai gument to formulae such as are here 
presented to us.” The grand difficulty, they said, is to obtain 
your syllogism, not to judge of its coirectness when obtained. 
On the matter of fact, both they and Di. Whewell are right. 
The greatest difficulty m both cases is first that of obtaining 
the evidence, and next, of reducing it to the form which tests 
its conclusiveness Rut if we try to reduce it without know¬ 
ing to illicit, we are not likely to make much progress It is 
a more difficult thing to solve a geometrical problem, than to 
judge whether a proposed solution is conect but if people 
weie not able to judge of the solution when found, they would 
have little chance of finding it. And it cannot be pretended 
that to judge of an induction when found, is perfectly easy, is 
a thing for which aids and instruments are superfluous; for 
erroneous inductions, false inferences from experience, are quite 
as common, on some subjects much commoner, than true ones. 
The business of Inductive Logic is to provide rules and models 
(such as the Syllogism and its rules are for ratiocination) to 
which if inductive arguments conform, those arguments are 
conclusive, and not otherwise. This is what the Four 
U Methods piofess to be, and what I believe they are universally 
* considered to be by experimental philosophers, who had prac¬ 
tised all of them long before any one sought to reduce the 
practice to theory. 

The assailants of the Syllogism had also anticipated Dr 
Whewell m the other branch of his argument. They said 
that no discoveries weie ever made by syllogism, and Dr. 
Whewell says, or seems to say, that none were ever made by 
the four Methods of Induction. To the former objectors, 
Archbishop Whately very pertinently answered, that their 
argument, if good at all, was good against the reasoning pro- 



478 


INDUCTION. 


cess altogether, for whatever cannot be reduced to syllogism, 
is not reasoning. And Dr. Whew ell’s argument, if good at 
all, is good against all inferences fiom experience In saying 
that no discoveries were ever made by the four Methods, he 
affirms that none were ever made by observation and experi¬ 
ment , for assuiedly if any weie, it was by processes reducible 
to one or other of those methods. 

This difference between us accounts for the dissatisfaction 
which my examples give him; foi I did not select them with 
a view to satisfy any one who required to be convinced that 
observation and experiment are modes of acquiring knowledge 
I confess that m the choice of them I thought only of illus¬ 
tration, and of facilitating the conception of the Methods by 
concrete instances. If it had been my object to justify the 
piocesses themselves as means of investigation, there would 
have been no need to look far off, or make use of lecondite or 
complicated instances As a specimen of a truth ascertained 
by the Method of Agreement, I might have chosen the pro¬ 
position “Dogs bark.” This dog, and that dog, and the 
other dog, answer to A B C, A D E, A F G The circum¬ 
stance of being a dog, answeis to A Barking answers to a 
As a truth made known by the Method of Difference, “ Fire 
burns” might have sufficed Befoie I touch the fire I am not 
burnt; this 1 $ B 0, I touch it, and am burnt, this is A B C, 
a BO. 

Such familiar experimental processes are not regaided as 
inductions by Dr. Whewell, but they are perfectly homo¬ 
geneous with those by which, even on his own showing, the 
pyramid of science is supplied with its base. In vam he attempts 
to escape fiom this conclusion by laying the most arbitrary 
restrictions on the choice of examples admissible as instances 
of Induction : they must neither be such as aie still matter of 
discussion (p. 265), nor must any of them be drawn from 
mental and social subjects (p. 269), nor from oidinary obser¬ 
vation and practical life (pp. 24=1—247) They must be 
taken exclusively from the geneializations by which scientific 
thinkers have ascended to great and comprehensive laws of 
natural phenomena. Now it is seldom possible, m these com- 



EXAMPLES OF THE FOUR METHODS. 


479 


plicated inquiries, to go much beyond the initial steps, without 
calling m the instrument of Deduction, and the temporary 
aid of hypotheses, as I myself, m common with Dr Whewell, 
have maintained against the purely empirical school Since 
therefore such cases could not conveniently he selected to il¬ 
lustrate the principles of mere observation and experiment. 
Dr. Whewell is misled by their absence into representing 
the Experimental Methods as serving no purpose m scientific 
investigation; forgetting that if those methods had not sup¬ 
plied the first generalizations, there would have been no mate¬ 
rials for his own conception of Induction to work upon. 

His challenge, however, to point out which of the four 
methods are exemplified m certain important cases of scientific 
inquiry, is easily answered “ The planetary paths,” as far as 
they are a case of induction at all,-* fall under the Method of 
Agreement The law of “ falling bodies,” namely that they 
describe spaces proportional to the squares of the times, was 
historically a deduction from the first law of motion, but the 
experiments by which it was verified, and by which it might 
have been discovered, were examples of the Method of Agree¬ 
ment, and the apparent variation from the true law, caused 
by the resistance of the air, was cleared up by experiments 
m vacuo, constituting an application of the Method of Dif¬ 
ference. The law of “ refracted rays” (the constancy of the 
ratio between the sines of incidence and of refraction for each 
refracting substance) was ascertained by direct measurement, 
and therefore by the Method of Agreement. The fe cosmical 
motions” were determined by highly complex processes of 
thought, m which Deduction was predominant, but the 
Methods of Agreement and of Concomitant Variations had a 
large part m establishing the empirical laws Every case 
without exception of “ chemical analysis” constitutes a well- 
marked example of the Method of Difference To any one 
acquainted with the subjects—to Dr Whewell himself, there 
would not be the smallest difficulty m setting out “ the ABC 
and ab c elements” of these cases 


* See, on this point, the second chapter of the present Book 



4S0 


INDUCTION. 


If discoveries are ever made by observation and expenment 
without Deduction, the foui methods are methods of discoveiy * 
but even if they weie not methods of discovery, it would not 
be the less tine that they are the sole methods of Pi oof ; and 
m that character, even the results of deduction aie amenable 
to them. The gieat geneiahzations which begin as Hypo¬ 
theses, must end by being pioved, and are m i ealitv (as will 
be shown hereafter) pioved, by the Four Methods. Now it is 
with Pi oof, as such, that Logic is pimcipally concerned This 
distinction has indeed no chance of finding favour with 
Dr Whewell, for it is the peculiarity of his system, not to 
lecogmse, m cases of Induction, any necessity for proof If, 
after assuming an hypothesis and carefully collating it with 
facts, nothing is brought to light inconsistent with it, that is, 
if expenence does not dzsprove it, he is content at least 
until a simpler hypothesis, equally consistent with experience, 
presents itself If this he Induction, doubtless theie is no 
necessity for the four methods But to suppose that it is so, 
appears to me a radical misconception of the nature of the 
evidence of physical tiuths. 

So real and piactical is the need of a test foi induction, 
similai to the syllogistic test of latiocmation, that mfeiences 
which hid defiance to the most elementary notions of inductive 
logic are put forth without misgiving by persons eminent m 
physical science, as soon as they are off the ground on which 
they are conveisant with the facts, and not reduced to judge 
only by tbe arguments, and as for educated persons m gene¬ 
ral, it may be doubted if they are better judges of a good or 
a bad induction than they •were before Bacon wuote The 
improvement m the results of thinking has seldom extended 
to the processes; or has reached, if any process, that of inves¬ 
tigation only, not that of proof A knowledge of many laws 
of natuie has doubtless been arrived at, by framing hypotheses 
and finding that the facts corresponded to them , and many 
errors have been got rid of by coming to a knowledge of facts 
which were inconsistent with them, but not by discovering 
that tbe mode of thought which led to the errors was itself 
faulty, and might have been known to be such independently 



EXAMPLES OF THE FOUR METHODS. 48 

of the facts which disproved the specific conclusion. Henci 
it is, that while the thoughts of mankind have on many sub 
jects woiked themselves practically right, the thinking powe 
remains as weak as ever: and on all subjects on which th< 
facts which would check the result are not accessible, as ii 
what relates to the invisible woild, and even, as has been seei 
lately, to the visible world of the planetary regions, men o 
the greatest scientific acquirements argue as pitiably as th( 
merest ignoramus For though they have made many sounc 
inductions, they have not learnt from them (and Dr. Whewel 
thinks there is no necessity that they should learn) the pnn 
ciples of inductive evidence. 


VOL. i. 


81 



CHAPTER X. 


OF PLURALITY OF CAUSES , AND OF THE INTERMIXTURE 
OF EFFECTS. 

§ 1 In the preceding exposition of the four methods of 
obseivation and experiment, by which we contrive to distin¬ 
guish among a mass of coexistent phenomena the particular 
effect due to a given cause, or the particular cause which gave 
birth to a given effect, it has been necessary to suppose, m 
the first instance, for the sake of simplification, that this ana¬ 
lytical operation is encumbered by no other difficulties than 
what are essentially inherent m its nature, and to repiesent 
to ourselves, therefore, every effect, on the one hand as con¬ 
nected exclusively with a single cause, and on the other hand 
as incapable of being mixed and confounded with any other 
coexistent effect We have regarded abode, the aggregate 
of the phenomena existing at any moment, as consisting of 
dissimilar facts, a, b, c, d , and e, for each of which one, and 
only one, cause needs be sought, the difficulty being only 
that of singling out this one cause from the multitude of 
antecedent cncumstances, A, B, C, D, and E. The cause 
indeed may not be simple, it may consist of an assemblage of 
conditions, but we have supposed that there was only one 
possible assemblage of conditions, fiom which the given effect 
could result. 

If such were the fact, it would be comparatively an easy 
task to investigate the laws of natuie. But the supposition 
does not hold, m either of its parts. In the first place, it is 
not true that the same phenomenon is always produced by 
the same cause: the effect a may sometimes arise from A, 
sometimes from B. And, secondly, the effects of different 
causes aie often not dissimilar, but homogeneous, and marked 
out by no assignable boundaries from one another. A and B 



PLURALITY OF CAUSES. 


483 


may produce not a and 6, but diffei ent portions of an effect a 
The obscurity and difficulty of the investigation of the laws of 
phenomena is singularly increased by the necessity of ad¬ 
verting to these two circumstances, Intermixture of Effects, 
and Plurality of Causes To the latter, being the simpler of 
the two considerations, we shall first direct our attention. 

It is not true, then, that one effect must be connected with 
only one cause, or assemblage of conditions; that each phe¬ 
nomenon can be produced only in one way. Theie are often 
several independent modes m which the same phenomenon 
could have ongmated One fact may be the consequent m 
several invariable sequences, it may follow, with equal uni¬ 
formity, any one of several antecedents, or collections of ante¬ 
cedents Many causes may produce motion * many causes 
may produce some kinds of sensation many causes may pro¬ 
duce death. A given effect may really be produced by a 
certain cause, and yet be peifectly capable of being produced 
without it. 


§ 2. One of the principal consequences of this fact of 
Plurality of Causes is, to lender the first of the inductive 
methods, that of Agreement, uncertain To illustrate that 
method, we supposed two instances, ABC followed by a b c, 
and ADE followed by a d e. From these instances it might 
apparently be concluded that A is an invariable antecedent of 
a, and even that it is the unconditional invariable antecedent, 
or cause, if we could be sure that there is no other antecedent 
common to the two cases. That this difficulty may not stand 
in the way, let us suppose the two cases positively ascertained 
to have no antecedent m common except A. The moment, 
howevei, that we let m the possibility of a plurality of causes, 
the conclusion fails. Eor it involves a tacit supposition, that 
a must have been produced in both instances by the same 
cause If there can possibly have been two causes, those two 
may, for example, be C and E. the one may have been the 
cause of a m the former of the instances, the other m the 
latter, A having no influence m either case. 

Suppose, for example, that two great artists, or great philo- 
31—2 



484 


INDUCTION 


sophers, that two extremely selfish, or extremely generous 
chaiacters, were compared together as to the circumstances of 
their education and history, and the two cases were found to 
agree only m one cncumstance. would it follow that this one 
circumstance was the cause of the quality which chai actenzed 
both those individuals 9 Not at all, for the causes which 
may produce any type of character are innumerable, and the, 
two persons might equally have agreed m their character, 
though there had been no mannei of resemblance m their pre¬ 
vious history 

This, therefore, is a characteristic imperfection of the 
Method of Agreement, from which imperfection the Method 
of Difference is free. Tor if we have two instances, ABC 
and B C, of which B C gives b c, and A being added converts 
it into a b c, it is certain that m this instance at least, A was 
either the cause of a, or an indispensable portion of its cause, 
even though the cause which produces it m other instances 
may be altogether different Plurality of Causes, therefore, 
not only does not dimmish the reliance due to the Method of 
Difference, but does not even render a greater number of ob¬ 
servations or experiments necessary: two instances, the one 
positive and the other negative, are still sufficient for the most 
complete and rigorous induction Not so, however, with the 
Method of Agreement. The conclusions which that yields, 
when the number of instances compared is small, are of no 
real value, except as, m the character of suggestions, they may 
lead either to experiments bringing them to the test of the 
Method of Difference, or to reasonings which may explain and 
verify them deductively. 

It is only when the instances, being indefinitely multiplied 
and varied, continue to suggest the same result, that this re¬ 
sult acqunes any high degree of independent value. If there 
are hut two instances, ABC and A D E, though these in¬ 
stances have no antecedent m common except A, yet as the 
effect may possibly have been produced m the two cases by 
different causes, the result is at most only a slight probability 
in favour of A , there may be causation, but it is almost 
equally probable that there was only a coincidence But the 



PLURALITY OF CAUSES* 


485 


oftener we repeat the observation, varying the circumstances, 
the more we advance towards a solution of this doubt For 
if we try A F G, A H K, &c., all unlike one another except 
m containing the circumstance A, and if we find the effect a 
entering into the result m all these cases, we must suppose 
one of two things, either that it is caused by A, or that it has as 
many different causes as there are instances. With each addi¬ 
tion, theiefore, to the number of instances, the presumption is 
strengthened m favour of A. The mquner, of course, will not 
neglect, if an opportunity present itself, to exclude A from 
some one of these combinations, from A H K for instance, and 
by trying H K sepaiately, appeal to the Method of Difference 
m aid of the Method of Agreement By the Method of Dif¬ 
ference alone can it be ascertained that A is the cause of a , 
but that it is either the cause, or another effect of the same 
cause, may be placed beyond any reasonable doubt by the 
Method of Agreement, provided the instances are veiy nume¬ 
rous, as well as sufficiently various. 

After how great a multiplication, then, of varied instances, 
all agieemg m no other antecedent except A, is the supposition 
of a pluiality of causes sufficiently rebutted, and the conclu¬ 
sion that a is connected with A divested of the chaiactenstic 
impeifection, and 1 educed to a virtual certainty ? This is a 
question which we cannot be exempted fiom answering: but 
the consideration of it belongs to what is called the Theory of 
Probability, which will form the subject of a chapter hereafter. 
It is seen, however, at once, that the conclusion does amount 
to a practical certainty after a sufficient number of instances, 
and that the method, therefore, is not radically vitiated by the 
characteristic imperfection The result of these considerations 
is only, m the first place, to point out a new source of infe¬ 
riority m the Method of Agreement as compared with other 
modes of investigation, and new reasons for never resting con¬ 
tented with the results obtained by it, without attempting to 
confirm them either by the* Method of Difference, or by con¬ 
necting them deductively with some law or laws already ascer¬ 
tained by that superior method. And, m the second place, 
we learn from this the true theory of the value of mere number 



4S6 


INDUCTION. 


of instances m inductive inquiry. The Plurality of Causes is 
the only reason why mere numbei is of any importance. The 
tendency of unscientific inquirers is to rely too much on 
number, without analysing the instances , without looking 
closely enough into their nature, to ascertain what circum¬ 
stances aie or are not eliminated by means of them Most 
people hold their conclusions with a degree of assurance pio- 
poiboned to the mere mass of the experience on which they 
appear to rest, not considering that by the addition of in¬ 
stances to instances, all of the same kind, that is, differing 
horn one another only m points already recognised as imma¬ 
terial, nothing whatever is added to the evidence of the con¬ 
clusion A single instance eliminating some antecedent which 
existed m all the other cases, is of more value than the greatest 
multitude of instances which are reckoned by their number 
alone. It is necessary, no doubt, to assure ourselves, by 
repetition of the observation or experiment, that no error has 
been^committed concerning the individual facts observed , and 
until we have assured ourselves of this, instead of vaiymg the 
cncumstances, we cannot too scrupulously repeat the same 
experiment or observation without any change. But when 
once this assurance has been obtained, the multiplication of 
instances which do not exclude any more circumstances is 
entirely useless, piovided there have been already enough to 
exclude the supposition of Plurality of Causes. 

It is of importance to remark, that the peculiar modifica- 
tion of the Method of Agreement, which, as partaking m some 
degree of the nature of the Method of Difference, I have called 
the Joint Method of Agreement and Difference, is not affected 
by the characteristic imperfection now pointed out Por, in 
the joint method, it is supposed not only that the instances m 
which a is, agree only m containing A, but also that the 
instances m which a is not, agree only m not containing A. 
Now, if this be so, A must be not only the cause of a, but the 
only possible cause for if there were another, as for example 
B, then m the instances m which a is not, B must have been 
absent as well as A, and it would not be true that these 
instances agree only in not containing A. This, therefore, 



PLURALITY OF CAUSES. 


487 


constitutes an immense advantage of the joint method over 
the simple Method of Agreement. It may seem, indeed, that 
the advantage does not belong so much to the joint method, 
as to one of its two premises, (if they may he so called,) the 
negative premise. The Method of Agreement, when applied 
to negative instances, or those m which a phenomenon does 
not take place, is certainly free from the characteristic imper¬ 
fection which affects it m the affirmative case The negative 
premise, it might therefore he supposed, could he worked as 
a simple case of the Method of Agreement, without requiring 
an affirmative premise to he joined with it. But though this 
is true m principle, it is generally altogether impossible to 
work the Method of Agreement by negative instances without 
positive ones * it is so much more difficult to exhaust the field 
of negation than that of affirmation. For instance, let the 
question he, what is the cause of the transparency of bodies, 
with what prospect of success could we set ourselves to inquire 
directly m what the multifarious substances which are not 
transparent, agree ? But we might hope much sooner to 
seize some point of resemblance among the comparatively few 
and definite species of objects which are transparent, and this 
being attained, we should quite naturally be put upon examin¬ 
ing whether the absence of this one circumstance be not pre¬ 
cisely the point m which all opaque substances will be found 
to resemble. 

The Joint Method of Agreement and Difference, therefore, 
or, as I have otherwise called it, the Indirect Method of Diffe¬ 
rence (because, like the Method of Difference properly so called, 
it proceeds by ascertaining how and m what the cases where 
the phenomenon is present, differ from those m which it is 
absent) is, after the Direct Method of Difference, the most 
powerful of the remaining instruments of inductive investiga¬ 
tion , and m the sciences which depend on pure observation, 
with little or no aid from experiment, this method, so well ex¬ 
emplified in the speculation on the cause of dew, is the primary 
resource, so far as direct appeals to experience are concerned. 

§ 3. We have thus far treated Plurality of Causes only as 



488 


INDUCTION. 


a possible supposition, which, until removed, renders our induc¬ 
tions uncertain, and have only considered by what means, where 
the plurality does not really exist, we may be enabled to dis¬ 
prove it. But we must also consider it as a case actually 
occurring m nature, and which, as often as it does occur, our 
methods of induction ought to be capable of ascertaining and 
establishing. For this, however, there is requned no peculiar 
method When an effect is really producible by two 01 more 
causes, the process for detecting them is m no way different 
from that by which we discover single causes They may 
(first) be discovered as separate sequences, by separate sets of 
instances. One set of observations or experiments shows that 
the sun is a cause of heat, another that friction is a source of 
it, another that percussion, another that electricity, another 
that chemical action is such a souice. Or (secondly) the 
plurality may come to light m the course of collating a 
number of instances, when we attempt to find some circum¬ 
stance m which they all agiee, and fail m doing so. We find 
it impossible to trace, m all the cases m which the effect is 
met with, any common circumstance. We find that we can 
eliminate all the antecedents, that no one of them is present 
in all the instances, no one of them indispensable to the effect. 
On closer sciutmy, however, it appears that though no one is 
always present, one or other of several always is. If, on fur¬ 
ther analysis, we can detect m these any common element, we 
may be able to ascend from them to some one cause which is 
the really operative circumstance m them all. Thus it is now 
thought that m the production of heat by friction, percussion, 
chemical action, &c., the ultim ate source is one and the same. 
But if (as continually happens) we cannot take this ulterior 
step, the different antecedents must be set down provisionally 
as distinct causes, each sufficient of itself to produce the 
effect. 

We here close our remarks on the Plurality of Causes, and 
proceed to the stdl more peculiar and more complex case of 
the Intermixture of Effects, and the interference of causes 
with one another: a case constituting the principal part of 
the complication and difficulty of the study of nature, and 



INTERMIXTURE OF EFFECTS. 


489 


with which the four only possible methods of directly induc¬ 
tive investigation by observation and experiment, are for the 
most part, as will appeal presently, quite unequal to cope. 
The instrument of Deduction alone is adequate to unravel the 
complexities proceeding fiom this source, and the four 
methods have little more m their power than to supply pre¬ 
mises for, and a verification of, our deductions. 

§ 4 A concurrence of two or more causes, not separately 
producing each its own effect, hut inteifenng with or modify¬ 
ing the effects of one another, takes place, as has already 
been explained, m two different ways In the one, which is 
exemplified by the joint opeiation of different forces m 
mechanics, the separate effects of all the causes continue to 
he produced, hut are compounded with one another, and dis¬ 
appear m one total. In the other, illustrated by the case of 
chemical action, the separate effects cease entnely, and are 
succeeded by phenomena altogether different, and governed by 
different laws. 

Of these cases the former is by far the more frequent, and 
this case it is which, for the most part, eludes the grasp of 
our experimental methods. The other and exceptional case is 
essentially amenable to them. When the laws of the ongmal 
agents cease entirely, and a phenomenon makes its appearance, 
which, with reference to those laws, is quite heterogeneous, 
when, for example, two gaseous substances, hydrogen and 
oxygen, on being brought together, throw off their peculiar 
propel ties, and produce the substance called water, m such 
cases the new fact may be subjected to experimental inquiry, 
like any other phenomenon, and the elements which are said 
to compose it may be considered as the mere agents of its 
production; the conditions on which it depends, the facts 
which make up its cause. 

The effects of the new phenomenon, the properties of water, 
for instance, aie as easily found by experiment as the effects 
of any other cause But to discover the cause of it, that is, 
the particular conjunction of agents from which it results, is 
often difficult enough. In the first place, the origin and 



490 


INDUCTION. 


actual production of the phenomenon are most frequently in¬ 
accessible to our observation. If we could not have learned 
the composition of water until we found instances m which it 
was actually produced from oxygen and hydrogen, we should 
have been forced to wait until the casual thought stiuck some 
one of passing an electnc spaik through a mixture of the two 
gases, or inserting a lighted taper into it, merely to try what 
would happen. Besides, many substances, though they can 
be analysed, cannot by any known artificial means be recom¬ 
pounded. Further, even if we could have ascertained, by the 
Method of Agieement, that oxygen and hydrogen were both 
piesent when water is produced, no expenmentation on oxygen 
and hydrogen separately, no knowledge of their laws, could 
have enabled us deductively to infer that they would produce 
water. We require a specific experiment on the two com¬ 
bined 

Under these difficulties, we should geneially have been 
indebted for our knowledge of the causes of this class of effects, 
not to any inquiry directed specifically towards that end, but 
either to accident, or to the gradual progress of expenmenta- 
tion on the different combinations of which the pioducmg 
agents are susceptible , if it were not for a peculiarity belong¬ 
ing to effects of this description, that they often, under some 
particular combination of circumstances, leproduce their 
causes. If water results from the juxtaposition of hydrogen 
and oxygen whenever this can be made sufficiently close and 
intimate, so, on the other hand, if water itself be placed m 
certain situations, hydrogen and oxygen are reproduced from 
it: an abrupt termination is put to the new laws, and the 
agents reappear separately with their own properties as at 
first What is called chemical analysis is the process of 
searching for the causes of a phenomenon among its effects, 
or rather among the effects produced by the action of some 
other causes upon it. 

Lavoisier, by heating mercury to a high temperature in a 
close vessel containing air, found that the mercury increased 
in weight, and became what was then called red piecipitate, 
while the air, on being examined after the experiment, proved 



INTERMIXTURE OF EFFECTS. 


491 


to have lost weight, and to have become incapable of sup¬ 
porting life or combustion. When red precipitate was ex¬ 
posed to a still greater heat, it became meicury again, and 
gave off a gas which did support life and flame. Thus the 
agents which by their combination produced red precipitate, 
namely the mercury and the gas, reappear as effects resulting 
fiom that pi ecipitate when acted upon by heat So, if we 
decompose water by means of iron filings, we produce two 
effects, rust and hydiogen * now rust is aheady known by 
expenments upon the component substances, to be an effect 
of the union of iron and oxygen the iron we ourselves supplied, 
but the oxygen must have been produced from the water. 
The result therefore is that water has disappeared, and hydro¬ 
gen and oxygen have appealed m its stead or m other woids, 
the original laws of these gaseous agents, which had been 
suspended by the supermduction of the new laws called the 
pioperties of water, have again staited into existence, and the 
causes of water aie found among its effects. 

Wheie two phenomena, between the laws or properties of 
which considered m themselves no connexion can be traced, 
aie thus leciprocally cause and effect, each capable m its turn 
of being produced from the other, and each, when it produces 
the other, ceasing itself to exist (as water is produced from 
oxygen and hydrogen, and oxygen and hydrogen aie repro¬ 
duced fiom water), this causation of the two phenomena by 
one another, each being geneiated by the others destruction, 
is properly transformation. The idea of chemical composition 
is an idea ot tiansformation, but of a transformation which is 
incomplete , since we consider the oxygen and hydrogen to be 
piesent m the water as oxygen and hydrogen, and capable of 
being discovered m it if our senses were sufficiently keen * a 
supposition (for it is no more) grounded solely on the fact, 
that the weight of the water is the sum of the separate 
weights of the two ingredients. If there had not been this 
exception to the entire disappearance, m the compound, of the 
laws of the separate ingredients; if the combined agents had 
not, m this one particular of weight, preserved their own laws, 
and produced a joint result equal to the sum of their separate 



492 


INDUCTION. 


results , we should never, probably, have bad tbe notion now 
implied by tbe words cbemical composition . and, m tbe facts 
of water produced from bydiogen and oxygen, and hydiogen 
and oxygen produced from watei, as tbe transformation would 
bave been complete, we should have seen only a tiansfoimation 
The veiv promising generalization now commonly known 
as the Conseivation or Persistence of Foice, bears a close resem¬ 
blance to what tbe conception of cbemical composition would 
become, if divested of tbe one circumstance which now dis¬ 
tinguishes it fiom simple tiansfoimation. It has long been 
known that beat is capable of producing electricity, and 
electricity beat, that mechanical motion m numerous cases 
produces and is produced by them both, and so of all other 
physical forces. It has of late become tbe geneial belief of 
scientific inquirers that mechanical force, electricity, magnetism, 
heat, light, and cbemical action (to which has subsequently 
been added vital action) aie not so much causes of one 
another as conveitible into one another, and they aie now 
generally spoken of as forms of one and tbe same foice, 
varying only in its manifestations. This doctrine may 
he admitted, without by any means implying that Poice 
is a real entity, a Thing m itself, distinct from all its 
phenomenal manifestations to our organs Supposing tbe 
doctrine true, tbe several kinds of phenomena which it iden¬ 
tifies m respect of their origin would nevertheless lemam diffe¬ 
rent facts, facts which would be causes of one another— 
recipiocally causes and effects, which is the first element m the 
form of causation propelly called transformation. What the 
doctrine contains more than this, is, that m each of these cases 
of reciprocal causation, the causes are reproduced without 
alteration m quantity This is what takes place m the trans¬ 
formations of matter * when water has been converted into 
hydrogen and oxygen, these can be reconverted into precisely 
the same quantity of water from which they were produced. 
To establish a corresponding law m regard to Force, it has to 
he proved that heat is capable of being converted into elec¬ 
tricity, electricity into chemical action, chemical action into 
mechanical force, and mechanical force back again into the 
exact quantity of heat which was originally expended, and so 



INTERMIXTURE OF EFFECTS. 


493 


through all the interchanges. Were this proved, it would 
establish what constitutes transformation, as distinguished 
from the simple fact of reciprocal causation The fact m issue 
is simply the quantitative equivalence of all these natural 
agencies, whereby a given quantity of any oneTs convertible 
into, and interchangeable with, a given, and always the same, 
quantity of any other* this, no less, but also no more. It cannot 
yet be said that the law has been fully proved of any case, ex¬ 
cept that of interchange between heat and mechanical motion. 
It does seem to be ascertained, not only that these two are 
convertible into each other, but that after any number of con¬ 
versions the oiigmal quantities reappear without addition or 
diminution, like the original quantities of hydiogen and oxygen 
after passing through the condition of water If the same 
thing comes to be proved true of all the other forces, in rela¬ 
tion to these two and to one another, the law of Conservation 
will be established, and it will be a legitimate mode of ex¬ 
pressing the fact, to speak of Force, as we already speak of 
Matter, as indestructible. But Force will not the less remain, 
to the philosopher, a meie abstraction of the mind. All that 
will have been proved is, that m the phenomena of Nature, 
nothing actually ceases without generating a calculable, and 
always the same, quantity of some other natural phenomenon, 
which again, when it ceases, will in its turn either generate a 
calculable, and always the same, quantity of some third phe¬ 
nomenon, or reproduce the original quantity of the first. 

In these cases, where the heteropathic effect (as we called it 
in a former chaptei)* is but a transformation of its cause, or 
in other words, where the effect and its cause are reciprocally 
such, and mutually convertible into each other; the problem 
of finding the cause resolves itself into the far easier one of 
finding an effect, which is the kind of inquiry that admits of 
being prosecuted by direct experiment. But there are other 
cases of heteropathic effects to which this mode of investiga¬ 
tion is not applicable. Take, for instance, the heteropathic 
laws of mind, that portion of the phenomena of our mental 
nature which are analogous to chemical rather than to dyna- 


Ante, ch. vn § 1. 



494 


INDUCTION. 


mical phenomena, as when a complex passion is formed by the 
coalition of seveial elementary impulses, or a complex emotion 
by seveial simple pleasures or pains, of which it is the result 
without being the aggiegate, or in any lespect homogeneous 
with them The pioduct, m these cases, is generated by its 
various factors, but the factors cannot be reproduced from the 
product, just as a youth can grow into an old man, but an old 
man cannot grow into a youth We cannot ascertain ftom 
what simple feelings any of our complex states of mind are 
generated, as we ascertain the ingredients of a chemical com¬ 
pound, by making it, m its turn, generate them. We can only, 
theiefore, discover these laws by the slow piocess of studying 
the simple feelings themselves, and ascertaining synthetically, 
by experimenting on the various combinations of which they 
are susceptible, what they, by their mutual action upon one 
another, are capable of geneiatmg. 

§ 5 . It might have been supposed that the other, and 
apparently simpler variety of the mutual mteiference of causes, 
where each cause continues to produce its own proper effect 
according to the same laws to which it conforms m its separate 
state, would have presented fewer difficulties to the inductive 
inquirer than that of which we have just finished the con¬ 
sideration. It piesents, however, so far as direct induction 
apart from deduction is concerned, infinitely greater diffi¬ 
culties. When a concurrence of causes gives rise to a new 
effect, bearing no ielation to the separate effects of those 
causes, the resulting phenomenon stands forth undisguised, 
inviting attention to its peculiarity, and presenting no obstacle 
to our recognising its presence or absence among any number 
of surrounding phenomena It admits therefore of being easily 
brought under the canons of Induction, provided instances can 
he obtained such as those canons requne and the non-occur¬ 
rence of such instances, or the want of means to produce them 
artificially, is the real and only difficulty in such investiga¬ 
tions , a difficulty not logical, but m some sort physical It is 
otherwise with cases of what, m a piecedmg chapter, has been 
denominated the Composition of Causes. There, the effects of 



INTERMIXTURE OF EFFECTS, 


495 


the separate causes do not terminate and give place to others, 
thereby ceasing to form any part of the phenomenon to he 
investigated, on the contrary, they still take place, but are 
intermingled with, and disguised by, the homogeneous and 
closely allied effects of other causes. They are no longer 
a, 5, c, d } e, existing side by side, and continuing to be sepa¬ 
rately discernible, they are + a } — a, -J- b } — h, 2 b, &c , some 
of which cancel one another, while many others do not appear 
distinguishably, but merge m one sum. forming altogether 
a result, between which and the causes whereby it was pro¬ 
duced there is often an insurmountable difficulty m tracing by 
observation any fixed relation whatever 

The geneial idea of the Composition of Causes has been 
seen to be, that though two or more laws interfere with one 
another, and apparently frustrate or modify one another’s 
operation, yet m reality all are fulfilled, the collective effect 
being the exact sum of the effects of the causes taken sepa¬ 
rately. A familiar instance is that of a body kept m equili¬ 
brium by two equal and contrary forces One of the forces 
if acting alone would carry the body m a given time a certain 
distance to the west, the other if acting alone would carry it 
exactly as far towards the east, and the result is the same as 
if it had been first carried to the west as far as the one force 
would carry it, and then back towards the east as far as the 
other would cany it, that is, precisely the same distance; 
being ultimately left where it was found at first. 

All laws of causation are liable to be m this manner 
counteiacted, and seemingly frustrated, by coming into con¬ 
flict with other laws, the separate result of which is opposite 
to theirs, or more or less inconsistent with it. And hence, 
with almost eveiy law, many instances m which it really is 
entirely fulfilled, do not, at first sight, appear to be cases of 
its operation at all It is so in the example just adduced. a 
force, m mechanics, means neither more nor less than a cause 
of motion, yet the sum of the effects of two causes of motion 
may be rest Again, a body solicited by two forces m direc¬ 
tions making an angle with one another, moves m the diago¬ 
nal, and it seems a paradox to say that motion m the diagonal 



496 


INDUCTION. 


is the sum of two motions m two other lines. Motion, how¬ 
ever,, is but change of place, and at every instant the body is 
m the exact place it would have been m if the forces had 
acted during alternate instants instead of acting m the same 
instant, (saving that if we suppose two forces to act succes¬ 
sively which are in truth simultaneous, we must of course 
allow them double the time) It is evident, therefore, that 
each force has had, during each instant, all the effect which 
belonged to it, and that the modifying influence which one of 
two concurrent causes is said to exercise with respect to the 
other, may be considered as exerted not over the action of the 
cause itself, hut over the effect after it is completed For all 
purposes of predicting, calculating, or explaining their joint 
result, causes which compound their effects may be treated as 
if they produced simultaneously each of them its own effect, 
and all these effects coexisted visibly. 

Since the laws of causes are as really fulfilled when the 
causes are said to be counteracted by opposing causes, as 
when they are left to then own undistuibed action, we must 
be cautious not to express the laws m such terms as would 
render the assertion of their being fulfilled m those cases 
a contradiction If, for instance, it were stated as a law 
of nature that a body to which a force is applied moves 
m the direction of the force, with a velocity proportioned 
to the force directly, and to its own mass inversely, when 
m point of fact some bodies to which a foice is applied 
do not move at all, and those which do move (at least 
in the region of our earth) are, from the veiy first, 
retarded by the action of gravity and other resisting forces, 
and at last stopped altogether, it is clear that the general 
proposition, though it would be true under a certain hypo¬ 
thesis, would not express the facts as they actually occur To 
accommodate the expression of the law to the real pheno¬ 
mena, we must say, not that the object moves, but that it 
tends to move, in the direction and with the velocity specified. 
We might, indeed, guard our expression m a different mode, 
by saying that the body moves m that manner unless pre¬ 
vented, or except m so far as prevented, by some counteracting 



INTERMIXTURE OF EFFECTS. 


497 


cause. But the body does not only move in that manner 
unless counteracted, it tends to move m that manner even 
when counteracted , it still exerts, m the original direction, 
the same energy of movement as if its first impulse had been 
undisturbed, and produces, by that energy, an exactly equiva¬ 
lent quantity of effect. This is true even when the force 
leaves the body as it found it, m a state of absolute rest, as 
when we attempt to raise a body of three tons weight with 
a force equal to one ton. For if, while we are applying this 
force, wind or water or any other agent supplies an additional 
force just exceeding two tons, the body will be raised; thus 
proving that the force we applied exerted its full effect, by 
neutralizing an equivalent portion of the weight which it 
was insufficient altogether to overcome. And if while we are 
exerting this foice of one ton upon the object m a direction 
contrary to that of gravity, it be put into a scale and weighed, 
it will be found to have lost a ton of its weight, or m other 
woids, to piess downwards with a force only equal to the 
difference of the two forces 

These facts are correctly indicated by the expression 
tendency . All laws of causation, in consequence of their 
liability to be counteracted, require to be stated m words 
affirmative of tendencies only, and not of actual results. In 
those sciences of causation which have an accurate nomen- 
clatuie, theie are special woids which signify a tendency to 
the particular effect with which the science is conversant, 
thus presswe, in mechanics, is synonymous with tendency to 
motion, and forces are not reasoned on as causing actual 
motion, but as exerting pressure. A similar improvement 
m terminology would be very salutary m many other branches 
of science. 

The habit of neglecting this necessary element m the 
precise expression of the laws of nature, has given birth to 
the popular piejudice that all general truths have exceptions , 
and much unmerited distrust has thence accrued to the con¬ 
clusions of science, when they have been submitted to the 
judgment of minds insufficiently disciplined and cultivated. 
The rough generalizations suggested by common observation 
VOL. i. 32 



498 


INDUCTION. 


usually have exceptions, but principles of science, or m 
other words, laws of causation, have not £C What is thought 
to be an exception to a principle/’ (to quote words used on 
a different occasion,) “is always some other and distinct 
principle cutting into the former, some other force which 
impinges* against the first force, and deflects it from its 
direction. There are not a law and an exception to that law, 
the law acting m ninety-nine cases, and the exception in one 
/There are two laws, each possibly acting m the whole hundred 
cases, and bunging about a common effect by their conjunct 
opei ation. If the force which, being the less conspicuous of 
the two, is called the disturbing force, prevails sufficiently 
over the other force m some one case, to constitute that case 
what is commonly called an exception, the same disturbing 
force piobably acts as a modifying cause m many other cases 
which no one will call exceptions. 

“ Thus if it were stated to be a law of nature that all 
heavy bodies fall to the ground, it would probably be said 
that the lesistance of the atmosphere, which pi events a balloon 
from falling, constitutes the balloon an exception to that 
pretended law of natuie. But the leal law is, that all heavy 
bodies tend to fall, and to this theie is no exception, not even 
the sun and moon, for even they, as every astionomer knows, 
tend towaids the eaith, with a force exactly equal to that 
with which the earth tends towards them. The resistance of 
the atmosphere might, m the paiticular case of the balloon, 
from a misapprehension of what the law of gravitation is, be 
said to prevail over the law, but its disturbing effect is quite 
as leal m every other case, since though it does not prevent, 
it retaids the fall of all bodies whatever The rule, and the 
so-called exception, do not divide the cases between them, 
each of them is a comprehensive rule extending to all cases. 
To call one of these concurrent principles an exception to 
the other, is superficial, and contrary to the correct principles 


* It seems hardly necessary to say that the word impinge, as a general 
term to express collision of forces, is here used by a figure of speech, and not 
as expressive of any theory respecting the nature of force 



INTERMIXTURE OF EFFECTS. 


499 


of nomenclature and arrangement. An effect of precisely the 
same kind, and arising from the same cause, ought not to be 
placed m two different categories, merely as there does or does 
not exist another cause preponderating over it/’ # 

§ 6. We have now to consider according to what method 
these complex effects, compounded of the effects of many 
causes, are to be studied, how we are enabled to trace each 
effect to the concurrence of causes m which it originated, and 
ascertain the conditions of its recurrence—the circumstances 
m which it may be expected again to occur The conditions 
of a phenomenon which arises from a composition of causes, 
may be investigated either deductively or experimentally 

The case, it is evident, is naturally susceptible of the 
deductive mode of investigation. The law of an effect of this 
description is a result of the laws of the separate causes on 
the combination of which it depends, and is therefore m 
itself capable of being deduced from these laws. This is 
called the method a prion. The other, or ciposteriori method, 
professes to proceed according to the canons of experimental 
mquny. Considering the whole assemblage of concurrent 
causes which produced the phenomenon, as one single cause, 
it attempts to ascertain the cause m the ordinary manner, by a 
comparison of instances. This second method subdivides 
itself into two different varieties If it merely collates 
instances of the effect, it is a method of pure observation If 
it operates upon the causes, and tries different combinations of 
them, m hopes of ultimately hitting the precise combination 
which will produce the given total effect, it is a method of 
experiment. 

In order more completely to clear up the nature of each of 
these three methods, and determine winch of them deserves the 
preference, it will be expedient (conformably to a favourite 
maxim of Lord Chancellor Eldon, to which, though it has 
often incurred philosophical ridicule, a deeper philosophy will 
not refuse its sanction) to “ clothe them m circumstances ” 


Essays on some Unsettled Questions of Political Economy, Essa, V 
82—2 



500 


INDUCTION, 


We shall select for this purpose a case which as yet furnishes 
no very brilliant example of the success of any of the thiee 
methods, hut which is all the more suited to illustrate the 
difficulties inherent m them. Let the subject of inquiry be, 
the conditions of health and disease m the human body, 01 
(for greater simplicity) the conditions of recovery from a given 
disease; and m order to narrow the question still more, let it 
be limited., in the first instance, to this one inquiry * Is, or is 
not some particular medicament (mercury, for instance) a 
lemedy for the given disease. 

Now, the deductive method would set out fiom known 
piopeities of mercury, and known laws of the human body, 
and by reasoning fiom these, would attempt to discover 
whethei mercuiy will act upon the body when m the morbid 
condition supposed, m such a manner as to restore health. 
The experimental method would simply administer mercury m 
as many cases as possible, noting the age, sex, tempeiament, 
and other peculianties of bodily constitution, the particular 
form or variety of the disease, the paiticulai stage of its pro¬ 
gress, &c., lemaikmg m which of these cases it pioduced a 
salutary effect, and with what circumstances it was on those 
occasions combined The method of simple observation would 
compare instances of recovery, to find whether they agreed m 
having been pieceded by the administration of mercury, or 
would compaie instances of recovery with instances of failure, 
to find cases which, agreeing m all other respects, differed 
only m the fact that meioury had been administered, or that 
it had not. 

§ 7 . That the last of these three modes of investigation 
is applicable to the case, no one has ever seriously contended. 
No conclusions of value on a subject of such intricacy, ever 
weie ' obtained m that way The utmost that could result 
would he a vague general impression for or against the efficacy 
of mercury, of no avail for guidance unless confirmed by one 
of the other two methods. Not that the results, which this 
method stuves to obtain, would not he of the utmost possible 
value if they could be obtained. If all the cases of recovery 



INTERMIXTURE OF EFFECTS. 


501 


which presented themselves, m an examination extending to a 
great numbei of instances, were cases m which mercury had 
been admmisteied, we might generalize with confidence from 
this experience, and should have obtained a conclusion of real 
value But no such basis for generalization can we, m a case 
of this description, hope to obtain. The leason is that which 
we have spoken of as constituting the characteristic imperfec¬ 
tion of the Method of Agreement, Pluiality of Causes. Sup¬ 
posing even that meicury does tend to cure the disease, so 
many other causes, both natural and artificial, also tend to 
cure it, that there are sure to be abundant instances of recovery 
m which mercury has not been administered: unless, indeed, 
the piactice be to administer it m all cases, on which suppo¬ 
sition it will equally be found m the cases of failure. 

When an effect results from the union of many causes, the 
share which each has m the determination of the effect cannot 
m general be great: and the effect is not likely, even m its 
presence or absence, still less m its variations, to follow, even 
approximately, any one of the causes. Recovery from a 
disease is an event to which, in every case, many influences 
must concur. Mercury may be one such influence , but from 
the very fact that there are many other such, it will necessanly 
happen that although mercury is administered, the patient, 
for want of other concurring influences, will often not recover, 
and that he often will recover when it is not administered, the 
other favourable influences being sufficiently powerful without 
it. Neither, therefore, will the instances of recovery agree m 
the administration of mercury, nor will the instances of failure 
agree m its non-admimstration. It is much if, by multiplied 
and accurate returns from hospitals and the like, we can 
collect that there aie rather more recoveries and rather fewei 
failures when mercury is administered than when it is not, a 
result of very secondary value even as a guide to practice, 
and almost worthless as a contilbution to the theory of the 
subject. 

§ 8. The inapplicability of the method of simple obser¬ 
vation to ascertain the conditions of effects dependent on 



502 


INDUCTION* 


many concunmg causes, being thus recognised, we shall next 
inquire whether any greater benefit can be expected from the 
other branch of the ii posteriori method, that which proceeds 
by directly trying different combinations of causes, either arti¬ 
ficially produced or found m nature, and taking notice what is 
their effect as, for example, by actually trying the effect of 
mercury, in as many different circumstances as possible. This 
method differs from the one which we have just examined, m 
turning our attention directly to the causes or agents, instead 
of turning it to the effect, recovery from the disease. And since, 
as a general rule, the effects of causes are far more accessible 
to our study than the causes of effects, it is natural to think 
that this method has a much better chance of proving suc¬ 
cessful than the former. 

The method now under consideration is called the Empi¬ 
rical Method; and m order to estimate it fairly, we must sup¬ 
pose it to be completely, not incompletely, empirical. We 
must exclude from it everything which partakes of the nature 
not of an experimental but of a deductive operation. If for 
instance we try experiments with mercury upon a peison m 
health, m order to ascertain the general laws of its action upon 
the human body, and then reason from these laws to determine 
how it will act upon persons affected with a particular disease, 
this may be a really effectual method, but this is deduction. 
The experimental method does not derive the law of a com¬ 
plex case from the simpler laws which conspire to produce it, 
but makes its experiments directly upon the complex case. We 
must make entire abstraction of all knowledge of the simpler 
tendencies, the modi operandi of mercury m detail. Our ex¬ 
perimentation must aim at obtaining a direct answer to the 
specific question, Does or does not mercury tend to cure the 
particular disease ? 

Let us see, therefore, how far the case admits of the 
observance of those rules of experimentation, which it is found 
necessary to obsexve m other cases. W T hen we devise an ex¬ 
periment to ascertain the effect of a given agent, there are 
certain precautions which we never, if we can help it, omit. 
In the first place, we introduce the agent into the midst of a 



INTERMIXTURE OF EFFECTS. 


503 


set of circumstances which we have exactly ascertained. It 
needs hardly be remarked how far this condition is from being 
realized m any case connected with the phenomena of life , 
how far we are from knowing what are all the circumstances 
which pre-exist m any instance m which mercury is admi¬ 
nistered to a living being. This difficulty, however, though 
insuperable in most cases, may not be so m all, there are 
sometimes concurrences of many causes, m which we yet know 
accurately what the causes are. Moreover, the difficulty may 
be attenuated by sufficient multiplication of experiments, m 
circumstances rendering it improbable that any of the un¬ 
known causes should exist m them all. But when we have got 
clear of this obstacle, we encounter another still more serious. 
In other cases, when we intend to try an experiment, we do 
not reckon it enough that there be no circumstance m the 
case the presence of which is unknown to us We require 
also that none of the circumstances which we do know, shall 
have effects susceptible of being confounded with those of 
the agent whose properties we wish to study. We take the 
utmost pains to exclude all causes capable of composition with 
the given cause; or if forced to let m any such causes, we 
take caie to make them such that we can compute and allow 
for their influence, so that the effect of the given cause may, 
after the subduction of those other effects, be apparent as a 
residual phenomenon. 

These precautions are inapplicable to such cases as we are 
now considering. The mercuiy of our experiment being tried 
with an unknown multitude (or even let it be a known multi¬ 
tude) of other influencing circumstances, the mere fact of their 
being influencing circumstances implies that they disguise the 
effect of the meicurv, and preclude us from knowing whether 
it has any effect or not. Unless we already knew what and 
how much is owing to every other circumstance, (that is, 
unless we suppose the very problem solved which we are con¬ 
sidering the means of solving,) we cannot tell that those other 
circumstances may not have produced the whole of the effect, 
independently or even in spite of the mercury. The Method 
of Difference, in the ordinary mode of its use, namely by 



504 


INDUCTION. 


comparing the state of things following the experiment with 
the state which preceded it, is thus, in the case of intermixture 
of effects, entirely unavailing, because othei causes than that 
whose effect we are seeking to determine, have been operating 
during the transition. As for the other mode of employing 
the Method of Diffeience, namely by comparing, not the same 
case at two different periods, hut different cases, this m the 
present instance is quite chimerical In phenomena so com¬ 
plicated it is questionable if two cases, similar m all respects 
but one, ever occuired, and were they to occur, we could not 
possibly know that they were so exactly similar 

Anything like a scientific use of the method of experiment, 
m these complicated cases, is theiefore out of the question 
We can m the most favourable cases only discover, by a suc¬ 
cession of trials, that a certain cause is tery often followed by 
a certain effect For, m one of these conjunct effects, the 
portion which is determined by any one of the influencing 
agents, is generally, as we before remarked, but small; and it 
must be a more potent cause than most, if even the tendency 
which it really exerts is not thwarted by other tendencies m 
nearly as many cases as it is fulfilled. 

If so little can be done by the experimental method to 
determine the conditions of an effect of many combined causes, 
in the case of medical science, still less is this method appli¬ 
cable to a class of phenomena more complicated than even 
those of physiology, the phenomena of politics and history. 
There, Plurality of Causes exists m almost boundless excess, 
and effects are, for the most pait, inextricably interwoven 
with one another. To add to the embarrassment, most of the 
inquiries m political science relate to the production of effects 
of a most comprehensive description, such as the public wealth, 
public security, public morality, and the like results liable to 
be affected directly or indirectly either m plus or m minus by 
nearly every fact which exists, or event which occurs, m human 
society The vulgar notion, that the safe methods on political 
subjects are those of Baconian induction—that the true guide 
is not general reasoning, but specific experience—will one day 
be quoted as among the most unequivocal marks of a low state 



INTERMIXTURE OF EFFECTS. 


505 


of the speculative faculties m any age m which it is accredited 
Nothing can be more ludicrous than the sort of parodies on 
experimental reasoning which one is accustomed to meet with, 
not m popular discussion only, but m grave treatises, when 
the affairs of nations are the theme. “How,” it is asked, 
can an institution he bad, when the country has prospered 
under it (e How can such or such causes have contributed 
to the prosperity of one countiy, when another has prospered 
without them ?” Whoever makes use of an argument of this 
kmd, not intending to deceive, should he sent back to learn 
the elements of some one of the more easy physical sciences 
Such reasoners ignore the fact of Plurality of Causes m the 
very case which affords the most signal example of it. So 
little could be concluded, m such a case, from any possible 
collation of individual instances, that even the impossibility, 
m social phenomena, of making artificial experiments, a cir¬ 
cumstance otherwise so prejudicial to dnectly inductive inquiry, 
haidly affords, m this case, additional reason of regret For 
even if we could try experiments upon a nation or upon the 
human race, with as httle scruple as M Magendie tried them 
on dogs and rabbits, we should never succeed m making two 
instances identical m every respect except the presence or 
absence of some one definite circumstance. The nearest 
approach to an experiment m the philosophical sense, which 
takes place in politics, is the introduction of a new operative 
element into national affairs by some special and assignable 
measure of government, such as the enactment or repeal of a 
particular law. But where there are so many influences at 
work, it requires some time for the influence of any new cause 
upon national phenomena to become apparent; and as the 
causes operating m so extensive a sphere are not only infinitely 
numerous, but m a state of perpetual alteration, it is always 
certain that before the effect of the new cause becomes con¬ 
spicuous enough to be a subject of induction, so many of the 
other influencing circumstances will have changed as to vitiate 
the experiment. 

Two, therefore, of the three possible methods for the study 
of phenomena resulting from the composition of many causes, 



506 


INDUCTION. 


being, from tbe very nature of tbe case, inefficient and illu¬ 
sory, there remains only the third,—that which considers the 
causes sepaiately, and infers the effect from the balance 
of the different tendencies which pioduce it m short, the 
deductive, or a prion method The more particular con¬ 
sideration of this intellectual process requires a chapter to 
itself. 



CHAPTER XI. 


OF THE DEDUCTIVE METHOD. 

§ 1. The mode of investigation which, from the proved 
inapplicability of direct methods of observation and experiment, 
remains to us as the mam source of the knowledge we possess 
or can acquire respecting the conditions, and laws of recur¬ 
rence, of the more complex phenomena, is called, in its most 
general expression, the Deductive Method, and consists of 
thiee operations: the first, one of direct induction, the second, 
of ratiocination; the third, of verification. 

I call the first step m the process an inductive operation, 
because there must be a direct induction as the basis of the 
whole; though m many particular investigations the place 
of the induction may be supplied by a prior deduction , but the 
premises of this prior deduction must have been derived from 
induction. 

The problem of the Deductive Method is, to find the law 
of an effect, from the laws of the different tendencies of which 
it is the joint result. The first requisite, therefore, is to know 
the laws of those tendencies, the law of each of the concurrent 
causes and this supposes a previous process of observation or 
experiment upon each cause separately, or else a previous 
deduction, which also must depend for its ultimate premises 
on observation or experiment. Thus, if the subject be social 
or historical phenomena, the premises of the Deductive Method 
must be the laws of the causes which determine that class of 
phenomena, and those causes are human actions, together 
with the general outward circumstances under the influence of 
which mankind are placed, and which constitute man’s posi¬ 
tion on the earth. The Deductive Method, applied to social 
phenomena, must begin, therefore, by investigating, or must 
suppose to have been already investigated, the laws of human 



508 


INDUCTION 


action, and those properties of outwaid things by -which the 
actions of human beings m society are determined Some of 
these geneial truths will naturally be obtained by obseiration 
and experiment, otheis by deduction the moie complex laws 
of human action, for example, may be deduced from the 
simpler ones , but the simple or elementary laws will always, 
and necessarily, have been obtained by a directly inductive 
process. 

To ascertain, then, the laws of each separate cause which 
takes a shaie m producing the effect, is the first desideratum 
of the Deductive Method To know what the causes aie, 
which must be subjected to this process of study, may or may 
not be difficult In the case last mentioned, this first condi¬ 
tion is of easy fulfilment That social phenomena depend on 
the acts and mental impiessions of human beings, never could 
have been a matter of any doubt, however imperfectly it may 
have been known either by what laws those impressions 
and actions are governed, or to what social consequences their 
laws natuially lead Neithei, again, after physical science 
had attained a certain development, could there be any real 
doubt where to look for the laws on which the phenomena of 
life depend, since they must be the mechanical and chemical 
laws of the solid and fluid substances composing the organized 
body and the medium m which it subsists, together with the 
peculiar vital laws of the different tissues constituting the 
organic structure. In other cases, leally far more simple than 
these, it was much less obvious m what quarter the causes 
were to be looked for as m the case of the celestial pheno¬ 
mena Until, by combining the laws of certain causes, it was 
found that those laws explained all the facts which experience 
had proved concerning the heavenly motions, and led to pre¬ 
dictions which it always verified, mankind never knew that 
those were the causes. But whether we are able to put the 
question before, or not until after, we have become capable of 
answering it, m either case it must be answered, the laws of 
the different causes must be ascertained, before we can proceed 
to deduce from them the conditions of the effect. 

The mode of ascertaining those laws neither is, nor can be, 



THE DEDUCTIVE METHOD. 


509 


**any other than the fourfold method of experimental inquiry, 
falready discussed A few remarks on the application of that 
method to cases of the Composition of Causes, are all that is 
requisite. 

It is obvious that we cannot expect to find the law of a 
tendency, by an induction from cases m which the tendency 
is counteracted The laws of motion could never have been 
brought to light from the observation of bodies kept at rest 
by the equilibrium of opposing forces. Even where the ten¬ 
dency is not, m the ordinary sense of the word, counteracted, 
but only modified, by having its effects compounded with the 
effects arising from some other tendency or tendencies, we are 
still m an unfavourable position for tracing, by means of such 
cases, the law of the tendency itself. It would have been 
scaicely possible to discover the law that everybody m motion 
tends to continue moving m a straight line, by an induction 
from instances m which the motion is deflected into a curve, 
by being compounded with the effect of an accelerating force 
Notwithstanding the resources afforded m this description of 
cases by the Method of Concomitant Variations, the principles 
of a judicious experimentation prescribe that the law of each 
of the tendencies should be studied, if possible, m cases in which 
that tendency operates alone, or m combination with no agencies 
but those of which the effect can, from previous knowledge, be 
calculated and allowed for 

Accordingly, in the cases, unfortunately very numerous and 
important, m which the causes do not suffer themselves to be 
separated and observed apart, there is much difficulty inlaying 
down with due ceitamty the inductive foundation necessary to 
support the deductive method. This difficulty is most of all 
conspicuous in the case of physiological phenomena, it being 
seldom possible to sepaiate the different agencies which col¬ 
lectively compose an organized body, without destroying the 
veiy phenomena which it is our object to investigate. 

-following life, xn creatures we dissect, 

We lose it, in the moment we detect 

And for this reason I am inclined to the opinion, that phy- 



510 


INDUCTION 


siology (greatly and xapidly piogressive as it now is) is embar- 
lassed by greater natural difficulties, and is probably susceptible 
of a less degiee of ultimate perfection, than even the social 
science, inasmuch as it is possible to study the laws and ope¬ 
rations of one human mind apart from other minds, much less 
imperfectly than we can study the laws of one organ or tissue 
of the human body apart from the other organs or tissues. 

It has been judiciously remarked that pathological facts, 
or, to speak m common language, diseases m their different 
forms and degrees, afford m the case of physiological investi¬ 
gation the most valuable equivalent to experimentation pro- 
peily so called, inasmuch as they often exhibit to us a definite 
disturbance m some one organ or organic function, the remain¬ 
ing organs and functions being, in the first instance at least, 
unaffected. It is true that from the perpetual actions and re¬ 
actions which are going on among all paits of the organic 
economy, there can be no piolonged distuibance m any one 
function without ultimately involving many of the others; 
and when once it has done so, the experiment for the most 
part loses its scientific value All depends on obseivmg the 
early stages of the derangement, which, unfortunately, are of 
necessity the least marked If, however, the oigans and func¬ 
tions not disturbed m the first instance, become affected m a 
fixed older of succession, some light is thereby thrown upon 
the action which one organ exercises over another and we 
occasionally obtain a series of effects which we can refer with 
some confidence to the original local derangement, but for 
this it is necessary that we should know that the ongmal 
derangement was local If it was what is termed constitu¬ 
tional, that is, if we do not know m what pait of the animal 
economy it took its rise, or the precise nature of the disturb¬ 
ance which took place m that pait, we aie unable to determine 
which of the vanous derangements was cause and which 
effect, which of them were produced by one another, and 
which by the direct, though perhaps tardy, action of the 
original cause 

Besides natural pathological facts, we can produce patho¬ 
logical facts artificially, we can try experiments, even m the 



THE DEDUCTIVE METHOD 


511 


popular sense of the term, by subjecting the living being to 
some external agent, such as the mercury of our former ex¬ 
ample, or the section of a nerve to ascertain the functions of 
different parts of the nervous system. As this experimenta¬ 
tion is not intended to obtain a direct solution of any prac¬ 
tical question, but to discover general laws, from which 
afterwards the conditions of any particular effect may be ob¬ 
tained by deduction, the best cases to select are those of which 
the circumstances can be best ascertained and such are generally 
not those m which there is any practical object m view The 
experiments are best tried, not m a state of disease, which is 
essentially a changeable state, but m the condition of health, 
comparatively a fixed state. In the one, unusual agencies are 
at work, the results of which we have no means of predicting, 
m the other, the course of the accustomed physiological 
phenomena would, it may generally be presumed, remain un¬ 
disturbed, weie it not for the distuibmg cause which we 
introduce 

Such, with the occasional aid of the Method of Concomi¬ 
tant Variations, (the latter not less incumbered than the more 
elementary methods by the peculiai difficulties of the subject,) 
are our inductive resources for ascertaining the laws of the 
causes considered separately, when we have it not m our power 
to make trial of them m a state of actual sepai ation The 
insufficiency of these resources is so glaring, that no one can 
be surpnsed at the backward state of the science of physio¬ 
logy , m which indeed our knowledge of causes is so imperfect, 
that we can neither explain, nor could without specific expe¬ 
rience have predicted, many of the facts which are certified to 
us by the most ordinary observation. Fortunately, we are 
much better informed as to the empirical laws of the pheno¬ 
mena, that is, the uniformities respecting which we cannot 
yet decide whether they are cases of causation, or mere results 
of it. Not only has the order m which the facts of organiza¬ 
tion and life successively manifest themselves, from the first 
germ of existence to death, been found to be uniform, and 
very accurately ascertainable, but, by a great application of 
the Method of Concomitant Variations to the entire facts of 



512 


INDUCTION. 


comparative anatomy and physiology, the characteristic organic 
stiuetuie corresponding to each class of functions has been 
determined with considerable precision Whether these organic 
conditions aie the whole of the conditions, and m many cases 
whether they are conditions at all, or meie collateral effects of 
some common cause, we aie quite ignoiant. nor are we ever 
likely to know, unless we could construct an organized body, 
and tiy whether it would live. 

Under such disadvantages do we, m cases of this descrip¬ 
tion, attempt the initial, or inductive step, m the application 
of the Deductive Method to complex phenomena. But such, 
fortunately, is not the common case. In general, the laws of 
the causes on which the effect depends may be obtained by an 
induction from comparatively simple instances, or, at the 
worst, by deduction from the laws of simpler causes, so 
obtained. By simple instances are meant, of couise, those 
in which the action of each cause was not intermixed or inter¬ 
fered with, or not to any great extent, by other causes whose 
laws were unknown. And only when the induction which fur¬ 
nished the premises to the Deductive method rested on such 
instances, has the application of such a method to the ascer¬ 
tainment of the laws of a complex effect, been attended with 
brilliant results. 

§ 2. When the laws of the causes have been ascertained, 
and the first stage of the great logrcal operatron now under 
discussion satisfactorily accomplished, the second part follows, 
that of determining from the laws of the causes, what effect 
any given combination of those causes will produce. This is a 
process of calculation, m the wider sense of the term; and very 
often involves processes of calculation in the narrowest sense. 
It is a ratiocination, and when our knowledge of the causes is 
so perfect, as to extend to the exact numencal laws which 
they observe m producing their effects, the ratiocination may 
reckon among its premises the theorems of the science of 
number, m the whole immense extent of that science. Not 
only are the most advanced truths of mathematics often 
required to enable us to compute an effect, the numerical law 



THE DEDUCTIVE METHOD. 


513 


of which we already know; but, even by the aid of those most 
advanced truths, we can go but a little way. In so simple a 
case as the common pioblem of thiee bodies gravitating 
towards one another, with a force directly as then mass and 
inversely as the square of the distance, all the xesources of the 
calculus have not hitheito sufficed to obtain any geneiai solu¬ 
tion but an approximate one In a case a little more complex, 
but still one of the simplest which arise m piaetice, that of the 
motion of a piojectile, the causes which affect the velocity and 
range (for example) of a cannon-ball may be all known and 
estimated, the foice of the gunpowdei, the angle of elevation, 
the density of the an, the strength and direction of the wind, 
but it is one of the most difficult of mathematical problems to 
combine all these, so as to determine the effect resulting from 
their collective action. 

Besides the theorems of numbei, those of geometry also 
come m as premises, where the effects take place m space and 
involve motion and extension, as m mechanics, optics, acous¬ 
tics, astronomy. But when the complication mcieases, and 
the effects are under the influence of so many and such shift¬ 
ing causes as to give no loom either for fixed numbers, or for 
stiaight lines and regular curves, (as m the case of physio¬ 
logical, to say nothing of mental and social phenomena,) 
the laws of number and extension are applicable, if at all, 
only on that large scale on which precision of details becomes 
unimportant. Although these laws play a conspicuous pait 
m the most striking examples of the investigation of nature 
by the Deductive Method, as for example in the Newtonian 
theory of the celestial motions, they are by no means an indis¬ 
pensable part of every such piocess. All that is essential m 
it is reasoning from a general law to a particular case, that 
is, determining by means of the particular circumstances of 
that case, what result is required m that instance to fulfil the 
law. Thus m the Torricellian experiment, if the fact that air 
has weight had been previously known, it would have been 
easy, without any numerical data, to deduce from the general 
law of equilibrium, that the mercury would stand m the tube 
at such a height that the column of mercury would exactly 
vol. i. 33 



514 


INDUCTION, 


i 

balance a column of the afmospheie of equal diameter 
because, otherwise, equilibnum would not exist 

By such latiocmations from the sepaiate laws of the 
causes, we may, to a certain extent, succeed m answering 
either of the following questions. Gi\en a ceitam combina¬ 
tion of causes, what effect will follow ? and, TVhat combi¬ 
nation of causes, if it existed, would pioduce a given effect 0 
In the one case, we determine the effect to he expected m any 
complex circumstances of wdnch the diffeient elements aie 
known * m the othei case we leam, according to what law— 
under what antecedent conditions—a given complex effect 
will occur 

§ 3 But (it may heie be asked) are not the same argu¬ 
ments by which the methods of direct obseivation and expe¬ 
riment weie set aside as illusoiy when applied to the laws 
of complex phenomena, applicable with equal force agarnst 
the Method of Deduction ? When rn every srngle rnstance a 
multitude, often an unknown multrtude, of agencies, aie 
clashing and combining, wdiat security have we that m our 
computation a pi ion we have taken all these into our reck¬ 
oning ? How many must we not generally be ignorant of? 
Among those which we know, how piobable that some have 
been overlooked, and, even were all included, how vam the 
pretence of summing up the effects of many causes, unless we 
know accurately the numerical law of each,—a condition m 
most cases not to be fulfilled, and even when fulfilled, to 
make the calculation transcends, m any but veiy simple cases, 
tbe utmost power of mathematical science with all its most 
modem improvements. 

These objections have real weight, and would be altogether 
unanswerable, if there were no test by which, when we employ 
the Deductive Method, we might judge whether an error 
of any of the above descriptions had been committed or not. 
Such a test however there is and its application forms, under 
the name of Verification, the third essential component pait of 
the Deductive Method, without which all the results it can 
give have little other value than that of conjecture To 



THE DEDUCTIVE METHOD. 


515 


warrant reliance on the general conclusions arrived at by 
deduction, these conclusions must he found, on careful com- 
paiison, to accoid with the results of dnect observation 
jvheiever it can he had. If, when we have experience to com- 
paie with them, this experience confirms them, we may safely 
trust -o them in ocher cases of which our specific experience 
is yet to come. But if our deductions have led to the conclu¬ 
sion that from a particular combination of causes a given effect 
would result, then lm all known cases where that combination 
can be shown to have existed, and wheie the effect has not 
followed, we must be able to show (or at least to make a pro¬ 
bable suimise) what frustrated it if we cannot, the theory is 
imperfect, and not yet to be relied upon. Nor is the verifi¬ 
cation complete, unless some of the cases m which the theory 
is borne out by the observed result, are of at least equal com¬ 
plexity with any other cases m which its application could be 
called for. 

If dnect observation and collation of instances have fur¬ 
nished us with any empirical laws of the effect (whether true 
m all observed cases, or only true for the most part), the most 
effectual verification of which the theory could be susceptible 
would be, that it led deductively to those empmcal laws, 
that the uniformities, wliethei complete or incomplete, which 
were observed to exist among the phenomena, were accounted 
for by the laws of the causes—were such as could not but exist 
if those be really the causes by which the phenomena are pro¬ 
duced Thus it was very reasonably deemed an essentia 
requisite of any tiue theory of the causes of the celestial 
motions, that it should lead by deduction to Keplers laws: 
which, accordingly, the Newtonian theory did. v 

In older, therefore, to facilitate the verification of theones 
obtained by deduction, it is important that as many as pos¬ 
sible of the empmcal laws of the phenomena should be as¬ 
certained, by a comparison of instances, conformably to the 
Method of Agreement, as well as (it must be added) that 
the phenomena themselves should be descnbed, m the most 
comprehensive as well as accurate manner possible, by col¬ 
lecting from the observation of parts, the simplest possible 

33—2 



516 


INDUCTION. 


correct expressions for the corresponding wholes as when 
the series of the observed places of a planet was first expressed 
by a circle, then by a system of epicycles, and subsequently by 
an ellipse. 

It is worth remarking, that complex instances which 
would have been of no use for the discovery of the simple 
laws into which we ultimately analyse their phenomena, 
nevertheless, when they have served to veufy the analysis, 
become additional evidence of the laws themselves Although 
we could not have got at the law from complex cases, still 
when the law, got at otherwise, is found to be m accordance 
with the result of a complex case, that case becomes a new 
experiment on the law, and helps to confirm what it did 
not assist to discover. It is a new trial of the principle in 
a different set of cncumstances, and occasionally serves to 
eliminate some circumstance not previously excluded, and the 
exclusion of which might requne an experiment impossible to 
be executed This was stnkmgly conspicuous m the example 
formerly quoted, m which the difference between the observed 
and the calculated velocity of sound was ascertained to result 
fiom the heat extricated by the condensation which takes 
place in each sonorous vibration. This was a trial, m new 
circumstances, of the law of the development of heat by com¬ 
pression , and it added materially to the proof of the univer¬ 
sality of that law. Accordingly any law of nature is deemed 
to have gained m point of certainty, by being found to explain 
some complex case which had not previously been thought of 
m connexion with it, and this indeed is a consideration to 
which it is the habit of scientific inquirers to attach rather too 
much value than too little. 

To the Deductive Method, thus characterized in its three 
constituent parts, Induction, Ratiocination, and Verifica¬ 
tion, the human mind is indebted for its most conspicuous 
triumphs m the investigation of nature. To it we owe all 
the theories by which vast and complicated phenomena are 
embraced under a few simple laws, which, considered as the 
laws of those great phenomena, could never have been detected 
by their direct study. We may form some conception of 



THE DEDUCTIVE .METHOD 


517 


what the method has done for us, from the case of the celestial 
motions, one of the simplest among the greater instances of 
the Composition of Causes, since (except m a few cases not 
of primary importance) each of the heavenly bodies may he 
considered, without material inaccuracy, to be never at one time 
influenced by the attraction of more than two bodies, the sun 
and one othei planet or satellite, making, with the reaction of 
the body itself, and the force generated by the body’s own 
motion and acting m the dnection of the tangent, only four 
different agents on the concurrence of which the motions of that 
body depend, a much smaller number, no doubt, than that by 
which any other of the great phenomena of nature is determined 
or modified. Yet how could we ever have ascertained the 
combination of forces on which the motions of the earth and 
planets are dependent, by merely comparing the orbits or velo¬ 
cities of different planets, or the different velocities or positions 
of the same planet ? Notwithstanding the legularity which 
manifests itself m those motions, m a degree so rare among 
the effects of a concuirence of causes, and although the 
periodical recurrence of exactly the same effect, affords positive 
proof that all the combinations of causes which occur at all, 
recur periodically, we should not have known what the 
causes were, if the existence of agencies precisely similar on 
oui own earth had not, fortunately, brought the causes them¬ 
selves within the reach of experimentation under simple 
circumstances. As we shall have occasion to analyse, further 
on, this great example of the Method of Deduction, we shall 
not occupy any time with it here, but shall proceed to that 
secondary application of the Deductive Method, the result of 
which is not to piove laws of phenomena, but to explain 
them. 



CHAPTER XII 


OF THE EXPLANATION OF LAWS OF NATURE. 

§ 1 The deductive operation by wbicb we derive the 
law of an effect fiom the laws of the causes, the concurrence 
of which gives rise to it, may be undertaken either foi the 
purpose of discovenng the law, or of explaining a law alieady 
discovered. The word explanation occurs so continually and 
holds so important a place m philosophy, that a little 
time spent in fixing the meaning of it will be piofitably 
employed. 

An individual fact is said to be explained, by pointing out 
its cause, that is, by stating the law or laws of causation, of 
which its production is an instance. Thus, a conflagration 
is explained, when it is proved to have ansen from a spark 
falling into the midst of a heap of combustibles. And m a 
similar manner, a law or umfoimity m nature is said to be 
explained, when another law or laws are pointed out, of 
which that law itself is but a case, and from which it could be 
deduced. 

§ 2 There are three distinguishable sets of circumstances 
in winch a law of causation may be explained from, or, as it 
also is often expressed, lesolved into, other laws. 

The first is the case already so fully considered >, an 
intermixture of laws, producing a joint effect equal to the 
sum of the effects of the causes taken separately. The law 
of the complex effect is explained, by being resolved into the 
separate laws of the causes which contribute to it. Thus, 
the law of the motion of a planet is resolved into the law of 
the acquired force, which tends to produce an uniform 
motion m the tangent, and the law of the centripetal force 



EXPLANATION OF LAWS 


519 


which tends to produce an accelerating motion towards the sun, 
the real motion being a compound of the two 

It is necessary here to remark, that m this lesolution of the 
law of a complex effect, the laws of which it is compounded 
aie not the only elements It is resolved into the laws of the 
sepaiate causes, together with the fact of their coexistence 
The one is as essential an ingredient as the other; whether the 
object be to discover the law of the effect, 01 only to explain 
it To deduce the laws of the heavenly motions, we require 
not only to know the law of a lectihneal and that of a giavita- 
tive force, but the existence of both these foices m the celestial 
regions, and even then relative amount The complex laws of 
causation aie thus lesoived into two distinct kinds of elements 
the one, simpler laws of causation, the othei (m the aptly 
selected expiession of Dr Chalmers) collocations, the collo¬ 
cations consisting m the existence of certain agents or powers, 
m certain circumstances of place and time We shall hereafter 
have occasion to leturn to this distinction, and to dwell on it 
at such length as dispenses with the necessity of further insist¬ 
ing on it here. The first mode, then, of the explanation of 
Laws of Causation, is when the law of an effect is resolved into 
the various tendencies of which it is the result, together with 
the laws of those tendencies. 

§ 8 A second case is when, between what seemed the 
cause and what was supposed to be its effect, further observa¬ 
tion detects an intermediate link, a fact caused by the ante¬ 
cedent, and m its turn causing the consequent; so that the 
cause at first assigned is but the remote cause, operating 
thiough the intermediate phenomenon A seemed the cause 
of C, but it subsequently appeared that A was only the cause 
of B, and that it is B which was the cause of C. Lor example. 
mankind were aware that the act of touching an outward object 
caused a sensation. It was subsequently discoveied, that after 
we have touched the object, and before we experience the 
sensation, some change takes place m a kind of thread called 
a nerve, which extends from our outward organs to the bram. 
Touching the object, therefore, is only the remote cause of our 



520 


INDUCTION. 


sensation; that is, not the cause, pioperly speaking, hut the 
cause of the cause,—the leal cause of the sensation is the 
change m the state of the nerve. Future expenence may not 
only give us more knowledge than we now have of the parti¬ 
cular nature of this change, but may also mteipolate another 
link between the contact (for example) of the object with our 
outward organs. and the production of the change of state m 
the nerve, theie may take place some electric phenomenon ; 
or some phenomenon of a nature not lesemblmg the effects of 
any known agency. Hitherto, however, no such mteimediate 
link has been discovered, and the touch of the object must 
be consideied, piovisionally, as the proximate cause of the 
affection of the nerve The sequence, therefore, of a sensation 
of touch on contact with an object, is ascertained not to be 
an ultimate law, it is resolved, as the phrase is, into two other 
laws,—the law, that contact with an object produces an affec¬ 
tion of the nerve, and the law, that an affection of the nerve 
pioduces sensation. 

To take another example the more powerful acids corrode 
or blacken organic compounds This is a case of causation, 
but of remote causation; and is said to be explained when it 
is shown that theie is an intermediate link, namely, the separa¬ 
tion of some of the chemical elements of the organic structure 
from the rest, and their entering into combination with the 
acid The acid causes this separation of the elements, and the 
sepai ation of the elements causes the disorganization, and often 
the charring of the structuie. So, again, chlorine extracts 
colouring matters, (whence its efficacy m bleaching,) and 
purifies the air fiom infection. This law is resolved into the 
two following laws Chlorine has a powerful affinity for bases 
of all kinds, particularly metallic bases and hydrogen Such 
bases are essential elements of colouring matters and conta¬ 
gious compounds which substances, therefore, aie decomposed 
and destroyed by chlorine. 

§ 4 It is of importance to remark, that when a sequence 
of phenomena is thus resolved into other laws, they are always 
laws more general than itself. The law that A is followed by 



EXPLANATION OF LAWS. 


521 


C, is less geneial than either of the laws which connect B 
with C and A with B. This will appear from very simple 
considerations. 

All laws of causation are liable to be counteracted or frus¬ 
trated, by the non-fulfilment of some negative condition the 
tendency, therefore, of B to produce C may be defeated. Now 
the law that A pioduces B, is equally fulfilled whether B is 
followed by C or not, but the law that A produces C by 
means of B, is of course only fulfilled when B is really followed 
by 0, and is theiefore less general than the law that A pro¬ 
duces B. It is also less general than the law that B produces 
C. Bor B may have other causes besides A; and as A pro¬ 
duces 0 only by means of B, while B produces C whether it 
has itself been produced by A or by anything else, the second 
law embraces a greater number of instances,, coveis as it were 
a greater space of ground, than the fiist. 

Thus, m our former example, the law that the contact of 
an object causes a change m the state of the nerve, is more 
general than the law that contact with an object causes sensa¬ 
tion, since, for aught we know, the change m the nerve may 
equally take place when, from a counteracting cause, as for 
instance, strong mental excitement, the sensation does not 
follow, as m a battle, where wounds aie sometimes received 
without any consciousness of receiving them. And again, the 
law that change m the state of a nerve produces sensation, is 
more general than the law that contact with an object pro¬ 
duces sensation , since the sensation equally follows the change 
in the nerve when not produced by contact with an object, 
but by some other cause, as m the well-known case, when a 
person who has lost a limb, feels the same sensation which he 
has been accustomed to call a pain m the limb. 

Not only are the laws of more immediate sequence into 
which the law of a remote sequence is resolved, laws of greater 
generality than that law is, but (as a consequence of, or rather 
as implied m, their greater generality) they are more to be 
relied on; there are fewer chances of their being ultimately 
found not to be universally tiue. Brom the moment when 
the sequence of A and C is shown not to be immediate, but to 



INDUCTION. 


522 


depend on an intervening phenomenon, then, however con¬ 
stant and invariable the sequence of A and C has lntheito 
been found, possibilities anse of its failuie, exceeding those 
which can affect eithei of the moie immediate sequences, A, B, 
and B, C. The tendency of A to produce C may be defeated 
by whatever is capable of defeating either the tendency of A 
to produce B, 01 the tendency of B to pioduce C, it is tlieie- 
foie twice as liable to failure as either of those moie elementaly 
tendencies, and the geneialization that A is always followed 
by C, is twice as likely to be found enoneous. And so of the 
conveise geneialization, that C is always preceded and caused 
by A, which will be eironeous not only if tbeie should happen 
to be a second immediate mode of pioduction of C itself, but 
moreovei if theie be a second mode of pioduction of B, the 
immediate antecedent of 0 m the sequence. 

The resolution of the one geneialization into the other 
two, not only shows that theie aie possible limitations of the 
foimer, fiom which its two elements aie exempt, hut shows 
also wheie these are to be looked for. As soon as we know 
that B intervenes between A and C, we also know that if there 
be cases m which the sequence of A and C does not hold, 
these aie most likely to be found by studying the effects 01 
the conditions of the phenomenon B. 

It appears, then, that m the second of the three modes m 
which a law may be resolved into other laws, the latter aie 
more geneial, that is, extend to more cases, and are also less 
likely to require limitation fiom subsequent experience, than 
the law which they serve to explain. They aie moie neaily 
unconditional, they are defeated by fewer contingencies, 
they are a nearer approach to the universal truth of nature. 
The same observations are still more evidently true with regald 
to the first of the three modes of resolution When the law 
of an effect of combined causes is resolved into the separate 
laws of the causes, the nature of the case implies that the law 
of the effect is less general than the law of any of the causes, 
since it only holds when they ai e combined , while the law of 
any one of the causes holds good both then, and also when 
that cause acts apart fiom the rest. It is also manifest that 



EXPLANATION OF LAWS. 


523 


the complex law is liable to be oftener unfulfilled than any one 
of the simplei laws of which it is the result, since every con¬ 
tingency which defeats any of the laws prevents so much of 
the effect as depends on it, and thereby defeats the complex 
law. The mere lusting, for example, of some small part of a 
great machine, often suffices entirely to prevent the effect 
which ought to result from the joint action of all the parts 
The law of the effect of a combination of causes is always sub¬ 
ject to the whole of the negative conditions which attach to 
the action of all the causes seveially. 

There is anothei and an equally strong reason why the law 
of a complex effect must be less general than the laws of the 
causes which conspire to pioduce it The same causes, acting 
according to the same laws, and differing only m the propor¬ 
tions m which they are combined, often pioduce effects which 
differ not merely m quantity, but m kind The combination 
of a centripetal with a piojectile force, tn the pioportions 
which obtain m all the planets and satellites of oui solar 
system, gives rise to an elliptical motion, but if the ratio of 
the two forces to each other were slightly altered, it is demon¬ 
strated that the motion pioduced would be m a circle, or a 
paiabola, or an hyperbola. and it is thought that m the case 
of some comets one of these is probably the fact Yet the 
law of the parabolic motion would be resolvable into the very 
same simple laws into which that of the elliptical motion 
is resolved, namely, the law of the permanence of rectilineal 
motion, and the law of gravitation. If, therefore, in the 
course of ages, some circumstance were to manifest itself 
which, without defeating the law of either of those forces, 
should merely alter their proportion to one another, (such as 
the shock of some solid body, or even the accumulating effect 
of the resistance of the medium in which astionomers have 
been led to suimise that the motions of the heavenly bodies 
take place,) the elliptical motion might be changed into a 
motion m some other conic section , and the complex law, that 
the planetary motions take place m ellipses, would be deprived 
of its universality, though the discoveiy -would not at all de¬ 
tract from the universality of the simpler laws into which that 



524 


INDUCTION. 


complex law is resolved. The law, m short, of each of the 
concunent causes remains the same, howevei then colloca¬ 
tions may vaiy, but the law of their joint effect vanes with 
eveiy chffeience m the collocations There needs no more 
to show how much moie general the elementary laws must 
he, than any of the complex laws which aie derived fiom 
them. 


§ 5. Besides the two modes which have been tieated of, 
theie is a third mode m which laws are lesolved into one 
another, and m this it is self-evident that they aie lesolved 
into laws moie general than themselves. This third mode is 
the subsumption (as it has been called) of one law under 
anothei or (what comes to the same thing) the gathering up 
of seveial laws into one more geneial law which includes 
them all The most splendid example of this opeiation was 
when tenestnal gravity and the central force of the solar 
system weie biought together under the geneial law of gravi¬ 
tation It had been pioved antecedently that the eaith and 
the other planets tend to the sun, and it had been known 
from the earliest times that teirestnal bodies tend towaids the 
earth. These were similar phenomena, and to enable them 
both to be subsumed under one law, it was only necessary to 
prove that, as the effects were similar m quality, so also they, 
as to quantity, conform to the same rules. This was first 
shown to he tiue of the moon, which agieed with terrestrial 
objects not only m tending to a centre, but m the fact that 
this centre was the earth. The tendency of the moon towaids 
the earth being ascertained to vary as the inverse square of 
the distance, it was deduced from this, by direct calculation, 
that if the moon were as near to the eaith as terrestrial objects 
aie, and the acquned force m the direction of the tangent were 
suspended, the moon would fall towards the earth through ex¬ 
actly as many feet in a second as those objects do by virtue of 
their weight. Hence the inference was irresistible, that the 
moon also tends to the earth by virtue of its weight. and that 
the two phenomena, the tendency of the moon to the earth 
and the tendency of terrestrial objects to the earth, being not 



EXPLANATION OF LAWS. 


525 


only similar m quality, but, when m the same circumstances, 
identical m quantity, are cases of one and the same law of 
causation But the tendency of the moon to the earth, and 
the tendency of the earth and planets to the sun, weie already 
known to he cases of the same law of causation: and thus the 
law of all these tendencies, and the law of terrestrial gravity, 
were recognised as identical, and were subsumed under one 
general law, that of gravitation. 

In a similar manner, the laws of magnetic phenomena have 
moie recently been subsumed under known laws of electricity. 
It is thus that the most general laws of natuie are usually 
aruved at we mount to them by successive steps. For, to 
arrive by correct induction at laws which hold under such an 
immense vanety of circumstances, laws so general as to be 
independent of any varieties of space or time which we are 
able to observe, requires for the most part many distinct sets of 
experiments or observations, conducted at different times and 
by different people One pait of the law is first ascertained, 
afterwards another part one set of observations teaches us 
that the law holds good under some conditions, another 
that it holds good under other conditions, by combining which 
observations we find that it holds good under conditions much 
more general, or even universally. The general law, m this 
case, is literally the sum of all the partial ones, it is* the 
recognition of the same sequence m different sets of instances; 
and may, m fact, be regarded as merely one step m the pro¬ 
cess of elimination. That tendency of bodies towards one 
another, which we now call gravity, had at first been observed 
only on the earth’s surface, where it manifested itself only as a 
tendency of all bodies towards the earth, and might, therefore, 
be ascribed to a peculiar property of the earth itself. one of 
the circumstances, namely, the proximity of the earth, had 
not been eliminated. To eliminate this circumstance required 
a fresh set of instances m other parts of the universe: these 
we could not ourselves create; and though nature had created 
them for us, we were placed m very unfavourable circum¬ 
stances for observing them. To make these observations, fell 
naturally to the lot of a different set of persons from those 



526 


INDUCTION. 


who studied teirestnal phenomena, and had, indeed, been a 
raattei of gieat interest at a time when the idea of explaining 
celestial facts by tenestrial laws was looked upon as the con¬ 
founding of an indefeasible distinction When, howevei, the 
celestial motions weie accuiately ascertained, and the deduc¬ 
tive processes performed, from which it appeared that their 
laws and those of tenestnal gravity corresponded, those celes¬ 
tial observations became a set of instances which exactly 
eliminated the cncumstance of proximity to the eaith, and 
proved that m the original case, that of terrestrial objects, it 
was not the earth, as such, that caused the motion or the 
pressure, but the circumstance common to that case with the 
celestial instances, namely, the presence of some great body 
within certain limits of distance. 

§ 6 There are, then, three modes of explaining laws of 
causation, or, which is the same thing, resolving them into 
other laws First, when the law of an effect of combined 
causes is resolved into the separate laws of the causes, together 
with the fact of their combination. Secondly, when the law 
which connects any two links, not proximate, m a chain of 
causation, is resolved into the laws which connect each with 
the intermediate links Both of these are cases of resolving 
one law into two or more; m the third, two or more are 
resolved into one when, after the law has been shown to hold 
good m several different classes of cases, we decide that what 
is true m each of these classes of cases, is true under some 
more general supposition, consisting of what all those classes 
of cases have m common. "We may here remark that this last 
operation involves none of the uncertainties attendant on 
induction by the Method of Agreement, since we need not 
suppose the result to be extended by way of inference to any 
new class of cases, different from those by the comparison of 
which it was engendered 

In all these three processes, laws are, as we have seen, 
resolved into laws more geneial than themselves, laws ex¬ 
tending to all the cases which the former extended to, and 
others besides. In the first two modes they are also resolved 



EXPLANATION OF LAWS 


527 


into laws more ceitam, in other words, moie nniveisally tine 
than themselves , they are, m fact, proved not to be themselves 
laws of natme, the chaiacter of which is to he umvei sally true, 
hut results of laws of natme, which may he only tiue condi¬ 
tionally, and for the most pait No difference of this soit exists 
m the thud case, since here the partial laws aie, m fact, the 
-very same law as the general one, and any exception to them 
would he an exception to it too 

By all the three piocesses, the range of deductive science is 
extended, since the laws, thus lesolved, may he thenceforth 
deduced demonstratively from the laws into which they aie 
lesolved As already remarked, the same deductive process 
which proves a law or fact of causation if unknown, serves to 
explain it when known 

The word explanation is heie used m its philosophical sense. 
What is called explaining one law of nature hy another, is 
hut substituting one mysteiy for another, and does nothing 
to lender the geneial course of nature other than mysteiious: 
we can no more assign a why for the more extensive laws 
than for the partial ones The explanation may substitute a 
mysteiy which has become familiar, and has grown to seem 
not mysteiious, for one which is still strange. And this is the 
meaning of explanation, m common pailance But the process 
with which we are heie concerned often does the very contraiy . 
it lesolves a phenomenon with which we aie familial, into one 
of which we pieviously knew little or nothing, as when the 
common fact of the fall of heavy bodies was resolved into the 
tendency of all particles of matter towaids one anothei. It 
must he kept constantly m view, theiefore, that m science, 
those who speak of explaining any phenomenon mean (or 
should mean) pointing out not some more familiar, but merely 
some moie geneial, phenomenon, of which it is a partial exem¬ 
plification , or some kvws of causation which pioduce it hy their 
joint or successive action, and from which, theiefore, its con¬ 
ditions may he determined deductively. Eveiy such operation 
brings us a step nearer towards answenng the question which 
was stated m a pievious chapter as comprehending the whole 
problem of the investigation of nature, viz. What are the fewest 



528 


INDUCTION. 


assumptions, which being gianted, the older of nature as it 
exists would be the result 9 What are the fewest geneial pro¬ 
positions from which all the uniformities existing m nature 
could be deduced 9 

The laws, thus explained or resolved, are sometimes said 
to be accounted for ; but the expression is incorrect, if taken 
to mean anything more than what has been alieady stated In 
mmds not habituated to accurate thinking, there is often a 
confused notion that the general laws ai e the causes of the 
partial ones, that the law of general gravitation, for example, 
causes the phenomenon of the fall of bodies to the earth. But 
to assert this, would be a misuse of the word cause terrestrial 
giavity is not an effect of general gravitation, but a case of it, 
that is, one kind of the particular instances m which that 
general law obtains. To account for a law of nature means, 
and can mean, nothing more than to assign other laws more 
general, together with collocations, which laws and collocations 
being supposed, the partial law follows without any additional 
supposition. 



CHAPTER XIII 


MISCELLANEOUS EXAMPLES OF THE EXPLANATION OF 
LAWS OF NATURE. 

§ 1. The most striking example which the history of 
science presents, of the explanation of laws of causation and 
other uniformities of sequence among special phenomena, by 
resolving them into laws of greater simplicity and generality, 
is the great Newtonian generalization: respecting which 
typical instance so much having already been said, it is 
sufficient to call attention to the great number and variety of 
the special observed uniformities which are m this case 
accounted for, either as particular cases or as consequences of 
one very simple law of universal nature. The simple fact of 
a tendency of every particle of matter towards every other 
particle, varying inversely as the square of the distance, 
explains the fall of bodies to the earth, the revolutions of the 
planets and satellites, the motions (so far as known) of comets, 
and all the various regularities which have been observed m 
these special phenomena; such as the elliptical orbits, and 
the variations from exact ellipses; the relation between the 
solar distances of the planets and the duration of their 
revolutions; the precession of the equinoxes ; the tides, and a 
vast number of minor astronomical truths. 

Mention has also been made m the preceding chapter of 
the explanation of the phenomena of magnetism from laws of 
electricity, the special laws of magnetic agency having been 
affiliated by deduction to observed laws of electric action, in 
which they have ever since been considered to be included as 
special cases. An example not so complete in itself, but even 
more fertile m consequences, having been the starting point 
of the really scientific study of physiology, is the affiliation, 
vox. i. 34 



530 


INDUCTION. 


commenced by Bichat, and earned on by subsequent biologists, 
of the properties of the bodily organs, to the elementary 
properties of the tissues into which they are anatomically 
decomposed. 

Another striking instance is afforded by Dalton's gene¬ 
ralization, commonly known as the atomic theory. It had 
been known from the very commencement of accurate chemical 
observation, that any two bodies combine chemically with 
one another m only a certain number of proportions, but 
those proportions were m each case expressed by a percentage 
—so many parts (by weight) of each ingredient, m 100 of the 
compound, (say 35 and a fraction of one element, 64 and a 
fraction of the other): in which mode of statement no relation 
was perceived between the proportion in which a given element 
combines with one substance, and that m which it combines 
with others. The gieat step made by Dalton consisted m per¬ 
ceiving, that a unit of weight might be established for each 
substance, such that by supposing the substance to enter into 
all its combinations in the ratio either of that unit, or of some 
low multiple of that unit, all the different proportions, previously 
expressed by percentages, were found to result. Thus 1 being 
assumed as the unit of hydrogen, if 8 were then taken as that 
of oxygen, the combination of one unit of hydrogen with one 
unit of oxygen would produce the exact proportion of weight 
between the two substances which is known to exist m water; 
the combination of one unit of hydrogen with two units of 
oxygen would produce the proportion which exists in the other 
compound of the same two elements, called peroxide of 
hydrogen; and the combinations of hydrogen and of oxygen 
with all other substances, would correspond with the suppo¬ 
sition that those elements enter into combination by single 
units, or twos, or threes, of the numbers assigned to them, 
1 and 8, and the other substances by ones or twos or threes 
of other determinate numbers proper to each. The result is 
that a table of the equivalent numbeis, or, as they are called, 
atomic weights, of all the elementary substances, comprises in 
itself, and scientifically explains, all the proportions m which 
any substance, elementary or compound, is found capable of 



EXAMPLES OF THE EXPLANATION OF LAWS. 531 

entering into chemical combination with any other substance 
whatever. 

§ 2 Some interesting cases of the explanation of old uni¬ 
formities by newly ascertained laws are afforded by the re¬ 
searches of Piofessor Graham That eminent chemist was 
the first who drew attention to the distinction which may be 
made of all substances into two classes, termed by him crystal¬ 
loids and colloids; or rather, of all states of matter into the 
crystalloid and the colloidal states, for many substances are 
capable of existing in either. When in the colloidal state, 
their sensible properties are very different from those of the 
same substance when crystallized, or when m a state easily 
susceptible of crystallization. Colloid substances pass with 
extreme difficulty and slowness into the crystalhne state, and 
are extremely inert m all the ordinary chemical relations Sub¬ 
stances m the colloid state are almost always, when combined 
with water, more or less viscous or gelatinous. The most 
prominent examples of the state are certain animal and vege¬ 
table substances, particularly gelatine, albumen, starch, the 
gums, caramel, tannin, and some others. Among substances 
not of organic origin, the most notable instances are hydrated 
silicic acid, and hydrated alumina, with other metallic per¬ 
oxides of the aluminous class. 

Now it is found, that while colloidal substances are easily 
penetrated by water, and by the solutions of crystalloid sub¬ 
stances, they are very little penetrable by one another: which 
enabled Professor Graham to introduce a highly effective 
process (termed dialysis) for separating the crystalloid sub¬ 
stances contained m any liquid mixture, by passing them 
through a thin septum of colloidal matter, which does not 
suffer anything colloidal to pass, or suffers it only in very 
minute quantity. This property of colloids enabled Mr. 
Graham to account for a number of special results of obser¬ 
vation, not previously explained. 

Tor instance, “ while soluble crystalloids are always highly 
sapid, soluble colloids are singularly insipid,” as might be ex¬ 
pected ; for, as the sentient extremities of the nerves of the 

34—2 



532 


INDUCTION. 


palate (C are probably protected by a colloidal membrane/' im¬ 
permeable to othei colloids, a colloid, when tasted, piobably 
never readies those nerves. Again, c£ it has been observed that 
vegetable £C gum is not digested m the stomach , the coats of 
that organ dialyse the soluble food, absorbing crystalloids, 
and 1 ejecting all colloids." One of the mysterious piocesses 
accompanying digestion, the secretion of free munatic acid by 
the coats of the stomach, obtains a probable hypothetical ex¬ 
planation through the same law Finally, much light is thrown 
upon the observed phenomena of osmose (the passage of fluids 
outwaid and mwaid through animal membianes) by the fact 
that the membranes, are colloidal In consequence, the water 
and saline solutions contained m the animal body pass easily 
and rapidly through the membranes, while the substances 
directly applicable to nutrition, which are mostly colloidal, are 
detained by them + 

The piopertv which salt possesses of preseivmg animal 
substances from putrefaction is resolved by Liebig into two 
more general laws, the strong attiaction of salt for water, 
and the necessity of the presence of water as a condition of 
putrefaction. The intermediate phenomenon which is interpo¬ 
lated between the remote cause and the effect, can here be not 
merely inferred but seen, for it is a familiar fact, that flesh 
upon which salt has been thrown is speedily found swimming 
in brine 

The second of the two factors (as they may be termed) 
into which the preceding law has been resolved, the necessity 
of water to putrefaction, itself affords an additional example 
of the Resolution of Laws. The law itself is proved by the 
Method of Difference, since flesh completely dried and kept 
in a dry atmosphere does not putrefy, as we see m the case of 
dried provisions, and human bodies m very dry climates. A 
deductive explanation of this same law results from Liebig's 
speculations. The putrefaction of animal and other azotised 

* Vide Memoir by Thomas Graham, P.RS, Master of the Mint, “On 
Liquid Diffusion Applied to Analysis,” in the Philosophical Transactions for 
3862, reprinted m the Journal of the Chemical Society , and also separately as a 
pamphlet. 



EXAMPLES OF THE EXPLANATION OF LAWS. 533 

bodies is a chemical process, by which they are gradually dis¬ 
sipated m a gaseous foim, chiefly in that of carbonic acid and 
ammonia , now to convert the carbon of the animal substance 
into caibonic acid requues oxygen, and to conveit the azote 
into ammonia requires hydrogen, which are the elements of 
water The extreme rapidity of the putiefaction of azotised 
substances, compared with the gradual decay of non-azotised 
bodies (such as wood and the like) by the action of oxygen 
alone, he explains from the general law that substances are 
much moie easily decomposed by the action of two different 
affinities upon two of their elements, than by the action of 
only one 

§ 3 . Among the many impoitant propeities of the nervous 
system, which have either been fust discovered or stiikmgly 
illustrated by Di. Biown-Sequard, I select the reflex influ¬ 
ence of the nervous system on nutrition and secretion. By 
reflex nervous action is meant, action which one part of the 
nervous system exerts over another part, without any inter¬ 
mediate action on the biam, and consequently without 
consciousness, or which, if it does pass through the brain, 
at least produces its effects independently of the will There 
are many experiments which prove that irritation of a nerve in 
one pait of the body may m this manner excite powerful 
action m another pait, for example, food injected into the 
stomach through a divided oesophagus, nevertheless produces 
secretion of saliva, warm water injected into the bowels, and 
various other irritations of the lower intestines, have been found 
to excite secretion of the gastric juice, and so foith. The reality 
of the power being thus pioved, its agency explains a great 
variety of apparently anomalous phenomena , of which I select 
the following from Dr. Brown-Sequard’s Lectures on the 
Nervous System. 

The production of tears by irritation of the eye, or of the 
mucous membrane of the nose : 

The secretions of the eye and nose increased by exposure 
of other parts of the body to cold: 

Inflammation of the eye, especially when of traumatic 



534 


INDUCTION. 


origin, very frequently excites a similar affection m the other 
eye, which may he cured hy section of the intervening neive : 

Loss of sight sometimes produced hy neuralgia, and has 
been known to he at once cured hy the extirpation (for in¬ 
stance) of a carious tooth : 

Even cataract has been produced in a healthy eye hy 
cataract m the other eye, or hy neuralgia, or hy a wound of 
the frontal neive: 

The well-known phenomenon of a sudden stoppage of the 
hearts action, and consequent death, produced by irritation 
of some of the nervous extremities: e g ., hy drinking very 
cold water, or by a blow on the abdomen, or other sudden 
excitation of the abdominal sympathetic nerve, though this 
nerve may he irritated to any extent without stopping the 
heart’s action, if a section he made of the communicating 
nerves • 

The extraordinary effects produced on the internal organs 
by an extensrve burn on the surface of the body, consistrng 
in violent inflammation of the tissues of the abdomen, chest, 
or head : which, when death ensues from this kind of injury, 
is one of the most frequent causes of it: 

Paralysis and anaesthesia of one part of the body from 
neuralgia m another part; and muscular atrophy from neu¬ 
ralgia, even when there is no paralysis. 

Tetanus produced by the lesion of a nerve; Dr. Bitiwn- 
Sequard thinks it highly probable that hydrophobia is a phe¬ 
nomenon of a similar nature: 

Morbid changes m the nutrition of the brain and spinal 
cord, manifesting themselves by epilepsy, choiea, hysteria, and 
other diseases, occasioned by lesion of some of the nervous 
extremities m remote places, as by worms, calculi, tumours, 
carious bones, and in some cases even by very slight irrita¬ 
tions of the skin 

§ 4 . Eiom the foregoing and similar instances, we may 
see the impoitance, when a law of nature previously unknown 
has been brought to light, or when new light has been thrown 
upon a known law by experiment, of examining all cases 



EXAMPLES OF THE EXPLANATION OF LAWS. 535 

which present the conditions necessary for bringing that law 
into action; a process fertile m demonstrations of special laws 
previously unsuspected, and explanations of otheis already 
empirically known. 

For instance, Faraday discovered by experiment, that 
voltaic electricity could be evolved from a natural magnet, 
provided a conducting body were set in motion at right angles 
to the direction of the magnet. and this he found to hold 
not only of small magnets, but of that gieat magnet, the earth. 
The law being thus established experimentally, that electricity 
is evolved, by a magnet, and a conductor moving at right 
angles to the direction of its poles, we may now look out for 
fresh instances in which these conditions meet. Wherever a 
conductor moves or revolves at right angles to the direction 
of the earth’s magnetic poles, there we may expect an evolu¬ 
tion of electricity In the northern regions, where the polar 
direction is nearly perpendicular to the horizon, all honzontal 
motions of conductors will produce electricity; horizontal 
wheels, for example, made of metal, likewise all running 
streams will evolve a current of electricity, which will circulate 
round them; and the air thus charged with electricity may be 
one of the causes of the Aurora Borealis In the equatorial 
regions, on the contrary, upright wheels placed parallel to the 
equator will originate a voltaic circuit, and waterfalls will 
natuially become electric 

For a second example, it has been proved, chiefly by 
the researches of Professor Graham, that gases have a 
strong tendency to permeate animal membranes, and diffuse 
themselves through the spaces which such membranes in¬ 
close, notwithstanding the presence of other gases m those 
spaces. Proceeding from this general law, and reviewing a 
variety of cases m which gases lie contiguous to membranes, 
we are enabled to demonstrate or to explain the following 
more special laws: 1st. The human or animal body, when 
surrounded with any gas not already contained within the 
body, absorbs it rapidly; such, for instance, as the gases of 
putrefying matters which helps to explain malaria. 2nd. The 
carbonic acid gas of effervescing drinks, evolved in the stomach. 



536 


INDUCTION. 


permeates its membranes, and rapidly spreads through the 
system. 3rd. Alcohol taken into the stomach passes into vapour 
and spreads through the system with gieat rapidity; (which, 
combined with the high combustibility of alcohol, or m other 
words its ready combination with oxygen, may perhaps help 
to explain the bodily warmth immediately consequent on 
drinking spmtuous liquors ) 4th. In any state of the body in 
which peculiar gases are formed within it, these will rapidly 
exhale through all parts of the body, and hence the rapidity 
with which, m certain states of disease, the surrounding atmo¬ 
sphere becomes tainted. 5th. The putrefaction of the interior 
parts of a carcase will proceed as rapidly as that of the 
extenor, from the ready passage outwards of the gaseous pro¬ 
ducts 6th The exchange of oxygen and carbonic acid m the 
lungs is not prevented, but rather promoted, by the inter¬ 
vention of the membrane of the lungs and the coats of the 
blood-vessels between the blood and the air It is necessary, 
however, that there should be a substance m the blood with 
which the oxygen of the air may immediately combine, 
otherwise instead of passing into the blood, it would permeate 
the whole organism: and it is necessary that the carbonic 
acid, as it is formed m the capillaries, should also find a sub¬ 
stance m the blood with which it can combine, otherwise it 
would leave the body at all points, instead of being discharged 
through the lungs. 

§ 5. The following is a deduction which confirms, by 
explaining, the old but not undisputed empirical generaliza¬ 
tion, that soda powders weaken the human system. These 
powders, consisting of a mixture of tartaric acid with bicar¬ 
bonate of soda, from which the carbonic acid is set free, must 
pass into the stomach as tartrate of soda. Now, neutral tar¬ 
trates, citrates, and acetates of the alkalis are found, m their 
passage through the system, to be changed into carbonates, 
and to convert a tartrate into a carbonate requires an addi¬ 
tional quantity of oxygen, the abstraction of which must lessen 
the oxygen destined for assimilation with the blood, on the 



EXAMPLES OF THE EXPLANATION OF LAWS. 537 


quantity of which the vigorous action of the human system 
partly depends 

The instances of new theories agreeing with and explaining 
old empiricisms, aie mnumeiable. All the just remarks made 
by experienced persons on human character and conduct, are 
so many special laws, which the general laws of the human 
mind explain and resolve. The empirical generalizations on 
which the operations of the arts have usually been founded, 
are continually justified and confiimed on the one hand, oi 
corrected and improved on the other, by the discovery of the 
simpler scientific laws on which the efficacy of those operations 
depends The effects of the rotation of crops, of the various 
manuies, and other processes of improved agriculture, have 
been for the fiist time resolved m our own day into known laws 
of chemical and organic action, by Davy, Liebig, and others. 
The processes of the medical art are even now mostly empirical: 
then efficacy is concluded, m each instance, from a special and 
most precarious experimental generalization hut as science 
advances in discovering the simple laws of chemistry and phy¬ 
siology, progress is made m ascertaining the intermediate links 
m the senes of phenomena, and the more general laws on 
which they depend, and thus, while the old piocesses are 
either exploded, or their efficacy, m so far as real, explained, 
better processes, founded on the knowledge of proximate 
causes, are continually suggested and brought into use.* 
Many even of the truths of geometry were generalizations 
from experience before they were deduced from first prin- 


* It was an old generalization m surgery, that tight bandaging had a ten¬ 
dency to prevent or dissipate local inflammation This sequence, bemg, in the 
progress of physiological knowledge, resolved into moie general laws, led to 
the important surgical invention made by Dr Arnott, the treatment of local 
inflammation and tumours by means of an equable pressure, produced by a 
bladdei partially filled with an The pressure, by keeping back the blood from 
the part, prevents the inflammation, or the tumour, from being nounshed m 
the case of inflammation, it removes the stimulus, which the organ is unfit to 
receive, in the case of tumours, by keepmg back the nutritive fluid, it causes 
the absorption of matter to exceed the supply, and the diseased mass is 
gradually absorbed and disappears. 




538 


INDUCTION. 


ciples. The quadrature of the cycloid is said to have been 
first effected by measurement, or rather by weighing a 
cycloidal card, and comparing its weight with that of a piece 
of similar card of known dimensions. 

§ 6. To the foregoing examples from physical science, 
let us add another from mental. The following is one of the 
simple laws of mind: Ideas of a pleasurable or painful cha¬ 
racter form associations more easily and strongly than other 
ideas, that is, they become associated after fewer repetitions, 
and the association is moie durable. This is an experimental 
law, grounded on the Method of Difference. By deduction 
from this law, many of the more special laws which expe¬ 
rience shows to exist among particular mental phenomena 
may be demonstrated and explained.—the ease and rapidity, 
for instance, with which thoughts connected with our passions 
or our more cherished interests are excited, and the fiim hold 
which the facts relating to them have on our memoiy, the 
vivid recollection we retain of minute circumstances which 
accompamed any object or event that deeply interested us, 
and of the times and places m which we have been very happy 
or very miserable, the horror with which we view the acci¬ 
dental instrument of any occunence which shocked us, 01 the 
locality where it took place, and the pleasure we derive from 
any memorial of past enjoyment, all these effects being pro¬ 
portional to the sensibility of the individual mind, and to the 
consequent intensity of the pam or pleasure from which the 
association originated. It has been suggested by the able 
writer of a biographical sketch of Dr. Priestley m a monthly 
periodical,* that the same elementary law of our mental con¬ 
stitution, smtably followed out, would explain a variety of 
mental phenomena previously inexplicable, and m particular 
some of the fundamental diversities of human character and 
genius. Associations being of two sorts, either between 
synchronous, or between successive impressions; and the 
influence of the law which lenders associations stronger m 


Since acknowledged and reprinted in Mr. Martmeau’s Miscellanies . 



EXAMPLES OF THE EXPLANATION OF LAWS. 539 

proportion to the pleasurable or painful character of the impres¬ 
sions, being felt with peculiar force m the synchronous class 
of associations, it is remarked by the writer referred to, that 
in minds of strong organic sensibility synchronous associations 
will be hkely to predominate, producing a tendency to conceive 
things m pictures and in the concrete, nchly clothed in attn- t 
butes and circumstances, a mental habit which is commonly 
called Imagination, and is one of the peculiarities of the painter 
and the poet, while persons of more moderate susceptibility to 
pleasure and pain will have a tendency to associate facts chiefly 
in the order of their succession, and such persons, if they pos¬ 
sess mental superiority, will addict themselves to history or 
science rather than to creative art. This interesting specula¬ 
tion the author of the present work has endeavoured, pn an¬ 
other occasion, to pursue farther, and to examine how far it 
will avail towards explaining the peculiarities of the poetical 
temperament* It is at least an example which may serve, 
instead of many others, to show the extensive scope which 
exists for deductive investigation m the important and hitherto 
so imperfect Science of Mind. 

§ 7. The copiousness with which the discovery and ex¬ 
planation of special laws of phenomena by deduction from 
simpler and more general ones has here been exemplified, was 
prompted by a desire to characterize clearly, and place in its 
due position of importance, the Deductive'Method; which, in 
the present state of knowledge, is destined henceforth irrevo¬ 
cably to predominate m the course of scientific investigation. 
A revolution is peaceably and progressively effecting itself in 
philosophy, the reverse of that to which Bacon has attached 
his name. That great man changed the method of the sciences 
from deductive to experimental, and it is now rapidly reverting 
from experimental to deductive. But the deductions which 
Bacon abolished were from premises hastily snatched up, or 
arbitrarily assumed The principles were neither established 
by legitimate canons of experimental inquiry, nor the results 


Dissertations and Discussions, vol. 1., fourth paper. 




540 


INDUCTION. 


tested by that indispensable element of a rational Deductive 
Method, verification by specific experience. Between the pri¬ 
mitive method of Deduction and that which I have attempted 
to characterize, there is all the difference which exists between 
the Aristotelian physics and the Newtonian theory of the 
heavens. 

It would, however, be a mistake to expect that those great 
geneializations, from which the subordinate truths of the more 
backwaid sciences will probably at some future period be de¬ 
duced by reasoning (as the truths of astronomy are deduced 
from the generalities of the Newtonian theory), will be found, 
in all, or even m most cases, among truths now known and 
admitted. We may lest assured, that many of the most 
geneial laws of nature are as yet entnely unthought of, and 
that many others, destined hereafter to assume the same cha¬ 
racter, are known, if at all, only as laws or pioperties of some 
limited class of phenomena, just as electricity, now recognised 
as one of the most universal of natural agencies, was once 
known only as a curious property which certain substances 
acquired by fnction, of first attracting and then repelhng light 
bodies If the theories of heat, cohesion, crystallization, and 
chemical action, are destined, as there can be little doubt that 
they are, to become deductive, the truths which will then be 
regarded as the pnncipia, of those sciences would probably, if 
now announced, appear quite as novel* as the law of gravita¬ 
tion appeared to the eotemporanes of Newton, possibly even 
more so, since Newton's law, after all, was but an extension of 
the law of weight—that is, of a generalization familiar from of 
old, and which already comprehended a not inconsiderable 
body of natural phenomena The general laws of a similarly 
commanding character, which we still look forward to the dis¬ 
covery of, may not always find so much of their foundations 
already laid. 

These general truths will doubtless make their first ap¬ 
pearance m the character of hypotheses, not proved, nor even 


* Written before the rise of the new views respecting the relation of heat 
to mechanical force, but confirmed lather than contradicted by them. 



EXAMPLES OF THE EXPLANATION OF LAWS. 5' 

admitting of proof, in the first instance, but assumed as pi 
mises for the purpose of deducing from them the known la 
of concrete phenomena. But this, though their initial, cann 
he their final state. To entitle an hypothesis to he received 
one of the truths of nature, and not as a mere technical he 
to the human faculties, it must he capable of being tested 1 
the canons of legitimate induction, and must actually ha 
been submitted to that test. When this shall have been don 
and done successfully, premises will have been obtained fro 
which all the other propositions of the science will thencefon 
be presented as conclusions, and the science will, by means i 
a new and unexpected Induction, be rendered Deductive. 




v 





END OF VOL I.