Skip to main content

Full text of "The common sense of the exact sciences"

See other formats


THE 

INTERNATIONAL  SCIENTIFIC  SERIES. 

Each  Book  Complete  in  One  Volume.     Crown  8vo.  cloth. 


I.  FORMS  of  WATER:  in  Clouds  and  Rivers,  Ice  and 
Glaciers.  By  J.  TYXUAU.,  LL.D.,  F.R.S.  With  ao  Illu<tnition<.  Nii.th 
Edition.  5.<. 

II.   PHYSICS  and  POLITICS;    or,  Thoughts  ou  the  Application 
of  the  Principles  of  'Natural  selection'  and  •Inheritance'  to   i 
-iicirty.     l!y  W.U.TKII  BACJKHOT.     Eighth  Edition.     -!«. 

]If.  FOODS.    By  EDWA.BD  SMITH,  M.D.,  LL.B.,  F.R.S.    With  inn 

Illustrations.     Ninth  Edition,     as. 

IV.  MIND  and  BODY:  the  Theories  and  their  Relation.  Hy 
AI.KXANDKU  BAIN,  LL.D.  With  Four  Illustrations.  Seventh  Edition.  4.-. 

V.  The  STUDY  of  SOCIOLOGY.  By  HERHEKT.SPK.VCKK.  Twelt'rh 
Edition.  i>.i. 

VI.  On  the  CONSERVATION  of  ENERGY.  By  BALK. mo 
t-iT.u'AiiT,  M.A.,  LL.D.,  K.H.S.  With  14  Illustrations.  Seventh  Edition.  •">.-. 

VII.  ANIMAL  LOCOMOTION;  or,  Walking,  Swimming,  a:.: 
Flyini.'.  By  J.  B.  PETTK;KKW,  M.D..  F.R.S.,  &c.  \Vith  Kio  Illustratioiis. 
Third  Edition.  5*. 

VIII.   RESPONSIBILITY  in    MENTAL   DISEASE.      I'.y   HEXHY 
MAI-IISLEY,  M.D.     Kutirth  Edition,     of. 

IX.   The  NEW  CHEMISTRY.     By  Professor   J.  P.   COOKK. 
Harvard  University.     With  31  Illu>trations.     Eighth  Edition,     ns. 

\.  Th.e  SCIENCE  of  LAW.     By  Professor  SHBLDON  AMOS,      yixth 

Edition.     5a. 

XI.  ANIMAL  MECHANISM:  a  Treatise  on  Terrestrial  and  Acrid 
Locomotion.  By  Professor  K.  J.  MAKF.Y.  Witli  1 1  7  Illustnitinns.  Third 
Edition.  -~>x. 

XII.   The    DOCTRINE   of  DESCENT   and  DARWINISM.     P.y 

Professor  Osc  A  it  SCHMIDT  (Stnu-liurg  University).     With  ;'li  Illustration.-. 
S.-venth  Edition.     •'». 

XIII.   The  HISTORY  of    the  CONFLICT  between   RELIGION 
and    SCIENCE.       By  J.   W.   DKAPKK,  M.D.,  LL.D.      Nit 
Edition.    5*. 

XIV.  FUNGI:  their  Nature,  Influences,  U*es,  &c.  By  M.  C  COUKK, 
M.A.,  LL.D.  Edited  by  the  Rev.  M.  J.  BKHKRI.KV,  M.A..  F.L..S.  Wi::i 
nnmorous  Illustrations.  Third  Edition.  5.t. 


London:  KEG  AN  PAUL,  TRENCH,  &  CO.,  1  Paternoster  Square. 


The  International  Scientific  Series — continued. 


XV.  The  CHEMICAL  EFFECTS  of  LIGHT  and  PHOTO 
GRAPHY.  By  Dr.  HERMANN  VOGEL  (Polytechnic  Academy  of 
Berlin).  Translation  thoroughly  revised.  With  100  Illustrations.  Fourth 
Edition.  5.i. 

XVI.  The  LIFE  and  GROWTH  of  LANGUAGE.     By  WIJ.UAM 
DWIOHT  WHITNEY.    Fifth  Edition.    5i. 

XVII.  MONEY  and   the   MECHANISM  of  EXCHANGE.     By 

W.  STANLEY  JEVONS,  M.A.,  F.R.S.    Eighth  Edition.    5j. 

XVIII.  The  NATURE  of  LIGHT,  with  a  General  Account  of 
PHYSICAL  OPTICS.  By  Dr.  EUGENE  LOMMEL.  With  188  Illus- 
trations  and  a  Table  of  Spectra  in  Chromo-lithograjjhy.  Fourth  Edition.  5.«. 

XIX.  ANIMAL  PARASITES  and  MESSMATES.  By  Monsieur 
VAN  BENEDEN.  With  83  Illustrations.  Third  Edition.  5j. 

XX.  FERMENTATION.  By  Professor  SCHDTUWBKBOEB.  With 
28  Illustrations.  Fourth  Edition.  St. 

XXI.  The  FIVE  SENSES  of  MAN.  By  Professor  BKHNSTKIW. 
With  91  Illustrations.  Fifth  Edition.  5s. 

XXII.  The  THEORY  of  SOUND  in  its  RELATION  to  MUSIC. 

By  Profes.«or  PIKTHO  BLASKRXA.    With  numerous  Illustrations.      Third 
Edition.    .".<. 

XXIII.  STUDIES  in   SPECTRUM  ANALYSIS.     By  J    NOBMAV 

I/>CKYKU,  F.R.S.      With  Six  Photographic  Illustrations  of  Spectra  and 
merous  Engravings  on  Wood.    Fourth  Edition.     &s.  6rf. 

XXIV.  A  HISTORY  of  the  GROWTH  of  the  STEAM  ENGINE 

ir  Professor  R.  U.  THURSTO.V.    With  numerous  Illustrations.    Fourth 
Edition.     6j.  6d. 

XXV.  EDUCATION  as  a  SCIENCE.     By  ALEXAWDJCB  BAIN,  LL  I) 

Sixth  Edition.     ;>s. 

XXVI.  The  HUMAN  SPECIES.  By  Professor  A.  M  Qc  ATKKFAOES, 
Membre  de  1'Institut.  Fourth  Edition.  5s. 

XXVII.  MODERN  CHROMATICS.  With  Applicat.on  to  Art  and 
Industry.  By  OGHE.V  N.  ROOD.  Second  Edition.  With  ISO  original  mus. 
tratious.  os. 


London:  KEGAN  PAUL,  TRENCH,  &  CO.,  1  Paternoster  Square. 


The  International  Scientific  Series— continue-!. 

XXVIII    The   CRAYFISH:   au  Introduction  to  the  Study  of  Z.wlogy. 
By  T.  H.  HL-XLKY,  F.B.8.    Fourtl,  Edition.    With  82  Illustrations. 

\\IX    The  BRAIN  as  an  ORGAN  of  MIND.     By  H    CHM...ION 

BASTIAX,  M.D.     Thinl   Edition.     With  184  Illustrations.     S 

XXX    The  ATOMIC  THEORY.     By  Professor  A.  Wr«-rz.    Tr;m> 

lated  by  E.  CLH.MINSHAW,  F.C.S.    Fourth  Edition.    5*. 

XXXI.  The    NATURAL    CONDITIONS    of    EXISTENCE    a, 
they  affect  Animal   Life.     By   KARL  SKMPKU. 
With  2  Maps  and  106  Woodcuts.     5*. 

XXXII    GENERAL  PHYSIOLOGYof  MUSCLES  and  NERVES. 
By  Prof.  J.  KOSKXTHAL.    Third  Edition.     With  75  Illustrate 

XXXIII    SIGHT:    *n    Exposition  of  the   Principles  of   Monocular  a.,1 
Binocular  Vision.   By  J«*KPH  L.  Cox ,  K,  LL.D.     Second  Edition.     Will 
132  Illustrations.    5s. 
XXXIV.  ILLUSIONS:  a  Psychological  Study.      By  JAMK> 

Second  Edition.    5*. 
XXXV    VOLCANOES:  what  they  are  and  what  they  teach.    By 

JOHN  W.  Jrmi,  K.B.S.    Third  Edition.     With  %  Illustratioi 

XXXVI.   SUICIDE  :   an  Essay  on  Comparative  Moral  Statistics 
Uy  Professor  II.  MOKSKI.I.I.     Second  Kditiou.     *>. 

XXXVII    THE    BRAIN    AND    ITS    FUNCTIONS.      By  J.  L"> 

"    Vhysiciaa  to  the   Ho.pi.-e    du   lu   Salpetrifere.      With    nutnerous    I 

trations.     S-cond  Edition.    r». 
XXXVIII.  MYTH  AND   SCIENCE  :   an  Essay. 

Third  Edition.    5«. 
XXXIX.  THE  SUN.      By  0.  A.  YOUNG.  Ph.D.,  LL.D.     Third  K 

With  numerous  Illustrations.     .V». 

XI     ANTS    BEES,  and  WASPS.     A  Record  of  Observations 
"     0,1   the   Habits  of    the   Social   Hymenoptera.     By   Sir    JOHN 

Bart.,  M.P.     Xinth  Edition.     With  o  Chromo-lithographi< 
XLI.  ANIMAL    INTELLIGENCE.     l!y  GK.>I«;K  J.    ROMAKKS, 

LL.D.,  F.K.S.     Fourth  Edition.    5j. 
XLII    The  'CONCEPTS     and     THEORIES     of     MODERN 

PHYSICS.     By  J.  I!.  STAI.I.O.    Thir.l  Edition,    i 

XLIII.  DISEASES    of    MEMORY.       Au    E.ssay    iu    th.    Furtive 
Psychology.    By  TH.  Bm«'T.    Third  Edition.    5.<. 

London:  KEGAN  PAUL,  TKENCH,  &  CO. ,  1  Paternoster  Square 


The  International  Scientific  Series — continued. 


XL1V.  MAN  BEFORE   METALS.     By  N.  JOLY,   Correspondent 
de  1'Institut  de  France.    Third  Edition.    With  148  Illustrations.    5s. 

XLV.  THE    SCIENCE     of    POLITICS.        By    Prof.    SHELDON 
AMOS.     Third  Kilition.     5s. 

XLVI.  ELEMENTARY     METEOROLOGY.       By    ROBERT    H. 

.Si  M-JT.     Fourth  Edition.     o.«. 

XLVII.  THE    ORGANS    of    SPEECH.       By    GEORG    HERMANN 
vox  MKYKH.     With  47  Illustrations.    5x. 

XLVIII.  FALLACIES  :    a    View  of  Logic  from    the   Practical  ^Side. 
Second  Edition.     By  ALFRED  SIPGWICK.    5.«. 

XLIX.    THE    ORIGIN     OF      CULTIVATED    PLANTS.       By 

ALCHONSK  DE  CAXDOLLK.    5.«. 

L.  JELLY  FISH,  STAR   FISH,  AND    SEA   URCHINS. 

Being  a  Research  on  Primitive  Nervous  Systems.     By  G.  .1.  RIIMINKS, 
LL.D.,  F.R.S.     5*. 

LI.  THE  COMMON  SENSE  OF  THE  EXACT 
SCIENCES.  By  the  late  WILLIAM  KIXGDON  CLIFFORD.  Second  Edition 
With  1UO  Figures.  5*. 

LII.  PHYSICAL    EXPRESSION  :    its  Modes  and  Principles. 
B>  FKAXCIS  WARXKR,  M.D.,  F.K.C.P.     With  30  Illustrations.    5s. 

L1II.  ANTHROPOID    APES.     By    ROBERT    HARTMANN.     With 
<J3  Illustrations.     5t. 

L1V.  THE     MAMMALIA      IN     THEIR     RELATION     TO 

PRIMEVAL  TIMES.    By  OSCAR  SCHMIDT.     With  51  Woodcuts.    5.?. 

LV.  COMPARATIVE     LITERATURE.      By    H.     MACAUI.AY 
POSNKTT,  LL.D.     o.«. 

LVI.  EARTHQUAKES  and  other   EARTH    MOVEMENTS. 

By  Prof.  JOHN  MILNE.    With  38  Figures.    5s. 

LVII.  MICROBES,    FERMENTS,    and  MOULDS.     By  E.    L. 

TH.H-ESSAKT.     With  KIT  Illustrations,    ox. 

LVIII.  GEOGRAPHICAL    and    GEOLOGICAL    DISTRIBU 
TE  iN  nt  ANIMALS.     By  Prof.  A.  HEILPUIN.     5.s. 

LIX.  'WEATHER:  a  Popular  Exposition  of  the  Nature  of  Weather 
Changes  from  Day  to  Day.  By  the  Hon.  RALPH  ABERCROMBT.  With 
!Ui  Figures.  Second  Edition.  5s. 

LX.  ANIMAL  MAGNETISM.     By  ALFRED  B.NET  and  CHARLES 
FKRE.    «.«. 

LX].  MANUAL  OF  BRITISH  DISCOMYCETES,  with  descrip 
tions  of  all  the  Six-cies  of  Fungi  hitherto  found  in  Britain  included  in  the 
•amily.and  Illustrations  of  the  Genera.  By  WILLLA.M  PHILLIPS,  F.L.S.  5s. 

LXII.  INTERNATIONAL  LAW.  With  Materials  for  a  Code  of 
International  Law.  By  Professor  LEONK  LKVI.  5s. 

LXIII. .  THE  ORIGIN  OF  FLORAL  STRUCTURES  THROUGH 
INSECT  AGENCY.    By  Prof.  G-.  HKVSLOW.    5,. 

London:  KF.GAN  PAUL,  TRENCH.  AGO.,  1  Paternoster  Square. 


THE 


INTERNATIONAL  SCIENTIFIC  SERIES 

VOL.    LI. 


THE 


COMMON    SENSE 


OF    THE 


EXACT     SCIENCES 


WITH     100     FIGURES 


'For  information  commences  with  the  senses;  but  the  whole  business 
terminates  in  works.  .  .  .  The  chief  cause  of  failure  in  work  (especially 
after  natures  have  been  diligently  investigated)  is  the  ill  determination 
and  measurement  of  the  forces  and  actions  of  bodies.  Now  the  forces 
and  actions  of  bodies  are  circumscribed  and  measured,  either  by  distances 
of  space,  or  by  moments  of  time,  or  by  concentration  of  quantity,  or  by 
predominance  of  virtue  ;  and  unless  these  four  things  have  been  well 
and  carefully  weighed,  we  shall  have  sciences,  fair  perhaps  in  theory, 
but  in  practice  inefficient.  The  four  instances  which  are  useful  in  this 
point  of  view  I  class  under  one  head  as  Mathematical  Instances  and 
Instances  of  Measurement' — A'ovum  Organum,  Lib.  ii,  Aph.  xliv 


SECOND    EDITION 


LONDON 

KEGAN  PAUL,  TRENCH,  &  CO.,  1  PATERNOSTER  SQUARE 

1886 


L.O 


rights  of  translation  and  of  reproduction  are  reserved ) 


PBEFACE. 


IN  March  1879  Clifford  died  at  Madeira;  six  years 
afterwards  a  posthumous  work  is  for  the  first  time 
placed  before  the  public.  Some  explanation  of  this 
delay  must  be  attempted  in  the  present  preface.1 

The  original  work  as  planned  by  Clifford  was  to 
have  been  entitled  The  First  Principles  of  the  Mathe 
matical  Sciences  Explained  to  the  Non-Mathematical,  and 
to  have  contained  six  chapters,  on  Number,  Space, 
Quantity,  Position,  Motion,  and  Mass  respectively.  Of 
the  projected  work  Clifford  in  the  year  1875  dictated 
the  chapters  on  Number  and  Space  completely,  the 
first  portion  of  the  chapter  on  Quantity,  and  somewhat 
later  nearly  the  entire  chapter  on  Motion.  The  first 
two  chapters  were  afterwards  seen  by  him  in  proof,  but 
never  finally  revised.  Shortly  before  his  death  he  ex 
pressed  a  wish  that  the  book  should  only  be  published 

1  A  still  more  serious  delay  seems  likely  to  attend  the  publication  of 
the  second  and  concluding  part  (Kinetic)  of  Clifford's  Elements  of  Dynamic, 
the  manuscript  of  which  was  left  in  a  completed  state.  I  venture  to 
think  the  delay  a  calamity  to  the  mathematical  world. 


VI  PHEFACE. 

after  very  careful  revision,  and  that  its  title  should  be 
changed  to  The  Common  Sense  of  the  Exact  Sciences. 

Upon  Clifford's  death  the  labour  of  revision  and 
completion  was  entrusted  to  Mr.  E.  C.  Eowe,  then 
Professor  of  Pure  Mathematics  at  University  College, 
London.  That  Professor  Eowe  fully  appreciated  the 
difficulty  and  at  the  same  time  the  importance  of  the 
task  he  had  undertaken  is  very  amply  evidenced  by  the 
time  and  care  he  devoted  to  the  matter.  Had  he  lived 
to  complete  the  labour  of  editing,  the  work  as  a  whole 
would  have  undoubtedly  been  better  and  more  worthy 
of  Clifford  than  it  at  present  stands.  On  the  sad  death 
of  Professor  Eowe,  in  October  1884, 1  was  requested  by 
Messrs.  Kegan  Paul,  Trench,  &  Co.  to  take  up  the 
task  of  editing,  thus  left  incomplete.  Tt  was  with  no 
light  heart,  but  with  a  grave  sense  of  responsibility  that 
I  undertook  to  see  through  the  press  the  labour  of  two 
men  for  whom  I  held  the  highest  scientific  admiration 
and  personal  respect.  The  reader  will  perhaps  appre 
ciate  my  difficulties  better  when  I  mention  the  exact 
state  of  the  work  when  it  came  into  my  hands. 
Chapters  I.  and  II.,  Space  and  Number  ;  half  of  Chapter 
III.,  Quantity  (then  erroneously  termed  Chapter  IV.) ; 
and  Chapter  V.,  Notion,  were  in  proof.  With  these 
proofs  I  had  only  some  half-dozen  pages  of  the 
corresponding  manuscript,  all  the  rest  having  un- 


PREFACE.  Vll 

fortunately  been  considered  of  no  further  use,  and 
accordingly  destroyed.  How  far  the  contents  of  the 
later  proofs  may  have  represented  what  Clifford  dictated 
I  have  had  no  means  of  judging  except  from  the  few 
pages  of  manuscript  in  my  possession.  In  revising  the 
proofs  of  the  first  two  chapters,  which  Clifford  himself 
had  seen,  I  have  made  as  little  alteration  as  possible, 
only  adding  an  occasional  foot-note  where  it  seemed 
necessary.  From  page  65  onwards,  however,  I  am, 
with  three  exceptions  in  Chapter  V.,  responsible  for 
all  the  figures  in  the  book. 

After  examining  the  work  as  it  was  placed  in  my 
hands,  and  consulting  Mrs.  Clifford,  I  came  to  the 
conclusion  that  the  chapter  on  Quantity  had  been 
misplaced,  and  that  the  real  gaps  in  the  work  were  from 
the  middle  of  Chapter  III.  to  Chapter  V.,  and  again  at 
the  end  of  Chapter  V.  As  to  the  manner  in  which 
these  gaps  were  to  be  filled  I  had  no  definite  information 
whatever ;  only  after  my  work  had  been  completed  was 
an  early  plan  of  Clifford's  for  the  book  discovered.  It 
came  too  late  to  be  of  use,  but  it  at  least  confirmed  our 
rearrangement  of  the  chapters. 

For  the  latter  half  of  Chapter  III.  and  for  the  whole 
of  Chapter  IV.  (pp.  116-226)  I  am  alone  responsible. 
Yet  whatever  there  is  in  them  of  value  I  owe  to  Clifford ; 
whatever  is  feeble  or  obscure  is  my  own. 


Vlll  PREFACE. 

With  Chapter  V.  my  task  has  been  by  no  means  I 
light.     It  was   written  at   a  time  when   Clifford   was 
much  occupied  with  his  theory  of  '  Graphs/  and  found  ] 
it  impossible  to  concentrate  his  mind  on  anything  else  : 
parts  of   it  are  clear   and  succinct,   parts   were   such 
as   the    author   would    never    have   allowed   to  go  to 
press.     I  felt  it  impossible  to  rewrite  the  whole  without 
depriving  the  work  of  its  right  to  be  called  Clifford's, 
and  yet  at  the  same  time  it  was  absolutely  necessary 
to  make  considerable  changes.     Hence  it  is  that  my 
revision  of  this  chapter  has  been  much  more  extensive 
than  in  the  case  of  the  first  two.     With  the  result  I 
fear  many  will  be  dissatisfied;  they  will,  however,  hardly 
be  more  conscious  of  its  deficiencies  than  I  am.     I  can 
but  plead  the  conditions  under  which  I  have  had  to 
work.      One  word  more  as  to  this  chapter.      Without 
any  notice  of  mass  or  force  it  seemed  impossible  to  close 
a  discussion  on  motion ;  something  I  felt  must  be  added. 
I  have  accordingly  introduced  a  few  pages  on  the  laws 
of  motion.     I  have  since  found  that  Clifford  intended 
to  write  a  concluding  chapter  on  mass.     How  to  express 
the  laws  of  motion  in  a  form  of  which  Clifford  would 
have  approved  was  indeed  an  insoluble  riddle  to  me, 
because  I  was  unaware  of  his  having  written  anything 
on  the  subject.     I  have  accordingly  expressed,  although 
with  great  hesitation,  my  own  views  on  the  subject; 


PREFACE.  IX 

these  may  be  concisely  described  as  a  strong  desire  to 
see  the  terms  matter  and  force,  together  -with  the  ideas 
associated  with  them,  entirely  removed  from  scientific 
terminology — to  reduce,  in  fact,  all  dynamic  to  kine 
matic.  I  should  hardly  have  ventured  to  put  forward 
these  views  had  I  not  recently  discovered  that  they  have 
(allowing  for  certain  minor  differences)  the  weighty 
authority  of  Professor  Mach,  of  Prag.1  But  since  writing 
these  pages  I  have  also  been  referred  to  a  discourse 
delivered  by  Clifford  at  the  Eoyal  Institution  in  1873, 
some  account  of  which  appeared  in  Nature,  June  1 0, 
1880.  Therein  it  is  stated  that  '  no  mathematician 
can  give  any  meaning  to  the  language  about  matter, 
force,  inertia  used  in  current  text-books  of  mechanics.' 2 
This  fragmentary  account  of  the  discourse  undoubtedly 
proves  that  Clifford  held  on  the  categories  of  matter 
and  force  as  clear  and  original  ideas  as  on  all  subjects 
of  which  he  has  treated ;  only,  alas  !  they  have  not 
been  preserved. 

In  conclusion  I  must  thank  those  friends  who  have 
been  ever  ready  with  assistance  and  advice.  Without 
their  aid  I  could  not  have  accomplished  the  little  that 

1  See  his  recent  book,  Die  MecJtanik  in  ihrer  Entwickelung.     Leipzig, 
1883. 

2  Mr.  R.  Tucker,  -who  has  kindly  searched  Clifford's  note-books  for 
anything  on  the  subject,  sends  me  a  slip  of  paper  with  the  following 
words  in  Clifford's  handwriting :  '  Force  is  not  a  fact  at  all,  but  an  idea 
embodying  what  is  approximately  the  fact.' 


X  PREFACE. 

has  been  done.  My  sole  desire  has  been  to  give  to  the  H 
public  as  soon  as  possible  another  work  of  one  whose  K 
memory  will  be  revered  by  all  who  have  felt  the  MI 
invigorating  influence  of  his  thought.  Had  this  work  I: 
been  published  as  a  fragment,  even  as  many  of  us  I 
wished,  it  would  never  have  reached  those  for  whom  i 
Clifford  had  intended  it.  Completed  by  another  hand,  I 
we  can  only  hope  that  it  will  perform  some,  if  but  a  I 
small  part,  of  the  service  which  it  would  undoubtedly 
have  fulfilled  had  the  master  lived  to  put  it  forth. 

K.  P. 

UNITEBSITT  COLLEGE,  LONDON  : 
February  26. 


CONTENTS. 


CHAPTER   I. 


NUMBER. 

PA  OB 

6KCTIOH 

1.    Number  is  Independent  of  the  order  of  Count    »    . 

1 

2. 

A  Sum  is  Independent  of  the  order  of  Adding 

2 

3. 

A  Product  is  Independent  of  the  order  oi  Multiplying      . 

6 

4. 

The  Distributive  Law 

.     14 

5. 

On  Powers         

.     16 

6. 

Square  of  a  +  1     

.     17 

7. 

On  Powers  of  a  +  b    . 

.     19 

8. 

On  the  Number  of  Arrangements  of  a  Group  of  Letters 

.     21 

9. 

On  a  Theorem  concerning  any  Power  of  a  +  b 

•     -7 

10. 

On  Operations  which  appear  to  be  without  Meaning  . 

.     32 

0   1 

11. 

Steps          

.            •  J   I 

38 

12. 
13. 

Addition  and  Multiplication  of  Operations 

.     40 

14. 

Division  of  Operations          

.     42 

15. 

General  Results  of  our  Extension  of  Terms     . 

.     45 

CHAPTER  II. 

SPACE. 

1. 

.     47 

2. 

Lengths  can  be  Moved  without  Change        .... 

.     52 

3. 

The  Characteristics  of  Shape    . 

55 

4. 

The  Characteristics  of  Surface  Boundaries  .... 

.     63 

5. 

The  Plane  and  the  Straight  Line 

.     M 

6. 

Properties  of  Triangles         

.     G9 

7. 

Properties  of  Circles  ;  Related  Circles  and  Triangles 

.     75 

8. 

The  Conic  Sections 

.     81 

9. 

On  Surfaces  of  the  Second  Order 

87 

10. 

How  to  form  Curves  of  the  Third  and  Higher  Orders  . 

.     91 

Xll  CONTENTS. 

CHAPTER  HI. 

QUANTITY. 

SECTION  pAC(B 

1.  The  Measurement  of  Quantities 95 

2.  The  Addition  and  Subtraction  of  Quantities        .  .99 

3.  The  Multiplication  and  Division  of  Quantities         .        .  .  100 

4.  The  Arithmetical  Expression  of  Ratios         .  .        102 

5.  The  Fourth  Proportional .  105 

6.  Of  Areas;  Stretch  and  Squeeze     ....  .  113 

7.  Of  Fractions .116 

8.  Of  Areas;  Shear   ......  .  120 

9.  Of  Circles  and  their  Areas        ...  ...  123 

10.  Of  the  Area  of  Sectors  of  Curves          ....  130 

11.  Extension  of  the  Conception  of  Area 131 

12.  On  the  Area  of  a  Closed  Tangle 135 

13.  On  the  Volumes  of  Space-Figures    .         .        .  138 

14.  On  the  Measurement  of  Angles .  141 

15.  On  Fractional  Powers .  144. 

CHAPTER  IV. 

POSITION. 

1.  All  Position  is  Relative    ...                 .  .  147 

2.  Position  may  be  Determined  by  Directed  Steps  .        .         .  149 

3.  The  Addition  of  Directed  Steps  or  Vectors       .         .        .  .153 

4.  The  Addition  of  Vectors  obeys  the  Commutative  Law         .  .  158 

5.  On  Methods  of  Determining  Position  in  a  Plane       .         .  .  159 

6.  Polar  Co-ordinates .164 

7.  The  Trigonometrical  Ratios      ....  .166 

8.  Spirals jg- 

9.  The  Equiangular  Spiral 171 

10.  On  the  Nature  of  Logarithms       ...  176 

11.  The  Cartesian  Method  of  Determining  Position        .        .  .181 

12.  Of  Complex  Numbers  ....  Igg 

13.  On  the  Operation  which  turns  a  Step  through  a  given  Angle  .  192 

14.  Relation  of  the  Spin  to  the  Logarithmic  Growth  of  Unit  Step  195 

15.  On  the  Multiplication  of  Vectors  .        ...  .198 

16.  Another  Interpretation  of  the  Product  of  Two  Vectors     .  .  204 

17.  Position  in  Three-Dimensioned  Space  .        .        .  .207 

18.  On  Localised  Vectors  or  Rotors         .        .  t  210 

19.  On  the  Bending  of  Space      ....  .214 


CONTENTS.  XU1 


CHAPTER  V. 

MOTION. 

BICTIOS  PAGE 

1.  On  the  Various  Kinds  of  Motion 227 

2.  Translation  and  the  Curve  of  Positions         ....  230 

3.  Uniform  Motion 235 

4.  Variable  Motion 237 

5.  On  the  Tangent  to  a  Curve  243 

6.  On  the  Determination  of  Variable  Velocity          .        .        .     .  250 

7.  On  the  Method  of  Fluxions 253 

8.  Of  the  Relationship  of  Quantities,  or  Functions  .        .        .     .  255 

9.  Of  Acceleration  and  the  Hodograph 260 

10.  On  the  Laws  of  Motion 267 

11.  Of  Mass  and  Force   .  .  269 


THE 

COMMON    SEXSE 

OF    THE 

EXACT     SCIENCES. 

CHAPTER   I. 

NUMBER. 

§  1.  Number  is  Independent  of  the  order  of  Count  in  a 

THE  word  which  stands  at  the  head  of  this  clir 
contains  six  letters.  In  order  to  find  out  that  there 
are  six,  '  ;e  count  them  ;  n  one,  u  two,  m  three,  b  four, 
e  five,  if  six.  In  this  process  we  have  taken  the  letters 
one  by  one,  and  have  put  beside  them  six  words  whk-h 
are  the  first  six  out  of  a  series  of  words  that  we  always 
carry  about  with  us,  the  names  of  numbers.  After  putting 
these  six  words  one  to  each  of  the  letters  of  the  word 
number,  we  found  that  the  last  of  the  words  was  .<-•/  •• ;  and 
accordingly  we  called  that  set  of  letters  by  the  name  .six. 

If  we  counted  the  letters  in  the  word  '  chapter  :  in 
the  same  way,  we  should  find  that  the  last  of  the 
numeral  words  thus  used  would  be  seven;  and  accor 
dingly  we  say  that  there  are  seven  letters. 

But  now  a  question  arises.  Let  us  suppose  tha^  the 
letters  of  the  word  number  are  printed  upon  separate 


2        THE   COMMON   SENSE   OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

small  pieces  of  wood  belonging  to  a  box  of  letters  ;  fhs. 
we  put  these  into  a  bag  and  shake  them  up  and  brin^ 
them  out,  putting  them  down  in  any  other  order,  an  I 
then  count  them  again ;  we  shall  still  find  that  thei 
are  six  of  tnem.      For  example,  if  they  come  out  ij 
the  alphabetical  order  b  e  m  n  r  u,  and  we  put  to  eacl 
of  these  one  of  the  names  of  numbers  that  we  havj 
before  used,  we  shall  still  find  that  the  last  name  \vi| 
be  six.     In  the  assertion  that  any  group  of  things  coi 
sists  of  six  things,  it  is  implied  that  the  word  six  wil 
be   the  last  of  the  ordinal  words  used,  in   whatevel 
order  we  take  up  this  group  of  things  to  count  them! 
That  is  to   say,   the  number  of  any  set  of  things  is  th\ 
same  in  whatever  order  we  count  them. 

Upon  this  fact,  which  we  have  observed  with  regard 
to  the  particular  number  six,  and  which  is  true  of  all 
numbers  whatever,  the  whole  of  the  science  of  numbe] 
is  based.  We  shall  now  go  on  to  examine  somJ 
theorems  about  numbers  which  may  be  deduced  from  itl 

§  2.  A  Sum  is  Independent  of  the  order  of  Adding. 

Suppose  that  we  have  two  groups  of  things  ;  say  th< 
letters  in  the  word  '  number,'  and  the  letters  in  th< 
word  '  chapter.'  We  may  count  these  groups  separately 
and  find  that  they  come  respectively  to  the  numbers 
six  and  seven.  We  may  then  put  them  all  together,  anc 
we  find  in  this  case  that  the  aggregate  group  which  is 
so  formed  consists  of  thirteen  letters. 

Now  this  operation  of  putting  the  things  all  togethe 
may  be  conceived  as  taking  place  in  two  different  ways 
We  may  first  of  all  take  the  six  things  and  put  them  ir 
a  heap,  and  then  we  may  add  the  seven  things  to  then- 
one  by  one.  The  process  of  counting,  if  it  is  performed 


NUMBER.  3 

in  this  order,  amounts  to  counting  seven  more  ordinal 
words  after  the  word  six.  We  may  however  take  the 
seven  things  first  and  put  them  into  a  heap,  and  then 
add  the  six  things  one  by  one  to  them.  In  this  case  the 
process  of  counting  amounts  to  counting  six  more 
ordinal  words  after  the  word  seven. 

But  from  what  we  observed  before,  that  if  we  count 
any  set  of  things  we  come  to  the  same  number  in  what 
ever  order  we  count  them,  it  follows  that  the  number 
we  arrive  at,  as  belonging  to  the  whole  group  of  things, 
must  be  the  same  whichever  of  these  two  processes  we 
use.  This  number  is  called  the  sum  of  the  two  numbers 
6  and  7 ;  and,  as  we  have  seen,  we  may  arrive  at  it  either 
by  the  first  process  of  adding  7  to  6,  or  by  the  second 
process  of  adding  6  to  7. 

The  process  of  adding  7  to  6  is  denoted  by  a  short 
hand  symbol,  which  was  first  used  by  Leonardo  da  Vinci. 
A  little  Maltese  cross  (  +  )  stands  for  the  Latin  j>/7/.s>, 
or  the  English  increased  by.  Thus  the  words  six  increased 
by  seven  are  written  in  shorthand  6  +  7.  Now  we 
have  arriv  1  at  the  result  that  six  increased  by  seven  is 
the  same  n  amber  as  seven  increased  by  six.  To  write  this 
wholly  in  shorthand,  we  require  a  symbol  for  the  words, 
is  the  same  number  as.  The  symbol  for  these  is  =  ;  it  was 
first  used  by  an  Englishman,  Robert  Recorde.  Our 
result  then  may  be  filially  written  in  this  way  : — 

6  +  7  =  7  +  6. 

The  proposition  which  we  have  written  in  this 
symbolic  form  states  that  the  sum  of  two  numbers  G 
and  7  is  independent  of  the  order  in  which  they  are 
added  together.  But  this  remark  which  we  have  madf 
about  two  particular  numbers  is  equally  true  of  any 
two  numbers  whatever,  in  consequence  of  our  funda- 

B   'A 


4       THE    COMMON   SEXSE    OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

mental  assumption  that  the  number  of  things  in  anjl 
group  is  independent  of  the  order  in  which  we  count! 
them.  For  by  the  sum  of  any  two  numbers  we  mean! 
a  number  which  is  arrived  at  by  taking  a  group  on 
tilings  containing  the  first  number  of  individuals,  and 

D  O 

adding  to  them  one  by  one  another  group  of  things 
containing  the  second  number  of  individuals  ;  or,  if  we 
like,  by  taking  a  group  of  things  containing  the  second 
number  of  individuals,  and  adding  to  them  one  by  one 
the  group  of  things  containing  the  first  number  of 
individuals.  Now,  in  virtue  of  our  fundamental 
assumption,  the  results  of  these  two  operations  must  be 
the  same.  Thus  we  have  a  right  to  say,  not  only  that 
6  +  7  =  7  +  6,  but  also  that  5  +  13  =  13  +  5,  and 
so  on,  whatever  two  numbers  we  like  to  take. 

This  we  may  represent  by  a  method  which  is  due  to 
Vieta,  viz.,  by  denoting  each  number  by  a  letter  of  the 
alphabet.  If  we  write  a  in  place  of  the  first  number 
in  either  of  these  two  cases,  or  in  any  other  case,  and  b 
in  place  of  the  second  number,  then  our  formula  will 
stand  thus  : — 

a  +  b  =  b  +  a. 

By  means  of  this  representation  we  have  made  a 
statement  which  is  not  about  two  numbers  in  particu 
lar,  but  about  all  numbers  whatever.  The  letters  a  and 
1)  so  used  are  something  like  the  names  which  we  give 
to  things,  for  example,  the  name  horse.  When  we  say 
a  horse  has  four  legs,  the  statement  will  do  for  any 
particular  horse  whatever.  It  says  of  that  particular 
horse  that  it  has  four  legs.  If  we  said  (  a  horse  has  as 
many  legs  as  an  ass,'  we  should  not  be  speaking  of  any 
particular  horse  or  of  any  particular  ass,  but  of  any 
horse  whatever  and  of  any  ass  whatever.  Just  in  the 
same  way,  when  we  assert  that  a  +  b  —  b  +  a,  we  are 


NUMBER.  5 

mot  speaking  of  any  two  particular  numbers,  but  of  all 
numbers  whatever. 

We  may  extend  this  rule  to  more  numbers  than 
two.  Suppose  we  add  to  the  sum  a  +  b  a  third 
number,  c,  then  we  shall  have  an  aggregate  group  of 
things  which  is  formed  by  putting  together  three  groups, 
and  the  number  of  the  aggregate  group  is  got  by  adding 
together  the  numbers  of  the  three  separate  groups.  This 
number,  in  virtue  of  our  fundamental  assumption,  is 
the  same  in  whatever  order  we  add  the  three  groups 
together,  because  it  is  always  the  same  set  of  things 
that  is  counted.  Whether  we  take  the  group  of  a 
things  first,  and  then  add  the  group  of  6  things  to  it 
one  by  one,  and  then  to  this  compound  group  of  a  +  h 
things  add  the  group  of  c  things  one  by  one;  or 
whether  we  take  the  group  of  c  things,  and  add  to  it 
the  group  of  b  things,  and  then  to  the  compound  group 
of  c  +  b  things  add  the  group  of  a  things,  the  sum 
must  in  both  cases  be  the  same.  We  may  write  this 
result  in  the  ymbolic  form  a  +  &  +  c  =  c  +  b  +  a,  or 
we  may  state  in  words  that  the  sum  of  three  numbers  /x 
in<L'lii'n<lt:nt  of  the  order  in  which  they  are  added  /</'/<'//c;/-. 

This  rule  may  be  extended  to  the  case  of  any 
number  of  numbers.  However  many  groups  of  things 
we  have,  if  we  put  them  all  together,  the  number  of 
things  in  the  resulting  aggregate  group  may  be  counted 
in  various  ways.  We  may  start  with  counting  any  one 
of  the  original  groups,  then  we  may  follow  it  with  any 
one  of  the  others,  following  these  by  any  one  of  those 
left,  and  so  on.  In  whatever  order  we  have  taken  these 
groups,  the  ultimate  process  is  that  of  counting  the 
whole  aggregate  group  of  things  ;  and  consequently 
the  numbers  that  we  arrive  at  in  these  different  ways 
must  all  be  the  same. 


6        TPIE   COMMOX   SEXSE   OF   THE   EXACT  SCIEXCES. 

§  3.  A  Product  is  Independent  of  the  order  of  Multiply ing\ 

Now  let  us  suppose  that  we  take  six  groups  oJ 
things  which  all  contain  the  same  number,  say  5,  and! 
that  we  want  to  count  the  aggregate  group  which  is! 
made  by  putting  all  these  together.  We  may  count! 
the  six  groups  of  five  things  one  after  another,  which] 
amounts  to  the  same  thing  as  adding  5  five  times  over 
to  5.  Or  if  we  like  we  may  simply  mix  up  the  whole! 
of  the  six  groups,  and  count  them  without  reference  to) 
their  previous  grouping.  But  it  is  convenient  in  this 
case  to  consider  the  six  groups  of  five  things  as  arranged 
in  a  particular  way. 

Let  us  suppose  that  all  these  things  are  dots  which 
are  made  upon  paper,  that  every  group  of  five  things  is 
five  dots  arranged  in  a  horizontal  line,  and  that  the 
six  groups  are  placed  vertically  under  one  another  as  in 
the  figure. 


We  then  have  the  whole  of  the  dots  of  these  six 
groups  arranged  in  the  form  of  an  oblong  which  con 
tains  six  rows  of  five  dots  each.  Under  each  of  the  five 
dots  belonging  to  the  top  group  there  are  five  other  dots 
belonging  to  the  remaining  groups;  that  is  to  say,  we 
have  not  only  six  rows  containing  five  dots  each,  but  five 
columns  containing  six  dots  each.  Thus  the  whole  set 


NUMBER.  7 

of  dots  can  be  arranged  in  five  groups  of  six  each,  just 
as  well  as  in  six  groups  of  five  each.  The  whole  number 
of  things  contained  in  six  groups  of  five  each,  is  called 
six  times  five.  We  learn  in  this  way  therefore  that 
six  times  five  is  the  same  number  as  five  times  six. 

As  before,  the  remark  that  we  have  here  made  about 
two  particular  numbers  may  be  extended  to  the  case  of 
any  two  numbers  whatever.  If  we  take  any  number  of 
groups  of  dots,  containing  all  of  them  the  same  number 
of  dots,  and  arrange  these  as  horizontal  lines  one  under 
the  other,  then  the  dots  will  be  arranged  not  only  in 
lines  but  in  columns  ;  and  the  number  of  dots  in  every 
column  will  obviously  be  the  same  as  the  number  of 
groups,  while  the  number  of  columns  will  be  equal  to 
the  number  of  dots  in  each  group.  Consequently  the 
number  of  things  in  a  groups  of  b  things  each  is  equal 
to  the  number  of  things  in  b  groups  of  a  things  each, 
no  matter  what  the  numbers  a  and  b  are. 

The  number  of  things  in  a  groups  of  b  things  each 
is  called  a  time?  b  ;  and  we  learn  in  this  way  that  a 
times  b  is  equa'i  to  b  times  a.  The  number  a  times  b 
is  denoted  by  writing  the  two  letters  a  and  b  together, 
a  coming  first ;  so  that  we  may  express  our  result  in  the 
symbolic  form  ab  =  ba. 

Suppose  now  that  we  put  together  seven  such  com 
pound  groups  arranged  in  the  form  of  an  oblong  like 
that  we  constructed  just  now.  They  cannot  now  be  repre 
sented  on  one  sheet  of  paper,  but  we  may  suppose  that 
instead  of  dots  we  have  little  cubes  which  can  be  put 
into  an  oblong  box.  On  the  floor  of  the  box  we  shall 
have  six  rows  of  five  cubes  each,  or  five  columns  of  six 
cubes  each ;  and  there  will  be  seven  such  layers,  one  on 
the  top  of  another.  Upon  every  cube  therefore  which 
is  in  the  bottom  of  the  box  there  will  be  a  pile  of  six. 


8      THE   COMMON   SENSE   OF   THE   EXACT  SCIENCES. 

cubes,  and  we  shall  have  altogether  five  times  six  such 
piles.  That  is  to  say,  we  have  five  times  six  groups  of 
seven  cubes  each,  as  well  as  seven  groups  of  five  times 
six  cubes  each.  The  whole  number  of  cubes  is  indepen 
dent  of  the  order  in  which  they  are  counted,  and  con 
sequently  we  may  say  that  seven  times  five  times  six  is 
the  same  thing  as  five  times  six  times  seven. 

But  it  is  here  very  important  to  notice  that  when  we 
say  seven  times  five  times  six,  what  we  mean  is  that 
seven  layers  have  been  formed,  each  of  which  contains 
five  times  six  things ;  but  when  we  say  five  times  six 
times  seven,  we  mean  that  five  times  six  columns  have 
been  formed,  each  of  which  contains  seven  things. 
Here  it  is  clear  that  in  the  one  case  we  have  first  multi 
plied  the  last  two  numbers,  and  then  multiplied  the  result 
by  the  first  mentioned  (seven  times  five  times  six  =  seven 
times  thirty),  while  in  the  other  case  it  is  the  first  two 
numbers  mentioned  that  are  multiplied  together,  and 
then  the  third  multiplied  by  the  result  (five  times  six 
times  seven  =  thirty  times  seven).  Now  it  is  quite 
evident  that  when  the  box  is  full  of  these  cubes  it  may 
be  set  upon  any  side  or  upon  any  end ;  and  in  all  cases 
there  will  be  a  number  of  layers  of  cubes,  either  5  or  6 
or  7.  And  whatever  is  the  number  of  layers  of  cubes, 
that  will  also  be  the  number  of  cubes  in  each  pile. 
Whether  therefore  we  take  seven  layers  containing 
five  times  six  cubes  each,  or  six  layers  containing 
seven  times  five  cubes  each,  or  five  layers  containing  six 
times  seven  cubes  each,  it  comes  to  exactly  the  same 
thing. 

We  may  denote  five  times  six  by  the  symbol  5x6,  and 
then  we  may  write  five  times  six  times  seven,  5x6x7. 

But  now  this  form  does  not  tell  us  whether  we 
are  to  multiply  together  6  and  7  first,  and  then  take  5 


NUMBER.  9 

times  the  result,  or  whether  we  are  to  multiply  5  and  G 
first,  and  take  that  number  of  sevens.  The  distinction 
between  these  two  operations  may  be  pointed  out  by 
means  of  parentheses  or  brackets  ;  thus,  5  x  (G  x  7) 
means  that  the  6  and  7  must  be  first  multiplied  to 
gether  and  5  times  the  result  taken,  while  (5  x  6)  x  7 
means  that  we  are  to  multiply  5  and  6  and  then  take 
the  resulting  number  of  sevens. 

We  may  now  state  two  facts  that  we  have  learned 
about  multiplication. 

First,  that  the  brackets  make  no  difference  in  the 
result,  although  they  do  make  a  difference  in  the  pro 
cess  by  which  the  result  is  attained;  that  is  to  say, 
5x  (Gx7)  =  (5xG)x7. 

Secondly,  that  the  product  of  these  three  numbers 
is  independent  of  the  order  in  which  they  are  multi 
plied  together. 

The  first  of  these  statements  is  called  the  assocm- 
tive  law  of  multip1  cation,  and  the  second  the  commuta 
tive  law. 

Xow  these  remarks  that  we  have  made  about  the 
[result  of  multiplying  together  the  particular  three 
numbers,  5,  6,  and  7,  are  equally  applicable  to  any 
three  numbers  whatever. 

We  may  always  suppose  a  box  to  be  made  whose 
height,  length,  and  breadth  will  hold  any  three  num 
bers  of  cubes.  In  that  case  the  whole  number  of 
cubes  will  clearly  be  independent  of  the  position  of  the 
box  ;  but  however  the  box  is  set  down  it  will  contain  a 
certain  number  of  layers,  each  layer  containing  a  cer 
tain  number  of  rows,  and  each  row  containing  a  certain 
number  of  cubes.  The  whole  number  of  cubes  in  the 
box  will  then  be  the  product  of  these  three  numbers ; 
and  it  will  be  got  at  by  taking  any  two  of  the  three 


10        THE   COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

numbers,  multiplying  them  together,  and  then  multi 
plying  the  result  by  the  third  number. 

This  property  of  any  three  numbers  whatever  may 
now  be  stated  symbolically. 

In  the  first  place  it  is  true  that  a(bc)  —  (ab)c;  that 
is,  it  comes  to  the  same  thing  whether  we  multiply  the 
product  of  the  second  and  third  numbers  by  the  first, 
or  the  third  number  by  the  product  of  the  first  and 
second. 

In  the  next  place  it  is  true  that  abc  =  acb  =  l>ca,  &c., 
and  we  may  say  that  the  product  of  any  three  numbers 
is  independent  of  the  order  and  of  the  mode  of  group 
ing  in  which  the  multiplications  are  performed. 

We  have  thus  made  some  similar  statements  about 
two  numbers  and  three  numbers  respectively.  This 
naturally  suggests  to  us  that  we  should  inquire  if  cor 
responding  statements  can  be  made  about  four  or  five 
numbers,  and  so  on. 

We  have  arrived  at  these  two  statements  by  con 
sidering  the  whole  group  of  things  to  be  counted  as 
arranged  in  a  layer  and  in  a  box  respectively.  Can 
•we  go  any  further,  and  so  arrange  a  number  of  boxes  as 
to  exhibit  in  this  way  the  product  of  four  numbers? 
It  is  pretty  clear  that  we  cannot. 

Let  us  therefore  now  see  if  we  can  find  any  other 
sort  of  reason  for  believing  that  what  we  have  seen  to 
be  true  in  the  case  of  three  numbers — viz.,  that  the  re 
sult  of  multiplying  them  together  is  independent  of 
the  order  of  multiplying — is  also  true  of  four  or  more 
numbers. 

In  the  first  place  we  will  show  that  it  is  possible  to 
interchange  the  order  of  a  pair  of  these  numbers  which 
are  next  to  one  another  in  the  process  of  multiplying, 
without  altering  the  product. 


NUMBER.  11 

Consider,  for  example,  the  product  of  four  numbers, 

rZ.  We  will  endeavour  to  show  that  this  is  the  same 
;hing  as  the  product  acid.  The  symbol  abed  means 
:liat  we  are  to  take  c  groups  of  d  things  and  then  6 
Croups  like  the  aggregate  so  formed,  and  then  finally  a 
groups  of  bed  things. 

Now,  by  what  we  have  already  proved,  b  groups  of 
\d  things  come  to  the  same  number  as  c  groups  of  bd 
brings.  Consequently,  a  groups  of  bed  things  are  the 
lame  as  a  groups  of  cbd  things ;  that  is  to  say,  abcd  = 
acbd. 

It  will  be  quite  clear  that  this  reasoning  will  hold 
no  matter  how  many  letters  come  after  d.  Suppose, 
for  example,  that  we  have  a  product  of  six  numbers 
abcdef.  This  means  that  we  are  to  multiply  /  by  e,  the 
result  by  cZ,  then  def  by  c,  and  so  on. 

Now  in  this  case  the  product  def  simply  takes  the 
place  which  the  numb  r  d  had  before.  And  b  groups  of 
times  def  things  come  to  the  same  number  as  c  groups 
of  b  times  def  things,  for  this  is  only  the  product  of  three 
numbers,  b,  c,  and  def.  Since  then  this  result  is  the 
same  in  whatever  order  b  and  c  are  written,  there  can 

no  alteration  made  by  multiplications  coming  after, 
that  is  to  say  if  we  have  to  multiply  by  ever  so 
many  more  numbers  after  multiplying  by  a.  It  follows 
therefore  that  no  matter  how  many  numbers  are  multi 
plied  together,  we  may  change  the  places  of  any  two  of 
them  which  are  close  together  without  altering  the 
product. 

In  the  next  place  let  us  prove  that  we  may  change 
the  places  of  any  two  which  are  not  close  together. 
For  example,  that  dbcdef  is  the  same  thing  as  aecdbf, 
where  b  and  e  have  been  interchanged.  We  may  do 
this  by  first  making  the  e  march  backwards,  changing 


12      THE    COMMON    SEXSE    OF   THE    EXACT    SCIENCES. 

places    successively   with   d   and   c   and  b,    when   the 
product  is    changed  into  aebcdf;  and   then  making 
march  forwards  so  as  to  change  places  successively  with 
c  and  d,  whereby  we  have  now  got  e  into  the  place  of  b. 

Lastly,  I  say  that  by  such  interchanges  as  these 
we  can  produce  any  alteration  in  the  order  that  we  like. 
Suppose  for  example  that  I  want  to  change  abcdef  into 
dcfbea.  Here  I  will  first  get  d  to  the  beginning;  I 
therefore  interchange  it  with  a,  producing  dbcaef. 
Next,  I  must  get  c  second  ;  I  do  this  by  interchanging 
it  with  b,  this  gives  dcbaef.  I  must  now  put  /  third 
by  interchanging  it  with  b,  giving  dcfaeb,  next  put  b 
fourth  by  interchanging  it  with  a,  producing  dcfbea. 
This  is  the  form  required.  By  five  such  interchanges 
at  most,  I  can  alter  the  order  of  six  letters  in  any 
way  I  please.  It  has  now  been  proved  that  this  alter 
ation  in  the  order  may  be  produced  by  successive  in 
terchanges  of  two  letters  which  are  close  together. 
But  these  interchanges,  as  we  have  before  shown,  do 
not  alter  the  product ;  consequently  the  product  of  six 
numbers  in  any  order  is  equal  to  the  product  of  the 
same  six  numbers  in  any  other  order ;  and  it  is  easy  to 
see  how  the  same  process  will  apply  to  any  number  o: 
numbers. 

But  is  not  all  this  a  great  deal  of  trouble  for  the 
sake  of  proving  what  we  might  have  guessed  before 
hand  ?  It  is  true  we  might  have  guessed  beforehand 
that  a  product  was  independent  of  the  order  and  group 
ing  of  its  factors  ;  and  we  might  have  done  good  work 
by  developing  the  consequences  of  this  guess  before  we 
were  quite  sure  that  it  was  true.  Many  beautiful 
theorems  have  been  guessed  and  widely  used  be 
fore  they  were  conclusively  proved;  there  are  some 
even  now  in  that  state.  But  at  some  time  or  other  the 


NUMBER.  ] 3 

inquiry  lias  to  be  undertaken,  and  it  always  clears  up 
our  ideas  about  the  nature  of  the  theorem,  besides 
giving  us  the  right  to  say  that  it  is  true.  And  this  is  not 
all ;  for  in  most  cases  the  same  mode  of  proof  or  of  in 
vestigation  can  be  applied  to  other  subjects  in  such  a 
way  as  to  increase  our  knowledge.  This  happens  with 
the  proof  we  have  just  gone  through ;  but  at  present,  as 
we  have  only  numbers  to  deal  with,  we  can  only  go 
backwards  and  not  forwards  in  its  application.  We 
have  been  reasoning  about  multiplication ;  let  us  see  if 
the  same  reasoning  can  be  applied  to  addition. 

What  we  have  proved  amounts  to  this.  A  certain 
result  has  been  got  out  of  certain  things  by  taking 
them  in  a  definite  order ;  and  it  has  been  shown  that 
if  u-e  can  interchange  any  two  consecutive  things  without 
altering  the  result,  then  we  may  make  any  change  whatever 
in  the  order  without  all  ring  the  result.  Let  us  apply 
this  to  counting.  The  process  of  counting  consists  in 
taking  certain  things  in  a  definite  order,  and  applying 
them  to  our  fingers  one  by  one  ;  the  result  depends  on 
the  last  finger,  and  its  name  is  called  the  number  of  the 
things  so  counted.  We  learn  then  that  this  result  will 
be  independent  of  the  order  of  counting,  provided  only 
that  it  remains  unaltered  when  we  interchange  any  two 
consecutive  things  ;  that  is,  provided  that  two  adjacent 
fingers  can  be  crossed,  so  that  each  rests  on  the  object 
previously  under  the  other,  without  employing  any  new 
fingers  or  setting  free  any  that  are  already  employed. 
With  this  assumption  we  can  prove  that  the  number  of 
any  set  of  things  is  independent  of  the  order  of  counting ; 
a  statement  which,  as  we  have  seen,  is  the  foundation 
of  the  science  of  number. 


14      THE   COMMON   SENSE   OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 


§  4.   The  Distributive  Law. 

There  is  another  law  of  multiplication  which  is, 
possible,  still  more  important  than  the  two  we  hav 
already  considered.  Here  is  a  particular  case  of  it 
the  number  5  is  the  sum  of  2  and  3,  and  4  times  5  i 
the  sum  of  4  times  2  and  4  times  3.  We  can  make  thi 
visible  by  an  arrangement  of  dots  as  follows  : — 


Here  we  have  four  rows  of  five  dots  each,  and  each  row  i 
divided  into  two  parts,  containing  respectively  two  dot 
and  three  dots.  It  is  clear  that  the  whole  number 
dots  may  be  counted  in  either  of  two  ways;  as  fou 
rows  of  five  dots,  or  as  four  rows  of  two  dots  togethe 
with  four  rows  of  three  dots.  By  our  general  principl 
the  result  is  independent  of  the  order  of  counting,  an 
therefore 

4  x  5  =  (4  x  2)  +  (4  x  3) ; 

or,  if  we  put  in  evidence  that  5  =  2-4-3, 

4  (2  +  3)  =  (4  x  2)  +  (4  x  3). 

The  process  is  clearly  applicable  to  any  three  num 
bers  whatever,  and  not  only  to  the  particular  numbers 
4,  2,  3.  We  may  construct  an  oblong  containing  a  rows 
of  b  +  c  dots  ;  and  this  may  be  divided  by  a  vertical  line 
into  a  rows  of  6  dots  and  a  rows  of  c  dots.  Counted 
in  one  way,  the  whole  number  of  dots  is  a(b  +  c)  ; 


NUMBER.  1  5 

counted  in  another  way,  it  is  ab  +  ac.     Hence  we  must 

always  have 

a  (b  +  c)  =  ab  -f  ac. 

This  is  the  first  form  of  the  distributive  law. 

Now  the  result  of  multiplication  is  independent  of 
the  order  of  the  factors,  and  therefore 

a  (b  +  c)  =  (b  +  c)  a, 
ab  =  6a, 
ac  =  ca  ; 

so  that  our  equation  may  be  written  in  the  form 
(b  +  c)  a  =  ba  +  ca. 

This  is  called  the  second  form  of  the  distributive  law. 
Using  the  numbers  of  our  previous  example,  we  say  that 
since  5  is  the  sum  of  2  and  3,  5  times  4  is  the  sum  of  2 
times  4  and  3  times  4.  This  form  may  be  arrived  at  in 
dependently  and  very  simply  as  follows.  We  know  that 
2  things  and  3  things  make  5  things,  whatever  the  things 
are;  let  each  of  these  things  be  a  group  of  4  things; 
then  2  fours  and  3  fours  make  5  fours,  or 

(2x4)  +  (3x4)  =5x4. 

The  rule  may  now  be  extended.  It  is  clear  that  our 
oblong  may  be  divided  by  vertical  lines  into  more  parts 
than  two,  and  that  the  same  reasoning  will  apply.  This 


•      •      »  •     o     •     • 


tigure,  for  example,  makes  visible  the  fact  that  just  as 
2  and  3  and  4  make  9,  so  4  times  2,  and  4  times  3,  and 
4  times  4  make  4  times  i).  Or  generally— 


16       THE   COMMON    SEXSE    OF    THE    EXACT    SCIENCES. 

a  (b  -f  c  +  d)  =  ab  +  ac  +  ad, 
(b  +  c  +  d)  a  —  ba  +  ca  +  da ; 

and  the  same  reasoning  applies  to  the  addition  of  any 
number  of  numbers  and  their  subsequent  multiplication. 

§  5.  On  Powers. 

When  a  number  is  multiplied  by  itself  it  is  said  to 
be  squared.  The  reason  of  this  is  that  if  we  arrange  a 
number  of  lines  of  equally  distant  dots  in  an  oblong,  the 
number  of  lines  being  equal  to  the  number  of  dots  in 
each  line,  the  oblong  will  become  a  square. 

If  the  square  of  a  number  is  multiplied  by  the 
number  itself,  the  number  is  said  to  be  cubed  ;  because  if 
we  can  fill  a  box  with  cubes  whose  height,  length,  and 
breadth  are  all  equal  to  one  another,  the  shape  of  the 
box  will  be  itself  a  cube. 

If  we  multiply  together  four  numbers  which  are  all 
equal,  we  get  what  is  called  the  fourth  power  of  any  one 
of  them ;  thus  if  we  multiply  4  3's  we  get  81,  if  we 
multiply  4  2's  we  get  16. 

If  we  multiph"  together  any  number  of  equal  num 
bers,  we  get  in  the  same  way  a  power  of  one  of  them 
which  is  called  its  fifth,  or  sixth,  or  seventh  power,  and 
so  on,  according  to  the  number  of  numbers  multiplied 
together. 

Here  is  a  table  of  the  powers  of  2  and  3  : — 

Index    1234567  8 

Powers  of  2      ...     2        4        8         1C        32        64         128        2.36 
„         3      ...     3         9       27         81       243       729       2187       6561 

The  number  of  equal  factors  multiplied  together  is 
called  the  index,  and  it  is  written  as  a  small  figure 

*  o 

above  the  line  on  the  right-hand  side  of  the  number 
whose  power  is  thus  expressed.     To  write  in  shorthand 


NUMBER.  17 

the  statement  that  if  you  multiply  seven  threes  together 
you  get  2187,  it  is  only  needful  to  put  down  : — 

3     =   2187. 

It  is  to  be  observed  that  every  number  is  its  own 
first  power ;  thus  2'  =  2,  3'  =  3,  and  in  general  a}  —  a. 

§  6.  Square  o/a  +  1. 

may  illustrate  the  properties  of  square  numbers 
by  means  of  a  common  arithmetical  puzzle,  in  which 
one  person  tells  the  number  another  has  thought  of  by 
means  of  the  result  of  a  round  of  calculations  per 
formed  with  it. 

Think  of  a  number  ....         say  3 

Square  it  ......       9 

Add  1  to  the  original  number  ...       4 
Square  that      .          .          .          .          .          .     Ib 

Take  the  difference  of  the  two  squares      .       7 

This  last  is  always  an  odd  number,  and  the  number 
thought  of  is  what  we  may  call  the  less  half  of  it ;  viz., 
it  is  the  half  of  the  even  number  next  below  it.  Thus, 
the  result  being  given  as  7,  we  know  that  the  number 
thought  of  was  the  half  of  G,  or  3. 

We  will  now  proceed  to  prove  this  rule.  Suppose 
that  the  square  of  5  is  given  us,  in  the  form  of  twenty- 
five  dots  arranged  in  a  square,  how  are  we  to  form  the 
square  of  6  from  it?  We  may  add  five  dots  on  the 
right,  and  then  five  dots  along  the  bottom,  and  then 
one  dot  extra  in  the  corner.  That  is,  to  get  the  square 
of  6  from  the  square  of  5,  we  must  add  one  more  than 
twice  5  to  it.  Accordingly — 

36  =  25  +  10  +  1. 

c 


18       THE    COMMON   SEXSE    OF    THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 


And,  conversely,  the  number  5  is  the  less  half  of  thel 
difference  between  its  square  and  the  square  of  6.  I r; 


The  form  of  this  reasoning-  shows  that  it  holds  good 
for  any  number  whatever.  Having  given  a  square  of 
dots,  we  can  make  it  into  a  square  having  one  more 
dot  in  each  side  by  adding  a  column  of  dots  on  the 
riffht,  a  row  of  dots  at  the  bottom,  and  one  more  dot  in 

O         '  J 

the  corner.  That  is,  we  must  add  one  more  than  twice 
the  number  of  dots  in  a  side  of  the  original  square. 
If,  therefore,  this  number  is  given  to  us,  we  have  only 
to  take  one  from  it  and  divide  by  2,  to  have  the  num 
ber  of  dots  in  the  side  of  the  original  square. 

We  will  now  write  down  this  result  in.  shorthand. 
Let  a  be  the  original  number  ;  then  a+ 1  is  the  number 
next  above  it ;  and  what  we  want  to  say  is  that  the  square 
of  a+1,  that  is  (a  +  1)2,  is  got  from  the  square  of  a, 
which  is  a2,  by  adding  to  it  one  more  than  twice  a, 
that  is  2a  + 1.  Thus  the  shorthand  expression  is 

(a  +  1)  2  =  a2  +  2a  +  1. 

This  theorem  is  a  particular  case  of  a  more  general 
one,  which  enables  us  to  find  the  square  of  the  sum  of 


NUMBER. 


19 


any  two  numbers  in  terms  of  the  squares  of  the  two 
numbers  and  their  product.  We  will  first  ilhistrate 
this  by  means  of  the  square  of  5,  which  is  the  sum  of 
2  and  3. 


The  square  of  twenty-five  dots  is  here  divided  into 
two  squares  and  two  oblongs.  The  squares  are  respec 
tively  the  squares  of  3  and  2,  and  each  oblong  is  tin1 
product  of  3  and  2.  In  order  to  make  the  square  of  >'> 
into  the  square  of  3  +  2,  we  must  add  two  columns  on 
the  right,  two  rows  at  the  bottom,  and  then  the  square 
of  2  in  the  corner.  And  in  fact,  25  =  9  +  2x6  +  4. 

§  7.  On  Powers  of  a  +  b. 

To  generalise  this,  suppose  that  we  have  a  square 
with  a  dots  in  each  side,  and  we  want  to  increase  it  to 
a  square  with  a  +  b  dots  in  each  side.  We  must  add  b 
columns  on  the  right,  b  rows  at  the  bottom,  and  then 
the  square  of  b  in  the  corner.  But  each  column  and 
each  row  contains  a  dots.  Hence  what  we  have  to  add 
is  twice  ab  together  with  b2,  or  in  shorthand  : — 

(a  +  6)2  =  a2  +  2ab  +  b*. 

The  theorem  we  previously  arrived  at  may  be  got  from 
this  by  making  6  =  1. 

c  2 


20      THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

Now  this  is  quite  completely  and  satisfactorily 
proved  ;  nevertheless  we  are  going  to  prove  it  again  in 
another  way.  The  reason  is  that  we  want  to  extend 
the  proposition  still  further ;  we  want  to  find  an  ex 
pression  not  only  for  the  square  of  (a  +  fy,  but  for  any 
other  power  of  it,  in  terms  of  the  powers  and  products 
of  powers  of  a  and  b.  And  for  this  purpose  the  mode 
of  proof  we  have  hitherto  adopted  is  unsuitable.  We 
might,  it  is  true,  find  the  cube  of  a-t-b  by  adding  the 
proper  pieces  to  the  cube  of  a ;  but  this  would  be  some 
what  cumbrous,  while  for  higher  powers  no  such  repre 
sentation  can  be  used.  The  proof  to  which  we  now  pro 
ceed  depends  on  the  distributive  law  of  multiplication. 

According  to  this  law,  in  fact,  we  have 

(a  +  6)2  =  (a  +  6)  (a  +  b]  =  a  (a  +  1}  +  I  (a  +  b) 

=  aa  +  ab  +  ba  +  lib 
=  a?  +  2ab  +  l>\ 

It  will  be  instructive  to  write  out  this  shorthand  at 
length.  The  square  of  the  sum  of  two  numbers  means 
that  sum  multiplied  by  itself.  But  this  product  is  the 
first  number  multiplied  by  the  sum  together  with  the 
second  number  multiplied  by  the  sum.  Now  the  first 
number  multiplied  by  the  sum  is  the  same  as  the 
first  number  multiplied  by  itself  together  with  the  first 
number  multiplied  by  the  second  number.  And  the 
second  number  multiplied  by  the  sum  is  the  same  as 
the  second  number  multiplied  by  the  first  number  to 
gether  with  the  second  number  multiplied  by  itself. 
Putting  all  these  together,  we  find  that  the  square  of 
the  sum  is  equal  to  the  sum  of  the  squares  of  the  two 
numbers  together  with  twice  their  product. 

Two  things  may  be  observed  on  this  comparison. 
First,  how  very  much  the  shorthand  expression  gains 


NUMBER.  21 

in  clearness  from  its  brevity.  Secondly,  that  it  is  only 
shorthand  for  something  which  is  just  straightforward 
common  sense  and  nothing  else.  We  may  always 
depend  upon  it  that  algebra,  which  cannot  be  translated 
into  good  English  and  sound  common  sense,  is  bad 
algebra. 

But  now  let  us  put  this  process  into  a  graphical 
shape  which  will  enable  us  to  extend  it.  We  start 
with  two  numbers,  a  and  b,  and  we  are  to  multiply  each 
of  them  by  a  and  also  by  I,  and  to  add  all  the  results. 

a  +  b 

x\  x\ 

aa      la  ab      bb 

Let  us  put  in  each  case  the  result  of  multiplying  by  a 
to  the  left,  and  the  result  of  multiplying  by  b  to  the 
riLcht,  under  the  number  multiplied.  The  process  is 
then  shown  in  the  figure. 

If  we  now  want  to  multiply  this  by  a  +  b  again,  so  as 
to  make  (a  +  b)3,  we  must  multiply  each  part  of  the 
lower  line  by  a,  and  also  by  b,  and  add  all  the  results, 
thus : — 


x\ 

aba      bba  aab     bab 

Here  we  have  eight  terms  in  the  result.  The  first 
and  last  are  a3  and  b3  respectively.  Of  the  remaining 
six,  three  are  baa,  aba,  aab,  containing  two  a's  and  one 
b,  and  therefore  each  equal  to  a'*b ;  and  three  are  bb«, 
bab,  abb,  containing  one  a  and  two  b's,  and  therefore 
each  equal  to  ab2.  Thus  we  have  : — 

(a  +  b)3  =  a3  +  3a'2b  +  3ab*  +  b3. 


/         X 

22      THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF    THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 
For  example,  II3  =  1331.    Here  a  =  10,  6  =  1.  and 


for  it  is  clear  that  any  power  of  1  is  1. 

We  shall  carry  this  process  one 
step  further,  before  making  remarks 
which  will  enable  us  to  dispense 
with  it. 

In  this  case  there  are  sixteen 
terms,  the  first  and  last  being  a4  and 
&4  respectively.  Of  the  rest,  some 
have  three  a's  and  one  &,  some  two 
a's  and  two  6's,  and  some  one  a  and 
three  6's.  There  are  four  of  the 
first  kind,  since  the  &  may  come  first, 
second,  third,  or  fourth;  so  also 
there  are  four  of  the  third  kind,  for 
the  a  occurs  in  each  of  the~same  four 
places  ;  the  remaining  six  are  of  the 
second  kind.  Thus  we  find  that, 

(a  + iy  =  a*  +  4a3&  +  Ga2&2  +  4a&3  +  &4. 

We  might  go  on  with  this  process 
as  long  as  we  liked,  and  we  should 
get  continually  larger  and  larger 
trees.  But  it  is  easy  to  see  that  the 
process  of  classifying  and  counting 
the  terms  in  the  last  line  would 
become  very  troublesome.  Let  us 
then  try  to  save  that  trouble  by 
making  some  remarks  upon  the 
process. 

If  we  go  down  the  tree  last 
figured,  from  a  to  a&aa,  we  shall  find  that  the  term 


NUMBER.  23 

abaa  is  built  up  from  right  to  left  as  we  descend.  The 
a  that  we  begin  with  is  the  last  letter  of  dbaa ;  then  in 
descending  we  move  to  the  right,  and  put  another  a 
before  it ;  then  we  move  to  the  left  and  put  b  before 
that ;  lastly  we  move  to  the  right  and  put  in  the 
first  a.  From  this  there  are  two  conclusions  to  be 
drawn. 

First,  the  terms  at  the  end  are  all  different;  for  any 
divergence  in  the  path  by  which  we  descend  the  tree 
makes  a  difference  in  some  letter  of  the  result. 

Secondly,  every  possible  arrangement  of  four  A.7/>v-s 
which  are  either  a's  or  b's  is  produced.  For  if  any  Midi 
arrangement  be  written  down,  say  abab,  we  have  only 
to  read  it  backwards,  making  a  mean  '  turn  to  the 
left '  and  b  '  turn  to  the  right,'  and  it  will  indicate 
the  path  by  which  we  must  descend  the  tree  to  find 
that  arrangement  at  the  end. 

We  may  put  these  two  remarks  into  one  by  saying 
that  evert/  such  possible  arrangement  is  produced  once  "/"/ 
once  onli/. 

Xow  the  problem  before  ns  was  to  count  the 
number  of  terms  which  have  a  certain  number  of  //s  in 
them.  By  the  remark  just  made  we  have  shown  that 
this  is  the  same  thing  as  to  count  the  number  of 
possible  arrangements  having  that  number  of  b's. 

Consider  for  example  the  terms  containing  one  1>. 
When  there  are  three  letters  to  each  term,  the  number 
of  possible  arrangements  is  3,  for  the  b  may  be  first, 
second,  or  third,  baa,  aba,  aab.  So  when  there  are  four 
letters  the  number  is  4,  for  the  b  may  be  first,  second, 
third,  or  fourth;  b<nn^  tilma,  naha,  aaab.  And  generally 
it  is  clear  that  whatever  be  the  number  of  letters  in  each 
term,  that  is  also  the  number  of  places  in  which  the  6 
can  stand.  Or,  to  state  the  same  thing  ill  shorthand, 


24      THE   COMMON   SENSE   OP   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

if  n  be  the  number  of  letters,  there  are  n  terms  con 
taining  one  b.  And  then,  of  course,  there  are  n  terms 
containing  one  a  and  all  the  rest  &'s. 

And  these  are  the  terms  which  come  at  the  beginning 
and  end  of  the  nth  power  of  a  +  b ;  viz.  we  must  have 
(a  +  b)  —  a  +  nan~lb  +  other  terms  +  nab  ~l  +  bn. 

The  meaning  of  this  shorthand  is  that  we  have  n 
(a  +  b)'s  multiplied  together,  and  that  the  result  of  that 
multiplying  is  the  sum  of  several  numbers,  four  of 
which  we  have  written  down.  The  first  is  the  product  of 
n  a's  multiplied  together,  or  an  ;  the  next  is  n  times  the 
product  of  b  by  (n—  1)  a's,  namely,  nan~lb.  The  last 
but  one  is  n  times  the  product  of  a  by  (n  —  1)  &'s,  namely, 
nabn~l ;  and  the  last  is  the  product  of  n  b's  multiplied 
together,  which  is  written  6". 

O  * 

The  problem  that  remains  is  to  fill  up  this  state 
ment  by  finding  what  the  '  other  terms  '  are,  containing 
each  more  than  one  a  and  more  than  one  6. 


§  8.  On  the  Number  of  Arrangements  of  a  Group  of  Letters. 

This  problem  belongs  to  a  very  useful  branch  of 
applied  arithmetic  called  the  theory  of  '  permutations 
and  combinations,'  or  of  arrangement  and  selection. 
The  theory  tells  us  how  many  arrangements  may  be 
made  with  a  given  set  of  things,  and  how  many  selec 
tions  can  be  made  from  them.  One  of  these  questions 
is  made  to  depend  on  the  other,  so  that  there  is  an 
advantage  in  counting  the  number  of  arrangements 
first. 

With  two  letters  there  are  clearly  two  arrangements, 
ab  and  ba.  With  three  letters  there  are  these  six : — 


I 


NUMBER.  25 

f  namely,  two  with  a  at  the  beginning,  two  with  6  at  the 
beginning,  and  two  with  c  at  the  beginning ;  three 
times  two.  It  would  not  be  much  trouble  to  write 
down  all  the  arrangements  that  can  be  made  with  four 

f  letters  abed.  But  we  may  count  the  number  of  them 
without  taking  that  trouble ;  for  if  we  write  d  before 

\  each  of  the  six  arrangements  of  abc,  we  shall  have  six 
arrangements  of  the  four  letters  beginning  with  */, 
and  these  are  clearly  all  the  arrangements  which  can 
begin  with  d.  Similarly,  there  must  be  six  beginning 
with  a,  six  beginning  with  6,  and  six  beginning  with  c; 
in  all,  four  times  six,  or  twenty -four. 
Let  us  put  these  results  together  : 


3 


With  two  letters,  number  of  arrangements  is  two  =     2 
„     three     „  three  times  two      .  =     6 

„     four       „  four  times  three  times  two  =  21- 

Here  we  have  at  once  a  rule  suggested.  To  find  the 
number  of  arrangements  ivliich  can  be  made  with  a  (jiven 
group  of  letters,  multiply  tor/ether  the  numbers  two,  three, 
four,  &c.,  up  to  the  number  of  letters  in  the  group.  We 
have  found  this  rule  to  be  right  for  two,  three,  and 
four  letters ;  is  it  right  for  any  number  whatever  of 
letters  ? 

We  will  consider  the  next  case  of  five  letters,  and 
\  deal  with  it  by  a  method  which  is  applicable  to  all  cases. 
/  Any  one  of  the  five  letters  may  be  placed  first ;  there  are 
then  five  ways  of  disposing  of  the  first  place.  For  each 
of  these  ways  there  are  four  ways  of  disposing  of  the 
second  place ;  namely,  any  one  of  the  remaining  four 
letters  may  be  put  second.  This  makes  five  times  four 
ways  of  disposing  of  the  first  two  places.  For  each  of 
these  there  are  three  ways  of  disposing  of  the  third 
place,  for  any  one  of  the  remaining  three  letters  may 


26      THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF    THE    EXACT    SCIENCES. 

be  put  third.  This  makes  five  times  four  times  three 
ways  of  disposing  of  the  first  three  places.  For  each 
of  these  there  are  two  ways  of  disposing  of  the  last 
two  places;  in  all,  five  times  four  times  three  times 
two,  or  120  ways  of  arranging  the  five  letters. 

Now  this  method  of  counting  the  arrangements  will 
clearly  do  for  any  number  whatever  of  letters ;  so  that 
our  rule  must  be  right  for  all  numbers. 

We  may  state  it  in  shorthand  thus  :  the  number  of 
arrangements  of  n  letters  is  1  X  2  x  3  x  ...  X  »;  or 
putting  dots  instead  of  the  sign  of  multiplication,  it  is 
1.2.3...  n.  The  1  which  begins  is  of  course  not 
wanted  for  the  multiplication,  but  it  is  put  in  to  in 
clude  the  extreme  case  of  there  being  only  one  letter, 
in  which  case,  of  course,  there  is  only  one  arrange 
ment. 

The  product  1 .  2  .  3  ...  n,  or,  as  we  may  say,  the 
product  of  the  first  n  natural  numbers,  occurs  very  often 
in  the  exact  sciences.  It  has  therefore  been  found 
convenient  to  have  a  special  short  sign  for  it,  just  as 
a  parliamentary  reporter  has  a  special  sign  for  '  the  t 
remarks  which  the  Honourable  Member  has  thought 
fit  to  make.'  Different  mathematicians,  however,  have 
used  different  symbols  for  it.  The  symbol  \n  is  very 
much  used  in  England,  but  it  is  difficult  to  print. 
Some  continental  writers  have  used  a  note  of  admira-  J 
tion,  thus,  n  !  Of  this  it  has  been  truly  remarked  that  ^ 
it  has  the  air  of  pretending  that  you  never  saw  it 
before.  I  myself  prefer  a  symbol  which  has  the  weighty 
authority  of  Gauss,  namely  a  Greek  n  (Pi),  which  may 
be  taken  as  short  for  product  if  we  like,  thus,  Tin.  We 
may  now  state  that — 

111  =  1,  112  =  2,  113  =  6,  114  =  24,  05  =  120,  IIG  =  720, 
and  generally  that 


NUMBER.  27 

n  (n  +  1)  =  (n  +  1)  IIw, 
for  the  product  of  the  first  n+  1  numbers  is  equal  to  the 
product  of  the  first  n  numbers  multiplied  by  ?i  +  l. 

§  9.  On  a  Theorem  concerning  any  Power  of  a  +  b. 

We  will  now  apply  this  rule  to  the  problem  of 
counting  the  terms  in  (a  +  &)";  and  for  clearness'  sake, 
as  usual,  we  will  begin  with  a  particular  case,  namely 
the  case  in  which  91  =  0.  We  know  that  here  there  is 
one  term  whose  factors  are  all  a's,  and  one  whose 
factors  are  all  b's ;  five  terms  which  are  the  product  of 
four  a's  by  one  b,  and  five  which  are  the  product  of  one 
a  and  four  6's.  It  remains  only  to  count  the  number  of 
terms  made  by  multiplying  three  a's  by  two  I's,  which 
is  naturally  equal  to  the  number  made  by  multiplying 
two  a's  by  three  b's.  The  question  is,  therefore,  Itow 
many  different  arrangements  can  lie  made  with  three  ars 
and  two  b's  ? 

Here  the  three  a's  are  all  alike,  and  the  two  b's  are 
alike.  To  solve  the  problem  we  shall  have  to  think  of 
them  as  different ;  let  us  therefore  replace  them  for  the 
present  by  capital  letters  and  small  ones.  How  many 
different  arrangements  can  be  made  with  three  capital 
letters  ABC  and  two  small  ones  tie? 

In  this  question  the  capital  letters  are  to  be  con 
sidered  as  equivalent  to  each  other,  and  the  small 
letters  as  equivalent  to  each  other;  so  that  the  arrange 
ment  A  B  C  a"  e  counts  for  the  same  arrangement  as 
CABeo*.  Every  arrangement  of  capitals  and  smalls 
is  one  of  a  group  of  6  x  2  =  12  equivalent  arrangements; 
for  the  3  capitals  may  be  arranged  among  one 
another  in  113,  =  6  ways,  and  the  2  smalls  may  be 
arranged  in  112,  =  2.  ways.  Now  it  is  clear  that  by 


28      THE   COMMON   SENSE   OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

taking  all  the  arrangements  in  respect  of  capital  and 
small  letters,  and  then  permuting  the  capitals  among 
themselves  and  the  small  letters  among  themselves,  we 
shall  get  the  whole  number  of  arrangements  of  the 
five  letters  A  B  C  d  e ;  namely  IT5  or  1 20.  But  since 
each  arrangement  in  respect  of  capitals  and  smalls  is 
here  repeated  twelve  times,  and  since  12  goes  into  120  ten 
times  exactly,  it  appears  that  the  number  we  require  is 
ten.  Or  the  number  of  arrangements  of  three  a's  and 
two  &'s  is  115  divided  by  113  and  112. 
The  arrangements  are  in  fact — 

bbaaa,  babaa,  baaba,  baadb 

abbaa,  ababa,  abaab 

aabba,  aabab 

aaabb 

The  first  line  has  a&  at  the  beginning,  and  there  are 
four  positions  for  the  second  b ;  the  next  line  has  a  b  in 
the  second  place,  and  there  are  three  new  positions  for 
the  other  b,  and  so  on.  We  might  of  course  have  ar 
rived  at  the  number  of  arrangements  in  this  particular 
case  by  the  far  simpler  process  of  direct  counting, 
which  we  have  used  as  a  verification  ;  but  the  advantage 

*  D 

of  our  longer  process  is  that  it  will  give  us  a  general 
formula  applicable  to  all  cases  whatever. 

Let  us  stop  to  put  on  record  the  result  just  obtained  ; 
viz.  we  have  found  that 

(a  +  6)5  =  a5  +  5a4&  +  10a3Z>2  +  10a2&3  +  5a&4  +  65. 

Observe  that  1  +  5  +  10  +  10  +  5  +  1  =  32,  that  is,  we 
have  accounted  for  the  whole  of  the  32  terms  which 
would  be  in  the  last  line  of  the  tree  appropriate  to  this 
case. 

We  may  now  go  on  to  the  solution  of  our  general 
problem.  Suppose  that  p  is  the  number  of  a's  and  j  is 


NUMBER.  29 

ihe  number  of  6's  which,  are  multiplied  together  in  a 
3ertain  term ;  we  want  to  find  the  number  of  possible 
arrangements  of  these  p  a's  and  q  6's.  Let  us  replace 
;hem  for  the  moment  by  p  capital  letters  and  q  small 
ones,  making  p  +  q  letters  altogether.  Then  any  ar 
rangement  of  these  in  respect  of  capital  letters  and 
small  ones  is  one  of  a  group  of  equivalent  arrangements 
jot  by  permuting  the  capitals  among  themselves  and 
the  small  letters  among  themselves.  Now  by  per 
muting  the  capital  letters  we  can  make  lip  arrange 
ments,  and  by  permuting  the  small  letters  Uq  ar 
rangements.  Hence  every  arrangement  in  respect  of 
capitals  and  smalls  is  one  of  a  group  of  Tip  x  Yiq 
equivalent  arrangements.  Now  the  whole  number  of 
arrangements  of  the  p  +  q  letters  is  IT  (p  +  q) ;  and,  as 
we  have  seen,  every  arrangement  in  respect  of  capitals 
and  smalls  is  here  repeated  Yip  x  Tlq  times.  Conse 
quently  the  number  we  are  in  search  of  is  got  by  di 
viding  IT  (p  +  q)  by  lip  x  Uq.  This  is  written  in  the 
form  of  a  fraction,  thus  : — 

n  (p  +  g) 

Up .  113  ' 

although  it  is  not  a  fraction,  for  the  denominator  always 
divides  the  numerator  exactly.  In  iact,  it  would  be 
absurd  to  talk  about  half  a  quarter  of  a  way  of  arranging 
letters. 

We  have  arrived  then  at  this  result,  that  the  number 
of  ways  of  arranging  p  a's  and  q  b's  is 

n  (p  +  g] 

Up  .  ilq    ' 

This  is  also  (otherwise  expressed)  the  number  of  ways 
of  dividing  p  +  q  places  into  p  of  one  sort  and  q  of 


30      THE    COMMON    SEXSE    OF    THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

another ;  or  again,  it  is  the  number  of  ways  of  selectin" 
p  things  out  of  p  +  q  things. 

Applying  this  now  to  the  expression  of  («  +  &)",  \v( 
find  that  each  of  our  other  terms  is  of  the  form 


Up.Uq 

10 
where  p  +  q  =  n;    and  that  we  shall  get  them  all  by| 

giving  to  q  successively  the  values  1,  2,  3,  &c.,  and  to] 
p  the  values  got  by  subtracting  these  from  n.  For 
example,  we  shall  find  that 


The  calculation  of  the  numbers  may  be  considerably 
shortened.  Thus  we  have  to  divide  1.2.3.4.5.6  by 
1.2.3.4;  the  result  is  of  course  5  . 6.  This  has  to 
be  further  divided  by  2,  so  that  we  finally  get  5  .  3  or 
15.  Similarly,  to  calculate 

IT6 
113.  Q3' 

we  have  only  to  divide  4.5.6  by  1  .  2  .  3  or  6,  and  we 
get  simply  4  .  5  or  20. 

To  write  down  our  expression  for  (a  +  b)n  we  re 
quire  another  piece  of  shorthand.  We  have  seen  that 
it  consists  of  a  number  of  terms  which  are  all  of  the 
form 

Tin      aP,q 

Hp.Uq  a 

but  which  differ  from  one  another  in  having  for  p  and 
q  different  pairs  of  numbers  whose  sum  is  n.     Now  just 


NUMBER.  31 

as  we  used  the  Greek  letter  II  for  a  product  so  we  use 
the  Greek  letter  S  (Sigma)  for  a  sum.  Namely,  the 
sum  of  all  such  terms  will  be  written  down  thus  : — 

^        J.-LTZ          pi  q 

n  „     TT  ,          '  \-f  -I  -I  * 


Now  we  may  very  reasonably  include  the  two 
extreme  terms  a"  and  bn  in  the  general  shape  of  these 
terms.  For  suppose  we  made  p  =  n  and  q  =  0,  the 
corresponding  term  would  be  : — 

Tin 


lln  .  Ho 

and  this  will  be  simply  a  if  110  =  1  and  6°  =  1.  Of 
course  there  is  no  sense  in  '  the  product  of  the  first  no 
numbers  '  ;  but  if  we  consider  the  rule 

n  (n  +  1)  =  (n  +  1)  Tin, 

which  holds  good  when  n  is  any  number,  to  be  also 
true  when  n  stands  for  nothing,  arid  consequently 
n  +  1  =  1,  it  then  becomes 

ni  =  no, 

and  we  have  already  seen  reason  to  make  111  mean  1. 
Next  if  we  say  that  V1  means  the  result  of  multiplying 
1  by  b  q  times,  then  6°  must  mean  the  result  of  multi 
plying  1  by  b  no  times,  that  is,  of  not  multiplying  it  at 
all  ;  and  this  result  is  1. 

Making    the-n    these    conventional    interpretations, 
we  may  say  that 


it  being  understood  that  p  is  to  take  all  values  from  n 
down  to  0,  and  q  all  values  from  0  up  to  n. 

This  result  is  called  the  Binomial  Theorem,  and  was 
originally  given  by  Sir  Isaac  Newton.     An  expression 


32      THE    COMMON   SEXSE   OF   THE    EXACT   SCIEXCES. 

containing  two  terms,  like  a  +  6,  is  sometimes  callec 
binomial;  and  the  name  Binomial  Theorem  is  an  abbre-fci 
viation  for  theorem  concerning   any  power  of  a  binomial} 
expression. 

.  I 

§  10.  On  Operations  winch  appear  to  "be  without  Meaning. 

We  have  so  far  considered  the  operations  by  which,! 
when  two  numbers  are  given,  two  others  can  be  deter- j 
mined  from  them. 

First,  we  can  add  the  two  numbers  together  and  get ' 
their  sum. 

Secondly,  we  can  multiply  the  two  numbers  together 
and  get  their  product. 

To  the  questions  what  is  the  sum  of  these  two 
numbers,  and  what  is  the  product  of  these  two  numbers, 
there  is  always  an  answer.  But  we  shall  now  consider 
questions  to  which  there  is  not  always  an  answer. 

Suppose  that  I  ask  what  number  added  to  3  will 

prodiice  7.     I  know,  of  course,  that  the  answer  to  this 

is  4,  and  Lhe  operation  of  getting  4  is  called  subtracting 

3  from  7,  and  we  denote  it  by  a  sign  and  write  it 

7-3;=  4. 

But  if  I  ask,  what  number  added  to  7  will  make  3, 
although  this  question  seems  good  English  when  ex 
pressed  in  words,  yet  there  is  no  answer  to  it ;  and  if  I 
write  down  in  symbols  the  expression  3  —  7,1  am  asking 
a  question  to  which  there  is  no  answer. 

There  is  then  an  essential  difference  between  adding 
and  subtracting,  for  two  numbers  always  have  a  sum. 

If  I  write  down  the  expression  3  +  4,  I  can  use  it 
as  meaning  something,  because  I  know  that  there  is 
a  number  which  is  denoted  by  that  expression.  But  if 
I  write  down  the  expression  3  —  7,  and  then  speak  of  it 


NUMBER.  33 

as  meaning  something,  I  shall  be  talking  nonsense, 
because  I  shall  have  put  together  symbols  the  realities 
corresponding  to  which  will  not  go  together.  To  the 
question,  what  is  the  result  when  one  number  is  taken 
From  another,  there  is  only  an  answer  in  the  case 
where  the  second  number  is  greater  than  the  first. 

In  the  same  way,  when  I  multiply  together  two 
numbers  I  know  that  there  is  always  a  product,  and 
am  therefore  free  to  use  such  a  symbol  as  4  x  -5, 
Because  I  know  that  there  is  some  number  that  is 
denoted  by  it.  Cut  I  may  now  ask  a  question ;  I 
may  say,  What  number  is  it  which,  being  multiplied 
Dy  4,  produces  20  ?  The  answer  I  know  in  this  case 
.s  5,  and  the  operation  by  which  I  get  it  is  called 
dividing  20  by  4.  This  is  denoted  again  by  a  symbol, 
20-T-4  =  5. 

But  suppose  I  say  divide  21  by  4.  To  this  there  is 
no  answer.  There  is  110  number  in  the  sense  in  which 
we  are  at  present  using  the  word — that  is  to  say,  there 
s  no  whole  number — which  being  multiplied  by  4  will 
produce  21  :  and  if  I  take  the  expression  21-^4,  and 
speak  of  it  as  meaning  something,  I  shall  be  talking 
nonsense,  because  I  shall  have  put  together  symbols 
whose  realities  will  not  go  together. 

The  things  that  we  have  observed  here  will  occur 
again  and  again  in  mathematics  :  for  every  operation 
that  we  can  invent  amounts  to  asking  a  question, 
and  this  question  may  or  may  not  have  an  answer 
according  to  circumstances. 

If  we  write  down  the  symbols  for  the  answer  to  the 
question  in  any  of  those  cases  where  there  is  no  answer 
and  then  speak  of  them  as  if  they  meant  something,  we 
shall  talk  nonsense.  But  this  nonsense  is  not  to  be 
thrown  away  as  useless  rubbish.  We  have  learned  by 


34      THE   COMMON   SENSE    OF    THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 
very  long  and  varied  experience  that  nothing  is  mc 
valuable  than  the  nonsense  which  we  get  in  this  way 
only  i    is  to  be  recognised  as  nonsense,  and  by  mean 
of  that  recognition  made  into  sense. 

We  turn  the  nonsense  into  sense  by  givino-  a  nev 
meaning  to  the  words  or  symbols  which  shall  enable  th, 
ion  to  have   an  answer  that  previously  had    nc 
answer. 

Let  us  now  consider  in  particular  what  meaninc,  we 

can  glve  to  our  symbols  so  as  to  make  sense  out  of°the 

.t  present  nonsensical  expression,  3-7. 

§  11.  Steps. 

The  operation  of  adding  3  to  5    is  written  5  +  3 
and  the  result  is  8.     We  may  here  regard  the  +3  as 
L  way  of  stepping  from  5  to  8,  and  the  symbol   +3 
may  be  read  in  words,  step  forward  three. 

In  the  same  way,  if  we  subtract  3  from  5  and  get  2 
'  write  the  process  symbolically    5-3  =  2,    and   the 
-3  may  be  regarded  as  a  step  from  5  to  2 
the  former  step  was  forward  this  is  backward,  and 
wemay  accordingly  read   -  3  in  words,  step 


A   step   is   always   supposed  to   be    taken   from  - 
number  which  is  large  enough  to  make  sense  of  the 
'It.     This  restriction  does  not  affect  steps  forward, 
because  from  any  number  we  can  step  forward  as  far  a 
we  like  ;  but  backward  a  step  can  only  be  taken  from 
umbers  which  are  larger  than  the  step  itself 

The  next  thing  we  have  to  observe  about  steps  is 

hat  when  two  steps  are  taken  in  succession  from  any 

number,  it  does  not  matter  which  of  them  comes  first 

the  two  steps  are  taken  in  the  same  direction  this  is 

!ear  enough.      +3  +  4,  meaning   step   forward  3  and 


NUMBER.  35 

then  step  forward  4,  directs  us  to  step  forward  by 
the  number  which  is  the  sum  of  the  numbers  in  the 
two  steps;  and  in  the  same  way  —3  —  4  directs  us  to 
step  backward  the  sum  of  3  and  4,  that  is  7. 

If  the  steps  are  in  opposite  directions,  as,  for 
xample,  +3  —  7,  we  have  to  step  forward  3  and 
then  backward  7,  and  the  result  is  that  we  must  step 
backwards  4.  But  the  same  result  would  have  been 
attained  if  we  first  stepped  backward  7  and  then 
forward  3.  The  result,  in  fact,  is  always  a  step  which 
is  in  the  direction  of  the  greater  of  the  twTo  steps,  and 
is  in  magnitude  equal  to  their  difference. 

"We  thus  see  that  when  two  steps  are  taken  in  suc 
cession  they  are  equivalent  to  one  step,  which  is  inde 
pendent  of  the  order  in  which  they  are  taken. 

We  have  now  supplied  a  new  meaning  for  our 
symbols,  which  makes  sense  and  not  nonsense  out  of 
;he  symbol  3  —  7.  The  3  must  be  taken  to  mean  +3, 
;hat  is,  step  forward  3  ;  the  —  7  must  be  taken  to  mean 
step  backward  7,  and  the  whole  expression  no  longer 
means  take  7  from  3,  but  add  3  to  and  then  subtract 
7  from  any  number  which  is  large  enough  to  make 
sense  of  the  result.  And  accordingly  we  find  that  the 
result  of  this  operation  is  —4,  or,  as  we  may  write  it. 
3-7  =  -4. 

From  this  it  follows  by  a  mode  of  pi'Oof  precisely 
nnulogousto  that  which  we  used  in  the  case  of  multi- 
)lication,  that  any  number  of  steps  taken  in  succession 
lave  a  resultant  which  is  independent  of  the  order  in 
which  they  are  taken,  and  we  may  regard  this  rule  .is 
an  extension  of  the  rule  already  proved  for  the  addition 
of  numbers. 

A  step  may  be  multiplied  or  taken  a  given  number 
of  times,   for    example,  2(  —  3)  =—  tJ ;    that  is    to   say, 


36      THE   COMMON    SENSE    OF    THE    EXACT    SCIENCES. 

if  two  backward  steps  of  3  be  possible,  they  are  equiva 
lent  to  a  step  backwards  of  (5. 

In  this  operation  of  multiplying  a  step  it  is  cleai 
that  what  we  do  is  to  multiply  the  number  which  is 
stepped,  and  to  retain  the  character  of  the  step.  On 
multiplying  a  step  forwards  we  still  have  a  step  for 
wards,  and  on  multiplying  a  step  backwards  we  still 
have  a  step  backwards. 

This  multiplying  may  be  regarded  as  an  operation 
by  which  we  change  one  step  into  another.     Thus  in 
the  example  we  have  just  considered  the  multiplier  2 
changes  the  step  backwards  3  into  the  step  backwards 
6.     But  this  operation,  as  we  have  observed,  will  onl; 
change  a  step  into  another  of  the  same  kind,  and  th( 
question  naturally  presents  itself,  Is  it  possible  to  fin< 
an  operation  which  shall  change  a  step  into  one  of 
different  kind  ?     Such  an  operation  we  should  naturally 
call  reversal.     We  should  say  that  a  step  forwards 
reversed,  when  it  is  made  into  a  step  backwards ;  and  a 
step  backwards  is  reversed  when  it  is  made  into  a  stej 
forwards. 

If  we  denote  the  operation  of  reversal  by  the  letter 
r,  we  can,  by  combining  this  with  a  multiplication 
change  —3  into  +6,  a  step  backwards  3  into  a  ste] 
forwards  6 ;  viz.  we  should  have  the  expression 
r2 ( —  3 )  =  +6.  Now  the  operation,  which  is  performed  on 
one  step  to  change  it  into  another,  may  be  of  two  kinds  : 
either  it  keeps  a  step  in  the  direction  which  it  originally 
had,  or  it  reverses  it.  If  to  make  things  symmetrical 
we  insert  the  letter  k  when  a  step  is  kept  in  its 
original  direction,  we  may  write  the  equation  &2(  —  3) 
=  —  6  to  express  the  operation  of  simply  multiplying. 

Of  course  it  is  possible  to  perform  on  any  given 
gtep  a  succession  of  these  operations.     If  I  take  the 


NUMBER.  37 

tep  +  4,  treble  it,  and  reverse  it,  I  get  —12.  If  I 
Louble  this  and  keep  it,  I  get  —  24,  and  this  may 
>e  written,  &2(r3)(  +  4)  =  —24.  But  this  is  equal 
o  rG(  +  4),  which  tells  us  that  the  two  successive  opera- 
ions  which  we  have  performed  on  this  step,  trebling 
ind  reversing  it,  doubling  and  keeping  it,  are  equiva- 
ent  to  the  single  operation  of  multiplying  by  0  and 
e versing  it.  It  is  clear  also  that  whatever  step  we  had 
aken  the  two  first  operations  performed  successively 
ire  always  equivalent  to  the  third,  and  we  may  thus 
write  the  equation  7r2(r3)  =  rG. 

Suppose  however  we  take   another  step  and  treble 
t  and  reverse  it,   and  then   double  it  and  reverse  it 
.gain  ;  we  should  have  the  result  of  multiplying  it  by 
ix  and  keeping  its  direction  unchanged. 
This  may  be  written  r2(r3)  =  k  .  G. 
If  we  compare  the  last   two   formula}  with   those 
•which  we  previously  obtained,   viz.  /i2(  —  3)  =  —  G  and 
r2(  — 3)  =  +6,  we  shall  see  that  the  two  sets  are  alike, 
except  that  in  the  one  last  obtained  k  and  r  are  written 
instead  of  -I-  and  —  respectively. 

The  two  sets  however  express  entirely  different 
things.  Thus,  taking  the  second  formula?  of  either  set 
on  the  one  hand,  the  statement  is,  Double  and  reverse 
the  step  backward  3,  and  you  have  a  step  forward  G  ; 
on  the  other  hand,  Treble  and  reverse  and  then  double 
and  reverse  any  step  whatever,  and  you  have  the  effect 
of  sextupling  and  keeping  the  step.  We  shall  find  that 
this  analogy  holds  good  in  general,  that  is,  if  we  write 
down  the  effect  of  any  number  of  successive  operations 
performed  upon  a  step,  there  will  always  be  a  correspond 
ing  statement  in  which  this  stepping  is  replaced  by  ;m 
operation  ;  or  we  may  say,  any  operation  which  convert  s 
one  step  into  another  will  also  convert  one  operation  into 


38      THE   COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

another  where  the  converted  operation  is  a  multiplying 
by  the  number  expressing  the  step  and  a  keeping  01 
reversing  according  as  th*e  step  is  forward  or  backward 


§  12.  Extension  of  the  Meaning  of  Symbols. 

We  now  proceed  to  do  something  which  must  appa 
rently  introduce  the  greatest  confusion,  but  which,  on 
the  other  hand,  increases  enormously  our  powers. 

Having  two  things  which  we  have  so  far  quite 
rightly  denoted  by  different  symbols,  and  finding  that 
we  arrive  at  results  which  are  uniform  and  precisely 
similar  to  one  another  except  that  in  one  of  them  one 
set  of  symbols  is  used,  in  the  other  another  set,  we  alter 
the  meaning  of  our  symbols  so  as  to  see  only  one  set 
instead  of  two.  We  make  the  symbols  +  and  —  mean 
for  the  future  what  we  have  here  meant  by  k  and  r, 
viz.  keep  and  reverse.  We  give  them  these  meanings 
in  addition  to  their  former  meanings,  and  leave  it  to  the 
context  to  show  which  is  the  right  meaning  in  any 
particular  case.  Thus,  in  the  equation  (  —  2)  (  — .3)  =  +  6 
there  are  two  possible  meanings  ;  the  —3  and  +6,  may 
both  mean  steps,  in  this  case  the  statement  is :  Double 
and  reverse  the  step  backwards  of  3  and  you  get  the 
step  forward  6.  But  the  —3  and  the  +6  may  also 
mean  not  steps  but  operations,  and  in  this  case  the 
meaning  is  triple  and  reverse  and  then  double  and 
reverse  any  step  whatever,  and  you  get  the  same  result 
as  if  you  had  sextupled  and  kept  the  step. 

Let  us  now  see  what  the  reason  is  for  saying  that 
these  two  meanings  can  always  exist  together.  Let  us 
first  of  all  take  the  second  meaning,  and  frame  a  rule 
for  finding  the  result  of  any  number  of  successive 
operations. 


NUMBER.  39 

First,  the  number  which  is  the  multiplier  in  the 
result  must  clearly  be  the  product  of  all  the  numbers 
n  the  successive  operations. 

Next,  every  pair  of  reversals  cancel  one  another,  so 
ihat,  if  there  is  an  even  number  of  them,  the  result 
must  be  an  operation  of  retaining. 

This  then  is  the  rule  :  Multiply  together  the 
numbers  in  the  several  operations,  prefixing-  to  them 

if  there  is  an  even  number  of  minus  or  reversing 
operations,  prefixing  —  if  there  is  an  odd  number. 

In  the  next  place,  suppose  that  many  successive 
operations  are  performed  upon  a  step.  The  number 
n  the  resulting  step  will  clearly  be  the  product  of  all 
-he  numbers  in  the  operations  and  in  the  original  step. 

If  there  is  an  even  number  of  reversing  operations, 
lie  resulting  step  will  be  of  the  same  kind  as  the 
original  one ;  if  an  odd  number,  of  the  opposite 
find.  Now  let  us  suppose  that  the  original  step 
vere  a  step  backwards  ;  then  if  there  is  an  even  number 
of  reversing  operations,  the  resulting  step  will  also  be  a 
step  backwards.  But  in  this  case  the  number  of  (—  ) 
signs,  reckoned  independently  of  their  meaning,  will  be 
odd ;  and  so  the  rule  coincides  with  the  previous  one. 

If  an  odd  number  of  reversing  operations  is  per 
formed  on  a  negative  step,  the  result  is  a  positive  step. 
But  here  the  whole  number  of  (  — )  signs,  irrespective 
of  their  meaning,  is  an  even  number  ;  and  the  result 
again  agrees  with  the  previous  one. 

In  all  cases  therefore  by  using  the  same  symbols 
to  mean  either  a  'forward'  and  a  'backward'  step 
respectively,  or  '  keep  '  and  '  reverse  '  respectively,  we 
shall  be  able  to  give  to  every  expression  two  interpreta 
tions,  and  neither  of  these  will  ever  be  untrue. 

In  the  process  of  examining  this  statement  we  have 


40      THE    COMMON   SEXSE    OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

shown  by  the  way  that  the  result  of  any  number  of 
successive  operations  on  a  step  is  independent  of  the 
order  of  them.  For  it  is  always  a  step  whose  magnitude 
is  the  product  of  the  numbers  in  the  original  step  and 
in  the  operations,  and  whose  character  is  determined 
by  the  number  of  reversals. 


§  13.  Addition  and  Multiplication  of  Operations. 

We  may  now  go  on  to  find  a  rule  which  connects 
together  the  multiplication  and  the  addition  of  steps. 

If  I  multiply  separately  the  steps  +3  and  —7  by  4, 
and  then  take  the  resultant  of  the  two  steps  which  I  so 
obtain,  I  shall  get  the  same  thing  as  if  I  had  first 
formed  the  resultant  of  +3  and  —7,  and  then  multi 
plied  it  by  4.  In  fact,  +12  -  28  '=  --16.  which  is 
4(  —  4) .  This  is  true  in  general,  and  it  obviously 
amounts  to  the  original  rule  that  a  set  of  things  comes 
to  the  same  number  in  whatever  order  we  count  them. 
Only  that  now  some  of  the  counting  has  to  be  done 
backwards  and  some  again  forwards. 

But  now,  besides  adding  together  steps,  we  may 
also  in  a  certain  sense  add  together  operations.  It 
seems  natural  to  assume  at  once  that  by  adding  toge 
ther  -f  3  and  —  7  regarded  as  operations,  we  must  needs 
get  the  operation  —4.  It  is  very  important  not  to 
assume  anything  without  proof,  and  still  more  import 
ant  not  to  use  words  without  attaching  a  definite 
meaning  to  them. 

The  meaning  is  this.  If  I  take  any  step  whatever, 
treble  it  without  altering  its  character,  and  combine 
the  result  with  the  result  of  multiplying  the  original 
step  by  7  and  reversing  it,  then  I  shall  get  the  same 
result  as  if  I  had  multiplied  the  original  step  by  4  and 


NUMBER.  4 1 

eversed  it.  This  is  perfectly  true,  and  we  may  see  it 
o  be  true  by,  as  it  were,  performing  our  operations  in 
he  form  of  steps.  Suppose  I  take  the  step  +  5,  and 
rant  to  treble  it  and  keep  its  chai-acter  unchanged.  I 
;an  do  this  by  taking  three  steps  of  five  numbers  each  in 
he  same  direction  (viz.  the  forward  direction)  as  the 
)riginal  step  was  to  be  taken.  Similarly,  if  I  want  to 
nultiply  it  by  —  7,  this  means  that  I  must  take  7  steps 
>f  five  numbers  each  in  the  opposite  or  backward  direc- 
ion.  Then  finally,  what  I  have  to  do  is  to  take  three 
teps  forwards  and  seven  steps  backwards,  each  of  these 
teps  consisting  of  five  numbers  ;  and  it  appears  at  once 
hat  the  result  is  the  same  as  that  of  taking  4  steps 
>ackwards  of  five  numbers  each. 

We  have  thus  a  definition  of  the  sum  of  two 
Derations  ;  and  it  appears  from  the  way  in  which  we 
lave  arrived  at  it  that  this  sum  is  independent  of  the 
order  of  the  operations. 

We  may  therefore  now  write  the  formuke : — 

a  +  b  =  b     +  a 

a  (b  +  c)  =  ab  +  ac 

(a  +  l)c  —  ac   +  be 

ab  =  ba, 

and  consider  the  letters  to  signify  operations  performed 
upon  steps.  In  virtue  of  the  truth  of  these  laws  the  whole 
of  that  reasoning  which  we  applied  to  finding  a  power 
of  the  sum  of  two  numbers  is  applicable  to  the  finding 
of  a  power  of  the  sum  of  two  operations.  If  it  did  not 
take  too  much  time  and  space,  we  might  go  through  it 
again,  giving  to  all  the  symbols  their  new  meanings. 

It  is  worth  while,  perhaps,  by  way  of  example,  to 
explain  clearly  what  is  meant  by  the  square  of  the  sum 
of  two  operations. 


42      THE    COMMON    SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT    SCIENCES. 

We  will  take  for  example,  +5  and  —3. 

The  formula  tells  us  that  (  +  5  —  3)2  is  equal  to 
(  +  5)2  +  (_3)2  +  2(  +  5)(-3).  This  means  that  if  AVC 
apply  to  any  step  twice  over  the  sum  of  the  operations 
-f  5  and  —  3,  that  is  to  say,  if  we  multiply  it  by  5  anci 
keep  its  direction,  and  combine  with  this  step  the  resull 
of  multiplying  the  original  step  by  3  and  reversing  it 
and  then  apply  the  same  process  to  the  result  so  obtained 
we  shall  get  a  step  which  might  also  have  been  arrived 
at  by  combining  together  the  following  three  steps  : — 

First,  the  original  step  twice  multiplied  by  5. 

Secondly,  the  original  step  twice  multiplied  by  £ 
and  twice  reversed ;  that  is  to  say,  unaltered  in 
direction. 

Thirdly,  twice  the  result  of  tripling  the  original  step 
and  reversing  it,  and  then  multiplying  by  5  and  retain 
ing  the  direction. 

§  14.  Division  of  Operations. 

We  have  now  seen  what  is  meant  by  the  multipli 
cation  of  operations ;  let  us  go  on  to  consider  whal 
sort  of  question  is  asked  by  division. 

Let.  us  take  for  example  the  symbolic  statemenl 
—  3(  +  5)  =  — 15  ;  and  let  us  give  it  in  the  first  place 
the  meaning  that  to  triple  and  reverse  the  step  forwarc 
5  gives  the  step  backward  15.  We  may  ask  two 
questions  upon  this  statement.  First,  What  operation 
is  it  which,  being  performed  on  the  step  forwards  5,  wil 
give  the  step  backwards  15?  The  answer,  of  course, 
is  triple  and  reverse.  Or  we  may  ask  this  question 
What  step  is  that,  which,  being  tripled  and  reversed, 
will  give  the  step  backward  15?  The  answer  is,  Step 
forwards  5.  But  we  have  only  one  word  to  describe 
the  process  by  which  we  get  the  answer  in  these  two 


NUMBER.  43 

jases.  In  the  first  case  we  say  that  we  divide  the  step 
— 15  by  the  step  +5;  in  the  second  case  we  say  we 
livide  the  step  —15  by  the  operation  —3. 

The  word  divide  thus  gets  two  distinct  meanings. 
But  it  is  very  important  to  notice  that  symbolically  the 
inswer  is  the  same  in  the  two  cases,  although  the 
interpretation  to  be  given  to  it  is  different. 

The  step  —15  may  be  got  in  two  ways ;  by  tripling 
and  reversing  the  forward  step  +  5,  or  by  quintupling 
the  backward  step  —3.  In  symbols, 

(-3)  (  +  5)  =  (+5)  (-3)  =  -15. 

Hence    the   problem,   Divide  —  15   by    —3    may  moan 

ither  of  these-  two  questions  :  What  step  is  that  which, 

jeing  tripled  and  reversed,  gives  the  step  —15?     Or, 

"What  operation  is  that  which,  performed   on   the  step 

—  3,  gives    the  step   —15?     The   answer  to   the  first 
question  is,  the  step  -f  5  ;  the  answer  to  the  second  is 
jhe  operation  of  quintupling   and  retaining  direction, 
that  is,  the  operation  +5.     So  that  although  the  word 
divide,  as  we  have  said,  gets  two  distinct  meanings,  yet 
the  two  different  results  of  division  are  expressed  by 
the  same  symbol. 

In  general  we  may  say  that  the  problem,  Divide 
the  step  a  by  the  step  b,  means,  Find  the  operation  (if 
any)  which  will  convert  b  into  a.  But  the  problem, 
Divide  the  step  a  by  the  operation  b,  means,  Find  the 
step  (if  any)  which  b  will  convert  into  «.  In  both  cases, 
however,  the  process  and  the  symbolic  result  are  the 
same.  We  must  divide  the  number  of  a  by  the  number 
of  b,  and  prefix  to  it  +  if  the  signs  of  a  and  b  are  alike, 

—  if  they  are  different. 

We  may  also  give  to  our  original  equation 
(-3)   x   (  +  5)  =  -15 


44      THE    COMMON    SEXSE    OF  THE  EXACT  SCIENCES. 

its  other  meaning,  in  which  both  —3  and  +5  are  ope 
rations,  and  —  15  is  the  operation  which  is  equivalent 
to  performing  one  of  them  after  the  other.  In  this  case 
the  problem,  Divide  the  operation  —15  by  the  operation 

—  3  means,  Find  the  operation  which,  being  succeeded 
by  the  operation  —  3,  will  be  equivalent  to  the  operation 

—  15.      Or  generally,  Divide  the  operation  a  by  the 
operation  &,  means,  Find  the  operation  which,  being 
succeeded  by  6,  will  be  equivalent  to  a. 

Now  it  is  worth  noticing  that  the  division  of  step 
by  step  and  the  division  of  operation  by  operation,  have 
a  certain  likeness  between  them,  and  a  common  differ 
ence  from  the  division  of  step  by  operation.  Namely, 
the  result  of  dividing  a  by  b,  or,  as  we  may  write  it, 

-,  when  a  and  6  are  both  steps  or  both  operations,  is 

an  operation  which  converts  6  into  a.  This  we  may 
write  in  shorthand, 

a     7 

-  .  i  =  «. 

But  when  a  is  a  step  and  6  an  operation,  the  result  of 
division  is  a  step  on  which  the  operation  6  must  be 
performed  to  convert  it  into  a  ;  or,  in  shorthand, 

7     a 

b  .  —  =  a. 
o 

The  fact  that  the  symbolic  result  is  the  same  in  the 
two  cases  may  be  stated  thus  :  — 


and  in  this  form  we  see  that  it  is  a  case  of  the  commu 
tative  law.  So  long,  then,  as  the  commutative  law  is 
true,  there  is  no  occasion  for  distinguishing  symboli 
cally  between  the  two  meanings.  But,  as  we  shall  see 


NUMBER.  45 

oy-and-by,  there  is  occasion  to  deal  with  other  kinds 
of  steps  and  operations  in  which  the  commutative  law 
•loes  not  hold ;  and  for  these  a  convenient  notation  has 

>een  suggested  by  Professor  Cayley.    Namely,  —  means 

:he  operation  wrhich  makes    b   into   a  •    but    -  -  repre- 

°\ 
sents  that  which  the  operation  b  will  convert  into  a.     So 

fchat- 

J  .  b  =  a,  but  b  .  —-  =  a. 
I  b  }> 

[t  is  however  convenient  to  settle  beforehand  that  when 
ever  the  symbol  -  is  used  without  warning  it  is  to  have 
b 

the  first  meaning— namely,  the  operation  -which  makes 
!>  into  a, 

§  15.  General  Results  of  our  Extension  of  Terms. 

It  will  be  noticed  that  we  have  hereby  passed  from 
the  consideration  of  mere  numbers,  with  which  we 
gan,  to  the  consideration  first  of  steps  of  addition  or 
subtraction  of  number  from  number,  and  then  of 
operations  of  multiplying  and  keeping  or  multiplying 
and  reversing,  performed  011  these  steps  ;  and  that  we 
have  greatly  widened  the  meaning  of  all  the  words  that 
we  have  employed. 

To  addition,  which  originally  meant  the  addition  of 
two  numbers,  has  been  given  the  meaning  of  a  combina 
tion  of  steps  to  form  a  resultant  step  equivalent  in  effect 
to  taking  them  in  succession. 

To  nntltijilii-iifinii,  which  was  originally  applied  to 
two  numbers  only,  has  been  given  the  meaning  of  a 
combination  of  operations  upon  steps  to  form  a  resultant 
operation  equivalent  to  their  successive  performance. 


46       THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

We  have  found  that  the  same  properties  \vhicl 
characterise  the  addition  and  multiplication  of  numbers 
belong  also  to  the  addition  and  multiplication  of  steps 
and  of  operations.  And  it  was  this  very  fact  of  the 
similarity  of  properties  which  led  us  to  use  our  ol( 
words  in  a  new  sense.  We  shall  find  that  this  same 
process  is  carried  on  in  the  consideration  of  those 
other  subjects  which  lie  before  us  ;  but  that  the  precise 
similarity  which  we  have  here  observed  in  the  pro 
perties  of  more  simple  and  more  complex  operations 
will  not  in  every  case  hold  good ;  so  that  while  this 
gradual  extension  of  the  meaning  of  terms  is  perhaps 
the  most  powerful  instrument  of  research  which  has 
yet  been  used,  it  is  always  to  be  employed  with  a  cau 
tion  proportionate  to  its  importancet 


47 


CHAPTER   II. 

SPACE. 

§  1.  Boundaries  take  up  no  Room. 

GEOMETRY  is  a  physical  science.  It  deals  with  the 
sizes  and  shapes  and  distances  of  things.  Just  as  we 
have  studied  the  number  of  things  by  making  a  simple 
and  obvious  observation,  and  then  using  this  over  and 
over  again  to  see  where  it  would  bring  us  ;  so  we  shall 
study  the  science  of  the  shapes  and  distances  of  things 
by  making  one  or  two  very  simple  and  obvious  obser 
vations,  and  then  using  these  over  and  over  again,  to 
see  what  we  can  get  out  of  them. 

The  observations  that  we  make  are  : — 

First,  that  a  thing  may  be  moved  about  from  one 
place  to  another  without  altering  its  size  or  shape. 

Secondly,  that  it  is  possible  to  have  things  of  the 
same  shape  but  of  different  sizes. 

Before  we  can  use  these  observations  to  draw  any 
exact  conclusions  from  them,  it  is  necessary  to  consider 
rather  more  precisely  what  they  mean. 

Things  take  up  room.  A  table,  for  example,  takes 
up  a  certain  part  of  the  room  where  it  is,  and  there  is 
another  part  of  the  room  where  it  is  not.  The  tiling 
makes  a  difference  between  these  two  portions  of  space. 

Between  these  two  there  is  what  we  call  the  surface 
of  the  table. 

We  may  suppose  that  the  space  all  round  the  table 


48       THE    COMMON    SEXSE    OF    THE    EXACT    SCIENCES. 

is  filled  with  air.  The  surface  of  the  table  is  thei 
something  just  between  the  air  and  the  wood,  whicl 
separates  them  from  one  another,  and  which  is  neithei 
the  one  nor  the  other. 

It  is  a  mistake  to  suppose  that  the  surface  of  th( 
table  is  a  very  thin  piece  of  wood  on  the  outside  of  it 
We  can  see  that  this  is  a  mistake,  because  any  reason 
which  led  us  .to  say  so,  would  lead  us  also  to  say  that 
the  surface  was  a  very  thin  layer  of  air  close  to  the 
table.  The  surface  in  fact  is  common  to  the  wood  and 
to  the  air,  and  takes  up  itself  no  room  whatever.1 

Part  of  the  surface  of  the  table  may  be  of  one  colou 
and  part  may  be  of  another. 

On  the  surface  of  this  sheet  of  paper  there  is  drawn 
a  round  black  spot.     We  call  the  black  part  a  circle 

FIG.  1. 

^Jt  divides  the  surface  into  two  parts,  one  where  it  is  an< 
one  where  it  is  not. 

This  circle  takes  up  room  on  the  surface,  although 
surface  itself  t&ke|*wp  no  room  in  space.     We  ar 
5  led  to  considerTwrl^lifferent  kinds  of  room  ;  space 
room,  in  which  solid  bodies  are,  and    in    which    the 
'i  move  about ;  an9.i^Afte-room,  which  may  be  regarde 


•£kth 

££*** 
•T*1'01 


1  It  is  certain  that  however  smooth  a  na.t.i,ral  surface  may  appear  to  be, 
it  could  be  magnified  to  roughness.  Hence,  in  the  case  of  the  surface  of 
the  table  and  the  air,  it  would  seem  probable  that  there  is  a  layer  in  which 
particles  of  wood  and  air  are  mingled.  The  boundary  in  this  case  of  air 
and  table  would  not  be  what  we  '  see  and  feel '  (cf.  p.  48),  nor  would  it 
correspond  to  the  surface  of  the  geometer.  We  are,  I  think,  compelled  to 
consider  the  surface  of  the  geometer  as  an  'idea  or  imaginary  conception,' 
drawn  from  the  apparent  (not  leal)  boundaries  of  physital  objects,  such  as 
the  writer  is  describing.  Strongly  as  I  feel  the  ideal  nature  of  geometrical 
conceptions  in  the  exact  sciences,  I  have  thought  it  unadvisable  to  alter 
the  text.  The  distinction  is  made  by  Clifford  himself  (Essays,  I.  pp.  306- 
321).-  K.P. 


SPACE.  49 

rom  two  different  points  of  view.  From  one  point  of 
iew  it  is  the  boundary  between  two  adjacent  portions 
f  space,  and  takes  up  no  space-room  whatever.  From 
lie  other  point  of  view  it  is  itself  also  a  kind  of  room 
ehieh  may  be  taken  up  by  parts  of  it. 

These  parts  in  turn  have  their  boundaries. 

Between  the  black  surface  of  the  circle  and  the 
srhite  surface  of  the  paper  round  it  there  is  a  line,  the 
ircmnference  of  the  circle.  This  line  is  neither  part  of 
he  black  nor  part  of  the  white,  but  is  between  the  two. 
t  divides  one  from  the  other,  and  takes  up  no  surface- 
oom  at  all.  The  line  is  not  a  very  thin  strip  of  surface, 
ny  more  than  the  surface  is  a  very  thin  layer  of  solid. 

Anything  which  led  us  to  say  that  this  line,  the 
oundary  of  the  black  spot,  was  a  thin  strip  of  black, 
vould  also  lead  us  to  say  that  it  was  a  thin  strip  of  white. 

We  may  also  divide  a  line  into  two  parts.  If  the 
aper  with  this  black  circle  upon  it  were  dipped  into 


ater  so  that  part  of  the  black  circle  were  sub 
merged,  then  the  line  surrounding  it  would  be  partly  in 
;he  water  and  partly  out. 

The  submerged  part  of  the  line  takes  up  room  on  it. 
[t  goes  a  certain  part  of  the  way  round  the  circum 
ference.  Thus  we  have  to  consider  line-room  as  well  as 
space-room  and  surface-room.  The  line  takes  up 
absolutely  no  room  on  the  surface;  it  is  merely  the 
boundary  between  two  adjacent  portions  of  it.  Still 
less  does  it  take  up  any  room  in  space.  And  yet  it  has 
a  certain  room  of  its  own,  which  may  be  divided 
into  parts,  and  taken  up  or  tilled  by  those  parts. 

E 


50      THE    COMMON    SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT    SCIENCES. 

These  parts  again  have  boundaries.  Between 
submerged  portion  of  the  circumference  and  the  othei 
part  there  are  two  points,  one  at  each  end.  These 
points  are  neither  in  the  water  nor  out  of  it.  They  are 
in  the  surface  of  the  water,  just  as  they  are  in  the  sur 
face  of  the  paper,  and  on  the  boundary  of  the  black  spot. 
Upon  this  line  they  take  up  absolutely  no  room  at  all. 

A  point  is  not  a  very  small  length  of  the  line,  any 
more  than  the  line  is  a  very  thin  strip  of  surface.  It  is 
a  division  between  two  parts  of  the  line  which  are  next 
one  another,  and  it  takes  up  no  room  on  the  line  at  all. 

The  important  thing  to  notice  is  that  we  are  no1 
here  talking  of  ideas  or  imaginary  conceptions,  but 
only  making  common-sense  observations  about  matters 
of  every-day  experience. 

The  surface  of  a  thing  is  something  that  we  con 
stantly  observe.  We  can  see  it  and  feel  it,  and  it  is  a  mere 
common-sense  observation  to  say  that  this  surface  is  com 
mon  to  the  thing  itself  and  to  the  space  surrounding  it. 

A  line  on  a  surface  which  separates  one  part  of  the 
surface  from  another  is  also  a  matter  of  every-day 
experience.  It  is  not  an  idea  got  at  by  supposing  a 
string  to  become  indefinitely  thin,  but  it  is  a  thing 
given  directly  by  observation  as  belonging  to  both  por 
tions  of  the  surface  which  it  divides,  and  as  being  there 
fore  of  absolutely  no  thickness  at  all.  The  same  may  be 
said  of  a  point.  The  point  which  divides  the  part  of 
our  circumference  which  is  in  water  from  the  part  which 
is  out  of  water  is  an  observed  thing.  It  is  not  an  idea 
got  at  by  supposing  a  small  particle  to  become  smaller 
and  smaller  without  any  limit,  but  it  is  the  boundary 
between  two  adjacent  parts  of  a  line,  which  is  the 
boundary  between  two  adjacent  portions  of  a  surface, 
which  is  the  boundary  between  two  adjacent  portions  of 


SPACE.  51 

pace.  A  point  is  a  thing  which  we  can  see  and  know, 
tot  an  abstraction  which  we  build  up  in  our  thoughts. 
When  we  talk  of  drawing  lines  or  points  on  a  sheet 
•f  paper,  we  use  the  language  of  the  draughtsman  and 
lot  of  the  geometer.  Here  is  a  picture  of  a  cube 
•epresented  by  lines,  in  the  draughtsman's  sense. 
Sach  of  these  so-called  '  lines '  is  a  black  streak  of 
winter's  ink,  of  varying  breadth,  taking  up  a  certain 


FIG.  3. 

imount  of  room  on  the  paper.  By  drawing  such  '  lines ' 
lufficiently  close  together,  we  might  entirely  cover  up 
is  large  a  patch  of  paper  as  we  liked.  Each  of  these 
itreaks  has  a  line  on  each  side  of  it,  separating  the 
)lack  surface  from  the  white  surface ;  these  are  true 
geometrical  lines,  taking  up  no  surface-room  whatever. 
Millions  of  millions  of  them  might  be  marked  out 
Between  the  two  boundaries  of  one  of  our  streaks,  and 
Between  every  two  of  these  there  would  be  room  for 
millions  more. 

Still,  it  is  very  convenient,  in  drawing  geometrical 
igures,  to  represent  lines  by  black  streaks.  To  avoid 
ill  possible  misunderstanding  in  this  matter,  we  shall 
make  a  convention  once  for  all  about  the  sense  in 
which  a  black  streak  is  to  represent  a  line.  When  the 
streak  is  vertical,  or  comes  straight  down  the  page,  like 
this  |  ,  the  line  represented  by  it  is  its  riyld-liand  boun 
dary.  In  all  other  cases  the  line  shall  be  the  upptr 
boundary  of  the  streak. 

So  also  in  the  case  of  a  point.  When  we  try  to 
represent  a  point  by  a  dot  on  a  sheet  of  paper,  we 

E    2 


52       THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF    THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

make  a  black  patch  of  irregular  shape.  The  boundary 
of  this  black  patch  is  a  line.  When  one  point  of  this  if" 
boundary  is  higher  than  all  the  other  points,  thai 
highest  point  shall  be  the  one  represented  by  the  dot. 
When  however  several  points  of  the  boundary  are  ai 
the  same  height,  but  none  higher  than  these,  so  thai 
the  boundary  has  a  flat  piece  at  the  top  of  it,  then  the 
right-hand  extremity  of  this  flat  piece  shall  be  thej 
point  represented  by  the  dot. 

This  determination  of  the  meaning  of  our  figures 
is  of  no  practical  use.  We  "lay  it  down  only  that  the 
reader  may  not  fall  into  the  error  of  taking  patches 
and  streaks  for  geometrical  points  and 


§  2.  Lengths  can  be  Moved  without  Change. 

Let  us  now  consider  what  is  meant  by  the  first  of 
our  observations  about  space,  viz.,  that  a  thing  can  be 
moved  about  from  one  place  to  another  without  altering 
its  size  or  shape. 

First  as  to  the  matter  of  size.  We  measure  the  size 
of  a  thing  by  measuring  the  distances  of  various  points 
on  it.  For  example,  we  should  measure  the  size  of  a 
table  by  measuring  the  distance  from  end  to  end,  or  the 
distance  across  it,  or  the  distance  from  the  top  to  the 
bottom.  The  measurement  of  distance  is  only  possible 
when  we  have  something,  say  a  yard  measure  or  a  piece 
of  tape,  which  we  can  carry  about  and  which  does  not 
alter  its  length  while  it  is  carried  about.  The  measure 
ment  is  then  effected  by  holding  this  thing  in  the  place 
of  the  distance  to  be  measured,  and  observing  what 
part  of  it  coincides  with  this  distance. 

Two  lengths  or  distances  are  said  to  be  equal  when 
the  same  part  of  the  measure  will  fit  both  of  them. 


SPACE.  53 

Tims  we  should  say  that  two  tables  are  equally  broad, 
.f  we  marked  the  breadth  of  one  of  them  on  a  piece  of 
rape,  and  then  carried  the  tape  over  to  the  other  table 
ind  found  that  its  breadth  came  up  to  just  the  same 
nark.  Now  the  piece  of  tape,  although  convenient,  is 
not  absolutely  necessary  to  the  finding  out  of  this  fact. 
We  might  have  turned  one  table  up  and  put  it  on  top 
of  the  other,  and  so  found  out  that  the  two  breadths 
were  equal.  Or  we  may  say  generally  that  two  lengths 
or  distances  of  any  kind  are  equal,  when,  one  of  them 
>eirig  brought  up  close  to  the  other,  they  can  be  made 
to  fit  without  alteration.  But  the  tape  is  a  thing  far 
more  easily  carried  about  than  the  table,  and  so  in  prac 
tice  we  should  test  the  equality  of  the  two  breadths  by 
measuring  both  against  the  same  piece  of  tape.  We 
ind  that  each  of  them  is  equal  to  the  same  length  of 
;ape  ;  and  we  assume  thatfat'o  lengths  which  are  equal  to 
the  same  length  are  equal  to  each  other.  This  is  equiva- 
ent  to  saying  that  if  our  piece  of  tape  be  carried 
round  any  closed  curve  and  brought  back  to  its  original 
position,  it  will  not  have  altered  in  length. 

How  so  ?  Let  us  assume  that,  when  not  used,  our 
riece  of  tape  is  kept  stretched  out  on  a  board,  with  one 
?nd  against  a  fixed  mark  on  the  board.  Then  we  know 
what  is  meant  by  two  lengths  being  equal  which  are 
Doth  measured  along  the  tape  from  that  end.  Now  take 
;hree  tables,  A,  B,  C,  and  suppose  we  have  measured 
and  found  that  the  breadth  of  A  is  equal  to  that  of  B, 
and  the  breadth  of  B  is  equal  to  that  of  C,  then  we 
say  that  the  breadth  of  A  is  equal  to  that  of  C.  This 
means  that  we.  have  marked  off  the  breadth  of  A  on 
the  tape,  and  then  carried  this  length  of  tape  to  B,  and 
found  it  fit.  Then  we  have  carried  the  same  length 
from  B  to  C,  and  found  it  fit.  In  saying  that  the 


54      THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

breadth  of  C  is  equal  to  that  of  A,  we  assert  that  01 
taking  the  tape  from  C  to  A,  whether  we  go  near  B  orj 
not,  it  will  be  found  to  fit  the  breadth  of  A.     That  is,| 
if  we  take  our  tape  from  A  to  B,  then  from  B  to  C,  andj 
then  back  to  A,  it  will  still  fit  A  if  it  did  so  at  first. 

These  considerations  lead  us  to  a  very  singular  con-j 
elusion.     The  reader  will  probably  have  observed  that 
we  have   defined   length   or   distance   by   means   of  a 
measure  which  can  be  carried  about  without  changing  ] 
its   length.      But   how   then   is   this  property   of    the 
measure  to  be  tested?     We  may  carry  about  a  yard 
measure  in  the  form  of  a  stick,  to  test  our  tape  with; 
but  all  we  can  prove  in  that  way  is  that  the  two  things 
are  always  of  the  same  length  when  they  are  in  the 
same  place ;  not  that  this  length  is  unaltered. 

The  fact  is  that  everything  would  go  on  quite  as 
well  if  we  supposed  that  things  did  change  in  length 
by  mere  travelling  from  place  to  place,  provided  that 
(1)  different  things  changed  equally,  and  (2)  anything 
which  was  carried  about  and  brought  back  to  its  original 
position  filled  the  same  space.1  All  that  is  wanted  is 
that  two  things  which  fit  in  one  place  should  also  fit  in 
another  place,  although  brought  there  by  different 
paths  ;  unless,  of  course,  there  are  other  reasons  to  the 
contrary.  A  piece  of  tape  and  a  stick  which  fit  one 
another  in  London  will  also  fit  one  another  in  New 
York,  although  the  stick  may  go  there  across  the 
Atlantic,  and  the  tape  via  India  and  the  Pacific.  Of 
course  the  stick  may  expand  from  damp  and  the  tape 
may  shrink  from  dry  ness ;  such  non-geometrical  cir 
cumstances  would  have  to  be  allowed  for.  But  so  far 
us  the  geometrical  conditions  alone  are  concerned — the 

1  These  remarks  refer  to  the  geometrical,  and  not  necessarily  to  all  the 
physical  properties  of  bodies. — K.  P 


SPACE. 


55 


•iere  carrying  about  and  change  of  place — two  things 
Haich  fit  in  one  place  will  fit  in  another. 

Upon  this  fact  are  founded,  as  we  have  seen,  the 
Lotion  of  length  as  measured,  and  the  axiom  that 
jngths  which  are  equal  to  the  same  length  are  equal 
one  another. 

Is  it  possible,  however,  that  lengths  do  really 
Change  by  mere  moving  about,  without  our  knowing  it  ? 
Whoever  likes  to  meditate  seriously  upon  this  ques 
tion  will  find  that  it  is  wholly  devoid  of  meaning.  But 
'ihe  time  employed  in  arriving  at  that  conclusion  will 
liot  have  been  altogether  thrown  away. 


§  3.   The  Characteristics  of  Shape. 

We  have  now  seen  what  is  meant  by  saying  that  a 
[thing  can  be  moved  about  without  altering  its  size  ; 

namely,  that  any  length  Avhich  fits  a  certain  measure  in 
lone  position  will  also  fit  that  measure  when  both  have 

been  moved  by  any  paths  to  some  other  position.     Let 
rus  now  inquire  what  we  mean  by  saying  that  a  thing 

can  be  moved  about  without  altering  its  shape. 

First  let  us  observe  that  the  shape  of  a  thing 
(depends  only  on  its  bounding  surface,  and  not  at  all 
iupon  the  inside  of  it.  So  that  we  may  always  speak 
I  of  the  shape  of  the  surface,  and  we  shall  mean  the 

same  thing  as  if  we  spoke  of  the  shape  of  the  thing. 


Fio.  4. 

Let  us  observe  then  some  characteristics  of  the  sur 
face  of  things.    Here  are  a  cube,  a  cylinder,  and  a  sphere. 


56       THE    COMMON   SENSE   OP   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

The  surface  of  the  cube  has  six  flat  sides,  with  edgea 
and  corners.  The  cylinder  has  two  flat  ends  and  a 
round  surface  between  them ;  the  flat  ends  being 
divided  from  the  round  part  by  two  circular  edges. 
The  sphere  has  a  round  smooth  surface  all  over. 

We  observe  at  once  a  great  distinction  in  shape  be 
tween  smooth  parts  of  the  surface,  and  edges,  and  corners. 
An  edge  being  a  line  011  the  surface  is  not  any  part  oi 
it,  in  the  sense  of  taking  up  surface  room ;  still  less  is 
a  corner,  which  is  a  mere  point.  But  still  we  may  divide 
the  points  of  the  surface  into  those  where  it  is  smooth 
(like  all  the  points  of  the  sphere,  the  round  and  flat  parts 
of  the  cylinder,-  and  the  flat  sides  of  the  cube),  into 
points  on  an  edge,  and  into  corners.  For  convenience,  let 
us  speak  of  these  points  respectively  as  smooth-points, 
edge-points,  and  corner-points.  We  may  also  put  the 
edges  and  corners  together,  and  call  them  rough- 
points. 

Now  let  us  take  the  sphere,  and  put  it  upon  a  flat 
face  of  the  cube  (fig.  5).  The  two  bodies  will  be  in  con- 


Fio.  5. 

tact  at  one  point ;  that  is  to  say,  a  certain  point  on  the 
surface  of  the  sphere  and  a  certain  point  on  the  surface 
of  the  cube  are  made  to  coincide  with  one  another  and 
to  be  the  same  point.  And  these  are  ooth  smooth-points. 
Now  we  cannot  move  the  sphere  ever  so  little  without  separ 
ating  thqse  points,  If  we  roll  it  a  very  little  way  on  the 


SPACE.  57 

face  of  the  cube,  we  shall  find  that  a  different  point  of 
the  sphere  is  in  contact  with  a  different  point  of  the  cube. 


And  the  same  thing  is  true  if  we  place  the    sphere  in 
contact  with  a  smooth-point  on  the  cylinder  (fig.  6). 

Next  let  us  put  the  round  part  of  the  cylinder  on 
the  flat  face  of  the  cube.  In  this  case  there  will  be 
:ontact  all  along  a  line.  At  any  point  of  this  line,  a 
certain  point  on  the  surface  of  the  cylinder  and  a 
:ertain  point  on  the  surface  of  the  cube  have  been  made 
to  coincide  with  one  another  and  to  be  the  same  point. 
And  these  are  both  smooth-points.  It  is  just  as  true 
as  before,  that  we  cannot  move  one  of  these  bodies  ever 
so  little  relatively  to  the  other  without  separating  the 


FIG.  7. 

points  of  their  surfaces  which  are  in  contact.  If  we 
roll  the  cylinder  a  very  little  way  on  the  face  of  the 
cube,  we  shall  find  that  a  different  line  of  the  cylinder 
is  in  contact  with  a  different  line  of  the  cube.  All  the 
points  of  contact  are  changed. 

Now  put  the  flat  end  of  the  cylinder  011  the  face  of 
the  cube.  These  two  surfaces  fit  throughout  and  make 
but  one  surface  ;  we  have  contact,  not  (as  before)  at  a 
point  or  along  a  line,  but  over  a  surface.  Let  us  fix 


58      THE    COMMON    SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

our  attention  upon  a  particular  point  on  the  flat  surface 
of  the  cylinder  and  the  point  on  the  face  of  the  cube 
with  which  it  now  coincides ;  these  two  being  smooth- 


points.  We  observe  again,  that  it  is  impossible  to  move 
one  of  these  bodies  ever  so  little  relatively  to  the  other 
without  separating  these  two  points.'1 

Here,  however,  something  has  happened  which  will 
give  us  further  instruction.     We  have  all  along  sup 


posed  the  flat  face  of  the  cylinder  to  be  smaller  than 
the  flat  face  of  the  cube.     When  these  two  are  in  con- 

1  In  all  these  cases  (figs.  5-8)  the  relative  motion  spoken  of  must  be 
either  motion  of  translation  or  of  tilting;  one  body  might  have  a  spin 
about  a  vertical  axis  without  any  separation  of  these  two  points.  The  true 
distinction  between  the  contact  of  smooth-points  and  of  smooth  and  rough- 
points  seems  to  be  this :  in  the  former  case  without  separating  two  points 
'..here  is  only  one  degree  of  freedom— namely,  spin  about  an  axis  normal  to 
the  smooth  surfaces  at  the  points  in  question ;  in  the  latter  c=ise  there  are 
at  least  two  (edge-point  or  smooth-point)  and  may  be  an  infinite  number  of 
degrees  of  freedom — namely,  spins  about  two  or  more  axes  passing  through 
the  rough-point.  The  reader  will  understand  these  terms  better  after  the 
chapter  on  Motion. — K.  P. 


SPACE. 


59 


tact,  let  the  cylinder  stand  on  the  middle  of  the  cube, 
as  in  fig.  8,  the  circle  being  wholly  enclosed  by  the 
square.  Then  when  we  tilt  the  cylinder  over  we  shall 
get  it  into  the  position  of  fig.  9.  We  have  already 
observed  that  in  this  case  no  smooth-points  which  were 
previously  in  contact  remain  in  contact.  But  there  are 
two  points  which  remain  in  contact ;  for  in  the  tilted 
position  a  point  on  the  circular  edge  of  the  cylinder 
rests  on  a  point  on  the  face  of  the  cube ;  and  these  two 
points  were  in  contact  before.  We  may  tilt  the  cylinder 
as  much  or  as  little  as  we  like— provided  we  tilt  always 
in  the  same  direction,  not  rolling-  the  cylinder  on  its 
edge — and  these  two  points  will  remain  in  contact. 
We  learn  therefore  that  when  an  edge-point  is  in  contact 
with  a  smooth-point,  it  may  be  possible  to  move  one  of  the 
two  bodies  relatively  to  the  other  witlwut  separating  those 
two  points. 

The  same  thing  may  be  observed  if  we  put  the 
round  or  flat  surface  of  the  cylinder  against  an  edge 
of  the  cube,  or  if  we  put  the  sphere  against  an  edge  of 
either  of  the  other  bodies.  Holding  either  of  them 
fast,  we  may  move  the  other  so  as  to  keep  the  same  two 
points  in  contact ;  but  in  order  to  do  this,  we  must 
always  tilt  in  the  same  direction. 

If,  however,  we  put  a  corner  of  the  cube  in  contact 
with  a  smooth  point  of  the  cylinder,  as  in  tig.  10,  we 


Fio.  10. 

shall  find  that  we  can  keep  these  two  points  in  contact 
without  any  restriction  on  the  direction  of  tilting.     We 


60      THE    COMMON    SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT    SCIENCES. 

may  tilt  the  cube  any  way  we  like,  and  still  keep  its 
corner  in  contact  with  the  smooth-point  of  the  cylinder. 

When  we  put  two  edge-points  together,  it  makes  a 
difference  whether  the  edges  are  in  the  same  direction 
at  the  point  of  contact  or  whether  they  cross  one 
another.  In  the  former  case  we  may  be  able  to  keep 
the  same  two  points  in  contact  by  tilting  in  a  particular 
direction  ;  in  the  latter  case  we  may  tilt  in  any  direc 
tion.  So  if  a  corner  is  in  contact  with  an  edge-point 
there  is  no  restriction  on  the  direction  of  tilting,  and 
much  more  if  a  corner  is  in  contact  with  a  corner. 

The  upshot  of  all  this  is,  that  in  a  certain  sense  all 
surfaces  are  of  the  same  shape  at  all  smooth-points ;  for 
when  we  put  two  smooth-points  in  contact,  the  surfaces 
so  fit  one  another  at  those  points  that  we  cannot  move 
one  of  them  relatively  to  the  other  without  separating 
the  points.1 

It  is  possible  for  two  edges  to  fit  so  that  we  cannot 
move  either  of  the  bodies  without  separating  the  points 
in  contact.  For  this  it  is  necessary  that  one  of  them 
should  be  re-entrant  (that  is,  should  be  a  depression  in 
the  surface,  not  a  projection),  as  in  fig.  11 ;  and  here 


FIG.  11. 


we  can  see  the  propriety  of  saying  that  the  two  surfaces 

are    of  the  same  shape   at  a  point  where  they  fit  in 

this  way.     The  body  placed  in  contact  with  the  cube 

:  See,  however,  the  footnote,  p.  58. — K.  P. 


SPACE.  61 

is  formed  by  joining  together  two  spheres  from  which 
pieces  have  been  sliced  off.  If  only  very  small  pieces 
aave  been  sliced  off,  the  re-entrant  edge  will  be  very 
sharp,  and  it  will  be  impossible  to  bring  the  cube-edge 
into  contact  with  it  (fig.  12)  ;  if  nearly  half  of  each 


FIG.  12.  FIG.  13.  .b'iG.  14. 

sphere  has  been  cut  off  the  re-entrant  edge  will  be  wide 
open,  and  the  cube  will  rock  in  it  (fig.  13).  There  is 

jlearly  one  intermediate  form  in  which  the  two  edges 
will  just  fit  (fig.  14) ;  contact  at  the  edge  will  be 

Dossible,  but  no  rocking.  Now  in  this  case,  although 
one  edge  sticks  out  arid  the  other  is  a  dint,  we  may 
still  say  that  the  two  surfaces  are  of  the  same  shape 
at  the  edge.  For  if  we  suppose  our  twin-sphere 

)ody  to  be  made  of  wood,  its  surface  is  not  only  sur 
face  of  the  wood,  but  also  surface  of  the  surrounding 
air.  And  that  which  is  a  dint  or  depression  in  the 
wood  is  at  the  same  time  a  projection  in  the  air.  In 
just  the  same  way,  each  of  the  projecting  edges  and 
corners  of  the  cube  is  at  the  same  time  a  dint  or 
depression  in  the  air.  But  the  surface  belongs  to  one 
as  much  as  the  other ;  it  knows  nothing  of  the  differ 
ence  between  inside  and  outside ;  elevation  and  depres 
sion  are  arbitrary  terms  to  it.  So  in  a  thin  piece  of 
embossed  metal,  elevation  on  one  side  means  depression 
on  the  other,  and  vice  versa ;  but  it  is  purely  arbitrary 


62      THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

which  side  we  consider  the  right  one.  (Observe  thai 
the  thin  piece  of  metal  is  in  no  sense  a  representation 
of  a  surface  ;  it  is  merely  a  thin  solid  whose  two  surfaces 
are  very  nearly  of  the  same  shape.) 

Thus  we  see  that  the  edge  of  wood  in  our  cube  is 
of  the  same  shape  as  the  edge  of  air  in  the  twin-sphere 
solid  ;  or,  which  is  the  same  thing,  that  the  two  surfaces 
are  of  the  same  shape  at  the  edge. 

Now  this  twin-sphere  solid  is  a  very  convenient  one 
because  we  can  so  modify  it  as  to  make  an  edge  of  any 
shape  we  like.  Hitherto  we  have  supposed  the  slices 
cut  off  to  be  less  than  half  of  the  spheres  ;  let  us  now 
fasten  together  these  pieces,  and  so  form  a  solid  with  a 
projecting  edge,  as  in  fig.  15.  The  two  solids  so  formed, 
one  with  a  re-entrant  edge  from  the  larger  pieces,  the 
other  with  a  projecting  edge  from  the  smaller  pieces, 
will  be  found  always  to  have  their  edges  of  the  same 
shape,  or  to  fit  one  another  at  the  edge  in  the  sense 
just  explained. 


FIG.  15. 

Now  suppose  that  we  cut  our  spheres  very  nearly  in 
half.  (Of  course  they  must  always  be  cut  both  alike, 
or  the  flat  faces  would  not  fit  together.)  Then  when 
we  join  together  the  larger  pieces  and  the  smaller 
pieces,  we  shall  form  solids  with  very  wide  open  edges. 
The  projecting  edge  will  be  a  very  slight  ridge,  and  the 
re-entrant  one  a  very  slight  depression. 

If  we  now  go  a  step  further,  and  cut  our  spheres 
actually  in  half,  of  course  each  of  the  new  solids  will 
be  again  a  sphere ;  and  there  will  be  neither  ridge  nor 


SPACE. 


63 


tij  epression  ;  the  surfaces  will  be  smooth  all  over.     But 
tigj/e  have  arrived  at  this  result  by  considering  a  project- 


(vi)     (vii) 


FIG.  16. 

ing  edge  as  gradually  widening  out  until  the  ridge  dis 
appears,  or  by  considering  a  re-entrant  edge  as  gradually 
widening  out  until  the  dint  disappears.  Or  we  may 
suppose  the  projecting  edge  to  go  on  widening  out  till 
it  becomes  smooth,  and  then  to  turn  into  a  re-entrant 
edge.  We  might  represent  this  process  to  the  eye  by 
putting  into  a  wheel  of  life  a  succession  of  pictures  like 
that  in  fig.  16,  and  then  rapidly  turning  the  wheel.  We 
should  see  the  two  spheres,  at  first  separate,  coalesce 
into  a  single  solid  in  (ii)  and  (iii),then  form  one  sphere  as 
at  (iv),  then  contract  into  a  smaller  and  smaller  lens  at 
(v),  (vi),  (vii).  The  important  thing  to  notice  is  that  the 
single  sphere  at  (iv)  is  a  step  in  the  process ;  or,  what 
is  the  same  thing,  that  a  smooth-point  is  a  particular  case 
of  an  edge-point  coming  between  the  projecting  and  the  re 
entrant  edges.  As  being  this  particular  case  of  the 
edge-point,  we  say  that  at  all  smooth-points  the  sur 
faces  are  of  the  same  shape. 


§  4.   The  Characteristics  of  Surface  Boundaries. 

Remarks  like  these  that  we  have  made  about  solid 
bodies  or  portions  of  space    may  be  made  also  about 


64      THE    COMMON    SEXSE    OF    THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

portions  of  surface.     Only  we  cannot  now  say  that  th* 
shape  of  a  piece  of  surface  depends  wholly  on  that  of 
the  curve  which  bounds  it.     Still  the  only  thing  that 
remains  for  us  to  consider  is  the  shape  of  the  boundary,! 
because  we  have  already  discussed  (so  far  as  we  profit-] 
ably  can  at  present)  the  shape  of  the  included  surface. 

We  shall  find  it  useful  to  restrict  ourselves  still] 
further,  and  only  consider  those  boundaries  which  have 
no  rough  points  of  the  surface  in  them.  Thus  on  the 
surface  of  the  cube  we  will  only  consider  portions  which 
are  entirely  included  in  one  of  the  plane  faces  ;  on  the 
surface  of  the  cylinder,  only  portions  which  are  entirely 
included  in  one  of  the  flat  faces,  or  in  the  curved  part, 
or  which  include  one  of  the  flat  faces  and  part  of  the 
curved  portion. 

This  being  so,  the  characteristics  which  we  have  to 
remark  in  the  boundaries  of  pieces  of  surface  may  be 
sufficiently  studied  by  means  of  figures  drawn  on  paper. 
We  may  bend  the  paper  to  assure  ourselves  that  the 
same  general  properties  belong  to  figures  on  a  cylinder, 
and  to  make  our  ideas  quite  distinct  it  is  worth  while 
to  draw  some  on  a  sphere  or  other  such  surface. 

In  fig.  17  are  some  patches  of  surface;  a  square,  a 
three-cornered  piece,  and  two  overlapping  circles.  For 


FIG.  17. 

distinctness,  the  part  where  the  circles  overlap  is  left 
white,  the  rest  being  made  black. 

Attending  now  specially  to  the  boundary  of  these 
patches,  we  observe  that  it  consists  of  smooth  parts  and 
of  corners  or  angles.  Some  of  these  corners  project 


SPACE.  65 

and  some  are  re-entrant.  The  pieces  of  surface  are  not 
solid  moveable  tilings  like  the  portions  of  space  we 
considered  before,  but  we  can  in  a  measure  imitate  our 
previous  experiments  by  cutting  out  the  figures  with  a 
penknife,  so  as  to  leave  their  previous  positions  marked 
by  the  holes.  We  shall  then  find,  on  applying  the  cut 
out  pieces  to  one  another,  or  to  the  holes,  that  at  all 
smooth-points  the  boundaries  fit  one  another  in  a  cer 
tain  sense.  Namely,  if  we  place  two  smooth-points  in 
contact  we  cannot  roll  one  figure  on  the  other  without 
separating  these  points ;  whereas  if  we  place  a  sharp- 
point  (or  angle)  on  a  smooth-point  we  can  roll  one  figure 
on  the  other  without  separating  the  points.  If  we 
attempt  to  put  two  angles  together  without  letting  the 
figures  overlap,  the  same  things  may  happen  that  we 
found  true  in  the  case  of  the  edges  of  solid  bodies. 
Suppose,  for  example,  that  we  try  to  put  an  angle  of  the 
square  into  one  of  the  re-entrant  angles  of  the  figure 
made  by  the  two  overlapping  circles.  If  the  re-entrant 
angle  is  too  sharp,  we  shall  not  be  able  to  get  it  in  at 
all;  this  is  the  case  of  fig.  12.  If  it  is  wide  enough, 
the  square  will  be  able  to  rock  in  it ;  this  is  the  case  of 
fig.  13.  Between  these  two  there  is  an  intermediate 
case  in  which  one  angle  just  fits  the  other ;  actual 
,  contact  takes  place,  and  no  rocking  is  possible.  In 
'  this  case  we  say  that  the  two  angles  are  of  the  same 
•  shape,  or  that  they  are  equal  to  one  another. 

From  all  this  we  are  led  to  conclude  that  shape-  is  a 
matter  of  angles,  and  that  identity  of  shape  depends  on 
equality  of  angle.  We  dealt  with  the  sixe  of  a  body  by 
considering  a  simple  case  of  it,  viz.  length  or  distance, 
and  by  measuring  a  sufficient  number  of  lengths  in  dif 
ferent  directions  could  find  out  all  that  is  to  be  known 
about  the  size  of  a  body.  It  is,  indeed,  also  true  that  a 

F 


66      THE   COMMON   SENSE   OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

knowledge  of  all  the  lengths  which  can  be  measured 
in  a  body  would  carry  with  it  a  knowledge  of  its  shape; 
but  still  length  is  not  in  itself  an  element  of  shape. 
That  which  does  the  same  for  us  in  regard  to  shape 
that  length  does  with  regard  to  size,  is  angle.  In  other 
words,  just  as  we  say  that  two  bodies  are  of  the  same 
size  if  to  any  line  that  can  be  drawn  in  the  one  there 
corresponds  an  exactly  equal  line  in  the  other,  so  we  say 
that  two  bodies  are  of  the  same  shape,  if  to  every  angle 
that  can  be  drawn  on  one  of  them  there  corresponds  an 
exactly  equal  angle  on  the  other. 

Just  as  we  measured  lengths  by  a  stick  or  a  piece  of 
tape  so  we  measure  angles  with  a  pair  of  compasses ; 
at'd  two  angles  are  said  to  be  equal  when  they  fit  the 
same  opening  of  the  compasses.  And  as  before,  the 
statement  that  a  thing  can  be  moved  about  without 
altering  its  shape  maybe  shown  to  amount  only  to  this, 
that  two  angles  which  fit  in  one  place  will  fit  also  in 
another,  no  matter  how  they  have  been  brought  from 
the  one  place  to  the  other. 


§  5.  The  Plane  and  the  Straight  Line. 

We  have  now  to  describe  a  particular  kind  of  surface 
and  a  particular  kind  of  line  with  which  geometry  is 
very  much  concerned.  These  are  the  plane  surface  and 
the  straight  line. 

The  plane  surface  may  be  defined  as  one  which  is  of 
the  same  shape  all  over  and  on  both  sides.  This  pro 
perty  of  it  is  illustrated  by  the  method  which  is  practi 
cally  used  to  make  such  a  surface.  The  method  is  to 
take  three  surfaces  and  grind  them  down  until  any  two 
will  tit  one  another  all  over.  Suppose  the  three  surfaces 
to  be  A,  B,  c  ;  then,  since  A  will  fit  B,  it  follows  that  the 


SPACE.  67 

space  outside  A  is  of  the  same  shape  as  the  space  inside 
B  ;  and  because  B  will  fit  c,  that  the  space  inside  B  is  of 
the  same  shape  as  the  space  outside  c.  It  follows  there 
fore  that  the  space  outside  A  is  of  the  same  shape  as  the 
space  outside  c.  But  since  A  will  fit  o  when  we  put 
them  together,  the  space  inside  A  is  of  the  same  shape 
as  the  space  outside  c.  But  the  space  outside  c  was 
shown  to  be  of  the  same  shape  as  the  space  outside  A  ; 
consequently  the  space  outside  A  is  of  the  same  shape  as 
the  space  inside ;  and  so,  if  three  surfaces  are  ground 
together  so  that  each  pair  of  them  will  fit,  each  of  them 
becomes  a  surface  which  is  of  the  same  shape  on  both 
sides  :  that  is  to  say,  if  we  take  a  body  which  is  partly 
bounded  by  a  plane  surface,  we  can  slide  it  all  over  this 
surface  and  it  will  fit  everywhere,  and  we  may  also  turn 
it  round  and  apply  it  to  the  other  side  of  the  surface 
and  it  will  fit  there  too.  This  property  is  sometimes 
more  technically  expressed  by  saying  that  a  plane  is  a 
surface  which  divides  space  into  two  congruent  regions. 

A  straight  line  may  be  defined  in  a  similar  way.  It 
is  a  division  between  two  parts  of  a  plane,  which  two 
parts  are,  so  far  as  the  dividing  line  is  concerned,  of  the 
same  shape ;  or  we  may  say  what  comes  to  the  same 
effect,  that  a  straight  line  is  a  line  of  the  same  shape  all 
along  and  on  both  .sides. 

A  body  may  have  two  plane  surfaces  ;  one  part  of  it, 
that  is,  may  bo  bounded  by  one  plane  and  another  part 
by  another.  If  these  two  plane  surfaces  have  a  common 
edge,  this  edge,  which  is  called  their  intersection,  is  a 
straight  line.  We  may  then,  if  we  like,  take  as  our 
definition  of  a  straight  line  that  it  is  the  intersection  of 
two  planes. 

It  must  be  understood  that  when  a  part  of  the  sur 
face  of  a  body  is  plane,  this  plane  may  be  conceived  as 

F   2 


68      THE   COMMON   SEXSE   OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

extending  beyond  the  body  in  all  directions.  For 
instance,  the  upper  surface  of  a  table  is  plane  and 
horizontal.  Now  it  is  quite  an  intelligible  question  to 
ask  about  a  point  which  is  anywhere  in  the  room  whether 
it  is  higher  or  lower  than  the  surface  of  the  table.  The 
points  which  are  higher  will  be  divided  from  those  which 
are  lower  by  an  imaginary  surface  which  is  a  continua 
tion  of  the  plane  surface  of  the  table.  So  then  we  are 
at  liberty  to  speak  of  the  line  of  intersection  of  two 
plane  surfaces  of  a  body  whether  these  are  adjacenl 
portions  of  surface  or  not,  and  we  may  in  every  case 
suppose  them  to  meet  one  another  and  to  be  prolonged 
across  the  edge  in  which  they  meet. 

Leibniz,  who  was  the  first  to  give  these  definitions 
of  a  plane  and  of  a  straight  line,  gave  also  another 
definition  of  a  straight  line.  If  we  fix  two  points  of  a 
body,  it  will  not  be  entirely  fixed,  but  it  will  be  able  to 
turn  round.  All  points  of  it  will  then  change  their 
position  excepting  those  which  are  in  the  straight  line 
joining  the  two  fixed  points;  and  Leibniz  accordingly 
defined  a  straight  line  as  being  the  aggregate  of  those 
points  of  a  body  which  are  unmoved  when  it  is  turned 
about  with  two  points  fixed.  If  we  suppose  the  body  to 
have  a  plane  face  passing  through  the  two  fixed  points, 
this  definition  will  fall  back  on  the  former  one  which 
defines  a  straight  line  as  the  intersection  of  two  planes. 

It  hardly  needs  any  words  to  prove  that  the  first 
two  definitions  of  a  plane  are  equivalent;  that  is,  that 
two  surfaces,  each  of  which  is  of  the  same  shape  all  over 
and  on  both  sides,  will  have  for  their  intersection  a  line 
which  is  of  the  same  shape  all  along  and  on  both  sides. 
For  if  we  slide  each  plane  upon  itself  it  will,  being  of 
the  same  shape  all  over,  occupy  as  a  whole  the  same 
unchanging  position  (i.e.  wherever  there  was  part  of 


SPACE.  69 

the  planes  before  there  will  be  part,  though  a  different 
part,  of  the  planes  now),  so  that  their  line  of  inter 
section  occupies  the  same  position  throughout  (though 
the  part  of  the  line  occupying  any  particular  position 
is  different).  The  line  is  therefore  of  the  same  shape 
all  along.  And  in  a  similar  way  we  can,  without 
changing  the  position  of  the  planes  as  a  whole,  move 
them  so  that  the  right-hand  part  of  each  shall  become 
the  left-hand  part,  and  the  upper  part  the  lower;  and 
this  will  amount  to  changing  the  line  of  intersection 
end  for  end.  But  this  line  is  in  the  same  place  after 
the  change  as  before ;  and  it  is  therefore  of  the  same 
shape  on  both  sides. 

From  the  first  definition  we  see  that  two  straight 
lines  cannot  coincide  for  a  certain  distance  and  then 
diverge  from  one  another.  For  since  the  plane  surface 
is  of  the  same  shape  on  the  two  sides  of  a  straight  line, 
we  may  take  up  the  surface  on  one  side  and  turn  it 
over  and  it  will  fit  the  surface  on  the  other  side.  If 
this  is  true  of  one  of  our  supposed  straight  lines,  it  is 
quite  clear  that  it  cannot  at  the  same  time  be  true  of  the 
other;  for  we  must  either  be  bringing  over  more  to  lit 
less,  or  less  to  fit  more. 

§  6.  Properties  of  Triangles. 

can  now  reduce  to  a  more  precise  form  our  first 
observation  about  space,  that  a  body  may  be  moved 
about  in  it  without  altering  its  size  or  shape.  Let  us 
suppose  that  our  body  has  for  one  of  its  faces  a  tri«n<jl<>, 
that  is  to  say,  the  portion  of  a  plane  bounded  by  three 
straight  lines.  We  find  that  this  triangle  can  be  moved 
into  any  new  position  that  we  like,  while  the  lengths  of 
its  sides  and  its  angles  remain  the  same ;  or  we  may 


70      THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

put  the  statement  into  the  form  that  when  any  triangl 
is  once  drawn,  another  triangle  of  the  same  size  an 
shape  can  be  drawn  in  any  part  of  space. 

From  this  it  will  follow  that  if  there  are  two  triangle 
which  have  a  side  of  the  one  equal  to  a  side  of  the  othei 
and  the  angles  at  the  ends  of  that  side  in  the  one  equa 
to  the  angles  at  the  ends  of  the  equal  side  in  the  othei 
then  the  two  triangles  are  merely  the  same  triangle  i: 
different  positions  ;  that  is,  they  are  of  the  same  siz 
and  shape.  For  if  we  take  the  first  triangle  and  so  fa 
put  it  into  the  position  of  the  second  that  the  two  equa 
sides  coincide,  then  because  the  angles  at  the  ends  c 
the  one  are  respectively  equal  to  those  at  the  ends  c 
the  other,  the  remaining  two  sides  of  the  first  triangl 
will  begin  to  coincide  with  the  remaining  two  sides  c 
the  second.  But  we  have  seen  that  straight  lines  canno 
begin  to  coincide  and  then  diverge ;  and  consequent!, 
these  sides  will  coincide  throughout  and  the  triangle 
will  entirely  coincide. 

Our  second  observation,  that  we  may  have  thing 
which  are  of  the  same  shape  but  not  of  the  same  sizt 
may  also  be  made  more  precise  by  application  to  th 
case  of  triangles.  It  tells  us  that  any  triangle  miy  b 
magnified  or  diminished  to  any  degree  without  alterin; 
its  angles,  or  that  if  a  triangle  be  drawn,  anothe 
triangle  having  the  same  angles  may  be  drawn  of  an 
size  in  any  part  of  space. 

From  this  statement  we  are  able  to  deduce  two  ver 
important  consequences.  One  is,  that  two  straigh 
lines  cannot  intersect  in  more  points  than  one ;  and  th 
other  that,  if  two  straight  lines  can  be  drawn  in  th 
same  plane  so  as  not  to  intersect  at  all,  the  angles  the, 
make  Avith  any  third  line  in  their  plane  which  meet 
them,  will  be  equal. 


SPACE.  7 1 

To  prove  the  first  of  these,  let  AB  and  AC  (fig.  18)  be 
two  straight  lines  which  meet  at  A.  Draw  a  third  line 
BC,  meeting  both  of  them,  and  the  three  lines  then  form  a 
triangle.  If  we  now  make  a  point  p  travel  along  the  line 
AB  it  must,  in  virtue  of  our  second  observation,  be  always 
possible  to  draw  through  this  point  a  line  which  shall 
meet  AC  in  Q  so  as  to  make  a  triangle  A  p  Q  of  the  same 


shape  as  ABC.  But  if  the  line  AC  were  to  meet  AB  in 
some  other  point  D  besides  A,  then  through  this  point 
D  it  would  clearly  not  be  possible  to  draw  a  line  so  as 
to  make  a  triangle  at  all.  It  follows  then  that  such 
a  point  as  D  does  not  exist,  and  in  fact  that  two 
straight  lines  which  have  once  met  must  go  on  diverg 
ing  from  each  other  and  can  never  meet  again.1 

To  prove  the  second,  suppose  that  the  lines  A  c  and 
BD  (fig.  19)  are  in  the  same  plane,  and  are  such  as 


7 


FIG.  19. 

never  to  meet  at  all  (in  which  case  they  are  called 
parallel),  while  the  line  A  B  meets  them  both.  If  we 
make  a  point  p  travel  along  B  A  towards  A,  and,  as  it 
moves,  draw  through  it  always  a  line  making  the  same 
angle  with  B  A  that  B  D  makes  with  B  A,  then  this 

1  This  property  might  also  be  deduced  from  the  first  definition  of  a 
straight  line,  by  the  method  already  used  to  show  that  two  straight  lines 
cannot  coincide  for  part  of  their  length  and  then  diverge. 


72      THE   COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

moving  line  can  never  meet  A  c  until  it  wholly  coincides 
with.  it.  For  if  it  can,  let  p  Q  be  such  a  position  of 
the  moving  line ;  then  it  is  possible  to  draw  through 
B  a  line  which,  with.  A  B  and  A  c,  shall  form  a  tri 
angle  of  the  same  shape  as  the  triangle  A  p  Q.  But 
for  this  to  be  the  case  the  line  drawn  through  B  must 
make  the  same  angle  with  A  B  that  p  Q  makes  with  it, 
that  is,  it  must  be  the  line  B  D.  And  the  three  lines  B  D, 
B  A,  A  c  cannot  form  a  triangle,  for  B  D  and  A  c  never 
meet.  Consequently  there  can  be  no  such  triangle  as 
A  P  Q,  or  the  moveable  line  can  never  meet  A  c  until  it 
entirely  coincides  with  it.  But  since  this  line  always 
makes  with  B  A  the  same  angle  that  B  D  does,  and  in 
one  position  coincides  with  A  c,  it  follows  that  A  c 
makes  with  B  A  the  same  angle  that  B  D  does.  This  is 
the  famous  proposition  about  parallel  lines.1 

The  first  of  these  deductions  will  now  show  us  that 
if  two  triangles  have  an  angle  of  the  one  equal  to  an 
angle  of  the  other  and  the  sides  containing  these  angles 
respectively  equal,  they  must  be  equal  in  all  particulars. 
For  if  we  take  up  one  of  the  triangles  and  put  it  down 

1  Two  straight  lines  which  cut  one  another  form  at  the  point  where  they 
cross  four  angles  which  are  equal  in  pairs.  It  is  often  necessarj7  to  dis 
tinguish  between  the  two  different  angles  which  the  lines  make  with  one 
another.  This  is  done  by  the  understanding  that  A  B  shall  mean  the  line 


0)  (ii) 

drawn  from  A  to  B,  and  B  A  the  line  drawn  from  B  to  A,  so  that  the  angle 
between  AB  and  CD  (i)  is  the  angle  BOD,  but  the  angle  between  BA  and 
C  D  (ii)  is  the  angle  D  o  A. 

So  the  angle  spoken  of  above  as  made  by  A  c  with  B  A  is  not  the  angle 
CAB  (which  is  clearly,  in  general,  unequal  to  the  angle  DBA),  but  the 
angle  c  A  E,  where  E  is  a  point  in  B  A  produced  through  A. 


SPACE.  73 

on  the  other  so  that  these  angles  coincide  and  equal 
sides  are  on  the  same  side  of  them,  then  the  con 
taining  sides  will  begin  to  coincide,  and  cannot  there 
fore  afterwards  diverge.  But  as  they  are  of  the  same 
length  in  the  one  triangle  as  they  are  in  the  other,  the 
ends  of  them  belonging  to  the  one  triangle  will  rest 
upon  the  ends  belonging  to  the  other,  so  that  the  re 
maining  sides  of  the  two  triangles  will  have  their  ends  in 
common  and  must  therefore  coincide  altogether,  since 
otherwise  two  straight  lines  would  meet  in  more  points 
than  one.  The  one  triangle  will  then  exactly  cover  the 
other ;  that  is  to  say,  they  are  equal  in  all  respects. 

In  the  same  way  we  may  see  that  if  two  triangles 
have  two  angles  in  the  one  equal  to  two  angles  in  the 
other,  they  are  of  the  same  shape.  For  one  of  them 
can  be  magnified  or  diminished  until  the  side  joining 
these  two  angles  in  it  becomes  of  the  same  length  as 
the  side  joining  the  two  corresponding  angles  in  the 
other ;  and  as  no  alteration  is  thereby  made  in  the 
shape  of  the  triangle,  it  will  be  enough  for  us  to  prove 
that  the  new  triangle  is  of  the  same  shape  as  the  other 
given  triangle.  But  if  we  now  compare  these  two,  we 
see  that  they  have  a  pair  of  corresponding  sides  which 
have  been  made  equal,  and  the  angles  at  the  ends  of 
these  sides  equal  also  (for  they  were  equal  in  the 
original  triangles,  and  have  not  been  altered  by  the 
change  of  size),  so  that  we  fall  back  on  a  case  already 
considered,  in  which  it  was  shown  that  the  third  angles 
are  equal,  and  the  triangles  consequently  of  the  same 
shape. 

If  we  apply  these  propositions  not  merely  to  two 
different  triangles  but  to  the  same  triangle,  we  find 
that  if  a  triangle  has  two  of  its  sides  equal  it  will  have 
the  two  angles  opposite  to  them  also  equal  j  and  that, 


74      THE    COMMON   SENSE   OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

conversely,  if  it  has  two  angles  equal  it  will  have  the  two 
sides  opposite  to  them  also  equal ;  for  in  each  of  these 
cases  the  triangle  may  be  turned  over  and  made  to  fit 
itself.  Such  a  triangle  is  called  isosceles. 

The  theorem  about  parallel  lines  which  we  deduced 
from  our  second  assumption  about  space  leads  Tery 
easily  to  a  theorem  of  especial  importance,  viz.  that 
the  three  angles  of  a  triangle' are  together  equal  to  two 
right  angles. 

If  we  draw  through  A,  a  corner  of  the  triangle 
ABC  (fig.  20),  a  line  DAE,  making  with  the  side  A o 

IE  AD 


FIG.  20. 

the  same  angle  as  B  c  makes  with  it,  this  line  will, 
as  we  have  proved,  never  meet  B  c,  that  is.  it  will  be 
parallel  to  it.  It  will  consequently  make  with  A  B  the 
same  angle  as  B  c  makes  with  it,1  so  that  the  three 
angles  ABO,  BAG,  and  BOA  are  respectively  equal  to 
the  angles  E  A  B,  BAG,  and  CAD,  and  these  three  make 
up  two  right  angles. 

Another  statement  of  this  theorem  is  sometimes  of 
use. 

If  the  sides  of  a  triangle  be  produced,  what  are 
called  the  exterior  angles  of  the  triangle  are  formed.  If, 
for  example,  the  side  B  o  of  the  triangle  ABC  (fig.  21) 
is  produced  beyond  c  to  D,  A  c  D  is  an  exterior  angle  of 
the  triangle,  while  of  the  interior  angles  of  the  triangle 
A  c  B  is  said  to  be  adjacent,  and  CAB  and  A  B  c  to  be 
opposite  to  this  exterior  angle.  It  is  clear  that  as 

1  The  convention  mentioned  in  the  last  footnote  must  be  remembered. 


SPACE.  75 

each   side   of  the   triangle  may  be   produced   in   two 
directions,  any  triangle  has  six  exterior  angles. 


B  CD 

FIG.  21. 

The  other  form  into  which  our  proposition  may 
be  thrown  is  that  either  of  the  exterior  angles  of  a 
triangle  is  equal  to  the  sum  of  the  two  interior  angles 
opposite  to  it.  For,  in  the  figure,  the  exterior  angle 
A  c  D,  together  with  AGE,  makes  two  right  angles,  and 
it  must  therefore  be  equal  to  the  sum  of  the  two  angles 
•which  also  make  up  two  right  angles  with  A  c  B. 

§  7.  Properties  of  Circles;  Related  Circles  and  Triangles. 

We  may  now  apply  this  proposition  to  prove  an  im 
portant  property  of  the  circle,  viz.  that  if  we  take  two 
fixed  points  on  the  circumference  of  a  circle  and  join 
them  to  a  third  point  on  the  circle,  the  angle  between 
the  joining  lines  will  depend  only  upon  the  first  two 
points  and  not  at  all  upon  the  third.  If,  for  example, 
we  join  the  points  A,  B  (fig.  22)  to  c  we  shall  show  that, 
wherever  on  the  circumference  c  may  be,  the  angle 
A  c  B  is  always  one-half  of  A  o  B  ;  o  being  the  centre  of 
the  circle. 

Let  co  produced  meet  the  circumference  in  D. 
Then  since  the  triangle  o  A  c  is  isosceles,  the  angles  o  A  c 
and  OCA  are  equal,  and  so  for  a  similar  reason  are  the 
angles  o  B  c  and  o  c  B. 

But  we  have  just  shown  that  the  exterior  angle 
AO  D  is  equal  to  the  sum  of  the  angles  o  A  c  and  OCA; 


76      THE   COMMON   SEXSE    OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

and  since  these  are  equal  to  one  another  it  must  be 
double  of  either  of  them,  say  of  OCA.  Similarly  the 
angle  B  o  D  is  double  of  o  c  B,  and  consequently  A  0  B  is 
double  of  A  c  B. 

In  the  case  of  the  first  figure  (i)  we  have  taken  the 
sum  of  two  angles  each  of  which  is  double  of  another, 
and  asserted  that  the  sum  of  the  first  pair  is  twice  the 
sum  of  the  second  pair ;  in  the  case  of  the  second 
figure  (ii)  we  have  taken  the  difference  of  two  angles 


FIG.  22. 

each  of  which  is  double  of  another,  and  asserted  that 
the  difference  of  the  first  pair  is  twice  the  difference  of 
the  second  pair. 

Since  therefore  A  c  B  is  always  half  of  A  o  B,  wher 
ever  c  may  be  placed  in  the  upper  of  the  two  segments 
into  which  the  circle  is  divided  by  the  straight  line  A  B, 
we  see  that  the  magnitude  of  this  angle  depends  only 
on  the  positions  of  A  and  B,  and  not  on  the  position  of 
c.  But  now  let  us  consider  what  will  happen  if  c  is  in 
the  lower  segment  of  the  circle.  As  before,  the  tri 
angles  o  A  c  and  o  B  c  (fig.  23)  are  isosceles,  and  the 
angles  DO  A  and  DOB  are  respectively  double  of  OCA 
and  o  c  B.  Consequently,  the  whole  angle  A  o  B  formed 
by  making  o  A  turn  round  o  into  the  position  o  B,  so  as 
to  pass  through  the  position  OD  (in  the  way,  that  is, 


SPACE.  77 

in  which  the  hands  of  a  clock  turn),  this  whole  angle  is 
double  of  A  c  B. 

By  our  previous  reasoning  the  angle  A  D  B,  formed 
by  joining  A  and  B  to  D,  is  one-half  of  the  angle  A  o  B, 
which  is  made  by  turning  o  B  towards  o  A  as  the  hands 
of  a  clock  move.  The  sum  of  these  two  angles,  each 
of  which  we  have  denoted  by  A  o  B,  is  a  complete  re 
volution  about  the  point  o ;  in  other  words,  is  four 


right  angles.  Hence  the  sum  of  the  angles  A  D  B,  AGE, 
which  are  the  halves  of  these,  is  two  right  angles.  Or 
we  may  put  the  theorem  otherwise,  and  say  that  the 
opposite  angles  of  a  four-sided  figure  whose  angles  lie 
on  the  circumference  of  a  circle  are  together  equal  to 
two  right  angles. 

We  appear  therefore  to  have  arrived  at  two  dif 
ferent  statements  according  as  the  point  c  is  in  the 
one  or  the  other  of  the  segments  into  which  tin; 
circle  is  divided  by  the  straight  line  A  B.  But  these 
statements  are  really  the  same,  and  it  is  easy  to  include 
them  in  one  proposition.  If  AVO  produce  AC  in  the  last 
figure  to  E,  the  angles  A  c  B  and  B  c  E  are  together  equal 
to  two  right  angles ;  and  consequently  B  c  E  is  equal  to 
A  D  B.  This  angle  B  c  E  is  the  angle  through  which  c  B 
must  be  turned  in  the  way  the  hands  of  a  clock  move, 


78      THE   COMMON   SENSE   OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

so  that  its  direction  may  coincide  with  that  of  A  c.  But 
we  may  describe  in  precisely  the  same  words  the  angle 
A  c  B  in  fig.  22,  where  c  was  in  the  upper  segment  of  the 
circle ;  so  that  we  may  always  put  the  theorem  in  these 
words :— If  A  and  B  are  fixed  points  on  the  circumfer 
ence  of  a  circle,  and  o  any  other  point  on  it,  the  angle 
through  which  c  B  must  be  turned  clockwise  in  order  to 
coincide  with  c  A  or  AC,  whichever  happens  first,  is 
equal  to  half  the  angle  through  which  o  B  must  be 
turned  clockwise  in  order  to  coincide  with  o  A. 

We  shall  now  make  use  of  this  to  prove  another  in 
teresting  proposition.     If  three  points  D,  E,  F  (fig.  24) 


FIG.  24. 

be  taken  on  the  sides  ot  a  triangle  A  B  c,  D  being  on  B  0, 
E  on  c  A,  F  on  A  B,  then  three  circles  can  be  drawn 
passing  respectively  through  A  F  E,  B  D  F,  c  E  D.  These 
three  circles  can  be  shown  to  meet  in  the  same  point  o. 
For  let  o  in  the  first  place  stand  for  the  intersection  of 
the  two  circles  A  F  E  and  B  F  D,  then  the  angles  F  A  E 
and  FOE  make  up  two  right  angles,  and  so  do  the 
angles  D  o  F  and  DBF.  But  the  three  angles  at  o  make 
four  right  angles,  and  the  three  angles  of  the  triangle 
ABC  make  two  right  angles  :  and  of  these  six  angles 
two  pairs  have  been  shown  to  make  up  two  right 


SPACE. 


79 


ingles  each.  Therefore  the  remaining  pair,  viz.  the 
ingles  DOE  and  D  c  E,  make  up  two  right  angles.  It 
follows  that  the  circle  which  goes  through  the  points 
D  E  D  will  pass  through  o,  that  is,  the  three  circles  all 
meet  in  this  point. 

There  is  no  restriction  imposed  on  the  positions  of 
the  points  D,  E,  p,1  they  may  be  taken  either  on  the  sides 


FIG.  25. 

of  the  triangle  or  on  those  sides  produced,  and  in  pnr- 
ticular  we  may  take  them  to  lie  on  any  fourth  straight 
line  D  E  F  ;  and  the  theorem  may  be  stated  thus  : — If 
any  four  straight  lines  be  taken  (fig.  25),  one  of  which 
meets  the  triangle  ABC  formed  by  the  other  three  in 
the  points  D,  E,  F,  then  the  circles  through  the  points 

1  If  either  of  the  points  D,  E,  F,  is  taken  on  a  side  produced,  the  proof 
given  above  will  not  apply  literally;  but  the  necessary  changes  are  slight 
and  obvious. 


80      THE    COMMON"    SEXSE    OF    THE    EXACT    SCIEXCES. 

AFE,  BDP,  CED  meet  in  a  point.  But  there  is  ncjj 
reason  why  we  should  not  take  A  F  E  as  the  triangle! 
formed  by  three  lines,  and  the  fourth  line  D  c  B  as  tha 
line  which  cuts  the  sides  of  this  triangle.  The  propo-l 
sition  is  equally  true  in  this  case,  and  it  follows  thai] 
the  circles  through  ABC,  BCD,  FED  will  meet  in  onel 
point.  This  must  be  the  same  point  as  before,  sincel 
two  of  the  circles  of  this  set  are  the  same  as  two  of  the! 
previous  set;  consequently  all  four  circles  meet  in  a| 
point,  and  we  can  now  state  our  proposition  as  follows : 

Given  four  straight  lines,  there  can  be  formed  from 
them  four  triangles  by  leaving  out  each  in  turn ;  the 
circles  which  circumscribe  these  four  triangles  meet  in 
a  point. 

This  proposition  is  the  third  of  a  series. 

If  we  take  any  two  straight  lines  they  determine  a 
point,  viz.  their  point  of  intersection. 

If  we  take  three  straight  lines  we  get  three  such 
points  of  intersection  ;  and  these  three  determine  a 
circle,  viz.  the  circle  circumscribing  the  triangle  formed 
by  the  three  lines. 

Four  straight  lines  determine  four  sets  of  three 
lines  by  leaving  out  each  in  turn;  and  the  four  circles 
belonging  to  these  sets  of  three  meet  in  a  point. 

In  the  same  way  five  lines  determine  five  sets  of 
four,  and  each  of  these  sets  of  four  gives  rise,  by  the 
proposition  just  proved,  to  a  point.  It  has  been  shown 
by  Miquel,  that  these  five  points  lie  on  the  same  circle. 

And  this  series  of  theorems  has  been  shown  l  to  be 
endless.  Six  straight  lines  determine  six  sets  of  five  by 
leaving  them  out  one  by  one.  Each  set  of  five  has,  by 

1  By  Prof.   Clifford   himself  in  the   Oxford,   Cambridge,  and  Dublin 
Messenger  of  Mathematics,  vol.  V.  p.  124.     See  his  Mathematical  Paptrs,  . 
pp.  51-54. 


SPACE.  81 

Miquel's  theorem,  a  circle  belonging  to  it.  These  six 
circles  meet  in  the  same  point,  and  so  on  for  ever.  Any 
even  number  (2n)  of  straight  lines  determines  a  point 
as  the  intersection  of  the  same  number  of  circles.  It 
we  take  one  line  more,  this  odd  number  (2w  +  l)  deter 
mines  as  many  sets  of  2n  lines,  and  to  each  of  these 
sets  belongs  a  point ;  these  2n  +  1  points  lie  on  a  circle. 

§  8.   The  Conic  Sections. 

The  shadow  of  a  circle  cast  on  a  flat  surface  by  a 
luminous  point  may  have  three  different  shapes.  These 
are  three  curves  of  great  historic  interest,  and  of  the 
utmost  importance  in  geometry  and  its  applications. 
The  lines  we  have  so  far  treated,  viz.  the  straight  line 
ind  circle,  are  special  cases  of  these  curves ;  and  we  may 
naturally  at  this  point  investigate  a  few  of  the  properties 
}f  the  more  general  forms. 

If  a  circular  disc  be  held  in  any  position  so  that  it 
:s  altogether  below  the  flame  of  a  candle,  and  its  shadow 
36  allowed  to  fall  011  the  table,  this  shadow  will  be  of 
in  oval  form,  except  in  two  extreme  cases,  in  one  of 
tfhich  it  also  is  a  circle,  and  in  the  other  is  a  straight 
ine.  The  former  of  these  cases  happens  when  the  disc 
s  held  parallel  to  the  table,  and  the  latter  when  the 
lisc  is  held  edgewise  to  the  candle ;  or,  in  other  words, 
s  so  placed  that  the  plane  in  which  it  lies  passes 
through  the  luminous  point.  The  oval  form  which, 
vith  these  two  exceptions,  the  shadow  presents  is  called 
(tn  ellipse  (i) .  The  paths  pursued  by  the  planets  round 
ihe  sun  are  of  this  form. 

If  the  circular  disc  be  now  held  so  that  its  highest 
I'oint  is  just  on  a  level  with  the  flame  of  the  candle,  the 
hadow  will  as  before  be  oval  at  the  end  near  the  candle; 

G 


82      THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

but  instead  of  closing  up  into  another  oval  end  as  we 
move  away  from  the  candle,  the  two  sides  of  it  will  con 
tinue  to  open  out  without  any  limit,  tending  however 
to  become  more  and  more  parallel.     This,  form  of  the 
shadow  is  called  a,  parabola  (ii).     It  is  very  nearly  the 
orbit  of  many  comets,  and  is  also  nearly  represented  b] 
the  path  of  a  stone  thrown  up  obliquely.    If  there  were 
no  atmosphere   to  retard  the   motion  of  the  stone  i 
would  exactly  describe  a  parabola. 


FIG.  26. 

If  we  now  hold  the  circular  disc  higher  up  still,  S( 
that  a  horizontal  plane  at  the  level  of  the  candle  flam 
divides  it  into  two  parts,  only  one  of  these  parts  wil 
cast  any  shadow  at  all,  and  that  will  be  a  curve  sucl, 
as  is  shown  in  the  figure,  the  two  sides  of  whicl 
diverge  in  quite  different  directions,  and  do  not,  as  iij 
the  case  of  the  parabola,  tend  to  become  parallel  (iii).  , 

But  although  for  physical  purposes  this  curve  is  th 
whole  of  the  shadow,  yet  for  geometrical  purposes  it  i| 
not  the  whole.     We  may  suppose  that  instead  of  bein 
a  shadow  our  curve  was  formed  by  joining  theluminoui 


SPACE.  83 

point  by  straight  lines  to  points  round  the  edge  of  the 
disc,  and  producing  these  straight  lines  until  they  meet 
the  table. 

This  geometrical  mode  of  construction  will  equally 
pply  to  the  part  of  the  circle  which  is  above  the  candle 
ame,  although  that  does  not  cast  any  shadow.     If  we 
oin  these  points  of  the  circle  to  the  candle  flame,  and 
rolong  the  joining  lines  beyond  it,  they  will  meet  the 
able  on  the  other  side  of  the  candle,  and  will  trace  out 
curve  there  which  is  exactly  similar  and  equal  to  the 
hysical  shadow  (iv).    We  may  call  this  the  anti-shadow 
r  geometrical  shadow  of  the  circle.     It  is  found  that  for 
eometrical  purposes  these  two  branches  must  be  con- 
idered  as  forming  only  one  curve,  which  is  called  an 
yperbola.     There  are  two  straight  lines  to  which  the 
urve  gets  nearer  and  nearer  the  further  away  it  goes 
•oni  their  point  of   intersection,  but  which  it  never 
ctually  meets.     For  this  reason  they  are  called  asymp- 
otes,  from    a  Greek    word    meaning    '  not    falling   to 
gether.'     These  lines  are  parallel  to  the  two  straight 
mes  which  join  the  candle  flame  to  the  two  points  of 
tie  circle  which  are  level  with  it. 

We  saw  some  time  ago  that  a  surface  was  formed 
y  the  motion  of  a  line.     Now  if  a  rigrht  line  in  its 

•/ 

notion  always  passes  through  one  fixed  point,  the  surface 
Inch  it  traces  out  is  called  a  cone,  and  the  fixed  point 
8  called  its  vertex.  And  thus  the  three  curves  which  we 
lave  just  described  are  called  conic  sections,  for  they 
nay  be  made  by  cutting  a  cone  by  a  plane.  In  fact,  it 
s  in  this  way  that  the  shadow  of  the  circle  is  formed ; 
or  if  we  consider  the  straight  lines  which  join  the 
andle  flame  to  all  parts  of  the  edge  of  the  circle  we  see 
hat  they  form  a  cone  whose  vertex  is  the  candle  flame 
-nd  whose  base  is  the  circle. 

u  2 


84      THE   COMMON   SEXSE   OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

We  must  suppose  these  lines  not  to  end  at  the  flame 
but  to  be  prolonged  through  it,  and  we  shall  so  gel 
what  would  commonly  be  called  two  cones  with  their 
points  together,  but  what  in  geometry  is  called  one 
conical  surface  having  two  sheets.  The  section  of  this 
conical  surface  by  the  horizontal  plane  of  the  table  is 
the  shadow  of  the  circle ;  the  sheet  in  which  the  circle 
lies  gives  us  the  ordinary  physical  shadow,  the  other 
sheet  (if  the  plane  of  section  meets  it)  gives  what  we 
have  called  the  geometrical  shadow. 

The  consideration  of  the  shadows  of  curves  is 
method  much  used  for  finding  out  their  properties,  for 
there  are  certain  geometrical  properties  which  are 
always  common  to  a  figure  and  its  shadow.  For  ex 
ample,  if  we  draw  on  a  sheet  of  glass  two  curves  which 
cut  one  another,  then  the  shadows  of  the  two  curves 
cast  through  the  sheet  of  glass  on  the  table  will  also  cui 
one  another.  The  shadow  of  a  straight  line  is  alway 
a  straight  line,  for  all  the  rays  of  light  from  the  flame 
through  various  points  of  a  straight  line  lie  in  a  plane 
and  this  plane  meets  the  plane  surface  of  the  table  in  a 
straight  line  which  is  the  shadow.  Consequently  iJ 
any  curve  is  cut  by  a  straight  line  in  a  certain  numbei 
of  points,  the  shadow  of  the  curve  will  be  cut  by  the 
shadow  of  the  straight  line  in  the  same  number  of  points 
Since  a  circle  is  cut  by  a  straight  line  in  two  points  01 
in  none  at  all,  it  follows  that  any  shadow  of  a  circle 
must  be  cut  by  a  straight  line  in  two  points  or  in  none 
at  all. 

When  a  straight  line  touches  a  circle  the  two  pointi 
of  intersection  coalesce  into  one  point.  We  see  thei 
that  this  must  also  be  the  case  with  any  shadow  of  the 
circle.  Again,  from  a  point  outside  the  circle  it  is  pos 
sible  to  draw  two  lines  which  touch  the  circle  ;  so  frorr 


I 


SPACE.  85 

a  point  outside  either  of  the  three  curves  which  we  have 
just  described,  it  is  possible  to  draw  two  lines  to  touch 
the  curve.  From  a  point  inside  the  circle  no  tangent 
can  be  drawn  to  it,  and  accordingly  no  tangent  can  be 
drawn  to  any  conic  section  from  a  point  inside  it. 

This  method  of  deriving  the  properties  of  one  curve 
from  those  of  another  of  which  it  is  the  shadow,  is 
called  the  method  of  projection. 

The  particular  case  of  it  which  is  of  the  greatest 
use  is  that  in  which  we  suppose  the  luminous  point 
by  which  the  shadow  is  cast  to  be  ever  so  far  away. 
Suppose,  for  example,  that  the  shadow  of  a  circle  held 
obliquely  is  cast  on  the  table  by  a  star  situated  directly 
overhead,  and  at  an  indefinitely  great  distance.  The 
lines  joining  the  star  to  all  the  points  of  the  circle  will 
then  be  vertical  lines,  and  they  will  no  longer  form  a 
cone  but  a  cylinder.  One  of  the  chief  advantages  of 
this  kind  of  projection  is  that  the  shadows  of  two 
parallel  lines  will  remain  parallel,  which  is  not  generally 
the  case  in  the  other  kind  of  projection.  The  shadow 
of  the  circle  which  we  obtain  now  is  always  an  ellipse ; 
and  we  are  able  to  find  out  in  this  way  some  very 
important  properties  of  the  curve,  the  corresponding 
properties  of  the  circle  being  for  the  most  part  evident 
at  a  glance  on  account  of  the  symmetry  of  the  figure. 

For  instance,  let  us  suppose  that  the  circle  whose 
shadow  we  are  examining  is  vertical,  and  let  uy  take  a 
vertical  diameter  of  it,  so  that  the  tangents  at  its  ends 
are  horizontal.  It  will  be  clear  from  the  symmetry  of 
the  figure  that  all  horizontal  lines  in  it  are  divided  into 
two  equal  parts  by  the  vertical  diameter,  or  we  may  s;iy 
that  the  diameter  of  the  circle  bisects  all  chords  parallel 
to  the  tangents  at  its  extremities.  When  the  shadow 
of  this  figure  is  cast  by  an  infinitely  distant  star  (which 


86      THE   COMMON   SENSE   OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

we  must  not  now  suppose  to  be  directly  overhead,  for 
then  the  shadow  would  be  merely  a  straight  line),  the 
point  of  bisection  of  the  shadow  of  any  straight  line 
is  the  shadow  of  the  middle  point  of  that  line,  and  thus 
we  learn  that  it  is  true  of  the  ellipse  that  any  line 
which  joins  the  points  of  contact  of  parallel  tangents 
bisects  all  chords  parallel  to  those  tangents.  Such  a 
line  is,  as  in  the  case  of  the  circle,  termed  a  diameter. 
Since  the  shadow  of  a  diameter  of  the  circle  is  a  dia 
meter  of  the  ellipse,  it  follows  that  all  diameters  of  the 
ellipse  pass  through  one  and  the  same  point,  namely, 
the  shadow  of  the  centre  of  the  circle ;  this  common 
intersection  of  diameters  is  termed  the  centre  also  of  the 
ellipse. 

Again,  a  horizontal  diameter  in  the  circle  just  con 
sidered  will  bisect  all  vertical  chords,  and  thus  we 
see  that  if  one  diameter  bisects  all  chords  parallel  to  a 
second,  the  second  will  bisect  all  chords  parallel  to  the 
first. 

The  method  of  projection  tells  us  that  this  is  also 
true  of  the  ellipse.  Such  diameters  ai*e  called  conjugate 
diameters,  but  they  are  no  longer  at  right  angles  in  the 
ellipse  as  they  were  in  the  case  of  the  circle. 

Since  the  shadow  of  a  circle  which  is  cast  in  this 
way  by  an  infinitely  distant  point  is  always  an  ellipse, 
we  cannot  use  the  same  method  in  order  to  obtain  the 
properties  of  the  hyperbola.  But  it  is  found  by  other 
methods  that  these  same  statements  are  true  of  the 
hyperbola  which  we  have  just  seen  to  be  true  of  the 
ellipse.  There  is  however  this  great  difference  be 
tween  the  two  curves.  The  centre  of  the  ellipse  is 
inside  it,  but  the  centre  of  the  hyperbola  is  outside  it. 
Also  all  lines  drawn  through  the  centre  of  the  ellipse 
nieet  the  curve  in  two  points,  but  it  is  only  certain 


SPACE.  87 

ines  through  the  centre  of  the  hyperbola  which  meet 
ihe  curve  at  all.  Of  any  two  conjugate  diameters  of 
ihe  hyperbola  one  meets  the  curve  and  the  other  does 

not.    But  it  still  remains  true  that  each  of  them  bisects 

all  chords  parallel  to  the  other. 

§  9.  On  Surfaces  of  the  Second  Order. 

We  began  with  the  consideration  of  the  simplest 
dnd  of  line  and  the  simplest  kind  of  surface,  the 
straight  line  and  the  plane ;  and  we  have  since  found 
out  some  of  the  properties  of  four  different  curved  lines 
— the  circle,  the  ellipse,  the  parabola,  and  the  hyperbola, 
jet  us  now  consider  some  curved  surfaces ;  and  first, 
ihe  surface  analogous  to  the  circle.  This  surface  is  the 

ere.  It  is  defined,  as  a  circle  is,  by  the  property 
ihat  all  its  points  are  at  the  same  distance  from  the 
centre. 

Perhaps  the  most  important  question  to  be  asked 
ibout  a  surface  is,  What  are  the  shapes  of  the  curved 
anes  in  which  it  is  met  by  other  surfaces,  especially 
jn.  the  case  when  these  other  surfaces  are  planes  ?  Now  a 
Mane  which  cuts  a  sphere  cuts  it,  as  can  easily  be  shown, 
n  a  circle.  This  circle,  as  we  move  the  plane  further  and 
drther  away  from  the  centre  of  the  sphere,  will  get 
imaller  and  smaller,  and  will  finally  contract  into  a 
joint.  In  this  case  the  plane  is  said  to  touch  the 
iphere;  and  we  notice  a  very  obvious  but  important 
?act,  that  the  sphere  then  lies  entirely  on  one  side  of 
ihe  plane.  If  the  plane  be  moved  still  further  away 
'rom  the  centre  it  will  not  meet  the  sphere  at  all. 

Again,  if  we  take  a  point  outside  the  sphere  we  can 
Iraw  a  number  of  planes  to  pass  through  it  and  touch  the 
phere,  and  all  the  points  in  which  they  touch  it  lie  on 


88      THE   COMMON   SENSE   OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

a  circle.  Also  a  cone  can  be  drawn  whose  vertex  is 
the  point,  and  which  touches  the  sphere  all  round  the 
circle  in  which  these  planes  touch  it.  This  is  called 
the  tangent-cone  of  the  point.  It  is  clear  that  from  a 
point  inside  the  sphere  no  tangent-cone  can  be  drawn. 

Similar  properties  belong  also  to  certain  other  sur 
faces  which  resemble  the  sphere  in  the  fact  that  they 
are  met  by  a  straight  line  in  two  points  at  most ;  such 
surfaces  are  on  this  account  called  of  the  second  order. 

Just  as  we  may  suppose  an  ellipse  to  be  got  from 
a  circle  by  pulling  it  out  in  one  direction,  so  we  may 
get  a  spheroid  from  a  sphere  either  by  pulling  it  out  so 
as  to  make  a  thing  like  an  egg,  or  by  squeezing  it  so 
as  to  make  a  thing  like  an  orange.  Each  of  these 
forms  is  symmetrical  about  one  diameter,  but  not  about 
all.  A  figure  like  an  orange,  for  example,  or  like  the 
earth,  has  a  diameter  through  its  poles  less  than  any 
diameter  in  the  plane  of  its  equator,  but  all  diameters  in 
its  equator  are  equal.  Again,  a  spheroid  like  an  egg 
has  all  the  diameters  through  its  equator  equal  to  one 
another,  but  the  diameter  through  its  poles  is  longer 
than  any  other  diameter. 

If  we  now  take  an  orange  or  an  egg  and  make  its 
equator  into  an  ellipse  instead  of  a  circle,  say  by  pull 
ing  out  the  equator  of  the  orange  or  squeezing  the 
equator  of  the  egg,  so  that  the  surface  has  now  three 
diameters  at  right  angles  all  unequal  to  one  another, 
we  obtain  what  is  called  an  ellipsoid.  This  surface 
plays  the  same  part  in  the  geometry  of  surfaces  that  the 
ellipse  does  in  the  geometry  of  curves.  Just  as  every 
plane  which  cuts  a  sphere  cuts  it  in  a  circle,  so  every 
plane  which  cuts  an  ellipsoid  cuts  it  in  an  ellipse.  It 
is  indeed  possible  to  cut  an  ellipsoid  by  a  plane  so  that 
the  section  shall  be  a  circle,  but  this  must  be  regarded 


SPACE.  89 

as  a  particular  kind  of  ellipse,  viz.  an  ellipse  with 
two  equal  axes.  Again,  just  as  was  the  case  with  the 
sphere,  we  can  draw  a  set  of  planes  through  an  exter 
nal  point  all  of  which  touch  the  ellipsoid.  Their  points 
of  contact  lie  on  a  certain  ellipse,  and  a  cone  can  be 
drawn  which  has  the  external  point  for  its  vertex  and 
touches  the  ellipsoid  all  round  this  ellipse.  The  ellip 
soid  resembles  a  sphere  in  this  respect  also,  that  when 


it  is  touched  by  a  plane  it  lies  wholly  on  one  side  of 
:hat  plane. 

There  are  also  surfaces  which  bear  to  the  hyperbola 
ind  the  parabola  relations  somewhat  similar  to  those 
aorne  to  the  circle  by  the  sphere,  arid  to  the  ellipse  by 
:he  ellipsoid.  We  will  now  consider  one  of  them,  a 
surface  with  many  singular  properties. 

Let  A  BCD  be  a  figure  of  card-board  having  four 
jqual  sides,  and  let  it  be  half  cut  through  all  along  B  D, 


90       THE    COMMON    SENSE    OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

so  that  the  triangles  A  B  D,  c  B  D  can  turn  about  the  line 
B  D.  Then  let  holes  be  made  along  the  four  sides  of  it  at 
equal  distances,  and  let  these  holes  be  joined  by  threads 
of  silk  parallel  to  the  sides.  If  now  the  figure  be  bent 
about  the  line  B  D  and  the  silks  are  pulled  tight  it  will 
present  an  appearance  like  that  in  fig.  27,  resembling 
a  saddle,  or  the  top  of  a  mountain  pass. 

This  surface  is  composed  entirely  of  straight  lines, 
and  there  are  two  sets  of  these  straight  lines ;  one  set 
which  was  originally  parallel  to  A  B,  and  the  other  set 
which  was  originally  parallel  to  A  D. 

A  section  of  the  figure  through  A  c  and  the  middle 
point  of  B  D  will  be  a  parabola  with  its  concave  side 
turned  upwards. 

A  section  through  B  D  and  the  middle  point  of  A  0 
will  be  another  parabola  with  its  concave  side  turned 
downwards,  the  common  vertex  of  these  parabolas 
being  the  summit  of  the  pass. 

The  tangent  plane  at  this  point  will  cut  the  surface 
in  two  straight  lines,  while  part  of  the  surface  will  be 
above  the  tangent  plane  and  part  below  it.  We  may 
regard  this  tangent  plane  as  a  horizontal  plane  at  the 
top  of  a  mountain  pass.  If  we  travel  over  the  pass,  we 
come  up  on  one  side  to  the  level  of  the  plane  and  then 
go  down  on  the  other.  But  if  we  go  down  from  a 
mountain  on  the  right  and  go  up  the  mountain  on  the 
left,  we  shall  always  be  above  the  horizontal  plane.  A 
section  by  a  horizontal  plane  a  little  above  this  tangent 
plane  will  be  a  hyperbola  whose  asymptotes  will  be 
parallel  to  the  straight  lines  in  which  the  tangent  plane 
meets  the  surface.  A  section  by  a  horizontal  plane  a 
little  below  will  also  be  a  hyperbola  with  its  asymptotes 
parallel  to  these  lines,  but  it  will  be  situated  in  the 
other  pair  of  angles  formed  by  these  asymptotes.  If 


SPACE.  9 1 

suppose  the  cutting  plane  to  move  downwards  from 
a  position  above  the  tangent  plane  (remaining  always 
lorizontal),  then  we  shall  see  the  two  branches  of  the 
irst  hyperbola  approach  one  another  and  get  sharper 
and  sharper  until  they  meet  and  become  simply  two 
crossing  straight  lines.  These  lines  will  then  have 
;heir  corners  rounded  off  and  will  be  divided  in  the 
other  direction  and  open  out  into  the  second  hyper- 
x>la. 

This  leads  us  to  suppose  that  a  pair  of  intersecting 
straight  lines  is  only  a  particular  case  of  a  hyperbola, 
and  that  we  may  consider  the  hyperbola  as  derived 
roin  the  two  crossing  straight  lines  by  dividing  them 
at  their  point  of  intersection  and  rounding  off  the 
corners. 

I  10.  How  to  form  Curves  of  the  Third  and  Higher  Orders. 

The  method  of  the  preceding  paragraph  may  be  ex- 
;ended  so  as  to  discover  the  forms  of  new  curves  by 
Hitting  known  curves  together.  By  a  mode  of  expres 
sion  which  sounds  paradoxical,  yet  is  found  convenient, 
a  straight  line  is  called  a  curve  of  the  first  order,  because 
.t  can  be  met  by  another  straight  line  in  only  one 
K)int ;  but  two  straight  lines  taken  together  are  called 
a.  curve  of  the  second  order,  because  they  can  be  met 
by  a  straight  line  in  two  points.  The  circle,  and  its 
hadows,  the  ellipse,  parabola,  and  hyperbola,  are  also 
sailed  curves  of  the  second  order,  because  they  can  be 
met  by  a  straight  line  in  two  points,  but  not  in  more 
than  two  points ;  and  we  see  that  by  this  process  of 
rounding  off  the  corners  and  the  method  of  projection 
we  can  derive  all  these  curves  of  the  second  order  from 
pair  of  straight  lines. 


92      THE   COMMON   SEXSE   OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 


A  similar  process  enables  us  to  draw  curves  of  the 
third  order.  An  ellipse  and  a  straight  line  taken  to 
gether  form  a  curve  of  the  third  order.  If  now  we 
round  off  the  corners  at  both  the  points  where  they 
meet  we  obtain  (fig.  28)  a  curve  consisting  of  an  oval 
and  a  sinuous  portion  called  a  '  snake.'  Now  just  as 
when  we  move  a  plane  which  cuts  a  sphere  away  from 
the  centre,  the  curve  of  intersection  shrinks  up  into  a 


H 


.  28. 


(i.)  Full  loop  and  snake. 
(ii.)  Shrunk  loop  and  snake. 


(iii.)  The  loop  has  shrunk  to  a  point, 
(iv.)  Snake  only. 


point  and  then  disappears,  so  we  can  vary  our  curve  of 
the  third  order  so  as  to  make  the  oval  which  belongs  to 
it  shrink  up  into  a  point,  s*nd  then  disappear  altogether,  I 
leaving  only  the  sinuous  part,  but  no  variation  will  get  i 
rid  of  the  '  snake.' 

We  may,  if  we  like,  only  round  off  the  corners  at 
one  of  the  intersections  of  the  straight  line  and  the 
ellipse,  and  we  then  have  a  curve  of  the  third  order 
crossing  itself,  having  a  knot  or  double  point  (fig.  29)  ; 
and  we  can  further  suppose  this  loop  to  shrink  up,  and 
the  curve  will  then  be  found  to  have  a  sharp  point  or 
cusp. 


SPACE. 


93 


It  was  shown  by  Newton  that  all  curves  of  the  third 
order  might  be  derived  as  shadows  from  the  five  forms 


(ivr) 


which  we  have  just  mentioned,  viz.  the  oval  and  snake, 
the  point  and  snake,  the  snake  alone,  the  form  with  a 
mot,  and  the  form  with  a  cusp. 

In  the  same  way  curves  of  the  fourth  order  may  be 
jot  by  combining  together  two  ellipses.    If  we  suppose 


FIG.  30. 


them  to  cross  each  other  in  four  points  we  may  round 
off  all  the  corners  at  once  and  so  obtain  two  different 
forms,  either  four  ovals  all  outside  one  another  or  an 


94      THE   COMMON    SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

oval  with,  four  dints  in  it,  and  another  oval  inside  it 
(fig.  30). 

But  the  number  of  forms  of  curves  of  the  fourth 
order  is  so  great  that  it  has  never  yet  been  completely 
catalogued;  and  curves  of  higher  orders  are  of  still 
more  varied  shapes. 


95 


CHAPTER  III. 

QUANTITY. 

§  1.   The  Measurement  of  Quantities. 

WE  considered  at  the  beginning  of  the  first  chapter, 
on  Number,  the  process  of  counting  things  which  are 
separate  from  one  another,  such  as  letters  or  men  or 
sheep,  and  we  found  it  to  be  a  fundamental  property  of 
this  counting  that  the  result  was  not  affected  by  the 
order  in  which  the  things  to  be  counted  were  taken ; 
that  one  of  the  things,  that  is,  was  as  good  as  another 
at  any  stage  of  the  process. 

We  may  also  count  things  which  are  not  separate 
but  all  in  one  piece.  For  example,  we  may  say  that  a 
room  is  sixteen  feet  broad.  And  in  order  to  count  the 
number  of  feet  in  the  breadth  of  this  room  we  should 
probably  take  a  foot  rule  and  measure  off  first  a  foot 
close  to  the  wall,  then  another  beginning  where  that 
ended,  and  so  on  until  we  reached  the  opposite  wall. 
Now  when  these  feet  are  thus  marked  off  they  may, 
just  like  any  other  separate  things,  be  counted  in 
whatever  order  we  please,  and  the  number  of  them 
will  always  be  sixteen. 

But  this  is  not  all  the  variety  in  the  process  of 
counting  which  is  possible.  For  suppose  that  we  take 
a  stick  whose  length  is  equal  to  the  breadth  of  the 
room.  Then  we  may  cut  out  a  foot  of  it  wherever  we 
please,  and  join  the  ends  together.  And  if  we  tlu-n 


'JO      THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

cut  out  another  foot  from  any  part  of  the  remainder 
and  join  the  ends,  and  repeat  the  process  fifteen  times, 
we  shall  find  that  there  will  always  be  a  foot  length 
left  when  the  last  two  ends  are  joined  together.  So, 
when  we  are  counting  things  that  are  all  in  one  piece, 
like  the  length  of  the  stick  or  the  breadth  of  the  room, 
not  only  is  the  order  in  which  we  count  the  feet  im 
material,  but  also  the  position  of  the  actual  feet  which 
we  count. 

Again,  if  we  say  that  a  packet  contains  a  pound,  or 
sixteen  ounces,  of  tea,  we  mean  that  if  we  take  any 
ounce  of  it  out,  then  any  other  ounce  out  of  what  is 
left,  and  so  on  until  we  have  taken  away  fifteen  ounces, 
there  will  always  be  an  ounce  left. 

If  I  say  that  I  have  been  writing  for  fifteen  minutes 
it  will  of  course  have  been  impossible  actually  to  count 
these  minutes  except  in  the  order  in  which  they  really 
followed  one  another,  but  it  will  still  be  true  that,  if 
any  separate  fourteen  minutes  had  been  marked  off 
during  that  interval  of  time,  the  remainder  of  it,  made 
np  of  the  interstices  between  these  minutes,  would 
amount  on  the  whole  to  one  minute. 

In  all  these  cases  we  have  been  counting  things  that 
hang  together  in  one  piece  ;  and  we  find  that  we  may 
choose  at  will  not  only  the  order  of  counting  but  even 
the  things  that  we  count  without  altering  the  result. 
This  process  is  called  the  measurement  of  quantities. 

But  now  suppose  that  when  we  measure  the  breadth 
of  a  room  we  find  it  to  be  not  sixteen  feet  exactly,  but 
sixteen  feet  and  something  over.  It  may  be  sixteen 
feet  and  five  inches.  And  if  so,  in  order  to  measure 
the  something  over,  we  merely  repeat  the  same  pro 
cess  as  before ;  only  that  instead  of  counting  feet  we 
count  inches,  which  are  smaller  than  feet.  If  the 


QT'AXTITY.  97 

breadth  is  found  not  to  be  an  exact  number  of  inches, 

but  that  something  is  left  beside  the  five  inches,  we 

might   measure    that  in  eighths    of  an    inch.     There 

might,  for  example,  be  three  eighths  of  an  inch  over. 

But  there  is  no  security  that  the  process  will  end  here  ; 

for  the  breadth  of  the  room  may  not  contain  an  exact 

number  of  eighths   of  an  inch.     Still  it  may  be  said 

hat  nobody  wants  to  know  the  breadth  of  a  room  more 

xactly  than  to  within  an  eighth  of  an  inch. 

Au'uin,  when  we  measure  a  quantity  of  tea  it  may  be 
learly,  but  not  exactly,  sixteen  ounces;  there  maybe 
-omething  over.  This  remainder  we  shall  then  measure 
n  grains.  And  here,  as  before,  we  are  repeating  \]\(. 
ame  process  by  which  we  count  things  which  are  all  in 
me  piece;  only  we  count  grains,  which  are  smaller 
hings  than  ounces.  There  may  still  not  be  an  exact 
lumber  of  grains  in  the  packet  of  tea,  but  then  nobody 
jvants  to  know  the  weight  of  a  packet  of  tea  so  nea:  iv 
is  to  a  grain. 

And  it  is  the  same  with  time.  A  geological  period 
nay,  if  we  are  very  accurate,  be  specified  in  hundreds 
)f  centuries ;  the  length  of  a  war  in  years  ;  the  time  of 
leparture  of  a  train  to  within  a  minute  ;  the  moment 
)f  an  eclipse  to  a  second  ;  our  care  being,  in  each  ruse, 
nerely  to  secure  that  the  measurement  is  accurate 
jnough  for  the  purpose  we  have  in  hand. 

To  sum  up.  There  is  in  common  use  a  rouirh  or 
ipproximate  way  of  describing  quantities,  which  con 
sists  in  saying  how  many  times  the  quantity  to  be 
lescribed  contains  a  certain  standard  quantity,  and  in 
leglecting  whatever  may  remain.  The  smaller  the 
standard  quantity  is  the  more  accurate  is  the  pro. 
}ut  it  is  in  general  no  better  than  an  approximation. 

If  then  we  want  to  describe  a  quantity  accurately 

H 


98      THE   COMMON   SENSE    OP   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

and  not  by  a  mere  approximation,  what  are  we  to  do? 
There  is  no  way  of  doing  this  in  words ;  the  only  pos 
sible  method  is  to  carry  about  either  the  quantity  itself 
or  some  other  quantity  which  shall  serve  to  represent 
it.  For  instance,  to  represent  the  exact  length  and 
breadth  of  a  room  we  may  draw  it  upon  a  scale  of,  say, 
one  inch  to  a  foot  and  carry  this  drawing  about. 

Here  we  are  representing  a  length  by  means  of 
another  length ;  but  it  is  not  necessary  to  represent 
weights  by  means  of  weights,  or  times  by  means  of 
times ;  they  are  both  in  practice  represented  by  lengths. 
When  a  chemist,  wishing  to  weigh  with  great  delicacy, 
has  gone  as  near  as  he  can  with  the  drachms  which  he 
puts  into  his  scales,  he  hangs  a  little  rider  upon  the 
beam  of  the  scale,  and  the  distance  of  this  rider  from 
the  middle  indicates  how  much  weight  there  is  over. 
And,  if  we  suppose  the  balance  to  be  perfectly  true, 
and  that  no  friction  or  other  source  of  error  has  to  be 
taken  into  account,  it  indicates  this  weight  with  real 
accuracy. 

Here  then  is  a  case  in  which  a  weight  is  indicated 
by  a  length,  namely,  the  distance  from  the  centre  of  the 
scale  to  the  rider.  Again,  we  habitually  represent  time 
by  means  of  a  clock,  and  in  this  case  the  minute  hand 
moves  by  a  succession  of  small  jerks,  possibly  twice  a 
second.  Such  a  clock  will  only  reckon  time  in  half 
seconds,  and  can  tell  us  nothing  about  smaller  intervals 
than  this.  But  we  may  easily  conceive  of  a  clock  in 
which  the  motion  of  the  minute  hand  is  steady,  and  not 
made  by  jerks.  In  this  case  the  interval  of  time  since 
the  end  of  the  last  hour  will  be  accurately  represented 
by  the  length  round  the  outer  circle  of  the  clocls 
measured  from  the  top  of  it  to  the  point  of  the  minutf 
hand.  And  we  notice  that  here  also  the  quantity 


QUANTITY.  99 

which  is  measured  in  this  way  by  a  length  is  probably 
not  the  whole  quantity  which  was  to  be  estimated,  but 
only  that  which  remains  over  after  the  greater  part  has 
been  counted  by  reference  to  some  standard  quantity. 

We  may  thus  describe  weight  and  time,  and  indeed 
uantities  of  any  kind  whatever,  by  means  of  the  lengths 
f  lines ;  and  in  what  follows,  therefore,  we  shall  only 
peak  of  quantities  of  length  as  completely  representing 
neasurable  things  of  any  sort. 

§  2.   The  Addition  and  Subtraction  of  Quantities. 

For  the  addition  of  two  lengths  it  is  plainly  sutHrient 
o  place  them  end  to  end  in  the  same  line.  And  we 
must  notice  that,  as  was  the  case  with  counting,  so  now, 
he  possible  variety  in  the  mode  of  adding  is  far  greater 
n  the  case  of  two  quantities  than  in  the  case  of  two 
numbers.  For  either  of  the  lengths,  the  aggregate 
of  which  we  wish  to  measure,  may  be  cut  up  into  any 
lumber  of  parts,  and  these  may  be  inserted  at  any 
>oints  we  please  of  the  other  length,  without  any  change 
n  the  result  of  our  addition. 

Or  the  same  may  be  seen,  perhaps  more  clearly,  by 
reference  to  the  idea  of  '  steps.'  Suppose  we  Lave  a 
straight  line  with  a  mark  upon  it  agreed  on  as  a  start 
ing-point,  and  a  series  of  marks  ranged  at  equal  distances 
ilong  the  line  and  numbered  1,  2,  :>,  4.  .  .  .  Then  any 
particular  number  is  shown  by  making  an  index  point  to 
he  right  place  on  the  line.  And  to  add  or  subtract 
my  other  number  from  this,  we  have  only  to  make  the 
ndex  move  forwards  or  backwards  over  the  con-espoml- 
ng  number  of  divisions.  But  in  the  case  of  lengths  we 
ire  not  restricted  to  the  places  which  are  marked  on  the 
scale.  Any  length  is  shown  by  carrying  the  index  to  a 

u  2 


TOO      THE    COMMON    SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

place  whose  distance  from  the  starting-point  is  the 
length  in  question  (of  which  places  there  may  be 
as  many  as  we  please  between  any  two  points  which 
correspond  to  consecutive  numbers),  and  another  length 
is  added  or  subtracted  by  making  the  index  take  a 
'  step  '  forwards  or  backwards  of  the  necessary  amount. 
It  is  seen  at  once  that,  for  quantities  in  general  as 
well  as  for  numbers,  a  succession  of  given  steps  may 
be  made  in  any  order  we  please  and  the  result  will 
always  be  the  same. 


§  3.   The  Multiplication  and  Division  of  Quantities. 

We  have  already  considered  cases  in  which  a  quan 
tity  is  multiplied ;  that  is  to  say,  in  which  a  certain 
number  of  equal  quantities  are  added  together,  a  process 
called  the  multiplication  of  one  of  them  by  that  number. 
Thus  the  length  sixteen  feet  is  the  result  of  multiplying 
one  foot  by  sixteen. 

We  may  now  ask  the  inverse  question :  Given  two 
lengths,  what  number  must  be  used  to  multiply  one  of 
them  in  order  to  produce  the  other  ?  And  it  has  been 
implied  in  what  we  have  said  about  the  measurement  of 
quantities  that  it  is  only  in  special  cases  that  we  can  find 
a  number  which  will  be  the  answer  to  this  question.  If 
we  ask,  for  example,  by  what  number  a  foot  must  be 
multiplied  in  order  to  produce  fifteen  inches,  the  word 
'  number'  requires  to  have  its  meaning  altered  and  ex 
tended  before  we  can  give  an  answer.  We  know  that 
an  inch  must  be  multiplied  by  fifteen  in  order  to  become 
fifteen  inches.  We  may  therefore  first  ask  by  what 
a  foot  must  be  multiplied  in  order  to  produce  an  inch. 
And  the  question  seems  at  first  absurd ;  because  an 
inch  must  be  multiplied  by  twelve  in  order  to  give  a 


QUANTITY.  101 

foot,  and  a  foot  has  to  be,  not  multiplied  at  all,  but 
divided  by  twelve,  in  order  to  become  an  inch. 

In  order  then  to  turn  a  foot  into  fifteen  inches,  we 
must  go  through  the  following  process  ;  we  must  divide 
it  into  twelve  equal  parts  and  take  fifteen  of  them  ;  or, 
shortly,  divide  by  twelve  and  multiply  by  fifteen.  Or 
we  may  produce  the  same  result  by  performing  the 
steps  of  our  process  in  the  other  order  :  we  may  first 
multiply  by  fifteen,  so  that  we  get  fifteen  feet,  and  then 
divide  this  length  into  twelve  equal  parts,  each  of  which 
will  be  fifteen  inches. 

Now  if  instead  of  inventing  a  new  name  for  this 
compound  operation  we  choose  to  call  it  by  the  old  name 
of  multiplication,  we  shall  be  able  to  speak  of  multiply 
ing  a  foot  so  as  to  get  fifteen  inches.  The  operation  of 
multiplying  by  fifteen  and  dividing  by  twelve  is  written 
thus:  -j :";  ;  and  so,  to  change  a  foot  into  fifteen  inches, 
we  multiply  by  the  fraction  |-f .  Of  this  fraction  the 
upper  number  (15)  is  termed  the  numerator,  the  lower 
12)  the  dunomliKitor. 

Now  it  was  explained  in  the  first  chapter,  that 
;he  formula}  of  arithmetic  and  algebra  are  capable  of  a 
louble  interpretation.  For  instance,  such  a  symbol 
is  3  meant,  in  the  first  place,  a  number  of  letters  or 
lien,  or  any  other  things  ;  but  afterwards  was  regarded 
is  meaning  an  operation,  namely,  that  of  trebling  any- 
;hing.  And  so  now  the  symbol  }  ":  may  betaken  either 
meaning  '  so  much  '  of  a  foot,  or  as  meaning  the 
peration  by  which  a  foot  is  changed  into  fifteen  inches. 
The  degree  in  which  one  quantity  is  greater  or  less 
,,;|;han  another;  or,  to  put  it  more  precisely,  that  amount. 
f  stretching  or  squeezing  which  must  be  applied  to  the 
atter  in  order  to  produce  the  former,  is  called  the  rat  in 
f  the  two  quantities.  If  a  and  b  are  any  two  lengths, 


J02      THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

the  ratio  of  a  to  &  is  the  operation  of  stretching  or 
squeezing  which  will  make  b  into  a;  and  this  operation 
can  be  always  approximately,  and  sometimes  exactly, 
represented  by  means  of  numbers. 


§  4.   The  Arithmetical  Expression  of  Ratios. 

For  the  approximate  expression  of  ratios  there 
are  two  methods  in  use.  In  each,  as  in  measuring 
quantities  in  general,  we  proceed  by  using  standards 
which  are  taken  smaller  and  smaller  as  we  go  on.  In 
the  first,  these  standards  are  chosen  according  to  a  fixed 
law ;  in  the  second,  our  choice  is  suggested  by  the  par 
ticular  ratio  which  we  are  engaged  in  measuring. 

The  first  method  consists  in  using  a  series  of  stan 
dards  each  of  which  is  a  tenth  part  of  the  preceding. 
Thus  to  express  the  ratio  of  fifteen  inches  to  a  foot,  we 
proceed  thus.  The  fifteen  inches  contain  a  foot  once, 
and  there  is  a  piece  of  length  three  inches,  or  a  quar 
ter  of  a  foot,  left  over.  This  quarter  of  a  foot  is  then 
measured  in  tenths  of  a  foot,  and  we  find  that  it  is 
2-tenths,  with  a  piece — which  proves  to  be  half  a  tenth 
— over.  So,  if  we  chose  to  neglect  this  half-tenth  we 
should  call  the  ratio  1 2-tenths,  or  as  we  write  it 
1-2.  But  if  we  do  not  neglect  the  half -tenth,  it  has  to 
be  measured  in  hundredths  of  a  foot ;  of  which  it  makes 
5  exactly.  So  that  the  result  is  125  hundredths,  or 
1'25,  accurately. 

Again  we  will  try  to  express  in  this  way  the  length 
of  the  diagonal  of  a  square  in  terms  of  a  side.  We  find 
at  once  that  the  diagonal  contains  the  side  once,  with  a 
piece  over  :  so  that  the  ratio  in  question  is  1  together 
with  some  fraction.  If  we  now  measure  this  remaining 
piece  in  tenth  parts  of  a  side  we  shall  find  that  it  contains 


QUANTITY.  103 

4  of  them,  with  something  left.  Thus  the  ratio  of  the 
diagonal  to  the  side  may  be  approximately  expressed  by 
14- tenths,  or  1*4.  If  we  now  measure  the  piece  left  over 
in  hundredth  parts  of  the  side  we  shall  find  that  it  con 
tains  one  and  a  bit.  Thus  141-hundredths,  or  1'41  is  a 
more  accurate  description  of  the  ratio.  And  this  bit  can 
be  shown  to  contain  4-thousandths  of  the  side,  and  a 
bit  over ;  so  that  we  arrive  at  a  still  more  accurate 
value,  1414-thousandths,  or  1'414.  And  this  process 
might  be  carried  on  to  any  degree  of  accuracy  that  was 
required;  but  in  the  present  case,  unlike  that  con 
sidered  before,  it  would  never  end ;  for  the  ratio  of  the 
diagonal  of  a  square  to  its  side  is  one  which  cannot  be 
accurately  expressed  by  means  of  numbers. 

The  other  method  of  approximation  differs  from  tlu> 
one  just  explained  in  this  respect — that  the  successively 
smaller  and  smaller  standard  quantities  in  terms  of 
which  we  measure  the  successive  remainders  are  not 
fixed  quantities,  an  inch,  a  tenth  of  an  inch,  u. 
hundredth  of  an  inch,  and  so  on;  but  are  suggested 
to  us  in  the  course  of  the  approximation  itself. 

We  begin,  as  we  did  before,  by  finding  how  many 
times  the  lesser  quantity  is  contained  in  the  greater, 
say,  the  side  of  a  square  in  its  diagonal.  The  answer 
in  this  case  is,  once  and  a  piece  over.  Let  the  piece 
left  over  be  called  a.  We  then  go  on  to  try  how  many 
times  this  remainder,  a,  is  contained  in  the  side  of  the 
square.  It  is  contained  twice,  and  there  is  a  remainder, 
say  6.  We  then  find  how  many  times  b  is  contained  in 
a.  Again  twice,  with  a  piece  over,  say  c.  And  this 
process  is  repeated  as  often  as  we  please,  or  until  no 
remainder  is  left.  It  will,  in  the  present  case,  be  found 
that  each  remainder  is  contained  twice,  with  something 
over,  in  the  previous  remainder. 


104      THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF    THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

Let  us  now  inquire  how  this  process  enables  us  to 
find  successive  approximations  to  the  ratio  of  the 
diagonal  to  the  side  of  the  square. 

Suppose,  first,  that  the  piece  a  had  been  exactly  half 
the  length  of  the  side ;  that  is,  that  we  may  neglect  the 
remainder  b.  Then  the  diagonal  would  be  equal  to  the 
side  together  with  half  the  side,  that  is,  to  three-halves 
of  the  side. 

Next  let  us  include  b  in  our  approximation,  but 
neglect  c ;  that  is,  let  us  suppose  that  b  is  exactly  one  • 
half  of  a.  Then  the  side  contains  a  twice,  and  half  of 
a ;  that  is  to  say,  contains  five-halves  of  a  ;  or  a  is  two- 
fifths  of  the  side.  But  the  diagonal  contains  the  side 
together  with  or,  that  is,  contains  the  side  and  two-fifths 
of  the  side,  or  seven-fifths  of  the  side.  The  piece 
neglected  is  here  less  than  6,  and  6  is  one-fifth  of  the 
side  of  the  square. 

Again,  let  us  include  c  in  our  approximation,  and 
suppose  it  to  be  exactly  one  half  of  6.  Then  a,  which 
contains  b  twice  with  c  over,  will  be  five-halves  Of  6, 
that  is  b  will  be  two-fifths  of  a.  Hence  the  side  will 
contain  twice  a  and  two-fifths  of  a,  that  is,  twelve-fifths  - 
of  a ;  so  that  a  is  five-twelfths  of  the  side.  And  the 
diagonal  is  equal  to  the  side  together  with  a;  that  is; 
to  seventeen-twelfths  of  the  side.  Also  this  approxi-. 
nuition  is  closer  than  the  preceding,  for  the  piece 
neglected  is  now  less  than  c,  which  is  one-half  of  b, 
which  is  two-fifths  of  a,  which  is  five-twelfths  of  the 
side  ;  so  that  it  is  less  than  one-twelfth  of  the  side. 

By  continuing  this  process  we  may  find  an  approxi 
mation  of  any  required  degree  of  accuracy. 

The   first   method  of   approximation  is  called  the 
method  of  decimals;  the  second,  that  of  continued  frac-- 
tions. 


QUANTITY.  105 


§  5.  The  Fourth  Proportional. 

One  of  the  chief  differences  between  quantities  and 
numbers  is  that,  while  the  division  of  one  number  by 
another  is  only  possible  when  the  first  number  happens 
to  be  a  multiple  of  the  other,  in  the  case  of  quantities 
it  appears,  and  we  are  indeed  accustomed  to  assume, 
that  any  quantity  may  be  divided  by  any  number  wo 
like;  that  is  to  say,  any  length — quantities  of  all  kinds 
being  represented  by  lengths — may  be  divided  into  anv 
given  number  of  equal  parts.  And,  if  division  is  always 
possible,  that  compound  operation  made  up  of  multi 
plication  and  division  which  we  have  called  '  multiplv- 
ing  by  a  fraction '  must  also  be  always  possible ;  for 
example,  we  can  find  five-twelfths  not  only  of  a  foot 
but  of  any  other  length  that  we  like. 

The  question  now  naturally  arises  whether  that 
general  operation  of  stretching  or  squeezing  which  we 
have'called  a  ratio  can  be  applied  to  all  quantities  alike. 
If  we  have  three  lengths,  a,  I,  c,  there  is  a  certain 
operation  of  stretching  or  squeezing  which  will  convert 
a  into  b.  Can  the  same  operation  be  performed  upon  c 
with  the  re-suit  of  producing  a  fourth  quantity  <?,  such 
that  the  ratio  of  c  to  d  shall  be  the  same  as  the  ratio  of 
a  to  b  ?  We  assume  that  this  quantity — tlae  fourth 
proportional,  as  it  is  called — does  always  exist;  and 
this  assumption,  as  it  really  lies  at  the  base  of  all 
subsequent  mathematics,  is  of  so  great  importance  as 
to  deserve  further  study. 

We  shall  find  that  it  is  really  included  in  the  second 
of  the  two  assumptions  that  we  made  in  the  chapter 
about  space  ;  namely,  that  figures  of  the  same  shapu 
may  be  constructed  of  different  sixes.  We  found,  in 


106       THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT    SCIENCES. 

considering  this  point,  that  it  was  sufficient  to  take  the 
case  of  triangles  of  different  sizes  of  which  the  angles 
were  equal;  and  showed  that  one  triangle  might  be 
made  into  another  of  the  same  shape  by  the  equal 
magnifying  of  all  its  three  sides ;  that  is  to  say,  when 
two  triangles  have  the  same  angles,  the  three  ratios  of 
either  side  of  one  to  the  corresponding  side  of  the  other 
are  equal.  If  this  is  true,  it  is  clear  that  the  problem  of 
finding  the  fourth  proportionalisreduccd  to  that  of  draw 
ing  two  triangles  of  the  same  shape.  Thus,  for  example, 
let  A  B  and  A  c  represent  the  first  two  given  quantities, 
and  A  D  the  third  (fig.  31)  ;  and  let  it  be  required  to 
find  that  quantity  which  is  got  from  A  D  by  the  same 


operation  of  stretching  as  is  required  to  turn  A  B  into 
A  c.  Suppose  that  we  join  B  D,  and  draw  the  line  c  E 
making  the  angle  ACE  equal  to  the  angle  A  B  D.  The  two 
triangles  ABD  and  ACE  are  now  of  the  same  shape,  and 
consequently  ACE  can  be  got  from  ABD  by  the  equal 
stretching  of  all  its  sides ;  that  is  to  say,  the  stretching 
which  makes  A  B  into  A  c  is  the  same  as  the  stretching 
which  makes  A  D  into  AE.  A  E  is  therefore  the  fourth  pro 
portional  required. 

To  render  these  matters  clearer,  it  is  well  that  we 
should  get  a  more  exact  notion  of  what  we  mean  by  the 
fourth  proportional.  We  have  so  far  only  described  it 
as  something  \\hich  is  got  from  A  D  by  the  same  process 
which  makes  A  B  into  A  c.  In  what  way  are  we  to  tell 
whether  the  process  is  the  same?  We  might,  if  we 


QUANTITY.  107 

liked,  give  a  geometrical  definition  of  it,  founded  upon 
the  construction  just  explained ;  and  say  that  the  ratio 
of  A  D  to  A  E  shall  be  called  '  equal '  to  the  ratio  of  A  B  to 
A  c,  when  triangles  of  the  same  shape  can  have  for  their 
respective  sides  the  lengths  A  B,  A  D,  A  c,  and  A  E.  But  it 
is  better,  if  we  can  do  it,  to  keep  the  science  of  quantity 
distinct  from  the  science  of  space,  and  to  find  some 
definition  of  the  fourth  proportional  which  depends 
upon  quantity  alone.  Such  a  definition  has  been  found, 
and  it  is  very  important  to  notice  the  nature  of  it.  For 

shall  find  that  similar  definitions  have  to  be  given  of 
other  quantities  whose  existence  is  assumed  by  what  is 
called  the  principle  of  continuity.  This  principle  is 
simply  the  assumption,  which  we  have  stated  already, 
that  all  quantities  can  be  divided  into  any  given  number 
of  equal  parts. 

If  we  apply  two  different  operations  of  stretching 
to  the  same  quantity,  that  which  produces  the  greater 
result  is  naturally  looked  upon  as  an  operation  which 
under  like  circumstances  will  always  produce  a  greater 
effect.  Now  we  will  make  our  definition  of  the  fourth 
proportional  depend  upon  the  very  natural  assumption 
that,  if  two  processes  of  stretching  are  applied  to  two 
different  quantities,  that  process  which  produces  the 
greater  result  in  the  one  case  will  also  produce  the 
greater  result  in  the  other. 

Suppose  now  that  we  have  tried  to  approximate  to 
'the  ratio  which  A  c  bears  to  A  B,  and  that  we  have 
[found  that  A  c  is  between  seventeen-twelfths  and 
ighteen-twelfths  of  A  B,  then  we  have  two  processes 
')£  stretching  which  can  be  applied  to  A  B,  the  process 
jlenoted  by  -JJ-  (that  is,  multiplying  by  17  and  dividing 
j>y  12),  and  the  process  which  makes  A  c  of  it.  The 
•esult  of  the  former  process  is,  by  hypothesis,  less  than 


108      THE   COMMON    SENSE    OF    THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

the  result  of  the  latter,  because  A  c  is  more  than  seven- 
teen-twelfths  of  AB.  Let  us  now  apply  these  two 
processes  to  AD.  The  former  will  produce  seventeen- 
twelfths  of  A  D,  the  latter  will  produce  the  fourth  pro 
portional  required.  Consequently  this  fourth  propor 
tional  must  be  greater  than  seventeen-twelfths  of  A  D. 

But  we  know  further  that  A  c  is  less  than  eighteen- 
twelf ths  of  A  B.  Then  the  operation  which  makes  A  B 
into  A  c  gives  a  less  result  than  the  operation  of  multi 
plying  by  18  and  dividing  by  12.  Let  us  now  perform 
both  upon  A  D.  It  will  follow  that  the  fourth  propor 
tional  required  is  less  than  eighteen-twelf'ths  of  A  D. 
The  same  thing  will  be  true  of  any  fractions  we  like  to 
take,  and  we  may  state  our  result  in  this  general 
form  : — 

According  as  A  c  is  greater  or  is  less  than  any  speci 
fied  fraction  of  A  B,  so  will  the  fourth  proportional  (if  it 
exists)  be  greater  or  be  less  than  the  same  fraction  of  A  D. 

But  we  shall  now  show  that  this  property  is  of 
itself  sufficient  to  define,  without  ambiguity,  the  fourth 


FIG.  32. 

proportional ;  that  is  to  say,  we  shall  show  that  there 
cannot  be  two  different  lengths  satisfying  this  condition 
at  the  same  time. 

If  possible,  let  there  be  two  lengths,  A  E  and  A  E',  each 
of  them  a  fourth  proportional  to  A  B,  AC,  AD  (fig.  32). 
Then  by  taking  a  sufficient  number  of  lengths  each1 


QUANTITY. 

qua!  to  E  E',  the  sum  of  them  can  be  made  greater 

han   A  D.      Suppose   for   example  that   500   of  them 

ust  fell  short  of  the  length  A  D,  and  that  501  exceeded 

t;  then,  if  we  divide  AD  into  501  equal  parts,  each  of 

hese  parts  will  be  less  than  E  E'.     Secondly,  if  we  go 

:>n  marking  off  lengths  from  D  towards  E,  each  equal 

o  one  of  these  small  parts  of  A  D,  one  of  the  points  of 

.ivision    must    fall   between    E    and    E'  ;    since    E  E'    is 

reater  than  the  distance  between  two  of  them.     Let 

his  point  of  division  be  at  F.     Then  A  F  is  got  from 

&.V  by  multiplying  by  some  number  or  other  and  then 

ividing  by  501.     If  we  apply  this  same  process  to  A  B 

we  shall  arrive  at  a  length  A  G,  which  must  be  either 

O  * 

greater  or  less  than  AC.  If  it  is  less  than  A  c,  then  the 
Deration  by  which  the  length  A  B  is  made  into  A  G  is  a 
ess  amount  of  stretching  than  the  operation  by  which 
A  B  is  made  into  A  c.  Consequently  the  operation 
which  turns  A  D  into  A  F  is  a  less  amount  of  stretching 
hail  that  which  gets  A  E,  and  also  less  than  that  which 
jets  A  E'  from  A  D.  Therefore  A  F  must  be  less  than  A  E, 
d  also  less  than  A  E'.  But  this  is  impossible,  because 
lies  between  E  and  E'.  And  the  argument  would  be 
imilar  if  we  had  supposed  A  G  greater  than  A  c. 

Thus  we  have  proved  that  there  is  only  one  length 
hat  satisfies  the  condition  that  the  process  of  making 
^  D  into  it  is  greater  than  all  the  fractions  which  are 
(ss  than  the  process  of  making  A  B  into  AC,  and  less 
han  all  the  fractions  which  are  greater  than  this  same 
>rocess. 

Let  us  note  more  carefully  the  nature  of  this  defi- 
lition. 

First  of  all  we  say  that  if  any  fraction  whatever  be 
aken,  and  if  it  be  greater  than  the  ratio  of  A  c  to  A  B,  it 
also  be  greater  than  the  ratio  of  A  E  to  A  D,  and  if 


110      THE   COMMON   SENSE    OF    THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

it  be  less  than  the  one  it  will  also  be  less  than  the 
other. 

This  is  a  matter  which  can  be  tested  in  regard  to 
any  particular  fraction.  If  a  length  A  E  were  given  t 
us  as  the  fourth  proportional  we  could  find  outwhethe 
it  obeyed  the  rule  in  respect  of  any  one  given  fraction 
But  if  there  is  a  fourth  proportional  it  must  satisf 
this  rule  in  regard  to  all  fractions  whatever.  We  can 
not  directly  test  this ;  but  we  may  be  able  to  give 
proof  that  the  quantity  which  is  supposed  to  be  a  fourt 
proportional  obeys  the  rule  for  one  particular  fraction 
which  proof  shall  be  applicable  without  change  to  an 
other  fraction.  It  will  then  be  proved,  for  this  case 
not  only  that  a  fourth  proportional  exists,  but  that  thi 
particular  quantity  is  the  fourth  proportional.  Thi 
is,  in  fact,  just  what  we  can  do  with  the  sides  of  siinila 


triangles.  If  the  length  A  B  (fig.  33)  is  divided  into  airj 
number  of  equal  parts,  and  lines  are  drawn  through  the 
points  of  division,  making  with  A  B  the  same  angle  thai 
B  D  makes  with  it,  they  will  divide  A  D  into  the  saint! 
number  of  equal  parts. 

If  now  we  set  off  points  of  division  at  the  sam( 
distance  from  one  another  from  B  towards  c,  anc 
through  them  draw  lines  making  the  same  angl< 
with  the  line  AC  that  BD  does,  these  lines  will  als< 
cut  off  equal  distances  from  D  towards  E.  If  any  on< 
of  these  lines  starts  from  A  c  on  the  side  of  c  toward 


QUANTITY.  1 1 1 

A,  it  will  meet  A  E  on  the  side  of  E  towards  A  ;  because 
be  triangle  which  it  forms  with  the  lines  A  c  and  A  E 

must  have  the  same  shape  as  A  c  E.  So  also  any  one  of 
aese  lines  which  starts  from  A  c  on  the  side  of  c  away 
rom  A  will  meet  AE  oil  the  side  of  E  away  from  A. 

Looking  then  at  the  various  fractions  of  A  B  which 
re  now  marked  off,  it  is  clear  that,  if  one  of  them 
3  less  than  A  c,  the  corresponding  fraction  of  A  D  is  less 
hau  A  E  ;  and  if  greater,  greater.  It  follows,  therefore, 
hat  the  line  AE  which  is  given  by  this  construction 
atisfies,  in  the  case  of  any  fraction  we  choose,  the  con- 
.ition  which  is  necessary  for  the  fourth  proportional. 
Consequently,  if  the  second  assumption  which  we  made 
,bout  space  be  true,  there  always  is  a  fourth  propor- 
ional,  and  this  process  will  enable  us  to  find  it. 

There  is,  however,  still  one  objection  to  be  made 

against  our  definition   of  the   fourth  proportional,   or 

rather  one  point  in  which  we  can  make  it  a  firmer 
ground- work  for  the  study  of  ratios.  For  it  assumes 
hat  quantities  are  continuous  ;  that  is,  that  any  quan- 
ity  can  be  divided  into  any  number  of  equal  parts, 
his  being  implied  in  the  process  of  taking  any  numer- 
cal  fraction  of  a  quantity. 

We  say,  for  example,  that  if  a,  b,  c,  <7,  are  propor- 
ionals,  and  if  a  is  greater  than  three-fifths  of  b,  c  will 
)e  greater  than  three-fifths  of  d.  Xow  the  process  of 
hiding  three-fifths  of  b  is  one  or  other  of  the  following 
wo  processes.  Either  we  divide  b  into  five  equal  parts 
ind  take  three  of  them,  or  we  multiply  b  by  three  and 
livide  the  result  into  five  equal  parts.  (We  know  of 
:ourse  that  these  two  processes  give  us  the  same  result.) 
But  it  is  assumed  in  both  cases  that  we  can  divide  ;i 
jiven  quantity  into  five  equal  parts. 

Now  in  a  definition  it  is   desirable   to   assume  as 


112       THE    COMMOX    SEXSE    OF    THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

little  as  possible ;  and  accordingly  the  Greek  geometers 
in  defining  proportion,  or  (which  is  really  the  same 
thing)  in  denning  the  fourth  proportional  of  three 
given  quantities,  have  tried  to  avoid  this  assumption. 

Nor  is  it  difficult  to  do  this.     For  let  us  conside 
the  same  example.     We  say  that  if  a  is  greater  thai 
three-fifths  of  b,  c  will  be  greater  than  the  same  fractio 
of  d.     Now  let  us  multiply  both  the  quantities  a  and 
by  five.     Then  for  a  to  be  greater  than  three-fifths  of  6 
the  quantity  which  a  has  now  become  must  be  greate 
than  three-fifths  of  the  quantity  which  b  has  become 
that  is,  if  the  new  b  be  divided  into  five  equal  parts  th 
new  a  must  be  greater  than  three  of  them.     But  each  o 
these  five  equal  parts  is  the  same  as  the  original  b ;  an 
so  our  statement  as  to  the  relative  greatness  of  a  and 
is  the  same  as  this,  that  five  times  a  is  greater  thai 
three  times  b ;  and  similarly  for  c  and  d. 

Now  every  fraction  involves  two  numbers.     It  is 
compound   process    made    up    of   multiplying   by    on 
number  and  dividing  by  another,  and  it  is  clear  there 
fore  that  we  may,  not  only  in  this  particular  case  o 
three-fifths  but  in   general,  transform  our  rule  for  th 
fourth  proportional  into  this  new  form.     According 
m  times  a  is  greater  or  less  than  n  times  b,  so  is  m  times 
c  greater  or  less  than  n  times  d,  where  m  and  n  are  ani 
whole  numbers  whatever. 

This  last  form  is  the  one  in  which  the  rule  is  givei 
by  the  Greek  geometers ;  and  it  is  clear  that  it  doe 
not  depend  on  the  continuity  of  the  quantities  con 
sidered,  for  whether  it  be  true  or  not  that  we  cai 
divide  a  number  into  any  given  number  of  equal  parts 
we  can  certainly  take  any  multiple  of  it  that  w 
like. 

These  fundamental  ideas,  of  ratio,  of  the  equality  c 


QUANTITY.  US 

r;iti»s,  and  of  the  nature  of  the  fourth  proportional 
ire  now  established  generally,  and  with  reference  to 
quantities  of  any  kind,  not  with  regard  to  lengths  alone  ; 
provided  merely  that  it  is  always  possible  to  take  any 
*iven  multiple  of  any  given  quantity. 

§  6.  Of  Areas  ;  Stretch  and  Squeeze. 

We  shall  now  proceed  to  apply  these  ideas  to  areas, 
>r  quantities  of  surface,  and  in  particular  to  plane  areas, 
phe  simplest  of  these  for  the  purposes  of  measurement 
!?  a  rectangle.  The  finding  of  the  area  of  a  rectangle 
5  in  many  cases  the  same  process  as  numerical  multi- 
lication.  For  example,  a  rectangle  which  is  7  inches 
)ng  and  5  inches  broad  will  contain  35  square  inches, 
nd  this  follows  from  our  fundamental  ideas  about 
multiplication  of  numbers.  But  this  process,  the 
raltiplication  of  numbers,  is  only  applicable  to  the 
in  which  we  know  how  many  times  each  side  of 
rectangle  contains  the  unit  of  length,  and  it  then 
us  how  many  times  the  area  of  the  rectangle  con- 
ins  the  square  described  upon  the  unit  of  length.  It 
mains  to  find  a  method  which  can  always  be  used. 

For  this  purpose  we  first  of  all  observe  that  when 
e  side  of  a  rectangle  is  lengthened  or  shortened  in 
ratio,  the  other  side  being  kept  of  a  fixed  length, 
.e  area  of  the  rectangle  will  be  increased  or  diminished 
exactly  the  same  ratio. 

In  order  then  to  make  any  rectangle  OP K  Q  out  of  a 
iare  o  A  c  B,  we  have  first  of  all  to  stretch  the  side  o  A 
til  it  becomes  equal  to  o  P,  and  thereby  to  stretch  the 
.ole  square  into  the  rectangle  o  D,  which  increases  its 
in  the  ratio  of  o  A  to  o  P.     Then  we  must  stretch 
side  o  B  of  this  figure  until  it  is  equal  to  o  Q,  and 

i 


114      THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 


thereby  the  figure  o  D  becomes  o  E,  and  its  area  is  in 
creased  in  the  ratio  of  o  B  to  o  Q.     Or  we  may,  if  we 


FIG.  34. 

like,  first  stretch  o  B  to  the  length  o  Q,  whereby  the 
square  o  c  becomes  o  E,  and  then  stretch  o  A  to  0  P,  b; 
which  o  E  becomes  o  E. 

Thus  the  whole  operation  of  turning  the  square  o  c 
into  the  rectangle  o  E  is  made  up  of  two  stretches  ;  or 
as  we  have  agreed  to  call  them,  '  multiplications ' ;  viz 
the  square  has  to  be  multiplied  by  the  ratio  of  o  P  tc 
o  A,  and  by  the  ratio  of  0  Q  to  OB;  and  we  may  fine 
from  the  result  that  the  order  of  these  two  processes 
is  immaterial. 

For  let  us  represent  the  ratio  of  o  P  to  o  A  by  th< 
letter  a,  and  the  ratio  of  OQ  to  OB  by  b.  Then  th< 
ratio  of  the  rectangle  o  D  to  the  square  o  c  is  also  a ;  ii 
other  words,  a  times  o  c  is  equal  to  o  D.  And  the  rati« 
of  o  E  to  0  D  is  b,  so  that  b  times  o  D  is  equal  to  o  E 
that  is,  b  times  a  times  oc  is  equal  to  OE,  or,  as  w 
write  it,  b  a  times  o  c  is  o  E.1 

And  in  the  same  way  b  times  o  c  is  equal  to  0 
and  a  times  6  times  o  c  is  a  times  o  E,  which  is  o  E. 

1  It  is  a  matter  of  convention  which  has  grown  up  in  consequence  of  o>| 
ordinary  habit  of  reading  from  left  to  right,  that  we  always  read  tl| 
symbols  of  a  multiplication,  or  of  any  other  operation,  from  riff  hi  to  le,\ 
Thus  a  b  times  any  quantity  x,  means  a  times  b  times x ;  that  is  to  say,  i| 
first  multiply  x  by  b,  and  then  by  a  ;  that  operation  being  first  perform' 
vrhobe  symbol  comes  last. 


QUANTITY.  115 

Consequently  we  have  b  a  times  0  c  giving  the  same 
result  as  a  6  times  o  c  ;  or,  as  we  write  it 

6  a  =  ab, 

which  means  that  the  effect  of  multiplying  first  by  the 
ratio  a  and  then  by  the  ratio  b  is  the  same  as  that  of 
multiplying  first  by  the  ratio  b  and  then  by  the 
ratio  a. 

This  proposition,  that  in  multiplying  by  ratios  we 
may  take  them  in  any  order  we  please  without  affecting 
the  result,  can  be  put  into  another  form. 

Suppose  that  we  have  four  quantities,  a,  6,  c,  d, 
then  I  can  make  a  into  d  by  two  processes  performed 
in  succession  ;  namely,  by  first  multiplying  by  the  ratio 
of  b  to  a,  which  turns  it  into  b,  and  then  by  the  ratio 
of  d  to  b.  But  I  might  have  produced  the  same  effect 
on  a  by  first  multiplying  it  by  the  ratio  of  c  to  a,  which 
turns  it  into  c,  aud  then  multiplying  by  the  ratio  of  d  to 
c.  We  are  accustomed  to  write  the  ratio  of  6  to  a  in 
shorthand  in  any  of  the  four  following  ways : — 

b:  a,    b,    6-f-a,     >/a, 

Or 

ind  so  the  fact  we  have  just  stated  may  be  written 
ms  : — 

V.    ><    "/>  =   Va    X    "/, 

Now  let  us  assume  that  the  four  quantities,  a,  b, 
d,  are  proportionals  ;  that  is,  that  the  ratios  b/ a  and 
I1/,,  are  equal  to  one  another.  It  follows  then  that  the 
Ratios  c/0  and  d/b  are  equal  to  one  another. 

This    proposition   may  be  otherwise   stated  in  this 
lorm ;  that  if  a,  6,  c,  d  are  proportionals,  then  a,b,  6,  d 
nil  also  be   proportionals :  provided   always  that  this 
itter  statement  has  any  meaning,  for  it  is  quite  possible 
lat  it  should  have  no  meaning  at  all.     Suppose,  for  in- 
ince,  that  a  and  6  are  two  lengths,  c  and  d  two  intervals 

i  2 


116      THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

of  time,  then  we  understand  what  is  meant  by  the  ratio 
of  6  to  a,  and  the  ratio  of  d  to  c,  and  these  ratios  may 
very  well  be  equal  to  one  another  ;  but  there  is  no  such 
thing-  as  a  ratio  of  c  to  a,  or  of  d  to  6,  because  the 
quantities  compared  are  not  of  the  same  kind.  When, 
however,  four  quantities  of  the  same  kind  are  propor 
tionals,  they  are  also  proportionals  when  taken  alter 
nately  ;  that  is  to  say,  when  the  two  middle  ones  are 
interchanged. 

§  7.  Of  Fractions. 

We  have  seen  in  §  3,  page  101,  that  a  ratio  may  be 
expressed  in  the  form  of  a  fraction.     Thus,  let  a  be 

D  7* 

represented  by  the  fraction^-  and  b  by  the  fraction  ~, 

q  s 

where  p,  q,  r,  s  are  numbers.  Then  the  result  on  page 
115  may  be  written — 

p       r        r       p 

£_    x     —  X   —  » 

q        s        s        q 

Let  us  examine  a  little  more  closely  into  the  mean 
ing  of  either  side  of  this  equation.     Suppose  we  were 

P  R'      P 


)                 as 

FIG.  35. 

to  take  a  rectangle  o  Q  T  s,  of  which  one  side,  o  Q,  con 
tained  q  units  of  length,  and  another,  OS,  s  units. 
Then  this  rectangle  could  be  obtained  from  the  unit 
square  by  operating  upon  it  with  the  two  stretches  g| 
and  s.  Its  area  would  thus  contain  q  s  square  units,  j 


QUANTITY.  1 1  7 

Now  let  us  apply  to  this  rectangle  in  succession  the 

fV\  A» 

two  stretches  denoted  by  t  and  -.     If  we  stretch  the 

q          s 

rectangle  in  the  direction  of  the  side  o  Q  in  the  ratio  of 

?.,  we  divide  the  side  o  Q  into  q  equal  parts,  and  then 

1 

take  o  P  equal  p  times  one  of  those  parts.     But  each  of 

these  parts  will  be  equal  to  unity,  hence  o  P  contains 

p  units.     We  thus  convert  our  rectangle  o  T  into  one 

OP',  of  which  one  side,  OP,  contains  p  and  the   other, 

os,  s  units.     Now  let  us  apply  to  this  rectangle  the 

stretch  -  parallel  to  the  side  os  (as  the  figure  is  drawn 
s 

r  denotes  a  squeeze).  We  must  divide  o  s  into  s  equal 
s 

parts  and  take  r  such  parts,  or  we  must  measure  a 
length  o  R  along  o  s  equal  to  r  units.  Thus  this  second 
stretch  converts  the  rectangle  o  p'  into  a  rectangle 

CJ  O 

o  R',  of  which  the  side  o  P  contains  p  and  the  side 
OR  contains  r  units  of  length,  or  into  a  rectangle 
containing  p  r  square  units.  Hence  the  two  stretches 

"P-  and  -  applied  in  succession  to  the  rectangle  o  T  con- 
q  s 

vert  it  into  the  rectangle  o  R'.  Now  this  may  be 
written  symbolically  thus  : — 

*-  x  -  .  rectangle  o  T  =  rectangle  o  R 
q        s 

=  p  r  unit-rectangles. 
Now  unit-rectangle   may  obviously  be   obtained  from 

the  rectangle  o  T  by  squeezing  it  first  in  the  ratio     in 

the  direction  of  OQ,  and  then  in  the  ratio  —  in  the  di- 

s 

rection  o  S.     Now  this  is  simply  saying  that  o  T  contains 


118      THE   COMMON   SENSE   OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

q  s  unit-rectangles.     Hence  the  operation  ?  x  —  applied 

q      s 

to  unit-rectangle  must  produce  —  of   the  result   of  its 

qs 

application  to  the  rectangle  o  T.     That  is  : — 

±  x  -  .  unit-rectangle  =  —  .  p  r  unit-rectangle, 
q       s  qs 

or,  in  our  notation,  =  ^—  .  unit-rectangle. 
qs 

Hence  we  may  say  that  ±-  x  —  operating  upon  unity 

is  equal  to  the  operation  denoted  by  ^1,  or  to  multi 
plying  unity  by  p  r  and  then  dividing  the  result  by  q  s. 
This  equivalence  is  termed  the  multiplication  of  frac 
tions. 

A   special   case  of  the  multiplication  of  fractions 
arises  when  s  equals  r.     We  then  have — 

P.  x  -  =  £T. 
q        r       qr' 

¥ 

But  the  operation  -  denotes  that  we  are  to  divide  unity 

into  r  equal  parts,  and  then  take  r  of  them  ;  in  other 
words,  we  perform  a  null  operation  on  unity.  The 
symbol  of  operation  may  therefore  be  omitted,  and  we 

read — 

p  pr 

q       ~^r' 

This  result  is  then  expressed  in  words  as  follows : 
Given  a  fraction,  we  do  not  alter  its  value  by  multiply 
ing  the  numerator  and  denominator  by  equal  quanti 
ties. 

From  this  last  result  we  can  easily  interpret  the 
operation 


QUANTITY.  119 


2         s 
For,  by  the  preceding  paragraph  — 

p  ps  -,  r  qr 
±-  =f__,  and  -  =  *-. 
q  qs  s  qs 

Hence  — 

P.  +  t  =  PJ*  +  1*. 
q        s        qs        qs 

Or,  to  apply  first  the  operation  *-  to  unity  and  then  to 

add  to  this  the  result  of  the  operation  -   is  the  same 

s 

thing  as  dividing  unity  into  qs  parts,  taking  ps  of 
those  parts,  and  then  adding  to  them  q  r  more  of  the 
like  parts.  But  this  is  the  same  thing  as  to  take  at 
once  p  s  +  q  r  of  those  parts.  Thus  we  may  write  — 

p        r  _  ps  +  qr 
q        s  qs 

This  result  is  termed  the  addition  of  fractions.  The 
reader  will  find  no  difficulty  in  interpreting  addition 
graphically  by  a  succession  of  stretches  and  squeezes  of 
the  unit-rectangle. 

We  term  division  the  operation  by  which  we  reverse 
the  result  of  multiplication.     Hence  when  we  ask  the 

meaning  of  dividing  by  the  fraction  *-  we  put  the 
question  :  What  is  the  operation  which,  following  on 
the  operation  ^,  just  reverses  its  effect? 

I        -NT  r       p       p       r       pr 

Now,  _  x  i  =  i-  x  -=  ^-—  . 

s       q      q       s       q  s 
Suppose  we  take  r  =  q,  s  =  p. 


120      THE   COMMON    SENSE    OF    THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

Then  VXP=M. 

p        q        qp 

or,  to  multiply  unity  by  ^,  and  then  by  5,  is  to  perform 

the   operation   of   dividing   unity   into   qp   parts   and 
then  taking  p  q  of  them,  or  to  leave  unity  unaltered. 

Hence  the  stretch  i  completely  reverses  the  stretch  "  ;\ 
P  2| 

it  is,  in   fact,  a   squeeze   which  just  counteracts   the 

preceding  stretch.     Thus  multiplying  by  ^  must  be  an 
operation  equivalent  to  dividing  by  £-.      Or,  to   divide 

by  ^  is  the  same  thing  as  to  multiply  by  ^.     This  result 
q  p 

is  termed  the  division  of  fractions. 


§  8.  Of  Areas  ;  Shear. 

Hitherto  we  have  been  concerned  with  stretching 
or  squeezing  the  sides  of  a  rectangle.  These  opera 
tions  alter  its  area,  but  leave  it  still  of  rectangular 
shape.  We  shall  now  describe  an  operation  which 
changes  its  angles,  but  leaves  its  area  unaltered. 


D  F     C 


a  A  B  6 

FIG.  36. 

Let   A  B  c  D   be   a  rectangle,  and   let  A  B  E  p   be  a  j 

parallelogram  (or  a  four- sided  figure  whose  opposite  sides 
are  equal),  having  the  same  side,  AB,  as  the  rectangle, 
but  having  the  opposite  side,  E  p  (equal  to  A  B,  and 


QUANTITY.  121 

therefore  to  CD),  somewhere  in  the  same  line  as  CD. 
Then,  since  c  D  is  equal  to  E  p,  the  points  E  and  p  are 
equally  distant  from  c  and  D  respectively,  and  it  follows 
that  the  triangles  B  c  E  and  A  D  F  are  equal.  Hence  if 
the  triangle  B  c  E  were  cut  off  the  parallelogram  along 
B  c  and  placed  in  the  position  A  D  p,  we  should  have 
converted  the  parallelogram  into  the  rectangle  without 
changing  its  area.  Thus  the  area  of  the  parallelogram 
is  equal  to  that  of  the  rectangle.  Now  the  area  of  the 
rectangle  is  the  product  of  the  numerical  quantity  which 
represents  the  length  of  AD  into  that  quantity  which 
represents  the  length  of  A  B.  A  B  is  termed  the  bate 
of  the  parallelogram,  and  A  D,  the  perpendicular  dis 
tance  between  its  base  and  the  opposite  side  E  F,  is 
termed  its  height.  The  area  of  the  parallelogram  is 
then  briefly  said  to  be  '  the  product  of  its  base  into 
its  height.' 

Suppose  c  D  and  A  B  were  rigid  rods  capable  of  slid 
ing  along  the  parallel  lines  c  d  and  a  b.     Let  us  imagine 
them    connected    by  a  rectangular   elastic    membrane, 
A  B  c  D  ;  then  as  the  rods  were  moved  along  a  b  and  c  d 
the  membrane  would  change  its  shape.     It  would,  how 
ever,  always  remain  a  parallelogram   with   a  constant 
base  and  height;  hence  its  area  would  be  unchanged, 
it  the  rod  A  B  be   held  fixed  in  position,  and  the  rod 
D  pushed  along  c  d  to  the  position  E  F.     Then  any  line, 
H,  in  the  membrane  parallel  and  equal  to  A  B  will  be 
toved  parallel  to  itself  into  the  position  I  J,  and  will 
tot  change   its   length.     The   distance  through  which 
has  moved  is  c  E,  and  the  distance  through  which  G 
moved  is  G  I.     Since   the  triangles  c  B  E  and  G  B  I 
ive  their  sides  parallel  they  are  similar,  and  we  have 
ie  ratio  of  c  E  to  G  i  the  same  as  that  of  B  c  to  n  G  ; 
>r.  when  the  rectangle  A  B  c  D  is  converted   into  the 


122       THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF    THE    EXACT    SCIENCES. 


parallelogram  A  B  E  F,  any  line  parallel  to  A  B  remains 
unchanged  in  length,  and  is  moved  parallel  to  itself 
through  a  distance  proportional  to  its  distance  from  A  B. 
Such  a  transformation  of  figure  is  termed  a  shear,  and 
we  may  consider  either  our  rectangle  as  being  sheared 
into  the  parallelogram  or  the  latter  as  being  sheared 
into  the  former.  Thus  the  area  of  a  parallelogram  is 
equal  to  that  of  a  rectangle  into  which  it  may  be 
sheared. 

The  same  process  which  converts  the  parallelogram 
A  B  E  F  into  the  rectangle  A  B  c  D  will  convert  the  tri 
angle  ABE,  the  half  of  the  former,  into  the  triangle 


FIQ.  37. 


ABC,  the  half  of  the  latter.  Hence  we  may  shear  any 
triangle  into  a  right-angled  triangle,  and  this  will  not 
alter  its  area.  Thus  the  area  of  any  triangle  is  half  I 
the  area  of  the  rectangle  on  the  same  base,  and  with 
height  equal  to  the  perpendicular  upon  the  base  from 
the  opposite  angle.  This  height  is  also  termed  the 
altitude,  or  height  of  the  triangle,  and  we  then  briefly 
say :  The  area  of  a  triangle  is  half  the  product  of  its  base 
into  its  altitude. 

A  succession  of  shears  will  enable  us  to  reduce  any 
figure  bounded  by  straight  lines  to  a  triangle  of  equal 
area,  and  thus  to  determine  the  area  the  figure  encloses 
by  finally  shearing  this  triangle  into  a  right-angled 


QUANTITY.  123 

triangle.     For  example,  let  A  B  c  D  E  be  a  portion  of  the 

boundary   of  the    figure.      Suppose    A  c   joined  ;  then 

shear  the  triangle  ABC  so  that  its  vertex  B  falls  at  B' 

on  D  c  produced.     The  area  A  B'  c  is  equal  to  the  area 

ABC.     Hence  we  may  take  A  B'  D  E  for  the  boundary  of 

our  figure  instead  of  A  B  c  D  E  ;  that  is,  we  have  reduced 

be  number  of  sides  in  our  figure  by  one.     By  a  suc- 

ession  of  shears,  therefore,  we   can  reduce  any  figure 

>ounded  by  straight  lines  to  a  triangle,  and  so  find  its 

rea. 

§  9.  Of  Circles  and  their  Areas. 

One  of  the  first  areas  bounded  by  a  curved  line  which 
suggests  itself  is  that  of  a  sector  of  a  circle,  or  the 


FIG.  38. 

>ortion  of  a  circle  intercepted  by  two  radii  and  the 
,rc  of  the  circumference  between  their  extremities. 
[Before  we  can  consider  the  area  of  this  sector  it  will 
necessary  to  deduce  some  of  the  chief  properties  of 
complete  circle.  Let  us  take  a  circle  of  unit 
lius  and  suppose  straight  lines  drawn  at  the  extre- 
lities  of  two  diameters  AB  and  c  D  at  right  angles  ;  then 
circle  will  appear  as  if  drawn  inside  a  square  (see 
.  39).  The  sides  of  this  square  will  be  each  2  and 
area  4. 

Now  suppose   the   figure  composed   of  circle   and 
juare  first  to  receive  a  stretch  such  that  every  line 


124      THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT  SCIENCES. 


parallel  to  the  diameter  A  B  is  extended  in  the  ratio  of 
a  :  1,  and  then  another  stretch  such  that  every  line 
parallel  to  c  D  is  again  extended  in  the  ratio  of  a  :  1. 
Then  it  is  obvious  that  we  shall  have  stretched  the 
square  of  the  first  figure  into  a  second  square  whose 
sides  will  now  he  equal  to  2  a. 


FIG.  39. 

It  remains  to  be  shown  that  we  have  stretched  the 
first  circle  into  another  circle.  Let  o  p  be  any  radius 
and  p  M,  PN  perpendiculars  on  the  diameters  A  B,  c  D/ 
As  a  result  of  the  first  stretch  the  equal  lengths  o  M 
and  N  P  are  extended  into  the  equal  lengths  o'  M'  and"! 

,    ,,    ,  o  M         N  p         1     0.    .. 

N  P,  which  are  such  that  — - — -  =     ,—-  =  _.    Similarly, 

o  M        N  p'        a 

as  a  result  of   the  second  stretch  M  p  and  o  N,  which 
remained  unaltered  during  the  first  stretch,  are  con-1 

verted  into  M'  p'  and  O'N'J   so  that  °-~  =  ?LZ  =  ?. 

ON         M  p'        a 

During  this  second  stretch  o'M'and  N'P' remain  un-3 
altered.  Thus  as  the  total  outcome  of  the  two  stretches 
we  find  that  the  triangle  o  p  N  has  been  changed  into  the 
triangle  o' P' N'.  Now  these  two  triangles  are  of  the 
same  shape  by  what  was  said  on  p.  106,  for  the  angles 
at  N  and  N'  are  equal,  being  both  right  angles,  and  we 
have  seen  that — 


QUANTITY.  1  'JO 

N  P  1      _  O  M 

N'P'  "  a       O'M'' 

Thus  it  follows  that  the  third  side  o  P  must  be  to 

third  side  o'  P'  in  the  ratio  of  1  to  a ;  or,  since  o  P 
s  of  unit  length,  o'  P'  must  be  equal  to  the  constant 
uantity  a.  Further,  since  the  angles  P  o  x,  P'  o'  N' 
re  equal,  o'  P'  is  parallel  to  O  P.  Hence  the  circle  of 
nit  radius  has  been  stretched  into  a  circle  of  radius  <i. 
n  fact,  the  two  equal  stretches  in  directions  at  right 
ngles,  which  we  have  given  to  '  the  first  figure,  have 
erformed  just  the  same  operation  upon  it,  as  if  we 
ad  placed  it  under  a  magnifying  glass  which  enlarged 
i  uniformly,  and  to  such  a  degree  that  every  line  in  it 
as  magnified  in  the  ratio  of  a  to  1. 

It  follows  from  this  that  the  circumference  of  the 
econd  circle  must  be  to  that  of  the  first  as  a  is  to  1. 
r,  the  circumferences  of  circles  are  as  their  radii, 
gain,  if  the  arc  P  Q  is  stretched  into  the  arc  P'  Q' — that 
,  if  o'  P',  o'  Q'  are  respectively  parallel  to  o  P,  o  Q — then 
le  arc  P'  Q'  is  to  the  arc  P  Q  in  the  ratio  of  the  radii  of 
he  two  circles.  Since  the  arcs  P  Q,  P'  Q'  are  equal  to 
ny  other  arcs  which  subtend  the  same  angles  at  the 
mtres  of  their  respective  circles,  we  state  generally 
lat  the  arcs  of  two  circles  which  subtend  equal  angles  at 
keir  respective  centres  are  in  the  ratio  of  the  corre- 
wnding  radii. 

Since  the  second  figure  is  an  uniformly  magnified 
nage  of  the  first,  every  element  of  area  in  the  first  has 
sen  magnified  at  the  same  uniform  rate  in  the  second. 
bw  the  square  in  the  first  figure  contains  four  units 
'area,  and  in  the  second  figure  it  contains  4  a2  units 
:  area.  Hence  every  element  of  area  in  the  first 
ure  has  been  magnified  in  the  second  in  the  ratio  of 
to  1.  Thus  the  area  of  the  circle  in  the  first  figure 


126      THE    COMMON    SENSE   OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES,    i 

must  be  to  the  area  of  the  circle  in  the  second  figure 
as  1  is  to  a2.  Or  :  The  areas  of  circles  are  as  the  squares 
of  their  radii. 

It  is  usual  to  represent  the  area  of  a  circle  of  unit 
radius  by  the  quantity  TT  ;  thus  the  area  of  a  circle  of 
radius  a  will  be  represented  by  the  quantity  IT  a2. 

If,  after  stretching  A  B  to  A'  B'  in  the  ratio  of  a  to  1, 
we  had  stretched  or  squeezed  CD  to  c'  D'  in  the  ratio  of 
6  to  1,  where  b  is  some  quantity  different  from  a,  om 
square  would  have  become  a  rectangle,  with  sides  equal 
to  2  a  and  2  b  respectively.  It  may  be  shown  that  we 


should  have  distorted  our  circle  into  the  shape  of  that 
shadow  of  a  circle  which  we  have  termed  an  ellipse. 
Furthermore,  elements  of  area  have  now  been  stretched} 
in  the  ratio  of  the  product  of  a  and  b  to  1 ;  or,  the  area 
of  the  ellipse  is  to  the  area  of  the  circle  of  unit  radius) 
as  a  b  is  to  1 :  whence  it  follows  that  the  area  of  the  I 
ellipse  is  represented  by  Trab,  where  a  and  b  are  its 
greatest  and  least  radii  respectively. 

We  shall  now  endeavour  to  connect  the  area  of  a 
circle  of  unit  radius,  which  we  have  written  TT,  with  the 
number  of  linear  units  in  its  circumference.  Let  us 


QUANTITY. 


127 


take  a  number  of  points  uniformly  distributed  round 
the  circumference  of  a  circle,  A  B  c  D  E  F.  Join  them  in 
succession  to  each  other  and  to  o,  the  centre  of  the  circle, 
and  draw  the  lines  perpendicular  to  these  radii  (or  the 
tangents)  at  A  B  c  D  E  F  ;  then  we  shall  have  constructed 
two  perfectly  symmetrical  figures,  one  of  which  is  said 
to  be  inscribed,  the  other  circumscribed  to  the  circle. 
Now  the  areas  of  these  two  figures  differ  by  the  sum  of 
such  triangles  as  A  a  B,  and  the  area  of  the  circle  is 
obviously  greater  than  the  area  of  the  inscribed  and 
[ess  than  the  area  of  the  circumscribed  figure.  Thus 


FIG.  41. 

;he  area  of  the  circle  must  differ  from  that  of  the  in- 
cribed  figure  by  something  less  than  the  sum  of  all  the 
ittle  triangles  A  a  B,  B  /9  c,  &c.  Now  from  symmetry  all 
ihese  little  triangles  are  equal,  and  their  areas  are 
iherefore  equal  to  one  half  the  product  of  their  heights, 
>r  a  n,  into  their  bases,  or  such  quantities  as  A  B.  Hence 
;he  sum  of  their  areas  is  equal  to  one  half  of  the  product 
)f  an  into  the  sum  of  the  sides  of  the  inscribed  figure, 
w  the  sum  of  the  sides  of  the  inscribed  figure  is 
lever  greater  than  the  circumference  of  the  circle.  If 
re  take,  therefore,  a  great  number  of  points  uniformly 
istributed  round  the  circumference  of  our  circle,  A  and 


128      THE   COMMON    SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

B  may  be  brought  as  close  as  we  please,  and  the  nearer 
\ve  bring  A  to  B,  the  smaller  becomes  a  n.  Hence,  by 
taking  a  sufficient  number  of  points,  we  can  make  the 
sum  of  the  triangles  A  a  B,  B  /3  c,  &c.  as  small  as  we 
please,  or  the  areas  of  the  inscribed  and  circumscribed 
figures,  together  with  the  area  of  the  circle  which  lies 
between  them,  can  be  made  to  differ  by  less  than  any 
assignable  quantity.  In  the  limit  then  we  may  say 
that  by  taking  an  indefinite  number  of  points  we  can 
make  these  areas  equal.  Now  the  area  of  the  inscribed 
figure  is  the  sum  of  the  areas  of  all  such  triangles  as 
A  o  B,  and  the  area  of  the  triangle  A  o  B  is  equal  to 
half  the  product  of  its  height  o  n  into  its  base  A  B  ;  or 
if  we  write  for  the  '  perimeter,'  or  sum  of  all  the  sides 
A  B,  EC,  &c.  the  quantity  p,  the  area  of  the  inscribed 
figure  will  equal  ^ p  x  on.  Again  if  p'  be  the  sum 
of  the  sides  a  ft,  ft  7,  &c.  of  the  circumscribed  figure, 
its  area  =  |  p'  x  OB. 

Since  the  triangles  o  a  B,  o  B  n  are  of  the  same  shape, 
being  right-angled  and  again  equi-angled  at  o,  we  have 
the  ratio  of  B  n  to  a  B,  or  of  their  doubles  A  B  to  a  /3,  the 
same  as  that  of  o  n  to  o  B.  But  p  is  obviously  to  p'  in 
the  same  ratio  as  A  B  to  a  ft  ;  hence  p  is  to  p'  as  o  n  to 
o  B.  By  taking  a  sufficient  number  of  points  we  can 
make  o  n  as  nearly  equal  to  o  B  as  we  please ;  thus  we 
can  make  p  as  nearly  equal  to  p',  and  therefore  either 
of  them  as  nearly  equal  to  the  circumference  of  the 
circle  (which  lies  between  them),1  as  we  please.  Hence 
in  the  limit  p  will  equal  the  circumference  of  the  circle, 
and  o  n  its  radius,  and  we  may  state  that  the  areas  of  the 
inscribed  and  circumscribed  figures,  which  approach 
nearer  and  nearer  to  the  area  of  the  circle  as  we  in 
crease  the  number  of  their  sides,  become  ultimately 
1  In  the  case  of  the  circle  the  reader  will  recognise  this  intuitively. 


QUANTITY.  129 

equal  to  each  other  and  to  half  the  product  of  the  cir 
cumference  of  the  circle  into  its  radius.  This  must  there 
fore  be  the  area  of  the  circle.  Hence  we  have  the  fol 
lowing  equality : — The  area  of  a  circle  of  radius  a  equals 
one  half  its  circumference  x  a.  But  it  equals  also  ira2 ; 
whence  it  follows  that  the  circumference  of  a  circle 
equals  TT  .  '2  a.  We  may  express  this  result  in  two 
different  ways : — 

(i)  The  ratio  of  the  circumference  of  a  circle  to  its 
diameter  (2  a)  is  a  constant  quantity  TT. 

(ii)  The  number  of  linear  units  (2  TT)  in  the  cir 
cumference  of  a  circle  of  unit-radius  is  twice  the 
number  of  units  of  area  (TT)  contained  by  that  circum 
ference. 

The  value  of  TT,  the  ratio  of  the  circumference  of  a 
circle  to  its  diameter,  is  found  to  be  a  quantity  which, 
like  the  ratio  of  the  diagonal  of  a  square  to  its  side  (f,v 
p.  108),  cannot  be  expressed  accurately  by  numbers  ; 
its  approximate  value  is  3*141 59. 

We  have  now  no   difficulty  in  finding  the   area  of 

»/ 

the  sector  of  a  circle,  for  if  we  double  the  arc  of  a 
sector  we  obviously  double  its  area ;  if  we  treble  it,  we 
treble  its  area ;  shortly,  if  we  take  any  multiple  of  it, 
we  take  the  same  multiple  of  its  area.  Hence  it 
follows  by  §  5,  that  two  sectors  are  to  each  other 
in  the  ratio  of  their  arcs,  or  a  sector  must  be  to  the 
rhole  circle  in  the  ratio  of  its  arc  to  the  whole  circum 
ference. 

If  we  represent  by  s  the  area  of  a  sector  of  a  circle 
of  which  the  arc  contains  s  units  of  length  and  the 
radius  a  units,  we  may  write  this  relation  symboli 
cally — 

R  S 

Tra2       2  TT  a  ' 


130      THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

Thus  we  deduce  s  =  ^  s  x  a ;  or, 

The  area  of  a  sector  is  half  the  product  of  the  length  of  its\ 

arc  into  its  radius. 


§  10.  Of  the  Area  of  Sectors  of  Curves. 

The  knowledge  of  the  area  of  a  sector  of  a  circle! 
enables  us  to  find  as  accurately  as  we  please  the  area 
of  a  sector  whose  arc  is  any  curve  whatever.     Let  the 
arc  P  Q  be  divided  into  a  number  of  smaller  arcs  P  A,  A  B, 
B  c,  c  D,  D  Q.     We  shall  suppose  that  P  A  subtends  the 
greatest  angle  at  o  of  all  these  arcs.     Further  we  shall 
consider  only  the  case  where  the  line  OP  diminishes] 
continuously  if  P  be  made  to  pass  along  the  arc  from  p 


to  Q.  If  this  be  not  the  case,  the  sector  QOP  can 
always  be  split  up  into  smaller  sectors,  of  which  it  shall 
be  true  that  a  line  drawn  from  the  point  o  to  the  arc  con 
tinuously  diminishes  from  one  side  of  the  sector  to  the 
other,  and  then  for  the  area  of  each  of  these  sectors  the 
following  investigation  will  hold.  With  o  as  centre  de 
scribe  a  circle  of  radius  o  p  to  meet  o  A  produced  in  p';  with 
the  su,me  centre  and  radius  OA  describe  a  circle  to  meet 


QUANTITY 

OB  in  A'  and  OP  in  a  ;  similarly  circles  with  radius  OB  to 
meet  OA  in  b  and  oc  in  B',  with  radius  oc  to  meet  OB  in 
e  and  OD  in  c',  with  radius  OD  to  meet  oc  in  d  andoQin 
D',  and  finally  with  radius  OQ  to  meet  OD  in  e,  OA  in/, 
and  OP  in  Q'.  Then  the  area  of  the  sector  obviously  lie-i 
between  the  areas  of  the  figure  bounded  by  OP,  OD'  and 
the  broken  line  PP'  AA'BB'CC'DD',  and  of  the  figure 
bounded  by  oa,  OQ  and  the  broken  line  axbttccdveq. 
Hence  it  differs  from  either  of  them  by  less  than  their 
difference  or  by  less  than  the  sum  of  the  areas  p'a,  A'//, 
B'C,  c' d,  D' e.  Now  since  the  angle  at  POP'  is  greater 
than  any  of  the  other  sectorial  tingles  at  o,  the  sum  of 
all  these  areas  must  be  less  than  that  of  the  figure  p  P'/Q', 
and  the  area  of  this  figure  can  be  made  as  small  as  wr 
please  by  making  the  angle  AOP  sufficiently  small.  Tin* 
can  be  achieved  by  taking  a  sufficient  number  of  points 
like  ^,B,C,D,  £c.  We  are  thus  able  to  find  a  series  of 
circular  sectors,  the  sum  of  whose  areas  differs  by  as 
small  a  quantity  as  we  please  from  the  area  of  the 
sector  POQ;  in  other  words,  we  reduce  the  problem  of 
finding  the  area  of  anv  h'u'uiv  bounded  by  a  curved  lin^ 

\t  CT1  J 

to  the  problem  already  solved  of  finding  the  area  of  a 
sector  of  a  circle.  The  difficulties  which  then  ari^e 
are  purely  those  of  adding  together  a  very  great 
number  of  quantities  ;  for,  it  may  be  necessary  to  take  a 
hvery  great  number  of  points  such  as  A  BCD  .  .  .  in 

>rder  to  approach  with  sufficient  accuracy  to  the  mag- 

itude  of  the  area  POQ. 


§11.  Extension  of  the  Conception  of  Area. 

Let  ABCD  be  a  closed  curve  or  loop,  and  o  a  point 
[.nside  it.  Then  if  a  point  p  move  round  the  perimeter 
bf  the  loop,  the  line  OP  is  sai  1  to  trace  out  the  area  of 


132      THE   COMMON    SENSE    OF    THE   EXACT  SCIENCES. 

the  loop  ABCD.  By  this  is  meant  that  successive  poofl 
tions  of  the  line  o  P,  pair  and  pair,  form  together  with! 
the  intervening  elements  of  arc  elementary  sectors,  the] 
sura  of  the  areas  of  which  can,  by  taking  the  successive 


FIG.  43. 


positions  sufficiently  close,  be  made  to  differ  as  little  ai 
we  please  from  the  area  bounded  by  the  loop. 

Now  suppose  the  point  o  to  be  taken   outside  th<1 
loop  ABCD,  and  let  us  endeavour  to  find  the  area  then 


FIG.  44. 


traced  out  by  the  line  0  P  joining  o  to  a  point  P  whicl 
moves  round  the  loop.  Let  OB  and  OD  be  the  extrem 
positions  of  the  line  OP  to  the  left  and  to  the  right  a 
p  moves  round  the  loop  ABCD;  then  as  P  moves  alonj 


QUANTITY.  133 

the  portion  of  the  loop  DAB,  OP  moves  counter-clock 
wise  from  right  to  left  and  traces  out  the  area  bounded 
by  the  arc  DAB  and  the  lines  OD  and  OB.  Further,  as 
p  moves  along  the  portion  of  the  loop  BCD,  OP  moves 
clockwise  from  left  to  right  and  traces  out  the  area 
doubly  shaded  in  our  h'gure,  or  the  area  bounded  by 
the  arc  BCD  and  the  lines  OB  and  OD.  It  is  the  differ 
ence,  of  these  two  areas  which  is  the  area  of  the  loop 
ABCD.  If,  then,  we  were  to  consider  the  latter  area 
OBCDO  as  negative,  the  line  OP  would  still  trace  out  the 
area  of  the  loop  ABCD  as  p  moves  round  its  perimeter. 
Now  the  characteristic  difference  in  the  method  of  de 
scribing  the  areas  ODABO  and  OBCDO  is,  that  in  the 
former  case  OP  moves  counter-clockwise  round  o,  in  the 
latter  case  it  moves  clockwise.  Hence  if  we  make  a  con 
vention  tbat  areas  traced  out  by  OP  when  it  is  moving 
counter-clockwise  shall  be  considered  positive,  but  areas 
traced  out  by  OP  when  it  is  moving  clockwise  shall  be 
considered  negative,  then  wherever  o  may  be  inside  or 
outside  the  loop,  the  line  OP  will  trace  out  its  area  pro 
vided  P  move  completely  round  its  circumference. 

But  it  must  here  be  noted  that  p  may  describe  the 
loop  in  two  different  methods,  either  going  round  it 
counter-clockwise  in  the  order  of  points  ABCD,  or 
clockwise  in  the  order  of  points  A  D  c  B.  In  the  former 
case,  according  to  our  convention,  the  greater  area 
ODAI5O  is  positive,  in  the  latter  it  is  negative.  Hence 
we  arrive  at  the  conception  that  <in  area  men/  have  a 
sign;  it  will  be  considered  positive  or  negative  accord 
ing  as  its  perimeter  is  supposed  traced  out  by  a  point 
moving  counter-clockwise  or  clockwise.  This  extended 
conception  of  area,  as  having  not  only  magnitude  but 
tense,  is  of  fundamental  importance,  not  only  in  many 


134      THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

brandies  of  the  exact  sciences,  but  also  for  its  many 
practical  applications.1 

Let  a  perpendicular  o  N  be  erected  at  o  (which  is, 
as  we  have  seen,  any  point  in  the  plane  of  the  loop) 
to  the  plane  of  the  loop,  and  let  the  length  o  N  be 
taken  along  it  containing  as  many  units  of  length  as 
there  are  units  of  area  in  the  loop  A  B  c  D.  Then  o  N 
will  represent  the  area  of  the  loop  in  magnitude;  it 
will  also  represent  it  in  sense,  if  we  agree  that  ON  shall 
always  be  measured  in  such  a  direction  from  o,  that  to 
a  person  standing  with  his  feet  at  o  and  head  at  N  the 
point  P  shall  always  appear  to  move  counter-clockwise. 
Thus,  for  a  positive  area,  N  will  be  above  the  plane  ; 
for  a  negative  area,  in  the  opposite  direction  or  below 
the  plane.  We  are  now  able  to  represent  any  number 
of  areas  by  segments  of  straight  lines  or  steps  per 
pendicular  to  their  planes.  The  sum  of  any  number  of 
areas  lying  in  the  same  plane  will  then  be  obtained  by 
adding  algebraically  all  the  lines  which  represent  these  • 
areas. 

When  the  areas  do  not  all  lie  in  one  plane  the  j 
representative  lines  will  not  all  be  parallel.  In  this  I 
case  there  are  two  methods  of  adding  areas.  We  may  I 
want  to  know  the  total  amount  of  area ,  as,  for  example,  ! 
when  we  wish  to  find  the  cost  of  painting  or  gilding  ; 
a  many-sided  solid.  In  this  case  we  add  all  the  repre-  ^ 
sentative  lines  without  regard  to  their  direction. 

In  many  other  cases,  however,  we  wish  to  find  some 
quantity  so  related  to  the  sides  of  a  solid  that  it  can  I 
only  be   found  by  treating  the  lines  which  represent 
their  areas  as   directed   magnitudes.     Such    cases,  for 
example,  arise  in  the  discussion  of  the  shadows  cast  by 

1  As  in  calculating  the  cost  of  levelling  and  embanking,  in  the  indicator 
diagram,  &c.     It  was  first  introduced  by  Mobius. 


QUANTITY.  135 

the  sun  or  of  the  pressure  of  gases  upon  the  sides  of 
a  containing  vessel,  &c.  A  method  of  combining 
directed  magnitudes  will  be  fully  discussed  in  the 
following  chapter.  The  conception  of  areas  as  directed 
magnitudes  is  due  to  Hayward. 

§  12.   On  the  Area  of  a  Closed  Tangle. 

Hitherto  we  have  supposed  the  areas  we  have  talked 
about  to  be  bounded  by  a  simple  loop.  It  is  easy, 
however,  to  determine  the  area  of  a  combination  of 
loops.  Thus  consider  the  figure  of  eight  in  fig.  45  which 
has  two  loops  :  if  we  go  round  it  continuously  in  the 
direction  indicated  by  the  arrow-heads,  one  of  these 
loops  will  have  a  positive,  the  other  a  negative  area,  and 
(therefore  the  total  area  will  be  their  difference,  or  zero 
if  they  be  equal.  When  a  closed  curve,  like  a  figure 
of  eight,  cuts  itself  it  is  termed  a  tangle,  and  the  points 
where  it  cuts  itself  are  called  knots.  Thus  a  figure  of 
3ight  is  a  tangle  of  one  knot.  In  tracing  out'the  area 
)f  a  closed  curve  by  means  of  a  line  drawn  from  a  fixed 
Doint  to  a  point  moving  round  the  curve,  the  area  may 
rary  according  to  the  direction  and  the  route  by  which 
Ive  suppose  the  curve  to  be  described.  If,  however,  we 
suppose  the  curve  to  be  sketched  out  by  the  moving 
point,  then  its  area  will  be  perfectly  definite  for  that 

articular  description  of  its  perimeter. 

We  shall  now  show  how  the  most  complex  tangle 
| lay  be  split  up  into  simple  loops  and  its  whole  area 
ijetermined  from  the  areas  of  the  simple  loops.  We 
lhall  suppose  arrow-heads  to  denote  the  direction  in 
•j'hich  the  perimeter  is  to  be  taken.  Consider  either 
If  the  accompanying  figures.  The  moving  line  o  P 

ill  trace  out  exactly  the  same  area  if  we  suppose  it 


136      THE    COMMOX   SEXSE    OF    THE    EXACT    SCIENCES. 

not  to  cross  at  the  knot  A  but  first  to  trace  out  the 
loop  A  c  and  then  to  trace  out  the  loop  A  B,  in  both 
cases  going  round  these  two  loops  in  the  direction 


FIG.  45. 

indicated  by  the  arrow-heads.  We  are  thus  able  in 
all  cases  to  convert  one  line  cutting  itself  in  a  knot 
into  two  lines,  each  bounding  a  separate  loop,  which 
just  touch  at  the  point  indicated  by  the  former  knot. 
This  dissolution  of  knots  may  be  suggested  to  the 
reader  by  leaving  a  vacant  space  where  the  boundaries 
of  the  loops  really  meet.  The  two  knots  in  the  fol 
lowing  figure  are  shown  dissolved  in  this  fashion : — 


FIG.  46. 


The  reader  will  now  find  no  difficulty  in  separating 
the  most  complex  tangle  into  simple  loops.  The  posi 
tive  or  negative  character  of  the  areas  of  these  loops 


QUANTITY. 


137 


be   sufficiently  indicated  by  the   arrow-heads   on 
their  perimeters.     We  append  an  example  : — 


FIG.  47. 


In  this  case  the  tangle  reduces  to  a  negative  loop 
a,  and  to  a  large  positive  loop  b,  within  which  are  two 
other  positive  loops  c  and  d,  the  former  of  which  con- 


FIG.  48. 


tains  a  fifth  small  positive  loop  e.  The  area  of  the 
entire  tangle  then  equals  b  +  c  +  d  +  e—  a.  The 
ispace  marked  s  in  the  n'rst  figure  will  be  seen  from  the 
second  to  be  no  part  of  the  area  of  the  tangle  at  all. 


138      THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 


§  13.  On  the  Volumes  of  Space-Figures. 

Let  us  consider  first  the  space-figure  bounded  by 
three  pairs  of  parallel  planes  mutually  at  right  angles. 
Such  a  space-figure  is  technically  termed  a  *  rectangular 
parallelepiped,'  but  might  perhaps  be  more  shortly 
described  as  a  '  right  six-face.'  We  may  first  observe 
that  when  one  edge  of  such  a  right  six-face  is 
lengthened  or  shortened  in  any  ratio,  the  other  non- 
parallel  edges  being  kept  of  a  fixed  length,  the  volume 


/ 

/ 

l> 

ii 

- 

/i/i 

/ 

/I 

! 

/ 

a 

/ 

A, 

/ 

L 

/ 

FIG.  49. 

will  be  increased  in  precisely  the  same  ratio.  Hence, 
in  order  to  make  any  right  six-face  out  of  a  cube  we 
have  only  to  give  the  cube  three  stretches  (or  it  may  ' 
be  squeezes),  parallel  respectively  to  its  three  sets  of 
parallel  edges.  Let  o  A,  o  B,  o  c  be  the  three  edges  of 
the  cube  which  meet  in  a  corner  o.  Let  o  A  be 
stretched  to  o  A',  so  that  the  ratio  of  o  A'  to  o  A  is 
represented  by  a ;  then  if  the  figure  is  to  remain  right 
all  lines  parallel  to  o  A  will  be  stretched  in  the  same  i 
ratio.  The  figure  has  now  become  a  six- face  whose 
section  perpendicular  to  o  A'  only  is  a  square.  Now 
stretch  o  B  to  o  B',  so  that  the  ratio  o  B'  to  o  B  be 
represented  by  6,  and  let  all  lines  parallel  to  o  B  be 


QUANTITY. 


139 


increased  in  the  same  ratio  ;  the  figure  is  now  a  right 
six-face,  only  one  set  of  edges  of  which  are  equal  to  the 
edge  of  the  original  square.  Finally  stretch  o  c  to  0  c', 
so  that  o  C  and  all  lines  parallel  to  it  are  increased  in 
the  ratio  of  o  c'  to  o  c,  -which  we  will  represent  by  c. 
By  a  process  consisting  of  three  stretches  we  have  thus 
converted  our  original  cube  into  a  right  six-face.  If 
the  cube  had  been  of  unit-volume,  the  volume  of  our 
six-edge  would  obviously  be  abc,  and  we  may  show  as 
in  the  case  of  a  rectangle  (see  p.  115)  that  abc  =  cba 
=  bac,  &c.  ;  or  the  order  of  multiplying  together  three 
ratios  is  indifferent.  If  we  term  the  face  A'  c'  of  our 


Fio.  50. 

right  six-face  its  base  and  OB'  its  height,  ac  will  repre 
sent  the  area  of  its  base,  and  6  its  height,  or  the  volume 
of  a  right  six-face  is  equal  to  the  product  of  its  base 
ito  its  height. 

Let  us  now  suppose  a  right  six-face  OADCEBFG 
receive  a  shear,  or  the  face  B  E  F  G  to  be  moved  in  its 
)wn  plane  in  such  fashion  that  its  sides  remain  parallel 
their  old  positions,  and  B  and  E  move  respectively 
ilong  B  F  and  E  G.  If  B'  E'  G'  F'  be  the  new  position  of 
face  B  E  G  F,  it  is  easy  to  see  that  the  two  wedge- 
jihaped  figures  B  E  E'  B'  o  c  and  F  G  G'  F'  A  D  are  exactly 
jual;  this  follows  from  the  equality  of  their  corre 
sponding  faces.  Hence  the  volume  of  the  sheared 


140      THE   COMMON    SENSE    OF   THE   EXACT    SCIENCES. 

figure  must  be  equal  to  the  volume  of  the  right  six-face. 
Now  let  us  suppose  in  addition  that  the  face  B'  E'  G-'  F' 
is  again  moved  in  its  own  plane  into  the  position  B"  E" 
G"  F",  so  that  E'  and  E'  move  along  B'  E'  and  F'  G' 
respectively.  Then  the  slant  wedge-shaped  figures 
B'  E"  F"  F'  A  o  and  E'  E"  G"  F'  D  c  will  again  be  equal, 
and  the  volume  of  the  six-face  B''  E"  G"  F"  A  D  c  o 
obtained  by  this  second  shear  will  be  equal  to  the 
volume  of  the  figure  obtained  by  the  first  shear,  and 
therefore  to  the  volume  of  the  right  six-face.  But  by 
means  of  two  shears  we  can  move  the  face  B  E  G  F  to 
any  position  in  its  plane,  B"  E"  G"  F",  in  which  its  sides 
remain  parallel  to  their  former  position.  Hence  the 
volume  of  a  six- face  will  remain  unchanged  if,  one  of  its 
faces,  o  c  D  A,  remaining  fixed,  the  opposite  face,  B  E  G  F, 
be  moved  anywhere  parallel  to  itself  in  its  own  plane. 
We  thus  find  that  the  volume  of  a  six- face  formed  by 
three  pairs  of  parallel  planes  is  equal  to  the  product  of 
the  area  of  one  of  its  faces  and  the  perpendicular 
distance  between  that  face  and  its  parallel.  For  this 
is  the  volume  of  the  right  six-face  into  which  it  may 
be  sheared ;  and,  as  we  have  seen,  shear  does  not  alter 
volume. 

The  knowledge  thus  gained  of  the  volume  of  a  six- 
face  bounded  by  three  pairs  of  parallel  faces,  or  of  a 
so-called  parallelepiped,  enables  us  to  find  the  volume 
of  an  oblique  cylinder.  A  right  cylinder  is  the  figure 
generated  by  any  area  moving  parallel  to  itself  in  such 
wise  that  any  point  p  moves  along  a  line  p  p'  at  right 
angles  to  the  area.  The  volume  of  a  right  cylinder  is 
the  product  of  its  height  P  P'  and  the  generating  area. 
For  we  may  suppose  that  volume  to  be  the  sum  of  a 
number  of  elementary  right  six-faces  whose  bases,  as 
at  P,  may  be  taken  so  small  that  they  will  ultimately 


QUANTITY. 


141 


completely  fill  the  area  ACBD,  and  whose  heights  are 
all  equal  to  P  P'. 


i 


We  obtain  an  oblique  cylinder  from  the  above  right 
cylinder  by  moving  the  face  A'C'B'D'  parallel  to  itself 
anywhere  in  its  own  plane.  But  such  a  motion  will 
only  shear  the  elementary  right  six-faces,  such  as  P  P'. 
and  so  not  change  their  volume.  Hence  the  volume 
of  an  oblique  cylinder  is  equal  to  the  product  of  its 
base,  and  the  perpendicular  distance  between  its  faces. 


§  14.  On  the  Measurement  of  Angles. 

Hitherto  we  have  been  concerned  with  quantities  of 
area  and  quantities  of  volume  ;  we  must  now  turn  to 
quantities  of  angle.     In  our  chapter  on  Space  (p.  66) 
we  have  noted  one  method  of  measuring  angles ;  but 
that  was  a  merely  relative  method,  and  did  not  lead  us 
to  fix  upon  an  absolute  unit.     We  might,  in  fact,  have 
i  taken  any  opening  of  the  compasses  for  unit  angle,  and 
'determined  the  magnitude  of  any  other  angle  by  its 
I  ratio  to  this   anMe.     But   there    is  an  absolute   unit 


142      THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

which  naturally  suggests  itself  in  our  measurement  of 
angles,  and  one  which  we  must  consider  here,  as  we 
shall  frequently  have  to  make  use  of  it  in  our  chapter 
on  Position. 

Let  A  o  B  be  any  angle,  and  let  a  circle  of  radius  a 
be  described  about  o  as  centre  to  meet  the  sides  of  this 


FIG.  52. 

angle  in  A  and  B.     Then  if  we  were  to  double  the  angle 

O  O 

A  o  B,  we  should  double  the  arc  A  B  ;  if  we  were  to  treble 
it,  we  should  treble  the  arc ;  shortly,  if  we  were  to  take 
any  multiple  of  the  angle,  we  should  take  the  same 
multiple  of  the  arc.  We  may  thus  state  that  angles  at 
the  centre  of  a  circle  vary  as  the  arcs  on  which  they 
stand.  Hence  it'  9  and  &  be  two  angles,  which  are 
subtended  by  arcs  s  and  s'  respectively,  the  ratio  of  6  to 
6'  will  be  the  same  as  that  of  s  to  s'.  Now  suppose  6' 
to  represent  four  right  angles  ;  then  s'  will  be  the  entire 
circumference,  or,  in  our  previous  notation,  2  TT  a.  We 
have  thus — 

0  =          8 

four  right  angles        2  TT  a ' 

Now  it  is  extremely  convenient  to  choose  a  unit 
angle  which  shall  be  independent  of  the  circle  upon 
which  we  measure  our  arcs.  We  should  obtain  such 
an  independent  unit  if  we  took  the  arc  subtended  by  it 


QUANTITY.  143 

equal  to  the  radius  of  the  circle  or  if  we  took  s  =  a. 
In   this  case  our  unit  equals  -  -  of  four  right  angles, 

1  7T 

=   —  of  two  right   angles,   =  '636  of  a  right  angle 

7T 

approximately. 

Thus  we  see  that  the  angle  subtended  at  the  centre 
of  any  circle  by  an  arc  equal  to  the  radius  is  a  constant 
fraction  of  a  right  angle. 

If  this  angle  be  chosen  as  the  unit,  we  deduce  from 
the  proportion  6  is  to  6'  as  s  is  to  s',  that  6  must  be  to 
unity  as  s  is  to  the  radius  a  ;  or : — 

s  =  a  Q. 

Thus,  if  we  choose  the  above  angle  as  our  unit  of 
angle,  the  measure  of  any  other  angle  will  be  the  ratio 
of  the  arc  it  subtends  from  the  centre  to  the  radius  ; 
but  we  have  seen  (p.  125)  that  the  arcs  subtended 
from  the  centre  in  different  circles  by  equal  angles  are 
I  in  the  ratio  of  the  radii  of  the  respective  circles. 
I  Hence  the  above  measurement  of  angle  is  independent 
'of  the  radius  of  the  circle  upon  vjhich  we  base  our 
^measurement.  This  is  the  primary  property  of  the  so- 
illed  circular  measurement  of  angles,  and  it  is  this 
rhich  renders  it  of  such  great  value. 

The  circular  measure  of  any  angle  is  thus  the  ratio  of 
the  arc  it  subtends  from  the  cer.tre  of  any  circle  to  the 
lius  of  the  circle.  It  follows  that  the  circular  mea- 
mre  of  four  right  angles  is  the  ratio  of  the  whole  circum 
ference  to  the  radius,  or  equals  "  -  ;  that  is,  equals 
!?r.  The  circular  measure  of  two  right  angles  will 
len  be  TT,  of  one  right  angle  -( ,  of  three  right 

a 

ijjles  —   and  so  on. 


144      THE   COMMON   SENSE   OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

§15.  On  Fractional  Powers. 

Before  we  leave  the  subject  of  quantity  it  will  be 
necessary  to  refer  once  more  to  the  subject  of  powers 
which  we  touched  upon  in  our  chapter  on  Number 
(p.  16). 

We  there  used  an  as  a  symbol  signifying  the  result 
of  multiplying  a  by  itself  n  times.  From  this  defini 
tion  we  easily  deduce  the  following  identity  :  — 

an  x  av  x  aq  x  ar  = 


For  the  left  hand  side  denotes  that  we  are  first  to 
multiply  a  by  itself  n  times,  and  then  multiply  this  by 
ap,  or  a  multiplied  by  itself  p  times,  and  so  on.  Hence 
we  may  write  the  left  hand  side  — 

(ax  ax  ax  a,  .  .  to  n  factors) 
x  (axaxaxa  .  .  to  p  factors) 
x  (axaxaxa  .  .  to  q  factors) 
x  (axaxaxa  .  .  to  r  factors)  . 

But  this  is  obviously  equal  to(axaxaxax  ...  to 
n+p  +  q  +  r  factors),  or  to  an  +  p  +  q  +  r. 

If  b  be  such  a  quantity  that  bn=a,  b  is  termed  an  nth 

root  of  a,  and  this  is  written  symbolically  b  =    \/  a. 

Thus,  since  8  =  23,  2  is  a  3rd,  or  cube  root  of  8.  Or, 
again,  since  243  =  35,  3  is  termed  a  5th  root  of  243. 

Now  we  have  seen  at  the  conclusion  of  our  first 
chapter  that  we  can  often  learn  a  very  great  deal  by 
extending  the  meaning  of  our  terms.  Let  us  now  see  if 
we  cannot  extend  the  meaning  of  the  symbol  a".  Does 
it  cease  to  have  a  meaning  when  n  is  a  fraction  or  I 
negative  ?  Obviously  we  cannot  multiply  a  quantity 
by  itself  a  fractional  number  of  times,  nor  can  we  do  \ 


QUANTITY.  145 

so  a  negative  number  of  times.  Hence  the  old  mean 
ing  of  a",  where  n  is  a  positive  integer,  becomes  sheer 
nonsense  when  we  try  to  adapt  it  to  the  case  of  n 
being  fractional  or  negative.  Is  then  an  in  this  latter 
case  meaningless? 

In  an  instance  like  this  we  are   thrown   back  upon 

the  results  of  our  definition,  and  we  endeavour  to  give 

to  our  symbol  such  a  meaning  that  it  will  satisfy  these 

results.     Now  the  fundamental  result  of  our  theory  of 

nteger  powers  is  that — 

It  '    '==-    Cl      X    CL      X    fl     X    Cl     X      .     .    . 

This  will  obviously  be  true  however  many  quantities, 

n,p,  q,  r,  AVC  take.     Now  let  us  suppose  we  wish  to  inter- 
i 

pret    G.~    where  —    is  a  fraction.     We   begin   by  as- 
ra 

uming  it  satisfies  the  above  relation,  and  in  order  to 
arrive    at    its    meaning    we    suppose  that  n  =  p  =  a 

=  ?•=...=  — ,  and  that  there  are  m  such  quantities. 
Then 

n+p+q+r  =  mx  —  =  / ; 

m 

i  i  i 

and  we  find  a1  =  a™   x  am  x  a7    x          .  to  m  factors 


-(•*)• 


Thus  am  must  be  such  a  quantity  that,  multiplied  by 
.tself  m  times,  it  equals  a1.  But  we  have  defined  above 
p.  144)  an  mth  root  of  a'  to  be  such  a  quantity  that, 

nultiplied  m  times    by  itself,  it  equals  a1.     Hence  we 

i_ 

">ay  that  a~  is  equal  to  an  ?/ith  root  of  a' ;  or,  as  it  is 
vritten  for  shortness, — 


146       THE    COMMON   SEXSE    OF    THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

We  have  thus  found  a  meaning  for  an  when  n  is  a  frac 
tion  from  the  fundamental  theorem  of  powers. 

We  can  with  equal  ease  obtain  from  the  same 
theorem  an  intelligible  meaning  for  an  when  n  is  a 
negative  quantity. 

We  have  an  x  a"  =  an  +  .  Now  let  us  assume 
p  =  —  n  in  order  to  interpret  a  ~ n.  We  find  a'1  x  a~n 
—  an  ~  n  =  a°  =  1  (by  p.  31).  Or  dividing  by  a", 

.--I., 

a"' 

that  is  to  say,  a  ~ n  is  the  quantity  which,  multi 
plied  by  a",  gives  a  product  equal  to  unity.  The  former 
quantity  is  termed  the  inverse  of  the  latter,  or  we  may 
say  that  a  ~  n  is  the  inverse  of  an.  For  example,  what 
is  the  inverse  of  4  ?  Obviously  4  must  be  multiplied 
by  £  in  order  that  the  product  may  be  unity.  Hence 
4  ~  1  is  equal  to  £.  Or,  again,  since  4  =  22,  we  may  say 
that  2  ~  2  is  the  inverse  of  4,  or  22. 

The  whole  subject  of  powers — integer,  fractional, 
and  negative — is  termed  the  Theory  of  Indices,  and  is 
of  no  small  importance  in  the  mathematical  investiga 
tion  of  symbolic  quantity.  Its  discussion  would,  how 
ever,  lead  us  too  far  beyond  our  present  limits.  It  has 
been  slightly  considered  here  in  order  that  the  reader 
may  grasp  that  portion  of  the  following  chapter  in 
which  fractional  powers  are  made  use  of. 


147 


CHAPTEE  IV. 

POSITION. 

§  1.  All  Position  is  Relative. 

THE  reader  can  hardly  fail  to  remember  instances  when 
he  has  been  accosted  by  a  stranger  with  some  such 
question  as :  'Can  you  tell  me  where  the  'George  '  Inn 
lies?  ' — '  How  shall  I  get  to  the  cathedral  ?  ' — '  Where 
is  the  London  Road  ?  '  The  answer  to  the  question, 
however  it  may  be  expressed,  can  be  summed  up  in  the 
one  word — There.  The  answer  points  out  the  position. 
of  the  building  or  street  which  is  sought.  Practically 
the  there  is  conveyed  in  some  such  phrase  as  the  follow 
ing :  'You  must  keep  straight  on  and  take  the  iirst 
turning  to  the  right,  then  the  second  to  the  left,  and 
you  will  find  the  '  George  '  two  hundred  yards  down 
the  street.' 

Let  us  examine  somewhat  closely  such  a  question 
and  answer.  '  Where  is  the  '  George  '  ?  '  We  may  ex 
pand  this  into  :  '  How  shall  I  get  from  liere '  (the  point 
at  which  the  question  is  asked)  'to  the  'George'?' 
This  is  obviously  the  real  meaning  of  the  query.  If  the 
stranger  were  told  that  the  '  George  '  lies  three  hundred 
paces  from  the  Town  Hall  down  the  High  Street, 
the  information  would  be  valueless  to  the  questioner 
unless  he  were  acquainted  with  the  position  of  the 
Town  Hall  or  at  least  of  the  High  Street.  Equally  idle 

i.  2 


14S       THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF    THE    EXACT   SCIEXCES. 

would  be  the  reply :  '  The  *  George '  lies  just  past 
the  forty-second  milestone  on  the  London  Road,'  sup 
posing-  him  ignorant  of  the  whereabouts  of  the  London 
Road. 

Yet  both  these  statements  are  in  a  certain  sense 
answers  to  the  question  :  '  Where  is  the  '  George  '  ?  ' 
They  would  be  the  true  method  of  pointing  out  the 
there,  if  the  question  had  been  asked  in  sight  of  the 
Town  Hall  or  upon  the  London  Road.  We  see,  then, 
that  the  query,  Where  ?  admits  of  an  infinite  number 
of  answers  according  to  the  infinite  number  of  posi 
tions—or  possible  heres — of  the  questioner.  The  ivhere 
always  supposes  a  definite  here,  from  which  the  desired 
position  is  to  be  determined.  The  reader  will  at  once 
recognise  that  to  ask,  '  Where  is  the  '  George '  ?  ' 
without  meaning,  '  Where  is  it  with  regard  to  some 
other  place  ?  '  is  a  question  which  no  more  admits  of  an 
answer  than  this  one :  '  How  shall  I  get  from  the 
'George'  to  anywhere?'  meaning  to  nowhere  in 
particular. 

This  leads  us  to  our  first  general  statement  with 
regard  to  position.  We  can  only  describe  the  where 
of  a  place  or  object  by  describing  how  we  can  get  at  it 
from  some  other  known  place  or  object.  We  determine 
its  where  relative  to  a  here.  This  is  shortly  expressed 
by  saying  that :  All  position  is  relative. 

Just  as  the  '  George '  has  only  position  relative  to 
the  other  buildings  in  the  town,  or  the  town  itself 
relative  to  other  towns,  so  a  body  in  space  has  only 
position  relative  to  other  bodies  in  space.  To  speak  of 
the  position  of  the  earth  in  space  is  meaningless  unless 
we  are  thinking  at  the  same  time  of  the  Sun  or  of 
Jupiter,  or  of  a  star — that  is,  of  some  one  or  other 
of  the  celestial  bodies.  This  result  is  sometimes 


POSITION.  149 

described  as  the  '  sameness  of  space.'  By  this  we  only 
mean  that  in  space  itself  there  is  nothing  perceptible  to 
the  senses  which  can  determine  position.1  Space  is,  as 
it  were,  a  blank  map  into  which  we  put  our  objects;  it 
is  the  coexistence  of  objects  in  this  map  which  enables 
us  at  any  instant  to  distinguish  one  object  from  another. 
This  process  of  distinguishing,  which  supposes  at  least 
two  objects  to  be  distinguished,  is  really  determining 
a  this  and  a  that,  a  here  and  a  there;  it  involves  the 
conception  of  relativity  of  position. 

§  2.  Position  may  be  Determined  by  Directed  Steps. 

Let  us  turn  from  the  question :  '  Where  is  the 
*  George'?'  to  the  answer:  '  You  must  keep  straight  on 
and  take  the  first  turning  to  the  right,  then  the  second 
to  the  left,  and  you  will  find  the  '  George '  200  yards 
down  the  street.' 

The  instruction  '  to  keep  straight  on '  means  to  keep 
in  the  street  wherein  the  question  has  been  asked,  and 
in  a  direction  ('  straight  on  ')  suggested  by  the  previous 
motion  of  the  questioner,  or  by  a  wave  of  the  hand  from 
the  questioned.  Assuming  for  our  present  purpose 
that  the  streets  are  not  curved,  this  amounts  to :  Keep 
a  certain  direction.  How  far?  This  is  answered  by  the 
second  instruction  :  Take  the  first  turning  on  the  right. 
More  accurately  we  might  say,  if  the  first  turning  to  the 
right  were  150  yards  distant:  Kt.-ep  this  direction  for 
150  yards.  Let  this  be  represented  in  our  figure  by  the 
step  A  B,  where  A  is  the  position  at  which  the  question 
is  asked.  At  B  the  questioner  is  to  turn  to  the  right 
and,  according  to  the  third  instruction,  he  is  to  pass  the 
first  turning  to  the  left  at  c  and  take  the  second  at  D. 

1  We  shall  return  to  thin  point  later. 


150      THE    COMMON    SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT    SCIENCES. 

More  accurately  we  might  state  the  distance  B  D  to  be, 
say,  J80  yards.  Then  we  could  combine  our  second  and 
third  instructions  by  saying :  From  B  go  180  yards  in 
a  certain  direction,  namely,  B  D.  To  determine  exactly 
what  this  direction  B  D  is  with  regard  to  the  first  direction 
A  B,  we  might  use  the  following  method.  If  the  stranger 
did  not  change  his  direction  at  B,  but  went  straight  on 
for  180  yards,  he  would  come  to  a  point  D'.  Hence  if 
we  measured  the  angle  D'B  D  between  the  street  in  which 
the  question  was  asked  and  the  first  turning  to  the  right, 


FIG.  53. 

we  should  know  the  direction  of  B  D  and  the  position  of 
D  exactly.  It  would  be  determined  by  rotating  B  D' 
about  B  through  the  measured  angle  D'B  D.  If  we  adopt 
the  same  convention  for  the  measurement  of  positive 
angles  as  we  adopted  for  positive  areas  on  p.  133,  the 
angle  D'B  D  is  the  angle  greater  than  two  right  angles 
through  which  B  D'  must  be  rotated  counter-clockwise 
in  order  to  take  it  to  the  position  B  D.  Let  us  term  this 
angle  D'B  D  for  shortness  yS,  then  we  may  invent  a  new 
symbol  {/?}  to  denote  the  operation  :  Turn  the  direction 
you  are  going  in  through  an  angle  fi  counter-clockwise. 


POSITION  151 

If  we  use  the  symbol  7r/2  to  denote  an  angle  equal  to  a 
right  angle,  we  have  the  following  symbolic  instructions : 

{     0     }    =   Keep  straight  on. 

{  7T/2  }    =  Turn  at  right  angles  to  the  left. 

{     TT    }    =   Turn  right  round  and  go  back. 

{3?r/2  }    =   Turn  at  right  angles  to  the  right. 
Thus  for  a  turning  from  A  B  to  the  left  the  angle  of 
our  symbolic  operation  will  be  less,  for  a  turning  from 
A  B  to  the  right  greater,  than  two  right  angles. 

If  the  directed  person  had  gone  to  D'  instead  of  to 
D,  he  would  have  walked  150  yards  to  B  and  then  180 
yards  to  D' ;  he  would  thus  have  walked  AB  +  BD',  or 
150  yards  +  180  yards.  In  order  to  denote  that  he  is 
not  to  continue  straight  on  at  B  we  introduce  the  opera 
tor  of  turning,  namely  {/3} ,  before  the  180  yards,  and 
read  150  +  {/3|  180  as  the  instruction:  Go  150  yards 
along  some  direction  A  B,  and  then,  turning  your  direc 
tion  through  an  angle  {3  counter-clockwise,  go  180 
yards  along  this  new  direction. 

We  are  now  able  to  complete  the  symbolic  expression 
of  our  instructions  for  finding  the  '  George.'  The 
fourth  instruction  runs  :  Take  a  turning  at  D  to  the 
left  and  go  200  yards  along  the  direction  thus  de 
termined.  Let  D  G'  represent  200  yards  measured 
from  D  along  B  D  produced,  then  we  are  to  revolve  D  G' 
through  a  certain  angle  G'D  G  counter-clockwise,  till  it 
takes  up  the  position  D  G.  Then  G  will  be  the  position 
of  the  '  George.'  Let  the  angle  G'D  G  be  represented 
by  7.  Our  final  instruction  may  be  then  expressed 
symbolically  by  {7}  200. 

Hence  our  total  instruction  may  be  written  symboli 
cally— 

150   +    {/3}180   +    (7/200, 

where  the  units  are  yards. 


152      THE    COMMON    SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT    SCIENCES. 

But  we  have  not  yet  quite  freed  this  symbolic  in 
struction  from  any  suggestion  of  direction  as  determined 
by  streets ;  the  first  150  yards  are  still  to  be  taken  along 
the  street  in  which  the  question  is  asked.  We  can  get 
rid  of  this  street  by  supposing  its  direction  determined 
by  the  angle  which  a  clock-hand  must  revolve  through 
counter-clockwise,  to  reach  that  direction,  starting  from 
some  other  fixed  or  chosen  direction.  For  example, 
suppose  the  stranger  to  have  a  compass  with  him,  and 
at  A  let  AN  be  the  direction  of  its  needle.  Then  we 
might  fix  the  position  of  the  street  A  B  by  describing  it 
as  a  direction  so  many  degrees  east  of  north,  or  still  to 
preserve  our  counter-clockwise  method  of  reckoning 
angles,  we  might  determine  it  by  the  angle  a  which 
the  needle  would  have  to  describe  through  west  and 
south  to  reach  the  position  A  B.  We  should  then  in 
terpret  the  notation  {a.}  150 :  Walk  150  yards  along  a 
direction  making  an  angle  a  with  north  measured 
through  west. 

Our  answer  expressed  symbolically  is  now  entirely 
cleared  of  any  conception  of  streets.  For, 

(a)  150    +    {/3}180   +    {7}  200 

is  a  definite  instruction  as  to  how  to  get  from  A  to  G 
quite  independent  of  any  local  characteristics.  It  ex 
presses  the  position  of  G  with  regard  to  A  in  a  purely 
geometrical  fashion,  or  by  a  series  of  directed  steps. 
Expanded  into  ordinary  English  our  symbols  read : 
From  a  point  A  in  a  plane,  take  a  step  A  B  of  150  units 
in  a  direction  making  an  angle  a  with  a  fixed  direction, 
from  B  take  a  step  B  D  of  180  units  making  an  angle  /3 
with  A  B,  and  finally  from  D  take  a  step  D  G  of  200  units 
making  an  angle  7  with  B  D.  All  the  angles  are  to  be 
measured  counter-clockwise  in  the  fashion  we  have 
described  above. 


POSITION.  153 

§  3.   The  Addition  of  Directed  Steps  or  Vectors. 

If  we  now  compare  our  figure  with  the  symbolical 
instruction  {a}  150  +  {/8J180  +  {7}  200,  we  see  that 
{a}  150  represents  the  step  A  B,  when  that  step  is 
considered  to  have  not  merely  magnitude  but  also 
direction.  Similarly  B  D  and  D  G  represent  more  than 
linear  expressions  for  number — they  are  also  directed 
steps.  We  shall  then  be  at  liberty  to  replace  our 
symbolically  expressed  instruction 

{a}  150    +    {/3J1SO    4-    {7}  200 
by  the  geometrical  equivalent 

AB     +     BD     +     D  G, 

provided  we  understand  by  the  segments  A  B,  B  D,  D  G 
and  the  symbol  +   something  quite    different   to   our 


FIG.  54. 

former   conceptions.     We   give    a   new  and   extended 
meaning  to  our  quantity  and  to  our  addition. 

AB  +  BD+DG  no  longer  directs  us  to  add  the 
number  of  units  in  B  D  to  that  in  A  B  and  to  the  sum  of 
these  the  number  in  D  G,  but  it  bids  us  take  a  step  A  B  in 
a  certain  direction,  then  a  step  B  D  from  the  finish  of 
the  former  step  in  another  determined  direction,  and 
finally  from  the  finish  D  of  this  second  step  a  third 


154      THE    COMMOX   SEXSE    OF   THE   EXACT    SCIEXCES. 

directed  step,  D  G.  The  entire  operation  brings  ua 
from  A  to  G.  Now  it  is  obvious  that  we  should  also 
have  got  to  G  had  we  taken  the  directed  step  AG. 
Hence,  if  we  give  an  extended  meaning  to  the  word 
'equal'  and  to  its  sign  =,  using  them  to  mark  the 
equivalence  of  the  results  of  two  operations,  we  may 
write 

AG  =  AB     +     BD     +     DG, 

and  read  this  expression  : — A  G  equals  the  sum  of  A  B, 
B  D  and  D  G. 

Steps  such  as  we  considered  in  our  chapter  on 
Quantity,  which  were  magnitudes  taken  along  any  one 
straight  line,  are  termed  scalar  steps,  because  they  have 
relation  only  to  some  chosen  scale  of  quantity.  We 
add  or  subtract  scalar  steps  by  placing  them  end  to  end 
in  any  straight  line  (see  §  2  of  Chapter  III.) 

A  step  which  has  not  only  magnitude  but  direction 
is  termed  a  vector  step,  because  it  carries  us  from  one 
position  in  space  to  another.  It  is  usual  to  mark  by  an 
arrow-head  the  sense  in  which  we  are  to  take  this 
directed  step.  For  example  in  fig.  54  we  are  to  step 
from  A  to  B,  and  thus  the  arrow-head  will  point  towards 
B  for  the  step  A  B.  In  letters  this  is  denoted  by  writing 
A  before  B.  The  method  by  which  we  have  arrived  at 
the  conception  of  vector  steps  shows  us  at  once  how  to 
add  them. 

Vector  steps  are  added  by  placing  them  end  to  end 
in  such  fashion  that  they  retain  their  own  peculiar 
directions,  and  so  that  a  point  moving  continuously 
along  the  zigzag  thus  formed  will  always  follow  the 
directions  indicated  by  the  arrow-heads.  This  may  be 
shortly  expressed  by  saying  the  steps  are  to  be  arranged 
in  continuous  sense.  The  sum  of  the  vector  steps  is 
then  the  single  directed  step  which  joins  the  start  of 


POSITION. 

the  zigzag  thus  formed  to  its  finish.  In  fig.  55  let  a  I,  c  <7, 
ef,  and  y  h  be  directed  steps.  Then  let  A  B  be  drawn 
equal  and  parallel  to  a  b ;  from  B  draw  B  c  equal  and 
parallel  to  cd,  from  c  draw  c  D  equal  and  parallel  to  ef, 
and  finally  from  D  draw  D  E  equal  and  parallel  to  g  h. 
We  have  drawn  our  zigzag  so  that  the  arrow-heads  all 
have  '  a  continuous  sense.'  Hence  the  directed  step 
A  E  is  the  sum  of  the  four  given  vert  <  »rs.  If,  for  example, 
at  c  we  had  stepped  c  D',  equal  and  parallel  to  ef,  but  on 
the  opposite  side  of  EC  to  c  D,  and  then  taken  D'E', 


Fio.  55. 

equal  and  parallel  to  gli,  the  reader  will  remark  at  once 
that  the  arrow-heads  in  B  c,  c  D'  and  B'F/  are  not  in 
continuous  sense,  or  we  have  not  gone  in  the  proper 
direction  at  c. 

Should  the  vector  steps  all  have  the  same  direction, 
the  zigzag  evidently  becomes  a  straight  line ;  in  this 
case  the  vector  steps  are  added  precisely  like  scalar 
quantities;  or,  when  vector  steps  may  be  looked  upon 
as  scalar,  our  extended  conception  of  addition  takes  the 
ordinary  arithmetical  meaning. 

We  can  now  state  a  very  important  aspect  of  position 


156      THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT    SCIENCES. 

in  a  plane ;  namely,  if  the  position  of  G  relative  to  A 
be  denoted  by  the  directed  step  or  vector  A  G,  it  may 
also  be  expressed  by  the  sum  of  any  number  of  directed 
steps,  the  start  of  the  first  of  such  steps  being  at  A  and 
the  finish  of  the  last  at  G  (see  fig.  56).  We  may  write 
this  result  symbolically  :— 

AG  =  AB     +    EC     +     CD     +     D  E     +    EP    +    FG. 

It  will  be  at  once  obvious  that  in  our  example  as  to 
finding  the  'George,'  the  stranger  might  have  been 
directed  by  an  entirely  different  set  of  instructions  to 


FIG.  56. 

his  goal.  In  fact,  he  might  have  been  led  to  make 
extensive  circuits  in  or  about  the  town  before  he  reached 
the  place  he  was  seeking.  But,  however  he  might  get 
to  G,  the  ultimate  result  of  his  wanderings  would  be 
what  he  might  have  accomplished  by  the  directed  step 
A  G  supposing  no  obstacles  to  have  been  in  his  way  (or, 
'as  the  crow  flies').  Hence  we  see  that  with  our 
extended  conception  of  addition  any  two  zigzags  of 
directed  steps,  A  B  c  D  E  F  G  and  A  B'  c'  D'  E'  F'  G  (which 
may  or  may  not  contain  the  same  number  of  com 
ponent  steps),  both  starting  in  A  and  finishing  in  G, 


POSITION.  157 

must  be  looked  upon  as  equivalent  instructions  ;  or,  we 
must  take 

AB    +     EC     +    CD     +     DE     +     EF    +     FG    =    AG    = 

AB'   +   B'C'   +   cV   +   D'E'   -(-   E'F'   +   F'G. 

In  other  words,  two  sets  of  directed  steps  must  be 
held  to  have  an  equal  sum,  when,  their  starts  being 
the  same,  the  steps  of  both  sets  will,  added  vector-wise 
have  the  same  finish. 

Now  let  us  suppose  our  stranger  were  unconsciously 
standing  in  front  of  the  '  George '  when  he  asked  his 
question  as  to  its  whereabouts,  and  further  let  us  sup 
pose  that  the  person  who  directed  him  gave  him  a  per 
fectly  correct  instruction,  but  sent  him  by  a  properly 
chosen  set  of  right  and  left  turnings  a  considerable 
distance  round  the  town  before  bringing  him  back  to 
the  point  A  from  which  he  had  set  out.  In  this  case 
we  must  suppose  the  '  George '  not  to  be  at  the  point 
G,  but  at  the  point  A.  The  total  result  of  the  stranger's 
wanderings  having  brought  him  back  to  the  place  from 
which  he  started  can  be  denoted  by  a  zero  step ;  or 
we  must  write  (fig.  56)  — 

We  may  read  this  in  words  :  The  sum  of  vector  steps 
which  form  the  successive  sides  of  a  closed  zigzag  is 
zero.  Now  we  have  found  above  that— 

Hence,  in  order  that  these  two  statements  (i)  and  (ii) 
•may  be  consistent,  we  must  have  —  G  A  equal  to  A  G,  or 

AG  +  G  A  =  0. 

This  is  really  no  more  than  saying  that  if  a  step  be 
taken  from  A  to  G,  followed  by  another  from  G  to  A,  the 
total  operation  will  be  a  zero  step.  Yet  the  result  is 


158      THE   COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

interesting  as  showing  that  if  we  consider  a  step  from 
A  to  G  as  positive,  a  step  from  G  to  A  must  be  considered 
negative.  It  enables  us  also  to  reduce  subtraction  of 
vectors  to  addition.  For  if  we  term  the  operation 
denoted  by  A  B  —  D  c  a  subtraction  of  the  vectors  A  TS 
and  DC,  since  D  c  +  c  D  =  0,  the  operation  indicated 
amounts  to  adding  the  vectors  A  B  and  c  D,  or  to 
A  B  +  c  D.  Hence,  to  subtract  two  vectors,  we  reverse 
the  sense  of  one  of  them  and  add. 


TJ  R  P  JS    Q  TV 

FIG.  57. 

The  result  A  G  4-  G  A  =  0  can  at  once  be  extended  to 
any  number  of  points  lying  on  a  straight  line.  Thus,  if 
pQESTUvbea  set  of  such  points — 

For  starting  from  p  and  taking  in  succession  the  steps 
indicated,  we  obviously  come  back  to  P,  or  have  per 
formed  an  operation  whose  result  is  equivalent  to  zero, 
or  to  remaining  where  we  started. 

§  4.   The  Addition  of  Vectors  obeys  the  Commutative 
Law. 

We  can  now  prove  that  the  commutative  law  holds 
for  our  extended  addition  (see  p.  5).  First,  we  can 
show  that  any  two  successive  steps  may  be  interchanged. 
Consider  four  successive  steps,  A  B,  B  c,  CD,  and  D  E. 
It'  at  B  instead  of  taking  the  step  B  c  we  took  a  step 
B  H  equal  to  C  D  in  magnitude,  sense  and  direction,  we 
could  then  get  from  H  to  D  by  taking  the  step  H  D. 
Now  let  B  D  be  joined ;  then  in  the  triangles  B  H  D,  D  c  B 
the  angles  at  B  and  D  are  equal,  because  they  are  formed 
by  the  straight  line  B  D  falling  on  two  parallel  lines  B  H 


rosmox.  159 

and  c  D  ;  also  the  side  B  D  is  common,  and  B  H  is  equal 
to  c  D.  Hence  it  follows  (see  p.  73)  that  these  triangles 
are  of  the  same  shape  and  size,  or  H  D  is  equal  to  B  c  ; 
and  again  the  angles  B  D  H  and  DBG  are  equal,  or  H  D 
and  B  c  are  parallel.  Thus  the  step  H  D  is  equal  to  the 
step  B  c  in  direction,  magnitude  and  sense.  We  have 
then  from  the  two  methods  of  reaching  D  from  B, 

EC    +    C  D   =   B  D   =    BH    +    HD 

=   C  D    f    B  C 

by  what  we  have  just  proved. 


FIG.  58. 

Hence  any  two  successive  steps  may  be  inter 
changed.  By  precisely  the  same  reasoning  as  we  have 
used  on  p.  11  we  can  show  that  if  we  may  inter 
change  any  two  successive  steps  of  our  zigzag  we  may 
interchange  any  two  steps  whatever  by  a  series  of 
changes  of  successive  steps ;  that  is,  the  order  in 
which  vectors  are  added  is  indifferent. 

The  importance  of  the  geometry  of  vectors  arises 
from  the  fact  that  many  physical  quantities  can  be  re 
presented  as  directed  steps.  We  shall  see  in  the  suc 
ceeding  chapter  that  velocities  and  accelerations  are 
quantities  of  this  character. 

§  5.  On  Methods  of  Determining  Position  in  a  Plane. 

It  has  been  remarked  (see  p.  99)  that  scalar 
quantities  may  be  treated  as  steps  measured  along  a 


160      THE    COMMON    SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT    SCIENCES. 

straight  line.  In  this  case  we  only  require  one  point  on 
this  line  to  be  given,  and  we  can  determine  the  relative 
position  of  any  other  by  merely  stating  the  magnitude 
of  the  intervening  step.  A  line  is  occasionally  spoken 
of  as  being  a  space  of  one  dimension ;  in  one-dimensioned 
space  one  point  suffices  to  determine  the  relative  posi 
tion  of  all  others. 

When  we  consider  however  position  in  a  plane,  in 
order  to  determine  the  whereabouts  of  a  point  p  with 
regard  to  another  A  we  require  to  know  not  only  the 
magnitude  but  the  direction  of  the  step  A  P.  Hence 
what  scalar  steps  are  to  one-dimensioned  space,  that 


FIG.  59. 

are  vector  steps  to  plane  space.  In  order  to  deter 
mine  the  direction  of  a  step  A  p  we  must  know  at 
least  one  other  point  B  in  the  plane.  Space  which 
requires  two  points  to  determine  the  position  of  a  third 
is  usually  termed  space  of  two  dimensions.  There  are 
various  methods  in  general  use  by  which  position  in 
two-dimensioned  space  is  determined.  We  shall  men 
tion  a  few  of  them,  confining  our  remarks  however  to 
the  plane,  or  to  space  of  two  dimensions  which  is  of 
the  same  shape  on  both  sides. 

(a)  We  may  measure  the  distances  between  A  and 
p  and  between   B   and   p.     If  these   distances  are  of 


POSITION.  101 

scalar  magnitude  r  and  r'  respectively,  there  will  be 
:wo  points  corresponding  to  any  two  given  values  of 
r  and  r' ;  namely  P  and  p'  the  intersections  of  the  two 
jircles  with  centres  at  A  and  B  and  radii  equal  to  r  and 
ft  respectively.  We  may  distinguish  these  points  as 
jeing  one  above,  and  the  other  below  A  B.  Only  in 
:he  case  of  the  circles  touching  will  the  two  points 
coincide;  if  the  circles  do  not  meet,  there  will  be  no 
point. 

If  p  moves  so  that  for  each  of  its  positions  with  re 
gard  to  A  and  B  the  quantities  /•  and  /•'  satisfy  some  defi 
nite  relation,  we  shall  obtain  a  continuous  set  of  points 
in  the  plane  or  a  curved  line  of  some  sort.  For  example, 
if  we  fasten  the  ends  of  a  bit  of  string  of  length  I  to 


FIG.  60. 

pins  stuck  into  the  plane  of  the  paper  at  A  and  B,  and 
:hen  move  a  pencil  about  so  that  its  point  p  always 
remains  on  the  paper,  and  at  the  same  time  always 
xeeps  the  string  A  P  B  taut  round  its  point,  the  pencil 
will  trace  out  that  shadow  of  the  circle  which  we  have 
called  an  ellipse. 

In  this  case  r  +  r'  =  AP  +  PB  =  I,  the  constant  length 
of  the  string.  This  relation  r  +  r'  =  I  is  an  equation 
3etween  the  scalar  quantities  r,r'  and  /,  which  holds 
for  every  point  on  the  ellipse,  and  expresses  a  metric- 
property  of  the  curve  with  regard  to  the  points  A  and  B. 

If  on  the  other  hand  we  cause  P  to  move  so  that  the 
lifference  of  A  P  and  B  p  is  a  constant  length  (r  —  /  =  /), 
then  p  will  trace  out  the  curve  we  have  termed  the 

M 


1G2      THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF    THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

hyperbola.  We  can  cause  p  to  move  in  this  fashion  by 
means  of  a  very  simple  bit  of  mechanism.  Suppose  a 
rod  B  L  capable  of  revolving  about  one  of  its  ends  B  :  let 
a  string  of  given  length  be  fastened  to  the  other  end 
L  and  to  the  fixed  point  A.  Then  if,  as  the  rod  is 
moved  round  B,  the  string  be  held  taut  to  the  rod  by  a 


Fio.  61. 


pencil  point  p,  the  pencil  will  trace  out  the  hyperbola. 
For  since  LP  +  PA  equals  a  constant  length,  namely 
that  of  the  string,  and  L  P  +  p  B  equals  a  constant  length, 
namely  that  of  the  rod,  their  difference  or  PA  — PB  is 
equal  to  the  constant  length  which  is  the  difference  of 
the  string  and  the  rod. 


FIG.  62. 

The  points  A  and  B  are  termed  in  the  cases  of  both, 
ellipse  and  hyperbola  the  foci.  The  name  arises  from 
the  following  interesting  property.  Suppose  a  bit  of 
polished  watch  spring  were  bent  into  the  form  of  an 
ellipse  so  that  its  flat  side  was  turned  towards  the  foci 
of  the  ellipse ;  then  if  a  hot  body  were  placed  at  one 
focus  B,  all  the  rays  of  heat  or  light  radiated  from  I 


POSITION. 


1G3 


which  fell  upon  the  spring  would  be  collected,  or,  as  it  is 
termed,  '  f  ocussed '  at  A  ;  hence  A  wotild  be  a  much 
brighter  and  hotter  point  than  any  other  within  the 
ellipse  (B  of  course  excepted).  The  name  focus  is 
from  the  Latin,  and  means  a  fireplace  or  hearth. 
This  property  of  the  arc  of  an  ellipse  or  hyperbola,  that 
it  collects  rays  radiating  from  one  focus  in  the  other, 
depends  upon  the  fact  that  A  p  and  p  B  make  equal 
angles  with  the  curve  at  P.  This  geometrical  relation 
corresponds  to  a  physical  property  of  rays  of  heat  and 
igdit;  namely,  that  they  make  the  same  angle  \\ifh  • 
reflecting  surface  when  they  reach  it  and  when  tliev 
leave  it. 

A  third  remarkable  curve,  which  is  easily  obtained 
from  this  our  first  method  of  considering  position,  i ; 
the  lemniscate  of  James  Bernoulli  (from  the  Latin 
lemniscus,  a  ribbon).  It  is  traced  out  by  a  point  p  which 
moves  so  that  the  rectangle  under  its  distances  from  A 
and  B  is  always  equal  to  the  area  of  a  given  square 


(r./  =  c2).  If  the  given  square  is  greater  than  the 
square  on  half  A  B,  it  is  obvious  that  P  can  never 
cross  between  A  and  B  ;  if  it  is  equal  to  the  square 
on  half  A  B,  the  lemniscate  becomes  a,  figure  of  oigh'  : 
while  if  it  is  less,  the  curve  breaks  up  into  two  loops 
In  our  figure  a  series  of  lemniseates  are  represented. 
A  set  of  curves  obtained  by  varying  a  constant,  like  the 

M   2 


1G4      THE    COMMON    SEN7SE    OP    THE    EXACT    SCIENCES. 

given  square  in  the  case  of  the  lemniscate,  is  termed  a 
family  of  curves.  Such  families  of  curves  constantly 
occur  in  the  consideration  of  physical  problems. 


§  6.  Polar  Co-ordinates. 

(13}  The  points  A  and  B  determine  a  line  whose 
direction  is  A  B.  If  we  know  the  length  A  p  and  the 
angle  BAP,  we  shall  have  a  means  of  finding  the 
position  of  P.  Let  r  be  the  number  of  linear  units  in 
A  P  and  Q  the  number  of  angular  units  in  BAP,  where 
r  and  6  may  of  course  be  fractions.  In  measuring  the 
angle  6  we  shall  adopt  the  same  convention  as  we  have 
employed  in  discussing  areas  (see  p.  134)  ;  namely,  if  a 
line  at  first  coincident  with  A  B  were  to  start  from 


FIG.  64. 

that  position,  and  supposed  pivoted  at  A  to  rotate 
counter-clockwise  till  it  coincided  with  A  p,  it  would 
trace  out  the  angle  6.  Angles  traced  out  clockwise  will 
like  areas  be  considered  negative.  Thus  the  angle  BAP' 
below  AB  would  be  obtained  by  a  rotation  clockwise 
from  AB  to  AP',  and  must  therefore  be  treated  as 
negative.  On  the  other  hand,  we  might  have  caused  a 
line  rotating  about  A  to  take  tip  the  position  A  p'  by 
rotating  it  counter  clockwise  through  an  angle  marked 
in  our  figure  by  the  dotted  arc  of  a  circle,  Further  we 


POSITION.  ]  65 

might  obviously  have  reached  A  p  by  a  line  rotating 
about  A  clockwise,  and  might  thus  represent  the  position 
of  P  by  a  negative  angle.  But  even  after  we  had  got  to 
p  we  might  cause  our  line  to  rotate  about  A  a  complete 
n Timber  of  times  either  clockwise  or  counter-clockwise, 
and  we  should  still  be  at  the  end  of  any  such  number 
of  complete  revolutions  in  the  same  position  A  p. 

We  have  then  the  following  four  methods  of  rotating 

~  r* 

a  line  about  A  from  coincidence  with  A  B  to  coincidence 
vith  A  P  :  — 

(i)   Counter-clockwise  from  A  B  to  A  P. 
(ii)   Clockwise  from  A  B  to  A  p. 

(iii)  The  first  of  these  combined  with  any  number 
of  complete  revolutions  clockwise  or  counter 
clockwise. 

(iv)  The  second  of  these  combined  with  any  number 
of  complete  revolutions  clockwise  or  counter 
clockwise. 

The  following  terms  have  been  adopted  for  this 
method  of  determining  position  in  space  : — 

The  line  A  B  from  which  we  begin  to  rotate  our  line  is 
iermed  the  initial  ('beginning')  line;  the  length  AP  is 
;ermed  the  null  us  vector  (from  two  Latin  words  signify  - 
ng  the  carrying  rod  or  spoke,  because  it  carries  the 
ooint  P  to  the  required  position);  the  angle  BAP  is 
ermed  the  rectorial  angle,  because  it  is  traced  out  by 
lie  radius  vector  in  moving  from  A  B  to  the  required 
position  A  P  ;  A  is  termed  the  pole,  because  it  is  the  end 
)f  the  axis  about  which  we  may  suppose  the  spoke  to 
;urn.  Finally  A  p  (=  r]  and  the  angle  B  A  p  (=  0}  are 
•ermed  the  polar  co-ordinates  of  the  point  p,  because 
hey  regulate  the  position  of  P  relative  to  the  pole  A  and 
he  initial  line  AB. 


166      THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 


§  7.   The  Trigonometrical  Ratios. 

If  p  M  be  a  perpendicular  dropped  from  p  on  A  B,  the 
ratios  of  the  sides  of  the  right-angled  triangle  PAM 
have  for  the  purpose  of  abbreviation  been  given  the 
following  names  : — 

P  Af 

— ,  or  the  ratio  of  the  perpendicular  to  the  hypo- 

A  Jr 

thenuse,  is  termed  the  sine  of  the  angle  BAP. 
— ,  or  the  ratio  of  the  base  to  the  hypothenuse,  is 
termed  the  cosine  of  the  angle  BAP. 

P  M 

— ,  or  the  ratio  of  the  perpendicular  to  the  base,  is 
termed  the  tangent  of  the  angle  BAP. 

— ,  or  the  ratio  of  the  base  to  the  perpendicular,  is 
PM 

termed  the  cotangent  of  the  angle  BAP. 

If  6  be  the  scalar  magnitude  of  the  angle  BAP  these 
ratios  are  written  for  shortness,  sin6,  cos6,  tand,  and 
cotO,  respectively.  Let  us  take  any  other  point  Q  on  A  P, 
and  drop  QN  perpendicular  to  A  B,  then  the  triangles 
Q  A  N,  PAM  are  of  the  same  shape  (see  p.  106),  and  thus 
the  ratios  of  their  corresponding  sides  are  equal.  It 
follows  from  this  that  the  ratios  sine,  cosine,  tangent, 
and  cotangent  for  the  triangles  Q  A  N  and  PAM  are  the 
same.  Hence  we  see  that  sin#,  cos#,  tan#,  and  cot0 
are  independent  of  the  position  of  p  in  AP;  they  are 
ratios  which  depend  only  on  the  magnitude  of  the  angle 
B  A  P  or  6.  They  are  termed  (from  two  Greek  words 
meaning  triangle-measurement)  the  trigonometrical 
ratios  of  the  angle  6.  The  discussion  of  trigonometrical 
ratios,  or  Trigonometry,  forms  an  important  element  of 


POSITION.  ]G7 


pure  mathematics.  The  names  of  the  trigonometrical 
ratios  themselves  are  derived  from  an  older  terminology 
which  connected  these  ratios  with  the  figure  supposed 
to  be  presented  by  an  archer  whose  bow  string  was 
placed  against  his  breast.1 

§  8.  Spirals. 

Let  us  suppose  the  spoke  A  p  to  revolve  about  the  pole 
A,  and  as  it  revolves  let  the  point  p  move  along  the  spoke 
in  such  fashion  that  the  magnitude  r  of  A  p  is  always  de 
finitely  related  in  some  chosen  manner  to  the  magnitude 
6  of  B  A  P.  Then  if  p  be  taken  as  the  point  of  a  pencil 
it  will  mark  out  a  curved  line  on  the  plane  of  the  paper. 


FIG.  65. 

Such  a  curved  line  is  termed,  a.  polar  curve  or  spiral, 
the  latter  name  from  a  Greek  word  denoting  the  coil, 
as  of  a  snake,  to  which  some  of  these  curves  may  be 
considered  to  bear  resemblance. 

One  of  the   most  interesting  of  these  spirals  was 
invented  by  Conon    of  Samos    (/.  B.C.  250),    but   its 

1  In  our  figure  the  angle  BAP  has  been  taken  /»>•.-•  than  a  right 
it  may  have  any  niairnitude  whatever.    It  has  been  found  u.-et'ul  to  establish 
a  convention  with  ivaranl  to  the  signs  of  the  perpendicular  i'  M  and  th- 
AM.     psiis  considered  positive  when   it  falls  above,  but   in-native  when  it 
falls  below  the  initial  line  AB;  AM  is  considered  pc>iiive  wh^n  M  falls  to 
the  right,  but  negative  when  it  falls  to  the  left  of  A.    The  reader  will  under 
stand  the  value  of  this  convention  better  after  examining  £§  11,  12. 


168      THE   COMMON    SENSE    OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

chief  properties  having  been  discussed  by  Archimedes, 
it  is  usually  called  by  his  name.  The  spiral  of  Archi 
medes  is  defined  in  the  following  simple  manner.  As 
the  spoke  A  p  moves  uniformly  round  the  pole,  the  point 
p  moves  uniformly  along  the  spoke.  Let  c  be  the  posi 
tion  of  P  when  the  spoke  coincides  with  the  starting 
line  A  B,  and  let  A  C  contain  a  units  of  length.  Then  if  p 
be  the  position  of  the  pencil-point  when  the  spoke  has 
described  an  angle  BAP  containing  6  units  of  angle,  and 
if  A  c'  be  measured  along  A  P  equal  to  A  c,  the  point  will 
have  described  the  distance  c'  P  while  the  spoke  was 
turning  through  the  angle  CAP.  But  since  the  point 
and  spoke  are  moving  uniformly,  the  distance  c'  p  must 
be  proportional  to  the  angle  CAP,  or  their  ratio  must 
be  an  unchangeable  quantity  for  all  distances  and 
angles.  Let  b  be  the  distance  traversed  by  the  point 
along  the  spoke  while  it  turns  through  unit  angle, 
then  c'  P  must  be  equal  to  the  number  of  units  in  c  A  P 
multiplied  by  b.  Using  r  to  denote  the  magnitude  of 
A  P  we  have 

c'  p  =  b  x   6,  but  c'  P  =  r  —  a ; 

Thus  :  r  =  a  +  b  6. 

This  relation  between  r  and  6  is  termed  the  polar  equa 
tion  to  the  spiral. 

The  following  easily  constructed  apparatus  will 
enable  us  to  draw  a  spiral  of  Archimedes.  D  E  F  is  a 
circular  disc  of  chosen  radius ;  upon  the  edge  of  this 
disc  is  cut  a  groove.  To  the  centre  A  of  the  disc  is 
attached  a  rod  or  spoke  which  can  be  revolved  about  A 
as  a  pole  ;  at  the  other  end  of  this  rod  is  a  small  grooved 
wheel  or  pulley  G.  A  string  is  then  fastened  to  some 
point  D  in  the  groove  of  the  disc,  and  passing  round 
the  pulley  G  is  attached  to  a  small  block  p  which  holds 


POSITION. 


169 


a  pencil  and  is  capable  of  sliding  in  a  slot  in  the  spoke. 
If  this  block  be  fastened  by  a  piece  of  elastic  to  A,  the 
string  from  p  to  G  and  then  from  G  to  the  groove  on  the 
disc  will  remain  taut.  Now  supposing  the  disc  to  be 
held  firmly  pressed  against  the  paper,  and  the  spoke 
A  c  to  be  turned  about  A  counter-clockwise,  the  pencil 
P  will  describe  the  required  spiral.  For  the  string 
touching  the  disc  in  the  point  T  the  figure  GAT  always 
remains  of  the  same  size  and  shape  as  we  turn  the 
spoke  about  the  pole ;  hence  the  length  of  string  G  T  is 


FIG.  66. 

constant.  Thus  if  a  length  of  string  represented  by 
the  arc  D  T  be  wound  on  to  the  disc  as  we  turn  the 
spoke  from  the  position  A  B  to  the  position  A  P,  the 
length  P  G  (since  the  length  G  T  always  remains  the 
same)  must  lose  a  length  equal  to  D  T  as  P  moves  from 
0  to  P.  But  the  amount  of  string  D  T  wound  on  to  the 
disc  is  proportional  to  the  angle  through  which  the 
spoke  A  P  has  been  turned ;  hence  the  point  p  must  have 
moved  towards  G  through  a  distance  proportional  to 
this  angle,  or  it  has  described  a  spiral  of  Archimedes. 


170       THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

Once  in  possession  of  a  good  spiral  of  this  kind  we 
can  solve  a  problem  which  often  occurs,  namely  to  divide 
an  angle  into  any  number  of  parts  having  given  ratios. 
Let  the  given  angle  be  placed  with  its  vertex  at  the 
pole  of  the  spiral  and  let  the  radii  vectores  A  c  and  AP 
be  those  which  coincide  with  the  legs  of  the  angle. 
About  the  pole  A  describe  a  circular  arc  with  radius  A  c  to 
meet  A  p  in  c'.  Now  let  us  suppose  the  problem  solved 
and  let  the  radii  vectores  A  D,  A  E,  A  F  be  those  which 
divide  the  angle  into  the  required  proportional  parts. 
If  these  radii  vectores  meet  the  circular  arc  c  c'  in  D',  E', 


FIG.  67. 

F'  respectively,  then  by  the  fundamental  property  of  the 
spiral  we  have  at  once  the  lines  D'D,  E'E,  F'F,  C'P  in  the 
same  ratio  as  the  angles  CAD,  c  A  E,  c  A  F,  CAP.  Thus 
if  we  measure  lengths  A  d,  A  e,  A/  equal  to  A  D,  A  E,  A  F 
respectively  along  AP,  c' P  will  be  divided  in  definto 
lengths  which  are  proportional  to  the  required  angles. 
Conversely,  if  we  were  to  divide  C'P  into  segments  c'd,  d  e, 
ef,  and/p  in  the  same  ratio  as  the  required  angular 
division,  we  should  obtain  lengths  Ad,  AS,  A/,  which 
would  be  the  radii  of  circles  with  a  common  centre 
A  cutting  the  spiral  in  the  required  points  of  angular 
division.  The  spiral  of  Archimedes  thus  enables  us  to 


POSITION.  171 

1-educe  the  division  of  an  angle  in  any  fashion  to  the 
like  division  of  a  line. 

Now  the  division  of  a  line  in  any  fashion,  that  is, 
into  a  set  of  segments  in  any  given  ratio,  is  at  once 
solved  so  soon  as  we  have  learnt  by  the  aid  of  a  pair  of 
compasses  or  a '  set  square  '  to  draw  parallel  lines.  Thus 
suppose  -\ve  require  to  divide  the  line  c'p  into  segments  in 
the  ratio  of  3  to  5  to  4  ;  we  have  only  to  mark  off  along 
any  line  through  c',  say  C'Q,  steps  C'R,  R  s,  s  T  placed  end 
to  end  and  containing  3,  5,  and  4  units  of  any  kind  respec 
tively.  If  the  finish  of  the  last  step  T  be  joined  to  P 

0, 


and  the  parallels  Rr,  ss  to  T  P  through  R  and  s  be  drawn 
to  meet  c'p  in  r  and  s,  then  C'P  will  be  divided  in  r  and  s 
into  segments  in  the  required  ratio  of  3  to  5  to  4.  This 
follow.-;  at  once  from  our  theory  of  triangles  of  the  same 
shape  (see  p.  10(5).  For,  since  R  c'  r,  s  c'.s',  and  T  C'P  are 
such  triangles,  they  have  their  corresponding  sides  pro 
portional,  and  the  truth  of  the  proposition  is  obvious. 

A  spiral  of  Archimedes  accurately  cut  in  a  metal  or 
ivory  plate  is  an  extremely  useful  addition  1o  the  ordi 
nary  contents  of  a  box  of  so-called  mathematical  instru 
ments. 

§  9.   The  Equiangular  Spiral. 

Another  important  spiral  was  invented  by  Descartes, 
land  is  termed  from  two  of  its  chief  properties  either  the 
equiangular  or  the  logarithmic 


172       THE    COMMON    SENSE    OF    THE    EXACT    SCIENCES. 


Let  B  o  A  be  a  triangle  with  a  small  angle  at  o,  and 
whose  sides  o  A  and  o  B  are  of  any  not  very  greatly  differ 
ent  lengths.  Upon  o  B  and  upon  the  opposite  side  of  it 
to  A  construct  a  triangle  BOG  ot  the  same  shape  as  the 
triangle  A  o  B,  and  in  such  wise  that  the  angles  at  B  and 
A  are  equal.  Then  upon  o  c  place  a  triangle  COD  of  the 
same  shape  as  either  BOG  or  A  0  B  ;  upon  o  D  a  fourth 
triangle  DOE,  again  of  the  same  shape ;  upon  o  E  a  fifth 
triangle,  and  so  on.  We  thus  ultimately  form  a  figure 
consisting  of  a  number  of  triangles  A  o  B,  B  o  c,  c  0  D, 


V 


FIG.  69. 

DOE,  &c.,  of  the  same  shape,  all  placed  with  one  of  their 
equal  angles  at  o,  and  in  such  fashion  that  each  pair 
has  a  common  side  consisting  of  two  non-corresponding 
sides  (that  is,  of  sides  not  opposite  to  equal  angles) .  The 
points  A  B  c  D  E,  &c.,  will  form  the  angles  of  a  polygonal 
line,  and  if  the  angles  at  o  are  only  taken  small  enough, 
the  sides  of  this  polygon  will  appear  to  form  a  continuous 
curved  line.  This  curved  line,  to  which  we  can  approach 
as  closely  as  we  please  by  taking  the  angles  at  o  smaller 
and  smaller,  is  termed  an  equiangular  spiral.  It  derives 
its  name  from  the  following  property, — A  B,  B  c,  c  D,  &c., 


POSITION.  1"3 

being  corresponding  sides  of  triangles  of  the  same  shape, 
make  equal  angles  o  B  A,  o  c  B,  o  D  c,  &c.,  with  the  cor 
responding  sides  o  B,  o  c,  o  D,  &c. ;  but  when  the  angles 
at  o  are  taken  very  small  A  B,  B  c,  c  D,  &c.,  will  appear  as 
successive  elements  of  the  curved  line  or  spiral.  Hence 
the  arc  of  the  spiral  meets  all  rays  from  the  pole  o  at 
the  same  constant  angle. 

Let  us  now  endeavour  to  find  the  relation  between 
any  radius  vector  OP  (  =  r)  and  the  vectorial  angle  A  o  P 

0); 

Since  all  our  triangles  A  o  B,  BOG,  COD,  &c.,  are  of 
the  same  shape,  their  corresponding  sides  must  be  pro 
portional  (see  p.  100) ;  or, 

OB       _    OC  OD       _    OE       _    OP  o 

OA  OB  00  OD  OE 

Each  of  these  equal  ratios  will  therefore  have  the  snme 
scalar  value  ;  let  us  denote  that  value  by  the  symbol  p. 
Then  we  must  have 

O  B  =  /i  .  O  A  ;    O  C  =  /i  .  O  B  ;    O  D  =  /4  .  0  C  ;    &C. 

Or,  OB  =  /A.OA;oo=/i2.OA;OD  =  /i3 .  o  A,  and  so  on. 
Hence  if  o  N  be  the  radius  vector  which  occurs  after  n 
equal  angles  are  taken  at  o,  we  must  have 

ON  =  /j,n  .  o  A. 

Now  let  the  very  small  angles  at  o  be  each  taken 
equal  to  some  small  part  of  the  unit  angle  ;  thus  we 
might  take  them  yJ -^  or  -  (l\--  of  the  unit  angle.  We 
will  represent  this  fraction  of  the  unit  angle  by  1/6, 
where  we  may  suppose  b  a  whole  number  for  greater 
simplicity.  Further  let  us  use  X  to  denote  the  6th 
power  of  fj.,  or  A,  =  /A  With  the  notation  explained  on 
p.  144  we  then  term  /a,  a  6th  root  of  X,  and  write 


174       THE    COMMON    SEXSE    OF   THE    EXACT    SCIENCES. 

Hence  finally  we  have  o  N  =  o  A  .  \n  *  1/7),  or  in  words  : 
The  base  of  the  nih  equal-shaped  triangle  placed  about 
o  is  equal  to  the  base  of  the  first  multiplied  by  a 
certain  quantity  A,  raised  to  the  power  of  ft-times  the 
quantity  1/6  which  expresses  the  magnitude  of  the 
equal  angles  at  o  in  units  of  angle. 

Now  let  the  spoke  or  ray  o  P  fall  within  the  angle 
which  is  formed  by  the  successive  rays  o  N  and  o  Q  of 
the  system  of  equal-shaped  triangles  round  o.  Then  o  N 
makes  an  angle  n-times  1/6,  and  o  Q  an  angle  (n-t 
times  1/6  with  o  A.  Hence  the  angle  A  o  P,  or  0,  must  lie 
in  magnitude  between  n/b  and  (n  + 1)/ 6.  Similarly  the 
magnitude  of  o  P  must  lie  between  those  of  o  N  and  o  Q. 
Now  by  sufficiently  decreasing  the  angles  at  o  we  can 
approach  nearer  and  nearer  to  the  form  of  the  spiral, 
and  the  ray  o  P  must  always  lie  between  two  successive 
rays  of  our  system  of  triangles.  The  angle  6,  which  will 
thus  always  lie  between  njb  and  (u-fl)/6,  can  only 
differ  from  either  of  them  by  a  quantity  less  than  ]  /  6. 
If  then  6  be  taken  large  enough,  or  the  equal  angles  at 
o  small  enough  fractions  of  the  unit  angle,  this  dif 
ference  1/6  can  be  made  vanishingly  small.  In  this  case 
we  may  say  that  in  the  limit  the  angle  6  becomes  equal  to 
njb  and  the  ray  o  P  equal  to  o  N  or  o  Q,  which  will  tnus 
be  ultimately  equal.  Hence  o  p  =  o  A  .  \n'b  —  o  A  .  Xe,  or  in 
words  :  If  a  ray  o  P  of  the  equiangular  spiral  make 
an  angle  A  o  P  with  another  ray  o  A,  the  ratio  of  o  P  to 
o  A  is  equal  to  a  certain  number  A,  raised  to  the  power 
of  the  quantity  Q  which  expresses  the  magnitude  of  the 
angle  A  o  P  in  units  of  angle. 

If  a  and  r  be  the  numbers  which  express  the 
magnitudes  of  OA  and  OP,  we  have  r  =  a  \9.  This  is 
termed  the  polar  equation  of  the  spiral, 

We  proceed  to  draw  some  important  results  from  a 


POSITION.  175 

consideration  of  tins  spiral.  The  reader  will  at  once 
observe  that  the  ratio  of  any  pair  of  rays  o  P  and  0  Q  is 
equal  to  the  ratio  of  any  other  pair  which  include  an 
equal  angle,  for  the  ratio  of  any  pair  of  rays  depends 
only  on  the  included  angle.  Further,  if  we  wanted  to 
multiply  the  ratio  of  any  two  quantities  p  and  q  by  the 
ratio  of  two  other  quantities  /•  and  .•>•  we  might  proceed, 
as  follows  :  Find  rays  of  the  equiangular  spiral  o  P,  o  Q, 
O  R,  o  S  containing  the  same  number  of  linear  units  as 
)  fb  r>  6>  '-oiitain  units  of  quantity  (see  p.  (J(J),  and  let 


6  be  the  angle  between  the  first  pair,   </>  the   angle 
between  the  second  pair. 
Then 


OP  on 

whence   it   follows    that  —  -    x       --  =  X9  x  X*  = 

OP         OK 

or  is  equal  to  the  ratio  of  any  pair  of  rays  which 
include  an  angle  $+(/>.  Thus  if  the  angle  QOT  be 
taken  equal  to  $,  and  o  T  be  the  corresponding  ray  of 

O  I1 

the  spiral,  -       =   X9+*,  and  is  a  ratio  equal  to  the  pro 

duct  of  the  given  ratios.  Hence  to  find  the  product 
of  ratios  we  have  only  to  add  the  angles  between  pairs 
I  of  rays  in  the  given  ratios,  and  the  ratio  of  any  two 
rays  including  an  angle  equal  to  the  sum  will  be  equal 


176       THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

to  the  required  product.  Thus  the  equiangular  spiral 
enables  us  to  replace  multiplication  by  addition.  This  is 
an  extremely  valuable  substitution,  as  it  is  much  easier 
to  add  than  to  multiply. 

Since  — -  divided  by  —  =  V  divided  by  \*=  V~ 
OP  J  on 

it  is  obvious  that  we  may  in  like  fashion  replace  the 
division  of  two  ratios  by  the  subtraction  of  two 
angles.  A  set  of  quantities  like  the  angles  at  the  pole 
of  an  equiangular  spiral  which  enables  us  to  replace 
multiplication  and  division  by  addition  and  subtrac 
tion  is  termed  a  table  of  logarithms.  Since  the  equi 
angular  spiral  acts  as  a  graphical  table  of  logarithms, 
it  is  frequently  termed  the  logarithmic  spiral. 

§  10.  On  the  Nature  of  Logarithms. 

Since  in  the  logarithmic  spiral  o  p  =  o  A  x  \8,  where 
6  is  equal  to  the  angle  A  o  p,  we  note  that  as  0  increases, 
or  as  the  ray  o  p  revolves  round  o,  o  P  is  equally  mul 
tiplied  during  equal  increments  of  the  vectorial  angle 
A  o  P.  When  one  quantity  depends  upon  another  inj 
such  fashion  that  the  first  is  equally  multiplied  "fori 
equal  increments  of  the  second,  it  is  said  to  grow  ati 
logarithmic  rate.  This  logarithmic  rate  is  measured  byi 
the  ratio  of  the  growth  of  the  first  quantity  for  uniti 
increment  of  the  second  quantity  to  the  magnitude  of 
the  first  quantity  before  it  started  this  growth. 

Let  us  endeavour  to  apply  this  to  our  equiangular!] 
spiral.  Suppose  A  o  B,  B  o  c,  c  o  D  &c.  to  be  as  before11 
the  triangles  by  means  of  which  we  construct  it  (seeij 
fig.  69),  the  angles  at  o  being  all  equal  and  very  small. 
Along  o  B  measure  a  length  o  A'  equal  to  o  A  ;  along  o  c, 
a  length  o  B'  equal  to  OB;  along  o  D,  a  length  o  c' 


POSITION.  177 

iqual  to  oc,  and  so  on.     Then  A'B,  B'C,  C'D,  &c.,  will 
>e  the  successive  growths  as  a  ray  is  turned  succes 
sively  from  o  A  to  0  B,  from  o  B  to  o  c,  and  so  on.    Join 
A  A',   B  B',   c  c',   &c.     Now  the   triangles   A  o  B,    BOG, 
0  D,  Sec.,  are  all  of  the  same  shape ;  so  too  are   the 
sosceles  triangles  A  o  A',  B  o  B',  c  o  c',  &c.     Hence  the 
differences  of  the  corresponding  members  of  these  sets, 
A  A'B,  B  B'C,  c  C'D,  &c.,  must  also  be  of  equal  shape,  and 
;hus  their  corresponding  sides  proportional.    It  follows 
;hen  that  the  lengths 

A'B,  B'C,  C'D,  &c.,  are  in  the  same  ratio  as  the  lengths 
A'A,  B'B,  c'c,  &c.,  or  again  as  the  lengths 
OA,  OB,  oc,  &c. 

Whence  we  deduce  that 

A'B       B'C        C'D      „ 
—  _  -  -  =   -  -  =&c. 
o A      OB        oc 

the  growth  A'B  is  always  in  a  constant  ratio  to 
;he  growing  quantity  OA. 

Now,  if  the  angles  at  o  be  very  small,  the  line  A  A' 
practically  coincide  with  the  arc  of  a  circle  with 
:entre  o  and  radius  equal  to  o  A.  Hence  (see  p.  143) 
IA'  will  ultimately  equal  o  A.  x  the  angle  A  o  A',  while 
;he  angle  at  A'  will  ultimately  be  equal  to  a  right 
ingle. 

Further,  the  ratio  of  A'B  to  A  A'  remains  the  same 
'or  all  the  little  triangles  A  A'B,  BB'C,  CC'D,  &c.  It  is  in 
pach  case  the  ratio  of  the  base  to  the  perpendicular  when 
look  upon  these  triangles  with  regard  to  the  equal 
Angles  ABA',  B  c  B',  CD  c',  &c.  Now  these  are  the 
.ngles  of  the  triangles  which  give  the  spiral  its  name. 
!jet  any  one  of  them,  and  therefore  all  of  them,  be  equal 
a.  By  definition  the  cotangent  of  an  angle  (see  p.  1  GO) 
equal  to  the  ratio  of  the  base  to  the  perpendicular. 

N 


178      THE    COMMON    SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

Hence 

A'B  A'B 

cota  = 


A  A'        o  A  x  angle  A  o  A'' 

A'B  , 

or  —  —  angle  A  o  A    x  cota. 

OA 

Now  A  B  denotes  the  growth  for  an  angle  A  o  A 
supposed  very  small ;  whence  it  follows  that  the  loga 
rithmic  rate,  or  the  ratio  of  the  growth  to  the  growing 
quantity  for  unit  angle,  is  equal  to  cota.  Thus  the 
logarithmic  rate  for  the  growth  of  the  ray  of  the  equi 
angular  or  logarithmic  spiral,  as  it  describes  equa! 
angles  about  the  pole,  is  equal  to  the  cotangent  of  the 
angle  which  gives  its  name  to  the  spiral. 

Let  us  suppose  o  A  to  be  unit  of  length,  then,  since 
0  P  =  0  A  x  \9,  the  result  OP  of  revolving  the  ray  OA 
through  an  angle  0  equal  to  unity  will  be  X,  or  X  is  the 
result  of  making  unity  grow  at  logarithmic  rate  cota. 

Now  let  us  denote  by  the  symbol  e  the  result  oi 
making  unity  grow  at  logarithmic  rate  unity  during 
the  description  of  unit  angle.  Then  e  will  have  some 
definite  numerical  value.  This  value  is  found,  by  a  pro 
cess  of  calculation  into  which  we  cannot  enter  hei*e,  to  be 
nearly  equal  to  2*718.  This  means  that,  if  while  unri 
ray  were  turned  through  unit  angle  it  grew  at  loga 
rithmic  rate  unity,  its  total  growth  (1'718)  would  lie 
between  eight  and  nine-fifths  of  its  initial  length.  Since 
e  is  the  result  of  turning  unit  ray  through  unit  angle 
and  since  the  ray  is  equally  multiplied  for  equal  multi 
ples  of  angle,  ei  must  represent  the  result  of  turning  unil 
ray  through  7  unit  angles.  Hitherto  we  have  beer 
concerned  with  unit  ray  growing  at  logarithmic  rate 
unity  ;  now  let  us  suppose  unity  to  grow  at  logarithmic 
rate  7  ;  then  it  grows  7  times  as  much  as  if  it  grew  al 
log.iiithmic  rate  unity,  or  the  result  of  turning  unit  raj 


POSITIOX.  179 

througli  unit  angle,  while  it  grows  at  logarithmic  rate 
7,  must  be  the  same  as  if  we  spread  1/7  of  this  rate 
of  growth  over  7  unit  angles  ;  that  is,  as  if  we  caused 
unity  to  grow  at  logarithmic  unity  for  7  unit  angles, 
or  ey.  .Hence  ey  denotes  the  result  of  making  unit  ray 
grow  at  logarithmic  rate  unity  while  it  describes  7  unit 
angles,  or  again  of  making  unit  ray  grow  at  loga 
rithmic  rate  7  while  it  describes  a  unit  of  angle. 

Let  us  inquire  what  is  the  meaning  of  ey  when  7  is 
a  commensurable  fraction  equal  to  ,s/i,  s  and  t  bring 
integers.  Let  a-  be  the  as  yet  unknown  result  of  turn 
ing  unit  ray  througli  an  angle  equal  to  7  while  it 
grows  at  unit  logarithmic  rate  ;  then  <c'  will  be  the 
result  of  turning  unit  ray  through  t  angles  equal  to 
7  while  it  grows  at  unit  rate  ;  but  t  angles  equal  to  7 
form  an  angle  containing  s  units,  or  this  result  must 
be  the  same  as  the  result  of  turning  unity  through  an 
angle  s  while  it  grows-  at  logarithmic  rate  t.  Thus  we 
have  x'  =  es.  That  is,  x  is  a  £-th  root  of  e*,  or,  as  we  write 
it,  equal  to  e"  =  eY.  Thus  ey,  if  7  be  a  commensurable 
fraction,  is  the  result  of  causing  unit  rav  to  errow  at 

•/ 

logarithmic  rate  unity  through  an  angle  equal  to  7,  or 
as  we  have  seen  at  logarithmic  rate  7  through  unit 
angle. 

Now  let  us  suppose  it  possible  to  find  a  commen 
surable  fraction  7  equal  to  cota  ;  then  the  result  of 
making  unity  grow  at  logarithmic  rate  cota  as  it  is 
turned  through  unit  angle  must  be  &.  But  we  have 
seen  (see  p.  1V8)  that  it  is-  equal  to  X.  Hence 

\  =  &f. 

Further,  the  result  of  making  unity  grow  at  loga 
rithmic  rate  cota  as  it  is  turned  through  an  an^le  # 

zj  O 

is  \e  ;  or, 


N    2 


ISO      THE    COMMON    SENSE    OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

Tims  we  may  write     OP  =  OA.Xfl  =  OA.  ey°, 
or  with  our  previous  symbols, 

r  =  a .  ey9. 

This  is  therefore  the  equation  to  our  equiangular 
spiral  expressed  in  terms  of  the  quantity  e. 

If  we  take  a  spiral  in  which  a  is  the  unit  of  length, 
and  in  which  cota  or  7  is  also  unity,  we  find 

r  =  ee. 

The  symbol  ee  is  then  read  the  exponential  of  6,  and  6 
is  termed  the  natural  logarithm  of  r.  It  is  denoted 
symbolically  thus : — 

0  =  loger. 

The  quantity  e  is  termed  the  base  of  the  natural  system 
of  logarithms.     Our  spiral  would  in  this  case  form  a 
graphical  table  of  natural  logarithms. 
Returning  to  the  equation 

r  =  a  .  e"*9, 

let  us  suppose  7  so  chosen  that  e?=10 ;  then  7  will  re 
present  the  angle  through  which  unit  ray  must  be 
turned  in  order  that,  growing  at  unit  logarithmic  rate, 
it  may  increase  to  ten  units.  Again  taking  a  to  be 
of  unit  length  we  find  r  =  eYfl=10e.  0  is  in  this  case 
termed  the  logarithm  of  r  to  the  base  10,  and  this  is 
symbolically  expressed  thus  : — 

0  =  Iog10  r. 

The  spiral  obtained  in  this  case  would  form  a  graphical  I T 
table  of  logarithms  to  the  base  10.     Such  logarithms  |  f 
are  those  which  are  usually  adopted  for  the  purposes  of 
practical  calculation. 

Natural    logarithms   were   first   devised    by    John 
Napier,  who  published  his  invention  in  1614.1     Loga- 
1  Logarithmorum  Canonis  Descriptio.    4to.    Edinburgh,  1614. 


POSITION. 


181 


ritlims  to  the  base  10  are  now  used  in  all  but  the 
simplest  numerical  calculations  which  it  is  needful  to 
make  in  the  exact  sciences ;  their  value  arises  solely 
from  the  fact  that  addition  and  subtraction  are  easier 
operations  than  multiplication  and  division. 

§  11.   The  Cartesian  Method  of  Determining  Position. 

(7)  In  order  to  determine  the  position  of  a  point  p, 
in  space  of  two  dimensions,  we  may  draw  the  line  B  A  B', 
joining  the  given  points  A  B  and  another  line  c  A  c'  at 
right  angles  to  this  through  A.  These  will  divide  the 
plane  into  four  equal  portions  termed  <]_Ha<l,-<ii<t*.  Let 
P!  M  be  a  line  drawn  from  the  point  PJ  (the  position  of 


B'- 


M 


which  relative  to  A  we  wish  to  determine),  parallel  to 
C  A  and  meeting  B'A  B  in  M.  Then  we  may  state  the 
following  rule  to  get  from  A  to  P,  :  Take  a  step  A  M 
from  A  on  the  line  B'A  B,  and  then  a  step  to  the  left  at 
fight  angles  to  this  equal  to  M  P,.  Now  a  step  lik-> 
A  M  may  be  taken  either  forwards  along  A  B  or  back 
wards  along  AB'.  Precisely  as  before  (seep.  100)  w? 


1S2      Till-:    COMMON    SENSJS    OF    THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

shall  take  +  A  M  to  mean  a  step  fonvards  along  A  B, 
and  —AM  to  mean  a  step  AM'  backwards  along  A  B' 
through  the  same  distance  A  M.  Let  us  use  the  letter 

t? 

i  to  denote  the  operation,  which  we  have  represented 
by  (?r/2)  on  p.  151.  Thus  applied  to  unit  step  it  will 
signify  :  Step  forwards  in  the  direction  of  the  previous 
step  and  from  its  finish  unit  distance,  and  then 
rotate  this  unit  distance  through  a  right  angle 
counter-clockwise  about  the  finish  of  the  previous  step. 
The  operator  i  placed  before  a  step,  thus  i.  MPI?  will 
then  be  interpreted  as  follows:  Step  from  M  in  the 
direction  A  B  a  distance  equal  to  the  length  M  p,,  and 
then  rotate  this  step  M  PI  about  M  counter-clockwise 
through  a  right  angle.  We  are  thus  able  to  express 
symbolically  the  position  of  PI  relative  to  A,  or  the  step 
A  P15  by  the  relation 

AP,  =  AM  4-  i.M  Pr 

If  we  had  to  get  to  a  point  P4  in  the  quadrant  B  A  c', 
instead  of  to  p,,  we  should  have,  instead  of  stepping  for 
wards  from  M,  to  step  backwards  a  distance  M  P4,  and 
then  rotate  this  through  a  right  angle  counter-clock 
wise.  The  step  backwards  would  be  denoted  by  insert 
ing  a  —  sign  as  a  reversing  operation  (see  p.  39),  and 
we  should  have 

A  P4   =   A  M   —  i  .  M  P4. 

Next  let  us  see  how  we  should  get  to  a  point  like  P2 
in  the  quadrant  c  A  B',  where  P2  is  at  a  perpendicular 
distance  P2  M'  from  A  B'.  First,  we  must  take  a  step, 
A  M',  backwards ;  this  is  denoted  by  —AM';  secondly, 
we  must  step  forwards  from  M'  a  distance  M'  P2 ;  since 
this  step  is  forwards,  it  will  be  towards  A  ;  thirdly,  by 
applying  the  operation  i  to  this  step,  we  rotate  it  about 


POSITION.  183 

M'  counter-clockwise  through  a  right  angle,  and  so 
reach  P2.  Hence 

A  P2  =  —  A  M'  +  i  .  M'  P2. 

Finally,  if  we  wish  to  reach  P3  in  the  quadrant 
B'A  c',  we  must  step  backwards  A  M',  and  then  still 
further  backwards  a  step  M'  P3,  and  lastly  rotate  this 
step  counter-clockwise  through  a  right  angle.  This 
will  be  expressed  by 

A  P3    =    —  A  M'    —  i  .  M'  P2. 

Now  let  us  suppose  pp  P2,  P3,  P4,  to  be  the  four  corners 
of  a  rectangular  figure  whose  centre  is  at  A  and  whose 
sides  are  parallel  to  BAB'  and  c  A  c'.  L  't  the  number 
of  units  in  A  M  be  x,  and  the  number  in  M  Pt  be  y,  then 
we  may  represent  the  four  steps  which  determine  the 
positions  of  the  p's  relative  to  A  as  follows  :— 

AP,  =  x  +  iy  A  P2  =  —  x  +  iy 

A  P3  =  —  x  —  i  y  A  P4  =  x  —  i  y. 

Here  x  and  y  are  mere  numbers,  but,  when  we 
represent  these  numbers  by  steps  on  a  line,  the 
y-numbers  are  to  be  taken  on  a  certain  line  at  right 
angles  to  that  line  on  which  the  ^-numbers  are  taken. 
Thus  the  moment  we  represent  our  x  and  y  numbers 
by  lengths,  they  give  us  a  means  of  determining  posi 
tion. 

The  quantities  x  and  y  might  thus  be  used  to  deter 
mine  the  position  of  a  point,  if  we  supposed  them  to 
carry  with  them  proper  signs.  Our  general  rule  would 
then  be  to  step  forwards  from  A  along  A  B  a  distance  x, 
and  then  from  the  end  of  a;  a  distance  forwards  equal 
to  y ;  rotate  this  step  y  about  the  end  of  x  counter 
clockwise  through  a  right  angle,  and  the  finish  of  // 
will  then  be  the  point  determined  by  the  quantities  x,  y. 


184      THE   COMMON   SENSE   OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

If  x  or  y  be  negative,  the  corresponding  forwards  must 
be  read:  Step  forwards  a  negative  quantity,  that  is, 
step  backwards.  Thus  : — 

Pt,  or  position  in  the  quadrant  B  A  c  is  determined  by  x,  y. 


CAB 
B'AC' 

C' AB 


-y. 


The  quantities  x  and  y  are  termed  the  Cartesian  co 
ordinates  of  the  point  p,  this  method  of  determining  the 


u 


I  ! 
FIG.  72. 

position  of  a  point  having  been  first  used  by  Descartes. 
BAB'  and  c  A  c'  are  termed  the  co-ordinate  axes  of  x 
and  y  respectively,  while  A  is  called  the  origin  of  co 
ordinates.  For  example,  let  the  Cartesian  co-ordinates 
of  a  point  be  (  —  3,  2).  How  shall  we  get  at  it  from  the 
origin  A  ?  If  P  be  the  point,  we  have  A  p  =  —  3  +  i  .  2. 
Hence  we  must  step  backwards  3  units ;  from  this  point 
step  forwards  2  and  rotate  this  step  2  about  the  ex 
tremity  of  the  step  3  through  a  right  angle  counter 
clockwise  ;  we  shall  then  be  at  the  required  point. 

If  p  be  determined  by  its  Cartesian  co-ordinates  x 
and  y,  we  might  find  a  succession  of  points,  p,  by  always 


POSITION. 


185 


taking  a  step  y  related  in  a  certain  invariable  fashion  to 
any  step  x  which  has  been  previously  made. 

Such  a  succession  of  points  p,  obtained  by  giving 
*  every  possible  value,  will  form  a  line  or  curve,  and 
the  relation  between  x  and  y  is  termed  its  Cartesian 
equation. 

As  an  instance  of  this,  suppose  that  for  every  step 
«,  we  take  a  step  y  equal  to  the  double  of  it.  Then  we 
shall  have  for  our  relation  y  —  2  a;,  and  our  instructions 


LL 


I 


, 


• 


MM 





FIG.  73. 

to  reach  any  point  p  of  the  series  are  x  +  i.2  x.  Suppose 
'the  quadrant  BAG  divided  into  a  number  of'little  squares 
by  lines  parallel  to  the  axes,  and  let  us  take  the  sides  of 
(these  squares  to  be  of  unit  length.  Then  if  we  take  in 
Succession  x  =  l,  2,  3,  &c.,  we  can  easily  mark  off  our 
steps.  Thus  :  1  along  A  B  and  then  2  to  the  left ;  2 
(along  A  B  and  4  to  the  left ;  3  along  A  B  and  then  6  to 
the  left ;  4  along  A  B  and  then  8  to  the  left ;  5  along 
A  B  and  then  10  to  the  left,  and  so  on.  It  will  be 
iobvious  (by  p.  106)  that  our  points  all  lie  upon  a 


186       THE    COMMON   SEXSE    OF    THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

straight  line  through  A,  and  however  many  steps  we 
take  along  A  B,  followed  by  double  steps  perpendicular 
to  it,  we  shall  always  arrive  at  a  point  on  the  same 
line.  If  we  gave  x  negative  values  we  should  obtain 
that  part  of  the  line  which  lies  in  the  third  quadrant 
B'AC'.  Hence  we  see  that  y  =  2  x  is  the  equation  to 
a  straight  line  which  passes  through  A. 

Let  us  take  another  example.  Suppose  that  the 
rectangle  contained  by  y  and  a  length  of  2  units, 
always  contains  as  many  units  of  area  as  there  are 
square  units  in  x2.  Our  relation  in  this  case  may  be 
expressed  by  2  y  =  x2,  and  we  have  the  following  series 
of  steps  from  A  to  points  of  the  series  : — 

4  +  i.8,  5  +  /i.2-j-5,          C  +  'i.lS,  &c. 

We  can  by  means  of  our  little  squares  easily  follow 
out  the  operations  above  indicated  ;  we  thus  find  a  series 
of  points  like  those  in  the  quadrant  B  A  c  of  the  figure. 
If   however    we   had  taken  x   equal   to   the   negative 
quantities  —  1,  —2,  —3,  —  4,  —5,  —6,  &c.,  we  should 
have  found  precisely  the  same  values  for  y,  because  we 
have  seen  that  (  —  a)  x  (  —  a)=  a?  =(4- a)  x  (  +  a).     These 
negative  values  for  x  give  us  a  series  of  points  like  those 
in  the  quadrant  B'AC  of  the  figure.     It  is  impossible 
that  any  points  of  the  series  should  lie  below  B  A  B', 
because  both  negative  and  positive  values  for  x  give  \ 
when  squared  a  positive  value  for  the  step  y,  so  that  no  | 
possible  £-step  would  give  a  negative  y-step.   The  series  | 
of  points  obtained  in  this  fashion  are  found  to  lie  upon  I 
a  curve  which  is  one  of  those  shadows  of  a  circle  which  I 
we  have  termed  parabolas. 

Hence  we  may  say  that  2y=x^  is  the  equation  to  a  I 
parabola. 


rosmox. 


1ST 


This  method  of  plotting  out  curves  is  of  great  value, 
and  is  largely  used  in  many  branches  of  physical  inves 
tigation.  For  example,  if  the  differences  of  successive 
«-steps  denote  successive  intervals  of  time,  and  i/-steps 
the  corresponding  heights  of  the  column  of  mercury 
ill  a  barometer  above  some  chosen  mean  position, 


the  series  of  points  obtained  will,  if  the  intervals 
of  time  be  taken  small  enough,  present  the  appear 
ance  of  a  curve.  This  curve  gives  a  graphical  repre 
sentation  of  the  variations  of  the  barometer  for  the 
whole  period  during  which  its  heights  have  been  plotted 
out.  Barometric  curves  for  the  preceding  day  are  now 
given  in  several  of  the  morning  papers.  Heights  cor 
responding  to  each  instant  of  time  are  in  this  case 


188      THE   COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 


generally  registered  automatically  by  means  of  a  simple 
photographic  apparatus. 

The  plotting  out  of  curves  from  their  Cartesian 
equations,  usually  termed  curve  tracing,  forms  an  ex 
tremely  interesting  portion  of  pure  mathematics.  It 
may  be  shown  that  any  relation,  which  does  not  in 
volve  higher  powers  of  x  and  y  than  the  second,  is  the 
equation  to  some  one  of  the  forms  taken  by  the  shadow 
of  a  circle. 

§  12.  Of  Complex  Numbers. 

We  shall  now  return  to  our  symbol  of  operation  i, 
and  inquire  a  little  closer  into  its  meaning.  Let  the 
point  P  be  denoted  as  before  by  A  M  +  i .  M  p,  so  that  we 


FIG.  75. 

should  read  this  result :  Step  from  A  to  M  along  A  B, 
and  from  M  to  p'  along  the  same  line  (where  M  p'  =  M  p), 
finally  rotate  M  P'  about  M  counter-clockwise  through 
a  right  angle ;  M  p'  will  then  take  up  the  position  M  P. 
Now  let  M  Q'  be  taken  equal  to  A  p',  then  A  M  +  i  .  M  Q'  will 
mean  :  Step  from  A  to  M  and  then  from  M  perpendicular 


POSITION.  189 

to  A  M  to  the  left  through  a  distance,  M  Q',  equal  to  A  p'. 
Since  however  MQ'==AP'  =  AM  +  MP=MP  +  PQ',  PQ' 
must  be  equal  to  A  M  and  we  can  read  our  operation 

A  M  +  i  .  (M  p  +  p  Q'), 

which  denotes  two  successive  steps  at  right  angles  to 
A  M,  namely  M  p  followed  by  the  step  P  Q'.  Suppose  now 
we  wished  to  rotate  this  latter  step  through  a  right  angle 
counter-clockwise,  we  should  have  to  introduce  before 
it  the  symbol  i,  and  M  p  +  i  .  p  Q'  would  signify  the  step 
M  P  followed  by  the  step  p  Q  at  right  angles  to  it  to  the 
left.  Now  P  Q'  is  equal  to  A  M,  and  hence  the  result  of 
this  operation  must  bring  us  to  Q,  a  point  on  A  c  which, 
might  have  been  reached  by  the  simple  operation 
0  +  i '•  •  A  Q.  Thus  we  may  put 

0  +  i  .  A  Q  =  A  M  +  i  .  (M  P  +  i  •  P  Q) 

=  AM  +  t.MP  +  'i.i.PQ; 

or,  since  the  quantities  A  Q,  AM,  M  p,  and  p  Q  here 
merely  denote  numerical  magnitudes,  and  since  as  such 
A  Q  =  M  P  and  AM  =  P  Q,  we  must  have 

0   =  A  M  +  i  .  i  .  A  M, 

or  —  A  M  =  i  .  i  .  A  M. 

Thus  the  operation  i  is  of  such  a  character  that 
repeated  twice  it  is  equivalent  to  a  mere  reversor,  or,  as 
we  may  express  it  symbolically, 
-  1  =  i\ 

This  may  be  read  in  words :  Turn  a  step  counter 
clockwise  through  a  right  angle,  and  then  again 
counter-clockwise  through  another  right  angle,  and  we 
have  the  same  result  as  if  we  had  reversed  the  step. 
Now  we  have  seen  (p.  1 44)  that  if  ,t  be  such  a  quantity 
that  multiplied  by  itself  it  equals  a,  x  is  termed  the 
square  root  of  a,  and  written  Va.  Hence  since 
i2=  —1,  we  may  write  i=V  -  1. 


190      THE    COMMON    SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT    SCIENCES. 

This  symbol  is  completely  unintelligible  so  far  as 
quantity  is  concerned;  it  can  represent  no  quantity 
conceivable,  for  the  squares  of  all  conceivable  quantities 
are  positive  quantities.  For  this  reason  V  —  1  is  some 
times  termed  an  imaginary  quantity.  Treated  however 
as  a  symbol  of  operation  \/— 1  has  a  perfectly  clear  and 
real  meaning  ;  it  is  here  an  instruction  to  step  forwards 
a  unit  length  and  then  rotate  this  length  counter-clock 
wise  through  a  right  angle. 

Any  expression  of  the  form  x  +  V  —  1  y  is  termed  a 
complex  number. 

Let  P  be  any  point  determined  by  the  step  A  P  = 
AM  +  V  —  IMP,  and  let  r,  x,  y  be  the  numerical  values 
of  the  lengths  A  P,  AM,  and  p M.  It  follows  from  the 
right-angled  triangle  p  A  M  that  r2  =  x2  +  y2.  The 
quantity  r  is  then  termed  the  modulus  of  the  complex 
number  x  +  V  —  1  y. 

Further  let  the  angle  MAP  contain  6  units  of 
angle ;  then 

./,  PMty  -aAM          X 

sm0  =          =  -»       cos#  =  —  =  -, 
A  p       r  A  p        r 

or     y  =  r  sin<9,      x  =  r  cos#. 

The  angle  0  is  termed  the  argument  of  the  com 
plex  number.  Here  r  and  6  are  the  polar  co-ordinates 
of  P,  and  we  are  thus  able  to  connect  them  with  the  Car 
tesian  co-ordinates ;  they  are  respectively  the  modulus 
and  argument  of  the  complex  number  which  may  be 
formed  from  the  Cartesian  co-ordinates.  Since  r  is 
merely  numerical  we  may  write  the  complex  number 
x  -f-  V  —  ly  in  the  form  r  .  (cos#  +  V  — 1  sin0),  or  as 
the  product  of  its  modulus  and  the  operator 

cos0  +  V  —  1  siu#, 


rosmox. 


191 

Hence  we 


•which  depends  solely  on  its   argument  6. 
may  interpret  the  step 

A  p  =  r .  (cos#  +  V—  1  sin#) 

as  obtained  in  the  following  fashion:  Rotate  unit  length 
from  A  B  through  an  angle  0,  and  then  stretch  it  in 
the  ratio  of  r  :  1.  The  latter  part  of  this  operation 


B 


Fir.;.  76. 

will  be  signified  by  the  modulus  r,  the  former  by  the 
operator  (cos#  +  V—l  sinfl).  Thus  if  AD  be  of  unit 
length  and  lying  in  A  B,  we  may  read — 

A  p  =  r  .  (cosO  +  V  —  1  sin$)  .  A  D, 

and  we  look  upon  our  complex  number  as  a  symbol 
denoting  the  combination  of  two  operations  performed 
on  a  unit  step  A  D. 

Starting  then  from  the  idea  of  a  complex  mimbev 
as  denoting  position,  we  have  been  led  to  a  new  opera 
tion  represented  by  the  symbol  cos#  +  V  — 1  sin#. 
This  is  obviously  a  generalised  form  of  our  old  symbol 
V  —  l.  The  operator  cos#  +  V  —  l  sin#  applied  to 
any  step  bids  us  turn  the  step  through  an  angle  0. 
"We  shall  see  that  this  new  conception  has  important 
results. 


192      THE   COMMON   SENSE   OP   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 


§  13.  On  the  Operation  which  turns  a  Step  through  a 

given  Angle. 

Suppose  we  apply  the  operator  (cos#  +  V— 1  sin#) 
twice  to  a  unit  step.  Then  the  symbolic  expression 
for  this  operation  will  be 

(cos0  +  V^l  sind)  (cos0  +  V^l  sin0), 
or  (cos0  +  V^l  sintf)2. 

But  to  turn  a  step  first  through  an  angle  6  and  then 
through  another  angle  0  is  clearly  the  same  operation 
as  turning  it  by  one  rotation  through  an  angle  26,  or 
as  applying  the  operator  cos2#  +  V  — 1  sin20.  Hence 
we  are  able  to  assert  the  equivalence  of  the  operations 
expressed  by  the  equation — 

(cos0  +  V-I  sin(9)2  =  cos20  +  V-l  sin20. 
In  like  manner  the  result  of  turning  a  step  by  n 
operations  through  successive  angles  equal  to  6  must 
be   identical   with   the   result   of  turning   it   at   once" 
through  an  angle  equal  to  n  times  0,  or  we  may  write 

(cos#  +  V  —  1  sin#)w  =  cosnd  +  V—l  sinnd. 

This  important  equivalence  of  operations  was  first  ex 
pressed  in  the  above  symbolical  form  by  De  Moivre, 
and  it  is  usually  called  after  him  De  Moivre's  Theorem. 
We  are  now  able  to  consider  the  operation  by  means 
of  which  a  step  A  P  can  be  transformed  into  another  A  Q. 
\Ve  must  obviously  turn  AP  about  A  counter-clockwise 
till  it  coincides  in  position  with  A  Q  ;  in  this  case  p 
will  fall  on  p',  so  that  A  p'  =  A  p.  Then  we  must 
stretch  A  p'  into  A  Q ;  this  will  be  a  process  of  multiply 
ing  it  by  some  quantity  p,  which  is  equal  to  the  ratio 
of  A  Q  to  A  P'. 


[  POSITION.  193 

Expressing  this   symbolically,   if  </>  be   the   angle 
p  A  Q,  we  have 

(cos$  +  V  —I  sine/))  .  A  P  =  A  P'. 

p  .  (cOSff)  +  V  —  1  Sin<£)  .AP=/3.AP'  =  AQ. 

This  last  equation  we  can  interpret  in  various  ways : 
(i)  p .  (cos</>  +  V  —  1  sin</>)  is  a  complex  number  of 
which  p  is  the  modulus  and  </>  the  argument.  Hence 
we  may  say  that  to  multiply  a  step  by  a  complex  number 
is  to  turn  the  step  through  an  angle  equal  to  the  argu 
ment  and  to  alter  its  length  by  a  stretch  represented 
by  the  modulus. 

(ii)  Or,  again,  we  may  consider  the  step  A  p  as  itself 
representing  a  complex  number,  x  +  V  —  I  y,  or  if  r  be 


FIG.  77. 

the  scalar  value  of  A  p  and  6  the  angle  BAP,  we  may 
put  A  P  =  r(cos#  -f  V  —  I  sin#).  Similarly  A  Q  will  be  a 
complex  number,  and  its  scalar  magnitude  (=  p  .  A  P' 
=  p  r)  will  be  its  modulus,  while  the  angle  B  A  Q  =  6  +  <£ 
will  be  its  argument.  We  have  then  the  following 
identity — 


p  (coS(/>  +  V —  1  sin<£)  .  r  (cos^>  +  v  —  1  sin$)  = 
/>  r .  (cos#  +  (f>  +  V  —  1  cos(£  +  ^) . 

This  may  be  read  in  two  ways : 

First,  the  product  of  two  complex  numbers  is  itself 
a  complex  number,  and  has  the  product  of  the  moduli 
for  its  modulus,  the  sum  of  the  arguments  for  its 
argument. 

o 


194      THE    COMMON   SEXSE    OF    THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

Or  secondly,  if  we  turn  unit  step  through  an 
angle  0  and  give  a  stretch  r,  and  then  turn  the  result 
obtained  through  an  angle  <f>  and  give  it  a  stretch  p, 
the  result  will  be  the  same  as  turning  unit  step  through 
an  angle  6  +  <f>  and  giving  it  a  stretch  equal  to  p  r. 

Thus  we  see  that  any  relation  between  complex 
numbers  may  be  treated  either  as  an  algebraical  fact 
relating  to  such  numbers,  or  as  a  theorem  concerning 
operations  of  turning  and  stretching  unit  steps. 

(iii)  We  may  consider  what  answer  the  above  identity 
gives  to  the  question :  What  is  the  ratio  of  two 
directed  steps  A  Q  and  A  p  ?  Or,  using  the  notation  sug 
gested  on  p.  45,  we  ask :  What  is  the  meaning  of  the 

symbol   ,  — -=-!  ?     A  step   like  A  p  (or  A  Q)  which   has 
|  AP 

magnitude,  direction,  and  sense  is,  as  we  have  noted, 
termed  a  vector.  We  therefore  ask :  What  is  the  ratio 
of  two  vectors,  or  what  operation  will  convert  one 
into  the  other  ?  The  answer  is  :  An  operation  which 
is  the  product  of  a  turning  (or  spin)  and  a  stretch. 
Now  the  stretch  is  a  scalar  quantity,  a  numerical 
ratio  by  which  the  scalar  magnitude  of  A  p  is  con 
nected  with  that  of  AQ.  The  stretch  therefore  is  a 
scalar  operation.  Further,  the  turning  or  spin  converts 
the  direction  of  A  p  into  that  of  A  Q,  and  it  obviously 
takes  place  by  spinning  A  p  round  an  axis  perpendi 
cular  to  the  plane  of  the  paper  in  which  both  A  p 
and  AQ  lie.  Thus  the  second  part  of  the  operation 
by  which  we  convert  A  p  into  A  Q  denotes  a  spin 
(counter-clockwise)  through  a  definite  angle  about  a 
certain  axis.  The  amount  of  the  spin  might  be 
measured  by  a  step  taken  along  that  axis.  Thus,  for 
instance,  if  the  spin  were  through  6  units  of  angle, 
we  might  measure  6  units  of  length  along  the  axis  to 


POSITION.  195 

denote  its  amount.  We  may  also  agree  to  take  this 
length  along  one  direction  of  the  axis  ('  out  from  the 
face  of  the  clock  ')  if  the  spin  be  counter-clockwise,  and 
in  the  opposite  direction  ('  behind  the  face  of  the  clock ') 
if  the  spin  be  clockwise.  Thus  we  see  that  our  spinning 
operation  may  be  denoted  by  a  line  or  step  having 
magnitude,  direction,  and  sense ;  that  is,  by  a  vector. 
We  are  now  able  to  understand  the  nature  of  the  ratio 
of  two  vectors;  it  is  an  operation  consisting  of  the  pro 
duct  of  a  scalar  and  a  vector.  This  product  was  termed 
by  Sir  William  Hamilton  a  '/""/<, •/<''<>»,  and  made  the 
foundation  of  a  very  powerful  calculus. 

Thus  a  quaternion  is  primarily  the  operation  which 
converts  one  vector  step  into  another.  It  does  this  by 
means  of  a  spin  and  a  stretch.  If  we  have  three  points 
in  plane  space,  the  reader  will  now  understand  how 
the  position  of  the  third  with  regard  to  the  first  can  bo 
made  identical  with  that  of  the  second  by  means  of  a 
spin  arid  a  stretch  of  the  step  joining  the  first  to  the 
third,  that  is,  by  means  of  a  quaternion.1 

§  14.  Relation  of  the  Spin  to  the  Logarithmic  Growth 
of  Unit  Step. 

Let  us  take  a  circle  of  unit  radius  and  endeavour 
to  find  how  its  radius  grows  in  describing  unit  an^lo 
about  the  centre.  Hitherto  we  have  treated  of  growth 
only  in  the  direction  of  length  ;  and  hence  it  might  be 
supposed  that  the  radius  of  a  circle  does  not  '  grow '  at 
all  as  it  revolves  about  the  centre.  But  our  method  of 
adding  vector  steps  suggests  at  once  an  obvious  extension 
of  our  conception  of  growth.  Let  a  step  AP  become 

1  The  term  'stretch'  must  be  considered  to  include  a  squeeze  or  u 
stretch  denoted  by  a  scalar  quantity  p  less  than  unity. 

o  2 


1  06      THE    COMMON   SEXSE    OF    THE   EXACT    SCIENCES. 

A  Q  as  it  rotates  about  A  through  the  angle  P  A  Q,  then 
if  we  marked  off  A  Q  a  distance  A  P'  equal  to  A  P,  P'  Q 
would  be  the  scalar  growth  of  A  p ;  that  is,  its  growth 


FIG.  78. 

in  the  direction  of  its  length.  But  if  A  p  be  treated 
as  a  vector  (see  p.  153) 

or  the  directed  step  p  Q  must  be  added  to  A  P  in  order  to 
convert  it  into  A  Q  ;  p  Q  may  be  thus  termed  the  directed 
growth  of  A  P.  If  we  join  p  p',  we  shall  have  P  Q  equal 
to  the  sum  of  P  p'  and  P'  Q.  Now  if  the  angle  PAP'  be 
taken  very  small  p  p'  will  be  ultimately  perpendicular 
to  AP,  and  this  part  of  the  growth  PQ  might  be 
represented  by  V  —  1.  PP'.  Hence  we  are  led  to 
represent  a  growth  perpendicular  to  a  rotating  line  by 
a  scalar  quantity  multiplied  by  the  symbol  V—  1. 

We  can  now  consider  the  case  of  our  circle  of  unit 
radius.     Let  o  P  be  a  radius  which  has  revolved  through 


FIG.  79. 


an  angle  6  from  a  fixed  radius  o  A,  and  let  o  Q  be  an 
adjacent  position  of  o  P  such  that  the  angle  Q  o  P  is  very 
small.  Then  p  Q  will  be  a  small  arc  sensibly  coincident 


POSITION.  1 97 

with  the  straight  line  p  Q,  and  the  line  p  Q  will  be  to  all 
intents  and  purposes  at  right  angles  to  o  P.  Hence  to 
obtain  o  Q  we  must  take  a  step  P  Q  at  right  angles  to 
OP.  This  we  represent  by  V—  1  QP.  Since  the  radius 
of  the  circle  is  unity  the  arc  Q  P,  which  equals  the 
radius  multiplied  by  the  angle  QOP  (see  p.  143),  must 
equal  the  numerical  value  of  the  angle  QOP.  Or  the 
growth  of  o  P  is  given  by  V  -  1  x  angle  QOP.  Now 
according  to  our  definition  of  growing  at  logarithmic 
rate  (seep.  176),  since  OP  is  equally  multiplied  in  de 
scribing  equal  angles  about  o,  it  must  be  growing  at 
logarithmic  rate.  What  is  this  logarithmic  rate  for 
unit  angle  ? 

It  must  equal    —    divided  by  the  ratio  of  the  an <rle 
OP 

o  0  P  to  unit  angle  =  -  -   =  v  —  1  since  o  P 

OP  x  angle  QOP 

is  unity.  Thus  o  P  is  growing  at  logarithmic  rate  V  —  1 
as  it  describes  unit  angle ;  that  is  to  say,  the  result  of 
turning  OP  through  unit  angle  might  be  symbolically 
expressed  by  e"J~l.  Hence  the  result  of  turning  OP 
through  an  angle  6  must  be  e^~l().  We  may  then  write 
OP  =  o  A  .ev"l°. 

Drop  p  M  perpendicular  to  o  A  and  produce  it  to  meet 
the  circle  again  in  p',  then  by  symmetry  M  P  =  M  P',  and 
we  have 

OP  =  o  M  -t-  V—  1  M  P. 

OP'  =  OM  —  V—  1  MP'. 

Now  since  o  P  and  o  P'  are  of  unit  magnitude, 

OM  PM 

cos0  =—  =  OM,     8in0  =  Q--  =  P  M. 

Also  the  angle  P'OM  equals  the  angle  M  o  P,  but,  according 


198      THE    COMMON    SENSE    OF   THE   EXACT    SCIENCES. 

to  our  convention  as  to  the  measurement  of  angles, 
it  is  of  opposite  sense,  or  equals  —  d.  Thus  we  must 
write 

OP'  =  OA  .e~v~ld 

Substituting  their  values,  we  deduce  the  symbolical 
results 

'^1  sin  01 


Further, 

OP  —  o  P'  =  2  A/— 1  P  M 
OP  +  OP'=  2oM; 
that  is, 

-'-ie        -^-  ~     nflj  f.. 

) 

These  values  for  cos#  and  sin0  in  terms  of  the  ex 
ponential  e  were  first  discovered  by  Euler.  They  are 
meaningless  in  the  form  (ii)  when  cos$  and  sin#  are 
interpreted  as  mere  numerical  ratios ;  bat  they  have  a 
perfectly  clear  and  definite  meaning  when  we  treat 
each  side  of  the  equation  in  form  (i)  as  a  symbol  of 
operation.  Thus  cos(9  +  V— 1  sin#  applied  to  unit 
step  directs  us  to  turn  that  step  without  altering  its 
length  through  an  angle  6 ;  on  the  other  hand,  e  ^~lti 
applied  to  the  same  step  causes  it  to  grow  at  logarith 
mic  rate  unity  perpendicular  to  itself,  while  it  is  turned 
through  the  angle  0.  The  two  processes  give  the  same 
result. 

§  15.  On  the  Multiplication  of  Vectors. 

We  have  discussed  how  vector  steps  are  to  be 
added,  and  proved  that  the  order  of  addition  is  in 
different  ;  we  have  also  examined  the  operation  denoted 


POSITIOX.  199 

by  the  ratio  of  two  vectors.  The  reader  will  naturally 
ask :  Can  no  meaning  be  given  to  the  product  of  two 
vectors  ? 

If  both  the  vectors  be  treated  as  complex  numbers, 
or  as  denoting  operations,  we  have  interpreted  their 
product  (seep.  193)  as  another  complex  number  or  as  a 
resultant  operation.  Or  again  we  have  interpreted 
the  product  of  two  vectors  when  one  denotes  an  ope 
ration  and  the  other  a  step  of  position ;  the  product 
in  this  case  is  a  direction  to  spin  the  step  through  ;i 
certain  angle  and  then  stretch  it  in  a  certain  ratio. 
But  neither  of  these  cases  explains  what  we  are  to 
understand  by  the  product  of  two  steps  of  position. 

Let  A  P,  A  Q  be  two  such  steps  :  What  is  the  meaning 
of  the  product  AP  .  AQ  ?  Were  A  P  and  A  Q  merely 


FIG.  80. 


scalar  quantities  then  their  product  would  be  purely 
scalar,  and  we  should  have  no  difficulty  in  interpreting 
the  result  A  P  .  P  Q  as  another  scalar  quantity.  But 
when  we  consider  the  steps  A  P,  P  Q  to  possess  not  only 


A 

Fio.  81. 


magnitude  but  direction,  the  meaning  of  their  product 
is  by  no  means  so  obvious. 

If  A  Q  were  at  right  angles  to  A  P  (see  fig.  81),  we 
should  naturally  interpret  the  product  A  P  .  A  Q  as  the 


200      THE   COMMON   SENSE   OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

area  of  the  rectangle  on  A  Q  and  A  p,  or  as  the  area  of 
the  figure  Q  A  p  E.  Now  let  us  see  how  this  area  might 
be  generated.  Were  we  to  move  the  step  A  Q  parallel 
to  itself  and  so  that  its  end  A  always  remained  in  the 
step  A  P,  it  would  describe  the  rectangle  Q  A  p  E  while  its 
foot  A  described  the  step  A  p.  Hence  if  A  P  and  A  Q  are 
at  right  angles  we  might  interpret  their  product  as 
follows : 

The  product  A  p .  A  Q  bids  us  move  the  step  A  Q 
parallel  to  itself  so  that  its  end  A  traverses  the  step  A  p ; 
the  area  traced  out  by  A  Q  during  this  motion  is  the 
value  of  the  product  A  p  .  A  Q. 

It  will  be  noted  at  once  that  this  interpretation, 
although  suggested  by  the  case  of  the  angle  Q  A  p  being 
a  right  angle,  is  entirely  independent  of  what  that  angle 
may  be.  If  Q  A  P  be  not  a  right  angle  the  area  traced 
out  according  to  the  above  rule  would  be  the  parallelo 
gram  on  A  P,  A  Q  as  sides.  Hence  the  interpretation  we 
have  discovered  for  the  product  A  p .  A  Q  gives  us  an 
intelligible  meaning,  whatever  be  the  angle  Q  A  p. 

There  is,  however,  a  difficulty  which  we  have  not  yet 
solved.  An  area  is  a  directed  quantity  (see  p.  134),  and 
its  direction  depends  on  how  we  go  round  its  perimeter. 
Now  the  area  Q  A  p  R  will  be  positive  if  we  go  round  its 
perimeter  counter-clockwise,  or  from  A  to  p ;  that  is,  in 


FIG.  82. 


the  direction  of  the  first  step  of  the  product  or  in  the 
direction  of  motion  of  the  second  or  moving  step.  Thus 
the  product  A  P  .  A  Q  will  be  the  area  Q  A  p  E  taken  with 
the  sign  suggested  by  the  step  A  p.  The  product  A  Q.  AP 


POSITION.  201 

will  be  formed  by  causing  the  step  A  p  to  move 
parallel  to  itself  along  A  Q,  and  it  is  therefore  also  the 
area  of  the  parallelogram  on  A  Q  and  A  p  ;  but  it  is  to  be 
taken  with  the  sign  suggested  by  A  Q,  or  it  is  the  area 

PAQE. 

By  our  convention  as  to  the  sign  of  areas, 

PAQE   =    —   QAPE, 
Or  A  Q  .  A  P   =    —   A  P  .  A  Q. 

Hence  we  see  that,  with  the  above  interpretation,  the 
/product  of  two  vectors  does  not  follow  the  commutative 
law  (see  p.  45). 

If  we  suppose  the  angle  Q  A  P  to  vanish,  and  the 
vector  A  Q  to  become  identical  with  A  p,  the  area  of 
the  enclosed  parallelogram  will  obviously  vanish  also. 
Thus,  if  a  vector  step  be  multiplied  by  itself,  the  product 
is  zero ;  that  is, 

A  P  .  AP  =  (A  p)2  =  0. 

If  we  take  a  series  of  vector  steps,  a,  /3,  y,  8,  &c. 
then  relations  of  the  following  types  will  hold  among 
them  : 

a2  =  0,  /32  =  0,         72  =  0,        S2  =  0,  &c. 

a/3  =    —  /3a,       ay  =    —  y  a,      /3  y  =    —  y /3, 
87=  —  7  S,  &c. 

A  series  of  quantities  for  which  these  relations  hold 
was  first  made  use  of  by  Grassmann,  and  termed  by 
him.  alternate  units. 

The  reader  will  at  once  observe  that  alternate  units 
have  an  algebra  of  their  own.  They  dispense  with 
the  commutative  law,  or  rather  replace  it  by  another 
in  which  the  sign  of  a  product  is  made  to  alternate  with 
the  alternation  of  its  components.  Their  consideration 
will  suggest  to  the  reader  tluit  the  rules  of  arithmetic, 


202      THE    COMMON   SEXSE    OF   THE   EXACT    SCIENCES. 

which  he  is  perhaps  accustomed  to  assume  as  neces 
sarily  true  for  all  forms  of  symbolic  quantity,  have  only 
the  comparatively  small  field  of  application  to  scalar 
magnitudes.  It  becomes  necessary  to  consider  them  as 
mere  conventions,  or  even  to  lay  them  aside  entirely  as 
we  proceed  step  by  step  to  enlarge  the  meaning  of  the 
symbols  we  are  employing. 

Although  2  x  2  =  0  and  2x3=  —3x2  may  be  sheer 
nonsense  when  2  and  3  are  treated  as  mere  numbers,  it 
yet  becomes  downright  common  sense  when  2  and  3  are 
treated  as  directed  steps  in  a  plane. 

Let  us  take  two  alternate  units  a,  /3  and  interpret 
the  quantity  a  a  +  6  /3,  where  a  and  6  are  merely  scalar 


r' 


FIG.  83. 

magnitudes.  If  OA  be  the  vector  a,  a  a  signifies  that 
we  are  to  stretch  o  A  to  o  A'  in  the  ratio  of  1  to  a.  To 
this  o  A'  we  are  to  add  the  vector  o  R'  derived  from  o  B 
by  giving  it  the  stretch  &.  Hence  if  A'  p  =  o  R'  the1 
vector  o  P  represents  the  quantity  a  a  +  6/3,  which  is 
termed  an  alternate  number.  Let  o  Q  represent  a  second 
alternate  number  a'  a  +  b'  @,  obtained  by  adding  the 
results  of  applying  two  other  stretches  a'  and  &'  to  the 


POSITION.  203 

alternate  units  a  and  ft.  In  the  same  way  we  might 
obtain,  by  adding  the  results  of  stretching  three  alternate 
units  (a,  ft,y),  alternate  numbers  with  three  terms  (of  the 
form  a  a  +  b  ft  +  07),  and  so  on.  If  we  take  the^ro- 
duct  of  as  many  alternate  numbers  as  we  have  used 
alternate  units  in  their  composition,  we  obtain  a 
quantity  called  a  determinant,  which  plays  a  great  part 
in  the  modern  theory  of  quantity.  We  shall  confine 
ourselves  hei'e  to  the  consideration  of  a  determinant 
formed  from  two  alternate  units.  Such  a  determinant 
will  be  represented  by  the  product  o  P  .  o  Q,  which 
according  to  our  convention  as  to  the  multiplication  of 
vectors  equals  the  area  of  the  parallelogram  on  o  P, 
OQ  as  sides,  or  (by  p.  122)  twice  the  triangle  Q  o  p. 
Through  Q  draw  c  Q  A"  parallel  to  OB,  and  D  Q  B" 
parallel  to  o  A,  then  o  A"  =  a'  a  and  o  B"  =  b'  ft.  Join 
B'Q,  then  twice  the  triangle  B'Q  i>  equals  the  parallelo 
gram  B"  p.  Hence,  adding  to  both  these  the  parallelo 
gram  A'  B"  we  have  the  parallelogram  A'  B"  together 
with  twice  the  triangle  B'Q  p  equal  to  the  parallelogram 
B'A',  or  to  twice  the  triangle  B'O  p.  Hut  the  triangle 
B'O  P  equals  the  sum  of  the  triangles  <>Q  B',  B'Q  P,  and 
OPQ.  It  follows  then  that  the  parallelogram  A' B" 
must  equal  twice  the  triangle  OPQ  together  with  twice 
the  triangle  OQ  B'.  Now  twice  the  latter  equals  B'  A". 
Hence  the  difference  of  the  parallelograms  A'  B"  and 
B'A"  is  equal  to  twice  OPQ.  The  parallelogram  A' B" 
is  obtained  from  the  parallelogram  A  B  by  giving  it  two 
j|  stretches  a  and  b'  parallel  to  its  sides,  and  therefore  its 
area  equals  a  b'  times  the  area  A  B.  Similarly  B'A" 
equals  b  a'  times  the  area  A  B  ;  but  the  area  A  B  itself  is 
aft.  Thus  we  see  that  the  identity 

0  P  .  o'  Q  =  A'  B"  —  B'  A" 


204      THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

may  be  read 

(a a  +  1/3)  (of  a  +  &'/3)  =  (aV  -la'}  a/3. 

Or,  the  determinant  is  equal  to  the  parallelogram  on 
the  alternate  units  magnified  in  the  ratio  of  1  to 
a  6'  —  &  a'.  It  obviously  vanishes  if  a  V  —  &  of  =  0,  or  if 
a/6  =  of  /&'.  In  this  case  p  and  Q  lie,  by  the  property  of 
similar  triangles,  on  the  same  straight  line  through  o, 
and  therefore,  as  we  should  expect,  the  determinant 
o  P  .  o  Q  is  zero. 

The  reader  will  find  little  difficulty  in  discovering 
like  properties  for  a  determinant  formed  from  three 
alternate  units.  In  this  case  there  will  be  a  geometrical 
relation  between  certain  volumes,  which  may  be  ob 
tained  by  stretches  in  the  manner  explained  on  p.  139.1 

We  have  in  this  section  arrived  at  a  legitimate  I 
interpretation  of  the  product  of  two  directed  steps  or 
vectors.  We  find  that  their  product  is  an  area,  or  ac 
cording  to  our  previous  convention  (see  p.  134),  also  a 
directed  step  or  vector  whose  direction  is  perpendicular] 
to  the  plane  which  contains  both  steps  of  the  product. 


§  16.  Another  Interpretation  of  tlie  Product  of  Two 

Vectors. 

The  reader  must  remember,  however,  that  the  resulli 
of  the  preceding  paragraph  has  only  been  obtained 
means  of  a  convention ;  namely,  by  adopting  the  area  of 
certain  parallelogram  as  the  interpretation  of  the  vecto^ 

1  I  have  to  thank  my  friend  Mr.  J.  Eose-Innes  for  suggesting  the  int 
duction  of  the  above  remarks   as   to  determinants.     I  may,  perhaps, 
allowed  to  add  that  by  treating  the  alternate  units,   like  Grassmann,  aj 
points,  and  the  alternate  number  as  their  loaded  centroid,  a  determinarij 
of  the  second  order  is  represented  geometrically  by  a  length,  and  we  thv 
obtain  for  one  of  the  fourth  order  a  geometrical  interpretation  as  a  volumn 


POSITION. 


205 


product.  Only  as  long  as  we  observe  that  convention 
will  our  deductions  with  regard  to  the  multiplication  of 
vectors  be  true.  We  might  have  adopted  a  different 
convention,  and  should  then  have  come  to  a  different 
result.  It  will  be  instructive  to  follow  out  the  results 
of  adopting  another  convention,  if  only  by  so  doing  we 
can  impress  the  reader  with  the  fact  that  the  funda 
mental  axioms  of  any  branch  of  exact  science  are  based 
rather  upon  conventions  than  upon  universal  truths. 

Suppose   then    that    in    interpreting    the    product 
A  P .  A  Q  we  consider  A  p  to  be  a  directed  step  which 


FIG.  84. 

represents  the  area  D  E  F  G.  This  area  will  be  perpen 
dicular  to  the  direction  of  A  P,  and  we  might  assume  as 
our  convention  that  the  product  A  P  .  A  Q  shall  mean  the 
volume  traced  out  by  the  step  A  Q,  moving  parallel  to 
itself  and  in  such  wise  that  its  end  A  takes  up  every 
possible  position  in  the  plane  D  E  p  G.  This  volume  will 
be  the  portion  of  an  oblique  cylinder  on  the  base  D  E  F  G 
intercepted  by  a  plane  parallel  to  that  base  through  Q. 
We  have  seen  (p.  141)  that  the  volume  of  this  cylinder 
is  the  product  of  its  base  into  its  height,  viz.  the  per 
pendicular  distance  A  H  between  the  two  planes.  Now 
let  r  and  p  be  the  scalar  magnitudes  of  AP  and  AQ 


206       THE    COMMON   SENSE    OP   THE    EXACT    SCIENCES. 

respectively,  and  0  =  the  angle  PAQ.  Then  AH  = 
p  cos#,  and  the  volume  =  AP.AQ  =  r  p  cos$,  for  r  re 
presents  the  number  of  units  of  area  in  D  E  F  G.  Hence, 
since  a  volume  is  a  purely  numerical  quantity  having 
only  magnitude  and  no  direction,  we  find  that  with  this 
new  convention  the  product  of  two  vectors  is  a  purely 
scalar  quantity,  or  our  new  convention  leads  to  a  totally 
different  result  from  the  old. 

Further,  since  r  and  p  are  merely  numbers,  r  p  =  p  r, 
and  thus  A  p  .  A  Q  =  r  p  cos#  =  p  r  cos0  =  A  Q  .  A  p,  if 
A  Q  be  treated  as  the  directed  step  which  represents 
an  area  containing  p  units  of  area.  Thus  in  this  case 
the  vector  product  obeys  the  commutative  law,  which 
again  differs  from  our  previous  result.  We  can  then 
treat  the  product  of  two  vectors  either  as  a  vector  and 
\  as  a  quantity  not  obeying  the  commutative  law,  or  as  a 
scalar  and  as  a  quantity  obeying  the  commutative  law. 
We  are  at  liberty  to  adopt  either  convention,  provided 
we  maintain  it  consistently  in  our  resulting  investiga 
tions. 

The  method  of  varying  our  interpretation,  which  has 
been  exemplified  in  the  case  of  the  product  of  two 
vectors,  is  peculiarly  fruitful  in  the  field  of  the  exact 
sciences.  Each  new  interpretation  may  lead  us  to  vary 
our  fundamental  laws,  and  upon  those  varied  funda 
mental  laws  we  can  build  up  a  new  calculus  (algebraic 
or  geometric  as  the  case  may  be).  The  results  of  our 
new  calculus  will  then  be  necessarily  true  for  those 
quantities  only  for  which  we  formulated  our  funda 
mental  laws.  Thus  those  laws  which  were  formulated 
for  pure  number,  and  which,  like  the  postulates  of 
Euclid  with  regard  to  space,  have  been  frequently 
supposed  to  be  the  only  conceivable  basis  for  a  theory! 
of  quantity,  are  found  to  be  true  only  within  the  limits 


POSITION.  207 

of  scalar  magnitude.  When  we  extend  our  conception 
of  quantity  and  endow  it  with  direction  and  position, 
we  find  those  laws  are  no  longer  valid.  "We  are  com 
pelled  to  suppose  that  one  or  more  of  those  laws  cease 
to  hold  or  are  replaced  by  others  of  a  different  form. 
In  each  case  we  vary  the  old  form  or  adopt  a  new  one 
to  suit  the  wider  interpretation  we  are  giving  to  quan 
tity  or  its  symbols. 

§  17.  Position  in  Three-Dimensioned  Space. 

Hitherto  we  have  been  considering  only  position  in 
a  plane  ;  very  little  alteration  will  enable  us  to  consider 
the  position  of  a  point  p  relative  to  a  point  A  as  deter 
mined  by  a  step  A  p  taken  in  space. 

We  may  first  remark,  however,  that  while  two  points 
A  and  B  are  sufficient  to  determine  in  a  plane  the  position 
of  any  third  point  P,  we  shall  require,  in  order  to  fix  the 
position  of  a  point  p  in  space,  to  be  given  three  points 
A,  B,  c  not  lying  in  one  straight  line.  If  we  knew  only 
the  distances  of  P  from  two  points  A  and  B,  the  point 
p  might  be  anywhere  on  a  certain  circle  which  has  its 
centre  on  the  line  AB  and  its  plane  perpendicular  to 
that  line ;  to  determine  the  position  of  p  on  this  circle, 
we  require  to  know  its  distance  from  a  third  point  c. 
Thus  position  in  space  requires  us  to  have  at  least 
three  non-collinear  points  (or  such  geometrical  figures 
as  are  their  equivalent)  as  basis  for  our  determination 
of  position.  Space  in  which  we  live  is  termed  space  of 
three  dimensions ;  it  differs  from  space  of  two  dimen 
sions  in  requiring  us  to  have  three  and  not  two  points 
as  a  basis  for  determining  position. 

Three  points  will  fix  a  plane,  and  hence  if  we  are 
given  three  points  A,  B,  c  in  space,  the  plane  through 


THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

them  will  be  a  definite  plane  separating  all  space  into 
two  halves.  In  one  of  these  any  point  p  whose  position 
we  require  must  lie.  We  may  term  one  of  these  halves 
below  the  plane  and  the  other  above  the  plane.  Let  P  N 
be  the  perpendicular  from  p  upon  the  plane ;  then  if 
we  know  how  to  find  the  point  N  in  the  plane  ABC,  the 
position  of  p  will  be  fully  determined  so  soon  as  we 
have  settled  whether  the  distance  p  N  is  to  be  measured 
above  or  below  the  plane.  We  may  settle  by  convention 
that  all  distances  above  the  plane  shall  be  considered 
positive,  and  all  below  negative.  Further,  the  position 
of  the  point  N,  upon  which  that  of  P  depends,  may  be 


FIG.  85. 

determined  by  any  of  the  methods  we  have  employed 
to  fix  position  in  a  plane.  Thus  if  N  M  be  drawn 
perpendicular  to  A  B,  we  have  the  following  instruction 
to  find  the  position  of  P :  Take  a  step  A  M  along  A  B, 
containing,  say,  x  units ;  then  take  a  step  M  N  to  the  right 
and  perpendicular  to  A  B,  but  still  in  its  plane,  contain 
ing,  say,  y  units ;  finally  step  upwards  from  N  the  distance 
N  P  perpendicular  to  the  plane  ABC,  say,  through  z  units. 
We  shall  then  have  reached  the  same  point  P  as  if  we 
had  taken  the  directed  step  A  p.  If  a;  had  been  negative 
we  should  have  had  to  step  backwards  from  A  ;  if  y  had 
been  negative,  perpendicular  to  A  B  only  to  the  left ;  if 
z  had  been  negative,  perpendicular  to  the  plane  but 


POSITIOX. 


209 


downwards.  The  reader  will  easily  convince  himself 
that  by  observing  these  rules  as  to  the  sign  of  x,  y,  z 
he  could  get  from  A  to  any  point  in  space. 

Let  i  denote  unit  step  along  A  B,  j  unit  step  to  the 
right  perpendicular  to  A  B,  but  in  the  plane  ABC,  and 
k  unit  step  perpendicular  to  the  plane  ABC  upwards, 
from  foot  to  head.  Then  we  may  write 

A  p  =  x  .  i  +  y  .j  +  s  .  k, 

where  x,  y,  z  are  scalar  quantities  possessing  only 
magnitude  and  sign ;  but  i,  j,  k  are  vector  steps  in 
three  mutually  rectangular  directions. 


FIG.  86. 

The  step  A  p  may  be  regarded  as  the  diagonal  of  a 
solid  rectangular  figure  (a  riyht  six-face,  as  we  termed 
it  on  p.  J38),  and  thus  we  shall  get  to  the  same  point 
P  by  traversing  any  three  of  its  non-parallel  sides  in 
succession  starting  from  A.  But  this  is  equivalent  to 
saying  that  the  order  in  which  we  take  the  directed 
Isteps  x  .i,  y  .j,  and  z  .k  is  indifferent. 

The  reader  will  readily  recognise  that  the  sum  of  a 
number  of  successive  steps  in  space  is  the  equivalent 
ito  the  step  which  joins  the  start  of  the  first  to  the 


210      THE    COMMON    SENSE    OF    THE    EXACT    SCIENCES. 

finish  of  the  last ;  and  thus  a  number  of  propositions 
concerning  steps  in  space  similar  to  those  we  have 
proved  for  steps  in  a  plane  may  be  deduced.  By 
dividing  all  space  into  little  cubes  by  three  systems  of 
planes  mutually  at  right  angles,  we  may  plot  out  sur 
faces  just  as  we  plotted  out  curves.  Thus  we  shall  choose 
any  values  we  please  for  x  and  y,  and  suppose  the 
magnitude  of  the  third  step  related  in  some  constant 
fashion  to  the  previous  steps.  For  example,  if  we  take 
the  rectangle  under  z  and  some  constant  length  a, 
always  equal  to  the  differences  of  the  squares  on  x  and 
y,  or  symbolically  if  we  take  a  2  =  x^  —  y-,  we  shall 
reach  P  by  taking  the  step 

.   .   a;2  — 7/2    7 

AP  =  x.i  +  y  .y  + .  K- 

a 

The  series  of  points  which  we  should  obtain  in  this 
way  would  be  found  to  lie  upon  a  surface  resembling 
the  saddle-back  we  have  described  on  p.  89.  The 
above  relation  between  z,  x,  and  y  will  then  be  termed 
the  equation  to  a  saddle-back  surface. 

We  cannot,  however,  enter  fully  on  the  theory  of 
steps  in  space  without  far  exceeding  the  limits  of  our 
present  enterprise. 

§  18.  On  Localised  Vectors  or  Rotors. 

Hitherto  we  have  considered  the  position  of  a  point 
p  relative  to  a  point  A,  and  compared  it  with  the 
position  of  another  point  Q  relative  to  the  same  point 
A.  Thus  we  have  considered  the  ratio  and  product  of 
two  steps  A  P  and  A  Q. 

We  have  thereby  assumed  either  that  the  two  steps 
we  were  considering  had  a  common  extremity  A,  or  at 
least  were  capable  of  being  moved  parallel  to  themselves 


POSITION.  211 

till  they  had  such  a  common  extremity.  Such  steps  are, 
as  we  have  remarked,  termed  vector  steps. 

Suppose,  however,  that  instead  of  comparing  the 
position  of  two  points  p  and  Q  relative  to  the  same 
point  A,  we  compared  their  positions  relative  to  two 
different  points  A  and  B.  The  position  of  p  relative  to 
A  will  then  be  determined  by  the  step  A  p  and  the 
position  of  Q  relative  to  B  by  the  step  B  Q. 

Now  it  will  be  noted  that  these  steps  A  p  and  B  Q  have 
not  only  direction  and  magnitude,  bat  have  themselves 
position  in  space.  The  step  A  P  has  itself  position  in 
space  relative  to  the  step  B  Q.  It  is  no  longer  a  step 


FIG.  87. 

merely  indicating  the  position  of  p  with  regard  to  A, 
but  taken  as  a  whole  it  has  itself  attained  position 
when  considered  with  regard  to  the  step  B  Q.  This 
localising,  not  of  a  point  P  relative  to  a  point  A,  but 
of  a  step  A  P  with  regard  to  another  step  B  Q,  is  a  new 
-and  important  conception.  Such  a  localised  vector  is 
termed  a  rotor  from  the  part  it  plays  in  the  theory  of 
rotating  or  spinning  bodies. 

Let  us  try  and  discover  what  operation  will  convert 
[the  rotor  B  Q  into  the  rotor  A  P  ;  in  other  words :  What 

is  the  operation  r    — •'  ?     In  order  to  convert  B  Q  into 
I  BQ 

p  2 


212       THE    COMMON    SENSE    OP   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

A  p  we  must  make  the  magnitude  and  position  of  B  Q 
the  same  as  that  of  A  p.  Its  magnitude  may  be  made 
the  same  by  means  of  a  stretching  operation  which 
stretches  B  Q  to  A  p.  This  stretch,  as  we  have  seen  in  the 
case  of  a  quaternion  (see  p.  195),  may  be  represented 
by  a  numerical  ratio  or  a  mere  scalar  quantity.  Next 
let  c  D  be  the  shortest  distance  between  the  rotors  A  p 


/ 

/ 

/ 

I 

3 

_s. 

^r 

x>^.      ** 

Q 

FIG.  88. 

and  B  Q;  then  c  D  will  be  perpendicular  to  both  of  them.1 
B  Q  may  then  be  made  to  coincide  in  position  with  A  p 
by  the  following  process  : 

First  turn  B  Q  about  the  shortest  distance,  c  D, 
through  some  angle,  Q  D  Q',  till  it  takes  up  the  posi 
tion  B'Q'  parallel  to  A  P  ;  then  slide  B'Q'  along  the 

1  That  the  shortest  distance  between  two  lines  is  perpendicular  to  both 
of  them  may  be  proved  in  the  following  manner.  Let  us  suppose  the  lines 
replaced  by  perfectly  smooth  and  very  thin  rods,  and  let  two  rings,  one  on 
either  rod,  be  connected  by  a  stretched  elastic  string.  Obviously  the  rings 
will  slide  along  the  rods  till  the  elastic  string  takes  up  the  position  of  the 
shortest  distance;  for  that  will  correspond  to  the  least  possible  tension  of 
the  string.  Suppose  that  the  string  is  then  not  at  right  angles  to  one  of 
the  rods,  say,  at  the  point  c.  By  holding  the  string  firmly  at  E,  we  might 
shift  the  ring  at  c  along  the  rod  to  c',  so  that  the  angle  E  c'c  should  be  a 
right  angle.  Then  since  c'  is  a  right  angle  c  E  would  be  greater  than  C'E, 
being  the  side  opposite  the  greatest  angle  of  the  triangle  EC'  c.  Hence  the 
length  of  string  C'E  +  ED  is  less  than  the  length  CD,  or  CD  cannot  be  the 
shortest  distance  which  we  have  supposed  it  to  be.  Thus  the  shortest 
distance  must  be  at  right  angles  to  both  lines. 


POSITION.  213 

shortest  distance  parallel  to  itself  till  its  position  coin 
cides  with  A  P.  If  we  wished  B'Q'  to  coincide  point  for 
point  with  A  p',  we  should  further  have  to  slide  it  along 
A  P  till  B'  and  A  were  one. 

Now  the  two  operations  of  turning  a  line  about 
another  line  at  right  angles  to  it,  and  moving  it  along 
that  line,  are  just  akin  to  the  operations  which  are 
applied  to  the  groove  in  the  head  of  a  screw  when  we 
drive  the  screw  into  a  block  of  wood ;  or  again  to  the 
handle  of  a  corkscreAv  when  we  twist  the  screw  into  a 
cork.  The  handle  in  the  one  case  and  the  groove  in  the 
other  not  only  spin  round,  but  go  forward  in  the  direc 
tion  of  the  screw  axis.  Such  a  movement  along  an 
axis,  and  at  the  same  time  about  it,  is  termed  a  tivist.  The 
ratio  of  the  forward  space  described  to  the  angle  turned 
through  during  its  description  by  the  head  of  the  screw 
is  termed  the  pitch  of  the  screw.  This  pitch  will 
remain  constant  for  all  forward  spaces  described  if  the 
thread  of  the  screw  be  uniform.  Thus  turn  an  ordinary 
corkscrew  twice  round,  and  it  will  have  advanced  twice 
as  far  through  the  cork  as  when  it  has  been  turned 
only  once  round.  Let  us  see  whether  we  cannot  apply 
this  conception  of  a  screw  to  the  operations  by  which  we 
bring  the  rotor  B  Q  into  the  position  of  the  rotor  A  p. 
Upon  a  rod  placed  at  c  D,  the  shortest  distance,  suppose  a 
fiae  screw  cut  with  such  a  thread  that  its  pitch  equals 
the  ratio  of  c  D  to  the  angle  Q  D  Q'.  Then  if  we  suppose 
B  Q  attached  to  a  nut  upon  this  screw  at  D,  when  we 
turn  B  Q  through  the  angle  Q  D  Q',  the  nut  with  B  Q  will 
advance  (owing  to  the  pitch  we  have  chosen  for  the 
screw)  through  the  distance  DC.  In  other  words,  B  Q 
will  have  been  brought  up  to  A  P  and  coincide  with  it 
in  position  and  direction. 

Hence  the  operations  by  means  of  which  B  Q  can  be 


214      THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

made  to  coincide  with  A  p  are  a  stretch  followed  by  a 
twist  along  a  certain  screw.  A  screw  involves  direc 
tion,  position,  and  pitch ;  a  twist  (as  of  a  nut)  about 
this  axis  involves  something  additional,  namely  a 
magnitude,  viz.  that  of  the  angle  through  which  the 
nut  is  to  be  turned.  Magnitude  associated  with  a 
screw  has  been  termed  by  the  author  of  the  present 
book  a  motor1  (since  it  expresses  the  most  general 
instantaneous  motion  of  a  rigid  body).  Hence  the 
operation  by  which  one  rotor  is  converted  into  another 
may  be  described  as  a  motor  combined  with  a  stretch. 
This  operation  stands  in  the  same  relation  to  two  rotors 
as  the  quaternion  to  two  vectors.  The  motor  plays 
such  an  important  part  in  several  branches  of  physical 
inquiry  that  the  reader  will  do  well  to  familiarise  him 
self  with  the  conception. 

The  sum  of  two  vector  steps  is,  as  we  have  seen 
(p.  153),  a  third  vector  ;  but  unlike  vector  steps  the  sum 
of  two  rotors  is  in  general  a  motor ;  only  in  special 
cases  does  it  become  either  a  rotor  or  a  vector.  The 
geometry  of  rotors  and  motors,  which  we  have  only 
here  been  able  to  hint  at.  forms  the  basis  of  the  whole 
modern  theory  of  the  relative  rest  (Static)  and  the  rela 
tive  motion  (Kinematic  and  Kinetic)  of  invariable 
systems. 

§  19.  On  the  Bending  of  Space. 

The  peculiar  topic  of  this  chapter  has  been  position, 
position  namely  of  a  point  p  relative  to  a  point  A. 
This  relative  position  led  naturally  to  a  consideration  of 
the  geometry  of  steps.  I  proceeded  on  the  hypothesis 

1  '  Preliminary  Sketch    of  Biquaternions,'  Proceedings  of  the  London 
Mathematical  Society,  vol.  iv.  p.  383. 


POSITIOX.  215 

that  all  position  is  relative,  and  therefore  to  be  deter 
mined  only  by  a  stepping  process.  The  relativity  of 
position  was  a  postulate  deduced  from  the  customary 
methods  of  determining  position,  such  methods  in  fact 
always  giving  relative  position.  Relativity  of  position 
is  thus  a  postulate  derived  from  experience.  The  late 
Professor  Clerk-Maxwell  fully  expressed  the  weight  of 
this  postulate  in  the  following  words  :  — 

All  our  knowledge,  both  of  time  and  place,  is  relative. 
"\Yhen  a  man  has  acquired  the  habit  of  putting  words  together. 
without  troubling  himself  to  form  the  thoughts  which  ought  to 
correspond  to  them,  it  is  easy  for  him  to  frame  an  antithesis 
between  this  relative  knowledge  and  a  so-called  absolute  know 
ledge,  and  to  point  out  our  ignorance  of  the  absolute  position  of 
a  point  as  an  instance  of  the  limitation  of  our  faculties.  Any 
one,  however,  who  will  try  to  imagine  the  state  of  a  mind  con 
scious  of  knowing  the  absolute  position  of  a  point  will  ever  after 
be  content  with  our  relative  knowledge.1 

It  is  of  such  great  value  to  ascertain  how  far  we  can 
be  certain  of  the  truth  of  our  postulates  in  the  exact 
sciences  that  I  shall  ask  the  reader  to  return  to  our 
conception  of  position  albeit  from  a  somewhat  different 
standpoint.  I  shall  even  ask  him  to  attempt  an  exami 
nation  of  that  state  of  mind  which  Professor  Clerk- 
Maxwell  hinted  at  in  his  last  sentence. 

Suppose  we  had  a  tube  of  exceedingly  sr  all  bore 
bent  into  a  circular  shape,  and  within  this  tube  a  worm 
of  length  A  B.  Then  in  the  limiting  case  when  we 
make  the  bore  of  the  tube  and  the  worm  infinitely  fine, 
we  shall  be  considering  space  of  one  dimension.  For 
so  soon  as  we  have  fixed  one  point,  c,  011  the  tube,  the 
length  of  arc  c  A  suffices  to  determine  the  position  of 
the  worm.  Assuming  that  the  worm  is  incapable  of 

1  Matter  and  Motion,  p.  20. 


216       THE    COMMON    SENSE    OF    THE    EXACT    SCIENCES. 

recognising  anything  outside  its  own  tube-space,  it 
would  still  be  able  to  draw  certain  inferences  as  to  the 
nature  of  the  space  in  which  it  existed  were  it  capable 
of  distinguishing  some  mark  c  on  the  side  of  its  tube. 
Thus  it  would  notice  when  it  returned  to  the  point  c, 
and  it  would  find  that  this  return  would  continually 
recur  as  it  went  round  in  the  bore  ;  in  other  words,  the 
worm  would  readily  postulate  the  finiteness  of  space. 
Further,  since  the  worm  would  always  have  the  same 
amount  of  bending,  since  all  parts  of  a  circle  are  of  the 
same  shape,  it  might  naturally  assume  the  sameness  of 


all  space,  or  that  space  possessed  the  same  properties  at 
all  points.  This  assumption  is  precisely  akin  to  the  one 
we  make  when  we  assert  that  the  postulates  of  Euclidian 
geometry,  which,  experience  teaches  us,  are  practically 
true  for  the  space  immediately  about  us,  are  also  true 
for  all  space ;  we  assume  the  sameness  of  our  three- 
dimensioned  space.  The  worm  would,  however,  have 
better  reason  for  its  postulate  than  we  have,  because  it 
would  have  visited  .every  part  of  its  own  one-dimen 
sioned  space. 

Besides  the  finiteness  and  sameness  of  its  space  the 
worm  might  assert  the  relativity  of  position,  and  deter- 


POSITION.  217 

mine  its  position  by  the  length  of  the  arc  between  c 
and  A.  Let  us  now  make  a  variation  in  our  problem 
and  suppose  the  worm  incapable  either  of  making  or 
of  recognising  any  mark  on  the  tube.  Then  it  would 
clearly  be  impossible  for  the  worm  to  ascertain  whether 
its  space  were  limited  or  not ;  it  would  never  know 
when  it  had  made  a  complete  revolution  in  its  tube.  In 
fact,  since  the  worm  would  always  possess  the  same 
amount  of  bending,  it  would  naturally  associate  tl«it 
bending  with  its  plnjsical  constitution ,  and  not  with  tlie 
space  which  it  was  traversing.  It  might  thus  very 
reasonably  suppose  its  space  was  infinite,  or  that  it  was 
moving  in  an  infinitely  long  tube.  If  the  worm  thus 
associated  bending  with  its  physical  condition  it  would 
find  no  difference  between  motion  in  space  of  constant 
bend  (a  circle)  and  motion  in  what  is  termed  homaloulal 
or  flat  space  (a  straight  line)  ;  if  suddenly  transferred 
from  one  to  the  other  it  would  attribute  the  feeling 
arising  from  difference  of  bending  to  some  change 
which  had  taken  place  in  its  physical  constitution. 
Hence  in  one-dimensioned  space  of  constant  bend  all 
position  is  necessarily  relative,  and  the  finite  or  in 
finite  character  of  space  will  be  postulated  according  as 
it  is  possible  or  not  to  fix  a  point  in  it.1 

Let  us  now  suppose  our  worm  moving  in  a  different 
sort  of  tube  ;  for  example,  that  shadow  of  a  circle  \\  e 
have  called  an  ellipse.  In  such  a  tube  the  degree  of 
bending  is  not  everywhere  the  same ;  the  worm  as  it 
passes  from  the  place  of  least  bending  c  to  the  place  of 
most  bending  D,  will  pass  through  a  succession  of  bend- 
ings,  and  each  point  H  between  c  and  D  will  have  its 

1  This  supposes  the  one-dimensioned  space  of  constant  bend  to  lie  in  a 
plane;  the  argument  does  not  apply  to  space  like  tli.it  of  a  helix  (or  the 
form  of  a,  corkscrew),  which  is  of  constant  bend,  bat  yet  not  finite. 


218      THE    COMMON    SENSE    OF    THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

own  degree  of  bending.  Hence  there  is  something 
quite  apart  from  the  position  of  H  relative  to  c  which 
characterises  the  point  H  ;  namely,  associated  with  H  is 
a  particular  degree  of  bending,  and  the  position  of  the 
point  H  in  c  D  is  at  once  fixed  if  we  know  the  degree  of 
bending  there.  Thus  the  worm  might  determine  abso 
lute  position  in  its  space  by  the  degree  of  bending  asso 
ciated  with  its  position.  The  worm  is  now  able  to 
appreciate  differences  of  bend,  and  might  even  form  a 
scale  of  bending  rising  by  equal  differences.  The  zero 
of  such  scale  might  be  anywhere  the  worm  pleased,  and 


degrees  of  greater  and  less  bend  might  be  measured  as 
positive  and  negative  quantities  from  that  zero.  This 
zero  might  in  fact  be  purely  imaginary ;  that  is,  represent 
a,  degree  of  bending  non-existent  in  the  worm's  space ; 
for  example,  in  the  case  of  an  ellipse,  absolute  straight- 
ness,  a  conception  which  the  worm  might  form  as  a 
limit  to  its  experience  of  degrees  of  bend.1  Thus  it 
would  seem  that  in  space  of  '  varying  bend,'  or  space 
which  is  not  same,  position  is  not  necessarily  relative. 
The  relativity  has  ceased  to  belong  to  position  in  space ; 
it  has  been  transferred  to  the  scale  of  bending  formed 

1  Physicists  may  be  reminded  of  the  absolute  zero  of  temperature. 


POSITION.  21 9 

by  the  worm  ;  it  has  become  a  relativity  of  physical  feel 
ing.  In  the  case  of  an  elliptic  tube  there  are  owing  to 
its  symmetry  four  points  of  equal  bend,  as  H,  E,  F,  and 
G,  but  there  is  the  following  distinction  between  H,  p 
and  E,  G.  If  the  worm  be  going  round  in  the  direction 
indicated  by  the  letters  c  H  D  E,  at  H  or  F  it  will  be  pass 
ing  from  positions  of  less  to  positions  of  greater  bending, 
but  at  E  or  G  from  positions  of  greater  to  positions 
of  less  bending.  Thus  the  worm  might  easily  draw  a 
distinction  between  H,  F  and  E,  G.  It  would  only  be 
liable  to  suppose  the  points  H  and  F  identical  because 


FIG.  01. 

they  possess  the  same  degree  of  bending.  We  mi<_rht 
remove  even  this  possible  doubt  by  supposing  the  worm 
to  be  moving  in  a  pear-shaped  tube,  as  in  the  accom 
panying  figure ;  then  there  will  only  be  two  points  of 
equal  bend,  like  H  and  G,  which  are  readily  distinguished 
in  the  manne'r  mentioned  above. 

We  might  thus  conclude  that  in  one-dimensioned 
space  of  variable  bend  position  is  not  necessarily  • 
relative.  There  is,  however,  one  point  to  be  noted  with 
regard  to  this  statement.  We  have  assumed  that  the 
worm  will  associate  change  of  bending  with  change  of 
position  in  its  space,  but  the  worm  would  be  sensible  of 


220      THE    COMMON    SENSE    OF    THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

it  as  a  change  of  physical  state  or  as  a  change  of  feeling. 
Hence  the  worm  might  very  readily  be  led  into  the 
error  of  postulating  the  sameness  of  its  space,  and 
attributing  all  the  changes  in  its  bend,  really  due  to  its 
position  in  space,  to  some  periodic  (if  it  moves  uniformly 
round  its  tube)  or  irregular  (if  it  moves  in  any  fashion 
backwards  and  forwards)  changes  to  which  its  physical 
constitution  was  subject.  Similar  results  might  also 
arise  if  the  worm  were  either  moving  in  space  of  the 
same  bend,  which  bend  could  be  changed  by  some  ex 
ternal  agency  as  a  whole,  or  if  again  its  space  were  of 
varying  bend,  which  was  also  capable  of  changing  in 
any  fashion  with  time.  The  reader  can  picture  these 
cases  by  supposing  the  tube  made  of  flexible  material. 
The  worm  might  either  attribute  change  in  its  degree 
of  bend  to  change  in  the  character  of  its  space  or  to 
change  in  its  physical  condition  not  arising  from  its 
position  in  space.  We  conclude  that  the  postulate  of 
the  relativity  of  position  is  not  necessarily  true  for  one- 
dimensioned  space  of  varying  bend. 

When  we  proceed  from  one  to  two-dimensioned 
space,  we  obtain  results  of  an  exactly  similar  character. 
If  we  take  perfectly  even  (so  called  homaloidal)  space  of 
two  dimensions,  that  is,  a  plane,  then  a  perfectly  flat 
figure  can  be  moved  about  anywhere  in  it  without 
altering  its  shape.  If  by  analogy  to  an  infinitely  thin 
worm  we  take  an  infinitely  thin  flat-fish,  this  fish 
would  be  incapable  of  determining  position  could  it 
leave  no  landmarks  in  its  plane  space.  So  soon  as  it 
had  fixed  two  points  in  its  plane  it  would  be  able  to 
determine  relative  position. 

Now,  suppose  that  instead  of  taking  this  homaloidal 
space  of  two  dimensions  we  were  still  to  take  a  perfectly 
same  space  but  one  of  finite  bend,  that  is,  the  surface 


POSITION.  221 

of  a  sphere.  Then  let  us  so  stretch  and  bend  onr  flat 
fish  that  it  would  fit  on  to  some  part  of  the  sphere. 
Since  the  surface  of  the  sphere  is  everywhere  space  of 
the  same  shape,  the  fish  would  then  be  capable  of 
moving  about  on  the  surface  without  in  any  way  alter 
ing  the  amount  of  bending  and  stretching  which  we 
had  found  it  necessary  to  apply  to  make  the  fish  fit  in 
any  one  position..  Wore  the  fish  incapable  of  leaving 
landmarks  on  the  surface  of  the  sphere,  it  would  be 
totally  unable  to  determine  position;  if  it  could  leave 
at  least  two  landmarks  it  would  be  able  to  determine 
relative  position.  Just  as  the  worm  in  the  circular  tube, 
the  fish  without  landmarks  might  reasonably  suppose 
its  space  infinite,  or  even  look  upon  it  as  perfectly  flat 
(homaloidal)  and  attribute  the  constant  degree  of  bend 
and  stretch  to  its  physical  nature. 

Let  us  now  pass  to  some  space  of  two  dimensions 
which  is  not  same — to  some  space,  for  example,  like  the 
saddle-back  surface  we  have  considered  on  page  89, 
which  has  a  varying  bend.  In  this  case  the  fish,  if  it 
fitted  at  one  part  of  the  surface,  would  not  necessarily 
fit  at  another.  If  it  moved  about  in  its  space,  it  would 
be  needful  that  a  continual  process  of  bending  and 
stretching  should  be  carried  on.  Thus  every  part  of 
this  two-dimensioned  space  would  be  defined  by  the 
particular  amount  of  bend  and  stretch  necessary  to 
make  the  fish  fit  it,  or,  as  it  is  usually  termed,  by  the 
curvature.  In  surfaces  with  some  degree  of  symmetry 
there  would  necessarily  be  parts  of  equal  curvature,  and 
.  some  cases  the  fish  might  perhaps  distinguish 
;tween  these  points  in  the  same  fashion  as  the  worm 
stinguished  between  points  of  equal  curvature  in  the 
ise  of  an  elliptic  tube.  In  irregular  surfaces,  however, 
is  not  necessary  that  such  points  of  equal  curvature 


222      THE   COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES 

should  arise.  We  are  thus  led  to  conclusions  like  those 
we  have  formed  for  one-dimensioned  space,  namely : 
Position  in  space  of  two  dimensions  which  is  not'  same 
might  be  determined  absolutely  by  means  of  the  curva 
ture.  Our  fish  has  only  to  carry  about  with  it  a  scale 
of  degrees  of  bending  and  stretching  corresponding  to 
various  positions  on  the  surface  in  order  to  determine 
absolutely  its  position  in  its  space.  On  the  other  hand, 
the  fish  might  very  readily  attribute  all  these  changes 
of  bend  and  stretch  to  variations  of  its  physical  nature 
in  nowise  dependent  on  its  position  in  space.  Thus  it 
might  believe  itself  to  have  a  most  varied  physical  life, 
a  continual  change  of  physical  feeling  quite  indepen 
dent  of  the  geometrical  character  of  the  space  in  which 
it  dwelt.  It  might  suppose  that  space  to  be  perfectly 
same,  or  even  degrade  it  to  the  *  dreary  infinity  of  a 
hornaloid.' l 

As  a  result,  then,  of  our  consideration  of  one  and  two- 
dimensioned  space  we  find  that,  if  these  spaces  be  not 
same  (a  fortiori  not  homaloidal),  we  should  by  reason 
of  their  curvature  have  a  means  of  determining  absolute 
position.  But  we  see  also  that  a  being  existing  in 
these  dimensions  would  most  probably  attribute  the 
effects  of  curvature  to  changes  in  its  own  physical 
condition  in  nowise  connected  with  the  geometrical 
character  of  its  space. 

What  lesson  may  we  learn  by  analogy  for  the  three- 
dimensioned  space  in  which  we  ourselves  exist?  To 
begin  with,  we  assume  that  all  our  space  is  perfectly 
same,  or  that  solid  figures  do  not  change  their  shape  in 
passing  from  one  position  in  it  to  another.  We  base  this 
postulate  of  sameness  upon  the  results  of  observation 

1  In  this  case  of  two-dimensioned  space  assume  it  to  be  a  plane.     Cf. 
Clifford's  Lectures  and  Essays,  vol.  i.  p.  323. 


POSITION.  223 

n  that  somewhat  limited  portion  of  space  of  which 
we  are  cognisant.1  Supposing  our  observations  to 
correct,  it  by  no  means  follows  that  because  the 
wrtion  of  space  of  which  we  are  cognisant  is  for 
practical  purposes  same,  that  therefore  all  space  is 
same.2  Such  an  assumption  is  a  mere  dogmatic  ex- 
;ension  to  the  unknown  of  a  postulate,  which  may 
)erhaps  be  true  for  the  space  upon  which  we  can  ex 
periment.  To  make  such  dogmatic  assertions  with 
regard  to  the  unknown  is  rather  characteristic  of  the 
mediaeval  theologian  than  of  the  modern  scientist.  On 
;he  like  basis  with  this  postulate  as  to  the  sameness 
of  our  space  stands  the  further  assumption  that  it  is 
tiomaloidal.  When  we  assert  that  our  space  is  every 
where  same,  we  suppose  it  of  constant  curvature  (like 
;he  circle  as  one  and  the  sphere  as  two-dimensioned 
space)  ;  when  we  suppose  it  homaloidal  we  assume  that 
:his  curvature  is  zero  (like  the  line  as  one  and  the 
plane  as  two-dimensioned  space).  This  assumption 
appears  in  our  geometry  under  the  form  that  two 
parallel  planes,  or  two  parallel  lines  in  the  same  plane  — 

1  It  may  he  held  by  some   that  the  postulate  of  the  sameness  of  our 
space  is  based  upon  the  fact  that  no  one  has  hitherto  been  ;ibl..  to  form  any 
geometrical  conception  of  space-curvature.     Apart  from  the  fact  that  man 
kind  habitually  assumes  many  things  of  which  it  can  form  no  guometrieal 
conception  (mathematicians    the    circular  points    at   infinity,   theologians 
lansubstantiation),  I   may  remark  that  we    cannot    expect  any  being  to 
Form  a  geometrical  conception  of  the  curvature  of  his  space  till  he  views  it 
From  space  of  a  higher  dimension,  that  is,  practically,  never. 

2  Yet  it  must  be  noted  that,  because  a  snliil  li-uiv  vjij'tar*  to  us  to  retain 
the  same  shape  when  it  is  moved  about  in   that    pun  inn  of  space  with 

'hich  we  are  acquainted,  it  does  not  follow  that  the  figure  really  does 
retain  its  shape.  The  changes  of  shape  may  be  either  imperceptible  for 
th>  -M-  distances  through  which  we  are  able  to  move  the  figure,  or  if  they  do 
take  place  we  may  attribute  them  to  '  physical  causes' — to  heat,  light, 
or  magnetism — which  may  possibly  be  nitre  names  for  variations  in  the 
curvature  of  our  space. 


224       THE    COMMON   SEXSE    OF   THE    EXACT    SCIENCES. 

that  is,  planes,  or  lines  in  the  same  plane,  which  how 
ever  far  produced  will  never  meet — have  a  real  existence 
in  our  space.  This  real  existence,  of  which  it  is  clearly 
impossible  for  us  to  be  cognisant,  we  postulate  as  a 
result  built  upon  our  experience  of  what  happens  in 
a  limited  portion  of  space.  We  may  postulate  that 
the  portion  of  space  of  which  we  are  cognisant  is 
practically  homaloidal,  but  we  have  clearly  no  right 
to  dogmatically  extend  this  postulate  to  all  space.  A 
constant  curvature,  imperceptible  for  that  portion  oi 
space  upon  which  we  can  experiment,  or  even  a  cur 
vature  which  may  vary  in  an  almost  imperceptible 
manner  with  the  time,  would  seem  to  satisfy  all  that 
experience  has  taught  us  to  be  true  of  the  space  in 
which  we  dwell. 

But  we  may  press  our  analogy  a  step  further, 
and  ask,  since  our  hypothetical  worm  and  fish  might 
very  readily  attribute  the  effects  of  changes  in  the 
bending  of  their  spaces  to  changes  in  their  own  phy 
sical  condition,  whether  we  may  not  in  like  fashion  be 
treating  merely  as  physical  variations  effects  which  are 
really  due  to  changes  in  the  curvature  of  our  space ; 
whether,  in  fact,  some  or  all  of  those  causes  which  we 
term  physical  may  not  be  due  to  the  geometrical  con 
struction  of  our  space.  There  are  three  kinds  of 
variation  in  the  curvature  of  our  space  which  we  ought 
to  consider  as  within  the  range  of  possibility. 

(i)  Our  space  is  perhaps  really  possessed  of  a  curva 
ture  varying  from  point  to  point,  which  we  fail  to  appre 
ciate  because  we  are  acquainted  with  only  a  small 
portion  of  space,  or  because  we  disguise  its  small  varia 
tions  under  changes  in  our  physical  condition  which  we 
do  not  connect  with  our  change  of  position.  The  mind 
that  could  recognise  this  varying  curvature  might  be 


POSITION.  225 

assumed  to  know  the  absolute  position  of  a  point.  For 
such  a  mind  the  postulate  of  the  relativity  of  position 
would  cease  to  have  a  meaning.  It  does  not  seem  so 
hard  to  conceive  srfch  a  state  of  mind  as  the  late 
Professor  Clerk-Maxwell  would  have  had  us  believe. 
It  would  be  one  capable  of  distinguishing  those  so- 
called  physical  changes  which  are  really  geometrical 
or  due  to  a  change  of  position  in  space. 

(ii)  Our  space  may  be  really  same  (of  equal  curva 
ture),  but  its  degree  of  curvature  may  change  as  a 
whole  with  the  time.  In  this  way  our  geometry  ba>>-<l 
011  the  sameness  of  space  would  still  hold  good  for  all 
parts  of  space,  but  the  change  of  curvature  might 
produce  in  space  a  succession  of  apparent  physical 
changes. 

(iii)  We  may  conceive  our  space  to  have  everywhere 
a  nearly  uniform  curvature,  but  that  slight  variations  of 
the  curvature  may  occur  from  point  to  point,  and  them 
selves  vary  with  the  time.  These  variations  of  the 

icurvature  with  the  time  may  produce  effects  which  we 
not  unnaturally  attribute  to  physical  causes  indepen 
dent  of  the  geometry  of  our  space.  We  might  even  ^-o 
so  far  as  to  assign  to  this  variation  of  the  curvature  <>l 

|space  '  what  really  happens  in  that  phenomenon  which 

|we  term  the  motion  of  matter.' l 

1  This  remarkable  possibilit;/  seems  first  to  have  been  suggested  by 
afessor  Clifford  in  a  paper  prespnted  to  the    Cambridge  Philosophical 
(Society  in    1870  (Mathematical  Papers,  p.   21).     I  may  add  the  following 
emarks:  The  most  notable  physical  quantities  which  vary  with  position 
time  are  heat,  light,  and  electro-magnetism.     It  is  these  that  we  ought 
Jjeculiarly  to  consider  when  seeking  for  any  physical  changes,  which  may  bo 
lue  to  changes  in  the  curvature  of  spaco.     If  we  suppose  the  boundary  of 
ay  arbitrary  figure  in  spaco  to  be  distorted   by  the  variation  of  space- 
rurvature,  there  would,  by  analogy  from  one  and  two  dimensions,  be   no 
Lhange  in  the  volume  of  the  figure  arising  from  such  distortion.     Further, 
If  we  assume  as   an  axiom  that   space  resists  curvature  with  a  resistance 


226      THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT    SCIENCES. 

We  have  introduced  these  considerations  as  to  the 
nature  of  our  space  to  bring  home  to  the  reader  the 
character  of  the  postulates  we  make  in  the  exact 
sciences.  These  postulates  are*  not,  as  too  often 
assumed,  necessary  and  universal  truths ;  they  are 
merely  axioms  based  on  our  experience  of  a,  certain 
limited  region.  Just  as  in  any  branch  of  physical 
inquiry  we  start  by  making  experiments,  and  basing  on 
our  experiments  a  set  of  axioms  which  form  the  founda 
tion  of  an  exact  science,  so  in  geometry  our  axioms  are 
really,  although  less  obviously,  the  result  of  experience. 
On  this  ground  geometry  has  been  properly  termed  at 
the  commencement  of  Chapter  II.  a  physical  science. 
The  danger  of  asserting  dogmatically  that  an  axiom 
based  on  the  experience  of  a  limited  region  holds 
universally  will  now  be  to  some  extent  apparent  to  the 
reader.  It  ma}'  lead  us  to  entirely  overlook,  or  when 
suggested  at  once  reject,  a  possible  explanation  o1 
phenomena.  The  hypotheses  that  space  is  not  homa- 
loidal,  and  again,  that  its  geometrical  character  may 
change  with  the  time,  may  or  may  not  be  destined  to 
play  a  great  part  in  the  physics  of  the  future ;  yet  we 
cannot  refuse  to  consider  them  as  possible  explanations 
of  physical  phenomena,  because  they  may  be  opposed  to 
the  popular  dogmatic  belief  in  the  universality  oi 
certain  geometrical  axioms — a  belief  which  has  arisen' 
from  centuries  of  indiscriminating  worship  of  the 
genius  of  Euclid. 

proportional  to  the  change,  \ve  find  that  waves  of  '  space -displacement '  are 
precisely  similar  to  those  of  the  elastic  medium  which  we  suppose  to  propa 
gate  light  and  heat.  We  also  find  that '  space-twist '  is  a  quantity  exactly, 
corresponding  to  magnetic  induction,  and  satisfying  relations  similar  tc 
those  which  hold  for  the  magnetic  field.  It  is  a  question  whether  physicists 
might  not  find  it  simpler  to  assume  that  space  is  capable  of  a  varying 
curvature,  and  of  a  resistance  to  that  variation,  than  to  suppose  the  exist- 
•^nce  of  a  subtle  medium  pervading  an  invariable  homaloidal  space. 


227 


CHAPTER  V. 

MOTION. 

§  1.  On  the  Various  Kinds  of  Motion. 

WHILE  the  chapters  on  Space  and  Position  considered 
ihe  sizes,  the  shapes,  and  the  distances  of  things,  the 
>resent  chapter  on  Motion  will  tivat  of  the  changes  in 
;hese  sizes,  shapes,  and  distances,  which  take  place  from 
;ime  to  time. 

The  difference  between  the  ordinary  meaning  at- 
ached  to  the  word  '  change  '  in  everyday  life  and  the 
meaning  it  has  in  the  exact  sciences  is  perhaps  better 
llustrated  by  the  subject  of  this  chapter  than  by  any 
other  that  we  have  yet  studied.  \Ve  attained  exactness 
n  the  description  of  quantity  and  position  by  substitut 
ing  the  method  of  representing  them  by  straight  liii'-s 
Irawn  on  paper  for  the  method  of  representing  them  by 
means  of  numbers;  though  this,  at  lir.st  sight,  might 
iasily  seem  to  be  a  step  backwards  rather  than  a  step 
or  wards,  since  it  is  more  like  a  child's  sign  of  opening 
ts  arms  to  show  that  its  stick  is  so  long,  than  a  pro 
)f  scientific  calculation. 

It  is,  however,  by  no  means  an  easy  thing  to  give 
in  accurate  description  of  motion,  even  although  it  is 
tself  as  common  and  familiar  a  conception  as  quantity 
>r  position. 

Let  us  take  a  simple  case.  Suppose  that  a  man,  on  a 
•ailway  journey,  is  sitting  at  one  end  of  a  compartment 

Q    -1 


228       THE    COMMON    SENSE    OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

with  his  face  towards  the  engine ;  and  that,  while  th( 
train  is  going  along,  he  gets  up  and  goes  to  the  othei 
end  of  the  compartment  and  sits  down  with  his  back  to 
the  engine.      For  ordinary  purposes  this  description  is 
amply  sufficient,  but  it  is  very  far  indeed  from  being 
an  exact  description  of  the  motion  of  the  man  during 
that  time.     In  the  first  place,  the  train  was  moving 
and  it  is  necessary  to  state  in  what  direction,  and  how 
fast  it  was  going  at  every  instant  during  the  interva 
considered.     Next,  we  must  describe  the  motion  of  the 
man  relatively  to  the  train ;  and,  for  this  purpose,  we 
must  neglect  the  motion  of  the  train  and  consider  how 
the  man  would  have  moved  if  the  train  had  been  a 
rest.     First  of  all,  he  changes  his  position  from  one 
corner   of  the    compartment   to   the  opposite  corner 
next,  in  doing  this  he  turns  round  ;  and,  lastly,  as  he  is 
walking  along  or  rising  up  or  sitting  down,  the  size  am 
shape  of  many  of  his  muscles  are  altered.     We  shoulc 
thus  have  to  say,  first,  exactly  how  fast  and  in  wha 
direction  he  was  moving  at  every  instant,  as  we  had  to 
do  in  the  case  of  the  train ;  then,  how  quickly  he  was 
turning  round ;  and,  lastly,  what  changes  of  size  or 
shape  were  taking  place  in  his  muscles,  and  how  fas 
they  were  occurring. 

It  may  be  urged  that  this  would  be  a  very  trouble 
some  operation,  and  that  nobody  wants  to  describe  the 
motion  of  the  man  so  exactly.  This  is  quite  true  ;  the 
case  which  has  been  taken  for  illustration  is  not  one 
which  it  is  necessary  to  describe  exactly,  but  we  can 
easily  find  another  case  which  is  very  analogous 
to  this,  and  which  it  is  most  important  to  describe 
exactly.  The  earth  moves  round  the  sun  once  in  ever} 
year ;  it  is  also  rotating  on  its  own  axis  once  every  day ; 
the  floating  parts  of  it — the  ocean  and  the  air — aw 


MOTION.  229 

constantly  undergoing  changes  of  shape  and  state 
which  we  can  observe  and  which  it  is  of  the  utmost 

mportance  that  we  should  be  able  to  predict  and 
calculate ;  even  the  solid  nucleus  of  the  earth  is  con 
stantly  subject  to  slight  changes  in  size  and  shape, 
which,  however,  are  not  large  enough  to  admit  of  ac- 

urate   observation.     Here,  then,  is  a  problem  whose 
complexity  is  quite  as  great  as  that  of  the  former,  ;nul 
whose  solution  is  of  pressing  practical  importance. 
The    method    which  is  adopted  for  attacking  this 

>roblem  of  the  accurate  description  of  motion  is  to  begin 
with  the  simplest  cases.  By  the  simplest  cases  we  mean 

;hose  in  which  certain  complicating  circumstances  do 
not  arise.  We  may  first  of  all  restrict  ourselves  to  the 
study  of  the  motions  of  those  bodies  in  which  there  is 
no  change  of  size  or  shape.  A  body  which  preserves 

ts  size  and  shape  unaltered  during  the  interval  of  tinn- 
considered  is  called  a  rigid  body.  The  word  'rigid  '  is 

lere  used  in  a  technical  sense  belonging  to  the  science 
of  dynamic,  and  does  not  mean,  as  in  ordinary  lan- 

juage,  a  body  which  resists  alteration  of  size  and  shape, 

>ut   merely    a   body    which,    during    a    certain    time, 

lappens  not  to  be  altered  in  those  respects.    Then,  as  the 

irst  and  simplest  case,  we  should  study  that  motion  of 
a  rigid  body  in  which  there  is  no  turning  round,  and 

n  which  therefore  every  line  in  the  bodv  kf"j>s  the 
same  direction  (though  of  course  not  the  same  position) 

ihroughout  the  motion.  We  state  this  by  saying  that 
avery  line  'rigidly  connected'  writh  the  body  remains 

>arallel  to  itself.     Such  a  motion  is  called  a  motion  of 

'ranslation,  or  simply  a  translation ;  and  so  the  first  and 
amplest  case  we  have  to  study  is  the  translation  of 

igid  bodies.     After  that  we  nmst  proceed  to  consider 

iheir  turning  round,  or  rotation ;  and  then  we  have  to 


230      THE    COMMON    SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

describe  the  changes  of  size  or  shape  which  bodies  may 
undergo,  these  last  changes  being  called  strains.'  The 
study  of  motion  therefore  requires  the  further  study  of 
translations,  of  rotations,  and  of  strains,  and  further, 
the  art  of  combining  these  together.  When  we  have 
studied  all  this  we  shall  be  able  to  describe  motions 
exactly  ;  and  then,  but  not  till  then,  will  it  be  possible 
to  state  the  exact  circumstances  under  which  motions 
of  a  given  kind  occur.  The  exact  circumstances  under 
which  motions  of  a  given  kind  occur  we  call  a  law  of 
nature. 

§  2.   Translation  and  the  Curve  of  Positions. 

Let  us  talk,  to  begin  with,  of  the  translation  of  a 
rigid  body. 

Suppose  a  table  to  be  taken  from  the  top  to  the 
bottom  of  a  house  in  such  a  manner  that  the  surface  of 
it  is  always  kept  horizontal,  and  that  its  length  is  made 
always  to  point  due  north  and  south ;  it  may  be  taken 
down  a  staircase  of  any  form,  but  it  is  not  to  be  turned 
round  or  tilted  up.     The   table  will  then  undergo  a 
translation.     If  we  now  consider  a  particular  corner  of 
the  table,  or  the  end  of  one  of  its  legs,  or  any  other 
point,  this  point  will  have  described  a  certain  curve  ID 
a  certain  manner ;  that  is  to  say,  at  every  point  of 
curve  it  will  have  been  going  at  a  certain  definite  rateJ 
Now  the  important  property  of  a  motion  of  translation' 
which  makes  it  more  easy  to  deal  with  than  any  othei 
motion,  is  that  for  all  points  of  the  body  this  curve  if 
the  same  in  size  and  shape  and  mode  of  description 
That  this  is  so  in  the  case  of  the  table  is  at  once  seei  j 
from  the  fact   that   the  table  is  never   turned   roun< 
nor  tilted  up  during  the  motion,  so  that  the  differen 
points  of  it  must  at  any  instant  be  moving  in  the  sam< 


f  MOTION.  231 

direction  and  at  the  same  rate.  In  order  therefore  to 
describe  this  motion  of  the  table  it  will  be  sufficient  to 
describe  the  motion  of  any  point  of  it,  say  the  end  of 
one  of  its  legs.  And  so,  in  general,  the  problem  of 
describing  the  motion  of  translation  of  any  rigid  body 
is  reduced  to  the  problem  of  describing  the  motion  of 
a  point  along  a  curve. 

Now  this  is  a  very  much  easier  t;isk  than  our 
original  problem  of  describing  the  motion  of  the  e;irth 
or  the  motion  of  the  man  in  the  train;  but  we  shall 
see  that,  by  properly  studying  this,  it  will  be  easy  to 
^uild  up  out  of  it  other  more  complicated  cases.  Still, 
ven  in  this  form  our  problem  is  not  quite  simple 
nough  to  be  directly  attacked.  What  we  have  to  do, 
it  must  be  remembered,  is  to  state  exactly  where  a 
ertain  point  was,  and  how  last  it  was  going  at  every 
instant  of  time  during  a  certain  interval.  This  would 
require  us  first  to  describe  exactly  the  shape  of  the 
urve  along  which  the  point  moved  ;  next,  to  say  how 
lar  it  had  travelled  along  the  curve  from  the  beginning 
up  to  any  given  instant;  and  lastlv,  how  fast  it  wa> 
*oing  at  that  instant.  To  deal  with  this  problem  we 
must  first  take  the  very  simplest  case  of  it,  that,  namely, 
In  which  the  point  moves  along  a  straight  line,  and 
.eave  for  the  present  out  of  account  any  description  of 
ihe  rate  of  motion  of  the  point ;  so  that  we  have  only 
say  where  the  point  was  on  a  certain  straight  line 
at  every  instant  of  time  within  a  given  interval. 

But  we  have  already  considered  what  is  the  best  wav 
of  describing  the  position  of  a  point  upon  a  straight 
ine.  It  is  described  by  means  of  the  step  which  is 
required  to  carry  it  to  that  position  from  a  certain 
tandard  place,  viz.  a  step  from  that  place  so  far  to  the 
right  or  to  the  left.  To  specify  the  length  of  the  step, 


232       THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF    THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

if  we  are  to  describe  it  exactly,  we  must  not  make  use 
of  any  words  or  numbers,  but  must  draw  a  line  which 
will  represent  the  length  corresponding  to  every  instant 
of  time  within  a  certain  interval,  so  that  we  may 
always  be  able  to  answer  the  question,  Where  was 
the  point  at  this  particular  instant  ?  But  a  question, 
in  order  to  be  exactly  answered,  must  first  be  exactly 
asked  ;  and  to  do  this  it  is  necessary  that  the  instant 
of  time  about  which  the  question  is  asked  should  be 
accurately  specified. 

Now  time,  like  length,  is  a  continuous  quantity 
which  cannot  in  general  be  described  by  words  or 
numbers,  but  can  be  by  the  drawing  of  a  line  which  shall 
represent  it  to  a  certain  scale.  .Suppose,  then,  that  the 
interval  of  time  during  which  the  motion  of  a  point  has 
to  be  described  is  the  interval  from  twelve  o'clock  to 
one  o'clock.  We  must  mark  on  a  straight  line  a  point 
to  represent  twelve  o'clock  and  another  point  to  repre 
sent  one  o'clock;  then  every  instant  between  twelve 
o'clock  and  one  o'clock  will  be  represented  by  a  point 
which  divides  the  distance  between  these  two  marked 
points  in  the  same  ratio  in  which  that  instant  divides 
the  interval  between  twelve  o'clock  and  one  o'clock. 
Then  for  every  one  of  these  points  it  is  necessary  to 
assign  a  certain  length,  representing  (to  some  definite 
scale)  the  distance  which  the  point  has  travelled  up  to 
that  instant ;  and  the  question  arises,  In  what  way  shall 
we  mark  down  these  lengths  ? 

Let  us  first  of  all  observe  the  difficulty  of  answering 
this  question.  If  we  could  be  content  with  an  approxi 
mate  solution  instead  of  an  exact  one,  we  might  make 
a  table  and  put  down  in  inches  and  decimals  of  an  inch 
the  distances  travelled,  making  an  entry  for  every 
minute,  or  even  perhaps  for  every  second  during  the 


MOTION. 


233 


hour.  Such  tables  are  in  fact  constructed  and  pub 
lished  in  the  *  Nautical  Almanac  '  for  the  positions  of  the 
moon  and  of  the  planets.  The  labour  of  making  this 
table  will  evidently  depend  upon  its  degree  of  minute 
ness  ;  it  will  of  course  take  sixty  times  as  long  to  make 
a  table  showing  the  position  of  the  point  at  every 
second  as  to  make  one  showing  the  position  at  every 
minute,  because  there  will  be  sixty  times  as  many 
values  to  calculate.  But  the  problem  of  describing 
exactly  the  motion  of  the  point  requires  us  to  make  a 
table  showing  the  position  of  the  point  at  every  instant ; 
that  is,  a  table  in  which  are  entered  an  infinite  number 
of  values.  These  values  moreover  are  to  be  shown,  not 
in  inches  and  decimals  of  an  inch,  but  by  lengths  drawn 
upon  paper.  Yet  we  shall  find  that  this  pictorial  mode  of 
constructing  the  table  is  in  most  cases  very  much  easier 
than  the  other.  We  have  only  to  decide  where  we  shall 
put  the  straight  lines  which  represent  the  distances 
that  the  point  has  travelled  at  different  instants. 


FIG.  92. 

Let  a  b  be  the  length  which  represents  the  interval 
lof  time  from  twelve  o'clock  to  one  o'clock,  and  let  ra  be 
[the  point  representing  any  intermediate  instant.  Then 
lif  we  draw  at  m  a  line  perpendicular  to  a  b  whose  length 
Ishall  represent  (to  any  scale  that  we  may  choose)  the 
[distance  that  the  point  has  up  to  this  instant  travelled, 
Ithen  p,  the  extremity  of  this  line,  will  correspond  to 


234      THE    COMMON    SENSE    OP    THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

an  entry  in  our  table.  But  if  such  lines  be  drawn 
perpendicular  to  a  b  from  every  point  in  it,  all  the 
points  p,  which  are  the  several  extremities  of  these 
lines,  will  lie  upon  some  curve ;  and  this  curve  will  re 
present  an  infinite  number  of  entries  in  our  table.  For, 
when  once  the  curve  is  drawn,  if  a  question  is  asked  : 
What  was  the  position  of  the  point  at  any  instant 
between  twelve  o'clock  and  one  o'clock  ?  (this  instant 
being  specified  in  the  right  way  by  marking  a  point 
between  a  and  b  which  divides  that  line  in  the  same 
ratio  as'  the  given  instant  divides  the  hour),  then  the 
answer  to  this  question  is  obtained  simply  by  drawing 
a  line  through  the  marked  point  perpendicular  to  a  b 
until  it  meets  the  curve ;  and  the  length  of  that  line 
will  represent,  to  the  scale  previously  agreed  upon,  the 
distance  travelled  by  the  point. 

Such  a  curve  is  called  the  curve  of  positions  for  a 
given  motion  of  the  point ;  and  we  arrive  at  this  result, 
that  the  proper  way  of  specifying  exactly  a  translation 
along  a  straight  line  is  to  draw  the  curve  of  positions. 

We  have  now  learned  to  specify,  by  means  of  a 
curve,  the  positions  of  a  body  which  has  motion  of 
translation  along  a  straight  line ;  and  we  have  not 
only  represented  an  infinite  number  of  positions  in 
stead  of  a  finite  number,  which  is  all  a  numerical  table 
would  admit,  but  have  also  represented  each  position 
with  absolute  exactness  instead  of  approximately.  It 
is  important  to  notice  that  in  this  and  in  all  similar 
ca,ses  the  exactness  is  ideal  and  not  practical ;  it  is 
exactness  of  conception  and  not  of  actual  measurement. 
For  though  it  is  not  possible  to  measure  a  given  length 
and  to  state  that  measure  any  more  accurately  by 
drawing  a  line  than  it  is  by  writing  it  down  in  inches 
and  decimals  of  an  inch,  yet  the  representation  by 


MOTION.  235 

means  of  a  line  enables  us  to  reason  upon  it  with  an 
exactness  which  would  be  impossible  if  we  were  re 
stricted  to  numerical  measurement. 


§  3.   Uniform  ^lotion. 

Hitherto  we  have  supposed  our  point  to  be  moving 
along  a  straight  line,  but  were  it  to  move  along  a  curve 
the  construction  given  for  the  curve  of  positions  would 
still  hold  good,  only  the  distance  traversed  at  any 
instant  must  now  be  measured  from  some  standard 
position  aloiuj  the  curve.  Hence  any  motion  of  a  point, 
or  any  motion  of  translation  whatever,  can  be  specified 
by  a  properly  drawn  curve  of  positions,  and  the  problem 
of  comparing  and  classifying  different  motions  is  there 
fore  reduced  to  the  problem  of  comparing  and  classi 
fying  curves.  Here  again  it  is  advisable  and  even 
necessary  to  begin  with  a  simple  case.  Let  us  take 
the  case  of  uniform  motion,  in  which  ihe  h-idy  passes 
over  equal  distances  in  equal  times  ;  and  then,  as  we 
may  easily  see,  the  curve  of  positions  is  a  straight  line. 
Uniform  motion  may  also  be  described  as  that  in  \vhich 
a  body  alwavs  goes  at  the  same  rate,  and  not  quicker 
at  one  time  and  slower  at  another.  It  is  obvious  that 
in  this  case  any  two  equal  distances  would  require  equal 
times  for  traversing  them,  so  that  the  two  descriptions 
of  uniform  motion  are  equivalent. 

It  was  shown  by  Archimedes  ^the  proof  is  an  easy 
one,  depending  upon  the  definition  of  tin-  fourth  pro 
portional)   that  whenever  equal  distances  are  traversed 
in  equal  times,  different  distances  will  be  traversed  in 
times  proportional  to  them.     Assuming  this  proposition, 
becomes  clear  that  the  curve  of  positions  must  be  a 
J straight  line,  for  a  straight  line  is  the  only  curve  which 


236      THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

has  the  property  that  the  height  of  every  point  of  it  is 
proportional  to  its  horizontal  distance  from  a  fixed 
straight  line. 

We  may  also  see  in  the  following  manner  the  con 
nection  between  the  straight  line  and  uniform  motion. 

Suppose  we  walk  up  a  hill  so  as  always  to  get  over 
a  horizontal  distance  of  four  miles  in  an  hour.  The 
rate  at  which  we  go  up  will  clearly  depend  on  the  steep 
ness  of  the  hill ;  and  if  the  hill  is  a  plane,  i.e.  is  of  the 
same  steepness  all  the  way  up,  then  our  rate  of  ascent 
will  be  the  same  at  every  instant,  or  our  upward  motion 
will  be  uniform.  If  the  hill  be  four  miles  long  and 
one  mile  high,  then,  since  the  four  miles  of  horizontal 
distance  will  be  traversed  in  an  hour,  the  one  mile  of 
vertical  distance  will  also  be  traversed  in  an  hour,  and 
we  shall  be  gaining  height  at  the  uniform  rate  of  one 
mile  an  hour.  If  the  hill  were  two  miles  high,  or,  as  we 
say  twice  as  steep,  then  we  should  have  been  gaining 
height  at  the  rate  of  two  miles  an  hour.  Bat  now  if 
\ve  suppose  a  hill  of  varying  steepness,  so  that  the  out 
line  of  it  seen  from  one  side  is  a  curve,  then  it  is  clear 
that  the  rate  at  which  we  go  up  will  depend  upon  the 
part  of  the  hill  where  we  are,  assuming  that  the  rate  at 
which  we  go  forward  horizontally  remains  always  the 
same.  This  '  elevation  '  of  the  hill  may  be  taken  as  the 
curve  of  positions  for  our  vertical  motion ;  for  the 
horizontal  distance  that  we  have  gone  over,  being 
always  proportional  to  the  time,  may  be  taken  to  repre 
sent  the  time,  and  then  the  curve  will  have  been  con 
structed  according  to  our  rule,  viz.  a  horizontal  dis 
tance  will  have  been  taken  proportional  to  the  time 
elapsed,  and  from  the  end  of  this  line  a  perpendicular  j 
will  have  been  raised  indicating  the  height  which  we] 
have  risen  in  that  time.  Uniform  motion  then  has 


MOTION.    .  237 

for  its  curve  of  positions  a  straight  line,  and  the  rate 
of  the  motion  depends  on  the  steepness  of  the  line. 
Variable  motion,  on  the  other  hand,  has  a  curved  line 
for  its  curve  of  positions,  and  the  rate  of  motion 
depends  upon  its  varying  steepness. 

In  the  case  of  uniform  motion  it  is  very  easy  indeed 
to  understand  what  we  moan  by  the  rate  of  the  motion. 
Thus,  if  a  man  walks  uniformly  six  miles  an  hour, 
we  know  that  he  walks  a  mile  in  ten  minutes,  and  the 
tenth  part  of  a  mile  in  one  minute,  and  so  on  in  propor 
tion.  It  may  not,  however,  be  possible  to  specify  this 
rate  by  means  of  numbers  ;  that  is  to  say,  the  man  may 
not  walk  any  definite  number  of  miles  in  the  hour,  and 
the  exact  distance  that  he  walks  may  not  be  capable  of 
representation  in  terms  of  miles  and  fractions  of  a  mile. 
In  that  case  we  shall  have  to  represent  the  velocity  or 
rate  at  which  the  man  walks  in  much  the  same  way  as 
we  have  represented  other  continuous  quantities.  We 
must  draw  to  scale  upon  paper  a  line  representing  the 
length  that  he  has  walked  in  an  hour,  or  a  minute,  or 
any  other  interval  of  time  that  we  decide  to  select  ; 
thus,  for  example,  a  uniform  rate  of  walking  might  be 
specified  by  marking  points  corresponding  to  particular 
hours  upon  an  Ordnance  map.  The  rate  of  motion,  or 
velocity,  is  then  a  continuous  quantity  which  can  be 
exactly  specified,  as  we  specify  other  continuous  quan 
tities,  but  which  can  be  only  approximately  described  by 
means  of  numbers. 

§  4.   Variable  Motion. 

Let  us  now  suppose  that  the  motion  is  not  uniform, 
and  inquire  what  is  meant  in  that  case  by  the  rate  at 
which  a  body  moves. 


238      THE    COMMON    SEXSE    OF    THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

A  train,  for  example,  starts  from  a  station  and  in 
the  course  of  a  few  minutes  gets  up  to  a  speed  of  30 
miles  an  hour.  It  began  by  being  at  rest,  and  it  ends  by 
having  this  large  velocity.  What  has  happened  to  it  in 
the  meantime  ?  We  can  understand  already  in  a  rough 
sort  of  way  what  is  meant  by  saying  that  at  a  certain 
time  between  the  two  moments  the  train  must  have  been 
going  at  15  miles  an  hour,  or  at  any  other  intermediate 
rate ;  but  let  us  endeavour  to  make  this  conception  a 
little  more  exact.  Suppose,  then,  that  a  second  train, 
which  is  indefinitely  long, is  moving  in  the  same  direction 
at  a  uniform  rate  of  15  miles  an  hour  on  a  pair  of  rails 
parallel  to  that  on  which  the  first  train  moves ;  thus, 
when  our  first  train  is  at  rest  the  second  one  will  appear 
to  move  past  it  at  the  rate  of  15  miles  an  hour.  When 
the  first  train  starts  an  observer  seated  in  it  will  see 
the  second  train  going  apparently  rather  more  slowly 
than  before,  but  it  will  still  seem  to  be  moving  forwards. 
As  the  first  train  gets  up  its  speed,  this  apparent 
forward  motion  will  gradually  decrease  until  the  second 
train  will  appear  to  be  going  so  slowly  that  conversation 
may  be  held  between  the  two  ;  this  will  take  place  when 
the  rate  of  the  first  train  has  amounted  to  something 
nearly  but  not  quite  equal  to  15  miles  an  hour,  which 
we  supposed  to  be  the  constant  rate  of  the  second  train. 
But  as  the  rate  of  the  first  train  continues  to  increase 
there  will  come  a  certain  instant  at  which  the  second  train 
will  appear  to  stop  gaining  upon  the  first  and  to  begin 
to  lose.  At  that  particular  instant  it  will  be  neither 
gaining  nor  losing,  but  will  be  going  at  the  same  rate; 
at  that  particular  instant,  therefore,  we  must  say  that 
the  first  train  is  going  at  the  rate  of  15  miles  an 
hour.  And  it  is  at  that  instant  only,  for  the  equality 
of  the  rates  does  not  last  for  any  fraction  of  a  second, 


MOTION.  239 

however  small ;  the  very  instant  that  the  second  train 
appears  to  stop  gaining  it  also  appears  to  begin  losing. 
The  two  trains  then  run  exactly  together  for  no  distance 
at  all,  not  even  for  the  smallest  fraction  of  an  inch, 
and  yet  we  have  to  say  that  at  one  particular  instant 
our  first  train  is  going  at  the  rate  of  1 5  miles  an  hour, 
although  it  does  not  continue  to  go  at  that  rate  during 
the  smallest  portion  of  time.  There  is  no  way  of 
measuring  this  instantaneous  velocity  except  that  which 
has  just  been  described  of  comparing  the  motion  with  a 
uniform  motion  having  that  particular  velocity. 

Upon  this  we  have  to  make  the  very  important 
remark  that  the  rate  at  which  a  body  is  going  is  a 
property  as  purely  instantaneous  as  is  the  precise 
position  which  it  has  at  that  instant.  Thus,  if  a  stone 
be  let  fall  to  the  ground,  at  the  moment  that  it  hits 
the  ground  it  is  going  at  a  certain  definite  rate  ;  and  yet 
at  any  previous  moment  it  was  not  going  so  fast,  since 
it  does  not  move  at  that  rate  for  the  smallest  fraction  of 
a  second.  This  consideration  is  somewhat  difficult  to 
grasp  thoroughly,  and  in  fact  it  has  led  many  people  to 
reject  altogether  the  hypothesis  of  continuity  ;  but  still 
we  may  be  helped  somewhat  in  understanding  it  by 
means  of  our  study  of  the  curve  of  positions,  wherein 
we  saw  that  to  a  uniform  motion  corresponds  a  straight 
line  and  that  the  rate  of  the  motion  depends  on  the 
steepness  of  the  line. 

Let  us  now  suppose  a  motion  in  which  a  body  goes 
i  at  a  very  slow  but  uniform  rate   for  the   first  second, 
during  the  next  second  uniformly  but  somewhat  faster, 
[faster  again  during  the  third  second,  and  so  on.     The 
curve  of  positions  will  then  be  represented  by  a  series 
[of  straight  lines  becoming  steeper  and  steeper  and  form- 
g  part  of  a  polygon.     From  a  sufficient  distance  oft 


240      THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF    THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

this  polygon  will  look  like  a  curved  line  ;  and  if,  instead 
of  taking  intervals  of  a  second  during  which  the  rates 
of  motion  are  severally  considered  uniform,  we  had 
taken  intervals  of  a  tenth  of  a  second,  then  the  polygon 
would  look  like  a  curved  ]ine  without  our  going  so  far* 
away  as  before.  For  the  shorter  the  lengths  of  the  sides 
of  our  polygon,  the  more  will  it  look  curved,  and  if  the 
intervals  of  time  are  reduced  to  one-  tenth  the  sides 
will  be  only  one-tenth  as  long.  The  rate  at  which  the 
body  under  consideration  is  moving  when  it  is  in  the 
position  to  which  any  point  of  the  polygon  corresponds, 
is  obtained  by  prolonging  that  side  of  the  polygon 
which  passes  through  the  point;  the  rate  will  then 
depend  on  the  steepness  of  this  line,  since,  where  the 
line  is  a  side  of  the  polygon,  it  represents  the  uniform 
motion  which  the  body  has  during  a  certain  interval. 
When  the  polygon  looks  like  a  curve  the  sides  are  very 
short,  and  any  side,  being  prolonged  both  ways,  will 
look  like  a  tangent  to  the  curve. 

Now  in   considering  the   general   case  of  varying 
motion  we  should  have,  instead  of  the  above  polygon 
which  looks  like  a  curve,  an  actual  curve  ;  the  difference 
between  them  being  that,  if  we  look  at  the  curve-like 
polygon  with  a  sufficiently  strong  microscope,  we  shall  i 
be  able  to  see  its  angles,  but  however  powerful  a  micro 
scope  we  may  apply  to  the  curve  it  will  always  look  like  i 
a  curve.     But  there  is  this  property  in  common,  that  if 
we  draw  a  tangent  to  the  curve  at  any  point,  then,  since  j 
the  steepness  of  this  tangent  will  be  exactly  the  same  as 
the  steepness  of  the  curve  at  that  particular  point,  it  will  j 
give  the  rate  for  the  motion  represented  by  the  curve,  just! 
as  before  the  steepness  of  the  prolonged  small  side  of  thej 
polygon  gave  the  rate  for  the  motion  represented  by  the 
polygon.     That  is  to  say,  the  instantaneous  velocity  of 


MOTION. 


241 


a  body  in  any  position  may  be  learnt  from  its  curve  of 
positions  by  drawing  a  tangent  to  this  curve  at  the  point 
corresponding  to  the  position;  for  the  steepness  of  this 
tangent  will  give  us  the  velocity  or  rate  which  we  want, 
since  the  tangent  itself  corresponds  to  a  uniform 
motion  of  the  same  velocity  as  that  belonging  to  the 
given  varying  inotion  at  the  particular  instant.  From 
this  means  of  representing  the  rate  we  can  see  how  it 
is  that  the  instantaneous  velocity  of  a  body  generally 
belongs  to  it  only  at  an  instant  and  not  for  any  length 
of  time  however  short ;  for  the  steepness  of  the  curve 
is  continually  changing  as  we  go  from  one  part  of  it 
to  another,  and  the  curve  is  not  straight  for  any  portion 
of  its  length  however  small. 

The  problem  of  determining  the  instantaneous  ve 
locity  in  a  given  position  is  therefore  reduced  to  the 
problem  of  drawing  a  tangent  to  a  given  curve.  We 
have  a  sufficiently  clear  general  notion  of  what  is  meant 
by  each  of  these  things,  but  the  notion  which  is  suf 
ficient  for  purposes  of  ordinary  discourse  is  not  sufficient 
for  the  purposes  of  reasoning,  and  it  must  therefore  be 
i  made  exact.  Just  as  we  had  to  make  our  notion  of 
the  ratio  of  two  quantities  exact  by  means  of  a  definition 
(of  the  fourth  proportional,  or  of  the  equality  of  two 
ratios  which  were  expressed  in  terms  of  numbers,  so 
mere  we  shall  have  to  make  our  idea  of  a  velocity 
exact  by  expressing  it  in  terms  of  measurable  quan- 
Itities  which  do  not  change. 

We  have  no  means  of  measuring  the  instantaneous 
[velocity  of  a  moving  body;  the  only  thing  that  we  can 
leasure  is  the  space  which  it  traverses  in  a  given  interval 
fof  time.  In  the  case  in  which  a  body  is  moving  uni- 
Iformly,  its  instantaneous  velocity,  being  always  tho  same, 
Is  completely  specified  as  soon  as  we  know  how  far 


242      THE    COMMON    SENSE   OF    THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

the  body  has  gone  in  a  definite  time.  And,  as  we 
have  already  observed,  the  result  is  the  same  whatever 
this  interval  of  time  may  be  ;  the  rate  of  four  miles  an 
hour  is  the  same  as  eight  miles  in  two  hours,  or  two 
miles  in  half  an  hour,  or  one  mile  in  a  quarter  of  an 
hour.  But  if  a  body  be  moving  with  a  velocity  which 
is  continually  changing,  the  knowledge  of  how  far  it  has 
gone  in  a  given  interval  of  time  tells  us  nothing  about 
the  instantaneous  velocity  for  any  position  during  that 
interval.  To  say,  for  instance,  that  a  man  has 
travelled  a  distance  of  four  miles  during  an  hour,  does 
not  give  us  any  information  about  the  actual  rate  at 
which  he  was  going  at  any  moment  during  the  hour, 
unless  Are  know  that  he  has  been  going  at  a  uniform 
rate.  Still  we  are  accustomed  to  say  that  in  such 
a  case  he  must  have  been  going  on  an  average  at  the 
rate  of  four  miles  an  hour;  and,  as  we  shall  find  it 
useful  to  speak  of  this  rate  as  an  '  average  velocity,' 
its  general  definition  may  be  given  as  follows : — 

If  a  body  has  gone  over  a  certain  distance  in  a 
certain  time  its  mean  or  average  velocity  is  that  with 
which,  if  it  travelled  uniformly,  it  would  get  over  the] 
same  distance  in  the  same  time. 

This  mean  velocity  is  very  simply  represented  by] 
the  help  of  the  curve  of  positions.     Let  a  and  6  be  two] 
points   on    the    curve   of    positions ;    then   the    meanj 
velocity  between  the  position  represented  by  a  and  that 
represented   by   6   is   given   by  the    steepness    of   the 
straight  line  a  b.     This,  moreover,  enables  us  to  make 
some  progress  towards  a  method  of  calculating  instan 
taneous  velocity,  for  we  showed  that  the  problem  oJ;  r; 
finding  the  instantaneous  velocity  of  a  body  is,  in  thd 
above  method  of  representation,  the  problem  of  draw-] 
ing  a  tangent  to  a  curve.     Now  the  mean  velocity  of 


MOTION. 


243 


body  is  defined  in  terms  of  quantities  which  we  are 
already  able  to  measure,  for  it  requires  the  measure 
ment  of  an  interval  of  time  and  of  the  distance 
traversed  during  that  interval ;  and  further  the  chord 
of  a  curve,  i.e.  the  line  joining  one  point  of  it  to  another, 


Flti.  93. 

is  a  line  which  we  are  able  to  draw.  If  then  we  can 
lind  some  means  of  passing  from  the  chord  of  a  curve 
to  the  tangent,  the  representation  we  have  adopted  will 
help  us  to  pass  from  the  mean  to  the  instantaneous 
velocity. 

§  5.  On  tJie  Tangent  to  a  Curve. 

Now  let  us  suppose  the  chord  a  b  joining  the 
[points  on  the  curve  to  turn  round  the  point  a,  which 
remains  fixed;  then  b  will  travel  along  the  curve 


FIG.  94. 

towards  a ;   and  if  we  suppose  b  not  to  stop  in    this 

[notion  until  it  has  got  beyond  a  to  a  point  such  as  6 

|>n  the  other  side,  the  chord  will  have  turned  round 

ito  the  position  a  V.     Now,  looking  at  the  curve  which 

it    '2 


244      THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF    THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

is  drawn  in  the  figure,  we  see  that  the  tangent  to  the 
curve  at  a  obviously  lies  between  a  b  and  V  a.  Thus  if 
a  b  turn  round  a  so  as  to  move  into  the  position  a  V  it  will 
at  some  instant  have  to  pass  over  the  position  of  the 
tangent.  At  the  instant  when  it  passes  over  this 
position  where  is  the  point  b  ?  We  can  at  once  see 
from  the  figure  that  it  cannot  be  anywhere  else  than  at 
a,  and  yet  we  cannot  attach  any  definite  meaning  to  a 
line  described  as  joining  two  coincident  points.  If  we 
could,  the  determination  of  the  tangent  would  be  very 
easy,  for  in  order  to  draw  the  tangent  to  the  curve  at 
a,  we  should  merely  say,  Take  any  other  point  b  on  the 
curve ;  join  a  b  by  a  straight  line ;  then  make  b  travel 
along  the  curve  towards  a,  and  the  position  of  the  line 
a  b  when  b  has  got  to  a  is  that  of  the  tangent  at  a. 
Here  however  arises  the  difficulty  which  we  have  already 
pointed  out,  namely,  that  we  cannot  form  any  distinct 
conception  of  a  line  joining  two  coincident  points;; 
two  separate  points  are  necessary  in  order  to  fix  a 
straight  line.  But  it  is  clear  that,  although  it  is  not] 
yet  satisfactory,  there  is  still  something  in  the  defini-l 
tion  that  is  useful  and  correct ;  for  if  we  make  tl 
chord  turn  from  the  position  a  b  to  the  position  of  the 
tangent  at  a,  the  point  b  does  during  this  motion  move 
along  the  curve  up  to  the  point  a. 

This  difficulty  was  first  cleared  up  and  its  explana-l 
tion  made  a  matter  of  common  sense  by  Newton.  Th<  j 
nature  of  his  explanation  is  as  follows : — Let  us 
simplicity  take  the  curve  to  be  a  circle.  If  a  straighj 
stick  be  taken  and  bent  so  as  to  become  part  of  :| 
circle,  the  size  of  this  circle  will  depend  upon  thj 
amount  of  bending.  The  stick  may  be  bent  complete!! 
round  until  the  ends  meet,  and  then  it  will  make  a  verl 

.  ., 

small  circle  ;  or  it  may  be  bent  very  slightly  indeed,  an| 

•it  ,,„ 


MOTION. 


245 


then  it  will  become  part  of  a  very  large  circle.  Now, 
conversely,  suppose  that  we  begin  with  a  small  circle, 
and,  holding  it  fast  at  one  point,  make  it  get  larger 
and  larger,  so  that  the  piece  we  have  hold  of  gets  less 
and  less  bent ;  then,  as  the  circle  becomes  extremely 
large,  any  small  portion  of  it  will  more  and  more 
nearly  approximate  to  a  straight  line.  Hence  a  circle 
possesses  this  property,  that  the  more  it  is  magnified 
the  straightor  it  becomes  ;  this  property  likewise  be 
longs  to  all  the  curves  which  we  require  to  consider. 
It  is  sometimes  expressed  by  saying  that  the  curve  is 
straight  in  its  elements,  or  in  its  smallest  parts  ;  but 
the  statement  must  be  understood  to  mean  only  this, 
that  the  smaller  the  piece  of  a  curve  is  taken  the 
straighter  it  will  look  when  magnified  to  a  given 
length. 

Now  let  us  apply  tins  to  the  problem  of  determining 
the  position  of  a  tangent.  Let  us  suppose  the  tan 
gent  at  of  a  circle  to  be  already  drawn,  and  that  a 


FIG.  95. 

'certain  convenient  length  is  marked  off  upon  it;  from 
I  the  end  of  this  T  let  a  perpendicular  be  drawn  to  meet 
[the  circle  in  B,  and  let  a  be  joined  to  B  by  a  straight 
line.  We  have  now  to  consider  the  motion  of  the  point 
[B  along  the  circle  as  the  chord  a  P>  is  turning  round 
la  towards  the  position  a  T  ;  and  the  difficulty  in  our  wTay 
lis  clearly  that  figures  like  a  B  T  get  small,  as  for  ex- 
I ample  a  1 1,  and  continue  to  decrease  until  they  cease 
[to  be  large  enough  to  be  definitely  observed.  Newton 


246      THE   COMMON   SENSE   OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

gets  over  this  difficulty  by  supposing  tliat  the  figure  is 
always  magnified  to  a  definite  size  ;  so  that  instead 
of  considering  the  smaller  figure  a  b  t  we  magnify  it 
throughout  until  a  t  is  equal  to  the  original  length  a  T. 
But  the  portion  a  b  of  the  circle  with  which  we  are  now 
concerned  is  less  than  the  former  portion  a  B ;  conse 
quently  when  it  is  magnified  to  the  same  length  (or 
nearly  so)  it  must  appear  straighter.  That  is  to  say,  in 
the  new  figure  a  b'  T,  which  is  a  b  t  magnified,  the  point  b 
will  be  nearer  to  the  point  T  than  B  in  the  old  one  a  B  T ; 
consequently,  also,  as  b  moves  along  to  a  the  chord  a  b 
will  get  nearer  to  the  tangent  a  T,  or,  what  is  the  same 
thing,  the  angle  tab  will  get  smaller.  This  last  result 
is  clear  enough,  because,  as  we  previously  supposed,  the 
chord  a  b  is  always  turning  round  towards  the  position 
at. 

But  now  the  important  thing  is  that,  by  taking  b 
near  enough  to  a,  we  can  make  the  curve  in  the  magni 
fied  figure  as  straight  as  we  please ;  that  is  to  say,  we 


FIG.  96. 

can  make  V  approach  as  near  as  we  like  to  T.  If  we 
were  to  measure  off  from  T  perpendicularly  to  a  T  any 
length,  however  small,  say  T  d,  then  we  can  always 
draw  a  circle  which  shall  have  a  T  for  a  tangent  and 
which  shall  pass  between  T  and  d ;  and,  further,  if 
we  like  to  draw  a  line  a  d  making  a  very  small  angle 
with  a  T,  then  it  will  still  be  possible  to  make  b  go  so 
close  to  a  that  in  the  magnified  figure  the  angle  b'aT 
shall  be  smaller  than  the  angle  d  a  T  which  we  have 
drawn. 

Now  mark  what  this  process,  which  has  been  called  •; 


MOTION.  247 

Newton's  microscope,  really  means.  While  the  figure 
which  we  wish  to  study  is  getting  smaller  and  smaller, 
and  finally  disappears  altogether,  we  suppose  it  to  be 
continually  magnified,  so  as  to  retain  a  convenient  size. 
We  have  one  point  moving  along  a  curve  up  towards 
another  point,  and  we  want  to  consider  what  happens 
to  the  line  joining  them  when  the  two  points  approach 
indefinitely  near  to  one  another.  The  result  at  which 
we  have  arrived  by  means  of  our  microscope  is  that, 
by  taking  the  points  near  enough  together,  the  line 
may  be  made  to  approach  as  near  as  we  please  to  the 
tangent  to  the  curve  at  the  point  a.  This,  therefore, 
gives  us  a  definition  of  the  tangent  to  a  curve  in 
terms  only  of  measurable  quantities.  If  at  a  certain 
point  a  of  a  curve  there  is  a  line  a  t  possessing  the 
property  that  by  taking  b  near  enough  to  a  on  the  curve 
the  line  a  b  can  be  brought  as  near  as  we  like  to  a  t 
(that  is,  the  angle  bat  made  less  than  any  assigned 
angle,  however  small),  then  a  t  is  called  the  tangent  to 
the  curve  at  the  point  a.  Observe  that  all  the  things 
supposed  to  be  done  in  this  definition  are  things  which 
we  know  can  be  done.  A  very  small  angle  can  be 
assigned;  then,  this  angle  being  drawn,  a  position  of 

,the  point  b  can  be  found  which  is  such  that  a  b  makes 
with  at  an  angle  smaller  than  this.  A  supposition  is 
here  made  in  terms  of  quantities  which  we  already 
know  and  can  measure.  We  only  suppose  in  addition 
that,  however  small  the  assigned  angle  may  be,  the 
point  b  can  always  be  found ;  and  if  this  is  possible, 
then  in  the  case  in  which  the  assigned  angle  is  ex- 

itremely  small,  the  line   a  b  or  at  (for  they  now  coin- 

|cide)  is  called  a  tangent. 

It  is  worth  while  to  observe  the  likeness  between 

[this  definition  and  the  one  that  we  previously  discussed 


248       THE    COMMON    SENSE    OF    THE    EXACT    SCIENCES. 

of  the  fourth  proportional  or  of  the  equality  of  ratio. 
In  that  definition  we  supposed  that,  a  certain  fraction 
being  assigned,  if  the  first  ratio  were  greater  than  this 
fraction,  so  also  was  the  second  ratio,  and  if  less,  less ; 
and  the  question  whether  these  ratios  were  greater  or  less 
is  one  that  can  be  settled  by  measurement  and  com 
parison.  We  then  made  the  further  supposition  that 
whatever  fraction  were  assigned  the  same  result  would 
hold  good ;  and  we  said  that  in  that  ca.se  the  ratios 
were  equal.  Now  in  both  of  these  definitions,  applying 
respectively  to  tangents  and  to  ratios,  the  difficulty  is 
that  we  cause  a  particular  supposition  to  be  extended 
so  as  to  be  general ;  for  we  assume  that  a  statement 
which  can  be  very  easily  tested  and  found  true  in  any 
one  case  is  true  in  an  infinite  number  of  cases  in  which 
it  has  not  been  tested.  But  although  the  test  cannot 
be  applied  individually  to  all  these  cases  in  a  practical 
way,  yet,  since  it  is  true  in  any  individual  case,  we  know 
on  rational  grounds  that  it  must  be  satisfied  in  general ; 
and  therefore,  justified  by  this  knowledge,  we  are  able 
to  reason  generally  about  the  equality  of  ratios  and 
about  the  tangents  to  curves. 

Let  us  now  translate  the  definition  at  which  we 
have  thus  arrived  from  the  language  of  curves  and  tan 
gents  into  the  language  of  instantaneous  and  mean 
velocities.  The  steepness  of  the  chord  of  the  curve  of 
positions  indicates  the  mean  velocity,  while  the  steep 
ness  of  the  tangent  to  the  curve  at  any  point  indicates 
the  instantaneous  velocity  at  that  point.  The  process 
of  making  the  point  b  move  nearer  and  nearer  to  the 
point  a  corresponds  to  taking  for  consideration  a 
smaller  and  smaller  interval  of  time  after  that  moment 
at  which  the  instantaneous  velocity  is  wanted. 

Suppose,  then,  the  velocity  of  a  body,  viz.  a  railway 


MOTION.  249 

train,  to  be  varying,  and  that  we  want  to  find  what  its  value 
is  at  a  given  instant.  We  might  get  a  very  rough  approxi 
mation  to  it,  or  in  some  cases  no  approximation  at  all,  by 
taking  the  mean  velocity  during  the  hour  which  follows 
that  instant.  We  should  get  a  closer  approximation  by 
taking  the  mean  velocity  during  the  minute  succeeding 
that  instant,  because  the  instantaneous  velocity  would 
have  less  time  to  change.  A  still  closer  approximation 
would  be  obtained  were  we  to  take  the  mean  velocity 
during  the  succeeding  second.  In  all  motions  we  should 
have  to  consider  that  we  could  make  the  approximation 
as  close  as  we  like  by  taking  a  sufficiently  small  interval. 
That  is  to  say,  if  we  choose  to  name  any  very  small 
velocity,  such  as  one  with  which  a  body  going  uniformly 
would  move  only  an  inch  in  a  century,  then,  by  taking 
the  interval  small  enough,  it  will  be  possible  to  make  the 
mean  velocity  differ  from  the  instantaneous  velocity  by 
less  than  this  amount.  Thus,  finally,  we  shall  have  the 
following  definition  of  instantaneous  velocity  :  If  there  is 
a  certain  velocity  to  which  the  mean  velocity  during  the 
interval  succeeding  a  given  instant  can  be  made  to 
ipproach  as  near  as  we  like  by  taking  the  interval  small 
enough,  then  that  velocity  is  called  the  instantaneous 
velocity  of  the  body  at  the  given  instant. 

In  this  way  then  we  have  reduced  the  problem  of 
inding  the  velocity  of  a  moving  body  at  any  instant  to 
;he  problem  of  drawing  a  tangent  to  its  curve  of  posi- 
ions  at  the  corresponding  point ;  and  what  we  have 
ilready  proved  amounts  to  saying  that,  if  the  position  of 
:he  body  be  given  in  terms  of  the  time  by  means  of  a 
3urve,  then  the  velocity  of  the  body  will  be  given  in 
erms  of  the  time  by  means  of  the  tangent  to  this  curve. 

Now  there  are  many  curves  to  which  we  can  draw 
.an gents  by  simple  geometrical  methods,  as,  for  example, 


250      THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

to  the  ellipse  and  the  parabola ;  so  that,  whenever  the 
curve  of  positions  of  a  body  happens  to  be  one  of  these, 
we  are  able  to  find  by  geometrical  construction  the 
velocity  of  the  body  at  any  instant.  Thus  in  the  case 
of  a  falling  body  the  curve  of  positions  is  a  parabola, 
and  we  might  find  by  the  known  properties  of  the  tan 
gent  to  a  parabola  that  the  velocity  in  this  case  is  pro 
portional  to  the  time.  But  in  the  great  majority  of 
cases  the  problem  of  drawing  a  tangent  to  the  curve 
of  positions  is  just  as  difficult  as  the  original  problem 
of  determining  the  velocity  of  a  moving  body,  and  in 
fact  we  do  in  many  cases  solve  the  former  by  means  of 
the  latter.1 

§  6.  On  the  Determination  of  Variable  Velocity. 

What  is  actually  wanted  in  every  case  will  be 
apparent  from  the  consideration  of  the  problem  we 
have  just  mentioned — that  of  a  body  falling  down 
straight.  We  note,  from  the  experience  of  Galilei,  that 
the  whole  distance  which  the  body  has  fallen  from  rest 
at  any  instant  is  proportional  to  the  square  of  the  time  ; 
in  fact,  to  obtain  this  distance  in  feet  we  must  multiply 
the  number  of  seconds  by  itself  and  the  result  by  a 
number  a  little  greater  than  sixteen.  Thus,  for  instance, 
in  five  seconds  the  body  will  have  fallen  rather  more 
than  twenty-five  times  sixteen  feet,  or  400  feet.  Now 
what  we  want  is  some  direct  process  of  proving  that 
when  the  distance  traversed  is  proportional  to  the  square 
of  the  time  the  velocity  is  always  proportional  to  the 
time.  In  the  present  case  we  can  find  the  velocity  at 
the  end  of  a  given  number  of  seconds  by  multiplying 
that  number  by  thirty-two  feet ;  thus  at  the  end  of  five 
seconds  the  velocity  of  the  body  will  be  160  feet  per 

1  [The  method  is  due  to  Eobcrval  (1602-1675).— K.  P.] 


MOTION.  2-51 

second.1  Now  as  a  matter  of  fact  a  process  (of  winch 
there  is  a  simple  example  in  the  footnote)  has  been 
worked  out,  by  which  from  any  algebraical  rule  telling 
us  how  to  calculate  the  distance  traversed  iu  terms  of 
the  time  we  can  find  another  algebraical  rule  which 
will  tell  us  how  to  calculate  the  velocity  in  terms  of  the 
time.  One  case  of  the  process  is  this  :  If  the  distance 
traversed  is  at  any  instant  a  times  the  nth  power  of  the 
time,  then  the  velocity  at  any  instant  will  be  na  times 

1  The  following  may  be  taken  as  a  proof.  Let  a  lie  the  distance  from 
rest  moved  over  by  the  body  in  t'  seconds,  b  that  moved  over  l>y  it.  in  t  ~  t' 
seconds,  so  that  t'  seconds  is  the  interval  we  take  to  find  out  the  mean 
velocity.  Now  by  our  rule  just  quoted,  since  a  feet  are  passed  over  in  t 
seconds,  we  have 


and  similarly  b=  I6(t  +  O2=  1G  (t"  +  W  +  1'-*). 

Hence  \ve  have  b  —  a  =  \G(t-  +  2tC  +  t"-}-  IGt- 


giving  the  distance  moved  over  in  the  interval  H  .     But  the  mean  velocity 
during  this  interval  is  obtained  by  dividing  the  distance  moved  over  by  the 
time   taken   to  traverse   it;  hence  the  mean  velocity  in  our  ease  for  the 
interval  of  t'  seconds  immediately  succeeding  the  t  seconds 
=  b-a 
t' 


t' 

i!  + 
=  32t  +16C. 

Now  if  we  look  at  this  result,  which  we  have  obtained  for  the  mean  velocity, 
we  see  that  there  are  two  terms  in  it.  The  first,  viz.  3'2f.  is  quite  hide- 
^•pendent  of  the  interval  t'  which  we  have'taken  ;  the  second,  vix  lf>/',  depends 
^directly  on  it,  and  will  therefore  change  when  we  change  t  he  interval.  Now 
..—-he  distance  per  second  represented  by  IGf  feet  can  be  made  as  small  as 
we  like  by  taking  t'  small  enough  ;  so  that  the  mean  velocity  during  the 
.^•interval  t'  seconds  succeeding  the  given  instant  can  be  made  to  approach 
;.-,  ^32)'  feet  per  second  as  near  as  we  like  by  taking  t'  small  enough.  Recurring 
our  definition  of  instantaneous  velocity,  it  is  now  evident  that  the  instan- 
velocity  of  our  falling  body  at  the  end  of  t  seconds  is  Z'lt  feet  per 
'ond. 


252      THE   COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

the  (w-i)tli  power  of  the  time.  It  is  by  means  of  this 
process  of  altering  one  algebraical  rule  so  as  to  get 
another  from  it  that  both  of  the  problems  which  we 
have  shown  to  be  equivalent  to  one  another  are  s 

in  practice. 

There  is  yet  another  problem  of  very  great  import 
ance  in  the  study  of  natural  phenomena  which  can  be 
made  to  depend  on  these  two.  When  a  point  moves 
alono-  a  straight  line  the  distance  of  it  from  some  fixed 
point  in  the  line  is  a  quantity  which  varies  from  time 
to  time.  The  rate  of  change  of  this  distance  is  the 
same  thing  as  the  velocity  of  the  moving  point;  and 
the  rate  of  change  of  any  continuous  quantity  can  only 
be  properly  represented  by  means  of  the  velocity  of  a 

point. 

Thus,  for  instance,  the  height  of  the  tide  at  a  given 
port  will  vary  from  time  to  time  during  the  day,  and  it 
may  be  indicated  by  a  mark  which  goes  up  and  down 
on  a  stick.     The  rate  at  which  the  height  of  the  tide 
varies  will  obviously  be  the  same  thing  as  the  velocity 
with  which  this  mark  goes  up  and  down.     Again  the 
pressure  of  the  atmosphere  is  indicated  by  means  of  the 
height  of  a  mercury  barometer.     The  rate  at  which  this 
pressure  changes  is  obviously  the  same  thing  as  the  velo- 
citv  with  which  the  surface  of  the  mercury  moves  up  am 
down.     Now  whenever  we  want  to  describe  the  changes 
which  take  place  in  any  quantity  in  terms  of  the  time, 
we  may  indeed  roughly  and  approximately   do  so   by 
means  of  a  table.   But  this  is  also  the  most  troublesome 
way ;  the  proper  way  of  describing  them  is  by  drawing 
a  curve  in  which  the  abscissa,  or  horizontal  distance,  at 
any  point  represents  the  time,  while  the  height  of  1 
curve  at  that  point  represents  the  value  of  the  quantity 
at  that  time  (see  p.  184).     Whenever  this  is  done  we 


MOTION.  253 

practically  suppose  the  variation  of  the  quantity  to  be 
represented  by  the  motion  of  the  point  on  a  curve. 
The  quantity  can  only  be  adequately  represented  by 
marking  ofT  a  length  proportional  to  it  on  a  line  ;  so 
that  if  the  quantity  varies  then  the  length  marked  off 
will  vary,  and  consequently  the  end  of  this  length  will 
move  along  the  curve.  The  rate  at  which  the  quantity 
varies  is  the  rate  at  which  this  point  moves  ;  and  when 
the  values  of  the  quantity  for  different  times  are  repre 
sented  by  the  perpendicular  distances  of  points  on  a 
curve  from  the  line  which  represents  the  time,  its  rate 
of  variation  is  determined  by  the  tangent  to  tliat 
curve. 

§  7.  On  tlie  Method  of  Fluxions. 

Hence  we  have  three  problems  which  are  practically 
the  same.  First,  to  find  the  velocity  of  a  moving  point 
when  we  know  where  it  is  at  every  instant ;  secondly,  to 
draw  a  tangent  to  a  curve  at  any  point ;  thirdly,  to  find 
the  rate  of  change  of  a  quantity  when  we  know  how  great 
it  is  at  every  instant.  And  the  solution  of  them  all 
depends  upon  that  process  by  which,  when  we  take  the 
algebraical  rule  for  finding  the  quantity  in  terms  of  the 
time,  we  deduce  from  it  another  rule  for  finding  its 
rate  of  change  in  terms  of  the  time. 

This  particular  process  of  deriving  one  algebraical 
rule  from  another  was  first  investigated  by  Newton. 
He  was  accustomed  to  describe  a  varying  quantity  as 
a  fluent,  and  its  rate  of  change  he  called  the  fluxion  of 
the  quantity.  On  account  of  these  names,  the  entire 
method  of  solving  these  problems  by  means  of  the 
process  of  deriving  one  algebraical  rule  from  another 
was  termed  the  Method  of  Fluxions. 

In  general  the  rate  of  variation  of  a  quantity  will 


254      THE   COMMON    SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

itself  change  from  time  to  time;  but  if  we  consider 
only  an  interval  very  small  as  compared  with  that  re 
quired  for  a  considerable  variation  of  the  quantity,  we 
may  legitimately  suppose  that  it  has  not  altered  much 
during  that  interval.  This  is  practically  equivalent  to 
supposing  that  the  law  of  change  has  been  uniformly 
true  during  that  interval,  and  that  the  rate  of  change 
does  not  differ  very  much  from  its  mean  value.  Now 
the  mean  rate  of  change  of  a  quantity  during  an  interval 
of  time  is  just  the  difference  between  the  values  of  the 
quantity  at  the  beginning  and  at  the  end  divided  by 
the  interval.  If  any  quantity  increased  by  one  inch  in 
a  second,  then,  although  it  may  not  have  been  increas 
ing  uniformly,  or  even  been  increasing  at  all  during  the 
whole  of  that  second,  yet  during  the  second  its  mean 
rate  of  increase  was  one  inch  per  second.  Now  if  the 
rate  of  increase  only  changes  slowly  we  may,  as  an 
approximation,  fairly  suppose  it  to  be  constant  during 
the  second,  and  therefore  to  be  equal  to  the  mean  rate ; 
and,  as  we  know,  the  smaller  the  interval  of  time  is,  the 
less  is  the  error  arising  from  this  supposition.  This  is, 
as  a  matter  of  fact,  the  way  in  which  that  process  is 
established  by  means  of  which  a  rule  for  calculating 
position  is  altered  into  a  rule  for  calculating  velocity. 
The  difference  between  the  distances  of  the  moving 
point  from  some  fixed  point  on  the  line  at  two  different 
times  is  divided  by  the  interval  between  the  times,  and 
this  gives  the  mean  rate  of  change  during  that  interval. 
If  we  find  that,  by  making  the  interval  smaller  and 
smaller,  this  mean  rate  of  change  gets  nearer  and 
nearer  to  a  certain  value,  then  we  conclude  that  this 
value  is  the  actual  rate  of  change  when  we  suppose  the 
interval  to  shrink  up  into  an  instant,  or  that  it  is,  as 
we  call  it,  the  instantaneous  rate  of  change. 


MOTION.  255 

Because  two  differences  are  used  in  the  argument 
which  establishes  the  process  for  changing  the  one  rule 
into  the  other,  this  process  was  called,  first  in  other 
countries  and  then  also  in  England,  the  Differential 
Calculus.  The  name  is  an  unfortunate  one,  because  the 
rate  of  change  which  is  therein  calculated  has  nothing 
bo  do  with  differences,  the  only  connection  with 
differences  being  that  they  are  mentioned  in  the  argu 
ment  which  is  used  to  establish  the  process.  However 
bhis  may  be,  the  object  of  the  differential  calculus  or  of 
the  method  of  fluxions  (whichever  name  we  choose  to 
»ive  it)  is  to  find  a  rule  for  calculating  the  rate  of 
change  of  a  quantity  when  we  have  a  rule  for  calcu 
lating  the  quantity  itself;  and  we  have  seen  that  when 
bhis  can  be  done  the  problem  of  drawing  a  tangent  to 
a  curve  and  that  of  finding  the  velocity  of  a  moving 
point  are  also  solved. 

§  8.   Of  the  Relationship  of  Quantities,  or  Function*. 

But  we  not  only  have  rules  for  calculating  the  value 
of  a  quantity  at  any  time,  but  also  rules  for  calculating 
the  value  of  one  quantity  in  terms  of  another  quite  in 
dependently  of  the  time.  Of  the  former  class  of  rules  an 
example  is  the  one  mentioned  above  for  calculating  the 
rise  of  the  tide.  We  may  either  write  down  a  formula 
which  will  enable  us  to  calculate  it  at  a  given  instant, 
or  we  may  draw  a  curve  which  shall  represent  its  rise 
at  different  times  of  the  day.  Of  the  second  kind  of 
rule  a  good  example  is  that  in  which  the  pressure  of  a 
given  quantity  of  gas  is  given  in  terms  of  its  volume 
when  the  temperature  is  supposed  to  be  constant;  the 
algebraical  statement  of  the  rule  giving  the  relation 
between  them  is  that  the  two  things  vary  inversely  as 
one  another,  or  that  the  product  representing  them  is 


256      THE    COMMON   SENSE    OP   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

constant.  Thus  if  we  compress  a  mass  of  air  to  one- 
half  of  its  natural  volume  the  pressure  will  become  twice 
as  great,  or  will  be,  as  it  is  called,  two  '  atmospheres.' 
And  so  if  we  compress  it  to  one-fifth  of  the  volume  the 
pressure  will  become  five  times  as  great,  or  five  atmo 
spheres. 

If  we  like  to  represent  this  by  a  figure  we  shall 
draw  a  curve  in  which  the  abscissa,  or  horizontal 
distance  from  the  starting  point,  will  represent  the 
volume,  and  a  vertical  line  drawn  through  the  extremity 
of  this  abscissa  will  represent  the  pressure.  For  any 
particular  temperature  the  curve  traced  out  by  the  ex 
tremity  of  the  line  representing  the  pressure  will  be 
a  hyperbola  having  one  asymptote  vertical  and  the 
other  horizontal;  and  lor  different  temperatures  we 
shall  have  different  hyperbolas  with  the  same  asym 
ptotes.  Thus  every  point  in  the  plane  will  represent  a 
particular  state  of  the  body,  since  some  hyperbola  can 
be  drawn  through  it ;  the  horizontal  distance  of  the 
point  from  the  origin  will  represent  the  volume,  and  its 
vertical  distance  the  pressure,  while  the  particular 
hyperbola  on  which  it  lies  will  indicate  the  tempera 
ture.  We  have  here  an  example  of  the  physical  im 
portance  of  a  family  of  curves,  to  which  reference  was 
made  in  the  preceding  chapter  (see  p.  163). 

When  the  connection  between  two  quantities  has 
to  be  found  out  by  actual  observation,  this  is  done  by 
properly  plotting  down  points  on  paper  (as  in  §  11, 
Chap.  IV.)  to  represent  successive  observations.  Thus 
in  the  case  of  air  the  pressure  would  be  observed  for 
different  values  of  the  volume.  For  each  of  these 
observed  pairs  of  values  a  point  would  be  marked  in 
the  plane ;  and  when  a  sufficient  number  had  been 
marked  it  would  become  obvious  to  the  eye  that, 


MOTION  207 

roughly  speaking,  the  point  lay  on  a  hyperbolic  curve. 
But  it  is  to  be  noticed  that  it  is  only  roughly  that  this 
result  holds,  because  observations  are  never  so  accu- 
•ate  that  the  curve  does  not  require  to  be  drawn  pretty 
reely  in  passing  through  the  points.  But  directly  the 
geometer  has  seen  that  the  shape  of  the  curve  is  hyper- 
)olic  he  recognises  the  law  that  pressure  varies  inversely 
as  volume. 

We  have  here  the  relation  between  two  quantities 
sxpressed  by  means  of  a  curve.     Whenever  two  quanti- 
ies  are  related  in  some  such  way,  so  that  one  of  them 
>eing  given  the  other  can  be  calculated  or  found,  each 
s  said  to  be  a  function  of  the  other.     Now  a  function 
may  be  supposed  to  be  given  either  by  an  algebraical 
rule  or  by  a  curve.     Thus  to  find  the  pressure  corre 
sponding  to  a  given  volume  we  might  say  that  a  certain 
number  was  to  be  divided  by  the  number  representing 
volume,  and  the  result  would  be  the  number  of  units 
)f  pressure  ;  or  we  might  say  that  from  the  given  point 
f  the  horizontal  line  which  represented  the  volume  a 
>erpendicular  was  to  be  drawn  and  continued  till  it  met 
lie  curve,  and  that  the  ordinate  (or  the  part  of  this 
)etween  the  horizontal  line  and  the  curve)  represented 
jthe  pressure.     We  have  thus  a  connection  established 
>etweeii  the  science  of  geometry  and  the    science  of 
quantity,  as,  for  example,  the  relation  between  the  two 
[uantities,  volume  and  pressure,  is  expressed  by  means 
f  a  certain  curve. 

Now  every  connection  between  two  sciences  is  a 
ielp  to  both  of  them.  When  such  a  connection  is 
;:stablished  we  may  both  use  the  known  theorems 
«-bout  quantities  in  order  to  investigate  the  nature  of 
urves  (and  this  is,  in  fact,  the  method  of  co-ordinates 
troduced  by  Descartes),  or  we  may  make  use  of 

s 


258      THE   COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

known  geometrical  properties  of  curves  in  order  to 
find  out  theorems  about  the  way  in  which  quantities 
depend  upon  one  another.  For  the  first  purpose  the 
\  relation  between  the  two  quantities  is  regarded  as  an 
equation.  Thus,  instead  of  saying  that  a  pressure 
varies  inversely  as  a  volume  we  should  prefer  to  say 
that  the  product  of  the  pressure  and  the  volume  is 
equal  to  a  certain  constant,  the  temperature  being 
supposed  unaltered;  or,  paying  attention  only  to  the 
geometrical  way  of  expressing  this,  we  should  say  that, 
for  points  along  the  curve  we  are  considering,  the 
product  of  the  abscissa  and  the  ordinate  is  equal  to  a 
certain  fixed  quantity.  This  is  written  for  shortness 


and  from  such  an  equation  all  the  properties  of  a  hyper 
bola  may  be  deduced. 

But  we  may  also  make  use  of  the  properties  o 
known  curves  in  order  to  study  the  ways  in  whicl 
quantities  can  depend  on  one  another.  Thus  the  per 


FIG.  97. 

pendicular  distance  P  H  from  the  point  P  of  the  circld 
to  a  fixed  diameter  A  0  a  is  a  quantity  whose  ratio  ix 
the  radius  OP  depends  in  a  certain  definite  way  upoi 
the  magnitude  of  the  angle  POA,  or,  what  is  the  samr 
thing  (p.  143),  upon  the  length  of  the  arc  A  P.  Therati* 
is  in  fact  what  we  have  termed  the  sine  of  the  angle,  or 


MOTION.  259 

as  it  is  sometimes  called,  the  sine  of  the  arc.  If  the  arc 
AP  is  made  proportional  to  the  time,  or,  what  is  the 
same  thing,  if  P  is  made  to  move  uniformly  round  the 
circle,  then  the  length  of  the  line  PM  will  represent 
the  distance  from  the  centre  0  of  a  point  Q  oscillating 
according  to  a  law  which  is  defined  by  this  geometrical 
construction.  This  particular  kind  of  oscillation,  which 
is  called  simple  harmonic  motion,  occurs  when  the  air 
is  agitated  by  sound,  or  the  ether  by  light,  or  when 
any  elastic  body  is  set  into  a  tremor.  Relations  such 
as  that  which  we  have  just  mentioned  between  arcs  of 
a  circle  and  straight  lines  drawn  according  to  some 
simple  constructions  in  the  circle  give  rise  to  what  are 
often  termed  circular  functions.  Thus  the  trigono 
metrical  ratios  considered  in  §  7  of  Chapter  IV.  art 
functions  of  this  kind.  We  have  also  hyperbolic  func 
tions,  depending  on  the  hyperbola  in  somewhat  the 
same  way  in  which  circular  functions  depend  upon  the 
circle,  and  elliptic  functions,  so  called  because  by  means 
of  them  the  length  of  the  arc  of  an  ellipse  can  be  cal 
culated. 

But  the  most  valuable  method  of  studying  the 
properties  of  functions  is  derived  from  the  considera 
tions  of  which  we  have  been  treating  in  this  chapter, 
/iz.  considerations  of  the  rate  of  change  of  quantities. 
,Whenthe  relation  between  two  quantities  is  known,  the 
•elation  between  their  rates  of  change  can  be  found  by 
i  known  algebraical  process ;  and  we  have  shown  that 
e  problem  of  finding  this  relation  ultimately  comes 
o  the  same  thing  as  the  problem  of  drawing  a  tangent 
.r,j|o  the  curve  which  expresses  the  relation  between  the 
o  original  quantities.  Thus,  in  the  case  we  pre- 
'usly  considered  of  two  quantities  whose  product  is 
nstant  or  which  vary  inversely  as  one  another,  it  is 

s  2 


260      THE   COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

clear  that  one  must  increase  when  the  other  decreases  ; 
it  is  found  that  the  ratio  of  these  rates  of  change 
is  equal  to  the  ratio  of  the  quantities  themselves. 
Thus  the  rate  of  change  of  the  volume  of  a  gas  is 
to  the  rate  of  change  of  the  pressure  (the  temperature 
being  kept  constant)  as  the  volume  is  to  the  pres 
sure,  it  being  always  remembered  that  an  increase  of 
the  one  implies  a  decrease  of  the  other. 

The  consideration  of  this  ratio  of  the  rates  of  change 
is  of  great  importance  in  determining  one  of  the  fun 
damental  changeable  properties  of  a  body,  namely,  its 
elasticity.     We   define  the   elasticity  of  a  gas  as  the 
change  of  pressure  which  will  produce  a  given  contrac 
tion  ;  where  by  the  term  contraction  is  meant  the  change 
in  the  volume  divided  by  the  whole  volume  before  change. 
Thus  if  the  volume  of  a  gas  diminished  one  per  cent.,  it 
would  experience  a  contraction  of  y^^th.     If  then,  in 
accordance  with  our  definition,  we  divide  the  pressure  ; 
necessary  to  produce  this  contraction  by  y^-,  or,  what  i 
is  the  same  thing,  multiply  it  by  100,  we  shall   gel;; 
what  is  called  the  elasticity.  Now  in  our  case  the  change  c 
of  pressure  divided  by  the  whole  pressure  is  equal  to  what fl 
we  have  called  the  contraction,  that  is,   to  y^-;  anc  : 
therefore  the  change  of  pressure  is  equal  to  y^th  of  the  :. 
whole  pressure.    But  we  have  just  proved  that  the  elas-  n 
ticity  is  100  times  the  change  of  pressure  necessary  to  - 
produce  the  contraction  we  have  been  considering,  and  i  - 
is  therefore  equal  to  the  whole  pressure.    Consequent!;  [• 
the  elasticity  of  a  gas  is  measured  by  the  pressure  o'l  e: 
the  gas. 

§  9.  Of  Acceleration  and  the  Hodograph. 

We  may  then  consider  the  rate  of  change  of  an 
measurable  quantity  as  another  quantity  which  we  ca  £  - 


MOTION.  261 

find ;  and  we  have  derived  our  notion  of  it  from  the 
velocity  of  a  moving  point.  In  the  simplest  case, 
when  this  point  is  moving  along  a  straight  line,  the 
rate  at  which  it  is  going  is  the  rate  of  change  of 
its  distance  from  a  point  fixed  in  the  line.  But  in 
the  general  case,  when  the  point  is  moving  not  on  a 
straight  line,  but  along  any  sort  of  curve,  we  shall  not 
give  a  complete  description  of  its  state  of  motion  if  we 
only  say  how  fast  it  is  going;  it  will  be  necessary  to 
say  in  addition  in  what  direction  it  is  going.  Hence 
we  must  not  only  measure  the  quantity  of  a  velocity, 
but  also  a  certain  quality  of  it,  viz.  the  direction. 
Now  we  do  as  a  matter  of  fact  contrive  to  study  these 
two  things  together,  and  the  method  by  which  we  do  so 
is  perhaps  one  of  the  most  powerful  instruments  by 
which  the  scope  of  the  exact  sciences  has  been  extended 
in  recent  times.  Defining  the  velocity  of  a  moving 
point  as  the  rate  of  change  of  its  position,  we  are  met 
\>y  the  question,  What  is  its  position'? 

This  question  has  been  answered  in  the  preceding 
chapter.  The  position  of  a  moving  point  is  determined 
when  we  know  the  directed  step  or  vector  which  con 
nects  it  with  a  fixed  point.  If  then  the  velocity  of  the 
moving  point  means  the  rate  of  change  of  its  position, 
and  if  this  position  is  determined  by  the  vector  which 
would  carry  us  from  some  fixed  point  to  the  moving- 
point,  in  order  to  understand  velocity  we  shall  have  to 
get  a  clear  conception  of  Avhat  is  meant  by  the  rate  of 
change  of  a  vector. 


A 

FIG.  98. 


Let  us  <ro  bank  for  a  moment  to  the  simpler  case  of 
a  point  moving  along  a  straight  line  ;  its  position   is 


262       THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF    THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

determined  by  means  of  the  step  A  P  from  the  point  A 
fixed  in  the  straight  line  to  the  moving  point  P.  Now 
this  step  alters  with  the  motion  of  the  point ;  so  that 
if  the  point  comes  to  P'  the  step  is  changed  from  A  P 
to  A  P'.  How  is  this  change  made  in  the  step  ? 
Clearly  by  adding  to  the  original  step  A  P  the  new 
step  P  P',  and  we  specify  the  velocity  of  P  by  saying 
at  what  rate  this  addition  is  made. 

Now  let  us  resume  the  general  case.  We  have  the 
fixed  point  A  given  ;  and  the  position  of  the  moving 
point  P  is  determined  by  means  of  the  step  A  P.  As 
P  moves  about,  this  step  gets  altered,  so  that  when 
P  comes  to  P'  this  step  is  A  P' ;  it  is  therefore  obvious 
that  it  is  altered  not  only  in  magnitude  but  also  in 
direction.  Now  the  change  may  be  made  by  adding 
to  the  original  step  A  P  the  new  step  P  P' ;  and  it  is 
quite  clear  that  if  we  go  from  A  to  P  and  then  from 
P  to  P'  the  result  is  exactly  the  same  as  if  we  had  gone 


FIG.  99. 

directly  from  A  to  P'.  The  question  then  is  :  At  what 
rate  does  this  addition  take  place,  or  what  step  per 
second  is  added  to  the  position?  The  answer  as  before 
is  of  the  nature  of  a  step  or  vector — that  is,  the 
change  of  position  of  the  moving  point  has  not  only 
magnitude  but  direction.  We  shall  therefore  have 
to  say  that  the  rate  of  change  of  a  step  or  vector  is 
always  so  many  feet  per  second  in  a  certain  direction. 
To  sum  up,  then,  we  state  that  the  velocity  of  a 


MOTION.  263 

moving  point  is  the  rate  of  change  of  the  step  which 
specifies  the  position ;  and  that  in  order  to  describe 
accurately  this  velocity,  we  must  draw  a  line  of  given 
length  in  a  given  direction ;  we  observe  also  that 
the  rate  of  change  of  a  directed  quantity  is  itself  a 
directed  quantity.  This  last  remark  is  of  the  utmost 
importance,  and  we  shall  now  apply  it  to  a  considera 
tion  of  the  velocity  itself. 

If  a  point  is  moving  uniformly  in  a  straight  line  its 
velocity  is  always  the  same  in  magnitude  and  the  same 
in  direction  ;  and  consequently  a  line  drawn  to  re 
present  it  would  be  unaltered  during  the  motion.  But 
if  a  point  moves  uniformly  round  a  circle  its  velocity, 
although  always  the  same  in  magnitude,  will  be  con 
stantly  changing  in  direction,  and  the  line  which 
specifies  this  velocity  will  thus  be  always  of  the  same 
length,  but  constantly  turning  round  so  as  always 
to  keep  parallel  with  the  direction  of  motion  of  the 
moving  point.  And  so,  generally,  when  a  point  is 
moving  along  any  kind  of  curve  let  us  suppose  that 
through  some  other  point,  which  is  kept  fixed,  a  line  is 
always  drawn  which  represents  the  velocity  of  the 
moving  point  both  in  magnitude  and  direction.  Since 
the  velocity  of  the  moving  point  will  in  general  change, 
this  line  will  also  change  both  in  size  and  in  direction, 
and  the  end  of  it  will  trace  out  some  sort  of  curve. 
Thus  in  the  case  of  the  uniform  circular  motion,  since 
the  velocity  remains  constant,  it  is  clear  that  the  end 
of  the  line  representing  the  velocity  will  trace  out  a 
circle  ;  in  the  case  of  a  body  thrown  into  the  air  the 
end  of  the  corresponding  line  would  be  found  to  de 
scribe  a  vertical  straight  line.  This  curve  described 
by  the  end  of  the  line  which  represents  the  velocity  at 
any  instant  may  be  regarded  as  a  map  of  the  motion, 


264      THE    COMMON   SENSE   OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

and  was  for  that  reason  called  by  Hamilton  the 
hodograph.  If  we  know  the  path  of  the  moving  point 
and  also  the  hodograph  of  the  motion,  we  can  find  the 
velocity  of  the  moving  point  at  any  particular  position 
in  its  path.  All  we  have  to  do  is  to  draw  through  the 
centre  of  reference  of  the  hodograph  a  line  parallel  to 
the  tangent  to  the  path  at  the  given  position ;  the 
length  of  this  line  will  give  the  rate  of  motion,  or  the 
velocity  of  the  point  as  it  passes  through  that  position 
in  its  path.  Hamilton  proved  that  in  the  case  of  the 
planetary  orbits  described  about  the  sun  the  hodo 
graph  is  always  a  circle.  In  this  case  it  possesses 
other  interesting  properties,  as,  for  example,  that  the 
amount  of  light  and  heat  received  by  the  planet  during 
a  given  interval  of  time  is  proportional  to  the  length  of 
the  arc  of  the  hodograph  between  the  two  points  corre 
sponding  to  the  beginning  and  end  of  that  interval. 

But  the  great  use  of  the  hodograph  is  to  give  us  a 
clear  conception  of  the  rate  of  change  of  the  velocity. 
This  rate  of  change  is  called  the  acceleration.  Now,  it 
must  not  be  supposed  that  acceleration  always  means 
an  increase  of  velocity,  for  in  this  case,  as  in  many 
others,  mathematicians  have  adopted  for  use  one  word 
to  denote  a  change  that  may  have  many  directions ; 
thus  a  decrease  of  velocity  is  called  a  negative  accelera 
tion.  This  mode  of  speaking,  although  rather  puzzling 
at  first,  becomes  a  help  instead  of  a  confusion  when 
one  is  accustomed  to  it.  Now  a  velocity  may  be 
changed  in  magnitude  without  altering  its  direction — 
that  is  to  say,  it  may  be  changed  by  adding  it  to  a 
velocity  parallel  to  itself.  In  this  case  we  say  that  the 
acceleration  is  in  the  direction  of  motion.  But  a 
velocity  may  also  be  changed  in  direction  without  being 
changed  in  magnitude,  and  we  have  seen  that  then  the 


MOTION.  205 

hodograph  is  a  circle.  The  velocity  is  altered  by 
adding  to  it  a  velocity  perpendicular  to  itself,  for  the 
tangent  at  any  point  to  a  circle  is  at  right  angles  to 
the  radius  drawn  to  that  point,  and  in  this  case  we 
may  say  that  the  acceleration  is  at  right  angles  to  the 
direction  of  motion.  But  in  general  both  the  magni 
tude  and  the  direction  of  the  velocity  will  vary,  and  then 
we  shall  see  that  the  acceleration  is  neither  in  the 
direction  of  motion  nor  at  right  angles  to  it,  but  that 
it  is  in  some  intermediate  direction. 

If  we  consider  the  motion  in  the  hodograph  of  the 
end  of  the  line  representing  the  velocity,  we  observe  the 
motion  of  a  point  whose  position  is  defined  by  the  step 
to  it  from  the  centre  of  the  hodograph.  N  >w  this  step 
is  just  the  velocity  of  the  point  P  in  the  original  curve, 
for  the  line  0  Q,  is  supposed  to  be  drawn  at  every  instant 


FIG.  100. 

to  represent  the  velocity  of  P  in  magnitude  and  direc 
tion.     Now  we  saw  that  the  rate  of  change  of  the  step 
from  some  fixed  point  A  to  P  was  the  velocity  of  P. 
BtHence,  since  the  step  OQ  drawn  from  the  fixed  point 
I  '0  to  Q  defines  the  position  of  Q,  it  is  obvious  that  the 
I  rate  of  change  of  the  step  0  Q  is  the  velocity  of  Q.    Since 
B'O  Q  represents  the  velocity  of  P,  it  follows  that  the  velo 
city  of  the  point  Q  describing  the  hodograph  is  the  rate 
of  change  of  the  velocity  of  P ;  that  is  to  say,  it  is  the 
acceleration  of  the  motion  of   P.      This  acceleration 


2G6      THE    COMMON    SENSE    OF   THE    EXACT   SCIENCES. 

being  the  velocity  of  Q,  and  a  velocity  being  as  we  have 
seen  a  vector,  it  at  once  follows  that  the  acceleration 
is  a  vector  or  directed  quantity. 

In  changing  the  magnitude  and  direction  of  the 
velocity  of  a  moving  point  we  may  consider  that  we  are 
pouring  in,  as  it  were,  velocity  of  a  certain  kind  at  a 
certain  rate.  In  the  case  of  a  stone  thrown  up 
obliquely  and  allowed  to  fall  again  the  path  described 
is  a  parabola,  and  the  direction  of  motion,  which  ori 
ginally  pointed  obliquely  upwards,  turns  round  and 
becomes  horizontal,  and  then  gradually  points  more 
and  more  downwards.  But  what  has  really  been 
happening  the  whole  time  is  that  velocity  straight 
downwards  has  been  continually  added  at  a  uniform 
rate  during  every  second,  so  that  the  original  velocity 
of  the  stone  is  compounded  with  a  velocity  vertically 
downwards,  increasing  uniformly  at  the  rate  of  thirty- 
two  feet  a  second.  In  this  case,  then,  we  say  that  the 
acceleration,  or  rate  of  change  per  second  of  the  velocity 
of  the  stone,  is  constant  and  equal  to  thirty-two  feet  a 
second  vertically  downwards. 

If  we  whirl  anything  round  at  the  end  of  a  string 
we  shall  be  continually  pouring  in  velocity  directed 
towards  the  end  of  the  string  which  is  held  in  the  hand ; 
and  since  the  velocity  of  the  body  which  is  being 
whirled  is  perpendicular  to  the  direction  of  the  string, 
the  added  velocity  is  always  perpendicular  to  the  exist 
ing  velocity  of  the  body.  And  so  also  when  a  planet  is 
travelling  round  the  sun  there  is  a  continual  pouring  in 
of  velocity  towards  the  sun,  or,  as  we  say,  the  accelera 
tion  is  always  in  the  line  joining  the  planet  to  the  sun. 
In  addition  it  is  in  this  case  found  to  vary  inversely 
as  the  square  of  the  distance  from  the  sun. 


MOTION.  267 

§  10.  On  the  Laws  of  Motion. 

These  examples  prepare  us  to  understand  that  law 
of  motion  which  is  the  basis  of  all  exact  treatment  of 
physics.  When  a  body  is  moving  let  us  consider  -what 
it  is  that  depends  upon  the  circumstances,  meaning 
by  the  '  circumstances  '  the  instantaneous  position 
relative  to  it  of  other  bodies  as  well  as  the  instantane 
ous  state  of  the  body  itself  irrespective  of  its  motion. 
We  might  at  first  be  inclined  to  say  that  the  velocity 
of  the  body  depends  on  the  circumstances,  but  very 
little  reflection  will  show  us  that  in  the  same  cir 
cumstances  a  body  may  be  moving  with  very  different 
velocities.  At  a  given  height  above  the  earth's  surface, 
for  example,  a  stone  may  be  moving  upwards  or  down 
wards,  or  horizontally,  or  at  any  inclination,  and  in  any 
of  these  modes  with  any  velocity  whatever ;  and  there  is 
nothing  contrary  to  nature  in  supposing  a  motion  of  this 
sort.  Yet  we  should  find  that,  no  matter  in  what  way 
the  stone  may  move  through  a  given  position,  the  rate 
of  change  per  second  of  its  velocity  will  always  be  the 
same,  viz.  it  will  be  thirty-two  feet  per  second  vertically 
downwards.  When  we  push  a  chair  along  the  ice,  in 
order  to  describe  the  circumstances  we  must  state  the 
compression  of  those  muscles  which  keep  our  hands 
against  the  chair.  Now  the  rate  at  which  the  chair 
moves  does  not  depend  simply  upon  this  compression  ; 
'or  a  given  amount  of  push  may  be  either  starting  the 
;,lchair  from  rest  or  may  be  quickening  it  when  it  is 
[going  slowly,  or  may  be  keeping  it  up  at  a  high  rate. 

What  is  it,  then,  Avhich  does  depend  upon  the  cir- 
[sumstances  'P     In  whichever  of  these  ways,  or  in  what- 
sver  other  way  this  given  amount  of  push  is  used,  its 
Result  in  every  case  is  obviously  to  change  the  rate  of 


268      THE   COMMON   SENSE   OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

motion  of  the  chair;  and  this  change  of  the  rate  of 
motion  will  vary  with  the  amount  of  push.  Hence  it  is 
the  rate  of  change  of  the  velocity,  or  the  acceleration  of 
the  chair  which  depends  upon  the  circumstances,  and 
these  circumstances  are  partly  the  compression  of  our 
muscles  and  partly  the  friction  of  the  ice ;  the  one  is 
increasing  and  the  other  is  diminishing  the  velocity  in 
the  direction  in  which  the  chair  is  going. 

The  law  of  motion  to  which  allusion  has  just  been 
made  is  this  : — The  acceleration  of  a  body,  or  the  rate  of 
change  of  its  velocity  depends  at  any  moment  upon  the 
position  relative  to  it  of  the  surrounding  bodies,  but 
not  upon  the  rate  at  which  the  body  itself  is  going. 
There  are  two  different  ways  in  which  this  dependence 
takes  place.  In  some  cases,  as  when  a  hand  is  pushing 
a  chair,  the  rate  of  change  of  the  velocity  depends  on 
the  state  of  compression  of  the  bodies  in  contact ;  in. 
other  cases,  as  in  the  motion  of  the  planets  about  the 
sun,  the  acceleration  depends  on  the  relative  position 
of  bodies  at  a  distance. 

The  acceleration  produced  in  a  body  by  a  particular 
set  of  surrounding  circumstances  must  in  each  case  be 
determined  by  experiment,  but  we  have  learnt  by  ex 
perience  a  general  law  which  much  simplifies  the  expe 
riments  which  it  is  necessary  to  make.  This  law  is  as 
follows  : — If  the  presence  of  one  body  alone  produces  a 
certain  acceleration  in  the  motion  of  a  given  body,  and 
the  presence  of  a  second  body  alone  another  accelera 
tion  ;  then,  if  both  bodies  ai*e  present  at  the  same  time, 
the  one  has  in  general  no  effect  upon  the  acceleration 
produced  by  the  other.  That  is,  the  total  accelera 
tion  of  the  moving  body. will  be  the  combination  of  the 
two  simple  accelerations ;  or,  since  accelerations  are 
directed  quantities,  we  have  only  to  combine  the  simple 


MOTION.  269 

accelerations,  as  we  did  vector  steps  in  §  3  of  the  pre 
ceding  chapter,  in  order  to  find  the  result  of  super 
posing  two  sets  of  surrounding  circumstances. 

Now  while  this  great  law  of  nature  simplifies  ex 
tremely  our  consideration  of  the  motion  of  the  same 
body  under  different  surrounding  circumstances,  it 
does  not  enable  us  to  state  anything  as  to  the  motion 
of  different  bodies  under  the  same  surrounding  circum 
stances.  This  case,  however,  is  amply  provided  for  by 
another  comprehensive  law  which  experience  also  has 
taught  us.  We  may  thus  state  this  third  all-important 
law  of  motion  : — The  ratio  of  the  accelerations  which 
any  two  bodies  produce  in  each  other  by  their  mutual 
influence  is  a  constant  quantity,  quite  independent  of 
the  exact  physical  characteristics  of  that  influence. 
That  is  to  say,  however  the  two  bodies  influence  one 
another,  whether  they  touch  or  are  connected  by  a 
thread  or  being  at  a  distance  still  alter  one  another's 
velocities,  this  ratio  will  remain  in  these  and  all  other 
cases  the  same. 

§  11.  Of  Mass  and  Force. 

Let  us  see  how  we  can  apply  this  law.  Suppose  we 
take  some  standard  body  P  and  any  other  Q,  and  note 
the  ratios  of  the  accelerations  they  produce  in  each 
other  under  any  of  the  simplest  possible  circumstances 
of  mutual  influence.  Let  the  ratio  determined  by  ex 
periment  be  represented  by  ra,  or  ra  expresses  the  ratio  of 
the  acceleration  of  the  standard  body  P  to  that  of  the 
second  body  Q.  This  quantity  m  is  termed  the  mass 
of  the  body  Q.  Let  m-'  be  the  ratio  of  the  accelerations 
produced  in  the  standard  body  P  and  a  third  body  R  by 
their  mutual  influence.  Now  the  law  as  it  stands  above 
enables  us  to  treat  only  of  the  ratio  of  the  accelerations 


270      THE    COMMON   SENSE    OF   THE   EXACT   SCIENCES. 

of  P  and  Q,  or  again  of  P  and  R  under  varied  cir 
cumstances  of  mutual  influence.  It  does  not  tell  us 
anything  about  the  ratio  of  the  accelerations  which  Q, 
and  R  might  produce  in  each  other.  Experience,  how 
ever,  again  helps  us  out  of  our  difficulties  and  tells  us 
that  if  Q  and  R  mutually  influence  each  other,  the 
ratio  of  the  acceleration  of  Q  to  that  of  R  will  he  in 
versely  as  the  ratio  of  m  to  mf.  If  then  we  choose  to 
term  unity  the  mass  of  our  standard  body,  we  may 
state  generally  that  mutual  accelerations  are  inversely  as 
masses.  Hence,  when  we  have  once  determined  the 
masses  of  bodies  we  are  able  to  apply  our  knowledge 
of  the  effect  of  any  set  of  circumstances  on  one  body, 
to  calculate  the  effect  which  the  same  circumstances 
would  produce  upon  any  other  body. 

The  reader  will  remark  that  mass  as  defined  above 
is  a  ratio  of  accelerations,  or  in  other  words  a  mere 
numerical  constant  experimentally  deducible  for  any 
two  bodies.  It  is  found  that  for  two  bodies  of  the  same 
uniform  substance,  their  masses  are  proportional  to 
their  volumes.  This  relation  of  mass  to  volume  has 
given  rise  to  much  obscurity.  An  indescribable  some 
thing  termed  'matter  has  been  associated  with  bodies. 
Bodies  are  supposed  to  consist  of  matter  filling  space, 
and  the  mass  of  a  body  is  defined  as  the  amount  of  matter 
in  it.  An  additional  conception  termed  force  has  been 
introduced  and  is  supposed  to  be  in  some  way  resident  in 
matter.  The  force  of  a  body  P  on  a  body  Q,  of  mass  m 
is  a  quantity  proportional  to  the  mass  m  of  Q  and  to 
the  acceleration  which  the  presence  of  P  produces  in 
the  motion  of  Q.  It  will  be  obvious  to  the  reader  that 
this  conception  of  force  no  more  explains  why  the  pre 
sence  of  P  tends  to  change  the  velocity  of  Q,  than  the 
conception  of  matter  explains  why  mutual  accelerations 


MOTION. 


271 


are  inversely  as  masses.  The  custom  of  basing  our 
ideas  of  motion  on  these  terms  *  matter '  and  '  force ' 
has  too  often  led  to  obscurity,  not  only  in  mathematical, 
but  in  philosophical  reasoning.  We  do  not  know  why 
the  presence  of  one  body  tends  to  change  the  velocity 
of  another;  to  say  that  it  arises  from  the  force  resident 
in  the  first  body  acting  upon  the  matter  of  the  moving 
body  is  only  to  slur  over  our  ignorance.  All  that  we 
do  know  is  that  the  presence  of  one  body  may  tend 
to  change  the  velocity  of  another,  and  that,  if  it  does, 
the  change  can  be  ascertained  from  experiment,  and 
obeys  the  above  laws. 

To  calculate  by  means  of  the  laws  of  motion  from  the 
observed  effects  on  a  simple  body  of  a  simple  set  of  cir 
cumstances  the  more  complex  effects  of  any  combina 
tion  of  circumstances  on  a  complex  body  or  system  of 
bodies  is  the  special  function  of  that  branch  of  the  exact 
sciences  which  is  termed  Applied  Mathematics. 


FRIKTF.D  HT 

SrOTTISWOODE    AND    CO.,    XEW-sTi'.EKT    SQUARE 
LONDON' 


A   LIST   OF 

KEG  AN  PAUL,    TRENCH  &  CO:S 
PUBLICATIONS. 


11,87, 


I,  Paternoster  Square, 

London. 


A   LIST   OF 

KEGAN  PAUL,  TRENCH  &  CO.'S 
PUBLICATIONS. 


CONTENTS. 


PAGE 


GENERAL  LITERATURE .        .      2 
PARCHMENT  LIBRARY    .        .18 
PULPIT  COMMENTARY   .        .21 
INTERNATIONAL    SCIENTIFIC 
SERIES     ,  30 


PAGE 

33 


MILITARY  WORKS. 
POETRY  .....  35 
NOVELS  AND  TALES  .  .41 
BOOKS  FOR  THE  YOUNG  .  43 


GENERAL   LITERATURE. 

A.  K.  If.  B.  —  From  a  Quiet  Place.  A  Volume  of  Sermons. 
Crown  Svo,  5-r. 

ALEXANDER,  William,  D.D.,  Bishop  of  Derry.— The  Great  Ques 
tion,  and  other  Sermons.  Crown  Svo,  6s. 

ALLIES,  T.  W.,  M.A.—T?QT  Crucem  ad  Lucem.     The  Result  of  a 

Life.     2  vols.     Demy  Svo,  25^. 
A  Life's  Decision.     Crown  Svo,  "js.  6</. 

AMHERST,  Rev.  W.  J.— The  History  of  Catholic  Emancipa 
tion  and  the  Progress  of  the  Catholic  Church  in  the 
British  Isles  (chiefly  in  England)  from  1771-1820. 
2  vols.  Demy  Svo,  24^. 

AMOS,  Professor  Sheldon. — The  History  and  Principles  of  the 
Civil  Law  of  Rome.  An  aid  to  the  Study  of  Scientific  and 
Comparative  Jurisprudence.  Demy  Svo,  l6s. 

Ancient  and  Modern  Britons.  A  Retrospect.  2  vols.  Demy  Svo, 
24^. 

ARISTOTLE.— The  Nicomachean  Ethics  of  Aristotle.  Trans- 
lated  by  F.  H.  Peters,  M.A.  Third  Edition.  Crown  Svo,  6*. 

AUBERTIN,  J.  y.—K  Flight  to  Mexico.  With  7  full-page  Tllus, 
trations  and  a  Railway  Map  of  Mexico.  Crown  Svo,  7^.  6J. 


Regan  Paul,  Trench  &  Co.'s  Publications.          3 

AUBERTIN,  y.  J.— continued. 

Six  Months  in  Cape  Colony  and  Natal.  With  Illustra 
tions  and  Map.  Crown  Svo,  6s. 

Aucassin  and  Nicolette.  Edited  in  Old 'French  and  rendered  in 
Modern  English  by  F.  W.  BOURDILI.ON.  Fcap  8vo,  "js.  6d. 

AUCHMUTY,  A.  C.— Dives  and  Pauper,  and  other  Sermons. 
Crown  8vo,  3.?.  6d. 

A'/.ARIUS,  Brother.— Aristotle  and  the  Christian  Church. 
Small  crown  Svo,  3-f.  6d. 

BADGER,  George  Percy,  D.C.L. — An  English-Arabic  Lexicon. 
In  which  the  equivalent  for  English  Words  and  Idiomatic 
Sentences  are  rendered  into  literary  and  colloquial  Arabic. 
Royal  4to,  Sew. 

BAGEHOT,  Walter.  —  The  English  Constitution.  Fourth 
Edition.  Crown  SYO,  "s.  6d. 

Lombard  Street,  A  Description  of  the  Money  Market.  Eighth 
Edition.  Crown  Svo,  "js.  6:L 

Essays  on  Parliamentary  Reform.     Crown  Svo,  5..-. 

Some  Articles  on  the  Depreciation  of  Silver,  and  Topics 
connected  with  it.  Demy  Svo,  5.?. 

BAGOT,  Alan,  C.E.—  Accidents  in  Mines:  their  Causes  and 
Prevention.  Crown  Svo,  6s. 

The  Principles  of  Colliery  Ventilation.  Second  Edition, 
greatly  enlarged.  Crown  Svo,  5^. 

The  Principles  of  Civil  Engineering  as  applied  to 
Agriculture  and  Estate  Management.  Crown  Svo, 
TS.  6d. 

I3AIRD,  Henry  M. — The  Huguenots  and  Henry  of  Navarre. 
2  vol*.  With  Maps.  Svo,  2$s. 

BALDWIN,  Capt.  J.  //.—The  Large  and  Small  Game  of 
Bengal  and  the  North-Western  Provinces  of  India. 
With  20  Illustrations.  New  and  Cheaper  Edition.  Small  410, 
IOJ-.  6d. 

BALL, John,  F. R. S.—  Notes  of  a  Naturalist  in  South  America. 
With  Map.  Crown  Svo,  8j.  6</. 

HALLIN,  Ada  S.  and  F.  L.—K  Hebrew  Grammar.  With 
Exercises  selected  from  the  Bible.  Crown  Svo,  "js.  6d. 

BARCLAY,  Edgar.— Mountain  Life  in  Algeria.  With  numerous 
Illustrations  by  Photogravure.  Crown  4to,  i6s. 

BASU,  K.  P.,  M.A. — Students'  Mathematical  Companion. 
Containing  problems  in  Arithmetic,  Algebra,  Geometry,  and 
Mensuration,  for  Students  of  the  Indian  Universities.  Crown 
Svo,  6s. 


4  A  List  of 

BAUR,  Ferdinand,  Dr.  /%.— A  Philological  Introduction  to 
Greek  and  Latin  for  Students.  Translated  and  adapted 
from  the  German,  by  C.  KEGAN  PAUL,  M.A.,  and  E.  D. 
STONE,  M.A.  Third  Edition.  Crown  8vo,  6s. 

BAYLY,  Capt.  George. — Sea  Life  Sixty  Years  Ago.  A  Record  of 
Adventures  which  led  up  to  the  Discovery  of  the  Relics  of  the 
long-missing  Expedition  commanded  by  the  Comte  de  la  Perouse. 
Crown  Svo,  35.  6d. 

BENSON,  A.  C. — William  Laud,  sometime  Archbishop  of 
Canterbury.  A  Study.  With  Portrait.  Crown  Svo,  6s. 

BIRD,  Charles,  F.G.S. — Higher  Education  in  Germany  and 
England.  Small  crown  Svo,  2s.  6d. 

Birth  and  Growth  of  Religion.  A  Book  for  Workers.  Crown 
Svo,  cloth,  2s.  ;  paper  covers,  is. 

BLACKBURN,  Mrs.  Hugh.— Bible  Beasts  and  Birds.  22  Illus 
trations  of  Scripture  photographed  from  the  Original.  4to,  42^. 

BLECKLY,  Henry. — Socrates  and  the  Athenians  :  An  Apology. 
Crown  8vo,  2s.  6d. 

BLOOMFIELD,  The  Lady. — Reminiscences  of  Court  and  Dip 
lomatic  Life.  New  and  Cheaper  Edition.  With  Frontispiece. 
Crown  Svo,  6s. 

BLUNT,  The  Ven.  Archdeacon. — The  Divine  Patriot,  and  other 
Sermons.  Preached  in  Scarborough  and  in  Cannes.  New 
and  Cheaper  Edition.  Crown  Svo,  4^.  6</. 

BLUNT,  Wilfrid S.—  The  Future  of  Islam.     Crown  Svo,  6s. 
Ideas  about  India.     Crown  Svo.     Cloth,  6s. 

BODDY,  Alexander  A.— To  Kairwan  the  Holy.  Scenes  in 
Muhammedan  Africa.  With  Route  Map,  and  Eight  Illustrations 
by  A.  F.  JACASSEY.  Crown  Svo,  6s. 

BOSANQUET,  Bernard.— Knowledge  and  Reality.  A  Criticism 
of  Mr.  F.  H.  Bradley's  "Principles  of  Logic."  Crown  Svo,  9^. 

BOUVERIE-PUSEY,   S.  E.  ^.—Permanence  and   Evolution. 

An   Inquiry  into   the   Supposed   Mutability   of  Animal   Types. 

Crown  Svo,  $s. 
BOWEN,  H.  C.,  M.A.—  Studies  in  English.    For  the  use  of  Modern 

Schools.     Ninth  Thousand.     Small  crown  Svo,  is.  6d. 

English  Grammar  for  Beginners.    Fcap.  Svo,  is. 

Simple  English  Poems.  English  Literature  for  Junior  Classes. 
In  four  parts.  Parts  I.,  II.,  and  III.,  6d,  each.  Part  IV.,  i*. 
Complete,  35. 

BRADLEY,  F.  H.~ The  Principles  of  Logic.     Demy  Svo,  i6s. 

BRIDGETT,  Rev.  T.  £.— History  of  the  Holy  Eucharist  in 
Great  Britain,  2  vol?,  Demy  Svo,  1 8*. 


Kegan  Paul,   Trench  &  Co's  Publications.  § 

BROOKE,  JRn>.  Stopford  A.— The  Fight  of  Faith.  Sermons  preached 
on  various  occasions.  Fifth  Edition.  Crown  8vo,  "js.  6<?. 

The  Spirit  of  the  Christian  Life.  Third  Edition.  Crov.n 
8vo,  5.?. 

Theology  in  the  English  Poets.-  Cowper,  Coleridge,  Words 
worth,  and  Burns.  Sixth  Edition.  Post  Svo,  55. 

Christ  In  Modern  Life.     Sixteenth  Edition.     Crown  Svo,  5*. 
Sermons.     First  Series.    Thirteenth  Edition.     Crown  Svo,  5*. 
Sermons.     Second  Series.     Sixth  Edition.     Crown  Svo,  5^. 

RROWN,  Horatio  F. — Life  on  the  Lagoons.  With  2  Illustrations 
and  Map.  Crown  Svo,  6s. 

Venetian  Studies.     Cro\vn  Svo,  7.!-.  6Y. 

BROWN,  Rev.  J.  fiaUwin.—Yhe  Higher  Life.  Its  Reality,  Ex 
perience,  and  Destiny.  Sixth  Edition.  Crown  Svo,  $s. 

Doctrine  of  Annihilation  in  the  Light  of  the  Gospel  of 
Love.  Five  Discourses.  Fourth  Edition.  Crown  Svo,  2s.  6J. 

The  Christian  Policy  of  Life.  A  Book  for  Young  Men  of 
Business.  Third  Edition.  Crown  Svo,  3-r.  6</. 

nURDETT,  Henry  C.— Help  in  Sickness—  Where  to  Go  and 
What  to  Do.  Crown  Svo,  is.  6if. 

Helps  to  Health.  The  Habitation— The  Nursery— The  School 
room  and — The  Person.  With  a  Chapter  on  Pleasure  and  Health 
Resorts.  Crown  Svo,  is.  6J. 

BURKE,  Oliver  /.—South  Isles  of  Aran  (County  Galway). 
Crown  Svo,  2s.  6il. 

HURKE,  The  Late  Very  Rev.  7'.  .V.— His  Life.  By  W.  J.  FIT/.- 
PATRICK.  2  vols.  With  Portrait.  Demy  Svo,  30.?. 

BURTON,  Lady.— The  Inner  Life  of  Syria,  Palestine,  and 
the  Holy  Land.  Post  Svo,  6s. 

C.I. \~DLER,  C.— The  Prevention  of  Consumption.  A  Mode  of 
Prevention  founded  on  a  New  Theory  of  the  Nature  of  the 
Tubercle-Bacillus.  Demy  Svo,  los.  6i/. 

CAPES,  J.  Jr.— The  Church  of  the  Apostles :  an  Historical 
Inquiry.  Demy  Svo,  gs. 

Carlyle  and  the  Open  Secret  of  His  Life.  By  HENRY  LARKIX. 
Demy  Svo,  14^. 

CARPENTER,  W.  B.,  LL.D.,  !\T.D.,  F.R.S.,  etc.— The  Principles 
of  Mental  Physiology.  With  their  Applications  to  the 
Training  and  Discipline  of  the  Mind,  and  the  Study  of  its  Morbid 
Conditions.  Illustrated.  Sixth  Edition.  Svo,  12s. 


6  A  List  of 

Catholic  Dictionary.  Containing  some  Account  of  the  Doctrine, 
Discipline,  Rites,  Ceremonies,  Councils,  and  Religious  Orders  of 
the  Catholic  Church.  By  WILLIAM  E.  ADDIS  and  THOMAS 
ARNOLD,  M.A.  Third  Edition.  Demy  8vo,  2is. 

Century  Guild  Hobby  Horse.     Vol.  I.     Half  parchment,  I2s.  6d. 

CHARLES,  Rev.  R.  H. — Forgiveness,  and  other  Sermons.  Crown 
8vo,  &fS.  6d. 

CHEYNE,  Canon.— The  Prophecies  of  Isaiah.  Translated  with 
Critical  Notes  and  Dissertations.  2  vols.  Fourth  Edition.  Demy 
8vo,  25*. 

Job  and  Solomon  ;  or,  the  Wisdom  of  the  Old  Testament. 
Demy  Svo,  12s.  6d. 

The  Psalter  ;  or,  The  Book  of  the  Praises  of  Israel.  Translated 
with  Commentary.  Demy  Svo. 

CLAIRA  UT.  —  Elements  of  Geometry.  Translated  by  Dr. 
KAINES.  With  145  Figures.  Crown  Svo,  45.  6d. 

CLAPPERTON,  Jane  Hume.  —  Scientific  Meliorism  and  the 
Evolution  of  Happiness.  Large  crown  Svo,  8s.  6d. 

CLARKE,  Rev.  Henry  James,  A.K.C. — The  Fundamental  Science. 

Demy  Svo,  los.  6d. 

CLODD,  Edward,  F.R.A.S.—T^e.  Childhood  of  the  World  :  a 
Simple  Account  of  Man  in  Early  Times.  Eighth  Edition. 
Crown  Svo,  3s. 

A  Special  Edition  for  Schools,     is. 

The  Childhood  of  Religions.  Including  a  Simple  Account  of 
the  Birth  and  Growth  of  Myths  and  Legends.  Eighth  Thousand. 
Crown  Svo,  5-r. 

A  Special  Edition  for  Schools,     is.  6d. 

Jesus  of  Nazareth.  With  a  brief  sketch  of  Jewish  History  to  the 
Time  of  His  Birth.  Small  crown  Svo,  6^. 

COGHLAN,  J.  Cole,  D.D.—The  Modern  Pharisee  and  other 
Sermons.  Edited  by  the  Very  Rev.  H.  H.  DICKINSON,  D.D., 
Dean  of  Chapel  Royal,  Dublin.  New  and  Cheaper  Edition. 
Crown  Svo,  Js.  6d. 

COLERIDGE,  Sara.— Memoir  and  Letters  of  Sara  Coleridge. 
Edited  by  her  Daughter.  With  Index.  Cheap  Edition.  With 
Portrait.  7-r.  6d. 

COLERIDGE,  The  Hon.  Stephen.— Demetrius.     Crown  Svo,  5*. 

CONNELL,  A.  K. — Discontent  and  Danger  in   India.     Small 

crown  Svo,  3^.  6d. 
The  Economic  Revolution  of  India.     Crown  Svo,  4^.  6d. 

COOK,  Keningale,  LL.D.—  The  Fathers  of  Jesus.  A  Study  of  the 
Lineage  of  the  Christian  Doctrine  and  Traditions.  2  vols.  Demy 
Svo,  2S.f. 


Kegan  Paul,  Trench  &  Go's  Publications. 


CORK,  the  late  Rev.  T.  J.,  M.A.—  Favilla  ;  Tales,  Essays,  and  Poems. 
Crown  Svo,  5^. 

COR  Y,  William.—  A  Guide  to  Modern  English  History.  Part  I. 
— MDCCCXV.-MDCCCXXX.  Demy  Svo,  9^.  Part  II.— 
MDCCCXXX.-MDCCCXXXV.,  15*. 

COTTON,  H.  J.  S.— New  India,  or  India  in  Transition. 
Third  Edition.  Crown  Svo,  45.  6J.  ;  Cheap  Edition,  paper 
covers,  u. 

COUTTS,  Francis  Burddt  Money.— The  Training  of  the  Instinct 
of  Love.  With  a  Preface  by  the  Rev.  EDWARD  THKINC,  M.  A. 
Small  crown  Svo,  2s.  6J. 

COX,  Rev.  Sir  George   IV.,  M.A.,  Mart.— The   Mythology   of   the 

Aryan  Nations.      New  Edition.     Demy  Svo,  i6s. 
Tales  of  Ancient  Greece.     New  Edition.     Small  crown  Svo,  6s. 

A  Manual  of  Mythology  in  the  form  of  Question  and 
Answer.  New  Edition.  Fcap.  Svo,  $s. 

An  Introduction  to  the  Science  of  Comparative  Myth 
ology  and  Folk-Lore.  Second  Edition.  Crown  Svo.  "js.  6d. 

COX,  Rev.  Sir  G.  W.,  M.A.,  Bart.,  and  JONES,  EusLicc  Ilinlon.— 
Popular  Romances  of  the  Middle  Ages.  Third 
Edition,  in  I  vol.  Crown  Svo,  6s. 

COX,  Rev.  Samite!,  D.D. — A  Commentary  on  the  Book  of  Job 

With  a  Translation.     Second  Edition.     Demy  Svo,  i$s. 
Salvator  Mundi  ;  or,  'Is  Christ  the  Saviour  of  all  Men  ?    Tenth 

Edition.     Crown  Svo,  $s. 
The  Larger  Hope.     A  Sequel  to  "Salvator   Mundi."    Second 

Edition.      i6mo,  is. 
The  Genesis  of  Evil,  and  other  Sermons,  mainly  expository. 

Third  Edition.     Crown  Svo,  6s. 

Balaam.     An  Exposition  and  a  Study.     Crown  Svo,  $s. 
Miracles.     An  Argument  and  a  Challenge.     Crown  Svo,  2s.  6</. 
CRA  VEN,  Mrs.—K  Year's  Meditations.     Crown  Svo,  6s. 

CRAU'FURD,  Oswald.— Portugal,  Old  and  New.  With  Illustra 
tions  and  Maps.  New  and  Cheaper  Edition.  Crown  Svo,  6s. 

CRUISE,  Francis  Richard,  M.D.—  Thomas  a  Kempis.  Notes  of 
a  Visit  to  the  Scenes  in  which  his  Life  was  spent.  With  Portraits 
and  Illustrations.  Demy  Svo,  12s. 

L'XA'JXGIL-IM,  W.,  B.D  —Politics  and  Economics:  An  Essay 
on  the  Nature  of  thj  Principles  of  Political  Economy,  together 
with  a  survey  of  Recent  Legislation.  Crown  Svo,  $s. 

*)ANIELL,  Clarmont. — The  Gold  Treasure  of  India.  An  Inquiry 
into  its  Amount,  the  Cause  of  its  Accumulation,  and  the  Proper 
Means  of  using  it  as  Money.  Crown  Svo,  $s. 


8  A  List  of 

DA  N1ELL ,  Clarmont.  —continued. 

Discarded  Silver  :  a  Plan  for  its  Use  as  Money.     Small  crown 

8vo,  2s. 
DANIEL,  Gerard.     Mary  Stuart:    a  Sketch  and  a  Defence. 

Crown  8vo,  5-r. 

DARMESTETER,  Arsene.—The  Life  of  Words  as  the  Symbols 
of  Ideas.     Crown  8vo,  4.?.  6d. 

DAVIDSON,  Rev.  Samuel,  D.D.,  LL.D.— Canon  of  the  Bible; 

Its  Formation,  History,  and   Fluctuations.     Third  and  Revised 
Edition.     Small  crown  8vo,  $s. 

The  Doctrine  of  Last  Things  contained  in  the  New  Testa 
ment  compared  with  the  Notions  of  the  Jews  and  the  Statements 
of  Church  Creeds.  Small  crown  8vo,  31.  6d. 

DAIVSON,  Geo.,  M.A.  Prayers,  with  a  Discourse  on  Prayer 
Edited  by  his  Wife.  First  Series.  Ninth  Edition.  Crow 
8vo,  3.?.  6<t. 

Prayers,  with  a  Discourse  on  Prayer.     Edited  by  GEORG 
ST.  CLAIR.     Second  Series.     Crown  8vo,  6s. 

Sermons  on  Disputed  Points  and  Special  Occasions 
Edited  by  his  Wife.     Fourth  Edition.     Crown  8vo,  6s. 

Sermons  on  Daily  Life  and  Duty.  Edited  by  his  Wife 
Fourth  Edition.  Crown  8vo,  6s. 

The  Authentic  Gospel,  and  other  Sermons.  Edited  b 
GEORGE  ST.  CLAIR,  F.G.S.  Third  Edition.  Crown  8vo,  6j-. 

Biographical  Lectures.  Edited  by  GEORGE  ST.  CLAIR,  F.G.S 
Third  Edition.  Large  crown  8vo,  7-f.  6d. 

Shakespeare,  and  other  Lectures.  Edited  by  GEORGE  ST 
CLAIR,  F.G.S.  Large  crown  8vo,  "js.  6d. 

DE  JONCOURT,  Madame  Marie.—  Wholesome  Cookery.  Fourt! 
Edition.  Crown  8vo,  cloth,  u.  6d;  paper  covers,  is. 

DENT,  H.  C.— A  Year  in  Brazil.  With  Notes  on  Religion,  Meteor 
ology,  Natural  History,  etc.  Maps  and  Illustrations.  Dem 
8vo,  i8j. 

Doctor  Faust.  The  Old  German  Puppet  Play,  turned  into  English 
with  Introduction,  etc.,  by  T.  C.  H.  HEDDERWICK.  Lam 
post  8vo,  7.r.  6d. 

DOWDEN,  Edward,  LL.D.—  Shakspere  :  a  Critical  Study  of  his 
Mind  and  Art.  Eighth  Edition.  Tost  8vo,  12s. 

Studies  in  Literature,  1789-1877.  Fourth  Edition.  Large 
post  8vo,  6s. 

Transcripts  and  Studies.     Large  post  Svo. 
Dulce  Domum.     Fcap.  Svo,  5^. 


Regan  Paul,  Trench  &  Cols  Publications. 


DU  MONCEL,  Count.— The  Telephone,  the  Microphone,  and 
the  Phonograph.  With  74  iriustrations.  Third  Edition. 
Small  crown  8vo,  5-r.' 

DUt\\\\  //.  Percy—  Infant  Health.  The  Physiology  and  Hygiene 
of  Early  Life.  Crown  8vo. 

1)L''RUY,  Victor.— History  of  Rome  and  the  Roman  People. 
Edited  by  Prof.  MAHAFFY.  With  nearly  3000  Illustrations.  410. 
6  vols.  in  12  parts,  30^.  each  vol. 

Education  Library.     Edited  by  Sir  PHILIP  MAGNUS  : — 

An  Introduction  to  the  History  of  Educational 
Theories.  IJy  OSCAR  BROWNING,  M.A.  Second  Edition. 
35.  &/. 

Old  Greek  Education.  By  the  Rev.  Prof.  MAHAFFY,  M.A. 
Second  Edition.  3.?.  6if. 

School  Management.  Including  a  general  view  of  the  work 
of  Education,  Organi/ation  and  Discipline.  By  JOSEPH  LAMIUN. 
Sixth  Edition.  6s. 

EDWARDES,  Major-General  Sir  Herbert  7?.— Memorials  of  his 
Life  and  Letters.  By  his  Wife.  With  Portrait  and  Illustra 
tions.  2  vols.  Demy  Svo,  36^. 

ELSDALE,  Henry. — Studies  in  Tennyson's  Idylls.  Crown  Svo,  5.?. 

Emerson's  (Ralph  'Waldo)  Life.  By  OLIVER  WENDELL  HOLMES. 
English  Copyright  Edition.  With  Portrait.  Crown  Svo,  6s. 

"Fan  Kwae"  at  Canton  before  Treaty  Days  1825-1844. 

By  an  old  Resident.    With  Frontispiece.     Crown  Svo,  5^. 

Five  o'clock.  Tea.  Containing  Receipts  for  Cakes,  Savoury  Sand 
wiches,  etc.  Fcap.  Svo,  cloth,  is.  6d.  ;  paper  covers,  is. 

FOTHERINGHAM,  James.— Studies  in  the  Poetry  of  Robert 
Browning.  Crown  Svo.  6s. 

GARDINER,  Samuel  R.,  and  J.  BASS  MULLINGER,  ALA.— 
Introduction  to  the  Study  of  English  History.  Second 
Edition.  Large  crown  Svo,  gs. 

Genesis  in  Advance  of  Present  Science.  A  Critical  Investigation 
of  Chapters  I. -IX.  By  a  Septuagenarian  Beneficed  Presbyter. 
Demy  Svo,  IO.T.  6d. 

GEORGE,  Henry. — Progress  and  Poverty  :  An  Inquiry  into  the 
Causes  of  Industrial  Depressions,  and  of  Increase  of  Want  with 
Increase  of  Wealth.  The  Remedy.  Fifth  Library  Edition. 
Post  Svo,  7v.  6d.  Cabinet  Edition.  Crown  Svo,  i;.  6tt.  Also  a 
Cheap  Edition.  Limp  cloth,  is.  6</. ;  paper  covers,  is. 

Protection,  or  Free  Trade.  An  Examination  of  the  Tariff 
Question,  with  especial  regard  to  the  Interests  of  Labour.  Second 
Edition.  Crown  Svo,  55. 


io  A  List  of 

GEORGE,  Henry. — continued, 

Social  Problems.  Fourth  Thousand.  Crown  8vo,  $s.  Cheap 
Edition,  paper  covers,  is. 

GILBERT,  Mrs.  —  Autobiography,  and  other  Memorials. 
Edited  by  JOSIAH  GILBERT.  Fifth  Edition.  Crown  8vo, 
7-r.  6d. 

GLANVZLL,  Joseph. — Scepsis  Scientifica  ;  or,  Confest  Ignorance, 
the  Way  to  Science  ;  in  an  Essay  of  the  Vanity  of  Dogmatizing 
and  Confident  Opinion.  Edited,  with  Introductory  Essay,  by 
JOHN  OWEN.  Elzevir  8vo,  printed  on  hand-made  paper,  6s. 

Glossary  of  Terms  and  Phrases.  Edited  by  the  Rev.  H.  PERCY 
SMITH  and  others.  Second  and  Cheaper  Edition.  Medium 
8vo,  7j.  6d. 

GLOVER,  F.,  M.A. — Exempla  Latina.  A  First  Construing  Book, 
with  Short  Notes,  Lexicon,  and  an  Introduction  to  the  Analysis 
of  Sentences.  Second  Edition.  Fcap.  8vo,  2s. 

GOODENOUGH,  Commodore  J.  G. — Memoir  of,  with  Extracts  from 
his  Letters  and  Journals.  Edited  by  his  Widow.  With  Steel 
Engraved  Portrait.  Third  Edition;  Crown  8vo,  $s. 

GORDON,  Major-General  C.  G. — His  Journals  at  Kartoum. 
Printed  from  the  original  MS.  With  Introduction  and  Notes  by 
A.  EGMONT  HAKE.  Portrait,  2  Maps,  and  30  Illustrations. 
Two  vols.,  demy  8vo,  21  s.  Also  a  Cheap  Edition  in  I  vol.,  6s. 

Gordon's  (General)  Last  Journal.  A  Facsimile  of  the  last 
Journal  received  in  England  from  GENERAL  GORDON.  Repro 
duced  by  Photo-lithography.  Imperial  4to,  ,£3  35. 

Events  in  his  Life.  From  the  Day  of  his  Birth  to  the  Day  of 
his  Death.  By  Sir  H.  W.  GORDON.  With  Maps  and  Illus 
trations.  Second  Edition.  Demy  Svo,  js.  €>d. 

GOSSE,  Edmund.  —  Seventeenth  Century  Studies.  A  Contri 
bution  to  the  History  of  English  Poetry.  Demy  Svo,  los.  6d. 

GOULD,  Rev.  S.  Baring,  M. A.— Germany,  Present  and  Past. 
New  and  Cheaper  Edition.  Large  crown  Svo,  7s.  6d. 

The   Vicar   of   Morwenstow.      A   Life   of  Robert   Stephen 

Hawker.     Crown  Svo,  6.r. 

GO  WAN,  Major  Walter  E.—K.  Ivanoff's  Russian  Grammar. 
(i6th  Edition.)  Translated,  enlarged,  and  arranged  for  use  of 
Students  of  the  Russian  Language.  Demy  Svo,  6s. 

COWER,  Lord  Ronald.  My  Reminiscences.  MINIATURE  EDITION, 
printed  on  hand-made  paper,  limp  parchment  antique,  IDJ.  6d. 

Bric-a-Brac.  Being  some  Photoprints  taken  at  Gower  Lodge, 
Windsor.  Super  royal  Svo. 

Last  Days  of  Mary  Antoinette.  An  Historical  Sketch. 
With  Portrait  and  Facsimiles.  Fcap.  4to,  los.  6d. 


Kega)i  Paul,  Trench  &  Co.'s  Publications,         1 1 


OWER,  Lord  Ronald.— continued. 

Notes  of   a  Tour   from  Brindisi  to  Yokohama,  1883- 
1884.     Fcap.  8vo,  2s.  6d. 

RAHAM,  William,  M.4.—The  Creed  of  Science,  Religious,  Moral, 
and  Social.  Second  Edition,  Revised.  Crown  8vo,  6s. 

The    Social    Problem,    in    its    Economic,    Moral,    and 
Political  Aspects.     Demy  8vo,  145. 

REY,  Rowland. — In  Sunny  Switzerland.  A  Talc  of  Six  Weeks. 
Second  Edition.  Small  crown  Svo,  $s. 

Lindenblumen  and  other  Stories.     Small  crown  Svo,  5*. 

RIMLEY,  Rev.  II.  A".,  M.A. — Tremadoc  Sermons,  chiefly  on 
the  Spiritual  Body,  the  Unseen  "World,  and  the 
Divine  Humanity.  Fourth  Edition.  Crown  Svo,  6s. 

The  Temple  of  Humanity,  and  other  Sermons.     Crown  Svo, 
6s. 

URNEY,  Edmund. — Tertium  Quid  :  chapters  on  Various  Disputed 
Questions.  2  vols.  Crown  Svo,  12s. 

JADDON,  Carotin;. — The  Larger  Life,  Studies  in  Hinton's 
Ethics.  Crown  Svo,  $s. 

{A ECKEL,  Prof.  Ernst. — The  History  of  Creation.  Translation 
revised  by  Professor  E.  RAY  LANKESTEK,  M.A.,  F.R.S.  With 
Coloured  Plates  and  Genealogical  Trees  of  the  various  groups 
of  both  Plants  and  Animals.  2  vols.  Third  Edition.  Post 
Svo,  325. 

The  History  of  the  Evolution  of   Man.     With  numerous 
Illustrations.     2  vols.     Post  Svo,  32$. 

A  Visit  to  Ceylon.     Post  Svo,  fs.  6d. 

Freedom  in  Science  and  Teaching.     With  a  Prefatory  Note 
by  T.  H.  HUXLEY,  F.R.S.     Crown  Svo,  $s. 

amilton,  Memoirs  of  Arthur,  B.A.,  of  Trinity  College,  Cam 
bridge.  Crown  Svo,  6s. 

andbook  of  Home  Rule,  being  Articles  on  the  Irish  Question  by 
Various    Writers.      Edited    by  JAMES    BR.YCE,    M.P.      Second 
Edition.     Crown  Svo,  is.  sewed,  or  is.  6d.  cloth. 
'ARRIS,    William.— The    History  of    the  Radical   Party   in 
Parliament.     Demy  Svo,  15^. 

'AlVEIS,  Rci'.  H.  R.,  M.A.— Current  Coin.  Materialism— The 
Devil — Crime — Drunkenness — Pauperism — Emotion— Recreation 
—The  Sabbath.  Fifth  Edition.  Crown  Svo,  5*. 

Arrows  in  the  Air.     Fifth  Edition.     Crown  Svo,  5*. 
Speech  in  Season.     Fifth  Edition.    Crown  Svo,  $s. 
Thoughts  for  the  Times.     Fourteenth  Edition.    Crown  Svo,  $j. 


12  A  List  of 

HAWEIS,Rcv.II.  A".,  M.  A  .—continued. 

Unsectarian  Family  Prayers.  New  Edition.  Fcap.  Svo 
is.  6d. 

HA  WTHORNE,  Nathaniel.—  Works.  Complete  in  Twelve  Volume 
Large  post  Svo,  7^.  6d.  each  volume. 

HEATH,  Francis  George. — Autumnal  Leaves.  Third  and  cheape 
Edition.  Large  crown  Svo,  6.r. 

Sylvan  "Winter.     With  70  Illustrations.     Large  crown  Svo,  i 

Hegel's  Philosophy  of  Fine  Art.  The  Introduction,  translated  b 
BERNARD  BOSANQUET.  Crown  Svo,  5*. 

HENNESSY,  Sir  John  Pope.— Ralegh  in  Ireland.  With  his  Letter 
on  Irish  Affairs  and  some  Contemporary  Documents.  Large  crow 
Svo,  printed  on  hand-made  paper,  parchment,  IO.T.  6d. 

HENRY,  Philip.— Diaries  and  Letters  of.  Edited  by  MATTHE\ 
HENRY  LEE,  M.A.  Large  crown  Svo,  "js.  6d. 

HINTON,  J.— Life  and  Letters.  With  an  Introduction  by  Sir  W 
W.  GULL,  Bart.,  and  Portrait  engraved  on  Steel  by  C.  H.  Jeens 
Fifth  Edition.  Crown  Svo,  8s.  6d. 

Philosophy  and  Religion.  Selections  from  the  Manuscripts  o 
the  late  James  Hinton.  Edited  by  CAROLINE  HADDON.  Secon 
Edition.  Crown  Svo,  $s. 

The    Law    Breaker,    and   The    Coming    of    the   Law 

Edited  by  MARGARET  HINTON.     Crown  Svo,  6s. 

The  Mystery  of  Pain.     New  Edition.     Fcap.  Svo,  is. 

Homer's  Iliad.  Greek  text,  with  a  Translation  by  J.  G.  CORDERY 
2  vols.  Demy  Svo,  24?. 

HOOPER,  Mary. — Little  Dinners :  How  to  Serve  them  witl 
Elegance  and  Economy.  Twentieth  Edition.  Crowt 
Svo,  2s.  6d. 

Cookery  for  Invalids,  Persons  of  Delicate  Digestion 
and  Children.  Fifth  Edition.  Crown  Svo,  2s.  6d. 

Every-Day  Meals.  Being  Economical  and  Wholesome  Recipe 
for  Breakfast,  Luncheon,  and  Supper.  Seventh  Edition.  Crowi 
Svo,  2s.  6d. 

HOPKINS,  Ellice.  —  Work  amongst  Working 'Men.  Sixtl 
Edition.  Crown  Svo,  $s.  6d. 

HORNADAY,  W.  T.— Two  Years  in  a  Jungle.  With  Illustrations 
Demy  Svo,  21  s. 

HOSPITALIER,  E.—  The  Modern  Applications  of  Electricity 

Translated  and  Enlarged  by  JULIUS  MAIER,  Ph.D.  2  vols 
Second  Edition,  Revised,  with  many  additions  and  numerou 
Illustrations.  Demy  Svo,  255. 


Kegan  Paul,   Trench  &  Go's  Publications.         13 

HOWARD,  Robert,  M.A.—The  Church  of  England  and  other 
Religious  Communions.  A  course  of  Lectures  delivered  in 
the  Parish  Church  of  Clapham.  Crown  Svo,  Js.  6d. 

How  to  Make  a  Saint;  or,  The  Process  of  Canonization  in  the 
Church  of  England.  By  the  PKU;.  Fcap  Svo,  3_r.  6d. 

IIL'XTER,  William  C.— Bits  of  Old  China.     Small  crown  Svo,  6s. 

HYNDMAN,  H.  M.—  The  Historical  Basis  of  Socialism  in 
England.  Large  crown  Svo,  Ss.  6J. 

1DDESLEIGH,  Earl  c/.—The  Pleasures,  Danger ;,  and  Uses 
of  Desultory  Reading.  Fcap.  Svo,  in  Whatman  paper 
cover,  is. 

/.!/  THURN,  Everard  F.—  Among  the  Indians  of  Guiana. 
Being  Sketches,  chiefly  anthropologic,  from  the  Interior  of  British 
Guiana.  With  53  Illustrations  and  a  Map.  Demy  Svo,  iSs. 

JACCOUD,  Prof.  S.— The  Curability  and  Treatment  of  Pul 
monary  Phthisis.  Translated  and  edited  by  MONTAGU 
LUBKOCK,  M.D.  Demy  Svo,  ifj. 

Jaunt  in  a  Junk  :  A  Ten  Days'  Cruise  in  Indian  Seas.  Large  crown 
Svo,  is.  6d. 

JENA'J.\S,  F..,  and  RAYMOND,  J.—  The  Architect's  Legal 
Handbook.  Third  Edition,  revised.  Crown  Svo,  6s. 

Ji-'.XKlNS,  Rev.  Canon  R.  C. — Heraldry  :  English  and  Foreign. 
With  a  Dictionary  of  Heraldic  Terms  and  156  Illustrations. 
Small  crown  Svo,  3.^.  6</. 

The  Story  of  the  Caraffa  ;  the  Pontificate  of  Paul  IV. 
Small  crown  Svo,  3-r.  6J. 

JOEL,  L. — A  Consul's  Manual  and  Shipowner's  and  Ship 
master's  Practical  Guide  in  their  Transactions 
Abroad.  WTith  Definitions  of  Nautical,  Mercantile,  and  Legal 
Terms ;  a  Glossary  of  Mercantile  Terms  in  English,  French, 
German,  Italian,  and  Spanish  ;  Tables  of  the  Money,  Weights, 
and  Measures  of  the  Principal  Commercial  Nations  and  their 
Equivalents  in  British  Standards ;  and  Forms  of  Consular  and 
Notarial  Acts.  Demy  Svo,  izs. 

JOHNSTON,   H.   H.,   F.Z.S.— The   Kilima-njaro  Expedition. 

A  Record  of  Scientific  Exploration  in  Eastern  Equatorial  Africa, 
and  a  General  Description  of  the  Natural  History,  Languages, 
and  Commerce  of  the  Kilima-njaro  District.  With  6  Maps,  and 
over  80  Illustrations  by  the  Author.  Demy  Svo,  2is. 

JORDAN,  Fumcaux,  F.X.C.S.—Analomy  and  Physiology  in 
Character.  Crown  Svo,  5.?. 

JOYCE,  P.  W.,  LL.D.,  etc.— Old  Celtic  Romances.  Translated 
from  the  Gaelic.  Crown  8vo,  7-r.  6J. 


14  A  List  of 

KAUFMANN,  Rev.  M.,  B.A.— Socialism  :  its  Nature,  its  Dangers, 
and  its  Remedies  considered.  Crown  8vo,  'js.  6d. 

Utopias  ;  or,  Schemes  of  Social  Improvement,  from  Sir  Thomas 
More  to  Karl  Marx.  Crown  8vo,  $s. 

KA  Y,  David,  F.R.G.S. — Education  and  Educators.  Crown  8vo. 
7-r.  6d. 

KAY,  Joseph.— Free  Trade  in  Land.  Edited  by  his  Widow.  With 
Preface  by  the  Right  Hon.  JOHN  BRIGHT,  M.P.  Seventh 
Edition.  Crown  8vo,  $s. 
%*  Also  a  cheaper  edition,  without  the  Appendix,  but  with  a  Review 
of  Recent  Changes  in  the  Land  Laws  of  England,  by  the  RIGHT 
HON.  G.  OSBORNE  MORGAN,  Q.C.,  M.P.  Cloth,  is.  6d.  ;  paper 
covers,  is. 

KELKE,  W.  H.  Jf.—An  Epitome  of  English  Grammar  for 
the  Use  of  Students.  Adapted  to  the  London  Matriculation 
Course  and  Similar  Examinations.  Crown  Svo,  4$.  6d. 

KEAIPIS,  Thomas  a.— Of  the  Imitation  of  Christ.  Parchment 
Library  Edition. — Parchment  or  cloth,  6s.  ;  vellum,  Js.  6d.  The 
Red  Line  Edition,  fcap.  Svo,  cloth  extra,  2s.  6d.  The  Cabinet 
Edition,  small  Svo,  cloth  limp,  is.  ;  cloth  boards,  is.  6d.  The 
Miniature  Edition,  cloth  limp,  32mo,  is. 
%*  All  the  above  Editions  may  be  had  in  various  extra  bindings. 

Notes  of  a  Visit  to  the  Scenes  in  which  his  Life  was 
spent.  With  numerous  Illustrations.  By  F.  R.  CRUISE,  M.D. 
Demy  Svo,  izs. 

KETTLEWELL,  Rev.  51.— Thomas  a  Kempis  and  the  Brothers 
of  Common  Life.  With  Portrait.  Second  Edition.  Crown 
Svo,  7-r.  6d. 

KIDD,  Joseph,  M.D. — The  Laws  of  Therapeutics  ;  or,  the  Science 
and  Art  of  Medicine.  Second  Edition.  Crown  Svo,  6s. 

KINGSFORD,  Anna,  M.D.—The  Perfect  'Way  in  Diet.  A 
Treatise  advocating  a  Return  to  the  Natural  and  Ancient  Food  oJ 
our  Race.  Third  Edition.  Small  crown  Svo,  2s. 

KINGSLEY,  Charles,  M.A.— Letters  and  Memories  of  his  Life. 
Edited  by  his  Wife.  With  two  Steel  Engraved  Portraits,  and 
Vignettes  on  Wood.  Sixteenth  Cabinet  Edition.  2  vols.  Crown 
Svo,  12s. 

%*  Also  a  People's  Edition,  in  one  volume.    With  Portrait.    Crown 
Svo,  6s. 

All  Saints'  Day,  and  other  Sermons.      Edited  by  the  Rev.   W. 
HARRISON.     Third  Edition.    Crown  Svo,  7.?.  6d. 

True  Words    for    Brave  Men.     A  Book  for  Soldiers'  and 
Sailors'  Libraries.     Sixteenth  Thousand.     Crown  Svo,  2s.  6d. 

KNOX,  Alexander  A. — The  New  Playground  ;  or,  Wanderings  in 
Algeria.  New  and  Cheaper  Edition.  Large  crown  Svo,  6s. 


Kegan  Paul,  Trench  &  Co.'s  Publications.         15 

Kosmos  ;  or,  the  Hope  of  the  World.     3*.  6d. 

Land  Concentration  and  Irresponsibility  of  Political  Power, 
as  causing  the  Anomaly  of  a  Widespread  State  of  Want  by  the 
Side  of  the  Vast  Supplies  of  Nature.  Crown  Svo,  $s. 

LANDON,  Joseph, — School  Management ;  Including  a  General  View 
of  the  Work  of  Education,  Organization,  and  Discipline.  Sixth 
Edition.  Crown  Svo,  6s. 

LAURIE,  S.  S.— The  Rise  and  Early  Constitution  of  Univer 
sities.  With  a  Survey  of  Mediaeval  Education.  Crown  Svo,  6s. 

LEE,  Rev.  F.  G.,  D.C.L.— The  Other  World  ;  or,  Glimpses  of  the 
Supernatural.  2  vols.  A  New  Edition.  Crown  Svo,  15.?. 

LEFEVRE,  Right  Hon.  G,  Ska™.— Peel  and  O'Connell.  Demy 
Svo,  ioj.  6d. 

Letters  from  an  Unknown  Friend.  By  the  Author  of  "  Charles 
Lowder."  With  a  Preface  by  the  Rev.  W.  II.  CLEAVER.  Fcap. 

iSvo,  is, 
Life  of  a  Prig.     By  ONE.     Third  Edition.      Fcap.  Svo,  31.  6if. 
LILLIE,   Arthur,   HT.R.A.S.—l'h.z   Popular    Life    of    Buddha. 
Containing  an  Answer  to  the  Hibbcrt  Lectures  of  iSSi.     With 
Illustrations.     Crown  Svo,  6s. 

Buddhism   in   Christendom  ;    or,   Jesus   the   Essene.     With 
Illustrations.     Demy  Svo,  15.?. 

LONGFELLOU',  II.  Wadsu<c<rtJi.—L\te.  By  his  Brother,  SAMUEL 
LONGFELLOW.  With  Portraits  and  Illustrations.  3  vols.  Demy 
Svo,  42.?. 

LONSDALE,  Margaret.— Sister  Dora  :  a  Biography.  With  Portrait. 
Twenty-ninth  Edition.  Small  crown  Svo,  2s.  6d. 

George  Eliot :   Thoughts  upon  her  Life,  her  Books,  and 
Herself.     Second  Edition.     Small  crown  Svo,  is.  6d. 

^OUNSBURY,  Thomas  R.— James  Fenimore  Cooper.  With 
Portrait.  Crown  Svo,  $s. 

Charles. — A  Biography.     By  the  Author  of  "  St.  Teresa." 
Twelfth  Edition.     Crown  Svo.     With  Portrait.     35.  6d. 

'MCKES,  Eva  C.  E. — Lectures  on  General  Nursing,  delivered  to 
the  Probationers  of  the  London  Hospital  Training  School  for 
Nurses.  Second  Edition.  Crown  Svo,  2s.  6d. 

'.YALL,  William  Ro-i'c,  D.D. — Propsedeia  Prophetica  ;  or,  The 
Use  and  Design  of  the  Old  Testament  Examined.  New  Edition. 
With  Notices  by  GEORGE  C.  PEARSON,  M.A.,  Hon.  Canon  of 
Canterbury.  Demy  Svo,  lOs.  6d, 

.YTTON,  Edward  Bulwer,  Lord.—I*ife,  Letters  and  Literary 
Remains.  By  his  Son,  the  EARL  OF  LYTTON.  With  Portraits, 
Illustrations  nnd  Facsimiles.  Demy  Svo.  Vols.  I.  and  IT.,  32^. 


1 6  A  List  of 

MACAULAY,  G.  C.— Francis  Beaumont  :  A  Critical  Study.  Crown 
8vo,  5.!-. 

MACHIAVELLI,  Nitcolb.  —  l^ife.  and  Times.  By  Prof.  VILLARI. 
Translated  by  LINDA  VILLARI.  4  vols.  Large  post  Svo,  q&s. 

Discourses  on  the  First  Decade  of  Titus  Livius.  Trans 
lated  from  the  Italian  by  NINIAN  HILL  THOMSON,  M.A.  Large 
crown  Svo,  12s. 

The  Prince.  Translated  from  the  Italian  by  N.  H.  T.  Small 
crown  Svo,  printed  on  hand-made  paper,  bevelled  boards,  6s. 

MACNEILL,  J.  G.  Swift.— How  the  Union  was  carried 
Crown  Svo,  cloth,  is.  6d.  ;  paper  covers,  is. 

MAGNUS,  Lady. — About  the  Jews  since  Bible  Times.  From  the 
Babylonian  Exile  till  the  English  Exodus.  Small  crown  Svo,  6.?. 

MAGUIRE,  Thomas. — Lectures  on  Philosophy.     Demy  Svo,  9^ 

Many  Voices.  A  volume  of  Extracts  from  the  Religious  Writers  o 
Christendom  from  the  First  to  the  Sixteenth  Century.  With 
Biographical  Sketches.  Crown  Svo,  cloth  extra,  red  edges,  6s. 

MARKHAM,  Capt.  Albert  Hastings,  R.N.—  The  Great  Frozen  Sea 
A  Personal  Narrative  of  the  Voyage  of  the  Alert  during  the  Arctic 
Expedition  of  1875-6.     With  6  full-page  Illustrations,  2  Maps 
and  27  Woodcuts.     Sixth  and  Cheaper  Edition.     Crown  Svo,  dr. 

MARTINEAU,  Gertrude.— Outline  Lessons  on  Morals.  Smal 
crown  Svo,  3-r.  6d. 

MASON,  Charlotte  M. — Home  Education  ;  a  Course  of  Lectures  to 
Ladies.  Crown  Svo,  3.?.  6d. 

Matter  and  Energy  :  An  Examination  of  the  Fundamental  Concep 
ceptions  of  Physical  Force.  By  B.  L.  L.  Small  crown  Svo,  2s 

MAUDSLEY,  //.,  M.D.— Body  and  Will.  Being  an  Essay  con 
cerning  Will,  in  its  Metaphysical,  Physiological,  and  Pathologica 
Aspects.  Svo,  12s. 

Natural  Causes  and  Supernatural  Seemings.  Second 
Edition.  Crown  Svo,  6s. 

McGRATH,  Terence.—  Pictures  from  Ireland.  New  and  Cheaper 
Edition.  Crown  Svo,  2s. 

MEREDITH,  M.A. — Theotokos,  the  Example  for  "Woman. 
Dedicated,  by  permission,  to  Lady  Agnes  Wood.  Revised  by 
the  Venerable  Archdeacon  DENISON.  32mo,  limp  cloth,  is.  6d. 

MILLER,  Edward. — The  History  and  Doctrines  of  Irvingism  ; 
or,  The  so-called  Catholic  and  Apostolic  Church.  2  vols.  Xarge 
post  8vo,  15*. 

The  Church  in  Relation  to  the  State.    Large  crown  Svo, 


Kegan  Paul,  Trench  &  Co.'s  Publications.         17 

MILLS,  Herbert.—  Poverty  and  the  State  ;  or,  Work  for  the  Un 
employed.  An  Inquiry  into  the  Causes  and  Extent  of  Enforced 
Idleness,  with  a  Statement  of  a  Remedy.  Crown  8vo,  6s. 

MITCHELL,  Lucy  Af.—A.  History  of  Ancient  Sculpture.  With 
numerous  Illustrations,  including  6  Plates  in  Phototype.  Super- 
royal  8vo,  42.T. 

MOCKLER,  E. — A  Grammar  of  the  Baloochee  Language,  as 

it  is  spoken  in  Makran  (Ancient  Gedrosia),  in  the  Persia-Arabic 
and  Roman  characters.     Fcap.  Svo,  55. 

MOIIL,  Julius  and  Mary. — Letters  and  Recollections  of.  By 
M.  C.  M.  SIMPSON.  With  Portraits  and  Two  Illustrations.  Demy 
8vo,  15.?. 

MOLESIVORTH,  Rev.  W.  Nassau,  M.A.— History  of  the  Church 
of  England  from  166O.  Large  crown  Svo,  7s.  6rf. 

MORELL,J.  R.— Euclid  Simplified  in  Method  and  Language. 
Being  a  Manual  of  Geometry.  Compiled  from  the  most  important 
French  Works,  approved  by  the  University  of  Paris  and  tne 
Minister  of  Public  Instruction.  Fcap.  8vo,  2.'.  6rf. 

MORGAN,  C.  L/oycf.—The  Springs  of  Conduct.  An  Essay  in 
Evolution.  Large  crown  8vo,  cloth,  "js.  6d. 

MORISON,  J.  Cotter.  —  The  Service  of  Man  :  an  Essay  towards  the 
Religion  of  the  Future.  Second  Edition.  Demy  Svo,  10^.  6J. 

MORSE,  E.  S.,  Ph.D.—  First  Book  of  Zoology.  With  numerous 
Illustrations.  New  and  Cheaper  Edition.  Crown  Svo,  is.  M. 

My  Lawyer  :  A  Concise  Abridgment  of  the  Laws  of  England.  By  a 
Barrister-at-Law.  Crown  Svo,  6s.  6d. 

NELSOA7,  J.  //.,  M.A.— A  Prospectus  of  the  Scientific  Study 

of  the  Hindu  Law.     Demy  Svo,  9^. 
Indian  Usage  and  Judge-made  Law  in  Madras.     Demy 

Svo,  12s. 

NEWMAN,  Cardinal. — Characteristics  from  the  Writings  of. 
Being  Selections  from  his  various  Works.  Arranged  with  the 
Author's  personal  Approval.  Seventh  Edition.  With  Portrait. 
Crown  Svo,  6s. 

%*  A  Portrait  of  Cardinal  Newman,  mounted  for  framing,  can 
be  had,  2s.  6J. 

XEIVMAN,  Francis  W'illiam. — Essays  on  Diet.  Small  crown  Svo, 
cloth  limp,  2s. 

New  Social  Teachings.     By  POLITICUS.     Small  crown  Svo,  5-r. 

A7COLS,  Arthur,  F.G.S.,  F.R.G.S.— Chapters  from  the  Physical 
History  of  the  Earth  :  an  Introduction  to  Geology  and 
Palaeontology.  With  numerous  Illustrations.  Crown  Svo,  t,s. 

NIHILL,  Rn:  H.  D.—  The  Sisters  of  St.  Mary  at  the  Cross  : 
Sisters  of  the  Poor  and  their  Work.  Crown  Svo,  2s.  64. 


1 8  A  List  of 

NOEL,  The  Hon.  Roden. — Essays  on  Poetry  and  Poets.  Demy 
8vo,  I2s. 

A^OPS,  Marianne. — Class  Lessons  on  Euclid.  Part  I.  containing 
the  First  Two  Books  of  the  Elements.  Crown  Svo,  2s.  6d. 

Nuces :  EXERCISES  ON  THE  SYNTAX  OF  THE  PUBLIC  SCHOOL  LATIN 

PRIMER.     New  Edition  in  Three  Parts.     Crown  8vo,  each  u. 
%*  The  Three  Parts  can  also  be  had  bound  together,  y. 

OATES,  Frank,  F.R.G.S.— Matabele  Land  and  the  Victoria 
Falls.  A  Naturalist's  Wanderings  in  the  Interior  of  South 
Africa.  Edited  by  C.  G.  OATES,  B.A.  With  numerous  Illustra 
tions  and  4  Maps.  Demy  8vo,  215. 

O'BRIEN,  R.  Barry. — Irish  Wrongs  and  English  Remedies, 
with  other  Essays.  Crown  8vo,  $s. 

OGLE,  Anna  C. — A  Lost  Love.     Small  crown  8vo,  2s.  6d. 

O1  HEAR  A,  Kathleen.—  Henri  Perreyve  and  his  Counsels  to 
the  Sick.  Small  crown  8vo,  $s. 

One  and  a  Half  in  Norway.  A  Chronicle  of  Small  Beer.  By 
Either  and  Both.  Small  crown  Svo,  3^.  6d. 

O'NEIL,  the  late  Rev.  Lord. — Sermons.  With  Memoir  and  Portrait. 
Crown  Svo,  6s. 

Essays  and  Addresses.     Crown  Svo,  55. 

OTTLEY,  H.  Bickersteth.—Tlie  Great  Dilemma.  Christ  His  Own 
Witness  or  His  Own  Accuser.  Six  Lectures.  Second  Edition. 
Crown  Svo,  3-r.  6d. 

Our  Public  Schools — Eton,  Harrow,  "Winchester,  Rugby, 
Westminster,  Marlborough,  The  Charterhouse. 
Crown  SVG,  6s. 

PADGHAM,  Richard.— In  the  Midst  of  Life  we  are  in  Death. , 
Crown  Svo,  $s. 

PALMER,  the  late  William.— Notes  of  a  Visit  to  Russia  in 
1840-1841.  Selected  and  arranged  by  JOHN  H.  CARDINAL 
NEWMAN,  with  Portrait.  Crown  Svo,  8s.  6d. 

Early  Christian  Symbolism.  A  Series  of  Compositions  from 
Fresco  Paintings,  Glasses,  and  Sculptured  Sarcophagi.  Edited 
by  the  Rev.  Provost  NORTHCOTE,  D.D.,  and  the  Rev.  Canon 
BROWNLOW,  M.A.  With  Coloured  Plates,  folio,  42s.,  or  with 
Plain  Plates,  folio,  2$s. 

Parchment  Library.  Choicely  Printed  on  hand-made  paper,  limp 
parchment  antique  or  cloth,  6s.  ;  vellum,  7s.  6d.  each  volume. 

The  Poetical  "Works  of  John  Milton.     2  vols. 
Chaucer's  Canterbury  Tales.     Edited  by  A.  W.   POLLARD. 

2  Vols. 


Kegan  Paul,  Trench  &  Co.'s  Publications.         19 


Parchment  Library — continued. 

Letters  and  Journals  of  Jonathan  Swift.  Selected  and 
edited,  with  a  Commentary  and  Notes,  by  STANLEY  LANE  POOLE. 

De  Quincey's  Confessions  of  an  English  Opium  Eater. 
Reprinted  from  the  First  Edition.  Edited  by  RICHARD  GARNETT. 

The  Gospel  according  to  Matthew,   Mark,  and  Luke. 

Selections  from  the  Prose  Writings  of  Jonathan  Swift. 
With  a  Preface  and  Notes  by  STANLEY  LANE- POOLE  and 
Portrait. 

English  Sacred  Lyrics. 

Sir  Joshua  Reynolds's  Discourses.  Edited  by  EDMUND 
GOSSE. 

Selections  from  Milton's  Prose  Writings.  Edited  by 
ERNEST  MYERS. 

The  Book  of  Psalms.  Translated  by  the  Rev.  Canon  T.  K. 
CHEYNE,  M.A.,  D.D. 

The  Vicar  of  Wakefield.  With  Preface  and  Notes  by  AUSTIN 
DOBSON. 

English  Comic  Dramatists.     Edited  by  OSWALD  CRAWFURD. 
English  Lyrics. 

The  Sonnets  of  John  Milton.  Edited  by  MARK  PATTISON, 
With  Portrait  after  Vertue. 

French  Lyrics.  Selected  and  Annotated  by  GEORGE  SAINTS- 
BURY.  \Vith  a  Miniature  Frontispiece  designed  and  etched  by 
H.  G.  Glindoni. 

Fables  by  Mr.  John  Gay.  With  Memoir  by  AUSTIN  DOBSON, 
and  an  Etched  Portrait  from  an  unfinished  Oil  Sketch  by  Sir 
Godfrey  Kneller. 

Select  Letters  of  Percy  Bysshe  Shelley.  Edited,  with  an 
Introduction,  by  RICHARD  GARNETT. 

The  Christian  Year.  Thoughts  in  Verse  for  the  Sundays  and 
Holy  Days  throughout  the  Year.  With  Miniature  Portrait  of  the 
Rev.  J.  Keble,  after  a  Drawing  by  G.  Richmond,  R.A. 

Shakspere's  Works.     Complete  in  Twelve  Volumes. 

Eighteenth  Century  Essays.  Selected  and  Edited  by  AUSTIN 
DOBSON.  With  a  Miniature  Frontispiece  by  R.  Caldecott. 

Q.  Horati  Flacci  Opera.  Edited  by  F.  A.  CORNISH,  Assistant 
Master  at  Eton.  With  a  Frontispiece  after  a  design  by  L.  Alma 
Tadema,  etched  by  Leopold  Lowenstam. 

Edgar  Allan  Poe's  Poems.  With  an  Essay  on  his  Poetry  by 
ANDREW  LANG,  and  a  Frontispiece  by  Linlcy  Sambourne. 


2o  A  List  of 

Parchment  Library — continued. 

Shakspere's  Sonnets.  Edited  by  EDWARD  DOWDEN.  With  a 
Frontispiece  etched  by  Leopold  Lowenstam,  after  the  Death 
Mask. 

English  Odes.  Selected  by  EDMUND  GOSSE.  With  Frontis 
piece  on  India  paper  by  Hamo  Thornycroft,  A.R.A. 

Of  the  Imitation  of  Christ.  By  THOMAS  A  KEMPIS.  A 
revised  Translation.  With  Frontispiece  on  India  paper,  from  a 
Design  by  W.  B.  Richmond. 

Poems  :  Selected  from  PE.RCY  BYSSHE  SHELLEY.  Dedicated  to 
Lady  Shelley.  With  a  Preface  by  RICHARD  GARNETT  and  a 
Miniature  Frontispiece. 

PARSLOE,  Joseph.— Our  Railways.  Sketches,  Historical  and 
Descriptive.  With  Practical  Information  as  to  Fares  and  Rates, 
etc.,  and  a  Chapter  on  Railway  Reform.  Crown  8vo,  6s. 

PASCAL,  Blaise. — The  Thoughts  of.  Translated  from  the  Text  of 
Auguste  Molinier,  by  C.  KEGAN  PAUL.  Large  crown  8vo,  with 
Frontispiece,  printed  on  hand-made  paper,  parchment  antique,  or 
cloth,  125.  ;  vellum,  15^. 

PAUL,  Alexander. — Short  Parliaments.  A  History  of  the  National 
Demand  for  frequent  General  Elections.  Small  crown  8vo,  y.  6d. 

PAUL,  C.  A"<?§vztt.— Biographical  Sketches,  Printed  on  hand-made 
paper,  bound  in  buckram.  Second  Edition.  Crown  8vo,  Js.  6d. 

PEARSON,  Rev.  S. — Week-day  Living.  A  Book  for  Young  Men 
and  Women.  Second  Edition.  Crown  8vo,  $s. 

PENRICE,  Major  J.—  Arabic  and  English  Dictionary  of  the 
Koran.  410,  2is. 

PESCHEL,  Dr.    Oscar.— The  Races  of  Man  and  their  Geo- 

graphical    Distribution.      Second   Edition.     Large  crown 

8vo,  9.5-. 
PIDGEON,  D. — An  Engineer's  Holiday  ;  ois  Notes  of  a  Round 

Trip  from  Long,  o    to  o°.      New  and  Cheaper  Edition.     Large 

crown  8vo,  "js.  6d. 
Old  'World  Questions  and  New  World  Answers.   Second 

Edition.     Large  crown  8vo,  "js.  6d. 

Plain  Thoughts  for  Men.  Eight  Lectures  delivered  at  Forester's 
Hall,  Clerkenwell,  during  the  London  Mission,  1884.  Crown 
8vo,  cloth,  is.  6d ;  paper  covers,  is. 

PRICE,  Prof.  Bonamy.  —  Chapters  on  Practical  Political 
Economy.  Being  the  Substance  of  Lectures  delivered  before 
the  University  of  Oxford.  New  and  Cheaper  Edition.  Crown 
8vo,  5-r. 

Prig's  Bede  ".  the  Venerable  Bede,  Expurgated,  Expounded,  and  ExJ 
posed.  By  The  Prig.  Second  Edition.  Fcap.  8vo,  3*.  6tf. 


Kegan  Paul,  Treiick  &  Co.'s  Publications.         21 

Pulpit  Commentary,  The.  (Old  Testament  Series.)  Edited  by  the 
Rev.  J.  S.  EXELL,  M.A.,  and  the  Very  Rev.  Dean  H.  D.  M. 
SPENCE,  M.A.,  D.D. 

Genesis.  By  the  Rev.  T.  WHITELAW,  D.D.  With  Homilies  by 
the  Very  Rev.  J.  F.  MONTGOMERY,  D.D. ,  Rev.  Prof.  R.  A. 
REDFORD,  M.A.,  LL.B.,  Rev.  F.  HASTINGS,  Rev.  W. 
ROBERTS,  M.A.  An  Introduction  to  the  Study  of  the  Old 
Testament  by  the  Venerable  Archdeacon  FAKRAR,  D.D.,  F.R.S. ; 
and  Introductions  to  the  Pentateuch  by  the  Right  Rev.  H.  COT- 
TERILL,  D.D.,  and  Rev.  T.  WHITELAW,  M.A.  Eighth  Editien. 
I  vol.,  i$s. 

Exodus.  By  the  Rev.  Canon  RAWLINSOX.  With  Homilies  by 
Rev.  J.  ORR,  Rev.  D.  YOUNG,  B.A.,  Rev.  C.  A.  GOODHAKT, 
Rev.  J.  URQUHART,  and  the  Rev.  H.  T.  ROHJOIINS.  Fourth 
Edition.  2  vols.,  iSs. 

Leviticus.  By  the  Rev.  Prebendary  MEYRICK,  M.A.  With 
Introductions  by  the  Rev.  R.  COLLINS,  Rev.  Professor  A.  CAVE, 
and  Homilies  by  Rev.  Prof.  REDFORD,  LL.B.,  Rev.  J.  A. 
MACDONALD,  Rev.  W.  CLARKSON,  B.A.,  Rev.  S.  R.  ALDRIDGE, 
LL.B.,  and  Rev.  McCHEYNE  EDGAR.  Fourth  Edition.  15^. 

Numbers.  By  the  Rev.  R.  WINTKKBOTHAM,  LL.B.  With 
Homilies  by  the  Rev.  Professor  W.  BINNIE,  D.D.,  Rev.  E.  S. 
PROUT,  M.A.,  Rev.  D.  YOUNG,  Rev.  J.  WAITE,  and  an  Intro 
duction  by  the  Rev.  THOMAS  WHITELAW,  M.A.  Fifth 
Edition.  15^-. 

Deuteronomy.  By  the  Rev.  W.  L.  ALEXANDER,  D.D.  With 
Homilies  by  Rev.  C.  CLEMANCE,  D.D. ,  Rev.  J.  ORR,  B.D., 
Rev.  R.  M.  EDGAR,  M.A.,  Rev.  D.  DAVIES,  M.A.  Fourth 
edition.  15^. 

Joshua.  By  Rev.  J.  J.  LIAS,  M.A.  With  Homilies  by  Rev. 
S.  R.  ALDRIDGE,  LL.B.,  Rev.  R.  GLOVER,  REV.  E.  DE 
PRESSENSE,  D.D.,  Rev.  J.  WAITE,  B.A.,  Rev.  W.  F.  ADENEY, 
M.A.  ;  and  an  Introduction  by  the  Rev.  A.  PLUMMER,  M.A. 
Fifth  Edition.  12s.  6d. 

Judges  and  Ruth.  By  the  Bishop  of  BATH  and  WELLS,  and 
Rev.  T.  MORISON,  D.D.  With  Homilies  by  Rev.  A.  F.  MUIK, 
M.A.,"  Rev.  W.  F.  ADENEY,  M.A.,  Rev.  W.  M.  STATHAM,  and 
Rev.  Professor  J.  THOMSON,  M.A.  Fifth  Edition,  los.  6</. 

1  Samuel.  By  the  Very  Rev.  R.  P.  SMITH,  D.D.  With  Homilies 
by  Rev.  DONALD  PHASER,  D.D.,  Rev.  Prof.  CHAPMAN,  and 
Rev.  B.  DALE.  Sixth  Edition.  15^. 

1  Kings.  By  the  Rev.  JOSEPH  HAMMOND,  LL.B.  With  Homilies 
by  the  Rev.  E.  DE  PRESSENSE,  D.D.,  Rev.  J.  WAITE,  B.A., 
Rev.  A.  ROWLAND,  LL.B.,  Rev.  J.  A.  MACDONALD,  and  Rev. 
J.  URQUHART.  Fifth  Edition.  155. 


22  A  List  of 

Pulpit  Commentary,  The — continued. 

1  Chronicles.  By  the  Rev.  Prof.  P.  C.  BARKER,  M.A.,  LL.B. 
With  Homilies  by  Rev.  Prof.  J.  R.  THOMSON,  M.A.,  Rev.  R. 
TUCK,  B.A.,  Rev.  W.  CLARKSON,  B.A.,  Rev.  F.  WHITFIELD, 
M.A.,  and  Rev.  RICHARD  GLOVER.  15.5-. 

Ezra,  Nehemiah,  and  Esther.  By  Rev.  Canon  G.  RAWLINSON, 
M.A.  With  Homilies  by  Rev.  Prof.  J.  R.  THOMSON,  M.A.,  Rev. 
Prof.  R.  A.  REDFORD,  LL.B.,  M.A.,  Rev.  W.  S.  LEWIS,  M.A., 
Rev.  J.  A.  MACDONALD,  Rev.  A.  MACKENNAL,  B.A.,  Rev.  W. 
CLARKSON,  B.A.,  Rev.  F.  HASTINGS,  Rev.  W.  DINWIDDIE, 
LL.B.,  Rev.  Prof.  ROWLANDS,  B.A.,  Rev.  G.  WOOD,  B.A., 
Rev.  Prof.  P.  C.  BARKER,  M.A.,  LL.B.,  and  the  Rev.  J.  S. 
EXELL,  M.A.  Sixth  Edition.  I  vol.,  I2s.  6d. 

Isaiah.  By  the  Rev.  Canon  G.  RAWLINSON,  M.A.  With  Homilies 
by  Rev.  Prof.  E.  JOHNSON,  M.A.,  Rev.  W.  CLARKSON,  B.A., 
Rev.  W.  M.  STATHAM,  and  Rev.  R.  TUCK,  B.A.  Second 
Edition.  2  vols.,  15.?.  each. 

Jeremiah.  (Vol.  I.)  By  the  Rev.  Canon  T.  K.  CHEYNE,  M.A., 
D.D.  With  Homilies  by  the  Rev.  W.  F.  ADENEY,  M.A.,  Rev. 
A.  F.  MUIR,  M.A.,  Rev.  S.  CONWAY,  B.A.,  Rev.  J.  WAITE, 
B.A.,  and  Rev.  D.  YOUNG,  B.A.  Third  Edition.  15^. 

Jeremiah  (Vol.  II.)  and  Lamentations.  By  Rev.  T.  K. 
CHEYNE,  M.A.  With  Homilies  by  Rev.  Prof.  J.  R.  THOMSON, 
M.A.,  Rev.  W.  F.  ADENEY,  M.A.,  Rev.  A.  F.  MUIR,  M.A., 
Rev.  S.  CONWAY,  B.A.,  Rev.  D.  YOUNG,  B.A.  155. 

Hosea  and  Joel.  By  the  Rev.  Prof.  J.  J.  GIVEN,  Ph.D.,  D.D. 
With  Homilies  by  the  Rev.  Prof.  J.  R.  THOMSON,  M.A.,  Rev. 
A.  ROWLAND,  B.A.,  LL.B.,  Rev.  C.  JERDAN,  M.A.,  LL.B., 
Rev.  J.  ORR,  M.A.,  B.D.,  and  Rev.  D.  THOMAS,  D.D.  155. 

Pulpit  Commentary,  The.     (New  Testament  Series.) 

St.  Mark,  By  Very  Rev.  E.  BICKERSTETH,  D.D.,  Dean  of  Lich- 
field.  With  Homilies  by  Rev.  Prof.  THOMSON,  M.A.,  Rev.  Prof. 
J.  J.  GIVEN,  Ph.D.,  D.D.,  Rev.  Prof.  JOHNSON,  M.A.,  Rev.  A. 
ROWLAND,  B.A.,  LL.B.,  Rev.  A.  MUIR,  and  Rev.  R.  GREEN. 
Fifth  Edition.  2  vols.,  215. 

The  Acts  of  the  Apostles.  By  the  Bishop  of  BATH  and  WELLS. 
With  Homilies  by  Rev.  Prof.  P.  C.  BARKER,  M.A.,  LL.B.,  Rev. 
Prof.  E.  JOHNSON,  M.A.,  Rev.  Prof.  R.  A.  REDFORD,  LL.B., 
Rev.  R.  TUCK,  B.A.,  Rev.  W.  CLARKSON,  B.A.  Third  Edition. 
2  vols.,  2is. 

1  Corinthians.  By  the  Ven.  Archdeacon  FARRAR,  D.D.  With 
Homilies  by  Rev.  Ex-Chancellor  LIPSCOMB,  LL.D.,  Rev. 
DAVID  THOMAS,  D.D.,  Rev.  D.  FRASER,  D.D.,  Rev.  Prof. 
J.  R.  THOMSON,  M.A.,  Rev.  J.  WAITE,  B.A.,  Rev.  R.  TUCK, 
B.A.,  Rev.  E.  HURNDALL,  M.A.,  and  Rev.  H.  BREMNER,  B.D. 
Third  Edition.  I  $s. 


Kegan  Paul,  Trench  &  Co.'s  Publications.         23 

Pulpit  Commentary,  The — continued. 

2  Corinthians  and  Galatians.  By  the  Yen.  Archdeacon 
FARRAR,  D.D.,  and  Rev.  Prebendary  E.  HUXTABLE.  With 
Homilies  by  Rev.  Ex-Chancellor  LIPSCOMB,  LL.D.,  Rev.  DAVID 
THOMAS,  D.D.,  Rev.  DONALD  FRASER,  D.D.,  Rev.  R.  TUCK, 
B.A.,  Rev.  E.  HURNDALL,  M.A.,  Rev.  Prof.  J.  R.  THOMSON, 
M.A.,  Rev.  R.  FINLAYSON,  B.A.,  Rev.  W.  F.  ADENEY,  M.A., 
Rev.  R.  M.  EDGAR,  M.A.,  and  Rev.  T.  CROSKERY,  D.D.  2U. 

Ephesians,  Philippians,  and  Colossians.  By  the  Rev.  Prof. 
W.  G.  BLAIKIE,  D.D.,  Rev.  15.  C.  CAFFIN,  M.A.,  and  Rev.  G. 
G.  FINDLAY,  B.A.  With  Homilies  by  Rev.  D.  THOMAS,  D.D., 
Rev.  R.  M.  EDGAR,  M.A.,  Rev.  R.  FINLAYSON,  B.A.,  Rev. 
W.  F.  ADENEY,  M.A.,  Rev.  Prof.  T.  CROSKERY,  D.D.,  Rev. 
E.  S.  PROUT,  M.A.,  Rev.  Canon  VERNON  HUTTON,  and 
Rev.  U.  R.  THOMAS,  D.D.  Second  Edition.  2is. 

Thessalonians,  Timothy,  Titus,  and  Philemon.  By  the 
Bishop  of  Bath  and  Wells,  Rev.  Dr.  GI.OAG  anil  Rev.  Dr.  EALES. 
With  Homilies  by  the  Rev.  B.  C.  CAFFIN,  M.A.,  Rev.  R. 
FINLAYSON,  B.A.,  Rev.  Prof.  T.  CROSKERY,  D.D.,  Rev.  W.  F. 
ADENEY,  M.A.,  Rev.  W.  M.  STATHAM,  and  Rev.  D.  THOMAS, 
D.D.  i  ST. 

Hebrews  and  James.  By  the  Rev.  J.  BARMBY,  D.D.,  and  Rev 
Prebendary  E.  C.  S.  GIBSON,  M.A.  With  Homiletics  by  the 
Rev.  C.  JERDAN,  M.A.,  LL.B.,  and  Rev.  Prebendary  E.  C.  S. 
GIBSON.  And  Homilies  by  the  Rev.  W.  JONES,  Rev.  C.  NEW, 
Rev.  D.  YOUNG,  B.A.,  Rev.  J.  S.  BRIGHT,  Rev.  T.  F.  LOCKYER, 
B.A.,  and  Rev.  C.  JERDAN,  M.A.,  LL.B.  Second  Edition.  i$s. 
JUSEY,  Dr. — Sermons  for  the  Church's  Seasons  from 
Advent  to  Trinity.  Selected  from  the  Published  Sermons 
of  the  late  EDWARD  BOUVERIE  PUSEY,  D.D.  Crown  Svo,  5^. 

RANKE,  Leopold  von. — Universal  History.     The  oldest  Historical 

Group  of  Nations  and  the  Greeks.     Edited  by  G.  W.  PROTHERO. 

Demy  Svo,  i6s. 
RENDELL,    J.    AT.— Concise    Handbook    of     the    Island    of 

Madeira.    With  Plan  of  Funchal  and  Map  of  the  Island.    Fcap. 

Svo,  is.  6d. 

REVELL,  IV.  F.— Ethical  Forecasts.     Crown  Svo. 
REYNOLDS,   Rev.  J.    W.— The  Supernatural    in   Nature.     A 

Verification  by  Free  Use  of  Science,      Third  Edition,  Revised 

and  Enlarged.     Demy  Svo,  i^s. 

The  Mystery  of  Miracles.  Third  and  Enlarged  Edition. 
Crown  Svo,  6s. 

The  Mystery  of  the  Universe  our  Common  Faith.  Demy 
Svo,  14?. 

The  World  to  Come :  Immortality  a  Physical  Fact.  Crown 
Svo,  6s. 


24  A  List  of 

RLBOT,  Prof.  Th—  Heredity :  A  Psychological  Study  of  its  Phenomena, 
its  Laws,  its  Causes,  and  its  Consequences.  Second  Edition. 
Large  crown  Svo,  9,?. 

ROBERTSON,  The  late  Rev.  F.  W.,  M.A.—Life  and  Letters  of. 
Edited  by  the  Rev.  STOPFORD  BROOKE,  M.A. 

I.  Two  vols.,  uniform  with  the  Sermons.     With  Steel  Portrait, 

Crown  Svo,  Js.  6d. 

II.   Library  Edition,  in  Demy  Svo,  with  Portrait.      I2s. 
III.  A  Popular  Edition,  in  I  vol.     Crown  Svo,  6.r. 

ROBERTSON,  The  late  Rev.  F.  W.,  M.A. —continued. 

Sermons.     Four  Series.     Small  crown  Svo,  %s.  6d.  each. 

The  Human  Race,  and  other  Sermons.  Preached  at  Chelten 
ham,  Oxford,  and  Brighton.  New  and  Cheaper  Edition.  Small 
crown  Svo,  3^.  6d. 

Notes  on  Genesis.    New  and  Cheaper  Edition.    Small  crown  Svo, 

Expository    Lectures    on    St.    Paul's    Epistles    to    the 

Corinthians.     A  New  Edition.     Small  crown  Svo,  5.?. 
Lectures  and  Addresses,  with  other  Literary  Remains.     A  New 

Edition.     Small  crown  Svo,  $s. 
An  Analysis  of  Tennyson's  "  In  Memoriam."    (Dedicated 

by  Permission  to  the  Poet-Laureate.)     Fcap.  Svo,  2s. 
The  Education  of  the  Human  Race.     Translated  from  the 
German  of  GOTTHOLD  EPHRAIM  LESSING.     Fcap.  Svo,  zs.  6d. 
The  above  Works  can  also  be  had,  bound  in  half  morocco. 
%*  A  Portrait  of  the  late  Rev.  F.  W.  Robertson,  mounted  for  framing, 

can  be  had,  2s.  6d. 

ROMANES,  G.  J.  —  Mental  Evolution  in  Animals.  With  a 
Posthumous  Essay  on  Instinct  by  CHARLES  DARWIN,  F.R.S. 
Demy  Svo,  12s. 

ROOSEVELT,    Theodore.      Hunting    Trips    of    a    Ranchman. 

Sketches   of  Sport   on   the   Northern  Cattle   Plains.     With   26 

Illustrations.     Royal  Svo,  iSs. 

ROSMINI  SERB  ATI,  Antonio.—  Life.     By  the  REV.  W.  LOCKHART. 

Second  Edition.     2  vols.     With  Portraits.     Crown  Svo,  12s. 

Rosmini's   Origin   of    Ideas.      Translated  from  the   Fifth   Italian 

Edition  of  the  Nuovo  Saggio  Still'  origine  delle  idee.     3  vols. 

Demy  Svo,  cloth,  ios.  6d.  each. 
Rosmini's  Psychology.     3  vols.     Demy  Svo  [Vols.   I.  and  II.  now 

ready],  ios.  6d.  each. 
ROSS,  Janet. — Italian   Sketches.      With  14   full-page   Illustrations. 

Crown  Svo,  Js.  6d. 

RULE,  Martin,  M.A. — The  Life  and  Times  of  St.  Anselm, 
Archbishop  of  Canterbury  and  Primate  of  the 
Britains.  2  vols.  Demy  Svo,  32^. 


Kegan  Paul,   Trench  &  Co.'s  Publications.         25 

SAMUELL,  Richard. — Seven,  the  Sacred  Number  :  Its  use  in 
Scripture  and  its  Application  to  Biblical  Criticism.  Crown  8vo, 
IO.T.  6d. 

SAYCE,  Rtf.  Archibald  Henry. — Introduction  to  the  Science  of 
Language.  2  vols.  Second  Edition.  Large  post  8vo,  2is. 

SCOONES,  W.  Baptiste.—ToViT  Centuries  of  English  Letters  : 
A  Selection  of  350  Letters  by  150  Writers,  from  the  Period  of  the 
Paston  Letters  to  the  Present  Time.  Third  Edition.  Large 
crown  8vo,  6s. 

SEE,  Prof.  Germain. — Bacillary  Phthisis  of  the  Lungs.  Trans 
lated  and  edited  for  English  Practitioners  by  WILLIAM  HENRY 
WEDDELL,  M.R.C.S.  Demy  8vo,  los.  6d. 

Shakspere's  "Works.  The  Avon  Edition,  12  vols.,  fcap.  Svo,  cloth, 
iSs.  ;  in  cloth  box,  2is.  ;  bound  in  6  vols.,  cloth,  i$s. 

Shakspere's    "Works,  an  Index  to.     By  EVANGELINE  O'CONNOR. 

Crown  Svo,  $s. 
SHELLEY,    Percy  Bysshe.—T-Aie.      By   EDWARD    DOWDEN,   LL.D. 

2  vols.     With  Portraits.     Demy  Svo,  36^. 

SH2LLITO,  Rev.  Joseph. — "Womanhood  :  its  Duties,  Temptations, 
and  Privileges.  A  Book  for  Young  Women.  Third  Edition. 
Crown  Svo,  3^.  6</. 

Shooting,  Practical  Hints.  Being  a  Treatise  on  the  Shot  Gun  and 
its  Management.  By  "20  Bore."  With  55  Illustrations.  Demy 
Svo,  12s. 

Sister  Augustine,  Superior  of  the  Sisters  of  Charity  at  the  St. 
Johannis  Hospital  at  Bonn.  Authorized  Translation  by  HANS 
THARAU,  from  the  German  "Memorials  of  AMALIE  VON 
LASAULX."  Cheap  Edition.  Large  crown  Svo,  qs.  6d. 

SA'INNEK,  James. — A  Memoir.  By  the  Author  of  "Charles  Lowder. " 
With  a  Preface  by  the  Rev.  Canon  CARTER,  and  Portrait. 
Large  crown,  "js.  6d. 

%*  Also  a  cheap  Edition.    With  Portrait.    Fourth  Edition.    Crown 
Svo,  35.  6d. 

SMEATON,  D.  Mackenzie.  —  The  Loyal  Karens  of  Burma. 
Crown  Svo,  4^.  6d. 

SMITH,  Edward,  M.D.,  LL.B.,  F.A'. S.— Tubercular  Consump 
tion  in  its  Early  and  Remediable  Stages.  Second 
Edition.  Crown  Svo,  6s. 

SMITH,  Sir  W.  Cusack,  Bart.—QMV  "War  Ships.  A  Naval  Essay. 
Crown  Svo,  5^. 

Spanish  Mystics.     By  the  Editor  of  "  Many  Voices."     Crown  Svo,  5^. 

Specimens  of  English  Prose  Style  from  Malory  to  Ma- 
caulay.  Selected  and  Annotated,  with  an  Introductory  Essay, 
by  GEORGE  SAINTSBURV.  Large  crown  8vo,  printed  on  hand 
made  paper,  parchment  antique  or  cloth,  12s.  ;  vellum,  15*. 


26  A  List  of 

SPEDDING,  James. — Reviews  and  Discussions,  Literary, 
Political,  and  Historical  not  relating  to  Bacon.  Demy 
8vo,  i2s.  6d. 

Evenings  with  a  Reviewer ;  or,  Macaulay  and  Bacon. 
With  a  Prefatory  Notice  by  G.  S.  VENABLES,  Q.C.  2  vols. 
Demy  8vo,  i8j. 

Stray  Papers  on  Education,  and  Scenes  from  School  Life.    By  B.  H. 

Second  Edition.     Small  crown  8vo,  3^.  6d. 
STREATFEILD,  Rev.  G.  S., ^/.^.—Lincolnshire  and  the  Danes. 

Large  crown  8vo,  *js.  6d. 
STRECKER-  WISLICENUS.— Organic  Chemistry.    Translated  and 

Edited,   with   Extensive    Additions,    by   W.    R.    HODGKINSON, 

Ph.D.,  and  A.  J.  GREENAWAY,  F.I.C.     Second  and   cheaper 

Edition.     Demy  8vo,  I2s.  6d. 
Suakin,  1885  ",  being  a  Sketch  of  the  Campaign  of  this  year.     By  an 

Officer  who  was  there.     Second  Edition.     Crown  8vo,  2s.  6d. 
SULLY,    James,    M.A. — Pessimism  :    a   History    and    a   Criticism. 

Second  Edition.     Demy  8vo,  14^. 
Sunshine   and   Sea.     A  Yachting  Visit  to  the  Channel  Islands  and 

Coast  of  Brittany.     With  Frontispiece  from  a  Photograph  and  24 

Illustrations.     Crown  Svo,  6s. 
SWEDENBORG,  Eman.—~Dz  Gultu  et  Amore  Dei  ubi  Agitur 

de  Telluris  ortu,  Paradiso  et  Yivario,  turn  de  Pri- 

mogeniti  Seu  Adami  Nativitate  Infantia,  et  Amore. 

Crown  Svo,  6s. 
On  the  Worship  and  Love  of  God.     Treating  of  the  Birth 

of  the  Earth,    Paradise,   and    the  Abode   of  Living  Creatures. 

Translated  from  the  original  Latin.     Crown  Svo,  TS.  6d. 
Prodromus    Philosophies    Ratiocinantis     de    Infinite, 

et   Causa   Final!  Creationis  :    deque  Mechanismo  Opera- 

tionis  Animse  et  Corporis.     Edidit  THOMAS  MURRAY  GORMAN, 

M.A.     Crown  Svo,  7.?.  6d. 

TACITUS.— The  Agricola.     A  Translation.    Small  crown  8vo,  2s.  6d. 
TARRING,  C.  J.—  A  Practical  Elementary  Turkish  Grammar. 

Crown  Svo,  6s. 
TA  YLOR,  Rev.  Isaac. — The  Alphabet.     An  Account  of  the  Origin 

and   Development    of    Letters.       With    numerous    Tables    and 

Facsimiles.     2  vols.     Demy  Svo,  36^. 
TAYLOR,  Jeremy.— The    Marriage  Ring.      With   Preface,  Notes, 

and  Appendices.    Edited  by  FRANCIS  BURDETT  MONEY  COUTTS. 

Small  crown  Svo,  2s.  6d. 

TAYLOR,  Sedley.  —  Profit  Sharing  between  Capital  and 
Labour.  To  which  is  added  a  Memorandum  on  the  Industrial 
Partnership  at  the  Whitwood  Collieries,  by  ARCHIBALD  and 
HENRY  BRIGGS,  with  remarks  by  SEDLEY  TAYLOR.  Crown  Svo, 
2s.  6d. 


Kcgan  Paul,  Trench  &  Co.'s  Publications.         27 

THOM,  y.  Hamilton.— "Laws  of  Life  after  the  Mind  of  Christ. 
Two  Series.     Crown  Svo,  Js.  6d.  each. 

THOMPSON,  Sirff.—lDiei  in  Relation  to  Age  and  Activity. 
Fcap.  Svo,  cloth,  is.  €>d.  ;  paper  covers,  is. 

TIDMAN,  Paul  /'.—Money  and  Labour,     is.  6d. 

TIPPLE,  Rev.  S.  A. — Sunday  Mornings  at  Norwood.     Prayers 
and  Sermons.     Crown  Svo,  6s. 

TODHUXTER,  Dr.  J.—k.  Study  of  Shelley.     Crown  Svo,  ;j. 

TOLSTOI,  Count  Leo.— Christ's  Christianity.     Translated  from  the 
Russian.     Large  crown  Svo,  "js.  6J. 

TRANT,  William.—  Trade  Unions  :  Their  Origin,  Objects,  and 
Efficacy.     Small  crown  Svo,  is.  6J.  ;  paper  covers,  is. 

TRENCH,  The  late  R.  C.,  Archbishop.—  Notes  on  the  Parables  of 
Our  Lord.     Fourteenth  Edition.     Svo,   12s.     Cheap  Edition, 

•JS.   6:/. 

Notes  on  the  Miracles  of  Our  Lord.  Twelfth  Edition. 
Svo,  12s.  Cheap  Edition,  7*.  6d. 

Studies  in  the  Gospels.     Fifth  Edition,  Revised.     Svo,  IO.T.  6J. 

Brief  Thoughts  and  Meditations  on  Some  Passages  in 
Holy  Scripture.  Third  Edition.  Crown  Svo,  3.5-.  6</. 

Synonyms  of  the  New  Testament.  Tenth  Edition,  En 
larged.  Svo,  12s. 

Sermons  New  and  Old.     Crown  Svo,  6s. 

On  the  Authorized  Version  of  the  New  Testament. 
Second  Edition.  Svo,  "js. 

Commentary  on  the  Epistles  to  the  Seven  Churches  in 
Asia.  Fourth  Edition,  Revised.  Svo,  8s.  6d. 

The  Sermon  on  the  Mount.  An  Exposition  drawn  from  the 
Writings  of  St.  Augustine,  with  an  Essay  on  his  Merits  as  an 
Interpreter  of  Holy  Scripture.  Fourth  Edition,  Enlarged.  Svo, 
los.  6d. 

Shipwrecks  of  Faith.  Three  Sermons  preached  before  the 
University  of  Cambridge  in  May,  1867.  Fcap.  Svo,  2s.  6d. 

Lectures  on  Mediaeval  Church  History.  Being  the  Sub 
stance  of  Lectures  delivered  at  Queen's  College,  London.  Second 
Edition.  Svo,  12s. 

English,  Past  and  Present.  Thirteenth  Edition,  Revised  and 
Improved.  Fcap.  Svo,  55. 

On  the  Study  of  Words.  Nineteenth  Edition,  Revised. 
Fcap.  Svo,  $s. 


28  A  List  of 

TRENCH,  The  late  R.  C.,  Archbishop.— continued. 

Select  Glossary  of  English  "Words  Used  Formerly  in 
Senses  Different  from  the  Present.  Sixth  Edition, 
Revised  and  Enlarged.  Fcap.  8vo,  5^. 

Proverbs  and  Their  Lessons.  Seventh  Edition,  Enlarged. 
Fcap.  8vo,  4^. 

Poems.  Collected  and  Arranged  anew.  Ninth  Edition.  Fcap. 
8vo,  "js.  6d. 

Poems.     Library  Edition.     2  vols.     Small  crown  8vo,  IDJ. 

Sacred  Latin  Poetry.  Chiefly  Lyrical,  Selected  and  Arranged 
for  Use.  Third  Edition,  Corrected  and  Improved.  Fcap.  8vo,  Js. 

A  Household  Book  of  English  Poetry.  Selected  and 
Arranged,  with  Notes.  Fourth  Edition,  Revised.  Extra  fcap. 
8vo,  5.".  6d. 

An  Essay  on  the  Life  and  Genius  of  Calderon.  With 
Translations  from  his  "  Life's  a  Dream"  and  "Great  Theatre  of 
the  World."  Second  Edition,  Revised  and  Improved.  Extra 
fcap.  8vo,  5-r.  6J. 

Gustavus  Adolphus  in  Germany,  and  other  Lectures 
on  the  Thirty  Years'  War.  Third  Edition,  Enlarged. 
Fcap.  8vo,  4s. 

Plutarch  ;  his  Life,  his  Lives,  and  his  Morals.  Second 
Edition,  Enlarged.  Fcap.  8vo,  $s.  6d. 

Remains  of  the  late  Mrs.  Richard  Trench.  Being  Selec 
tions  from  her  Journals,  Letters,  and  other  Papers.  New  and 
Cheaper  Issue.  With  Portrait.  8vo,  6s. 

TUKE,  Daniel  Hack,  M.D.,  F.R.C.P.— Chapters  in  the  History 
of  the  Insane  in  the  British  Isles.  With  Four  Illustra 
tions.  Large  crown  8vo,  I2s. 

TWINING,  Louisa. — Workhouse  Visiting  and  Management 
during  Twenty-Five  Years.  Small  crown  8vo,  2s. 

VAUGHAN,  H.  Halford. — New  Readings  and  Renderings  of 
Shakespeare's  Tragedies.  3  vols.  DemySvo,  i2s.  6d.  each. 

VICARY,  J.  Fulford.-Sa.ga.  Time.  With  Illustrations.  Crown  Svo, 
7-r.  6d. 

VOGT,  Lieut.-Col.  Hermann.— The  Egyptian  War  of  1882. 
A  translation.  With  Map  and  Plans.  Large  crown  Svo,  6s. 

VOLCKXSOM,  E.  W.  v.—  Catechism  of  Elementary  Modern, 
Chemistry.  Small  crown  Svo,  3^. 

WALPOLE,  Ckas.  George.—  A  Short  History  of  Ireland  from  the 
Earliest  Times  to  the  Union  with  Great  Britain. 
With  5  Maps  and  Appendices.  Third  Edition.  Crown  Svo,  6s.  ] 


Kegan  Paul,  Trench  &  Go's  Publications.         29 

WARD,  Wilfrid.—  The  Wish  to  Believe.  A  Discussion  Concern- 
ing  the  Temper  of  Mind  in  which  a  reasonable  Man  should 
undertake  Religious  Inquiry.  Small  crown  8vo,  55. 

WARD,  William  George,  7V/.Z>.— Essays  on  the  Philosophy  of 
Theism.  Edited,  with  an  Introduction,  by  WILFRID  WARD. 
2  vols.  Demy  8vo,  2is. 

WARNER,  Francis,  M.D. — Lectures  on  the  Anatomy  of  Move 
ment.  Crown  8vo,  4^.  6d. 

WARTER,  J.  iy.—An  Old  Shropshire  Oak.     2  vols.     Demy  Svo, 

28j. 

WEDMORE,  Frederick.—  The  Masters  of  Genre  Painting.  With 
Sixteen  Illustrations.  Post  Svo,  "]s.  6J. 

WHITMAN,  Sidney.— Conventional  Cant:  its  Results  and  Remedy. 
Crown  Svo,  6s. 

WHITNEY,  Prof.  William  Dwighl.  —  Essentials  of  English 
Grammar,  for  the  Use  of  Schools.  Second  Edition.  Crown 
Svo,  3-y.  6d. 

WHITWORTH,  George  Clifford.— hn  Anglo-Indian  Dictionary  : 

a  Glossary  of  Indian  Terms  used  in  English,  and  of  such  English 
or  other  Non-Indian  Terms  as  have  obtained  special  meanings  in 
India.  Demy  Svo,  cloth,  \2s. 

WILSON,  Lieut. -Col.  C.  T.— The  Duke  of  Berwick,  Marshal 
of  France,  1702-1734.  Demy  Svo,  15^. 

WILSON,  Mrs.  R.  F.—  The  Christian  Brothers.  Their  Origin  and 
Work.  With  a  Sketch  of  the  Life  of  their  Founder,  the  Ven. 
JEAN  BAPTISTE,  de  la  Salle.  Crown  Svo,  6s. 

WOLTMANN,  Dr.  Alfred,  ami  WOERMANN,  Dr.  Karl—  History 
of  Painting.  With  numerous  Illustrations.  Medium  Svo. 
Vol.  I.  Painting  in  Antiquity  and  the  Middle  Ages.  2S.c.  ; 
bevelled  boards,  gilt  leaves,  30^.  Vol.  II.  The  Painting  of  the 
Renascence.  \2s.  ;  bevelled  boards,  gilt  leaves,  455. 

YOUMANS,  Edward  L.,  M.D.—  A  Class  Book  of  Chemistry,  on 

the  Basis  of  the  New  System.  With  200  Illustrations.  Crown 
Svo,  5*. 

YOUMANS,  Eliza  A.—  First  Book  of  Botany.  Designed  to 
Cultivate  the  Observing  Powers  of  Children.  With  300 
Engravings.  New  and  Cheaper  Edition.  Crown  Svo,  2s.  6d. 

VOL'NG,  Arthur.— Axial  Polarity  of  Man's  Word-Embodied 
Ideas,  and  its  Teaching.  Demy  4to,  155. 


3d  A  List  of 


THE    INTERNATIONAL    SCIENTIFIC    SERIES. 

I.  Forms  of  Water  in  Clouds  and  Rivers,  Ice  and  Glaciers. 

By  J.  Tyndall,  LL.D.,   F.R.S.     With  25  Illustrations.     Ninth 
Edition.     5.5-. 

II.  Physics  and   Politics  ;  or,  Thoughts  on  the  Application  of  the 

Principles  of  "Natural  Selection  "  and  "  Inheritance  "  to  Political 
Society.    By  Walter  Bagehot.     Eighth  Edition,     qs. 

III.  Foods.     By  Edward  Smith,  M.D.,  LL.B.,  F.R.S.     With  numerous 

Illustrations.     Ninth  Edition.     $s. 

IV.  Mind  and  Body  :  the  Theories  and  their  Relation.    By  Alexander 

Bain,  LL.D.     With  Four  Illustrations.     Eighth  Edition.     45. 

V.  The   Study  of   Sociology.      By  ^Herbert   Spencer.      Thirteenth 

Edition.     $s. 

VI.  On  the  Conservation  of  Energy.     By  Balfour  Stewart,  M.A., 

LL.D.,  F.R.S.     With  14  Illustrations.     Seventh  Edition.     $s. 

VII.  Animal  Locomotion  ;  or  Walking,  Swimming,  and  Flying.     By 

J.    B.    Pettigrew,   M.D.,    F.R.S.,  etc.     With  130  Illustrations. 
Third  Edition.     $s. 

VIII.  Responsibility  in  Mental  Disease.     By  Henry  Maudsley, 

M.D.     Fourth  Edition.     55. 

IX.  The  New  Chemistry.     By  Professor  J.   P.  Cooke.    With  31 

Illustrations.     Ninth  Edition.     55. 

X.  The  Science  of  Law.    By  Professor  Sheldon  Amos.    Sixth  Edition. 

5^- 

XI.  Animal  Mechanism  :  a  Treatise  on  Terrestrial  and  Aerial  Loco 

motion.     By   Professor  E.   J.    Marey.     With    117    Illustrations. 
Third  Edition.     5-r. 

XII.  The  Doctrine  of  Descent  and  Darwinism.     By  Professor 

Oscar  Schmidt.     With  26  Illustrations.     Seventh  Edition.     $s. 

XIII.  The  History  of    the  Conflict  between   Religion   and 

Science.     By  J.  W.  Draper,  M.D.,  LL.D.    Twentieth  Edition. 
5* 

XIV.  Fungi  :   their  Nature,  Influences,  Uses,  etc.     By  M.  C.  Cooke, 

M.D.,  LL.D.     Edited  by  the  Rev.  M.  J.  Berkeley,  M.A.,  F.L.S. 
With  numerous  Illustrations.     Third  Edition.     $s. 

XV.  The  Chemical  Effects  of  Light  and  Photography.     By 

Dr.    Hermann  Vogel.     With  loo  Illustrations.     Fourth  Edition. 
5*- 

XVI.  The  Life  and  Growth  of  Language.     By  Professor  William 

Dwight  Whitney.     Fifth  Edition.     55. 


Kegan  Paul,   Trench  &  Cots  Publications.         31 


XVII.  Money   and    the    Mechanism    of    Exchange.    By  \V 

Stanley  Jevons,  M.A.,  F.R.S.     Eighth  Edition.     5*. 

XVIII.  The  Nature  of  Light.     With  a  General  Account  of  Physical 
Optics.     By  Dr.  Eugene  Lommel.     With  188  Illustrations  and  a 
Table  of  Spectra  in  Chromo-lithography.     Fourth  Edition.     55. 

XIX.  Animal  Parasites  and  Messmates.     By  P.  J.  Van  Beneden. 

83  Illustrations.     Third  Edition. 


XX.  Fermentation.      By  Professor  Schiitzenberger.      With  28   Illus 
trations.     Fourth  Edition.     $s. 

,   XXI.  The  Five  Senses  of  Man.     By  Professor  Bernstein.     With 
91  Illustrations.     Fifth  Edition.     5*. 

XXII.  The  Theory  of  Sound  in  its  Relation  to  Music.    By  Pro 

fessor   Pietro   Blaserna.      With   numerous    Illustrations.      Third 
Edition.     5J-. 

XXIII.  Studies  in  Spectrum  Analysis.     By  J.  Norman  Lockyer, 
r.k.b.       \\ith  six   photographic   Illustrations    of   Spectra,   and 
numerous  engravings  on  Wrood.      Fourth  Edition.     6s.  6</. 

XXIV.  A  History  of  the  Growth  of  the  Steam  Engine.    By 

Professor  K.  H.  Thurston.    With  numerous  Illustrations.     Fourth 
Edition.     6s.  6d. 

XXV.  Education  as  a  Science.     By  Alexander  Bain,  LL.D.     sixth 

Edition.     55. 

X  XVI.  The  Human  Species.    By  Professor  A.  cle  Quatrefages.    Fourth 
Edition.     5^. 

XXVII.  Modern  Chromatics.      With  Applications  to  Art  and    In 
dustry.     By  Ogden  N.  Rood.     With   130  original  Illustrations. 
second  Edition.     5;-. 

XXVIII.  The  Crayfish  :  an  Introduction  to  the  Study  of  Zoology.  By 
Professor  T.  H.  Huxley.     With  82  Illustrations.      Fourth  Edition 
5^- 

XXIX.  The  Brain  as  an  Organ  of  Mind.    By  II.  Charlton  Bastian, 
M.D.      \\ithnumerouslllustrations.     Third  Edition.     5^. 

XXX.  The   Atomic   Theory.     By   Prof.    Wurtz.     Translated  by  G 

Clemmshaw,  F.C.S.     Fourth  Edition.     5*. 

XXXI.  The  Natural  Conditions  of  Existence  as  they  affect 
Animal    Life.     By   Karl   Semper.     With    2   Maps   and    106 
Woodcuts.     Third  Edition.     5^. 

XXXII.  General  Physiology  of  Muscles  and  Nerves.     By  Prof 
J.  Rosenthal.     Third  Edition.     With  Illustrations.     5,-. 

XXXIII.  Sight:   an   Exposition   of  the   Principles   of  Monocular  and 
Binocular  Vision.     By  Joseph  le  Conte,  LL.D.     Second  Edition 
With  132  Illustrations.     5*. 


32  A  List  of 

XXXIV.  Illusions  :  a  Psychological  Study.     By  James   Sully.     Third 
Edition.     5^. 

XXXV.  Volcanoes  :  what  they  are  and  what  they  teach. 
By   Professor  J.    W.   Judd,    F.R.S.     With   92   Illustrations   on 
Wood.     Third  Edition.     $s. 

XXXVI.  Suicide  :  an  Essay  on  Comparative  Moral  Statistics.     By  Prof. 
H.  Morselli.    Second  Edition.     With  Diagrams.     55. 

XXXVII.  The  Brain   and  its  Functions.      By  J.    Luys.     With 

Illustrations.     Second  Edition.     $s. 

XXXVIII.  Myth  and  Science  :  an  Essay.     By  Tito  Vignoli.     Third 
Edition.     $s. 

XXXIX.  The  Sun.     By  Professor  Young.     With  Illustrations.     Second 
Edition.     5-r. 

XL.  Ants,  Bees,  and  Wasps  :  a  Record  of  Observations  on  the 
Habits  of  the  Social  Hymenoptera.  By  Sir  John  Lubbock,  Bart., 
M.P.  With  5  Chromo-lithographic  Illustrations.  Eighth  Edition. 

5*. 

XLI.  Animal  Intelligence.  By  G.  J.  Romanes,  LL.D.,  F.R.S. 
Fourth  Edition.  5^. 

XLII.  The  Concepts  and  Theories  of  Modern  Physics.  By 
J.  B.  Stallo.  Third  Edition.  55. 

XLIII.  Diseases  of  the  Memory  ;  An  Essay  in  the  Positive  Psycho 
logy.  By  Prof.  Th.  Ribot.  Third  Edition.  5*. 

XLIV.  Man  before  Metals.  By  N.  Joly,  with  148  Illustrations. 
Fourth  Edition.  55. 

XLV.  The  Science  of  Politics.  By  Prof.  Sheldon  Amos.  Third 
Edition.  5.?. 

XLVI.  Elementary  Meteorology.  By  Robert  H.  Scott.  Fourth 
Edition.  With  Numerous  Illustrations.  $s. 

XLVII.  The  Organs  of  Speech  and  their  Application  in  the 
Formation  of  Articulate  Sounds.  By  Georg  Hermann 
Von  Meyer.  With  47  Woodcuts.  $s. 

XLVIII.  Fallacies.  A  View  of  Logic  from  the  Practical  Side.  By 
Alfred  Sidgwick.  Second  Edition.  5^. 

XLIX.  Origin  of  Cultivated   Plants.     By  Alphonse  de  Candolle. 

5'- 
L.  Jelly-Fish,  Star-Fish,  and  Sea-Urchins.     Being  a  Research 

on    Primitive    Nervous    Systems.      By    G.    J.    Romanes.       With 

Illustrations.     $s. 

LI.  The  Common  Sense  of  the  Exact  Sciences.  By  the  late 
William  Kingdon  Clifford.  Second  Edition.  With  100  Figures. 


Kegan  Paul,   Trench  &  Cols  Publications.         33 

LII.  Physical  Expression  :  Its  Modes  and  Principles.  By 
Francis  Warner,  M.D.,  F.R.C.P.,  Hunterian  Professor  of  Com 
parative  Anatomy  and  ^Physiology,  R.C.S.E.  With  5°  Illus 
trations.  5-r. 

LI  1 1.  Anthropoid  Apes.  By  Robert  Hartmnnn.  With  63  Illustra 
tions.  5^. 

LIV.  The  Mammalia  in  their  Relation  to  Primeval  Times. 
By  Oscar  Schmidt.  With  51  Woodcuts.  5.?. 

LV.  Comparative  Literature.    By  H.  Macaulay  Posnett,  LL.D.    5*. 

LVI.  Earthquakes  and  other  Earth  Movements.  By  Prof. 
John  Milne.  With  38  Figures.  Second  Edition.  $s. 

LVII.  Microbes,  Ferments,  and  Moulds.  By  E.  L.  Troue>sait. 
With  107  Illustrations.  55. 

LVIII.  Geographical  and  Geological  Distribution  of  Animal.-:. 
By  Professor  A.  Heilprin.  With  Frontispiece.  5^. 

LIX.  Weather.  A  Popular  Exposition  of  the  Nature  of  Weatlur 
Changes  from  Day  to  Day.  By  the  Hon.  Ralph  Abcrcromby. 
With  96  Illustrations.  5^. 

LX.   Animal  Magnetism.      By  Alfred  Binet  and  Charles  Fere.     $s. 

LXI.  Manual  of  British  Discomycetes,  with  descriptions  of  all  the 
Species  of  Fungi  hitherto  found  in  Britain  included  in  the  Family, 
and  Illustrations  of  the  Genera.  By  William  Phillips,  F.L.S.  $s. 

LXII.  International  Law.  With  Materials  for  a  Code  of  Inter 
national  Law.  By  Professor  Leone  Levi.  5.1'. 

LXIII.  The  Origin  of  Floral  Structures  through  Insect 
Agency.  By  Prof.  G.  Ilenslow. 


MILITARY    WORKS. 

BRACKRNBURY,  Col.  C.  £.,  A1..-/.  —  Military  Handbooks  for 
Regimental  Officers. 

I.  Military  Sketching  and  Reconnaissance.  By  Col. 
F.  J.  Hutchison  and  Major  II.  (>.  M;vt  ireyor.  Fifth 
Edition.  With  15  Plates.  Small  crown  Sv»,  .j  . 

II.  The  Elements  of  Modern  Tactics  Practically 
applied  to  English  Formations.  By  Lieut. -Col. 
Wilkinson  Shaw.  Sixth  Edition.  With  25  Plates  and 
Maps.  Small  crown  8vo,  <)s. 

III.  Field  Artillery.  Its  Equipment,  Organization  and  Tactics. 
By  Major  Sisson  C.  Pratt,  R.A.  With  12  Plates.  Thin't 
Edition.  Small  crown  Svo,  6s. 

L> 


34  ^  List  of 

BRACKENBURY,  Col.  C.  B.,  K.  A. —continued. 

IV.  The   Elements   of   Military   Administration.     First 

Part  :    Permanent   System    of  Administration.       By  Major 
J.  \V.   Buxton.     Small  crown  8vo,  7^.  6d. 

V.  Military   Law :    Its   Procedure  and   Practice.      By  Major 

Sisson  C.   Pratt,   R.A.     Third  Edition.     Small  crown  8vo, 
4s.  6d. 

VI.  Cavalry  in  Modern  War.     By  Col.  F.  Chenevix  Trench. 

Small  crown  8vo,  6s. 

VII.  Field  Works.     Their  Technical  Construction  and  Tactical 

Application.     By  the  Editor,  Col.  C.  B.  Brackenbury,  R.A. 
Small  crown  8vo. 

BRENT,  Brig.-Gen.  J.  L. — Mobilizable  Fortifications  and  their 
Controlling  Influence  in  War.  Crown  8vo,  $s. 

BROOKE,  Major,  C.  A'.— A  System  of  Field  Training.  Small 
crown  8vo,  cloth  limp,  2s. 

Campaign  of  Fredericksburg,  November — December,  1862. 
A  Study  for  Officers  of  Volunteers.  With  5  Maps  and  Plans. 
Crown  Svo,  5^. 

CLERY,  C.,  Lieut.- Col.  —Minor  Tactics.  With  26  Maps  and  Plans. 
Seventh  Edition,  Revised.  Crown  8vo,  9-r. 

COLVILE,  Lieut.  Col.  C.  .P.— Military  Tribunals.     Sewed,  2s.  6d. 

CRAUFURD,  Capt.  H.  J.—  Suggestions  for  the  Military  Train 
ing  of  a  Company  of  Infantry.  Crown  8vo,  is.  6d. 

HAMILTON,  Capt.  Ian,  A.D.C.—Ttie  Fighting  of  the  Future,    is. 

HARRISON,  Col.  R.— The  Officer's  Memorandum  Book  for 
Peace  and  "War.  Fourth  Edition,  Revised  throughout. 
Oblong  32mo,  red  basil,  with  pencil,  3^.  6d. 

Notes  on  Cavalry  Tactics,  Organisation,  etc.  By  a  Cavalry 
Officer.  With  Diagrams.  Demy  8vo,  12s. 

PARR,    Capt.    H.    Hallam,    C.M.G.— The    Dress,     Horses,    and 

Equipment  of  Infantry  and  Staff   Officers.    Crown 

Svo,  is. 
SCIIAW,  Col.  Jf.—Ttie  Defence  and  Attack  of  Positions  and 

Localities.      Third  Edition,  Revised  and  Corrected.      Crown 

Svo,  3^.  6d, 

STONE,  Capt.  F.  Gleadowe,  R.A.— Tactical  Studies  from  the 
Franco-German  "War  of  1870-71.  With  22  Lithographic 
Sketches  and  Maps.  Demy  Svo,  30^. 

WILKINSON,  H.  Spenser,  Capt.  zoth  Lancashire  R.V.  —  Citizen 
Soldiers.  Essays  towards  the  Improvement  of  the  Volunteer 
Force.  Crown  Svo,  2s.  6d. 


Kegan  Paul,  Trench  &  Co.'s  Publications.         35 


POETRY. 

ABBAY,  R.—  The  Castle  of  Knaresborough.  A  Tale  in  Verse. 
Crown  Svo,  6s. 

ADAM  OF  ST.  VICTOR.— The  Liturgical  Poetry  of  Adam  of 
St.  Victor.  From  the  text  of  GAUTIER.  With  Translations  into 
English  in  the  Original  Metres,  and  Short  Explanatory  Notes, 
by  DIGBY  S.  WRANGHAM,  M.A.  3  vols.  Crown  Svo,  printed 
on  hand-made  paper,  boards,  2is. 

AITCHISON,  James.— The  Chronicle  of  Mites.  A  Satire.  Small 
crown  Svo.  $s. 

ALEXANDER,  William,  D.D.,  Bishop  of  Derry.~<$>\.  Augustine's 
Holiday,  and  other  Poems.  Crown  Svo,  6s. 

AUCHMUTY,A.  C.— Poems  of  English  Heroism  :  From  Bmnan- 
burh  to  Lucknow  ;  from  Athelstan  to  Albert.  Small  crown  Svo, 
is.  6d. 

BARNES,  William.—  Poems  of  Rural  Life,  in  the  Dorset 
Dialect.  New  Edition,  complete  in  one  vol.  Crown  Svo, 
8s.  6d. 

BAYNES,  Rev.  Canon  H.  /'.—Home  Songs  for  Quiet  Hours. 
Fourth  and  Cheaper  Edition.  Fcap.  Svo,  cloth,  is.  6</. 

BEVINGTON,  L.  S.— Key  Notes.     Small  crown  Svo,  5*. 

BLUNT,  Wilfrid  Scan-en.  —  The  Wind  and  the  Whirlwind. 
Demy  Svo,  is.  6d. 

The  Love  Sonnets  of  Proteus.     Fifth  Edition,  iSmo.     Cloth 
extra,  gilt  top,  $s. 

B GIVEN,  H.  C.,  M.A.— Simple  English  Poems.  English  Literature 
for  Junior  Classes.  In  Four  Parts.  Parts  I.,  II.,  and  III.,  6</. 
each,  and  Part  IV.,  is.  Complete,  3^. 

BRYANT,  IV.  C. — Poems.  Cheap  Edition,  with  Frontispiece.  Small 
crown  Svo,  3.5-.  6ii. 

Calderon's  Dramas:  the  Wonder- Working  Magician  —  Life  is  a 
Dream — the  Purgatory  of  St.  Patrick.  Translated  by  DEMS 
FLORENCE  MACCARTHY.  Post  Svo,  los. 

Camoens'  Lusiads.  —  Portuguese  Text,  with  Translation  by  J.  J. 
AUBERTIN.  Second  Edition.  2  vols.  Crown  Svo,  12s. 

CAMPBELL,  Lewis.—  Sophocles.  The  Seven  Plays  in  English  Verse. 
Crown  Svo,  Js.  6d. 

CERVANTES.— Journey  to  Parnassus.  Spanish  Text,  with  Trans 
lation  into  English  Tercets,  ..Preface,  and  Illustrative  Notes,  by 
JAMES  Y.  GIBSON.  Crown  Svo,  i2s. 


36  A  List  of 

CER  V ANTES— continued. 

Numantia :  a  Tragedy.  Translated  from  the  Spanish,  with 
Introduction  and  Notes,  by  JAMES  Y.  GIBSON.  Crown  8vo, 
printed  on  hand-made  paper,  5^. 

Chronicles  of  Christopher  Columbus.  A  Poem  in  12  Cantos. 
By  M.  D.  C.  Crown  8vo,  Js.  6d. 

Cid  Ballads,  and  other  Poems. — Translated  from  Spanish  and 
German  by  J.  Y.  GIBSON.  2  vols.  Crown  8vo,  I2s. 

COX1IEAD,  Ethel.— Birds  and  Babies.  With  33  Illustrations. 
Imp.  l6mo,  gilt,  2s.  6d. 

Dante's  Divina  Commedia.  Translated  in  the  Terza  Rima  of 
Original,  by  F.  K.  H.  HASELFOOT.  Demy  8vo,  i6.r. 

DE  'BERANGER.—K  Selection  from  his  Songs.  In  English 
Verse.  By  WILLIAM  TOYNBEE.  Small  crown  8vo,  2s.  6d. 

DENNIS,  J.—  English  Sonnets.  Collected  and  Arranged  by.  Small 
crown  8vo,  2s.  6d. 

DE  VERE,  Aubrey.—  Poetical  'Works. 

I.  THE  SEARCH  AFTER  PROSERPINE,  etc.     6s. 
II.  THE  LEGENDS  OF  ST.  PATRICK,  etc.     6s. 
III.  ALEXANDER  THE  GREAT,  etc.     6.r. 

The  Foray  of  Queen  Meave,  and  other  Legends  of  Ireland's 
Heroic  Age.  Small  crown  8vo,  $s. 

Legends  of  the  Saxon  Saints.     Small  crown  8vo,  6s. 

Legends  and  Records  of  the  Church  and  the  Empire. 
Small  crown  Svo,  bs. 

DILLON,  Arthur. — Gods  and  Men.     Fcap.  4to,  js.  6d. 

DOBSON,  Austin.— Old  'World  Idylls  and  other  Verses.  Seventh 
Edition.  Elzevir  Svo,  gilt  top,  6s. 

At  the  Sign  of  the  Lyre.  Fifth  Edition.  Elzevir  Svo,  gilt 
top,  6.r. 

DOWDEN,  Edward,  LL.D.—  Shakspere's  Sonnets.  With  Intro- 
duction  and  Notes.  Large  post  Svo,  Is.  6d. 

DUTT,  Toru.—K  Sheaf  Gleaned  in  French  Fields.  New  Edition. 
Demy  Svo,  ioj.  6d. 

Ancient  Ballads  and  Legends  of  Hindustan.  With  an 
Introductory  Memoir  by  EDMUND  GOSSE.  Second  Edition, 
iSmo.  Cloth  extra,  gilt  top,  $s. 

EDWARDS,  Miss  Betham.—'Poems.     Small  crown  Svo,  35.  6<t. 

ELLIOTT,  Ebenezer,  The  Corn  Law  Rhymer.—  Poems.  Edited  by  his 
son,  the  Rev.  EDWIN  ELLIOTT,  of  St.  John's,  Antigua,  2  vols. 
Crown  Svo,  iSs. 


Kegan  Paul,  Trench  &  Co.'s  Publications.         37 

English   Verse.     Edited  by  W.  J.   LINTON  and   R.    H.   SlODDARD. 

5  vols.     Crown  8vo,  cloth,  5^.  each. 
I.  CHAUCER  TO  BURNS. 
II.  TRANSLATIONS. 

III.  LYRICS  OF  THE  NINETEENTH  CENTURY. 

IV.  DRAMATIC  SCENES  AND  CHARACTERS. 
V.  BALLADS  AND  ROMANCES. 

FOSKETT,  Edward.— Poems.     Crown  Svo,  6s. 

GOODCHILD,  John  A.—  Somnia  Medici.  Three  scries.  Small 
crown  Svo,  5_r.  each. 

GOSSE,  Edmund. — New  Poems.     Crown  Svo,  Js.  67. 

Firdausi  in  Exile,  and  other  Poems.     Second  Edition.      Klzevir 
Svo,  gilt  top,  6s. 

GURNEY,  Rev.  Alfred.—  The  Vision  of  the  Eucharist,  and  other 
Poems.  Crown  Svo,  $s. 

A  Christmas  Faggot.      Small  crown  Svo.  5.1-. 
HARRISON,  Clifford.— In  Hours  of  Leisure.     Crown  Svo,  55. 

HEYWOOD,  J.  C.—  Herodias,  a  Dramatic  Poem.  New  Edition, 
Revised.  Small  crown  Svo,  5^. 

Antonius.     A  Dramatic    Poem.     New  Edition,  Revised.     Small 
crown  Svo,  $s. 

Salome.     A  Dramatic  Poem.     Small  crown  Svo,  5_r. 

HICA'EY,  E.  //.—A  Sculptor,  and  other  Poems.  Small  crown 
Svo,  $5. 

HOLE,  W.  G. — Procris,  and  other  Poems.     Fcap.  Svo,  3^.  67. 

KEA  TS,  John.—  Poetical  "Works.  Edited  by  W.  T.  ARNOLD.  Lnr-e 
crown  Svo,  choicely  printed  on  hand-made  paper,  with  Portrait 
in  eau-forte.  Parchment  or  cloth,  12s.  ;  vellum,  15^. 

A'L\G,  Edu'ani.     A  Venetian  Lover.     Small  410,  6.r. 

KING,  Mrs.  Hamilton.— The  Disciples.  Ninth  Edition,  and  No'.c-;. 
Small  crown  Svo,  5-r. 

A  Book  of  Dreams.     Second  Edition.     Crown  Svo,  3..-.  6../. 

I.AFFAN,  Mrs.  R.  S.  De  Courcy.—h.  Song  of  Jubilee,  and  other 
Poems.  With  Frontispiece.  Small  crown  Svo,  y.  6d. 

LANG,  A.—  XXXII.  Ballades  in  Blue  China.     Elzevir  Svo,  5.?. 

Rhymes  a  la    Mode.      With   Frontispiece   by    E.    A.    Abbey. 
Second  Edition.     Elzevir  Svo,  cloth  extra,  gilt  top,  5-- 

LANGFORD,  /.  A.,  LL.D.—On  Sea  and  Shore.  Small  crown 
Svo,  5-r. 


38  A  List  of 

LASCELLES,  John.—  Golden  Fetters,  and  other  Poems.  Small 
crown  8vo,  3^.  6d. 

LAWSON,  Right  Hon.  Mr.  Justice.—  Hymni  Usitati  Latine 
Redditi  :  with  other  Verses.  Small  8vo,  parchment,  5.?. 

Living  English  Poets  MDCCCLXXXII.  With  Frontispiece  by 
Walter  Crane.  Second  Edition.  Large  crown  8vo.  Printed  on 
hand-made  paper.  Parchment  or  cloth,  1 2s.  ;  vellum,  I  $s. 

LOCKER,  F.—  London  Lyrics.  Tenth  Edition.  With  Portrait, 
Elzevir  Svo.  Cloth  extra,  gilt  top,  $s. 

Love  in  Idleness.  A  Volume  of  Poems'.  With  an  Etching  by  W.  B. 
Scott.  Small  crown  Svo,  5-r. 

LUMSDEN,  Lieut.- Col.  H.  W.—  Beowulf  :  an  Old  English  Poem. 
Translated  into  Modem  Rhymes.  Second  and  Revised  Edition. 
Small  crown  Svo,  $s. 

LYSAGHT,  Sidney  Royse. — A  Modern  Ideal.  A  Dramatic  Poem. 
Small  crown  Svo,  55. 

MAGNUSSON,  Eirikr,  M.A.,  and  PALMER,  E.  H.,  M.A.—  Johan 
Ludvig  Runeberg's  Lyrical  Songs,  Idylls,  and  Epi 
grams.  Fcap.  Svo,  55. 

MEREDITH,  Owen  [The  Earl  of  Lyttou}.—  Lucile.  New  Edition. 
With  32  Illustrations.  l6mo,  3-f.  6d.  Cloth  extra,  gilt  edges, 
4-r.  6d. 

MORRIS,  Lewis.— Poetical  Works  of.     New  and  Cheaper  Editions, 

with  Portrait.     Complete  in  3  vols.,  5-r.  each. 
Vol.  I.  contains  "Songs  of  Two  Worlds."    Twelfth  Edition. 
Vol.  II.  contains  "  The  Epic  of  Hades."     Twenty-first  Edition. 
Vol.   III.  contains   "  Gwen  "  and    "The  Ode  of  Life."     Seventh 

Edition. 
Vol.  IV.  contains  "Songs  Unsung"  and  "Gycia."     Fifth  Edition. 

Songs  of  Britain.     Third  Edition.     Fcap.  Svo,  5.?. 

The  Epic  of  Hades.  With  16  Autotype  Illustrations,  after  the 
Drawings  of  the  late  George  R.  Chapman.  4to,  cloth  extra,  gilt 
leaves,  2is. 

The  Epic  of  Hades.  Presentation  Edition.  4to,  cloth  extra, 
gilt  leaves,  los.  6d. 

The  Lewis  Morris  Birthday  Book.  Edited  by  S.  S.  COPE- 
MAN,  with  Frontispiece  after  a  Design  by  the  late  George  R. 
Chapman.  32mo,  cloth  extra,  gilt  edges,  2s. ;  cloth  limp,  is.  6d 

MORSHEAD,  E.  D.  A.  —  The  House  of  Atreus.  Being  the 
Agamemnon,  Libation-Bearers,  and  Furies  of  ^Eschylus.  Trans 
lated  into  English  Verse.  Crown  Svo,  7-r. 

The  Suppliant  Maidens  of  ^Eschylus.     Crown  Svo,  3*.  6d. 


Kegan  Paul,   Trench  &  Go's  Publications.         39 

MOZLEY,  J.  Rickardf. — The  Romance  of  Dennell.  A  Poem  in 
Five  Cantos.  Crown  Svo,  7^.  6d. 

MULHOLLAND,  Rosa.—  Vagrant  Verses.     Small  crown  Svo,  5^. 

NADEN,  Constance  C.  W. — A  Modern  Apostle,  and  other 
Poems.  Small  crown  Svo,  $s. 

NOEL,  The  Hon.  Roden.—K  Little  Child's  Monument.  Third 
Edition.  Small  crown  Svo,  35.  6d. 

The   House   of   Ravensburg.     New   Edition.     Small    crown 
Svo,  6s. 

The  Red   Flag,  and  other  Poems.     New  Edition.     Small  crown 
Svo,  6s. 

Songs  of  the  Heights  and  Deeps.     Crown  Svo,  6s. 
O'BRIEN,  Charlotte  Grace.— Lyrics.     Small  crown  Svo,  3*.  6d. 

0 'HAG 'AN,  John.—  The  Song  of  Roland.  Translated  into  English 
Verse.  New  and  Cheaper  Edition.  Crown  Svo,  $s. 

PFEIFFER,  Emily,— The  Rhyme  of  the  Lady  of  the  Rock, 
and  How  it  Grew.  Second  Edition.  Small  crown  Svo, 
35.  6ef. 

Gerard's   Monument,    and    other    Poems.       Second    Edition. 
Crown  Svo,  6s. 

Under   the   Aspens  :    Lyrical   and    Dramatic.      With    Portrait. 
Crown  Svo,  6s. 

PIATT,  J.  J.  —  Idyls  and  Lyrics  of  the  Ohio  Valley.  Crown 
Svo,  5j. 

PREVOST,  Francis.— Melilot.     3*.  6</. 

Fires  of  Green  "Wood.     Small  crown  Svo,  35-.  6<7. 

Rare  Poems  of  the  16th  and  17th  Centuries.  Edited  by  W.  J. 
LINTON*.  Crown  Svo,  $s. 

RHOADES,  Jaws.— The  Georgics  of  Virgil.  Translated  into 
English  Verse.  Small  crown  Svo,  5.r. 

Poems.     Small  crown  Svo,  4^.  6</. 

Dux  Redux.     A  Forest  Tangle.     Small  crown  Svo,  35.  6d. 

ROBINSON,  A.  Mary  F.—A  Handful  of  Honeysuckle.  Fcap. 
Svo,  3->-.  6d. 

The  Cro\vned  Hippolytus.     Translated  from  Euripides.    With 
New  Poems.     Small  crown  Svo,  $s. 

SCHILLER,  Friedrich.—  Wallenstein.  A  Drama.  Done  in  English 
Verse,  by  J.  A.  W.  HUNTER,  M.A.  Crown  Svo,  "js.  dti. 

SCHWARTZ,  J.  M.  W.—  Nivalis.  A  Tragedy  in  Five  Acts.  Small 
crown  Svo,  5-r. 


40  A  List  of 

SCOTT,  E.J.  L.—  The  Eclogues  of  Virgil.— Translated  into  English 
Verse.  Small  crown  8vo,  y.  6d. 

SHERBROOKE,  Viscottnt.—  Poems  of  a  Life.  Second  Edition. 
Small  crown  8vo,  2s.  6d. 

SINCLAIR,  Julian. — Nakiketas,  and  other  Poems.  Small  crown 
8vo,  2s.  6d. 

SMITH,  y.  W.  Gilbart.—T'h.e  Loves  of  Vandyck.    A  Tale  of  Genoa. 

Small  crown  8vo,  2s.  6d. 

The  Log  o'  the  "  Norseman."    Small  crown  8vo,  5^. 
Serbelloni.     Small  crown  8vo,  55. 

Sophocles  ;  The  Seven  Plays  in  English  Verse.  Translated  by  LEWIS 
CAMPBELL.  Crown  8vo,  7.?.  6d. 

STEWART,  PMtips.—'Poem.s.     Small  crown  8vo,  zs.  6d. 

SYMONDS,  John  Addington, — Vagabunduli  Libellus.  Crown 
8vo,  6s. 

Tasso's  Jerusalem  Delivered.  Translated  by  Sir  JOHN  KINGSTON 
JAMES,  Bart.  Two  Volumes.  Printed  on  hand-made  paper, 
parchment,  bevelled  boards.  Large  crown  8vo,  2is. 

TAYLOR,   Sir  II. — "Works.      Complete   in    Five    Volumes.      Crown 

8vo,  3cw. 

Philip  Van  Artevelde.     Fcap.  8vo,  $s.  6d. 
The  Virgin  Widow,  etc.     Fcap.  8vo,  3-r.  6d. 
The  Statesman.     Fcap.  8vo,  3.?.  6d. 

TODHUNTER,  Dr.  J.—  Laurella,  and   other    Poems.     Crown   Svo, 

6s.  6d. 

Forest  Songs.     Small  crown  Svo,  3^.  6d. 
The  True  Tragedy  of  Rienzi :  a  Drama.     35.  dd. 
Alcestis  :  a  Dramatic  Poem.     Extra  fcap.  Svo,  $s. 
Helena  in  Troas.     Small  crown  Svo,  zs.  6d. 

TOMKINS,  Zitella  .e.—Sister  Lucetta,  and  other  Poems.  Small 
crown  Svo,  $s.  6d. 

TYNAN,  Katherinc. — Louise  de  la  Valliere,  and  other  Poems. 
Small  crown  Svo,  y.  bd. 

Shamrocks.     Small  crown  Svo,  5.?. 
Unspoken  Thoughts.     Small  crown  Svo,  3^.  6d. 

Victorian  Hymns ".  English  Sacred  Songs  of  Fifty  Years. 
Dedicated  to  the  Queen.  Large  post  Svo,  IQJ-.  6</. 

WEBSTER,  Augusta.— In  a  Day  :  a  Drama.    Small  crown  Svo,  zs.  6d. 

Disguises  :  a  Drama.     Small  crown  Svo,  5^. 
WILLIAMS,   James; — A    Lawyer's   Leisure.      Small   crown   Svo, 


Kegan  Paul,   Trench  &   Co.'s  Publications.         41 

WOOD,  Edmund.—  Poems.     Small  crown  8vo,  31.  6J. 

Wordsworth  Birthday  Book,   The.      Edited  by  ADELAIDE  and 
VIOLET  WORDSWORTH.    321110,  limp  cloth,  is.  6J. ;  cloth  extra,  2 s. 

YOUNGS,  Ella  Sharfe.— Paphus,  and  other  Poems.    Small  crown  8vo, 
3-r.  6d. 

A  Heart's  Life,  Sarpedon,  and  other  Poems.      Small   crown 
8vo,  51.  6d. 

The  Apotheosis  of  Antinous,  and    other   Poems.     "With 
Portrait.     Small  crown  8vo,  IDJ-.  6J. 


NOVELS    AND    TALES. 

"  All  But  :  "  a  Chronicle  of  Laxenfortl  Life.  By  PEN  OLIVER,  F.R.C.S. 
With  20  Illustrations.  Second  Edition.  Crown  Svo,  6s. 

HANKS,  Mrs.  G.  L. — God's  Providence  House.  New  Edition. 
Crown  Svo,  3^.  6;/. 

CinCIIELE,  Mary.—  Doing  and  Undoing.  A  Story.  Crown  Svo, 
4-r.  6d. 

Danish  Parsonage.     By  an  Angler.     Crown  Svo,  6s. 

GRAY,  Maxwell.  —  The  Silence  of  Dean  Maitland.  Fifth 
Edition.  With  Frontispiece.  Crown  Svo,  6^. 

HUNTER,  .flay. —The  Crime  of  Christmas  Day.  A  Tale  of  the 
Latin  Quarter.  By  the  Author  of  "My  Ducats  and  my 
Daughter."  is. 

HUNTER,  Hay,  and  IVHYTE,  Jt'al/er.—My  Ducats  and  My 
Daughter.  New  and  Cheaper  Edition.  With  Frontispiece. 
Crown  Svo,  6s. 

INGELOW,  ytu«.— Off  the  Skelligs  :  a  Novel.  With  Frontispiece. 
Second  Edition.  Crown  Svo,  6s. 

JEArA'ZNS,  Edward.— A  Secret  of  Two  Lives.     Crown  Svo,  2s.  6J. 

KIELLAND,  Alexander  L. — Garman  and  'Worse.  A  Norwegian 
Novel.  Authorized  Translation,  by  W.  W.  Kettlewell.  Crown 
Svo,  6s. 

LANG,  Andrni'. — In  the  'Wrong  Paradise,  and  other  Stories. 
Second  Edition.  Crown  Svo,  6s. 

MACDONALD,  G.— Donal  Grant.  A  Novel.  Second  Edition. 
With  Frontispiece.  Crown  Svo,  6s. 

Home  Again.     With  Frontispiece.     Crown  Svo,  6s. 

Castle    'Warlock.     A  Novel.     Second  Edition.     With  Frontis 
piece.     Crown  Svo,  6.r. 


42  A  List  of 

MA  CD  ONALD,  G.  —contimied. 

Malcolm.     With    Portrait    of   the   Author    engraved    on    Steel. 
Eighth  Edition.     Crown  Svo,  6s. 

The  Marquis  of  Lossie.     Seventh  Edition.     With  Frontispiece. 
Crown  Svo,  6s. 

St.  George  and  St.   Michael.     Fifth  Edition.     With  Frontis 
piece.     Crown  Svo,  6s. 

What's   Mine's   Mine.     Second    Edition.     With  Frontispiece. 
Crown  Svo,  6s. 

Annals  of  a  Quiet  Neighbourhood.     Sixth  Edition.     With 
Frontispiece.     Crown  Svo,  6.?. 

The  Seaboard  Parish  :  a  Sequel  to  "Annals  of  a  Quiet  Neigh 
bourhood."   Fourth  Edition.    With  Frontispiece.    Crown  Svo,  6s. 

Wilfred  Cumbermede.     An  Autobiographical  Story.     Fourth 
Edition.     With  Frontispiece.     Crown  Svo,  6s. 

Thomas  Wingfold,  Curate.     Fourth  Edition.    With  Frontis 
piece.     Crown  Svo,  6s. 

Paul  Faber,  Surgeon.     Fourth  Edition.      With  Frontispiece. 
Crown  Svo,  6s. 

MALET,  Lucas.—  Colonel  Enderby's  Wife.     A  Novel.     New  and 
Cheaper  Edition.     With  Frontispiece.     Crown  Svo,  6s. 

AfULHOLLAND,Rosa.—WLa.TCe\\a.GTa.CQ.     An  Irish  Novel.     Crown 
Svo.  6s. 

PALGRA  VE,  W.  Gifford.— Hermann  Agha  :  an  Eastern  Narrative. 
Third  Edition.     Crown  Svo,  6s. 

SHA  W,  Flora  Z.— Castle  Blair  :  a  Story  of  Youthful  Days.     New  and 
Cheaper  Edition.     Crown  Svo,  3-r.  6d. 

STRETTON,  Hesla.— Through  a  Needle's  Eye  :  a  Story.     New 
and  Cheaper  Edition,  with  Frontispiece.     Crown  Svo,  6s. 

TAYLOR,   Col.  MeacLnvs,  C.S.I.,  M.R.I. A.—  Seeta  :   a  Novel.      With 
Frontispiece.     Crown  Svo,  6^. 

Tippoo  Sultaun  :  a  Tale  of  the  Mysore  War.    With  Frontispiece. 
Crown  Svo,  6s. 

Ralph  Darnell.     With  Frontispiece.     Crown  Svo,  6s. 
A  Noble  Queen.     With  Frontispiece.     Crown  Svo,  6s. 
The  Confessions  of  a  Thug.  With  Frontispiece.    Crown  Svo,  6s. 
Tara  i  a  Mahratta  Tale.     With  Frontispiece.     Crown  Svo,  6.?. 
Within  Sound  of  the  Sea.     With  Frontispiece.     Crown  Svo,  6.?. 


Kegan  Pan  I,   Trench  &  Co.'s  Publications.         43 


BOOKS    FOR    THE    YOUNG. 

Brave  Men's  Footsteps.  A  Book  of  Example  and  Anecdote  for 
Young  People.  By  the  Editor  of  "Men  who  have  Risen."  With 
4  Illustrations  by  C.  Doyle.  Ninth  Edition.  Crown  8vo,  $s.  6d. 

COXHEAD,  Ethel.— Birds  and  Babies.  With  33  Illustrations. 
Second  Edition.  Imp.  161110,  cloth  gilt,  2s.  bd. 

DA  VIES,  G.  Christopher, — Rambles  and  Adventures  of  our 
School  Field  Club.  With  4  Illustrations.  New  and  Cheaper 
Edition.  Crown  Svo,  35.  6d. 

EDMONDS,  Herbert.—  Well  Spent  Lives  :  a  Series  of  Modern  Bio 
graphies.  New  and  Cheaper  Edition.  Crown  Svo,  $s.  6J. 

EVANS,  Mark. — The  Story  of  our  Father's  Love,  told  to  Children. 
Sixth  and  Chfnpcr  Edition  of  Theology  for  Children.  With  4 
Illustrations.  Fcap,  Svo,  is.  6d. 

MAC  KENNA,  S.  J.—  Plucky  Fellows.  A  Hook  fur  Boys.  With 
6  Illustrations.  Fifth  Edition.  Crown  Svo,  3*.  6</. 

MA  LET,  Lucas. — Little  Peter.  A  Christmas  Morality  for  Children  CM 
any  Age.  With  numerous  Illustrations.  $s. 

REANEY,  Mrs.  G.  S. — 'Waking  and  "Working  ;  or,  From  Girlhood 
to  Womanhood.  New  and  Cheaper  Edition.  With  a  Frontis 
piece.  Crown  Svo,  35.  6d. 

Blessing  and  Blessed :  a  Sketch  of  Girl  Life.  New  and 
Cheaper  Edition.  Crown  Svo,  31.  6J. 

Rose  Gurney's  Discovery.  A  Story  for  Girls.  Dedicated  to 
their  Mothers.  Crown  Svo,  y.  6</. 

English  Girls:  Their  Place  and  Power.  With  Preface  by  the 
Rev.  R.  W.  Dale.  Fifth  Edition.  Fcap.  Svo,  2s.  6d. 

Just  Anyone,  and  other  Stones.  Three  Illustrations.  Royal 
i6mo,  is.  6d. 

Sunbeam  Willie,  and  other  Stories.  Three  Illustrations.  Royal 
i6mo,  is.  6</. 

Sunshine  Jenny,  and  other  Stories.  Three  Illustrations.  Royal 
iGmo,  is.  6d. 

STOXR,  Francis,  and  TURNER,  Hawes.—  Canterbury  Chimes; 
or,  Chaucer  Tales  re-told  to  Children.  With  6  Illustrations  from 
the  Ellesmere  Manuscript.  Third  Edition.  Fcap.  Svo,  3^.  6d. 

STRETTON,  Hesba.— David  Lloyd's  Last  Will.  With  4  Illustra 
tions.  New  Edition.  Royal  i6mo,  2s.  6d. 

WIIITAKER,  Florence. — Christy's  Inheritance.  A  London  Story. 
Illustrated.  Royal  161110,  is.  6J. 


PRINTED    BY    WILLIAM    CLOWES    AND   SONS,    L1MI1EIJ, 
LONDON    AND    BECCLES. 


MESSRS. 

KEGAN    PAUL,  TRENCH   &  CO.'S 


EDITIONS    OF 


SHAKSPERE'S    WORKS. 


THE  PARCHMENT  LIBRARY  EDITION, 


THE  A  VON  EDITION. 


The  Text  of  these  Editions  is  mainly  that  of  Deliits.  Wher 
ever  a  variant  reading  is  adopted,  some  good  and  recognized 
Shaksperian  Critic  has  been  followed.  In  no  case  is  a  iieii> 
render! tig  of  tJie  text  proposed ;  nor  has  it  been  thought  ne 
cessary  to  distract  the  reader's  attention  by  notes  or  comments. 


i,  PATERNOSTER  SQUARE. 


[P.  T.  O. 


SHAKSPERE'S   WORKS. 

THE  AVON  EDITION. 

Printed   on   thin    opaque   paper,    and    forming    12   handy 
volumes,  cloth,  18^.,  or  bound  in  6  volumes,  15^. 

The  set  of  1 2  volumes  may  also  be  had  in  a  cloth  box, 
price  215-.,  or  bound  in  Roan,  Persian,  Crushed  Persian 
Levant,  Calf,  or  Morocco,  and  enclosed  in  an  attractive 
leather  box  at  prices  from  3  is.  6d.  upwards. 


SOME   PRESS   NOTICES. 

"  This  edition  will  be  useful  to  those  who  want  a  good  text,  well  and 
clearly  printed,  in  convenient  little  volumes  that  will  slip  easily  into  an 
overcoat  pocket  or  a  travelling-bag." — Si.  fames 's  Gazette. 

"  We  know  no  prettier  edition  of  Shaksperefor  the  price." — Academy. 

"  It  is  refreshing  to  meet  with  an  edition  of  Shakspere  of  convenient 
size  and  low  price,  without  either  notes  or  introductions  of  any  sort  to 
distract  the  attention  of  the  reader. " — Saturday  Review. 

"It  is  exquisite.  Each  volume  is  handy,  is  beautifully  printed,  and 
in  every  way  lends  itself  to  the  taste  of  the  cultivated  student  of  Shak 
spere.  " — Scotsman. 


LONDON  ;  KEGAN  PAUL,  TRENCH  &  Co.,  i,  PATERNOSTER  SQUARE. 


SHAKSPERE'S   WORKS. 

THE  PARCHMENT  LIBRARY  EDITION. 

In  1 2  volumes  Elzevir  8vo.,  choicely  printed  on  hand-made 
paper,  and  bound  in  parchment  or  cloth,  price  ^3  12*., 
or  in  vellum,  price  £4.  los. 

The  set  of  1 2  volumes  may  also  be  had  in  a  strong  cloth 
box,  price  ,£3  17^.,  or  with  an  oak  hanging  shelf,  ^3  iSs. 


SOME   PRESS   NOTICES. 

"...  There  is,  perhaps,  no  edition  in  which  the  works  of  Shakspere 

can  be  read  in  such  luxury  of  type  and  quiet  distinction  of  form  as  this, 
and  we  warmly  recommend  it." — Pall  Mall  Gazette. 

"  For  elegance  of  form  and  beauty  of  typography,  no  edition  of 
Shakspere  hitherto  published  has  excelled  the  '  Parchment  Library 
Edition.'  .  .  .  They  are  in  the  .strictest  sense  pocket  volumes,  yet  the 
type  is  bold,  and,  being  on  fine  white  hand-made  paper,  can  hardly  tax 
the  weakest  of  sight.  The  print  is  judiciously  confined  to  the  text,  notes 
being  more  appropriate  to  library  editions.  The  whole  will  be  comprised 
in  the  cream-coloured  parchment  which  gives  the  name  to  the  series." 
—Daily  A~< 

"The  Parchment  Library  Edition  of  Shakspere  needs  no  further 
praise. " — Saturday  A'iz'icic. 


Just  published.     Price  54. 
AN  INDEX  TO  THE  WORKS  OF  SHAKSPERE. 

Applicable  to  all  editions  of  Shakspere,  and  giving  reference,  by  topics, 
to  notable  passages  and  significant  expressions  ;  brief  histories  of  the 
plays ;  geographical  names  and  historic  incidents ;  mention  of  all 
characters  and  sketches  of  important  ones  ;  together  with  explanations 
of  allusions  and  obscure  and  obsolete  words  and  phrases. 

By  EVANGELINE   M.    O'CONNOR. 


LONDON  :  KEGAN  PAUL,  TRENCH  6c  Co.,  i,  PATERNOSTER  SQUARE. 


SHAKSPERE'S    WORKS. 

SPECIMEN   OF  TYPE. 


4  THE  MERCHANT  OF  VENICE  ACT  t 

Salar.  My  wind,  cooling  my  broth, 

Would  blow  me  to  an  ague,  when  I  thought 
What  harm  a  wind  too  great  might  do  at  sea. 
I  should  not  see  the  sandy  hour-glass  run 
But  I  should  think  of  shallows  and  of  flats, 
And  see  my  wealthy  Andrew,  dock'd  in  sand, 
Vailing  her  high-top  lower  than  her  ribs 
To  kiss  her  burial.     Should  I  go  to  church 
And  see  the  holy  edifice  of  stone, 
And  not  bethink  me  straight  of  dangerous  rocks, 
Which  touching  but  my  gentle  vessel's  side, 
Would  scatter  all  her  spices  on  the  stream, 
Enrobe  the  roaring  waters  with  my  silks, 
And,  in  a  word,  but  even  now  worth  this, 
And  now  worth  nothing  ?     Shall  I  have  the  thought 
To  think  on  this,  and  shall  I  lack  the  thought 
That  such  a  thing  bechanc'd  would  make  me  sad  ? 
But  tell  not  me  :  I  know  Antonio 
Is  sad  to  think  upon  his  merchandise. 

Ant,  Believe  me,  no  :  I  thank  my  fortune  for  it, 
My  ventures  are  not  in  one  bottom  trusted, 
Nor  to  one  place  ;  nor  is  my  whole  estate 
Upon  the  fortune  of  this  present  year  : 
Therefore  my  merchandise  makes  me  not  sad. 

Salar.  Why,  then  you  are  in  love. 

Ant.  Fie,  fie  ! 

Salar.  Not  in  love  neither  ?    Then  let  us  say  you 

are  sad, 

Because  you  are  not  merry  ;  and  'twere  as  easy 
For  you  to  laugh,  and  leap,  and  say  you  are  merry. 
Because    you    are    not    sad.     Now,    by    two-headed 

Janus, 

Nature  hath  fram'cl  strange  fellows  in  her  time  : 
Some  that  will  evermore  peep  through  their  eyes 
And  laugh  like  parrots  at  a  bag- pi  per  ; 
And  other  of  such  vinegar  aspect 


LONDON  :.;KEGAN. PAUL,  TRENCH  &  Co.,  i,  PATERNOSTER  SQUARE. 


947 


PLEASE  DO  NOT  REMOVE 
CARDS  OR  SLIPS  FROM  THIS  POCKET 

UNIVERSITY  OF  TORONTO  LIBRARY