Skip to main content

Full text of "History of the inductive sciences"

See other formats


Google 



This is a digital copy of a book that was preserved for generations on library shelves before it was carefully scanned by Google as part of a project 

to make the world's books discoverable online. 

It has survived long enough for the copyright to expire and the book to enter the public domain. A public domain book is one that was never subject 

to copyright or whose legal copyright term has expired. Whether a book is in the public domain may vary country to country. Public domain books 

are our gateways to the past, representing a wealth of history, culture and knowledge that's often difficult to discover. 

Marks, notations and other maiginalia present in the original volume will appear in this file - a reminder of this book's long journey from the 

publisher to a library and finally to you. 

Usage guidelines 

Google is proud to partner with libraries to digitize public domain materials and make them widely accessible. Public domain books belong to the 
public and we are merely their custodians. Nevertheless, this work is expensive, so in order to keep providing tliis resource, we liave taken steps to 
prevent abuse by commercial parties, including placing technical restrictions on automated querying. 
We also ask that you: 

+ Make non-commercial use of the files We designed Google Book Search for use by individuals, and we request that you use these files for 
personal, non-commercial purposes. 

+ Refrain fivm automated querying Do not send automated queries of any sort to Google's system: If you are conducting research on machine 
translation, optical character recognition or other areas where access to a large amount of text is helpful, please contact us. We encourage the 
use of public domain materials for these purposes and may be able to help. 

+ Maintain attributionTht GoogXt "watermark" you see on each file is essential for in forming people about this project and helping them find 
additional materials through Google Book Search. Please do not remove it. 

+ Keep it legal Whatever your use, remember that you are responsible for ensuring that what you are doing is legal. Do not assume that just 
because we believe a book is in the public domain for users in the United States, that the work is also in the public domain for users in other 
countries. Whether a book is still in copyright varies from country to country, and we can't offer guidance on whether any specific use of 
any specific book is allowed. Please do not assume that a book's appearance in Google Book Search means it can be used in any manner 
anywhere in the world. Copyright infringement liabili^ can be quite severe. 

About Google Book Search 

Google's mission is to organize the world's information and to make it universally accessible and useful. Google Book Search helps readers 
discover the world's books while helping authors and publishers reach new audiences. You can search through the full text of this book on the web 

at |http: //books .google .com/I 



I 



000 





r 



000. 



HISTORY 



V . . OP THE 

» 



INDUCTIVE SCIENCES 



VOL. I. 



\< 



HISTORY 



OF THE 



INDUCTIVE SCIENCES, 



FROM THE EARLIEST TO THE PRESENT TIMES. 



BY THE 



REV. WILLIAM WHEWELL, M.A., 

FELLOW AND TUTOR OT TRINITY OOU<BOK, GAMRRIDOB ; PRUIOSNT OW THE OBOLOOICAL 

SOCIBTY or LONDON. 



IN THREE VOLUMES. 




AofiTrdbia ^xopt€S dtabwrovaiv dXXrjXois. 



VOLUME THE FIRST. 



LONDON : 

JOHN W. PARKER, WEST STRAND. 
CAMBRIDGE : J. awd J. J. DEIGHTON. 



M.DCCc.xxxyn 



I OOO, 



TO 



SIR JOHN FREDERICK WILLIAM HERSCHEL, 

K. G. H. 



Mt DEAR HeRSCHEL, 

It is with no common pleasure that I take up 
my pen to dedicate these volumes to you. They are the 
result of trains of thought which have often been the subject 
of our conversation, and of which the origin goes back to 
the period of our early companionship at the University. 
And if I had ever wavered in my purpose of combining 
such reflections and researches into a whole, I should have 
derived a renewed impulse and increased animation from 
your delightful Discourse on a kindred subject. For I could 
not have read it without finding this portion of philosophy 
invested with a fresh charm ; and though I might be well 
aware that I could not aspire to that large share of popu- 
larity which your work so justly gained, I should still have 
reflected, that something was due to the subject itself, and 
should have hoped that my own aim was so far similar 
to yours, that the present work might have a chance of 
exciting an interest in some of your readers. That it will 
interest you, I do not at all hesitate to believe. 
VOL. I. a 



VI DEDICATION. 

If you were now in England I should stop here : but 
when a friend is removed for years to a far distant land, 
we seem to acquire a right to speak openly of his good 
qualities. I cannot, therefore, prevail upon myself to lay 
down my pen without alluding to the affectionate admira- 
tion of your moral and social, as well as intellectual excel- 
lencies, which springs up in the hearts of yonr friends, 
whenever you are thought of. They are much delighted 
to look upon the halo of deserved fame which plays round 
your head ; but still more, to recollect, as one of them said, 
that your head is far from being the best part about you. 

May your sojourn in the southern hemisphere be as 
happy and successful as its object is noble and worthy of 
you ; and may your return home be speedy and prosperous, 
as soon as your purpose is attained ! 

Ever, my dear Herschel, 

Yours, 

W. Whkwell. 

6, Hyde Pabk Street, 
22 March, 1837. 



PREFACE. 



At the present day, any endeavour to improve and 
extend the Philosophy of Science may hope to 
excite some interest. All persons of cultivated 
minds will agree> that a very important advan- 
tage would be gained, if any light could be 
thrown upon the modes of discovering truth, the 
powers that we possess for this end, and the points 
to which these may most profitably be applied. 
Most men, too, will allow, that in these respects 
much .renuiins to be done. The attempts of this 
kind, made from time to time, are far from ren- 
dering future efforts superfluous. For example, the 
Great Reform of Philosophy and Method, in which 
Bacon so eloquently called upon men to unite their 
ezertioiui in his day, has, even in ours, been very 
imperfectly carried into effect. And, even if his plan 
had been fully executed, it would now require to be 
pursued and extended. If Bacon had weighed well 

all that Science had achieved in his time, and had 

a 2 



«•• 



Vlll PREFACE. 

laid down a complete scheme of rules for scientific 
research, so far as they could be collected from the 
lights of that age, it would still be incumbent upon 
the philosophical world to augment as well as pre- 
serve the inheritance which he left ; by combining 
with his doctrines such new views as the advances 
of later times cannot fail to produce or suggest; 
and by endeavouring to provide, for every kind of 
truth, methods of research as effective as those to 
which we owe the clearest and surest portions of 
our knowledge. Such a renovation and extension 
of the reform of philosophy appears to belong pecu- 
liarly to our own time. We may discern no few or 
doubtful presages of its approach ; and an attempt 
to give form and connexion to the elements of such 
a scheme cannot now be considered premature. 

The Novum Organon of Bacon was suitably 
ushered into the world by his Advancement of 
Learning ; and any attempt to continue and extend 
his Reform of the Methods and Philosophy of 
Science may, like his, be most fitly preceded by, 
and founded upon, a comprehensive Survey of the 
existing state of human knowledge. The wish to 
contribute something, however little it may be, to 
such a Reform, gave rise to that study of the His- 



PREFACE. ix 



tory of Science of which the present Work is the 
fruit. And the effect of these researches has been, 
a persuasion, that we need not despair of seeing, 
even in our own time, a renovation of sound 
philosophy, directed by the light which the History 
of Science sheds. Such a reform, when its Epoch 
shall arrive, will not be the work of any single 
writer, but the result of the intellectual tendencies 
of the age. He who is most forward in the work 
will wisely repeat the confession of his sagacious 
predecessor: Ipse certe (ut ingenue fatear) soleo 
sestimare hoc opus magis pro partu Temporis quam 
Ingenii. 

To such a work, whensoever and by whomso- 
ever executed, I venture to hope that the present 
Volumes may be usefully subservient. But I trust, 
also, that in its independent character, as a History, 
this book may be found not altogether unworthy of 
the aim which its title implies. 

It is impossible not to see that the writer of such 
a history imposes upon himself a task of no ordinary 
difficulty and delicacy ; since it is necessary for him 
to pronoimce a judgment upon the characters and 
achievements of all the great physical philosophers 
of all ages, and in all sciences. But the assumption 



X PREFACE. 

of this judicial position is so inevitably involved in 
the functions of the historian (whatever be his sub-* 
ject), that he cannot justly be deemed presumptuous 
on that account. It is true, that the historian of 
the progress of science is required by his undei^ 
taking to judge of the merits of men, in reference 
to subjects which demand a far intenser and more 
methodical study than the historian of practical life 
gives to the actions of which he treats; and the 
general voice of mankind, — ^which may often serve as 
a guide, because it rarely errs widely or permanently 
in its estimate of those who are prominent in public 
life, — ^is of little value when it speaks of things 
belonging to the region of exact science. But to 
balance these disadvantages, and to enable us to 
judge of the characters who must figure in our 
history, we may recollect that we have before us, 
not the record only of their actions, but the actions 
themselves; for the acts of a philosopher are his 
writings. We do not receive his exploits on tradi- 
tion, but by sight ; we do not read of him, we read 
him. And if I may speak of my own grounds of 
trust and encouragement in venturing on such a 
task, I knew that my life had been principally spent 
in those studies which were most requisite to enable 



PBSFAGE. Xi 

me to understand what had thus been done; and 
I had been in habits of intercourse with several 
of tiie most eminent men of science of our time, 
both in our own and in other countries* Having 
thus lived with some of the great intellects of the 
past and the present, I had found myself capable of 
rejoicing in their beauties, of admiring their endow- 
ments, and, I trusted, also, of understanding their 
discoveries and views, their hopes and aims. I did 
not, therefore, turn aside from the responsibility 
which the character of the Historian of Science 
imposed upon me. I have not even shrunk from 
it when it led me into the circle of those who are 
now alive, and among whom we move. For it 
seemed to me that to omit such portions of the 
history as I must have omitted to avoid thus speak- 
ing of my contemporaries, would have left my work 
mutilated and incomplete ; and would have prevented 
its forming a platform on which we might stand 
and look forward into the future. I trusted, 
moreover, that my study of the philosophers of 
former times had enabled me to appreciate the dis- 
coveries of the present, and that I should be able to 
speak of persons now alive, with the same impar- 
tiality and in the same spirit as if they were already 



211 PREFACE. 

numbered with the great men of the past. Seeking 
encouragement in these reflections, and in the 
labour and thought which I was conscious of having 
bestowed upon my task, I have conducted my history 
from the earliest ages of the speculative world up to 
our own days. 

To some persons it may iappear that I am not 
justified in calling thai a History of the Inductive 
Sciences, which contains an account of the progress 
of the physical sciences only. But it would have 
conveyed a false impression of my purpose, had I 
described my history in any manner which implied 
that the sciences which it embraces are partially 
selected or arbitrarily limited. Those of which the 
progress is exhibited in the present volumes, appear 
to me to form a connected and systematic body of 
knowledge. And if there be branches of knowledge 
which regard Morals, or Politics, or the Fine Arts, 
and which may properly be called Inductive (an 
opinion which I by no means gainsay) ; still it must 
be allowed, I think, that the processes of collectiug 
general truths from assemblages of special £EU3ts, and 
of ascending from propositions of a limited to those 
of a larger generality, which the term Indiu^tion 
peculiarly implies, have hitherto been far more 



PREFACE. Xiii 

dearly exhibited in the phjrsical sciences which form 
the subject of the present work, than in those hyper- 
physical sciences to which I have not extended my 
history. I will further add, that if I should be 
enabled hereafter to lay before the world a view of 
the Philosophy of Inductive Science in its general 
bearings, it will be requisite, in order to exhibit, in 
its due light the state of the philosophy of morals, 
or art, or any similar subject, to give a view of 
the steps by which it has reached its present 
position; and thus such a work will supply that 
which some may judge wanting to fill up the outline 
of this historical undertaking. 

As will easily be supposed, I have borrowed 
largely from other writers, both of the histories of 
special sciences and of philosophy in general*. I 
have done this without scruple, since the novelty of 
my work was intended to consist, not in its supe- 

* Among these, I may mention as works to which I have 
peculiar obligations, Tennemann's Geschichte der Philosophic, 
Degerando's Histoire Comparee des Systemes de Philosophic, 
Montucla's Histoire des Mathematiques, with Delambre's con- 
tinuation of it, Delambre's Astronomic Ancienne, Astronomic 
du Mojen ^ge, Astronomic Modeme, and Astronomic du Dix- 
huitiime Siecle ; Bailly's Histoire d' Astronomic Ancienne, and 
Histoire d' Astronomic Modeme, Voiron's Histoire d' Astronomic 



Xiv PRBFAOE. 

riority as a collection of &ct0» but in the point of 
view in which the facts were placed. I have, how- 
ever, in all cases, given references to my authorities^ 
and there are very few instances in which I have not 
verified the references of previous historians, and 
studied the original authors. According to the plan 
which I have pursued, the history of each science 
forms a whole in itself, divided into distinct but 
connected members, by the Epochs of its successive 
advances. If I have satisfied the competent Judges 
in each science by my selection of such epochs, the 
scheme of the work must be of permanent value, 
however imperfect may be the execution of any of 
its portions. 

With all these grounds of hope, it is still impos- 
sible not to see that such an undertaking is, in no 
small degree, arduous, and its event obscure. But 
all who venture upon such tasks must gather 
trust and encouragement from reflections like those 



(published as a continuation of Baillj), Fischer's Geschichte 
der Physik, Gmelin's Geschichte der Chemie, Thomson's History 
of Chemistry, Sprengel's History of Medicine, his History of 
Botany, and in aU branches of Natural History and Physiology, 
Cuviei^s works, in their historical, as in all other portions, most 
admirable and iostructire. 



PREFACE. XT 

by Mrhich their gr^at forerunner prepared himself 
for his endeavours; — ^by recollecting that they are 
aiming to advance the best interests and privileges 
of man ; and that they may expect all the best and 
wisest of men to join them in their aspirations and 
to aid them in their labours. 

"Concerning ourselves we speak not; but as 
touching the matter which we have in hand, this we 
ask ; — ^that men deem it not to be the setting up of 
an Opinion, but the performing of a Work; and 
that they receive this as a certainty ; that we are 
not laying the foundations of any sect or doctrine, 
but of the profit and dignity of mankiud : — Further- 
more, that being well disposed to what shall 
advantage themselves, and putting off factions and 
prejudices, they take common counsel with us, to 
the end that being by these our aids and appliances 
freed and defended from wanderings and impedi- 
ments, they may lend their hands also to the labours 
which remain to be performed : — ^And yet, further, 
that they be of good hope; neither feign and imagine 
to themselves this our Reform as something of infi- 
nite dimension and beyond the grasp of mortal man, 
when, in truth, it is, of infinite errour, the end and 
true limit ; and is by no means unmindful of the 



XVI PREFACE. 

condition of mortality and humanity, not confiding 
that such a thing can be carried to its perfect close 
in the space of one single age, but assigning it as a 
task to a succession of generations." 

Instaur. Mag. Prcef. ad fin. 



CONTENTS 



or 



THE FIRST VOLUME. 



Page 
Imtroduction . •••••• 3 

BOOK I. 

HISTORY OP THE GREEK SCHOOL PHILOSOPHY, WITH 
REFERENCE TO PHYSICAL SCIENCE. 

Chapter I. — ^Prelude to the Qreek School Philobophy. 

Sect. 1. First Attempts of the Speculatire Faculty in Phy- 
sical Inquiries • * . • . . 23 
Sect. 2. Primitiye Mistake in Greek Physical Philosophy . 32 

Chapter II. — The Greek School Philosophy. 

Sect. 1. The general Foundation of the Greek School Phi- 
losophy 37 

Sect. 2. The Aristotelian Physical Philosophy . . 41 

Sect. 3. Technical Forms of the Greek Schools . . 55 

1. . of the Aristotelian Philosophy . 55 

2. ■ of the Platonists ... 59 

3. — __ of the Pythagoreans . • 62 

4. — — — — of the Atomists and others . 63 

Chapter III. — ^Failure of the Greek School Philosophy. 

Sect. 1. Result of the Greek School Philosophy . • 67 
Sect. 2. Cause of the Failure of the Greek Physical Phi- 

losophy . . • . . • 72 



XViii CONTENTS OP THE FIRST VOLUME. 



BOOK 11. 

HISTORY OF THE PHYSICAL SaENCES IN ANCIENT 

OREECE. 

Page 

Introduction ^ • 89 

Chapter I. — Earliest Stages of Mechanics and 

Hydrostatics. 

Sect 1. Mechanics ...... 91 

Sect, 2. Hydrostatics 95 

Chapter II. — Earliest Stages of Optics. . . 98 
Chapter III. — Earliest Stages of Harmonics. . 102 

BOOK III. 
HISTORY OF GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

Introduction 109 

Chapter I. — Earliest Stages of Astronomy. 

S'tfc/. 1. Formation of the Notion of a Year . . .111 
Sect. 2, Fixation of the Civil Year . . . . 114 

Sect. 3. Correction of the Civil Year. (Julian Calendar) 120 
iS'ec^ 4. Attempts at the Fixation of the Month . .123 
Sect, 5. Invention of Lunisolar Years . . . 126 
Sect, 6. The Constellations ....«• 132 

Sect, 7. The Planets . ... . . . 137 

Sect, 8. The Circles of the Sphere » . • . 140 
Sect. 9. The Glohular Form of the Earth . . . 147 
Sect, 10. The Phases of the Moon . . . .150 

Sect, 11. Eclipses « 151 

Sect, 12. Sequel to the Early Stages of Astronomy . 154 

Chapter II. — Prelude to the Inductive Epoch op 

HiPPARCHUS. . . .157 

Chapter III. — lNDuc?rivE Epoch of Hipparchus. 

Sect, Ik Estahlishment of the Theory of Epicycles and 

Eccentrics 169 



CfONTRNTS OF THE FIRST VOLUICE. XIZ 

Page 
Sect. 2. Estimate of the Value of the Theory of Eooentiics 

and Epicycles . . . . • 179 

Sect 3. Discoyerj of the Precession of the Equinoxes . ]86 

Chapter IY. — Sequel to the Inductive Epoch of 

HiPPARCHUS. 

SecL 1. Researches which yerified the Theory *• .190 

Sect. 2. Researches which did not rerify the Theory « 194 
Sect. 3. Methods of Observation of the Greek Astronomers 197 

Sect, 4. Period from Hipparchus to Ptolemy . . • 205 

Sect. 5. Measures of the Earth . . . . 211 

Sect. 6. Ptolemy's Discovery of Evection . . .213 

Sect. 7. Conclusion of the History of Greek Astronomy . 220 

Sect. 8. Arabian Astronomy ..... 222 

BOOK IV. 

HISTORY OP PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE 

MIDDLE AGES. 

Introduction . . 235 

Chapter I.— On the Indistinctness op Ideas op the 

Middle Ages. . . . 237 

1. Collections of Opinions 239 

2. Indistinctness of Ideas in Mechanics . . . 241 

3. shown in Architecture . 246 

4. _— — in Astronomy . . . 248 

6. shown by Sceptics . . 249 

6. Neglect of Physical Reasoning in Christendom . . 252 

7* ' Question of Antipodes ..... 253 

8. Intellectual Condition of the Religious Orders • • 257 

9. Popular Opinions . • . . . . 260 

Chapter II. — ^The Commentatorial Spirit of the 

Middle Ages. • • . 264 * 

1 . Natural Bias to Authority 266 

2. Character of Commentators . • . « • 268 
3» Qreek Commentators on Aristotle • . . 271 



XX CONTENTS OF THE FDUST VOLUME. 

Page 

4. Greek Commentators on Plato and others • . 275 

5. Arabian Commentators on Aristotle . . . 276 

Chapter III. — Op the Mysticism op the Middle 

Ages 281 

1. Neoplatonic Theosophy 283 

2. Mystical Arithmetic 289 

3. Astrology 293 

4. Alchemy 303 

5. Magic 306 

Chapter IV. — Op the Dogmatism op the Middle 

Ages. 

1. Origin of the Scholastic Philosophy . . . .311 

2. Scholastic Dogmas .^. . . . . 316 

3. Scholastic Physics 324 

4. Authority of Aristotle among the Schoolmen . 325 

5. Subjects omitted. Civil Law. Medicine . . . 329 

Chapter V. — Progress op the Arts in the Middle 

Ages. 

1. Art and Science ....... 331 

2. Arabian Science ...... 336 

3. Experimental Philosophy of the Arabians . . . 338 

4. Roger Bacon ....... 341 

5. Architecture of the Middle Ages .... 343 

6. Treatises on Architecture 347 



BOOK V. 

HISTORY OP FORMAL ASTRONOMY AFTER THE 

STATIONARY PERIOD. 
Introduction . . . . . . . .355 

Chapter I.-p-Prelude to the Inductive Epoch op 

Copernicus. . . . 359 

Chapter II. — Induction of Copernicus. The Helio- 
centric Theory asser^fj) on formj^l Grounds. . 368 



CONTENTS OF THE FIRST VOLUME, XXI 

Page 
Chapter III. — SEauEL to Copernicus. The Reception 

AND DeVELOPEMENT OF THE CoPERNICAN ThEOBY. 

Sect 1. First Reception of the Copemican Theory . . 381 
Sect 2. Diffusion of the Copemican Theory . . 384 
Sect. 3. The Heliocentric Theory confirmed by Facts. 

Galileo's Astronomical DiscoYeries . . 392 
Sect. 4. The Copemican System opposed on Theological 

Grounds ...... 397 

Sect. 5. The Heliocentric Theory confirmed on Physical 
Considerations. (Prelude to Kepler's Astro- 
nomical Discoveries.) .... 404 

Chapter IV. — Inductive Epoch op Kepler. 

Sect^ 1 , Intellectual Character of Kepler , . . 410 
Sect. 2. Kepler's Discovery of his Third Law . .415 

Sect. 3. Kepler's Discovery of his First and Second Laws. 

Elliptical Theory of the Planets . . 421 

Chapter V. — Sequel to the Epoch of Kepler. Reception, 
Verification, and Extension of the Elliptical Theory. 

Sect. 1. Application of the Elliptical Theory to the 

Planets ...... 430 

Sect. 2. Application of the Elliptical Theory to the 

Moon 432 

Sect. 3. Causes of further Progress of Astronomy . 435 



VOL. I. 



ADDITIONAL NOTE IN VOL. X. 



« Page 69 line 7* I lutve attempted to lUustrate Bomewhat haHkew the 
nature of Inductive reasoning, in a stmall work entitled the Mechanical 
Euclid, and in the Remarks annexed thereto. 



Pa^ 42, line 16^ for inscribed, read iatented. 



INDEX OP PROPER NAMES. 



Abdollatif, 0. 891 

Aboazen, a. 900 

Aboul Wef% ct. 228 

Achard, b. 516 

Achillini, c. 394 

Adam Marsh, a, 258 

Adanson, e», 338 

Adelbold, a. 258 

Adelhard Groth, a, 258 

Adet, 0. 134 

Achilles Tatius, a. 188 

^pinus, 0. 17, 24, 34 

Agassiz, 0. 373, 514, 544 

Agatharohus, 6. 842 

Airy, b. 107, 228^ 277, 364, 446 

AlbaJbe^ius, a. 224 

Albertus Magnus^ a. 308^ 826; d 

270 
Albmnazar, a. 300 
Alexander Aphrodisiensis, a, 272 
Alexander the Great, a. 167 
Alfarabi, a. 279 
Alfred, a. 257 
Algazel, a. 251 
Alhazen, a. 339 ; b, 345 
Alis-ben-Isa, a. 212 
Alkindi, a. 879 
Almansor, a. 224 
Almeric, a. 326 
Alpetragius, a. 225 
Alphonso X., a. 180 
Amauri^ a, 326 
Ammonius Bacoas, a. 273, 264 
Ampere, 6. 528 ; c. 75, 78, 81, 142 
Anaxagoras, a. 43 ; b, 848 
Anaximander, a. 143, 147, 151 
Anaximenes, a. 26 
Anderson, b, 56 
Anna Coninen% a* 274 
Anselm, a. 314 

Arago, b, 871, 884, 416, 435 ; e. 91 
Aratus, a. 208 

Archimedes, a. 91, 95 ; 6. 844 
Arduino, o. 506 
Aristarchus, a. 156, 363 
Aristillus, a. 167 



AristophaiMS, a. 135 

AristoUe, m. 41; b. 44, 896, 844, 

349 ; 0. 261, 344, 358, 357, 383, 

387» 883, 412, 001 
Arnold de Villa Nora, a. 898 
Arriaga, 6. 45 
Artedi, e. 362 
Artephius, a. 308 
Aryabatta^ a. 364 
Arzachel, a. 225 
Asclepiades, o, 384 
Asdepigenia, a. 288 
AseUi, 0. 407 
Aredbron, a. 318 
Averroes, a. 280 
Avicenna^ a. 251, 879 
Avienus, a. 209 
Aubriet, o. 303 
Audouin, o. 458 
Augustine, a. 256, 296, 318 
AutolycuB, a. 148, 140 
Auzout, b, 273 

Babbage, Professor, e. 98, 580 

Bachman, 0. 301 

Bacon,FhuiC]s, a.886) b, 187, Udy 

296, 310, 501 
Bacon, Roger, b. 845 
BaUly, a. 259 ; b. 229, 247 
BaliaJii, 6. 30, 65 
Banister, c. 291 
Barlow, b, 364; c. 56, 80, 02 
Bartholin, b. 366 
Barton^ 6« 453 
Bauhin, John, 0, 292 
Bauhin, Gaspard, c. 294 
Beaumont, Elie de, o» 586, 534, 

542, 600 
Beccaria, 0. 18 
Beccher, 0. 116 
Bede, a, 257, 317 
Bell, Sir Charles, e. 485 
B^lon, 0. 359, 446 
B^edetti, b. 10, 20, 26, 46 
Bentley, b. 191, 195 
Berard, 6» 493 

b2 



XXIV 



INDEX OF PBOPEB NAMES. 



Bergman, 0. 114, 138, 200 
Bernard of Chartres, a. 314 
BemouUi, Daniel, b. 109, 113, 116, 

119, 201, 308, 318, 322 
Bemonlli, James, 6. 83, 23 
Bernoulli, James, the yonnger, 6. 

327 
Bernoulli, John, h. 84, 87, 93, 98, 

99, 110, 141, 201, 308 
Bernoulli, John, the younger, 6. 

310 
Berthollet, c, 115, 132, 138 
BerzetiuB, c. 142, 151, 175, 222, 

241 
Bessel, b. 107 
Betancourt, b. 516 
Beudant, e. 243 
Bichat, 0. 425 
Bidone, 6. 70 
Biela, b. .239 
Biker, 6. 516 
Biot, b, 375, 386, 425, 476 ; e. 55, 

56,87 
Black, b. 500; c 124, 138 
Blair, b. 364 
Bloch, c, 368 
Blondel, 6. 56 
Bock, e. 276 
Boethius, a. 257, 273 
Boileao, b, 137 
Bonaparte, e, 73, 162 
Bonaventura, a. 320 
Bontius, 0. 310 

Borelli, b. 24, 132, 141, 162, 164 
Bossut, b, 70 
Bou^, Ami, 0. 520 
Bouguer, 6. 112 . 
Bouillet, b. 503 
Bourdon, c. 421 
Boumon, e. 208 
Bonvard, b. 224 
Boyle, b, 144, 383, 501 ; e. 109 
Boze, c. 14 

Bradley, 6. 214, 220, 244, 254, 258 
Brander, c. 495, 509 
Brasavola, c. 272 
Brewster, Sir David, b, 360, 376, 

385, 434, 449; 0. 217 
BriggB,a.391 

Brisbane, Sir Thomas, b. 278 
Brocchi, 0. 514, 6 11 
Brochant de Villiers, c. 525, 534 
Broderip, e, 572 
Brongniart, Alexandre, c, 508, 531 



Brongniart, Adolphe, e, 543 

Brook Taylor, b. 85, 110, 307 

Brooke, c. 207 

Brougham, Lord, 6. 382, 431 

Brown, Robert, c. 339, 442 

Brunfels, e. 273 

Bruno, Giordano, a. 384 

Buat, b, 70 

Buch, Leopold von, c. 520, 525, 

542, 563 
Buckland, Dr., c. 536 
Budseus, a. 57 
Buffon, c. 192, 419, 445 
BuMnger, b. 88 
Bullialdus, a. 216; b, 149 
Burckhardt, b, 222, 233 
Burg, b, 224 
Burkard, c. 418 
Burnet, c. 566, 602 

Cabanis, c. 467 
Csesalpinus, c. 192, 277? 280 
Calceolarius, 0. 495 
Calippus, a. 130, 161 
Callisthenes, a. 167 
Gamerarius, Joachim, c. 278 
Camerarius, Rudolph Jacob, c. 416, 

418 
Gampanella, a. 303, 326 
Campani, 6. 273 
Camper, c. 445 
Canton, e^ 17, 49 
Capelli, b. 209 
CappeUer, c. 194 
Cardan, b. 9, 17, 37, 45 
Carlini, b. 246 
Came, c. 540 
Caroline, Queen, b, 192 
Carpa, c. 394 
Casrseus, b. 30 
Cafisini, Dominic, b. 217, 241, 255, 

280, 311 
Castelli, b, 52, 55, 62, 67 
Catelan, 5. 82 
Cavallieri, b. 201 

Cavendish, 6. 246 ; c. 26, 125, 133 
Cauchy, b, 117, 328, 455 
Cans, Solomon de, b. 40 
Cesare Cesariano, a. 349 
Chalid ben Abdolmalic, a. 212 
Chatelet, Marquise du, b, 88 
Chaussier, c, 425 
Chladni, b. 324, 326 
Christie, c. 92 : 



INDEX OF PROPER NAMES. 



Christina, b. 136 

Chrompr^, c. 176 

Cicero, a. 124 

Cigna, 6. Ill; e. 22 

Clairaut, 6. 100, 103, 113, 171, 213, 

238, 243, 363 
Clarke, b. 88, 194 
Cleomedes, a, 198, 207 
Clusins, e. 288 
Cobo, c, 290 

Colombe, Lndovico delle, b, 62 
Colnmbus, Realdus, o. 396, 403 
Columna, Fabius, o. 292 
Commandinus, b, 14 
Comparetti, b. 382 
Condamine, b. 241 
Constantine of Africa, c. 270 
Conti, Abb^ de, b. 86 
Conybeare, o. 613, 623 
Copernicus, a. 368 
Cosmas Indicoplenstes, a, 266 
Cotes, b. 97, 196 
Coulomb, c. 26, 30, 34, 63 
Crabtree, a, 391, 431 ; b. 146 
Cramer, b. 316 
Cronstedt, 0. 230 
Craicksbaiiks, 0, 70 
Cumming, Prof., c, 90 
Cunsaus, 0. 14 
Cnvier, c. 366, 429, 448, 463, 466, 

472, 610, 617, 608 

D*Alembert, b. 89, 96, 101, 108, 
110, 116,228,308,318 

D*Alibard, c. 18 

Dalton, Dr. John, b, 497, 609, 616, 
621; e. 147, 152 

DanieU, b. 621 ; 0. 669 

Dante, a. 362 

D'Arcy, b, 119 

Davy, c. 141, 167, 162, I70 

Daubenton, c, 446 

Daubeny, Dr., e. 666 

Danssy, b. 261 

De CandoUe, Prof. c. 339, 441 

Deohen, M. von., c. 636 

Defrance, e. 608, 612 

Degerando, a. 261, 311 

De la Beche, 0. 613 

Delambre, b. 222, 232 

De la Rive, Professor, 6. 633 

De Lisle, b, 202 

De Lnc, b, 606, 620 

D^meste^c. 197 



Democritns, a. 64 ; c. 268 

Derham, 6. 602 

Desaguliers, ell 

Descartes, b. 24, 32, 60, 56, 66, 76| 

131, 199, 347, 360; 0. 51. 
Des Hayes, e. 614 
Desmarest,'c. 602, 606 
Dexippns, a. 275 
Digges, b. 37 
DiUenius, c. 329 
Diogenes Laertins, a. 239 
Dioscorides, 0. 266, 270 
DoUond, b. 273, 363 
Dominis, Antonio de, b, 847 
Dubois, 0. 394 
Dufay, e. 10, 13, 21 
Du Four, b. 382 
Dufr^noy, 0. 626, 634 
Dulong, 6. 485, 633 
Duns Scotus, a. 321, 327 
Dunthome, b. 209 
Dupuis, a. 134 
Durret, a. 406 
Dutens, a. 71 
Duvemay, e, 444 

Ebn lonnis, a, 224 

Encke, b. 239, 263, 287 

Eratosthenes, a. 193 

Ericsen, 6. 606 

Eristratus, 0. 407 

Etienne, 0, 394] 

Evelyn, 6. 191 

Euclid, a. 98, 146 

Eudoxus, a. 161, 166 

Euler, 6. 93, 101, 104, 109, 113, 119, 

213, 308, 323 
Eusebius, a. 263 
Eustachius, e. 396, 408 
Eustratus, a. 274 

Fabricius, «. 276 

Fabricius of Acquapendentc, e, 

396, 412 
Fabricius, David, a. 427 
Fallopius, 0, 396 
Faraday, Dr., e, 80, 91, 163, 170 
Format, b. 66, 73 
Fitton, Dr., 0. 621 
Flacourt, c, 291 
Flamsteed, a. 434 ; b, 170, 179, 197, 

210 
Fleischer, b, 347 
Fontaine, 6. 108 



XXVl 



INDEX OF PEOPEE NAKES, 



FonteneBe, b. 219, 217; o. 112, 407 
Forbes, Professor, 6. 494 
Forster, Rev. Charles, a. 388 
Fouroroy, 0. 138, 188 
Fourier, b, 470, 482, 489, 523 
Fowler, 0. 73 
Fracastoro, 0. 494 
Francis I. (king of France) a. 827 
Franklin, 0. 12, 15, 29, 33 
Fraunhofer, b. 274, 365, 411, 456 
Frederic II., Emperor, a, 326 
Fresnel, 6. 371, 402, 400, 420, 485, 

522 
Fries, 0.354 
Frondnus, a. 350 
Fuchs, 0. 221, 274 
Faohsel,0. 503 

Gartner, 0. 333 

Galen, 0. 885, 381, 893, 493, 496 

GaUleo, a. 393; k I7, 98, 96, 28, 

47,56,69 
Gall, 0. 425, 427 
GalYani, 0. 66, 72 
Gambart, b, 239 
Gascoigne, 5. 354 
Gassendi, a. 406; &. 54, 187, 140, 

311 
Gauss, b. 107, 238 
Gay-Lnasac, 6. 49f, 508, «99( c. 

141, 153 
Geher, a. 996, 304 
CreUiloand, 0. 48 
Geminns, a. 129, 165, X>7 
GenerelH, CiilBo, «w 607 
Gaoffiroj (botaaisl), c 417 
Geoffiroy (chemiii), c^ 119 
Geoffiroy Saint-Hdair% c 448, 4tt, 

457 
Geoige PSMhymeraa, «. 974 

Gerberi, «. 957 

I, Mile. St^pbio!, A. 898 



Gessaer, e. 199, 978, 4M 

Ghim, 0.908 

Gibbon, «• 336 

Gabari, «. 39; 5. 143; 0u f, 45^ 48, 

51,58 
Giordano l^nuio^ a 384 
Giiard,*. 78 
GirtaniMr, It. 588 
CHseke, 0. 393 
Glisson, r, 437 
Gm^in, r. dl3 



Godefroy of St. Victor, a. 816 

Groldfiiss, 0. 514 

Goppert, c. 693 

Gothe, 6. 357; 0.434,440 

Gongh, b. 512 

Graham, b. 268 ; 0. 49 

Gramatici, b. 209 

Grazia, Yincenzio de, b, 62 

Greenough, 0. 525 

Gregory, David, 6. 195, 909 

Gregory VII., Pope, a. 308 

Gregory IX., Pope, «. 326 

Gren, b. 516 

Grew, 0. 414, 444 

Grey, 0. 10 

Grignon, 0. 196 

Grimaldi, b, 55, 362, 381 

Grotthus, 0. 175 

Guericke, Otto, 6. 310; 0. 9 

Gnettard, 0. 498 

Gnliefanini, 0. 194 

Guyton de Morvean, 0. 139, 188 

Hachetie, b, 70 

Hadley, b. 2^ 

Haidinger, 0. 216 

Halicon, a. 178 

Haller, 0. 327, 429 

Halley, a. 434 ; 6. 77t 147, 158, 190, 

196, 910, 995, 937, 248, 982; 

0.47 
Haly, a. 301 
Hamilton, Sir W. (matbom.), 5. 

451,460 
Hampden, Dr., a. 311 
Hansftit, A. 107 
Hansteen, 0. 48 
Harding, 5.984 
Hairis, Snow, 0. 35 
Harrison, 5. 971 
Hart8oe^i»r, 5.973 
Harvey, e. 397, 488, 419 
Haosmann, 0* 914 
Hauy, c. 199^ 205, 988 
HawkttBba^ 0. % 19 
Hegel, iu 181 
He^moait, c^ 187 
Henckel, 0. 194 
H^mIow, IVotenr, «» 448 
H^raefitusi, «. 96 
HeanMB. FiBl» 0. 988 
Hennamk, Contractaib m. 888 
Hamann, JanM% A. 89^ 88» 8B; «. 

301 



IHDBX OF PBOPSE NAMM 



•• 



XXTU 



Hermolaufl BarbanUi «• 67 

Hernandez, o, 200 

Herodotus, a. 27; o. 260, 401 

Herophilus, o. 387 

Herrenschneider, b. 478 

Herschel, Sir John, 6. 208, 864, 
386; c. 92, 218, d61, 566 

Herschel, Sir William, b. 280 

Hevelius, 6. 236, 267, 281 

Higgins, e. 148 

Hill, c. 196, 330 

Hipparchus, a. 168 

Hippasus, a. 104 

Hippocrates, o, 383 

Hof, K. E. A. von, c. 561 

Hofifinann, o. 626 
Home, 0. 613 
Homer, c. 383 

Hooke, A. 26, 73, 76, 132, 148, 168, 
165, 164, 304, 386, 366, 378, 
381, 391 ; 0. 607 
Hopkins, b. 323; o. 664 
Horroz, a. 391, 431 $ b. 146 
Hoskins, 6. 77 
Howard, Mr. Luke, b, 623 
Hudson, c. 330 
Hugo of St. Victor, a. 316 
Humboldt, Alexander von, e, 48, 

620, 641, 664 
Humboldt, Wilhdm von, 0. 71 
Hunter, John, 0, 445 
Hutton (fossOist), c. 514 
Button (geqbgist), b, 246; 0. 506, 

603 
Huyghens, b. 48, 67, 74, 81, 112, 
132, 149, 174, 311, 855, 367, 
392 
Hyginus, a. 209 

lamblichus, a. 287 

Ideler, a. 118 

Ivory, b. 107 

Jacob of Edessa, a, 278 

Jameson, Professor, a. 226, 505 

Job, a. 133 

John of Damascus, a. 274 

John Philoponus, a. 273 

John of Salisbury, a. 318, 822 

John Scot Erigena, a. 814 

Jordanus Nemorarius, 5. 10, 89 

Joseph, a. 309 

Julian, a. 288 

Jung, Joaofaim, c. 897 



Adrian de,0.8M 
Jussieu, Antoine l4Mirent da, e. 

335 
Jussieu, Bernard de, 0. 835 

Ksdmpfer, r. 291 

Kant, c. 469 

Kazwiri, 0. 600 

Keckerman, a, 324 

Keill, b. 98, 196; 0. ll(| 

Kelland, Mr. Philip, ^. 454^ 400 

Kempelen, b, 385 

Kepler, a. 371, 388, 410; 6. 78» 128, 

181, 266, 347 
Key, 0. 130 
Kircher, a. 293 
Kirwan, 0. 127, 138 
Klaproth, 0. 134 
Klingenstiema, b. 273, 863 
Knaut, Christopher, 0. 801 
Knaut, Christian, p. 801 
Konig, 0. 613 
Krafft, b. 473; 0. 60 
Kratzenstein, b, 604 
Kriege, 0. 291 

Lacaille, b. 222, 242 

Lactantius, a. 263 

Lagrange, b. 100, 108, 104, 105, 

106, 107, 110, 120, 229, 8U, 

318, 322 
L*Ain^, b. 469 
La Hire, b, 216, 255 
Lalande, b, 218, 231 
Lamarck, 0. 339, 448, 51^ 
Lambert, b. 328, 473; c, 58 
Landen, b. 109 
Lansberg, a. 406, 481 
Laplace, b. 104, 105, 106, 826, 947» 

816, 470, 482, 580, 559 
Lasus, a. 104 
LatreUle, 0. 460 
Lavoisier, 0. 128, 136 
Laughton, 6. 196 
Launoy, a, 326 
Laurenoett 0. 469 
Lawrence, 0. 575 
Lecchi, b, 70 

Leeuwenhoek, 0. 414, 419 
Legendre, 0. 55 
L*Hopital, b. 84 
Leibnitz, b. 86, 140 
Le Monnier, b. 210, 813, 256 



XXVlll 



INDEX OF PBOPEE NAMES. 



Leonardo 6a Ymd, a. 351 ; b. 122 ; 

e. 493, e06 
Leonicenus, c. 272 
Le Boi, b. 604, 521 
LesUe, b, 478, 489, 525 
Levy, c. 217 
Leucippus, a. 64, 75 
Lexell, b. 231, 239 
Lhwyd, c, 495 

Libri, ft. 487 
Lindenau, 6. 219 
Lindley, c. 442, 514 
Liimseus, c, 195, 304, 364 
Linus, b. 354 
Lister, c. 497> 500 
Littrow, b. 277 
Lloyd, Professor, ft. 451, 460 
Lobeck, ft. 461 
Lobel, c. 292, 338 
Locke, ft. 191 

Longomontanus, a, 422, 431 
Lonville, ft. 203, 217 
Lubbock, ft. 107, 250 
Lucan, a. 245 
Lucas, ft. 355 

Lyell, e. 483, 530, 552, 556, 567, 
570, 612 

Macleay, c, 353 

Msestlin, a. 383, 405 

Magin, a. 382 

Mairan, ft. 88 

Malpighi, c. 413, 414 

Malus, ft. 369,374 

Manilius, a, 209 

Maraldi, ft. 216, 382 

Marcet, ft. 533 

Margrave, o. 360 

Marinus (anatomist), o. 423 

Marinus (Neoplatonist), a, 288 

Mariotte, ft. 59 

Marsilius Ficinus, a. 328 

Martianus Capella, a. 363 

Martyn,T. 0.329 

Matthioli, c. 293 

Maupertuis, ft. 99, 203, 242 

Mayer, Tobias, ft. 214, 480 ; o. 29, 53 

Mayo, Herbert, e. 425 

Mayow, c. 130 

Mazeas, ft. 383; c. 18 

M'Cullagh, Professor, ft. 448, 460 

Meckel, c. 463 

Melloni, ft. 493 



Menelans, a, 208 

Mersenne, ft. 32, 53, 55, 65, 13G, 

302,317 
Messa, c. 394 
Meton, a. 128 
Meyranx, c. 459 
Michael Scot, a, 308 
Michell, c. 501 
Michelotti, ft. 70 
Miller, Professor, c. 217 
Milton, a. 262, 389; ft. 53 
Mitscherlich, c, 220 
Mohs, c. 207, 213, 237 
Mondino, c, 394 
Monge, c. 127 
Monnet, e. 498 
Monnier, c. 16 
Monteiro, c, 217 
Montfau9on, a. 255 
Morin, a. 406 
Morison, c, 295 
More, Lazzaro, e. 607 
Morveau, Guyton de, c, 132, 138 
Mosotti, c. 39 
Munro, c. 445 
Murchison, c. 530 
Muschenbroek, ft. 503 

Napier, a. 391, 437 

NaudsBus, a. 308 

Naumann, c. 249 

Newton, ft. 58, 68, 73,77, 92, 153, 
155, 158. 165, 175, 183, 203, 
256, 311, 321, 352, 368, 373, 
379, 395, 472 ; c. 429 

Nicephorus Blemmydes, a. 274 

Nicholas de Cusa, a. 367 

Nicomachus, a. 102 

Nigidius Figolus, a. 296 

Nobili, ft. 493 

Nollet, c. 13 

Nordenskiold, c. 246 

Norman, c. 47 

Norton, ft. 37 

Numa, a. 122, 365 

Odoardi, c. 503, 507 
Oersted, Professor, c. 77 
(Eyenhausen, e. 535 
Oken, Professor, c, 447 
Olbers, ft. 232 
Orpheus, a. 287 
Osiander, a. 378 



INDEX OF PROPER NAMES. 



Ott, b. 478 

Otto Gaericke, 0. 9, 13 

Ovid, c, 491 

Pabst von Ohain, c, 231 

Packe, c. 498 

Pallas, 0. 445, 503 

Papin, b, 515 

Pappus, a. 241 

Paracelsus, a. 308 ; 0. 10? 

Pardies, b. 354 

Pascal, b. 63 

Paulus III., Pope> a, 377 

Pecquet, e. 408 

Pepys, b. 191 

Perrier, b. 66 

Peter of Apono, a, 308 

Peter Bungo, a. 293 

Peter Damien, a. 316 

Peter the Lombard, a. 317 

Peter de Vineis, a, 326 

Petit, b. 485, 533 

Petrarch, a. 328 

PhUip, Dr. Wilson, e. 410 

Phillips, William, c. 207, 234, 523 

Philolaus, a» 362 

Photius, a. 276 

Piazzi, b. 232 

Picard, 6. 161, 256, 267, 311 

Piccolomini, b, 46 

Pictet, b. 507 

Picus of Mirandula, a. 308, 328 

Plana, b. 107 

Playfair, 6. 192 

Pliny, a. 178,239,295; c. 191,258, 

264 
Plotinus, a, 275, 284 
Plumier, c. 29] 
Plutarch, a. 61, 366 
Poisson, 6. 107, 117, 323, 328, 527; 

c. 32, 55, 562 
Polemarchus, a. 161 
Poncelet, b, 70 
Pond, b, 277 

Pontanus, Jovianus, 0. 416 
Pont^coulant, 6. 107 
Pope, b. 196 
Porphyry, a. 272, 275 
Posidonius, a. 212 
Potter, Mn Richard, 6. 453, 460 
Powell, Prof., b. 455, 460, 493 
Prevost, Pierre, 6. 474 
Prevost, Constant, c. 611 
Prichardy Dr., 0. 483, 575 



Priestley, e. 123, 126, 134 
Proclus, a. 269, 275, 988, 291, 298 
Prony, 6. 70.516 
Proust, r. 115 
Prout, Dr., 0. 152, 410 
Psellus, a. 275 
Ptolemy, a. 214; 6. 299 
Ptolemy Euei^tes, a. 200 
Purbach, a. 426 
Pythagoras, «. 24, 63, 137, 291 
Pytheas, a. 199 

Quetelet, b. 460 

Raleigh, c. 289 

Ramsden, b. 268 

Ramus, a. 327, 429 

Raspe, c. 506, 509 

Ray, c. 297, 360 

Raymund Lully,'a. 308 

Reaumur, e. 497 

Recchi, 0. 290 

Redi, 0, 444 

Reinhold, a. 381 

Rennie, Mr. Oeorgc, b. 71 

Rheede, 0. 290 

Rheticus, a. 375, 380 

Riccioli, a, 406 ; b. 55, 

Richman, 6. 473 ; o. 19 

Richter, 0. 146 

Riffault, c. 175 

Riolan, 0. 399 

Rivinus, 0. 301 1 

Rivius, a. 350 ; 6. 28 

Robert GrostSte, a. 258, 308 

Robert of Lorraine, a. 258 

Robert Mai^h, a. 258 

Roberval, 6. 311 

Robins, 6. 56 

Robinson, Dr., b. 277 

Robison, 6. 508, 515; c. 29 

Roger Bacon, a. 258, 308, 339, 241 

Rohault, 6. 138 

Romd de lisle, c. 195, 108, 205 

Romer, 6. 257, 281,311 

Rondelet, c. 359 

Roscoe, c. 339, 340 

Ross, Sir John, 0, 48 

Rothman, a. 372 

Rouelle, c. 502, 507 

Rousseau, c. 328 

Rudberg, b, 456 

Ruellius, 0. 272 

Rufus, 0. 387 



INDBX OF PBOPBR NAHSS. 



Bumphe> 0. 290 

SalnceSyi. Ill 

Salusbury, a. 391 

Salviani, c, 359 

Santbach, b, 27 

Santorini, e, 424 

Saron, b, 231 

Savart, 6. 323, 330; c. 80 

Savile, a. 270 

Saussure, 6. 620 ; c. 603 

Sauveur, b, 304, 317 

Scheele, c. 123 

Schelling, 6. 367 

Schlottheim, c. 606, 614 

Schmidt, c. 616, 664 

Schomberg, Cardinal, a. 377 

Schweigger, c. 89 

Schwerd, b. 462 

Scilla, c. 494 

Scot, Michael, e. 270 

Scrope, Mr. Poulett, 0. 666 

Sedgwick, Professor, a, 635, 640 

Sedillot, M., a. 228 

Seebeck, Dr., b, 376,386; 0. 90 

Segner, b. 109 

Seneca, a. 210, 363; 6. 63, 66 

Sergius, a. 278 

Servetus, 0, 395 

Sextns Empiriens, a. 261 

S'Gravesande, b. 88 

Shaipe, b, 61 7 

Sherard, c. 291 

Simon of Genoa, 0. 270 

Simplicius, a, 269, 273 

Sloane, 0. 291, 829 

Smith, Mr. Archibald, b. 460 

Smith, Sir James Edward, 0, 330 

Smith, William, c. 607, 516 

Snell, b. 347 

Socrates, c. 390 

Solomon, a. 309; c. 260 

Sorge, b. 319 

Sofl^fenes, a. 122, 210 

Sonthem, d. 617 

Sowerby, c. 614 

SpaUanzani, c. 410 

Spix, c. 447 

Sprengel, 0. 440 

Stahl, c. 116 

Stancari, 5. 304 

Steno, c. 193, 494, 502 

Stephanus, c, 394 

Stevinns, b. 16, 46, 61 



Stillingfleet, c. 330 

Stobseus, a. 276 

Stokes, c 693 

Strabo, a. 268 ; c. 263, 607 

Strachey, c. 501 

Stukeley, c. 601 

Svanberg, b, 484 

Sarian, 0. 291 

Sylvester II. (Pope), a. 257, 808 

Sylvius, c. 108, 394, 396 

Symmer, c, 22 

Syncellus, a. 121 

Synesius, a. 206 

Tacitus, a. 294 

Tartalea, b. 13, 20, 27 

Tartini, b. 319 

Taylor, Brook, b. 85, 110, 307 

Tchong-Kang, a. 162, 199 . 

Telauge, a. 291 

Tennemann, a. 311 

Thales,a.24,26,37, 143 

Thebit, a. 308 

Thenard, 0. 141 

Theodore Metochjrtes, a. 274 

Theodosius, a. 207 

Theophrastus, a, 271 ; 0. 258, 261, 

276 
Thomas Aqninas, a. 308, 318, 

326 
Thomson, Dr., 0. 149, 162 
Tiberius, a. 297 
Timocharis, a. 167 
Torricelli, b. 48, 62, 65, 67 
Toomefort, 0. 301, 417 
Tostatus, a. 266 
Totaril, Cardinal, a. 327 
Tragus, 0. 276 
Trithemius, a. 308 
Troughton, 6. 268 
Turner, 0. 162 
Tycho Brahe, a. 422, 432 ; h. 346 

Vaillant, Sebastian, 0. 417 

VallisnCTi, 0. 494 

Van Helmont, 0. 107 

Varignon, b. 69; 0. 409 

Varolius, 0. 424 

Yarro, Michael, b. 10, 17, 30, 89 

Vesalins, 0. 392, 394, 423 

Vicq d*Azyr, a. 424, 445 

Vieussens, 0. 425 

Vincent, b, 77 

Ymcent of Beanvais, 0. 270 



INDEX OF PROPER NAMES. 



XXXI 



Yinciy Leonardo da, 6. 122; o. 493, 

606 
Virgil (bishop of Salzburg), a. 3^ * 
Vii^l (a necromancer), a. 809 
YiteUio, b. 346 
YitruviuB, a. 348, 360 ; b. 296 
Viviani, b. 49, 63 
Voet, b. 136 
Voigt, c. 441 
Volta, c. 68, 72 
Voltaire, & 80, 203 
Voltz, 0. 634 
Von Kleist, o. 14 

Ubaldi, 5. 10 
Ulugh Beigh, a, 226 
Ungem-Stemberg, Count, o« 664 
Uranus, a. 278 
Ure, Dr., *. 617 
Usteri, 0. 440 

Wallerius, b. 606 ; o. 197 

Wallis, a. 391; 6. 63, 67, 182, 146, 

317 
Walmesley, b. 218 
Warburton, b, 196 
Ward, Seth, a. 391 ; b. 146 
Wargentin, 6. 220 
Watson, 0. 12, 16, 22 
Weber, Ernest and William, 6. 820 
Weiss, Prof, 0. 210, 213 
Wel]s,6. 610, 619; 0. 73 
Wenzel, c, 146 



Werner, e. 197, 224, 231, 604, 616, 

619,603 
Whaatstone, 6. 329 
Wheler. c. 291 
Whewell, 6.260; <;.216 
Whistou, b, 195 
Wilke, 6. 600; c. 18,26 
Wilkins (Bishop), a. 390; 6. 40, 146 
William of llirsangen, a. 268 
Willis, Rev. Robert, «. 848; «. 884, 

336 
Willis, Thomas, e. 428, 427 
Willoughby, 0. 360, 362 
Wolf, Caspar Frederick, «. 488 
Wolff, b. 88, 602 
Wollaston, 6. 366, 887, 869, 386; 

c. 149, 207 
Woodward, c, 496, 600, 002 
Wren, a. 391 ; b. 67, 146, 190 
Wright, 6. 209 

Xanthus, 0, 268 

Yates, 0. 48 

Young, Thomas, b. 71, 829, 402, 
426, 431 

Zabaxella, a. 324 
Zach, b. 233 
Zeiddler, b, 616 
Ziegler, b. 616 
Zinunerman, 0. 664 



INDEX OF TECHNICAL TERMS. 



Abeb&atiok, b. 258 

Absolute and relative^ a. 48 

Accelerating force, b. 32 

Achromatism, b, 363 

Acid, c. 109 

Acoustics, b. 304 

Acronycal rising and setting, a. 146, 

and erreUa 
Action and reaction, 6. 58 
Acuation, c. 107 
Acumination, c. 197 
Acute harmonics, 5. 317 
iEtiology, c. 482 
Affinity (in Chemistry), c. 113 
Affinity (in Natural iffistory), c. 353 
Agitation, centre of, b, 81 
Alidad, a. 231 
Alineations, a. 192 
Alkali, c. 109 
Almacantars, a. 231 
Almagest, a. 214 
Almanac, a. 231 
Alphonsine tables, a. 225 
Alternation (of formations), o, 541 
Amphoteric sUicides, c. 250 
Anflogy (in Natural History), o. 

353, 355 
Analysis (chemical), c. 107 

^olar, of light), b. 384, 385 

Angle of cleavage, c, 202 
■ incidence, b, 342 

reflection, b. 342 

Animal electricity, c. 66 
Anion, c, 166 
Annus, a. 113 
Anode, e. 166 
Anomaly, a. 151, 171 
Antarctic circle, a. 144 
Antichthon, a. 70 
Anticlinal line, c. 539 
Antipodes, a, 253 
Apogee, a. 172 

Apotelesmatic astrology, a. 301 
Apothecee, o. 268 
Appropriate ideas, a. 80 
Arctic circle, a. 144 



Armed magnets, c. 49 

Armil, a. 200 

Art and science, a. 331 

Articulata, c, 449 

Artificial magnets, c. 50 

Ascendant, a. 300 

Astrolabe, a. 203 

Atmology, b, 466, 581 

Atom, a. 64 

Atomic theory, c. 145 

Axes of symmetry (of crystals), c. 

211 
Axis (of a mountain cliain), c, 539 
Azimuth, a. 231 
Azot, c. 129 

Ballistics, b, 97 
Bases (of salts), c. HI 
Basset (of strata), o. 502 
Beats, 6. 304 

Calippic period, a. 130 

Caloric, b, 474 

Canicular period, a. 122 

Canon, a. 172 

Capillary action, b, 113 

Carbonic acid gas, c. 129 

Carolinian tables, a. 434 

Catasterisms, a. 193 

Categories, a. 272 

Cathion, c. 166 

Cathode, c, 166 

Cation, c. 166 

Causes, material, formal, efficient, 

final, a, 53 
Centrifugal forces, b. 36 
Cerebral system, 0. 425 
Chemical attraction, <;. Ill 
Chyle, e. 407 
Chyme, c, 409 

Circles of the sphere, a. 140 
Circular polarization, 6. 388, 444 
Circular progression (in Natural 

History), c. 353 
Civil year, a. 120 
Climate, b, 479 



INDEX OF TECHNICAL TERMS« 



xxxni 



Coexistence of vibrations, b. 318 

Coexistent vibrations, 6. Ill 

Colures, a. 145 

Conditions of existence (of ani- 
mals), e. 467, 472 

ConducibUity, b, 475 

Conductibility, b, 475 

Conduction, b. 468 

Conductivity, b, 475 

Conductors, c. 11 

Conical refraction, 6. 451 

Conservation of areas, 6. 110 

Consistence (in Thermotics), b, 499 

Constellations, a. 132 

Constituent temperature, 6. 513 

Contact-theory of the Voltaic pile, 
c. 160 

Cor (of plants), c. 283 

Cosmical rising and setting, a, 146 

Cotidal lines, 6. 252 

Craters of elevation, c. 463 

DsBmon, a. 286 

D*Alembert*s principle, b. 96 

Day, a. Ill 

Decussation of nerves, c. 424 

Deduction, a. 15 

Definite proportions (in Chemis- 
try), 0, 145 

Delta, e. 553 

Dephlogisticated air, 0. 126 

Depolanzation, b, 384 

Depolarization of heat, b. 495 

Depolarizing axes, b, 385 

Descriptive phrase (in Botany), c. 
313 

Dew, 6. 519 

Dichotomized, a. 155 

Difiraction, b. 387 

Dimorphism, c* 223 

Dioptra, a. 204 

Dipolarization, 6. 384, 424 

Direct motion of planets, a, 150 

Discontinuous functions, 6. 316 

Dispensatoria, c. 268 

Dispersion (of light), b, 453 

Doctrine of the sphere, a. 144 

Dogmatic school (of medicine),o.384 

Double refraction, b, 366, 403, 413 

Eoeentric, a. 170 
fichineis, a, 245 
Eclipses, a. 151 
Eocene, a. 529 



Effective forces, b, 85 
Elective attraction, 0. 112 
Electrical current, c 74 
Electricity, c. 7 
Electrics, c. 11 
Electric tension, e. 74 
Electro-dynamical, 0. 81 
Electrodes, c. 166 
Electrolytes, c. 166 
Electro-magnetism, e, 77 
Electro-magnetic induction, c. 95 
Elements (chemical), c. 183 
Elliptical polarization, 6. 447 
Empiric school (of medicine), c. 384 
Empyrean, a. 70 
Enneads, a. 285 
Entelechy, a. 57 
Epicycles, a. 160, I70 
Epochs, a. 12 
Equation of time, a. 193 
Equator, a. 144 
Equinoctial points, a. 145 
Escarpment, c. 539 
Evection, a. 215 
Exchanges of heat, theory of, b, 474 

Facts and ideas, a. 6 

Faults (in strata), o. 539 

Final causes, 0. 389, 472 

Finite intervals (hypothesis of), b, 

454 
First law of motion, 6. 22 
Fits of easy transmission, b, 396 
Fixed air, c. 125 
Fixity of the stars, a. 191 
Formal optics, b. 340 
Franklinism, c. 22 
Fresnel's rhomb, 6. 424 
Fringes of shadows, 6. 382, 451 
Fuga vacui, b. 64 
Full months, a. 128 
Function (in Physiology), c. 377 

Galvanism, c. 69 
Galvanometer, c. 89 
Ganglionic system, c. 425 
Ganglions, c. 424 
Generalisation, a. 11 
Greocentric theory, a. 360 
Gnomon, a. 119 
Gnomonick, a, 155 
Golden number, a, 130 
Grave harmonics, 6. 319 
Gravitate, b. 163 



XXXIT 



mDEX OF TECHNICAL TEBMS. 



Habitations (of plants), e, 671 
Hsecceity, a. 321 
Hakemite tables, a. 2i6 
Halogenes, c. 183 
Haloide, c. 249 
Harmonics, acute, 6. 317 

gravO) ** 81^ 

Heat, h. 468 

latent, 6. 429 

Heccsedecaeteris, a. 127 
Height of a homogenous atmo- 
sphere, 6. 314 
Heliacal rising and setting, a. 145 
Heliocentric theory, a* 860 
Hemisphere of Berosus, a. 200 
Hollow months, a. 128 
Homoiomeria, a. 64 
Horizon, a, 146 
Horoscope, a. 300 
Horror of a vacuum, b, 64 
Houses (in Astrology), a. 300 
Hydracids, c. 142 
Hygrometer, b, 620 
Hygrometry, 5. 467 
Hypostatical principles, e, 107 

latro-chemists, 0. 108 
Ideas of the Platonists, tu 69 
Ilchanic tables, a. 226 
Impressed forces, b, 85 
Inclined plane, b, 9 
Induction (electric), c. 17 
Induction (logical), a. 6 
Inductive, a. 6 
Inductive charts, a. 13 
Inductive epochs, a. 12 
Inflammable air, c. 125 
Influences, a. 294 
Intercalation, a. 121 
Interferences, 6. 391, 403 
Ionic school, cu 24 
Isomorphism, c 220 
Isothermal lines, 6. 480 ; e. 641 
Italic school, a. 24 

Joints (in rocks), c, 640 
Judicial astrology, a. 301 
Julian calendar, a. 123 

Lacteals, c. 407 
Latent Heat, 5. 499 
Laws of motion, first, b, 22 

second, ft. 36 

third, 6. 44 



Leap year, a. 121 
Leyden phial, e, 14 
Librations (of planets), a, 421 
Idmb of an instrument, a. 199 
Longitudinal vibrations^ 0. 880 
Lunisolar year, a. 126 
Lymphatics, 0. 408 

Magnetic elements, e» 64 

equator, c. 48 

Magnetism, c. 46 

Matter and form, a, 66 

Mean temperature, b. 479 

Mechanidd mixture of gases, 6. 613 

Mechanico-chemieal sciences, 0. 6 

Meiocene, 0. 629 

Meridian line, a, 202 

Metals, 0. 180 

Meteorology, 6* 466 

Meteors, a. 78 

Methodic school (of medicine), 0. 
385 

Metonic cycle, a. 128 

Mineral aUcali, 0. 110 

Mineralogical axis, 0. 639 

Minutes, a. 201 

Miocene, 0. 629 

Mollusca, 0» 449 

Moment of inertia, 6. 80 

Momentum, 6. 49 

I^Ioon*s libration, b, 100 

Morphology, 0. 433, 436 

Moveable polarization, 6» 486 

Multiple proportions (in Chemis- 
try), 0. 146 

Music of the spheres, a. 71 

Mysticism, a. 281 

Nadir, a. 231 

Nebular hypothesis, 0. 486 

Neoplatonists, a, 276 

Neutral axes, ft. 386 

Neutralisation (in Chemistry), 0. 

109 
Newton's rings, b, 879, 460 
■ scale of colour, ft. 879 

Nitrous air, 0. 126 
Nomenclature, 0. 307 
Nominalists, a. 389 
Non-electrics, 0. 11 
Numbers of the Pythagoi^eans, s. 6fi! 
Nutation, ft. 260 
Nycthemer, a. 194 



INtlfiX Cnf TECHNICAL T&RMS. 



XXXV 



Octaeteris, a. 126 
Octants, a, 228 
Oolite, c, 530 
Optics, 6. 340 
Orgonical scicttices, e, 377 
Organic molecules, e. 419 
Organization, o. 377 
Oscillation, centre of, b. 79 
Outcrop (of strata), e. 502 
Oxide, e. 138 
Oxyd, c, 138 
Oxygen, c, 129 

Palaeontology, o. 0l3 
PalaBtiological sdences, c, 481 
Parallactic instrument, a, 204 
Parallax, a. 195 
Percussion, eentre of, 6, 81 
Perfectihabia, a, 58 
Perigee, a, 170 
Perijove, 6. 229 
Periodical colours, b. 403 
Phases of the moon, a. 150 
Philolaic tables, a, 434 
Phlogisticated air, c. 126 
Phlogiston, c. 118 
Phthongometer, b. 336 
PhjBictd optics, 6. 340 
Piston, 6. 63 
Pla^edral faces, b, 388 
Plane of maximum areas, 6. 119 
Pleiocene, c. 529 
Flesiomorphous, c, 222 
Pliocene, c. 529 
Plumb line, a. 202 
Pneumatic trough, c. 125 
Poikilite, c. 530 
Polar decompositions, c. 158 
Polarization, 6. 375, 403, 415, 535 

circular, b, 388, 444 

elliptical, b. 447 

movable, b. 425 

plane, b, 444 

of heat, b. 463 

Poles (voltaic), c 165 

-^— of maximum cold, b. 480 

Potential levers, b, 122 

Power and act, a, 56 

Precession of the equinoxes, a, 186 

Predicables, a. 272 

Predicaments, a. 272 

Preludes of epochs, a. 12 

Primary rocks, o. 503 

Primitive rocks, c, 503 



Primum calidum, a, 61 
Principal plane (of a rhomb), b. 373 
Principle of least action, 5. 119 
Prosthaphseresis, a. 171 
Provinces (of plants and animals), 

0.571 
Prutenic tables, a. 38S 
Pulses, 5. 312 
Pyrites, c. 249 

Quadrant, a. 202 
Quadrivium, a. 260 
Quiddity, a. 321 

Quinary division (in Natural His- 
tory), e. 853 
Quintessence, a, 54 

Radiata, c, 449 
Badiation, b. 468 
Rays, b. 342 
Realists, a. 329 
Refraction, b, 344 

of heat, b, 495 

Remora, tf. 245 
Resinous electricity, c. 12 
Rete mirabile, c. 424 
Retrograde motion of planets, a. 159 
Roman calendar, a. 131 
Rotatory vibrations, 6. 3S(0 
Rudolphine tables, a, 382, 431 

Saros, a. 154 

Scholastic philosophy, a. 315 

School philosophy, a, 19 

Science, a. 

Secondary rocks, c. 509 

meclianical science<:i, b, 

293 
Second law of motion, b. 36 
Seconds, a. 201 
Secular inequalities, b. l05 
Segregation, c. 565 
Seminal contagion, c. 419 

proportions, a. 65 

Sequels of epochs, a, 12 
Silicides, c. 250 
Silurian rocks, c, 530 
Sunples, c. 269 
Sine, a. 230 
Solar heat, b, 477 
Solstitial points, a. 145 
Solution of water in air, 5. 504 
Sothic period, a. 122 
Spaglric art, c. 107 



* 



XXXVl 



INDEX OF TECHNICAL TERMS. 



Specific heat, b. 498 
Sphere, a. 144 

Spontaneous generation, c. 414 
Statical electricity, c. 33 
Stationary periods, a. 15 

planets, a, 159 

Stations (of plants), c. 571 
Sympathetic sounds, 6. 317 
Systematic Botany, c, 254 

Zoology, c, 343 

Systems of crystsdUzation, c. 212 

Tahles, Solar (of Ptolemy), a. 172 

Hakemite, a. 226 

Toletan, a. 225 

Uchanic, a. 225 

Alphonsine, a. 225 

Prutenic, a. 382 

Rudolphine, a. 431 

Perpetual (of Lansberg), 

a. 431 

Philolaic, a. 434 

Carolinian, a, 434 

Tangential vibrations, b, 332 
Tautochronous curves, b. 108 
Technical terms, c. 307 
Temperament, 6. 335 
Temperature, b. 469 
Terminology, c. 307 
Tertiary rocks, c. 503 
Tetractys, a. 62 
Theqry of analogues, c. 457 
Thermomultiplier, 6. 493 
Tliermotics, b, 465 
Thick plates, colours of, b, 383 
Thin plates, colours of, b. 378 
Third law of motion, b, 44 
Three principles (in Chemistry), c. 

106 
Toletan tahles, a. 225 
Transition rocks, o. 530 






Transverse vibrations, b. 330, 403, 

419 
Travertin, e. 553 

Trepidation of the fixed stars, a. 227 
Trigonometry, a. 207 
Trivial names, c. 312 
Trivium, a. 260 
Tropics, a. 144 

Truncation (of crystals), c. 196 
Type (in Comparative Anatomy), 

0.446 

Variation of the moon, a. 221 
Vegetable alkali, c. 110 
Vertebrata, e. 449 
Vibrations, b. 330 
Vicarious elements, e. 221 

solicitations, b. 85 

Virtual velocities, 6. 41 
Vitreous electricity, c. 12 
Volatile alkali, c. 110 
Volta-electrometer, c, 166 
Voltaic electricity, c. 69 

pile, c. 70 

Volumes, theory of, c. 153 
Voluntary, violent, and natural 

motion, b, 18 
Vortices, b. 134 

Uniform force, b.3l 

Unity of composition (in Compa- 
rative Anatomy), c. 457 

Unity of plan (in Comparative 
Anatomy), e. 457 

Week, a. 139 

Year, a. 112 

Zenith, a. 231 
Zodiac, a. 145 
Zones, a, 154 



HISTORY 



OP 



INDUCTIVE SCIENCES, 



INTRODUCTION. 



VOL. 1. B 



^'A JUST story of learning, containing the antiquities and originals 
of KNOWLEDGES, and their sects; their inyeutioBS, their txaditions, 
their diverae administrations and managings; their flourishings, their 
oppositions, decays, depressions, oblivions, removes; with the causes 
and occasions of them, and all other events concerning learning, 
throughout all ages of the world; I may truly affirm to be wanting. 

^^ The use and end of which work I do not so much design for 
curiosity, or satisfaction of those that are the lovers of learning : but 
chiefly for a more serioaB and grave purpose; which is this, in few 
words, that it vill make learned men more wise in the use and 
administration of learning.'* 

Bacok, Advancement of Learning, book ii. 



INTRODUCTION. 



It is my purpose to write the history of some of 
the most important of the physical sciences, from 
the earliest to the most recent periods. I shall 
thus have to trace some of the most remarkable 
branches of human knowledge, from their first 
germ to their growth into a vast and varied assem- 
blage of undisputed truths; from the acute, but 
fruitless, essays of the early Greek philosophy, to 
the comprehensive systems, and demonstrated gene- 
ralizations, which compose such sciences as the 
Mechanics, Astronomy, and Chemistry, of modem 
times. 

The completeness of historical view which belongs 
to such a design, consists, not in accumulating aU 
the details of the cultivation of each science, but 
in marking clearly the larger features of its forma- 
tion. The historian must endeavour to point out 
how each of the important advances was made, by 
which the sciences have reached their present posi- 
tion; and when and by whom each of the valuable 
truthi^ was obtained, of which the aggregate now 
constitutes a costly treasure. 

B 2 



4 HISTORY OF INDUCmVE SCIENCES. 

Such a task, if fitly executed, must have a well- 
founded interest for all those who look at the exist* 
ing condition of human knowledge with complacency 
and jidmiration. The present generation finds itself 
the heir of a vast patrimony of science; and it must 
needs concern us to know the steps by which these 
possessions were acquired, and the documents by 
which they are secured to us and our heirs for ever. 
Our species, from the time of its creation, has been 
travelling onwards in pursuit of truth; and now 
that we have reached a lofty and commanding posi- 
tion, with the broad light of day around us, it must 
be grateful to look back on the line of our past 
progress; — to review the journey, begun in early 
twilight amid primeval wilds; for a long time con* 
tinned with slow advance and obscure prospects; 
and graduaUy and in later days followed along more 
open and lightsome paths, in a wide and fertile 
region. The historian of science, from early periods 
to the present times, may hope for favour on the 
score of the mere subject of his narrative, and in 
virtue of the curiosity which the men of the present 
day may naturally feel respecting the events and 
persons of his story. 

But such a survey may possess also an interest 
of another kind; it may be instructive as well as 
agreeable; it may bring before the reader the presait 
form and extent, the future hopes and proifiects of 
science, as well as its past progress. The eminence 
on which we stand may enable us to see the land 



INTRODUCTION. 5 

of promise as well as the wilderness through which 
we have passed. The examination of the steps by 
which our ancestors acquired our intellectual estate, 
may make us acquainted with our expectations as 
well as our possesions ; — may not only remind us 
of what we have, but may teach us bow to improve 
and increase our store. It will be universally ex- 
pected that a history of Inductive Science should 
point out to us a philosophical distribution of the 
existing body of knowledge, and afford us some 
indication of the most promising mode of directing 
our future efforts to add to its extent and complete- 
ness. 

To deduce such lessons from the past history of 
human knowledge, was the intention which originally 
gave rise to the pretent work. Nor is this portion 
of the design in any measure abandoned ; but its 
execution, if it take place, must be attempted in a 
separate and future treatise. On the PhUmophy of 
Inductive Science. An essay of this kind may, I 
trust, from the progress already made in it, be laid 
before the public at no long interval after the present 
history. 

Though, therefore, many of the principles and 
maxims of such a work will disclose themselves 
with more or less of distinctness in the course of 
the history on which we are about to enter, the 
systematic and complete exposition of such prin- 
ciples must be reserved for this other treatise. My 
attempts and reflections have led me to the opinion 



6 HISTORY OF INDUCTIVE SCIENCES. 

that justice cannot be done to the subject without 
such a diidslon of it. 

To this Aiture work, then, I must refer the 
reader who is disposed to require, at the outset, a 
precise explanation of the terms which occur in my 
title. It is not possible, without entering into this 
philosophy, to explain adequately how science whicb 
is Inductivb differs from that which is not so ; or 
why some portions of knowledge may properly be 
seled^ed from the general nuuss and termed Science. 
It will be sufficient at present to say, that the 
sciences of which we have here to treat, are those 
which are commonly known as the Physical Sciences; 
and that by IndmHon is to be understood that pro- 
cess of collecting general truths fit>m the examination 
of particular fects, by which such sciences have been 
formed. 

There are, however, two or three remarks, of 
which the application will occur so frequently, and 
will tend so much to give us a clearer view of some 
of the subjects which occur in our history^ that I 
will state them now in a brief and general manner. 

Facts and Ideas. — In the first place, then, I re- 
mark, that, to the formation of science, two things 
are requisite; — ^facts and ideas ; observation of things 
without, and an inward effort of thought; or, in 
other words, sense and reason. Neither of these 
elements, by itself, can constitute substantial general 
knowledge. The impressions of sense, unconnected 
by some rational and speculative principle, can only 



, INTKODUCnON. 7 

end in a practical acquaintance with indiTidoal 
olgects ; the operations of the rational fiu^nhies, on 
the other hand, if alloiiFBd to go on without a con- 
stant reference to external thiB^ can lead only to 
empty abstraction and barren ingenuity. Real 
specuhtive knowledge demands the combination of 
the two ingredients ;-^right reason, and feets to 
reason upon. It has been well said, that true know« 
ledge is the interpretation of nature; and thus it 
requires both the interpreting mind, and nature for 
its subject ; both the document^ and the ingenuity 
to read it aright. Thus invention, acuteness, and 
connexion of thought, arc necessary on the one 
hand, for the progress of philosophical knowledge; 
and on the other hand, the precise and steady 
application of these feculties to facts well known 
and clearly conceived. It is easy to point out 
instances in which science has fiedled to advance, in 
consequence of the absence of one or other of these 
requisites; indeed, by &r the greats part of the 
course of the woorld, the history of most times and 
most countries, exhibits a condition thus stationary 
with respect to knowledge. The jGstcts, the im- 
pressions on the senses, on which the first successful 
attempts at physical knowledge proceeded, were as 
well known long before the time when they were 
thus turned to account, as at that period. The 
motions of the stars, and the effects of weight, were 
fi^niiliflr to man before the rise of the Greek astro- 
nomy and mechanics : but the '' diviner mind" was 



8 HISTORY (HP INDUCmVK SCIENCES. 

sMU absent; the act of thoiiglit had not be^i ex** 
ertedy by which these facts were bound together 
under the fonn of hiws and principles. And ereti 
at this day, the tribes of uncivilized and half-civilized 
man over Uie whole face of the earth, have before 
their eyes a vast body of Acts, of exactly the same 
nature as those with whidi Europe ha« built the 
stately fitbric of her physical philosophy; but, in 
almost every other part of the earth, the process ci 
the intellect by which these facts beooma sci^ice, is 
unknown. The scientific ftcuity does not work. 
The scattered stones are indeed there, but the 
builder^s hand is wanting. And again, we have no 
lack of proof that the mere activity of thought is 
equally inefficient in producing real knowledge* 
Almost the whole of the career of the Greek schools 
of philosophy ; of the schoolmen of Europe in the 
middle ages; of the Arabian and Indian philoso- 
phers; shows us that we may have extreme ingenuity 
and subtlety, invention and connexion, demonstrar 
tion and method ; and yet that out of these germs, 
no physical science may be developed. We may 
obtain, by such means, logic and metaphysics, and 
even geometry and algebra ; but out of such mate- 
rials we shall never form mechanics and optics, 
chemistry and physiology. How impossible is the 
formation of these sciences without a constant and 
careful reference to observation and experiment ; — 
how rapid and prosperous may be their progress 
when they draw from such sources the materials on 



IMTRODUOnOI^. 9 

vMck the mind of the philosopher employs itsdf ^^ 
the history of those branches of knowledge for the 
last three hundred yeaxs abundantly teaches us. 

Accordingly, the existence of clear ideas applied 
to distinct &cts will be discernible in the History of 
Science^ whenever any marked advance takes place. 
And, in tracing the progress of the various provinces 
of knowledge which oome under our survey, it will 
be important for us to see, that, at all such epochs, 
such a combination has ooourred; that whenever 
any material step in general knowledge has been 
made,-«~wh6never any philosophical discovery arrests 
our attrition ; — ^some man or men come before us, 
who have possessed, in an eminent degree, a clear* 
ness of the ideas which belong to the subject in 
question* and who have applied such ideas in a 
vigorous and. distinct manner to ascertained fects 
and exact observations. We shall never proceed 
liirough any considerable range of our narrative, 
without having occasion to remind the reader of 
this reflection. 

Successive steps m Science. — ^But there is another 
remark which we must also make. Such sciences 
as we have here to do with, are, commonly, not 
formed by one single act ; — ^they are not completed 
by the discovery of one great principle. On the 
contrary, they consist in a long^continued advance ; 
a series of changes ; a repeated progress from one 
principle to another, different and often apparently 
contradictory. Now, it is important to remember 



10 HISTORY OP INDUCTTVK SCIENCES. 

that this eontradiction is apparent only. The prm^ 
ciples which constituted the trimnph of the pre- 
ceding stages of the science, may appear to be sub- 
verted and ejected by the later discoveries, but in 
fiict they are, (so £ur as they were true,) taken up 
into the subsequent doctrines and included in ihem* 
They continue to be an essential part of the science. 
The earlier truths are not expelled but absorbed^ 
not contradicted but extended ; and the history of 
each science, which may thus appear like a succes- 
sion of revolutions, is, in reality, a series of deve* 
lopements. In the intdleetual, as in the matmal 
worid,— 

Omnia mutantur nil interit 

Nee manet ut fuerat nee formas senrat easdem, 
Sed tamen ipsa eadem est. 

All ehanges, nought is lost ; the forms are changed, 
And that whidi has be^i is not ^at it was, 
Yet that whidi has heen is. 

Nothing which was done is useless or unessential, 
though it ceases to be conspicuous and primary. 

Thus the final fonn of each science contains the 
substance of each of its preceding modifications ; 
and all that was at any antecedent period discovered 
and established, ministers to the ultimate develope- 
ment of its proper branch of knowledge. Such 
previous doctrines may require to be made precise 
and definite, to have their superfluous and arbitraiy 
portions expunged, to be expressed in new language, 
to be taken up into the body of science by various 



INTRODUCTION* 11 

processes ; — ^but they do not on audi aoeonnts cease 
to be true dootrines, or to form a portion of the 
essential constituents of our knowledge. 

Terms record Discaveries. — ^The modes in which the 
earlier truths of science are preserved in its later 
forms, are indeed various. From being asserted at 
first as strange discoveries^ such truths come at last to 
be implied as ahnost self-evident axioms. They are 
recorded by some familiar maxim, or perhaps by some 
new word or phi«e. which forms paTofTe e«n«nt 
language of the philosophical world; and thus asserts 
a principle, while it appears merely to indicate a tran* 
sient notion ; — ^preserves as well as expresses a truth ; 
— and, like a medal of gold, is a treasure as well as a 
token. We shall frequently have to notice the man- 
ner in which great discoveries thus stamp their im- 
press upon the terms of a science; and, like great 
political revolutions, are recorded by the change of 
the current coin which has accompanied them. 

Generalizaiion. — The great changes which thus 
take place in the history of science, the revolutions 
of the intellectual world, have, as a usual and lead- 
ing character, this, that they are steps of ffeneraUzor 
turn /-^transitions firom particular truths to others of 
a wider extent, in which the former are included. 
This progress of knowledge, from individual facts to 
universal laws, — ^from particular propositions to 
general ones, — ^and from these to others still more 
general, with reference to which the former genera^, 
lizations are particular, — is so far familiar to men's 



12 HISTORY OF DTBUCnTE SCIENCES. 

minds, that without here entering into further ex-» 
{Sanation, its nature will be understood sufficiently 
to pr^are the reader to recognise the exemplifica- 
tions of such a process, which he will find at every 
step of our advance. 

Inductive Epochs ; Prdvdes ; Sequek.^^In our his- 
tory, it is the progress of knowledge only which we 
have to attend to. This is the main action of our 
drama ; and all the events which do not bear upon 
this, though they may relate to the cultivation and 
the etdtivators of philosophy, are not a necessary 
part of our theme. Our narrative will therefore 
consist mainly of successire steps of generalization, 
flNidh as have just been mentioned. But among 
these, we shall find some of eminent and decisive 
importance, which have more peculiarly influenced 
the fortunes of physical philosophy, and to which 
we may consider the rest as subordinate and auxi- 
liary. These primary movements, when the Induc- 
tive process, by which science is formed, has been 
exercised in a more energetic and powerful manner, 
may be distinguished as the Indtidwe Epochs of 
scientific history; and they deserve our more ex- 
press and pointed notice. They are, for the most 
port, marked by the great discoveries and the great 
philosophical names which all civilized nations have 
agreed in admiring. But, when we examine more 
Nearly the history of such discoveries, we find that 
these epochs have not occurred suddenly and with- 
out preparation. They have been preceded by a 



INTRODUCTION. 13 

period, whioh we may call their Prelude^ during 
which the ideas aad &ets on which they turned 
were called into action ; — were gradually evolved 
into clearness and connexion, permanency and cer- 
tainty ; till at last the discovery which marks the 
epoch, seized and fixed for ever the truth which had 
till then been obscurely and doubtfully discerned. 
And again, when this step has been made by the 
principal discoverer, there may generally be ob- 
served another period, which we may call the Sequd 
of the epoch, during whieb the discovery has acquired 
a more perfect certainty wti a more complete de^ 
velopement among the leaders • of the advance ; has 
been diffiised to the wider throng of the secondary 
cultivators of such knowledge, and traced into its 
distant consequences. This is a work, always of 
time and labour, often of difficulty and conflict. To 
distribute the history of scieoice into such epochs, 
with their preludes and sequels, if successfully 
attempted, must needs make the series and con- 
nexion of its occurrences more distinct and intel- 
ligible. Such periods form resting-places, where we 
pause till the dust of the confixsed march is laid, and 
the prospect of the path is clear. 

Inductive Charts. — Since the advance of science 
consists in collecting by induction general laws from 
particular facts, and in combining several laws into 
one higher generalization, in which they still retain 
their former truth, we might form a Chart, or Table, 
of the progress of each science, by setting down the 



14 HISTORY OF INDUCnTE SCIENCES. 

particulars which thus flow together, so as to form 
general truths, and marking the junction of these 
general truths into others more comprehensive. 
The table of the progress of any science would thus 
resemble the map of a river, in which the waters 
from separate sources unite and make rivulets, which 
again meet with rivulets from other fountains, and 
thus go on forming by their junction trunks of a 
higher and higher order. The representation of the 
state of a science in this form, would necessarily 
exhibit all the principal doctrines of the science ; 
for each general truth contains the particular truths 
from which it was dmved, and may be followed 
backwards till we have these before us in their sepa- 
rate state. And the last and most advanced gene* 
ralization would have, in such a scheme, its proper 
place and the evidence of its validity. Hence such 
an Indtictwe TaUe of each science would afford a 
criterion of the correctness of our distribution of the 
inductive epochs, by its coincidence vjith the views 
of the best judges, as to the substantial contents of 
the science in question. By forming, therefore, such 
Inductive Tables of the principal sciences of which 
I have here to speak, and by regulating by these 
tables, my views of the history of the sciences, I 
conceive that I have secured the distribution of my 
history from material error ; for no merely arbitrary 
division of the events could Satisfy such conditions. 
But though I have constructed such charts to direct 
the course of the present history, I shall not insert 



INTRODUCTION. 16 

them iu the work, reserving them for the illustration 
of the philosophy of the sulyect ; for to this they 
more properly belong* being a part of the Logic ijf 

Staiionmy Periods. — ^By the lines of such maps 
tiie real advance of science is depicted, and nothing 
else. But there are several occurrences of other 
kinds, too interesting and too instructive to be alto- 
gether omitted. In order to understand the condi- 
tions of the progress of knowledge, we must attend, 
in some measure, to the Mlures as well as the sue* 
cesses by which such attempts have been attended^ 
When we reflect during how small a portion of the 
whole history of human speculations, science has 
really been, in any marked degree, progressive, we 
must needs feel some curiosity to know what was 
doing in these staMonary periods ; what field could 
be found which admitted of so wide a deviation, or 
at least so protracted a wandering. It is highly 
necessary to our purpose, to describe the baffled 
enterprises as well as the achievements of human 
i|)eeulation. 

i70c?^^^on.•*^During a great part of such stationary 
periods, we shall find that the process which we have 
spoken of as essential to the formation of real sdence, 
the conjunction of dear ideas with distinct facts, was 
interrupted ; and, in su<ih cases^r men dealt with ideas 
alone. They employed themselves in reasoning from 
principles^ and they arranged, and classified, and 
analysed their ideas, so as to make their reasonings 



16 HISTORY OF INDUCTIVE SCIENCES. 

r 

satisfy the requisitions of our rational &eulties. 
This process of drawing conclusions from our prin- 
ciples, by rigorous and unimpeachable trains of 
demonstration, is termed Deduction. In its due 
place, it is a highly important part of every science ; 
but it has no value when the fundamental principles, 
on which the whole of the d^nonstration rests, have 
not first been obtained by the induction of &cts, so 
as to supply the sole materials of substantial truth. 
Without such materials, a series of demonstrationd 
resembles physical science only as a shadow resem- 
bles a real object. To give a real significance to 
our propositions, Induction must provide what De- 
duction itself cannot supply. From a pictured hook 
we can only hang a pictured chain. 

Distinction of common Noiiom and Scientific Ideas. — 
When the notions with which men are conversant 
in the common course of practical life, which give 
meaning to their fismiiliar language, and employment 
to their hourly thoughts, are compared with the 
ideas on which exact science is founded, we find that 
the two classes of intellectual operations have much 
that is common and much that is different. With- 
out here attempting fully to explain this relation, 
(which, indeed, is one of the hardest problems of our 
philosophy,) we may observe that they have this in 
common, that both are acquired by acts of the mind 
exercised in connecting external impressions, and 
may be employed in conducting a train of reasoning ; 
or, speaking loosely, (for we cannot here pursue the 



INTRODUCTION. 17 

subject so as to arrive at philosophical exactness,) 
we may say, that all notions and ideas are obtained 
by an inductive, and may be used in a deductive 
process* But scientific ideas and common notions 
differ in this, tliat the former are precise and stable, 
the latter vague and ambiguoujs; the former are 
possessed with dear insight, and employed in a sense 
rigorously limited^ and always identically the same ; 
the latter have grown up in the mind from a thou- 
sand div^*se and obscure suggestions, and the ob- 
scurity and inconsistency of liieir origin hangs about 
all their applications. Scientific ideas can often be 
adequately exhiUted for all the purposes of reason- 
ing, by means of definitions and axioms; all 
attempts to reason by means of definitions from 
common notions, lead to empty forms or entire 
confitsioxi. 

Such common notions are sufiicient for the 
conunon practical conduct of human life ; but man 
is not a practical creature merely ; he has within 
him a speculcUive tendency, a pleasure in the con- 
templation of ideal relations, a love of knowledge as 
knowledge. It is this speculative tendency which 
brings to light the difference of common notions 
and scientific ideas, of which we have spoken. The 
mind analyses such notions, reasons upon them, 
combines, constructs, infers ; for it feels that intel- 
lectual things ought to be able to bear such handling. 
Even practical knowledge, we see clearly, is not 
possible without the reason; and the speculative 

VOL. I. c 



18 HISTORY OP INDUCTIVE SCIENCES. 

reason is only the reason satisfying itself of its own 
consistency. This specnlative faculty cannot be 
controlled from acting. The mind cannot but claim 
a right to speculate concerning all its own acts and 
creations ; yet, when it exercises this right upon its 
common practical notions, we find that it runs into 
bairen abstractions and ever-recurring cycles of 
subtlety. Such notions are like waters naturally 
stagnant, and howeyer much we urge and agitate 
them, they only revolve in stationary whirlpools. 
But the mind is capable of acquiring scientific ideas, 
which are fitted to undergo this discussion and im* 
pulsion. When our speculations are duly fed from 
the spring-heads of observation, and often drawn ofi* 
to the region of applied science, we may have a 
living stream of consistent and progressive know- 
ledge. That science may be both real as to its 
import, and logical as to its form, the examples of 
many existing sciences sufficiently prove. 

School PAifo5()pA^.~- While, however, attempts are 
made to form sciences, without such a verification 
and realization of their Amdamental ideas, there is, 
in the natural series of speculation, no self-correcting 
principle. A philosophy constructed on notions 
obscure, vague, and unsubstantial, and not arrested 
in its career by the want. of correspondence between 
its doctrines and the actual train of physical events, 
may long subsist, and occupy men's minds. Such a 
philosophy must depend for its permanence upon 
the pleasure which men feel in tracing the operations 



INTRODUCTION. 19 

of their own and other men's minds, and in reducing 
them to logical consistency and systematical ar- 
rangement. 

In these cases the subjects of attention are not 
external objects, but speculations previously deliver- 
ed ; the object is not to interpret nature, but man's 
mind. The opinions of the masters are the facts 
which the disciples endeavour to reduce to unity, or 
to follow into consequences. A series of speculators 
who pursue such a course, may properly be termed 
a School^ and their philosophy a School PhUosophy ; 
whether their agreement in such a mode of seeking 
knowledge arise from personal communication and 
tradition, or be merely the result of a community of 
intellectual character and propensity. The two 
great periods of school philosophy (it will be recol- 
lected that we are here directing our attention mainly 
to physical science), were that of the Greeks and 
that of the middle ages, — ^the period of the first 
waking of science, and that of its mid-day slumber. 

What has been said thus briefly and imperfectly, 
would require great detail and much explanation, to 
give it its fiill significance and authority. But it 
was proper to state so much in this place, in order 
to render more intelligible and more instructive at 
the first aspect, the view of the attempted or effected 
progress of science. It is, perhaps, a disadvantage 
inevitably attending an undertaking like the present, 
that it must set out with statements so metaphy- 
sical, and, it may be, repulsive ; and must give them 

c 2 



20 HISTORY OF INDUCTIVE SCIENCES. 

without adequate developement and proof. Such 
an introduction may be compared to the geographical 
sketch of a country, with which the historian of its 
fortunes often begins his narration. So much of 
metaphysics is as necessary to us as such a portion 
of geography is to the historian of an empire ; and 
what has hitherto been said, is intended as a slight 
outline of the geography of that intellectual world, 
of which we have here to study the history. 
To that history we now proceed. 



BOOK I. 



HISTORY 



OF THE 



GREEK SCHOOL PHILOSOPHY, 



WITH RBFBRBNCB TO 



PHYSICAL SCIENCE. 



Tk yctp apxO' Bi^aro vaim\la<;; 
Tk Bk /clvSvvo<; Kparepol*; aSafiav- 

T0<: Srjaev a\o49; 
'BttcI S^ifi^oXov 

Kpcfiacrav ayxvpa^ virepOev 
Xpvaiav ')(elp€<Tat \afia)v <l>uiKav 
^Ap'xp^ €V TTpvfiva irarip ^OvpaviZav 
^Eyx^ecxipavvov Zrjvay kol m/cvTrSpov^ 
Kvfidrciyv phra^;^ avefitov r iKoKetj 
NvKTa<i re, koL irovrov KeKevOov^j 
^^Afiard T ev^povoy koX 
fiXlav vioToio fiolpav. 



PiKDAR. Ppi/L iv. 124, a49. 



Whence came their voyage ? them what peril held 
With adamantine rivets firmly bound ? 

But soon as on the vessel's bow 

The anchor was hung up. 
Then took the Leaders on the prow 

In hands a golden cup, 
And on great &ther Jove did call. 
And on the winds and waters all, 

Swept by the hurrying blast ; 
And on the nights, and ocean ways, 
And on the fiur auspicious days. 

And loved return at last 



BOOK I. 



mSTOBY OF THE GBEEK SCHOOL PHILOSOPHY, WITH 
REFERENCE TO PHYSICAL SCIENCE. 



CHAPTER I. 

Prelude to the GitEEK School Philosophy. 



SecL 1. — First Attempts of the Speculative Faculhf in 

Physical Inquiries. 

At an early period of history there appeared in men 
a propensity to speculative inquiries concerning the 
various parts and properties of the material world. 
What they saw excited them to meditate, to con- 
jecture, and to reason : they endeavoured to account 
for natural events, to trace their causes, to reduce 
them to their principles. This habit of mind, or, 
at least that modification of it which we have here 
to consider, seems to have been first unfolded 
among the Greeks. And during that obscure intro- 
ductory interval which elapsed while the speculative 
tendencies of men were as yet hardly disentangled 
from the practical, those who were most eminent in 
such inquiries were distinguished by the same term 
of praise which is applied to sagacity in matters of 
action, and were called loise men — iro<f>o\. But 



24 THE GREEK SCHOOL PHILOSOPHY. 

when it came to be clearly felt by such persons that 
their endeavours were suggested by the love of 
knowledge, a motive different from those which lead 
to the wisdom of active life, a name was adopted of 
a more appropriate, as well as of a more modest 
signification, and they were termed philosophers^ or 
lovers of wisdom. This appellation is said* to have 
been first assumed by Pythagoras. Yet he, in 
Herodotus, instead of having this title, is called a 

powerfill sophist — ^EXKrjvcuv oi rm aadeveardrcp ao<f>LaTy 

Ilvdayopr)*; the historian using this word, as it would 
seem, without intending to imply that misuse of 
reason which the term afterwards came to denote. 
The historians of literature place Pythagoras at the 
origin of the Italic school, one of the two main lines 
of succession of the early Greek philosophers : but 
the other, the Ionic school, which more peculiarly 
demands our attention, in consequence of its cha- 
racter and subsequent progress, is deduced from 
Thales, who preceded the age of philosophy, and 
was one of the sophi^ or " wise men of Greece." 

The Ionic school was succeeded in Greece by 
several others ; and the subjects which occupied the 
attention of these schools became very extensive. 
In fact, the first attempts were, to form systems 
which should explain the laws and causes of the 
material universe ; and to these were soon added all 
the great questions which our moral condition and 

' Cic. Tusc. T. 3. » Herod, iy. 95. 



PRELUDE. 25 

&culties suggest. The physical philosophy of these 
schools is especially deserving of our study, as 
exhibiting the character and fortunes of the most 
memorable attempt at universal knowledge which 
has ever been made. It is highly instructive to 
trace the principles of this undertaking; for the 
course pursued was certainly one of the most 
natural and tempting which can be imagined ; the 
essay was made by a nation unequalled in fine 
mental endowments, at the period of its greatest 
activity and vigour ; and yet it must be allowed, 
(for, at least so far as physical science is concerned, 
none will contest this,) to have been entirely unsuc- 
cessful. We cannot consider otherwise than as an 
utter failure, an endeavour to discover the causes of 
things, of which the most complete results are the 
Aristotelian physical treatises; and which, after 
reaching the point which these treatises mark, left 
the human mind to remain stationary, at any fBie on 
all such subjects, for nearly two thousand years. 

The early philosophers of Greece entered upon 
the work of physical speculation in a manner which 
showed the vigour and confidence of the question- 
ing spirit, as yet untamed by labours and reverses. 
It was for later ages to learn that the man must 
acquire, slowly and patiently, letter by letter, the 
alphabet in which nature writes her answers to such 
inquiries ; the first students wished to divine, at a 
single glance, the whole import of her book. They 
endeavoured to discover the origin and principle of 



26 THE GREEK SCHOOL PHILOSOPHY. 

the universe; according to Thales, waJUr was the 
origin of all things, according to Anajdmenes, airi 
and Heraclitus considered ^re as the essential prin* 
ciple of the universe. It has been conjectured, 
with ^reat plausibility, that this tendency to rive to 
their ^Iphy the form of . co^nogony. w« 
owing to the influence of the poetical cosmogonies 
and theogonies which had been produced and ad- 
mired at a still earlier age. Indeed, such wide and 
ambitious doctrines as those which have been men- 
tioned, were better suited to the dim magnificence 
of poetry, than to the purpose of a philosophy which 
was to bear the sharp scrutiny of reason. When 
we speak of the principles of things, the term, even 
now, is very ambiguous and indefinite in its import, 
but how much more was that the case in the first 
attempts to use such abstractions ! The term which 
is commonly used in this sense (^p%^), signified at 
first Me beginning; and in its early philosophical 
applications implied some obscure mixed reference 
to the mechanical, chemical, organic, and historical 
causes of the visible state of things, besides the 
theolc^cal views which at this period were only just 
beginning to be separated fix>m the physical. Hence 
we are not to be surprised if the sources from which 
the opinions of this period appear to be derived are 
rather vague suggestions and casual analogies, than 
any reasons which will bear examination. Aristotle 
conjectures, with considerable probability, that the 
doctrine of Thales, according to which water was 



PRELUDE. 27 

the universal element, resulted from the manifest 
importance of moisture in the support of animal 
and vegetable Iif6^ But such precarious analyses 
of these obscure and loose dogmas of early antiquity 
are of small consequence to our object. 

In more limited and more definite examples of 
curiosity concerning the causes of natural appear- 
ances, and in the attempts made to satisfy these, we 
appear to discern a more genuine prelude to the 
true spirit of physical inquiry. One of the most 
remarkable instances of this kind is to be foimd in 
the speculations which Herodotus records, relative 
to the cause of the floods of the Nile. " Concern- 
ing the nature of this river," says the fieither of his- 
tory*, " I was not able to learn anything, either from 
the priests or from any one besides, though I ques- 
tioned them very pressingly. For the Nile is 
flooded for a hundred days, beginning with the 
summer solstice ; and after this time it diminishes, 
and is, during the whole winter, very small. And 
on this head I was not able to obtain anything satis- 
factory from any one of the Egyptians, when I asked 
what is the power by which the Nile is in its nature 
the reverse of other rivers." 

We may see, I think, in the historian's account, 
that the Grecian mind felt a craving to discover the 
reasons of things which other nations did not feel. 
The Egyptians, it appears, had no theory^ and felt 

^ Metaph. i. 3. * Herod, ii. 19. 



28 THE GREEK SCHOOL PHILOSOPHY. 

the want of none. Not so the Greeks ; they had 
their reasons to render, though they were not such 
as satisfied Herodotus. " Some of the Greeks," he 
says, " who wish to be considered great philosophers, 

have propounded three ways of accounting for these 
floods. Two of them," he adds, " I do not think 
worthy of record, except just so far as to mention 
them." But as these are some of the earliest Greek 
essays in physical philosophy, it will be worth while, 
even at this day, to preserve the brief notice he has 
given of them, and his own reasonings upon the 
same subject. 

" One of these opinions holds that the Etesian 
winds [which blew from the north] are the cause of 
these floods, by preventing the Nile from flowing 
into the sea." Against this the historian reasons 
very simply and sensibly. " Very often when the 
Etesian winds do riot blow, the Nile is flooded 
nevertheless. And moreover, if the Etesian vrinds 
were the cause, all other rivers, which have their 
course opposite to these winds, ought to undergo 
the same changes as the Nile ; which the rivers of 
Syria and Libya so circumstanced do not." 

"The next opinion is still more unscientific, 
{dv€7ncrTrffjLov€<TTiprj) and is, in truth, marvellous for 
its folly. This holds that the ocean flows all round 
the earth, and that the Nile comes out of the ocean, 
and by that means produces its effects." " Now," 
says the historian, " the man who talks about this 



PRELUDE. 29 

ocean-river, goes into the region of fable, where it 
is not easy to demonstrate that he is wrong. I know 
of no such river. But I suppose that Homer or 
some of the earlier poets invented this fiction and 
introduced it into their poetry." 

He then proceeds to a third account, which to a 
modem reasoner would appear not at all unphilo- 
sophical in itself, but which he, nevertheless, rejects 
in a manner no less decided than the others. ^* The 
third opinion, though much the most plausible, is 
still more wrong than the others ; for it asserts an 
impossibility, namely, that the Nile proceeds from 
the melting of the snow. Now the Nile flows out 
of Libya, and through Ethiopia, which are very hot 
countries, and thus comes into Egypt, which is a 
colder region. How then can it proceed fit)m 
snow ?'' He then offers several other reasons " to 
show," as he says, *^ to any one capable of reasoning 

on such subjects {avBpl ye Xoyl^eaOai roiovray iripi 

ot<p T€ lorrt), that the assertion cannot be true. The 
winds which blow from the southern regions are 
hot; the inhabitants are black; the swallows and 
kites (UtIvoi) stay in the country the whole year ; 
the cranes fly the colds of Scythia, and seek their 
warm winter-quarters there; which would not be 
if it snowed ever so little." He adds another reason, 
founded apparently upon some limited empirical 
maxim of weather-wisdom taken from the climate 
of Greece. " Libya," he says, " has neither rain nor 
ice, and therefore no snow ; fovy in five days after* a 



30 THE GREEK SCHOOL PHILOSOPHY. 

£all of snow there must be a &11 of ram ; so that if 
it snowed in those regions it must rain too." I need 
not observe that Herodotus was not aware of the 
difference between the climate of high mountains 
and plains in a torrid region ; but it is impossible 
not to be struck both with the activity and the co- 
herency of thought displayed by the Greek mind in 
this primitive physical inquiry. 

But I must not omit the hypothesis which Hero- 
dotus himself proposes, after rejecting those which 
have been already given. It does not appear to me 
easy to catch his exact meaning, but the statement 
will still be curious. " If," he says, ** one who has 
condemned opuuon, ,r^^j U^gaM ™, 
put forwards his own opinion concerning so obscure 
a matter, I will state why it seems to me that the 
Nile is flooded in summer." This opinion he pro- 
pounds at first with an oracular brevity, which it is 
difficult to suppose that he did not intend to be 
impressive. " In winter the sun is carried by the 
seasons away from his former course, and goes to 
the upper parts of Libya. And thercy in short, is 
the whole account; for that region to which this 
divinity (the sun) is nearest, must naturally be most 
scant of water, and the river-sources of that country 
must be dried up." 

But the lively and garrulous Ionian immediately 
relaxes from this apparent reserve. " To explain 
the matter more at length," he proceeds, " it is thus. 
The sun, when he traverses the upper parts of Libya, 



PBELUDE. 31 

does what he commonly does in summer ; — he draws 
the water to him (^x^ret iif" k^vrov to 0&dp) and 
having thus drawn it, he pushes it to the upper 
regions (of the air probably,) and then the winds 
take it and disperse it till they melt in moisture. 
And thus the winds which blow from those coun- 
tries, Libs and Notus, are the most moist of all 
winds. Now when the winter relaxes and the sun 
returns to the north, he still draws water from all 
the rivers, but they are increased by showers and 
rain-torrents, so that they are in flood till the 
summer comes ; and then, the rain foiling and the 
sun still drawing them, they become small. But 
the Nile, not being fed by rains, but being dravm 
by the sun, is, alone of all rivers, much more scanty 
in the vrinter than in the summer. For in summer 
it is drawn like all other rivers, but in winter it 
alone has its supplies shut up. And in this way, I 
have been led to think the sun is the cause of the 
occurrence in question." We may remark that the 
historian here appears to ascribe the inequality of 
the Nile at different seasons to the influence of the 
sun upon its springs alone, the other cause of change, 
the rains, being here excluded : and that, on this 
supposition, the same relative effects would be pro- 
duced whether the sun increase the sources in winter 
by melting the snows, or diminish them in summer 
by what he calls dramng them upwards. 

This specimen of the early efforts of the Greeks 
in physical speculations, appears to me to speak 



32 THE GREEK SCHOOL PHILOSOPHY. 

strongly for the opinion that their philosophy on 
such subjects was the native growth of the Greek 
mind, and owed nothing to the supposed lore of 
Egypt and the East ; an opinion which has been 
adopted with regard to the Greek philosophy in 
general by the most competent judges on a full 
survey of the evidence*. Indeed, we have no evi- 
dence whatever that, at any period, the African or 
Asiatic nations, (with the exception perhaps of the 
Indians,) ever felt this importunate curiosity with 
regard to the definite application of the idea of 
cause and effect to visible phenomena ; or drew so 
strong a line between a fabulous legend and a reason 
rendered ; or attempted to ascend to a natural cause 
by classing together phenomena of the same kind. 
We may be well excused, therefore, for believing 
that they could not impart to the Greeks what they 
themselves did not possess ; and so far as our survey 
goes, physical philosophy has its origin, apparently 
spontaneous and independent, in the active and 
acute intellect of Greece. 

Sect. 2. — Primitive Mistake in Ghreek Physical 

Philosophy. 

We now proceed to examine with what success the 
Greeks followed the track into which they had thus 
struck. And here we • are obliged to confess that 

* Thirl wall, Hist, Gr.^ ii. 130 ; and, as there quoted, Ritter, 
Geschichte der Pkilosophie, i. 159 — 173. 



PRELUDE. 33 

they very soon turned aside from the right road to 
truth, and deviated into a vast field of error, in 
which they and their successors have wandered al- 
most up to the present time. It is not necessary 
here to decide why those feculties which appear to 
be bestowed upon us for the discovery of truth, were 
permitted by Providence to fidl so signally in 
answering that purpose; whether, like the powers 
by which we seek our happiness, they involve a 
responsibility on our part, and may be defeated by 
rejecting the guidance of a higher faculty; or 
whether these endowments, though they did not 
immediately lead man to profound physical know- 
ledge, answered some nobler and better purpose in 
his constitution and government. The fact un- 
doubtedly was, that the physical philosophy of the 
Greeks soon became trifling and worthless ; and it 
is proper to point out, as precisely as we can, in 
what the fundamental mistake consisted. 

To explain this, we may in the first place return 
for a moment to Herodotus's account of the cause 
of the floods of the Nile. 

The reader will probably have observed a remark- 
able phrase used by Herodotus, in his own explana- 
tion of these inundations. He says that the sun 
draws, or attracts, the water ; a metaphorical term, 
obviously intended to denote some more general 
and abstract conception than that of the visible 
operation which the word primarily signifies. This 
abstract notion of ' drawing' is, in the historian, as 

VOL. I. , D 



34 THE GREEK SCHOOL PHILOSOPHY. 

we see, very vague and loose ; it might, witli equal 
propriety, be explained to mean what we now un- 
derstand by mechanical or by chemical attraction, 
pressure, or evaporation. And in like manner, all 
the first attempts to comprehend the operations of 
nature, led to the introduction of abstract concep- 
tions, often vague indeed, but not, therefore, un- 
meaning; such as motion and velocity, force and 
pressure, impetus and momentum (po'^'v)* And the 
next step, in philosophizing, necessarily was to en- 
deavour to make these vague abstractions more clear 
and fixed, so that the logical faculty should be able 
to employ them securely and coherently. But there 
were two ways of making this attempt ; the one, by 
examining the words only, and the thoughts which 
they call up ; the other, by attending to the fects 
and things which bring these abstract terms into 
use. The latter, the method of real inquiry, was 
the way to success; but the Greeks followed the 
former, the verbal or notional course, and failed. 

If Herodotus, when the notion of the sun's at- 
tracting the waters of rivers had entered into his 
mind, had gone on to instruct himself, by attention 
to facts, in what manner this notion could be made 
more definite, while it still remained applicable to 
all the knowledge which could be obtained, he would 
have made some progress towards a true solution of 
his problem. If, for instance, he had tried to ascer- 
tain whether this attraction which the sun exerted 
upon the waters of rivers, depended on his influence 



PRELUDE. 35 

at their fountains only, or was exerted over their 
whole course, and over waters which were not parts 
of rivers, he would have been led to reject his 
hypothesis, for he would have found, by observations 
sufficiently obvious, that the sun's Attraction, as 
shown in such cases, is a tendency to lessen all ex- 
panded and open collections of moisture, whether 
flowing firom a spring or not ; and it would then be 
seen that this influence, operating on the whcrfe 
surfiaice of the Nile, must diminish it lus well Hi 
other rivers, in Summer, and therefore could not 
be the cause of its overflow. He would thus have 
corrected his first loose conjecture by a real study 
of nature, and might, in the course of his medita- 
tions, have been led to available notions of Evapora- 
tion, or other natursd actions. And, in like manner, 
in other cases, the i^ude attempts at explanation, 
which the first exercise of the speculative faculty 
produced, might have been gradually concentrated 
and refined, so as to fall in, both with the requisi- 
tions of the reason and the testimony of sense. 

But this was not the direction which the Greek 
speculators took. On the contrary ; as soon as they 
had introduced into their philosophy any abstract 
and general conceptions, they proceeded to scrutinize 
these by the internal light of the mind alone, with- 
out any longer looking abroad into the world of 
sense* They took for granted that philosophy must 
result from the relations of those notions which are 
involved in the common use of language, and they 

D 2 



36 THE GREEK SCHOOL PHILOSOPHY. 

proceeded to seek it by studying such notions. 
They ought to have reformed and fixed their usual 
conceptions by observation ; they only analysed and 
expanded them by reflection: they ought to have 
sought by trial, among the notions which passed 
through their minds, some one which admitted of 
exact application to facts ; they selected arbitrarily, 
and, consequently, erroneously, the notions according 
to which facts should be assembled and arranged : 
they ought to have collected clear fundamental ideas 
from the world of things by inductive acts of thought ; 
they only derived results by dedtwtion from one or 
other of their familiar conceptions. 

When this Mse direction had been extensively 
adopted by the Greek philosophers, we may treat of 
it as the method of their Schools. Under that title 
we must give a further account of it. 



37 



CHAPTER II. 

The Greek School Philosophy. 



Sect. 1. — ITie general Foundation of iJie Greek School 

Philosophy/. 

The physical philosophy of the Greek Schools was 
formed by looking at the material world through 
the medium of that common language which men 
employ to answer the common occasions of life; 
and by adopting, arbitrarily, as the grounds of com- 
parison of facts, and of inference from them, notions 
more abstract and large than those with which men 
are practically familiar, but not less vague and 
obscure. Such a philosophy, however much it 
might be systematized by classifying and analysing 
the conceptions which it involves, could not over- 
come the vices of its fundamental principle. But 
before speaking of these defects, we must give some 
indications of its character. 

The propensity to seek for principles in the com- 
mon us^'ges of language may be discerned at a very 
early period. Thus we have an example of it in a 
saying which is reported of Thales, the founder of 
Greek philosophy'. When he was asked " What is 
the greatest thing?" he replied, " Place; for all other 

* Plut. Conv» Sept, Sap, Diog. Laert. i. 35. 



38 THE GREEK SCHOOL PHILOSOPHY. 

m 

things are in the world, but the world is in it." In 
Aristotle we have the consummation of this mode 
of speculation. The usual point from which he 
starts in his inquiries is, that we say thus or thus in 
common language. Thus, when he has to discuss 
the question, whether there be, in any part of the 
universe, a void, or space in which there is nothing, 
he inquires first in how many senses we say that 
one thing is in another. He enumerates many of 
theses we say the part is in the whole, as the finger 
is in the hand ; again we say, the species is in the 
genus, as man is included in animal; again, the 
government of Greece is in the king; and various 
other senses are described or exemplified, but of all 
these the Tnmt proper is when we say a thing is m a 
vessel, and generally in place. He next examines 
what place is, and comes to this conclusion, that 
" if about a body there be another body including 
it, it is in place, and if not, not." A body moves 
when it changes its place; but he adds, that if 
water be in a vessel, the vessel being at rest, the 
parts of the water may still move, for they are in- 
cluded by each other ; so that while the whole does 
not change its place, the parts may change tiieir 
places in a circular order. Proceeding then to the 
question of a fxridj he, as usual, examines the dif* 
ferent senses in which the term is used, and adopts, 
as the most proper, piace without matter; with no 
useful result, as we shall soon see. 

■ Physic. Ausc. iy. 3. 



JTS FOUNDATION. 39 

AgainS in a question concerning mechanical 
action, he says, '^ When a man moves a stone by 
pushing it with a stick, we say both that the man 
moves the stone, and that the stick moves the stone, 
but the latter more properly.'^ 

Again, we find the Greek philosophers applying 
themselves to extract their dogmas from the most 
general and abstract notions which they could detect ; 
for example,— from the conception of the Universe 
as One or as Many things. They tried to determine 
how far we may, or must, combine with these con- 
ceptions that of a whole, of parts, of number, of 
limits, of place, of beginning or end, of fall or void, 
of rest or motion, of cause and effect, and the like. 
The analysis of such conceptions with such a view, 
occupies, for instance, almost the whole of Aristotle's 
Treatise on the Heavens, ]^ 

The Dialogue of Plato, which is entitled Par^ 
menidesy appears at first as if its object were to show 
the futility of this method of philosophizing; for 
the philosopher whose name it bears, ifif^represented 
as arguing with Aristotle, and, by a process of 
metaphysical analysis, reducing him at least to this 
conclusion, ^^ that whether One exist, or do not 
exist, it follows that both it and other things, with 
reference to themselves and to each other, all and in 
all respects, both are and are not, both appear and 
appear not." Yet the method of Plato, so &r as 
concerns truth of that kind with which we are here 

* Physic. Ausc. viii. 5. 



40 THE GREEK SCHOOL PHILOSOPHY. 

concerned, was little more efficacious than that of 
his rival. It consists mainly, as may be seen in 
several of the dialogues, and especially in the 
Timaeus, in the application of notions as loose as 
those of the Peripatetics ; for example, the concep- 
tions of the Good, the Beautiful, the Perfect ; and 
these are rendered still more arbitrary by assuming 
an acquaintance with the views of the Creator of 
the imiverse. The philosopher is thus led to maxims 
which agree with those of the Aristotelians, that 
there can be no void, that things seek their own 
place, and the like*. 

Another mode of reasoning, very widely applied 
in these attempts, was the doctrine of contrarieties, 
in which it was assumed, that adjectives or sub- 
stantives which are in common language, or in some 
abstract mode of conception, opposed to each other, 
must point at some fundamental antithesis in nature, 
which it is important to study. Thus Aristotle* 
says, that the Pythagoreans, from the contrasts 
which number suggests, coUected ten principles,- 
I^imited and Unlimited, Odd and Even, One and 
Many, Right and Left, Male and Female, Rest and 
Motion, Straight and Curved, Light and Darkness, 
Good and Evil, Square and Oblong. We shall see 
hereafter, that Aristotle himself deduced the doc- 
trine of four elements, and other dogmas, by oppo- 
sitions of the same kind. 

* Timaeus, p. 80. * Metaph. 1. 5. 



ARISTOTELIAN PHYSICS. 41 

The physical speculator of the present day will 
learn without surprise, that such a mode of discus- 
sion as this, led to no truths of real or permanent 
value. The whole mass of the Greek philosophy, 
therefore, shrinks into an almost imperceptible com- 
pass, when viewed with reference to the progress of 
physical knowledge. Still the general character of 
this system, and its fortunes from the time of its 
founders to the overthrow of their authority, are not 
without their instruction, and, it may be hoped, not 
without their interest. I proceed, therefore, to 
give some account of these doctrines in their most 
fully developed and permanently received form, that 
in which they were presented by Aristotle. 

Sect: 2. — The Aristotelian Physical Phihsophy. 

The principal physical treatises of Aristotle are, 
the eight Books of " Physical Lectures," the four 
Books "Of the Heavens," the two Books "Of 
Production and Destruction :" for the Book " Of the 
World" is now universally acknowledged to be 
spurious ; and the " Meteorologies," though fall of 
physical explanations of natural phenomena, does 
not exhibit the doctrines and reasonings of the 
school in so general a form ; the same may be said 
of the " Mechanical Problems." The treatises on 
the various subjects of Natural History, " On Ani- 
mals," " On the Parts of Animals," " On Plants," 
« On Physiognomonics," " On Colours," "On Sound," 



42 THE GREEK SCHOOL PHILOSOPHY. 

contain an extraordinarj accumulation of facts, and 
manifest a wonderful power of systematising ; but 
are not works which expound principles, and there- 
fore do not require to be here considered. 

The Physical Lectures are the work concerning 
which a well-known anecdote is related by Sim- 
pliciuSy a Greek commentator of the sixth century, 
as well as by Plutarch. It is said, that Alexander 
the Great wrote to his former tutor to this effect ; 
**You have not done well in pubUshing these 
lectures ; for how shall we, your pupils, excel other 
men, if you make that public to all, which we learnt 
from you.*' To this Aristotle is said to have replied ; 
'* My lectures are published and not published ; they 
will be intelligible to those who heard them, and to 
none beside." This may very easily be a story in- 
scribed and circulated among those who found the 
work beyond their comprehension ; and it cannot be 
denied, that to make out the meaning and reasoning 
of every part, would be a task very laborious and 
difficult, if not impossible. But we may follow ^he 
import of a laige portion of the work vnth sufficient 
clearness to apprehend the diaracter and principles 
of the reasoning; and this is what I shall endeavour 
to da 

The auihor^s introductory statement of his view 
of the nature of philosophy fidls in very closely with 
what has been said, that he takes his hcts and 
generalisations as they are implied in the structure 
of language. ** We must in aU cases proceed," he 



ARISTOTELIilN PHYSICB. 43 

3ays, " from what is known to what is unknown." 
This will not be denied ; bnt we can hardly follow 
him in his inference. He adds, *^ we must proceed, 
therefore, from universal to particular. And some- 
thing of this," he pursues, ^^ may be seen in lan- 
guage ; for names signify things in a general and 
indefinite manner, as cirde^ and by defining we un- 
fold them into particulars." He illustrates this by 
saying, ^^ thus children at first call all men father^ 
and all women mother^ but afterwards distinguish." 

In accordance with this view, he endeavours to 
settle several of the great questions concerning the 
universe, which had been started among subtle and 
speculative men, by unfolding the meaning of the 
words and phrases which are applied to the most 
general notions of things and relations. We have 
already noticed this method. A few examples will 
illustrate it farther: — ^Whether there was or was 
not a void, or place without matter, had already been 
debated among rival sects of philosophers. The 
antagonist arguments were briefly these: — ^There 
must be a void, because a body cannot move into a 
space except it is empty, and therefore without a 
void there could be no motion : — and, on the other 
hand, there is no void, for the intervals between 
bodies s^e filled with air, and air is something* 
These opinions had even been supported by reference 
to expCTiment. On the one hand, Anaxagoras and 
his school had shown, that air when confined, re- 
sisted compression, by squeezing a blown bladder. 



44 THE GREEK SCHOOL PHILOSOPHy. 

tad pressing down an inverted vessel in the water ; 
on the other hand, it was alleged that a vessel full 
of fine ashes held as much water as if the ashes 
were not there, which could only be explained by 
supposing void spaces among the ashes. Aristotle 
decides that there is no void, on such arguments as 
this* : — ^In a void there could be no difference of up 
and down ; for as in nothing there are no differences, 
so there are none in a privation or negation ; but a 
void is merely a privation or negation of matter ; 
therefore, in a void, bodies could not move up and 
down, which it is in their nature to do. It is easily 
seen that such a mode of reasoning elevates the 
familiar forms of language and the intellectual con-*' 
nexions of terms, to a supremacy over facts ; making 
truth depend upon whether terms are or are not 
privative, and whether we say that bodies fall 
naturally. In such a philosophy every new result 
of observation would be compelled to conform to 
the usual combinations of phrases, as they had been 
associated by the modes of apprehension previously 
familiar. 

It is not intended here to intimate that the com- 
mon modes of apprehension, which are the basis of 
common lansfuasfe, are limited and casual. They 

conditions of our perceptions and conceptions : thus 
all things axe necessarily apprehended as existing 

• Physic. Ausc. iv. 7* p« 215. 



ARISTOTELIAN PHYSICS. 45 

in time and space, and as connected by relations of 
cause and effect ; and so far as the Aristotelian phi*- 
losophj reasons from these assumptions, it has a 
real foundation, though even in this case the con- 
clusions are often insecure. We have an example 
of this reasoning in the eighth book^ where he 
proves that there never was a time in which change 
and motion did not exist ; " For if all things were 
?it rest, the first motion must have been produced 
by some change in some of these things ; that is, 
there must have been a change before the first 
change;" and again, "How can before and after 
apply when time is not ? or how can time be when 
motion is not ? If," he adds, " time is a numeration 
of motion, and if time be eternal, motion must be 
etemaL" But we have sometimes principles intro- 
duced of a more arbitrary character; and besides the 
general relations of thought^ the inventions of pre- 
vious speculators are taken for granted ; such, for 
instance, as the then commonly received opinions con- 
cerning the frame of the world. From the assertion 
that motion is eternal, proved in the manner just 
stated, Aristotle proceeds by a curious train of rea- 
soning, to identify this eternal motion with the 
diurnal motion of the heavens. " There must," he 
says, "be something which is the first moved":" 
this follows from the relation of causes and effectsc 
Again, "motion must go on constantly, and, there- 

^ Physic. Ausc. viii. 1. p. 251. 
* Physic. Ausc. viii. 6. p. 258. 



46 THE GREEK SCHOOL PHILOSOPHY. 

fore, must be either continuous or successive. Now 
what is continuous is more properly said to take place 
constandyy than what is successive. Also the con- 
tinuous is better ; but we always suppose that which 
is better to take place in nature, if it be "possible. 
The motion of the first mover will, therefore, be con- 
tinuous, if such an eternal motion be possible." We 
here see the vague judgment of better and worse 
introduced, as that of natural and unnatural ^as 
before, into physical reasonings. 

I proceed with Aristotle's argument*. " We have 
now, therefore, to show that there may be an infinite, 
single, continuous motion, and that this is circular." 
This is, in feet, proved, as may readily be conceived, 
from the consideration that a body may go on per- 
petually revolving uniformly in a circle. And thus 
we have a demonstration, on the principles of this 
philosophy, that thare is and must be a first mover, 
revolving etemally with a uniform circular motion. 

Though this kind of philosophy may appear too 
trifling to deserve being dwelt upon, it is important 
for our purpose so far to exemplify it, that we may 
afberwards advance, confid^it that we have done it 
no ii^ustice. 

I will now pass from the doctrines relating to the 
motions of the heavens, to those whi<^ concern the 
material elements of the universe. And here it 
mxy be remarked that the tendency (of which we 

• viii. a 



ARISTOTELIAN PHYSICS. 47 

are here tracing the devdopement) to extract specu- 
lative opinions from the relations of words, must be 
very natural to man ; for the very widely accepted 
doctrine of the four elements which appears to be 
founded on the opposition of the mectives hat and 
eddy wet and d/rjf^ is much older than Aristotle, and 
was probably one of the earliest of philosophical 
dogmas. The great master of this philosophy, how- 
ever, puts the opinion in a more systematic manner 
than his predecessors. 

" We seek," he says^*, " the principles of sensible 
things, that is, of tangible bodies. We must take, 
therefore, not all the contrarieties of quality, but 
those only which have reference to the touch. Thus 
black and white, sweet and bitter, do not differ as 
tangible qualities, tod therefore must be rejected 
from our consideration. 

" Now the contrarieties of quality which refer to 
the touch are these: hot, cold; dry, wet; heavy, 
light ; hard, soft ; unctuous, meagre ; rough, smooth ; 
dense, rare." He then proceeds to reject all but the 
four first of these, for various reasons; heavy and 
light, because they are not active and passive quali- 
ties ; the others, because they are combinations of 
the four first, which therefore he infers to be the 
four elementary qualities. 

" **Now in four things there are six combinations 
of two ; but the combinations of two opposites, as 



10 



De Gen. et Corrupt ii. 2. " iii. 3. 



48 THE GREEK SCItOOL PHILOSOPHY. 

hot and cold, must be rejected ; we have, therefore, 
four elementary combinations, which agree with the 
four apparently elementary bodies. Fire is hot and 
dry ; air is hot and wet (for steam is air) ; water is 
cold and wet, earth is cold and dry." 

It may be remarked that this disposition to assume 
that some common elementary quality must exist in 
the cases in which we habitually apply a common 
adjective, as it began before the reign of the Aris- 
totelian philosophy, so also survived its influence. 
Not to mention other cases, it would be difficult to 
free Bacon's Inquisitio in naturam calidi^ " Exami- 
nation of the nature of heat," from the charge of 
confounding together very different classes of phe- 
nomena under the cover of the word hot. 

The rectification of these opinions concerning the 
elementary composition of bodies belongs to an ad- 
vanced period in the history of physical knowledge, 
even after the revival of its progress. But there are 
some of the Aristotelian doctrines which particularly 
deserve our attention, from the prominent share they 
had in the very first beginnings of that revival, I 
mean the doctrines concerning motion. 

These are still founded upon the same mode of 
reasoning from adjectives ; but in this case, the result 
follows, not only from the opposition of the words, 
but also from the distinction of their being absolutely 
or relaiivehf true. " Former writers," says Aristotle, 
" have considered heavy and light relatively only, 
taking cases, where both things have weight, but one 



ARISTOTELIAN PHYSICS. 49 

is lighter than the other ; and they imagined that, 
in this way, they defined what was absolutely (ttTrXw?) 
heavy and light." We now know that things which 
rise by their lightness do so only because they are 
pressed upwards by heavier surrounding bodies; 
and this assumption of absolute levity, which is evi- 
dently gratuitous, or rather merely nominal, entirely 
vitiated the whole of the succeeding reasoning. 
The inference was, that fire must be absolutely light, 
since it tends to take its place above the other three 
elements ; earth absolutely heavy, since it tends to 
take its place below fire, air, and water. The phi- 
losopher argued also, with great acuteness, that air, 
which tends to take its place below fire and above 
water, must do so by its nature^ and not in virtue of 
any combination of heavy and light elements. " For 
if air were composed of the parts which give fire its 
levity, joined with other parts which produce gravity, 
we might assume a quantity of air so large, that il 
should be lighter than a small quantity of fire, 
having more of the light parts." It thus follows 
that each of the four elements tends to its own 
place, fire being the highest, air the next, water the 
next, and earth the lowest. 

The whole of this train of errors arises from fal- 
lacies which have a verbal origin ; — from considering 
light as opposite to heavy; and from considering 
levity as a quality of a body, instead of as the effect 
of surrounding bodies. 

It is worth while to notice that a difficulty which 

VOL. I. E 



60 THE GREEK SCHOOL PHILOSOPHY. 

often embarrasses persons on their entrance upon 
physical speculations, — ^the difficulty of conceiving 
that up and down are different direections in different 
places, — ^had been completely got over by Aristotle 
and the Greek philosophers. They were steadily con- 
vinced of the roundness of the earth, and saw that 
this truth led to the conclusion that all heavy bodies 
tend in converging directions to the centre. And as 
the heavy tends to the centre, the light tends to the 
exterior, " for exterior is opposite to centre as heavy 
is to Ught^V 

The tendencies of bodies downwards and up- 
wards, their weight, their fall, their floating or sink- 
ing, were thus accounted for in a manner which, 
however unsoimd, satisfied the greater part of the 
speculative world till the time of Galileo and Ste- 
vinus, though Archimedes in the mean time pub- 
lished the true theory of floating bodies, which is 
very different from that above stated. Other parts 
of the doctrines of motion were delivered by the 
Stagirite in the same spirit and with the same suc- 
cess. The motion of a body which is thrown along 
the ground diminishes and finally ceases ; the motion 
of a body which falls from a height goes on becoming 
quicker and quicker ; this was accounted for on the 
usual principle of opposition, by saying that the 
former is a violent, the latter a natural motion. And 
the later writers of this school expressed the charac- 



18 



De Ccelo, ir. 4. 



ARISTOTELIAN PHYSICS. 51 

ters of such motions in verse. The rule of natural 
motion was** 

Principium tepeat, medium cum fine calebit. 
Cool at the firfit, it warm and warmer glows. 

And of violent motion, the law was — 

Principium ferret, medium calet, ultima friget. 
Hot at the first, then barely warm, then cold. 

It appears to have been considered by Aristotle a 
difficult problem to explain why a stone thrown 
from the hand continues to move for some time, and 
then stops. If the hand was the cause of the mo- 
tion, how could the stone move at all when left to 
itself? if not, why does it ever stop? And he 
answers this difficulty by saying'*, "that there is a 
motion communicated to the air, the successive parts 
of which urge the stone onwards; and that each 
part of this medium continues to act for some while 
after it has been acted on, and the motion ceases 
when it comes to a particle which cannot act after 
it has ceagfed to be acted on." It will be readily 
seen that the whole of this difficulty, concerning a 
body which moves forwards and is retarded till it 
stops, arises from ascribing the retardation, not to the 
real cause, the surrounding resistances, but to the 
body itself, — ^to which the common forms of language 
attribute it, as the nominative of the verb " move." 

One of the doctrines which was the subject of the 
warmest discussion between the defenders and 

^' Alsted. Encyc. torn i. p. 687- ^* Phys. Ausc. viii. 10. 

E 2 



52 THE GREEK SCHOOL PHILOSOPHY. 

opposers of Aristotte, at the revival of physical 
knowledge, was that in which he asserts^* " That 
body is heavier than another which in an equal bulk 
moves downward quicker." The opinion maintained 
by the Aristotelians at the time of Galileo was, that 
bodies fall quicker exactly in proportion to their 
weight. The master himself asserts this in express 
terms, and reasons upon iV\ Yet in another passage 
he appears to distinguish between weight and actual 
motion downwards '^ "In physics, we call bodies 
heavy and light from their power of motion ; but 
these names are not applied to their actual opera- 
tions (ivepyeiai^) except any one thinks mommtum 
(poTTT)) to be a word of both applications. But 
heavy and light are, as it were, the embers or sparks 
of motion, and therefore proper to be treated of 
here." 

The distinction just alluded to between power 
or faculty of action, and actual operation or energy, 
is one very frequently referred to by Aristotle ; and 
though not by any means useless, may easily be so 
used as to lead to mere verbal refinements instead of 
substantial "knowledge. 

The Aristotelian distinction of causes has not any 
very immediate bearing upon the parts of physics 
of which we have here mainly spoken ; but it was 
so extensively accepted, and so long retained, that 
it may be proper to notice it*^ " One kind of 

'' De Coelo, iy. 1, p. 308. '' De Coelo, iii. 2. 

»7 De Ccelo, iv. 1, p. 307- '" Phys. ii. 3. 



ARISTOTELIAN PHYSICS. 53 

cause is the matter of which atiy thing is made, as 
bronze of a statue, and silver of a phial ;* another is 
the form and pattern, as the cause of an octave is 
the ratio of two to one ; again, there is the cause 
which is the origin of the production, as the father 
of the child ; and again, there is the end, or that 
for the sake of which anything is done, as health 
is the cause of walking." These four kinds of cause, 
the material, the formal, the efficient, and the ^nal, 
were long leading points in all speculative inquiries ; 
and our familiar forms of speech still retain traces of 
the influence of this division. 

It is my object here to present to the reader in 
an intelligible shape, the principles and mode of 
reasoning of the Aristotelian philosophy, not its 
results^ If this were not the case, it would be easy 
to excite a smile by insuliating some of the passages 
which are most remote from modem notions. I 
will only mention, as specimens, two such passages, 
both very remarkable. 

In the beginning of the book " On the Heavens," 
he proves '• the world to be perfect, by reasoning of 
•the following kind : " The bodies of which the world 
is composed are solids, and therefore have three 
dimensiouB ; now three is the most perfect number ; 
it is the first of numbers, for of one we do not speak 
as a number ; of two we say both ; but three is the 
first number of which we say all; moreover, it has 
a beginning, a middle, and an end." 

'' De Coelo, i. 1. 



54 THE GREEK SCHOOL PHILOSOPHY. 

The reader will still perceive the verbal fotuida- 
tions of opinions thus supported. 

" The simple elements must have simple motions, 
and thus fire and air have their natural motions 
upwards, and water and earth have their natural 
motions downwards; but besides these motions, 
there is motion in a circle, which is unnatural to 
these elements, but which is a more perfect motion 
than the other, because a circle is a perfect line, and 
a straight line is not ; and there must be something 
to which this motion is natural. From this it is 
evident," he adds, with obvious animation, " that 
there is some essence of body different from those 
of the four elements, more divine than those, and 
superior to them. If things which move in a circle 
move contrary to nature, it is marvellous, or* rather 
absurd, that this, the unnatural motion, should alone 
be continuous and eternal; for unnatural motions 
decay speedily. So that fipom all this, we must 
collect, that besides the four elements which we 
have here and about us, there is another removed 
far off, and the more excellent in proportion as it is 
more distant from us." This fifth element was the 
" quirda essentid' of after writers, of which we have 
a trace in our modern literature, in the word quiTdi- 
essence. 



ITS TECHNICAL FORMS. 55 

Sect 3. — Technical Forms of the Ghreek Schools. 

MVi^ have hitherto considered only the principle of 
the Greek Physics ; which was, as we have seen, to de- 
duce its doctrines by an analysis of the notions which 
common language involves. But though the Grecian 
philosopher began by studying words in their common 
meanings, he soon found himself led to fix upon 
some special shades or applications of these meanings 
as the permanent and standard notion, which they 
were to express ; that is, he made his language fecA- 
nical. The invention and establishment of technical 
terms is an important step in any philosophy, true 
or false ; we must, therefore, say a few words on this 
process, as exemplified in the ancient systems. 

1. TechnicdForimof the Aristotelian Philosophy. — 
We have already had occasion to cite some of the 
distinctions introduced by Aristotle, which may be 
considered as technical ; for instance, the classificatioji 
of causes as material^ formal^ ejicient^ bhA final; and 
the opposition of qualities as absdvte and relative. 
A few more of the most important examples may 
suffice. An analysis of objects into matter hxA form^ 
when metaphorically extended from visible objects 
to things conceived in the most general manner, 
became an habitual hypothesis of the Aristotelian 
school. Indeed this metaphor is even yet one 
of the most significant of those which we can 
employ, to suggest one of the most comprehensive 
and fiindamental antitheses with which philosophy 



56 THE GREEK SCHOOL PHILOSOPHY. 

Ims to do ; — ^the opposition of the sense and reason, of 
impressions and laws. In this application, the Ger- 
man philosophers have, up to the present time, rested 
upon this distinction a great part of the weight of 
their systems ; as when Kant says, that space and 
time are the forms of sensation. Even in our own 
language, we retain a trace of the influence of this 
Aristotelian notion, in the word information^ when 
used for that knowledge, which may be conceived as 
moulding the mind into a definite shape, instead of 
leaving it a mere ma&» of unimpressed susceptibility. 

Another favourite Aristotelian antithesis is that of 
power and «c< {hvvaiii^^ ivepyeia,} This distinction is 
made the basis of most of the physical philosophy of 
the school; being, however, generally introduced 
with a peculiar limitation. Thus, light is defined to 
be " the act of what is lucid, as far as it is lucid. 
And if," it is added, " the lucid be so in power but 
not in act, we have darkness." The reason of the 
limitation, " as fer as it is lucid," is, that a lucid body 
may act in other ways ; thus a torch may move as 
well as shine, but its moving is not its act as a Iticid 
body. 

Aristotle appears to be well satisfied with this 
explanation, for he goes on to say, " Thus light is not 
fire, nor any body whatever, or the emanation of any 
body, (for that would be a kind of body,) but it is the 
presence of something like fire in the body; it is, 
however, impossible that two bodies should exist in 
the same place, so that it is not a body;" and this 



ITS TECHNICAL FORMS. 57 

reasoning appears to leave him more satisfied with 
his doctrine, that light is an energy or dcL 

But we have a more distinctly technical form given 
to this notion. Aristotle introduced a word formed 
by himself, to express the act which is thus opposed 
to inactive power: this is the celebrated word 
evTe\e;^eta. Thus the noted definition of motion in 
the third book of the Physics '^ is that it is " the 
enidechy^ or act, of a moveable body in respect of 
being moveable ;" and the definition of the soul is 
that it is ^' the enidechy of a natural body which has 
life, by reason of its power." This word has been 
variously translated by the followers of Aristotle, 
and some of them . have declared it untranslateable. 
Act and action are held to be inadequate substitutes; 
the very act^ ipse cursm actionis is employed by some; 
primm acttis is employed by many, but another school 
use primm actus of a non-operating form. Budoeus 
uses efficacia, Cicero*^ translates it " quasi quandam 
continuatam motionem, et perennem ;" but this para* 
phrase, though it may fiiU in with the description of 
the soul, which is the subject with which Cicero is 
concerned, does not appear to agree with the general 
applications of the term. Hermolaus Barbarus is said 
to have been so much oppressed with this difliculty 
of translation, that he consulted the evil spirit by 
night, entreating to be supplied with a more common 
and femiliar substitute for this word : the mocking 

"Phys. iii. J. "' Tusc. i. 10. 



58 THE GREEK SCHOOL PHILOSOPHY. 

fiend, however, suggested only a word equally obscure, 
and the translator, discontented with this, invented 
for himself the word perfedihabia. 

We need not here notice the endless apparatus 
of technicalities which was, in later days, introduced 
into the Aristotelian philosophy; but we may remark, 
that their long continuance and extensive use show 
us how powerful technical phraseology is, for the 
perpetuation either of truth or error. The Aristo- 
telian terms, and the metaphysical views which they 
tend to preserve, are not yet extinct among us. In 
a very recent age of our literature it was thought 
a worthy employment by some of the greatest 
writers of the day, to attempt to expel this system 
of technicalities by ridicule. 

"Crambe regretted extremely that mbstantial 
formsy a race of harmless beings, which had lasted for 
many years, and afforded a comfortable subsistence 
to many poor philosophers, should now be hunted 
down like so many wolves, without a possibility of 
retreat. He considered that it had gone much harder 
with them than with essences^ which had retired from 
the schools into the apothecaries' shops, where some 
of them had been advanced to the degree of quint- 
esences^*. 

We must now say a few words on the technical 
terms which others of the Greek philosophical sects 
introduced. 



as 



Martinus Scriblerus, cap. vii. 



ITS TECHNICAL FORMS. 59 

2. Technical Forms of the PkUonists. — ^The other 
sects of the Greek philosophy, as well as the Aris- 
totelians, invented and adopted technical terms, and 
thus gave fixity to their tenets and consistency to 
their traditionary systems ; of these I will mention 
a few. 

A technical expression of a conteitporaiy school 
has acquired perhaps greater celebrity than any of 
the terms of Aristotle. I mean the Ideas of Plato. 
The account which Aristotle gives of the origin of 
these will serve to explain their nature". "Plato," 
says he, " who, in his youth, was in habits of com- 
munication first with Cratylus and the Heraclitean 
opinions, which represent all the objects of sense m in 
a perpetual flux, so that concerning these no science 
nor certain knowledge can exist, retained the same 
opinions at a later period also. When, afterwards, 
Socrates treated of moral subjects, and gave no 
attention to physics, but in the subjects which he 
did discuss, arrived at universal truths, and turned 
his thoughts to definitions, Plato adopted similar 
doctrines, and construed them in this way, that these 
truths and definitions must be applicable to some- 
thing else, and not to sensible things: for it was 
impossible, he conceived, that there should be a 
common definition of any sensible object, since such 
were always in a state of change. The things, then, 
which were the subjects of universal truths he called 

*' Arist. Metaph. i. 6. The same account is repeated, and 
the subject discussed, Metaph. xii. 4. 



60 THE GREEK SCHOOL PHILOSOPHY. 

ideas ; and held that objects of sense had their names 
according to them and after them ; so that things 
participated in that idea which had the same name 
as was applied to them." 

In agreement with this, we find the opinions 
suggested in the Parmenides of Plato, the dialogue 
which is considered by many to contain the most 
decided exposition of the doctrine of ideas. In this 
dialogue, Parmenides is made to say to Socrates, 
then a young man**, "O Socrates, philosophy has 
not yet claimed you for her own, as, in my judg- 
ment, she will claim you, and y<m will not dishonour 
her. As yet, like a young man as you are, you look 
to the opinions of men. But tell me this : it appears 
to you, as you say, that there are certain kinds or 
ideas (eiSr)) of which things partake and receive ap- 
plications according to that of which they partake : 
thus those things which partake of likeness are called 
like; those things which partake of greatness are 
called great; those things which partake of heandy 
and justice are called heavUful and justr To this 
Socrates assents. And in another part of the 
dialogue he shows that these ideas are not included 
in our common knowledge, from whence he infers 
that they are objects of the Divine mind. 

In the Phaedo the same opinion is maintained, and 
is sununed up in this way, by a reporter of the last 
conversation of Socrates" eZva* n cKaarov t&v dh&Vy 

** Parmenid., p. 131, abed. ** Phacdo, p. 102, a b. 



ITS TECHNICAL FORMS. 61 

Kol rovroov rdWa fieraXafifidvovra air&v - tovtodv rrjv 
errcovvfilav X<T'xeiv ; " that each kind has an existence, 
and that other things partake of these kinds, and are 
called according to the kind of which they partake." 

The inference drawn from this view was, that in 
order to obtain true and certain knowledge, men 
must elevate themselves, as much as possible, to 
these ideas of the qualities which they have to con- 
sider : and as things were thus called after the ideas, 
the ideas had a priority and pre-eminence assigned 
them. The idea of good, beautiful, and wise, was the 
" first good," the " first beautiful," the " first wise." 
This dignity and distinction were ultimately carried 
to a large extent. Those ideas were described as 
eternal and self-subsisting, forming an " intelligible 
world," fiill of the models or archetypes of created 
things. But it is not to our purpose here to con- 
sider the Platonic Ideas in their theological bearings. 
In physics they were applied in the same form as in 
morals. The primum calidum^ primum fngidum^ 
were those ideas or fundamental principles by par- 
ticipation of which, all things were hot or cold. 

This school did not much employ itself in the 
developement of its principles as applied to physical 
inquiries : but we are not without examples of such 
(peculations. Plutarch's Treatise Il^pi rov Jlptorov 
Wvxpov, " On the First Cold" may be cited as one. 
It is in reality a discussion of a question which has 
been agitated in modern times also; — whether cold 
be a positive quality or a mere privation. " Is there, 



62 THE GREEK SCHOOL PHILOSOPHY. 

O Favorinus," he begins, " a first power and essence 
of the Cold, as fire is of the Hot ; by a certain pre- 
sence and participation of which all other things are 
cold : or is rather coldness a privation of heat, as 
darkness is of light, and rest of motion ?" 

3. Technicd Forms of the Pythagoreans, — The 
Numbers of the Pythagoi-eans, when propounded as 
the explanation of physical phenomena, as they were, 
are still more obscure than the ideas of the Plato- 
nists. There were, indeed, considerable resemblances 
in the way in which these two kinds of notions were 
spoken of. Plato called his ideas unities^ monads; 
and as, according to him, ideas, so, according to the 
Pythagoreans, numbers, were the causes of things 
being what they are*^ But there was this difference^ 
that things shared the nature of the Platonic ideas 
" by participation," while they shared the nature of 
Pythagorean numbers *'by imitation." Moreover, 
the Pythagoreans followed their notion out into much 
greater developement than any other school, in- 
vesting particular numbers with extraordinary attri- 
butes, and applying them by very strange and forced 
analogies. Thus the number Four, to which they 
gave the name of TetractjfSy was held' to be the most 
perfect number, and was conceived to correspond to 
the human soul, in some way which appears to be 
very imperfectly understood by the commentators of 
this philosophy. 



26 



Arist. Metaph. i. 6. 



ITS TECHNICAL FORMS. 63 

It has been stated by a distinguished modern 
scholar"^ that the place which Pythagoras ascribed 
to his numbers is intelligible only by supposing that 
he confounded, first a numerical unit with a geo- 
metrical point, and then this with a material atom. 
But this criticism appears to place systems of physical 
philosophy under requisitions too severe. If all the 
essential properties and attributes of things were 
fiilly represented by the relations of number, the 
philosophy which supplied such an explanation of the 
universe, might well be excused from explaining also 
that existence of objects which is distinct from the 
existence of all their qualities and properties. The 
Pythagorean love of numerical speculations might 
have been combined with the doctrine of atoms, and 
the combination might have led to results well worth 
notice. But so far as we are aware, no such com- 
bination was attempted in the ancient schools of 
philosophy ; and perhaps we of the present day are 
only just beginning to perceive, through the dis* 
closures of chemistry and crystallography, the 
importance of such a line of inquiry. 

4. Technical Forms of the Atomists mid Others. — 
The atomic doctrine, of which we have just spoken, 
was one of the most definite of the physical doctrines 
of the ancients, and was applied with most perse- 
verance and knowledge, to the explanation of phe- 
nomena. Though, therefore, it led to no success of 

«^ Thirlwairs Hist. Gr. ii. 142. 



64 THE GKBEK SCHOOL PHILOSOPHY. 

any coasequ^ice in ancient times, it served to trans^ 
mit, through a long series of ages, a habit of really 
physical inquiry; and on this aoeomxt, has been 
thought worthy of an historieal disquisition by 
Bacon *\ 

The technical tenn, Aiom^ mari^ sufficiently the 
nature of the opinion. According to this theory, the 
world consists of a collection tof simple ^particles, of 
one kind of matter^ aztd of indivisible smaliness, (as 
the name indicates,) and hy the various configurations 
and motions of <thes6, sdl kinds of matter and all 
mat^al phenomena ^re produced. 

To this, the atoibie daotidne ^f Leucippus and 
Democritiis, wai opposed the H&moiomeria of Anax- 
agoras ; that is, the opinion that material things con* 
sist of particles which are homogeneous in each kind 
of body» but various in different kinds : and thus, for 
example, since by food the flesh and blood and bones 
of man increase, the author of this doctrine held that 
there are in food particles of flesh, and blood, and 
bone. As the former tenet points to the corpuscular 
theories of modern times, so the latter may be con- 
sidered as a dim glimpse of the idea of chemical 
analysis. The Stoics also, who were, especially at a 
later period, inclined to materialist views, had their 
technical modes of speaking on such subjects. They 
asserted that matter contained in itself tendencies or 
dispositions to certain forms, which dispositions 

" Parmenidis et Telesii et praecipue Democriti Philosophia, 
&c., works, vol. ix. 317- 



^ ITS TECHNICAL FOAHB. 65 

they called Xoy&i awepfAarticoi, seminal prapm'tioii^j or 
reasons. 

Whatever of sound view, or right direction, there 
might be in the notions which suggested these and 
other technical expressions, was, in all the schools of 
philosophy (so &r as physics was concerned), quenched 
and overlaid by the predominance of trifling and 
barren speculations; and by the love of subtilizing 
and commenting upon the works of earlier writers, 
instead of attempting to interpret the book of nature. 
Hence these technical terms served to give fixity and 
permanence to the traditional dogmas of the sect, 
but led to no progress of knowledge. 

The advances which were made in physical science 
proceeded^ not from these schools of philosophy, (if 
we except, perhaps, the obligations of the science of 
harmonies to the Pythagoreans,) but from reasoners 
who followed an independent path. The sequel of 
the ambitious hopes, the vast schemes, the confident 
undertakings of the philosophers of ancient Greece, 
was an entire failure in the physical knowledge of 
which it is our business to trace the history. Yet 
we are not, on that account, to think slightingly of 
these early speculators. They were men of extra- 
ordinary acuteness, invention, and range of thought ; 
and above all, they had the merit of first completely 
unfolding the speculative faculty ;*— of starting in that 
keen and vigorous chase of knowledge, by which all 
the subsequent culture and improvement of man's 
intellectual stores have been occasioned. The sages 

VOL. I. • F 



66 THE GREEK SCHOOL PHILOSOPHY. 

of early Greece form the heroic age of science. Like 
the first navigators in their own mythology, they 
boldly ventured their untried bark in a distant and 
arduous voyage, urged on by the hopes of a super- 
natural success ; and though they niissed the ima- 
ginary golden prize which they sought, they unlocked 
the gates of distant regions, and opened the seas to 
the keels of the thousands of adventurers, who, in 
succeeding times, sailed to and fro, to the indefinite 
increase of the mental treasures of mankind. 

But inasmuch as their attempts, in one sense, and 
at first, failed, we must proceed to offer some account 
of this failure, and of its nature and causes. 



67 



CHAPTER III. 

Failure of the Physical Philosophy of the 

Gbeek Schools. 



Sect 1. — ResitU of the Greek School PhUosophj/. 

The methods and forms of philosophizing which we 
have described as employed by the Greek schools, 
failed altogether in their application to physics. No 
discovery of general laws, no explanation of special 
phenomena, rewarded the acuteness and boldness of 
these early students of nature. Astronomy, which 
made considerable progress during the existence of 
the sects of Greek philosophers, gained perhaps 
something by the authority with which Plato taught 
the supremacy and universality of mathematical 
rule and order ; and the truths of harmonics, which 
had probably given rise to the Pythagorean passion 
for numbers, were cultivated with much care by that 
school. But after these first impulses, the sciences 
owed nothing to the philosophical sects; and the 
vast and complex accumulations and apparatus of 
the Stagirite do not appear to have led to any 
theoretical physical truths. 

This assertion hardly requires proof, since in the 
existing body of science there are no doctrines for 

F 2 



68 THE GREEK SCrfOOL PHILOSOPHY. 

which we are indebted to the Aristotelian school. 
Real truths, when once established, remain to the 
end of time a part of the mental treasure of man, 
and may be discerned through all the additions of 
later days. But we can point out no physical doc- 
trine now received, of which we trace the anticipation 
in Aristotle, in the way in which we see the Coper- 
nican system anticipated by Aristarchus, the resolu- 
tion of the heavenly appearances into circular motions 
suggested by Plato, and the numerical relations of 
musical intervals ascribed to Pythagoras. But it 
may be worth while to look at this matter more 
closely. 

Among the works of Aristotle, are thirty-eight 
chapters of ** Problems," which may serve to exem- 
plify thie progress he had really made in the reduc- 
tion of phenomena to laws and causes. Of these 
Problems, a large proportion are physiological, and 
these I pass by, as not illustrative of the state of 
physical knowledge. But those which are properly 
physical are, for the most part, questions concerning 
such facts and difficulties as it is the peculiar busi- 
ness of theory to explain. Now it may be truly said, 
that in scarcely any one instance are the answers, 
which Aristotle gives to his questions, of any value. 
For the most part, indeed, he propounds his answer 
with a degree of hesitation or vacillation, which of 
itself shows the absence of all scientific distinctness 
of thought ; and the opinions so offered never appear 
to involve any settled or general principle. 



ITS FAILURE. 6d 

We may take, as examples of this, the problems 
of the simplest kind, where the principles lay nearest 
at hand, — ^the mechanical ones. " Why," he asks*, 
« do smaU force8 move great weights by means of 
a lever, when they have thus to move the lever added 
to the weight ? Is it," he suggests, " because a greater 
radius moves faster ?" " Why does a small wedge 
split great weights'? Is it because the wedge is 
composed of two opposite levers?" "Why", when 
a man rises from a chair, does he bend his leg and 
his body to acute angles with his thigh ? Is it be- 
cause a right aagle is connected with equality and 
rest?" " Why* can a man throw a stone further 
with a sling than with his hand ? Is it that when he 
throws with his hand he moves the stone from rest, 
but when he uses the sling he throws it already in 
motion?" . "Why*, if a circle be thrown on the 
ground, does it first describe a straight liije and then 
a spiral, as it Mis ? Is it that the air first presses 
equally on the two sides and supports it, and after- 
wards presses on one side more?" "Why* is it 
difficult to distinguish a musical note from the octave 
above ? Is it that proportion stands in the place of 
equality ?" It must be allowed that these are very 
vague and worthless surmises ; for even if we were, 
as some commentators have done, to interpret some 
of them so as to agree with sound philosophy, we 
should still be unable to point out, in this author's 

' Mech. Prob. 4. ? lb. 18. » lb. 31. * lb. 13. 



70 THE GREEK SCHOOL PHttOSOPHY. 

works, any clear or permanent apprehension of the 
general principles which such an interpretation 
implies. 

Thus the Aristotelian physics cannot be considered 
as otherwise than a complete failure. It collected 
no general laws from facts ; and consequently, when 
it tried to explain facts, it had no principles which 
were of any avail. 

The same may be said of the physical speculations 
of the other schools of philosophy. They arrived at 
no doctrines from which they could deduce, by sound 
reasoning, such fiiets as they saw ; though they often 
venture so far to trust their principles as to infer 
from them propositions beyond the domain of sense. 
Thus, the principle that each element seeks its awn 
place, led to the doctrine, that, the place of fire being 
the highest, there is, above the air, a sphere of fire; 
of which doctrine the word empyreanj used by our 
poets, still conveys a reminiscence. The Pythagorean 
tenet that ten is a perfect number^ led them to assert 
that the heavenly bodies are in number ten ; and as 
nine only were known to them, they asserted that 
there was an antiehthon, or counter-earth, on the 
other side of the sun, invisible to us. Their opinions 
respecting numerical ratios, led to various other 
speculations concerning the distances and positions 
of the heavenly bodies : and as they had, in other 
cases, found a connexion between proportions of 

^ Arist. Metaph. 



ITS FAILURE. 71 

distance and musical notes, they assumed, on this 
suggestion, the music of the spheres. 

Although we shall look in vain in the physical 
philosophy of the Greek schools, for any results more 
valuable than those just mentioned, we shall not be 
surprised to find, recollecting how much an admirar 
tion for classical antiquity has possessed the minds 
of men, that some writers estimate their claims 
much more highly than they are stated here. Among 
such writers we may notice Dutens, who, in 1766, 
published his " Origin of the Discoveries attributed 
to the Modems ; in which it is shown that our most 
celebrated Philosophers have received the greatest 
part of their knowledge from the Works of the 
Ancients." The thesis of this work is attempted 
to be proved, as we might expect, by very large 
interpretations of the general phrases used by the 
ancients. Thus, when Tim«us, in Plato's dialogue, 
says of the Creator of the world S " that he infused 
into it two powers, the origins of motions, both of 
that of the same thing, and of that of diiferent things;" 
Dutens* finds in this a clear indication of the pro- 
jectile and attractive forces of modem science. And 
in some of the common declamation of the Pytha-^ 
goreans and Platonists, concerning the general pre- 
valence of numerical relations in the universe, he 
discovers their acquaintance with the law of the 
inverse square of the distance by which gravitation 

• Tim. 96 a. ' 3d ed. p. 83. 



72 THE GREEK SCHOOL PHILOSOPHY. 

is regulated, though he allows^® that it required all 
the penetration of Newton and his followers to 
detect this law in the scanty fragments by which it 
is transmitted. 

Argument of this kind is palpably insufficient to 
cover the failure of the Greek attempts at a general 
physical phUosophy; or rather we may say, that 
such arguments, since they are as good as can be 
brought in favour of such an opinion, show more 
clearly how entire the failure was. I proceed now 
to endeavour to point out its causes. 

Sect. 2. — Cause of the Failure of the Greek Physical 

PhUosophy. 

The cause of the failure of so toavlj of the at- 
tempts of the Greeks to construct physical science 
is so important, that we must, endeavour to bring it 
into view here ; though the ftdl developement of 
such subjects belongs rather to the philosophy of in- 
duction. The subject must, at present, be treated 
briefly only. 

I will first notice some errors which may naturally 
occur to the reader's mind, as possible causes of 
failTire, but which, we shall be able to show, were not 
the real reasons in this case. 

The cause of failure was iwt the neglect of facts. 
It is often said that the Greeks disregarded experi- 



10 



lb. p. 88. 



CAU»B OF IT8 FAILURE. 73 

ence, and spun their philosophy out of their own 
thoughts alone ; and this is supposed by many to be 
their essential error* It is^ no doubt, true, that the 
disregard of experience is a phrase which may be so 
interpreted as to express almost any defect of philo- 
sophical method ; since the coincidence of all theory 
with experience is requisite to its truth. But if we 
fix a more precise sense on our terms, I conceive it 
may be shown that the Greek philosophy did, in its 
opinions, recognise the necessity and paramount 
value of observations; did, in its origin, proceed 
upon observed facts ; and did employ itself to no 
small extent in classifying and arranging phen(»nena. 
We must endeavour to illustrate these assertions, 
because it is important to show that these steps 
alone do not necessarily lead to science. 

1. The acknowledgment of experience as the 
main ground of physical knowledge is so generally 
understood to be a distinguishing feature of later 
times, that it may excite surprise to find that 
Aristotle, and other ancient philosophers, not only 
asserted in the most pointed manner that all our 
knowledge must begin from experience, but also 
stated in language much resembling the habitual 
phraseology of the most modern schools of philoso- 
phising, that particular facts must be (xUected; that 
from these, general principles must be obtained by 
induction; and that these principles, when of the 
most general kind, are amoms. A few passages will 
show this. 



74 THE GREEK SCHOOL PHILOSOPHY. 

"The way^» must be the same/* says Aristotle, in 
speaking of the rules of reasoning, ** with respect to 
philosophy, as it is with respect to any art or science 
whatever ; we must collect the facts, and the things 
to which the fects happen, in each subject, and pro- 
vide as large a supply of these as possible." He 
then proceeds to say that we are net to look at once 
at all this collected mass, but to consider small and 
definite portions. "And thus it is the office of 
obserration to supply principles in ea«h subject ; for 
instance, astronomical observation supplies the prin- 
ciples of astronomical science. For the phenomena 
being properly assumed, the astronomical demon- 
strations were from these discovered. And the 
same applies to every art and science. So that if 
we take the fiawjts {ra inrapxovra) belonging to each 
subject, it is our task to mark out clearly the course 
of the demonstrations. For if in our natural history 
{Kaff ioTopvav) we have omitted nothing of the &cts 
and properties which belong to the subject, we 
shall learn what we can demonstrate and what we 
cannot." 

These facts, ra inrapxovra, he, at other times, in- 
cludes in the term sensation. Thus he says'S " It is 
obvious that if any sensation is wanting, there must 
be also some knowledge wanting which we are thus 
prevented from having, since we arrive at knowledge 
either by induction or by demonstration. Demon- 

'' Anal. Prior, i. 30 '« Anal. Post. i. 18. 



CAUSE OF ITS FAILURE. 76 

stration proceeds from universal propositions, induc- 
tion from particulars. But we cannot have universal 
theoretical propositions except from induction ; and 
we cannot make inductions without having sensa- 
tion ; for sensation has to do with particulars." 

In another placets after stating that principles 
must be prior to, and better known than conclu- 
sions, he distinguishes such principles into absolute, 
and relative to us ; '^ such principles, relative to us, 
are those which are nearer to the sensation; but 
absolute principles are those which are more remote 
from the sensation. The most general principles 
are the more remote, the more particular are nearer. 
The general principles which are necessary to know- 
ledge are aanoms,^^ 

We may add to these passages, that in which he 
gives an account of the way in which Leucippus was 
led to the doctrine of atoms. After describing the 
opinions of some earlier philosophers, he says^^ 
^^ Thus, proceeding in violation of sensation, and 
disregarding it, because, as they held, they must 
follow reason, some came to the conclusion that the 
universe was one, and infinite, and at rest. As it 
appeared, however, that though this ought to be by 
reason, it would go near to madness to hold such 
opinions as to the fact, (for no one was ever so mad as 
to think fire and ice to be one,) Leucippus, therefore, 
pursued a line of reasoning which was in accordance 

*' Anal.' Post. i. 2. '' De Gen. et Cor. i. i8. 



'■*' ^'^ iw>t irreeourileaWe 
'i«>ray. the motion and nml- 
*>t>vio«s that the school to 
ed tthe Ecleetje, miBt hsre 
rin- ^tnmeh- inniRseed nidi 
- "^ 'iieette* tmo i 






CAUSE OF ITS FAILURE. 77 

some measure platisible, and apparently confirmed 
by f5sw5ts. 

But the works of Aristotle show, in another way, 
how unjust it would be to accuse him of disregarding 
facts. Many large treatises of his consist almost 
(Butirely of collections of facts, as for instance, those 
" On Colours," " On Sounds," and the collection of 
Problems to which we have already referred ; to say 
nothing of the numerous collection of facts bearing 
on natural history and physiology, which form a great 
portion of his works, and are even now treasuries of 
information. A moment's reflection will convince 
us that the physical sciences of our own times, for 
example, mechanics and hydrostatics, are founded 
almost entirely upon facts with which the ancients 
were as familiar as we are. The defect of their phi- 
losophy, therefore, wherever it may lie, exists neither 
in the speculative depreciation of the value of facts, 
nor in the practical neglect of their use. 

3. Nor again, should we hit upon the truth, if we 
were to say that Aristotle and other ancient philoso- 
phers, did indeed collect facts; but that they took no 
steps in classifying and comparing them ; and that 
thus they failed to obtain from them any general 
knowledge. For, in reality, the treatises of Aristotle 
which we have mentioned, are as remarkable for the 
power of classifying and systematising which they 
exhibit, as for the industry shown in the accumula- 
tion. But it is not classification of facts merely 
which can lead us to knowledge, except we adopt 



78 THE GREEK SCHOOL PHILOSOPHY. 

that special arrangement, which, in each case, brings 
into view the principles of the subject. We may 
easily show how unprofitable an arbitrary or random 
classification is, however orderly and systematic it 
may be. 

For instance, for a long period all unusual fiery 
appearances in the sky were classed together as 
meteors. Comets, shooting-stars, and globes of fire, 
and the aurora borealis in all its forms, were thus 
grouped together, and classifications of considerable 
extent and minuteness were proposed with reference 
to these objects. But this classification was of a 
mixed and arbitrary kind. Figure, colour, motion, 
duration, were all combined as characters, and the 
imagination lent its aid, transforming these striking 
appearances into fiery swords and spears, bears and 
dragons, armies and chariots. The facts so classified 
were, notwithstanding, worthless; and would not 
have been one jot the less so, had they and their 
classes been ten times as numerous as they were. 
No rule or law that would stand the test of obser- 
vation was or could be thus discovered. Such clas- 
sifications have, therefore, long been neglected and 
forgotten. Even the ancient descriptions of these 
objects of curiosity are unintelligible, or unworthy of 
trust, because the spectators had no steady conception 
of the usual order of such phenomena. For, how- 
ever much we may fear to be misled by preconceived 
opinions, the caprices of imagination distort our 
impressions fer more than the anticipations of reason. 



CAUSE OF ITS FAILURE. 79 

In this case men had» indeed we may say with regard 
to many of these meteors, they still have, no science : 
not for want of &cts» nor even for want of classifica- 
tion of &cts ; but because the classification was one 
in which no real principle was contained. 

4. Since, as we have said before, two things are 
requisite to science, — ^facts and ideas ; and since, as 
we have seen, facts were not wanting in the physical 
speculations of the ancients, we are naturally led to 
ask. Were they then deficient in ideas ? Was there a 
want among them of mental activity, and logical 
connexion of thought? But it is so obvious that 
the answer to this inquiry must be in the negative, 
that we need not dwell upon it. No one who 
knows anything of the history of the ancient Greek 
mind, can question, that in acuteness» in ingeniuty, 
in the power of close and distinct reasoning, they 
have never been surpassed. The common opinion, 
which considers this defect of their philosophical 
character to reside in the exclusive activity of such 
qualities, is at least so &r just. 

5* We come back again, therefore, to the ques- 
tion. What was the radical and &tal defect in the 
physical speculations of the Greek philosophical 
schools ? 

To this I answer: The defect was, that though they 
had in their possession facts and ideas, the ideas were 
not dutinct and appropriate to the facts. 

The peculiar characters of scientific ideas, which 1 
have endeavoured to express by speaking of them as 



80 THE GREEK SCHOOL PHILOSOPHY. 

distinct and appropriate to the facts, must be more 
fiilly and formally set forth, when we come to the 
philosophy of the subject. In the mean time, the 
reader will probably have no difficulty in conceiving 
that, for each class of facts, there is some special set 
of ideas, by means of which the fects can be included 
in general scientific truths; and that these ideas, 
which may thus be termed appropriate^ must be pos- 
sessed with entire distinctness and clearness, in order 
that they may be successfully applied. It was the 
want of such ideas, having a reference to material 
phenomena, which rendered the ancient philosophers, 
with very few exceptions, helpless and unsuccessftil 
speculators on physical subjects. 

This must be illustrated by one or two examples. 
One of the facts which Aristotle endeavours to 
explain is this ; that when, the sun's light passes 
through a hole, whatever be the form of the hole, 
the bright image, if formed at any considerable dis- 
tance from the hole, is round, instead of imitating 
the figure of the hole, as shadows resemble their 
objects. We shall easily perceive this appearance to 
be a necessary consequence of the circular figure of 
the sun, if we conceive light to be diffiised from the 
luminary by means of straight rays proceeding from 
every point. But instead of this appropriate idea of 
ragfSy Aristotle attempts to explain the fact by saying 
that the sun's light has a circular nature, which it 
always tends to manifest. And this vague and loose 
conception of a circular qfjudityy employed instead of 



CAUSB OP ITS FAILURE. 81 

the distinct conception of rays, which is really appli- 
eable, jwevented Aristotle from giving a true ac- 
count, even of this very simple optical phenomenon. 

Again^ to pass to a more extensive failure : why 
was it that Aristotle, knowing the property of the 
lever, »nd many other mechanical truths, was unable 
to form them into a science of mechanics, as Archi- 
medes afterwards did? ' ' • 

The reason was, that, instead of cohWdering rest 
and motion directly, and difetinctly, with reference to 
the idea of cause, that is force, he'Wa'ndei'edin search 
of reasons among other ideas and notions, which 
could not be brought into steady connexion with the 
facts ; — ^the ideas of properties of cfrcles, of propor- 
tions of velocities, — ^the notions of iatrangeattd' com- 
mon, of natural and unnatural. -Thusi in the proem ' 
to his Mechanical Problems, after stating donie <>f the 
difficulties which he has to attack, he sayb, " Of all 
such cases, the circle cbntail!!^ the principle of the 
cause. And this is wha/t might be looked for ; for 
it is nothing absurd, if something wonderftd is derived 
from something more wonderfttl' still. Now the 
most wonderful thing is, that opposites should be 
combined ; and the circle is constituted of such com- 
binations of opposites. For it is constructed by a 
stationary point and a moving line, which are con- 
trary to eadi other in nature-; and hence we may 
the less be surprised at the resulting contrarieties. 
And in the fiw* place, the circumference of the circle, 
though a line witJiout breadth, has opposite qualities; 

VOL. I. G 



82 THE GREEK SCHOOL PHILOSOPHY. 

for it is both corner and concave. In the next place, 
it has, at the same time, opposite motions, for it 
moves forward and backward at the same time. For 
U„ ciH^^ferenee. .«tag ou. fro. .o, point, come, 
to t^e same point agafn, so that by a continuous 
progression, the last point becomes the first. So 
that, as was before stated, it is not surprising that 
the circle should be the principle of all wonderful 
properties." 

Aristotle afterwards proceeds to explain more 
specially how he applies the properties of the circle 
in this case. " The reason," he says, in his fourth 
problem, " why a force, acting at a ^eat^r distance 
fipom the fiilcruin, moves a weight more easily, is, 
that it describes a greater circle." He had already 
asserted that when a body at the end of a lever is 
put in motion, it may be considered as having two 
motions ; one in the direction of the tangent, and 
one in the direction of the radius ; the former motion 
is^ he says, nccording to nature^ the latter, contrary to 
natwe. Now in the smaller circle, the motion, con- 
trary to nature, is more considerable than it is in the 
larger circle. " Therefore," he adds, " the mover or 
weight at the larger arm will be transferred further 
by L same fo«e th«, the weight moved, which i, 
at the extremity of the shorter arm." 

These loose and inappropriate notions of natural 
and unnatural motions, were unfit to lead to any 
scientific truths; and, with the habits of thought 
which dictated these speculations, a perc^tion of 



CAUSE OF ITS FAILURE. 83 

the true grounds of mechanical properties was im- 
possible. 

Thus, in this instance, the error of Aristotle was 
the neglect of the idea appropriate to the fEU^ts, 
namely, the Idea of Mechanical Cause, which is 
Force; and the substitution of vague or inappli- 
cable notions involving only relations of space, or 
emotions of wonder. The errors of those who fitiled 
similarly in other instances, were of the same kind. 
To detail or classify these would lead us too fisu* into 
the philosophy of science ; since we should have to 
enumerate the ideas which are appropriate, and the 
various class of facts on which the different sciences 
are foimded, — a task not to be now lightly under- 
taken. But it will be perceived, without further 
explanation, that it is necessary, in order to obtain 
from facts any general truth, that we should apply 
to them that appropriate idea, by which permanent 
and definite relations are established among them. 

In such ideas the ancients were very poor, and the 
stunted and deformed growth of their physical sci- 
ence was the result of this penury. The ideas of 
space and time, number and motion, they did indeed 
possess distinctly ; and so fiir as these went, their sci- 
ence was tolerably healthy. They also caught a 
glimpse of the idea of a medium by which the quali- 
ties of bodies, as colours and sounds, are perceived. 
But the idea of substance remained barren in their 
hands ; in speculating about elements and qualities, 
they went the wrong way, assuming that the proper- 

G 2 



84 THE GREEK SCHOOL PHILOSOPHY. 

ties of the compounds must resemble those of the 
elements which detennine them; and their loose 
notions of contrariety never approached the form of 
those ideas of polarity, which, in modern times, regu- 
late many parts of physics and chemistry. 

If this statement should seem to any one to be 
technical or arbitrary, we must refer, for the justi- 
fication of it, to the philosophy of science, of which 
we hope hereafter to treat. But it will appear, even 
from what has been here said, that there are certain 
ideas or forms of mental apprehension, which may 
be applied to facts in such a manner as to bring into 
view fundamental principles of science; while the 
same facts, however arrayed or reasoned about, so 
long as these appropriate ideas are not employed, 
cannot give rise to any exact or substantial know- 
ledge. 

We shall, in the next book, see the influence of 
the appropriate generial ideas, in the formation of 
various sciences. It need only be observed, before 
we proceed, that, in order to do full justice to the 
physical knowledge of the Greek schools of philo- 
sophy, it is not necessary to study their course after 
the time of their founders. Their fortunes, in respect 
of such acquisitions as we are now considering, were 
not progressive. The later chiefs of the schools 
followed the earlier masters ; and though they varied 
much, they added little. The Romans adopted the 
philosophy of their Greek subjects ; but they were 
always, and, indeed, acknowledged themselves to be, 



CAUSE OF ITS FAILURE. 85 

inferior to their teachers. They were as arbitrary 
and loose in their ideas as the Greeks, without pos- 
sessing their invention, acuteness, and spirit of sys- 
tem. In addition to the vagueness which was com- 
bined with the more elevated trains of philosophical 
speculation among the Greeks, the Romans intro- 
duced into their treatises a kind of declamatory 
rhetoric, which arose probably from their forensic 
and political habits, and which still fiirther obscured 
the waning gleams of truth. Yet we may also trace, 
in the Roman philosophers to whom this charge 
mostly applies (Lucretius, Pliny, Seneca), the national 
vigour and ambition. There is ^something Roman 
in the public spirit and anticipait^on of universal 
empire which they display, as citizens of the intellec- 
tual republic. Though they speak sadly or slightingly 
of the achievements of their own generation, they 
betray a more abiding and vivid belief in the dignity 
and destined advance of human knowledge as a whole, 
than is obvious among the Greeks. 

We must, however, turn back, in order to describe 
steps of more definite value to the progress of science 
than those which we have hitherto noticed. 



•m^-: 



BOOK II. 



HISTORY 



OP THB 



PHYSICAL SCIENCES 



IN 



ANCIENT GREECE. 



Napdr}KQifKripfOTOV Sk 0rfp&p,ai irvpo^ 
Ilrfyfjv Kkoiralavi r) hiZd(TKaXo(; re^xyv^ 
HdaT}^ PpoTol^ Treijyfjve koX p,€ya<; iropo^. 

Prom. Vinct. 109. 

I brought to earth the spark of heavenly fire, 
Concealed at first, and small, but spreading soon 
Among the sons of men, and burning on. 
Teacher of art and use, and fount of power. 



BOOK 11. 



HISTORY OF PHYSICAL SCIENCES IN ANCIENT 

GREECE. 



INTRODUCTION. 

In order to the acquisition of any such exact and 
real knowledge of nature as that which we properly 
call physical science, it is requisite, as has already 
been said, that men should possess ideas both dis- 
tinct and appropriate, and should apply them to 
ascertained facts. They are thus led to propositions 
of a general character, which are obtained by induc- 
tion, as will elsewhere be more fully explained. We 
proceed now to trace the formation of sciences 
among the Greeks by such processes. The pro- 
vinces of knowledge which thus demand our atten- 
tion are, Astronomy, Mechanics and Hydrostatics, 
Optics and Harmonics ; of which I must relate, first, 
the earliest stages, and next, the subsequent 
progress. 

Of these portions of human knowledge, astronomy 
is, beyond doubt or comparison, much the most 
ancient and the most remarkable ; and probably 
existed, in somewhat of a scientific form, in Chaldea 
and Egypt, and other countries, before the period of 



90 PHYSICAL SCIENCES IN ANCIENT GREECE. 

the intellectual activity of the Greeks. But I will 
give a brief account of some of the other sciences 
before I proceed to astronomy, for two reasons ; first, 
because the origin of astronomy is lost in the obscu- 
rity of a remote antiquity ; and therefore we cannot 
exemplify the conditions of the first rise of science 
so well in that subject as we can in others which 
assumed their scientific form at known periods ; and 
next, in order that I may not have to interrupt, after 
I have once begun it, the history of the only pro- 
gressive science which the ancient world produced. 



91 



CHAPTER I. 

Earliest Stages op Mechanics and Hydro- 
statics. 



Sect 1. — Mechanics. 

Astronomy is a science so ancient that we can 
hardly ascend to a period when it did not exist ; 
Mechanics, on the other hand, is a science which 
did not begin to be till after the time of Aristotle ; 
for Archimedes must be looked upon as the author 
of the first sound knowledge on this subject. What 
is still more curious, and shows remarkably how 
little the continued progress of science follows 
inevitably from the nature of man, this department 
of knowledge, after the right road had been feirly 
entered upon, remained absolutely stationary for 
nearly two thousand years ; no single step was made, 
in addition to the propositions established by Archi- 
medes, till the time of Gralileo and Stevinus. This 
extraordinary halt will be a subject of attention 
hereafter ; at present we must consider the original 
advance. 

The great step made by Archimedes in mechanics 
was the establishing, upon true grounds, the general 
proposition concerning a straight lever, loaded with 



92 PHYSICAL SCIENCES IN ANCIENT GREECE. 

two heavy bodies, and resting upon a fulcrum. The 
proposition is, that two bodies so circumstanced will 
balance each other, when the distance of the smaller 
body from the fiilcrum is greater than the distance 
of the other, in exactly the same proportion in which 
the weight of the body is less. 

This proposition is proved by Archimedes in a 
work which is still extant, and the proof holds its 
place in our treatises to this day, as the simplest 
which can be given. The demonstration is made to 
rest on assumptions which amount in effect to such 
definitions and axioms as these, that those bodies 
are of equal weight which balance each other at 
equal arms of a straight lever, and that in every 
heavy body there is a definite point called a centre of 
gravity^ in which point we may suppose the weight 
of the body collected- 

The real principle, which is the foundation of the 
validity of this reasoning, and which is the condition 
of all experimental knowledge on the subject, is 
this ; — ^that when two equal weights are supported 
on a lever, they act on the fulcrum of the lever with 
the same effect as if they were both together sup- 
ported immediately at that point. Or more gene- 
rally, we may state the principle to be this ; — ^that 
the pressure by which a heavy body is supported con- 
tinues the same, however we alter the form or posi- 
tion of the body, so long as the magnitude and 
material continue the same. 

The experimental truth of this principle is a 



MECHANICS AND HYDROSTATICS. 93 

matter of obvious and universal experience. The 
weight of a basket of stones is not altered by 
shaking the stones into new positions. We cannot 
make the direct burden of a stone less by altering 
its position in our hands ; and if we try the effect 
on a balance or a machine of any kind, we shall see 
still more clearly and exactly that the altered posi- 
tion of one weight, or the altered arrangement of 
several, produces no change in their effect, so long 
as their point of support remains unchanged. 

This general fact is obvious, when we possess in 
our minds the ideas which are requisite to appre- 
hend it clearly. When we are so prepared, the 
truth appears to be manifest,, independent of expe- 
rience, and is seen to be a rule to which experience 
must conform. What then is the leading idea 
which thus enables us to reason effectively upon me- 
chanical subjects? By attention to the course of 
such reasonings, we perceive that it is the idea of 
pressure ; pressure being conceived as a measurable 
effect of heavy bodies at rest, distinguishable from 
all other effects, such as motion, change of figure, 
and the like. It is not here necessary to attempt 
to trace the history of this idea in our minds ; but 
it is certain that such an idea may be distinctly 
formed, and that upon it the whole science of sta- 
tics may be built. Pressure, load, weight, are names 
by which this idea is denoted when the effect is 
directly downwards; but we may have pressure 
without motion, or dead pull, - in other cases, as at 



94 PHYSICAL SCIENCES IN ANCIENT GREECE. 

the critical instant when two nicely-matched 
wrestlers are balanced by the exertion of the utmost 
strength of each. 

Pressure in any direction may thus exist without 
any motion whatever. But the causes which pro- 
duce such pressure are capable of producing motion, 
and are generally seen producing motion, as in the 
above instance of the wrestlers, or in a pair of scales 
employed in weighing, and thus men come to con- 
sider pressure as the exception, and motion as the 
rule; or perhaps they imagine to thefliselves the 
motion which might or would take place; for in- 
stance, the motion which the arms of a lever would 
have if they did move. They turn away from the 
case teally before them, which is that of bodies at 
rest, and balancing each other, and pass to another 
case, which is arbitrarily assumed to represent the 
first. Now this arbitrary and capricious evasion 
we contrast with the distinct and proper idea of 
pressure, by means of which the true principles of 
this subject can be apprehended. 

We have already seen that Aristotle was in the 
numberof those who thus evaded the difficulties of 
the problem of the lever, and consequently lost the 
reward of success. He failed, as has before been 
stated, in consequence of his seeking his principles 
in motions, either vague and loose, as the distinction 
of natural and unnatural motions, or else inappro- 
priate, as the circle which the weight ^w^^ describe, 
the velocity which it would have if it moved ; cir- 



MECHANICS AND HYDROSTATICS. 95 

cumstances which are not part of the fact under 
consideration. The influence of such modes of spe- 
culation was the main hinderance to the prosecution 
of the true Archimedean form of the science. 



Sect 2. — Hydrostatics. 

Archimedes not only laid the foundations of the 
statics of solid bodies, but also solved the principal 
problem of hyd/rostaiics^ or the statics of fluids ; 
namely, the conditions of the floating of bodies. 
This is the more remarkable, since not only did the 
principles which Ardiimedes established on this sub- 
ject remain unptirdued till the revival of science in 
modem tim^s, but, when they were again put for- 
ward, the main proposition was so far from obvious 
that it was termed, and is to this day called, the hy- 
drostatic paradox. The true doctrine of hydrostatics, 
however, assuming the idea of pressure, which it in- 
volves in common with statics, requires also a dis- 
tinct idea of a fluid, as a body whose parts are per- 
fectly moveable among each other by the slightest 
partial pressure, and m which all pressure exerted 
on one part is transferred to all other parts. From 
this idea of fluidity, necessarily follows that multi- 
plication of pressure which constitutes the hydro- 
static paradox ; and the notion being seen to be 
verified in nature, the consequences were also 
realised as facts. This notion of fluidity is expressed 
in the postulate which stands at the head of Archi- 



96 PHYSICAL SCIENCES IN ANCIENT GREECE. 

medes's " Treatise on Floating Bodies." And from 
this principle are deduced the solutions, not only of 
the simple problems of the science, but of some of 
considerable complexity. 

The difficulty of holding fast this idea of fluidity, 
so as to trace its consequences with infallible 
strictness of demonstration, may be judged of from 
the circumstance that, even at the present day, 
men of great talents, not unfamiliar with the sub- 
ject, sometimes admit into their reasonings an over- 
sight or fallacy with regard to this very point. The 
importance of the idea when clearly apprehended 
and securely held, may be judged of from this, that 
the whole science of hydrostatics in its most modem 
form is only the developement of the idea. And 
what kind of attempts at science would be made by 
persons destitute of this idea, we may see in the 
speculations of Aristotle concerning light and heavy 
bodies, which we have already quoted ; where, by 
considering light and heavy as opposite qualities, 
residing in things themselves, and by an inability to 
apprehend the effect of surrounding fluids in sup- 
porting bodies, the subject was made a mass of false 
or frivolous assertions, which the utmost ingenuity 
could not reconcile with facts, and still less deduce 
from them any additional truths. 

In the case of statics and hydrostatics, the most 
important condition of their advance was undoubt- 
edly the distinct apprehension of these two appropriate 
ideasy statical pressure^ and ht/drostatical pressure. For 



MECHANICS AND HYDROSTATICS. 97 

the ideas being once clearly possessed, the experi- 
mental laws which they served to express (that the 
whole pressure of a body downwards was always 
the same ; and that water, and the like, were fluids 
according to the idea of fluidity) were so obvious, 
that there was no doubt nor difficulty about them. 
These two ideas lie at the root of all mechanical 
science ; and the Arm possession of them is, to this 
day, the first requisite for a student of the subject. 
After being clearly awakened in the mind of Ar* 
chimedes, these ideas slept for many centuries, 
till they were again called up in Galileo, and more 
remarkably in Stevinus. This time, they were not 
destined again to slumber ; and the results of their 
activity have been the formation of two sciences, 
which are as certain and severe in their demonstra- 
tions as geometry itself, and as copious and interest- 
ing in their conclusions ; but which, besides this 
recommendation, possess one of a different order ;— * 
that they exhibit the exact impress of the laws of the 
physical world ; and unfold a portion of the rules 
according to which the phenomena of nature take 
place, and must take place, till nature herself shall 
alter. 



VOL. I. H 



98 PHYSICAL SCIENCES IN ANCIENT GREECE. 



CHAPTER ir. 

Earliest Stages of Optics. 

The progress made by the aBcients in Optics was 
nearly proportional to that which they made in 
statics. As they discovered the true grounds of the 
doctrine of equilibrium, without obtaining any sound 
principles concerning motion, bo they discovered the 
law of the reflection of light, but had none but the 
most indistinct notiotis concerning refraction. 

The extent of the principles which they really 
possessed is easily stated. They knew that vision is 
performed by rays which proceed in straight lines, 
and that these rays are reflected by certain sur&ces 
(mirrors) in such manner that the angles which they 
make with the surface on each side are equal. They 
drew various conclusions from these premises by the 
aid of geometry ; as, for instance, the convergence 
of rays which fell on a coneave specHlum. 

It may be observed that the idea which is here 
introduced, is that of visual rays, or lines along which 
vision is produced and light carried. This idea once 
clearly apprehended, it was not difficult to show that 
these lines are straight Hues, both in the case of 
light and of sight. In the beginning of Euclid's 
" Treatise on .Optics," some of the arguments are 
mentioned by which this was established. We are 



OPTICS. 99 

told in the Proem, " In explaining what concerns 
the sight, he adduced certain arguments from which 
he inferred that all light is carried in straight lines* 
The greatest proof of this is shadows, and the bright 
spots which are produced by light coming through 
windows and cracks, and which could not be, except 
the rays of the sun were carried in straight lines. 
So in fires, the shadows are greater than the bodies 
if the fire be small, but less than the bodies if the 
fire be greater." A clear comprehension of the 
principle would lead to the perception of innume- 
rable proofe df its truth on every side. 

The law of equality of angles of incidence and 
reflection was not quite so easy to verify ; but the 
exact resemblance of the object and jt3 image in a 
plane mirror, (as the sur&ce of still ' water, for in- 
stance,) which is a consequence of this law, would 
affi>rd convincing evidence of its truth in that case, 
and would be confirmed by the examuii|.tion of other 
cases. 

With these true principles was mixed much error 
and indistinctness, even in the best writers. Euclid, 
$asA the Platonists, maintained that vision is exer- 
cised by rays proceeding from the eye, not to it ; so 
that when we see objects, we learn their form as a 
bUnd man would do, by feeling it out with his staff 
This mistake, however, though Montucla speaks 
severely of it, was neither very discreditable nor very 
iiyurious ; for the mathematical conclusions on each 
supposition are necessarily the same. Another curious 

H 2 



100 PHYSICAL SCIENCES IN ANCIENT GREECE. 

m 

assumption is, that these visual rays are not close 
together, but separated by intervals, like the fingers 
when the hand is spread. The motive for this 
invention was the wish to account for the fact, that 
in looking for a small object, as a needle, we often 
cannot see it when it is under our nose ; which it 
was conceived would be impossible if the visual rays 
reached to all points of the surface before us. 

These errors would not have prevented the pro- 
gress of the science. But the Aristotelian physics, 
as usual, contained speculations more essentially 
faulty. Aristotle's views led him to try to describe 
the kind of causation by which vision is produced, 
instead of the laws by which it is exercised ; and the 
attempt consisted, as in other subjects, of indistinct 
principles, and ill-combined facts. According to him, 
vision must be produced by a medium, — ^by something 
between the object and the eye, — for if we press the ob-^ 
ject on the eye, we do not see it ; this medium is light, 
or " the transparent in action ;" darkness occurs when 
the transparency is potential not actual ; colour is not 
the absolute visible, but something which is on the 
absolute visible; colour has the power of setting 
the transparent in action; it is not, however, all 
colours that are seen by means of light, but only the 
proper colour of each object ; for some things, as the 
heads, and scales, and eyes of fish, are seen in the 
dark ; but then they are not seen with their proper 
colour '- 

^ De Anim. ii..6. 



OPTICS. 101 

In all this there is no steady adherence either to 
one notion, or to one class of fects. The distinction 
of power and act is introduced to modify the idea 
of transparency, according to the formula of the 
school; then colour is made to be something un- 
known in addition to visibility ; and the distinction 
of proper and improper colours is assumed, as suf- 
ficient to account for a phenomenon. Such classi- 
fications have in them nothing of which the mind 
can take steady hold ; nor is it difficult to see that 
they do not come under those conditions of successful 
physical speculation, which we have laid down. 



102 PHYSICAL SCIENCES IN ANCIENT GREECE. 



CHAPTER III. 

Earliest Stages of Harmonics. 

Among the ancients, the science of Music was an 
application of arithmetic, as optics and mechsmics 
were of geometry. The story which is told con- 
cerning the origin of their arithmetical music, is the 
following, as it stands in the Arithmetical Treatise of 
Nicomachus. 

Pythagoras, walking one day, meditating on the 
means of measuring musical notes, happened to pass 
near a blacksmith's shop, and had his attention 
arrested by hearing the hammers, as they struck the 
anvil, produce sounds which had a musical relation 
to each other. On listening further, he found that 
the intervals were a fourth, a fifth, and an octave ; 
and on wefghing the hammers, it appeared that the 
one which gave the octave was one-half the heaviest, 
the one which gave the fifth was two-thirds, and the 
one which gave the fourth was three-quarters. He 
returned home, reflected upon this phenomenon, and 
finally discovered, that if he stretched musical strings 
of equal length, by weights which have the same 
proportion as those above described, they also pro- 
duced the intervals above mentioned. This observa- 
tion gave an arithmetical measure of the principal 



HARMONICS. 103 

musical intervals, and made music an arithmetical 
subject of speculation. 

This story, if not entirely a philosophical fable, 
is undoubtedly inaccurate ; for the musical intervals 
thus spoken of, would not be produced by striking 
with hammers of the weights there stated. But the 
experiment of the strings is perfectly correct, and is 
to this day the groundwork of the theory of muoical 
concords and discords. 

It may at first appear that the truth, or even the 
possibility of this history, by referring the discovery 
to accident, disproves our doctrine, that this, like all 
other fundamental discoveries, required a distinct 
and well-pondered idea as its condition. In this, 
however, as in all cases of supposed aiseidental dis* 
coveries in science, it will be found, that it was 
exactly the possession of such an idea which made 
the .iideut poBsibla. 

Pytibagoras, assuming the truth of the tamlition, 
must have had an exact iumI ready apprehension 
of those relaidons of musical sounds* which are 
called lespectively an octave, a fifth, and a fourtii. 
If he had not been able to conceive distinctly this 
relation* the sounds of the anvil would have struck 
his ears to no more purpose than they did those of 
the smiths themselves. He must have had, too, a 
ready familiarity with numerical ratios ; and, more- 
over, (that in which, probably, his superiority most 
consisted,) a disposition to connect one notion with 
the other — the musical relation with the arithmetical, 



1 04 PHYSICAL SCIENCES IN ANCIENT GREECE. 

if it were found possible. When the connexion was 
once suggested, it was easy to devise experiments by 
which it might be confirmed. 

"The philosophers of the Pythagojrean school*, 
and in particular, Lasus of Hermione, and Hippasus 
of Metapontum, made many such experiments upon 
strings ; varying both their lengths and the weights 
which stretched them ; and also upon vessels filled 
with water, in a greater or less degree." And thus 
was established that connexion of the idea with the 
fact, which this science, like all others, requires. 



I shall quit the Physical Sciences of Ancient 
Greece, with the above brief statement of the dis- 
covery of the fundamental principles which they 
involved ; not only because such initial steps must 
always be the most important in the progress of 
science, but because, in reality, the Greeks made no ad- 
vances beyond these. There took place among them 
no additional inductive processes, by which new facts 
were brought under the dominion of principles, or 
by which principles were presented in a more com- 
prehensive shape than before. Their advance termi- 
nated in a single stride. Archimedes had stirred 
the intellectual world, but had not put it in pro- 
gressive motion : the science of mechanics stopped 

* Moutucla, iii. 10. 



HARMONICS. 105 

where he left it. And though, in some subjects, as 
in Harmonics, much was written, the works thus 
produced consisted of deductions from the fundar 
mental principles, by means of arithmetical calcular 
tions ; occasionally modified, indeed, by reference to 
the pleasures which music, as an art, affords, but 
not enriched by any new scientific truths. 



BOOK III. 



HISTORY 



OF 



GREEK ASTRONOMY. 



ToBe Be firjBei^ irork (^o^TfOy r&v 'JBXXiyvwv, C09 oi xpV 
irepi ra Oeia irork nrparffiareveaOai Ovrjroif^ Xvra^' irav Be 
TOVTOV Bcavoffdrjvai rovvavrlovy o>9 ovre a^pov €<m wore 
TO Oelovy ovre a/yvoei irov rfjv avdptoTrlvrjv <l>v<riv' dXX' olBev 
0TI9 BvBda-KovTO^ airroVf ^waKoXovOijaei xal fiadi^aerai ra 
BiZdaicofieva, 

Plato, Epinomis^ p. 988. 

Nor should any Greek have any micigiving of this kind ; that it is not 
fitting to inquire narrowly into the operations of superior Powers, such 
as those by which the motions of the heavenly bodies are produced : but, 
on the contrary, men should consider that the Divine Powers never act 
without purpose, and that they know the nature of man : they know 
that by their guidance and aid, man may follow and comprehend the 
lessons which are vouchsafed him on such subjects. 



INTRODUCTION. 



The earliest and fundamental conceptions of men 
respecting the objects with which Astronomy is con- 
cerned, are formed by &miliar processes of thought, 
without appearing to have in them anything tech* 
nical or scientific. Days, years, months, the sky, 
the constellations, are notions which the most un- 
cultured and incurious minds possess. Yet these 
are elements of the science of astronomy. The 
reasons why, in this case alone, of all the provinces 
of human knowledge, men were able, at an early 
and unenlightened period, to construct a science out 
of the obvious facts of observation, with the help 
of the common furniture of their minds, will be 
more apparent in the course of the philosophy of 
science; but I may here barely mention two of 
these reasons ; they are, first, that the familiar act of 
thought, exercised for the common purposes of life, 
by which we give to an assemblage of our impres- 
sions such a unity as is implied in the above no- 
tiojis and terms, a month, a year, the sky, and the 
like, is, in reality, an indtictive acU and shares the 
nature of the processes by which all sciences are 
formed ; and, in the next place, that the ideas ap- 
propriate to the induction in this case, are those 



110 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

which, even in the least cultivated minds, are very- 
clear and definite ; namely, the ideas of space and 
figure, time and number, motion and recurrence. 
Hence, from their first origin, the modifications of 
those ideas assume a scientific form. 

W© must now trace in detail the peculiar course 
which, in consequence of these causes, the know- 
ledge of man respecting the heavenly bodies took, 
from the earliest period of his history. 



Ill 



CHAPTER I. 



Earliest Stages of Astronomy. 



Sect. 1 . — Formation of the Notion of a Year. 

The notion of a Dat/ is early and obviously im- 
pressed upon man in almost any condition in which 
we can imagine him. The recurrence of light and 
darkness, of comparative warmth and cold, of noise 
and silence, of the activity and repose of animals ; — 
the rising, mounting, descending, and setting of the 
sun ; — ^the varying colours of the clouds, generally, 
notwithstanding their variety, marked by a daily 
progression of appearances ; — ^the calls of the desire 
of food and of sleep in himself, either exactly ad- 
justed to the period of this change, or at least readily 
capable of being accommodated to it; — ^these cir- 
cumstances, recurring at intervals, equal, so far as 
man's obvious judgment of the passage of time can 
decide ; and these intervals so short that the repe- 
tition is noticed with no eflfort of attention or 
memory; — ^this assemblage of suggestions makes 
the notion of a day necessarily occur to man, if we 



112 THE GREEK ASTRONOMV. 

suppose him to have the conception of time, and of 
recurrence. He naturally marks by a term such a 
portion of time, and such a cycle of recurrence ; he 
calls each portion of time, in which * this series of 
appearances and occurrences come round, a day: 
and such a group of particulars are considered as 
appearing or happening in the same day. 

A year is a notion formed in the same manner ; 
implying in the same way the notion of recurring facts; 
and also the faculty of atranging facts in time, and of 
appreciating thdr i*ecurrence. But the notion of a 
year, though undoulstedly very obvious, is, on many 
accounts, leas fio^than that of a day. The repetition 
of simiJar circumstaaees, at equal intervals, is less 
manifest in. this €ase, and the intervals being much 
kmgfia*,. some exertion of .memory becomes requisite 
in order that the recjurrence may be perceived. A 
cbild mi^t easily be persuaded that successive years 
were of unequal length; or, if the summer were 
cold, and the spring and autumn warm, might be 
made to believe, if all who spoke in its hearing 
agreed to supp(Hi; the delusion, that one year was 
two. It would be impossible to practise such a 
deception with regard to the day, without the use of 
some artifice beyond mere words. 

Still, the recurrence of the appearances which 
suggest the notion of a year is so obvious, that we 
can hardly conceive man without it. But though, 
in all climes and times, there would be a recurrence, 
and at the same interval in all, the recurring appear- 



EARLIEST STAGES OF ASTRONOMY. 113 

ances would be extremely different in diflferent 
countries; and the contrasts and resemblances of 
the seasons would be widely varied. In some places 
the winter utterly alters the face of the country, 
converting grassy hills, deep leafy woods of various 
hues of green, and running waters, into snowy and 
icy wastes, and bare snow-laden branches ; while in 
others, the field retains its herbage, and the tree its 
leaves, all the year ; and the rains and the sunshine 
alone, or various agricultural employments quite 
different from ours, mark the passing seasons. Yet 
in all parts of the world the yearly cycle of changes 
has been singled out from all others, and designated 
by a peculiar name. The inhabitant of the equa- 
torial regions has the sun vertically over him at the 
end of every period of six months, and similar trains 
of celestial phenomena fill up each of these intervals, 
yet we do not find years of six months among such 
nations. The Arabs alone ^ who practise neither 
agriculture nor navigation, have a year depending 
upon the moon only ; and borrow the word from other 
languages, when they speak of the solar year. 

In general nations have marked this portion of time 
by some word which has a reference to the returning 
circle of seasons and employments. Thus the Latin 
annus signified a ring, as we see in the derivative 
anntdus : the Greek term iyuLVTb<; implies something 
which returns into itself: and the word as it exists 

' Ideler, Berl. Trans. 18ia p. 51. 
VOL. I. I 



114 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

in Teutonic languages, of which our word year is an 
example, is said to have its origin in the word yr% 
which means a ring in Swedish, and is perhaps con- 
nected with the Latin gyms. 

Sect. 2. — Fiwaikm of the Civil Year. 

The year, considered as a recurring cycle of seasons 
and of general appearances, must attract the notice 
of man as soon as his attention and memory suffice 
to bind together the parts of a succession of the 
length of several years. But to make the same term 
imply a certain fixed number of days, we must know 
how many days the cycle of the seasons occupies ; a 
knowledge which requires iacultles and artifices 
beyond what we have already mentioned* For in* 
stance^ men cannot reckon as far as any number at 
all approaching the number of days in the year, 
without possessing a system of numeral terms, and 
methods of practical nuMeration on which such a 
system of terms is always founded ^ The South 
American Indians, the Koussa Caffires and Hotten<- 
tots, and the natives of New Holland, all of whom 
are said to be unable to reckon further thaa the 
fingers of their hands and feetS cannot include, in 
their notion of a year, the fact of its consisting of 
365 days, as we do. This feet is not likely to be 



* Arithm. in Encyc. Metrop. (by Mr. Peacock,) Art. 8. 
' Ibid. Art. 32. 



ITS EARLIEST STAGES. 115 

known to any nation except those which have ad- 
vanced f&T beyond that which may be considered as 
the earliest scientific process which we can trace in 
the theoretical history of the hnman race, the forma- 
tion of a method of designating the successive num- 
bers to an indefinite extent, by means of names, 
framed according to the decimal, quinary, or vigenary 
scale. 

But even if we suppose men to have the habit of 
recording the passage of each day, and of counting 
the score thus recorded, it would be by no means 
easy for them to determine the exact number of 
days in which the cycle of the seasons recurs ; for 
the indefiniteness of the appearances which mark the 
same season of the year, and the changes to which 
they are subject as the seasons are early or late^ 
would leave much uncertainty respecting the dura- 
tion of the year^ They would not obtain any accu- 
racy on this head, till they had attended for a 
considerable time to the motions and places of the 
sun ; circumstances which require more precision of 
notice than the general facts of the degrees of heat 
and light. The motions of the sun, the succession 
of the places of his rising and setting at different 
times of the year, the greatest heights which he 
reaches, the proportion of the length of day and 
night, would all exhibit several cycles. The re- 
turning back of the sun, when he had reached his 
greatest distance to the south or to the north, as 
shown either by his rising or by his height at noon, 

I 2 



116 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

would perhaps be the most observable of such cir- 
cumstances. Accordingly the rpoiraX ^eXioco^ the 
turnings of the sun, are used repeatedly by Hesiod 
as a mark from which he reckons the seasons of 
various employments. " Fifty days," he says, " after 
the turning of the sun, is a seasonable time for be- 
ginning a voyage*-" 

The phenomena would be different in different 
climates, but the recurrence would be common to 
all. Any one of these kinds of phenomena^ noted 
with moderate care for a year, would show what was 
the number of days of which a year consisted ; and 
if several years were included in the interval through 
which the scrutiny extended, the knowledge of the 
length of the year so acquired would be proportion- 
ally more exact. 

Besides those notices of the sun. which offered 
exact indications of the seasons, other more indefinite 
natural occurrences were used ; as the arrival of the 
swallow (xeXiBtoy) and the kite (iktiv.) The birds, 
in Aristophanes's play of that name, mention, as one 
of their offices, to mark the seasons ; Hesiod simi- 
larly notices the cry of the crane as an indication of 
the departure of winter *• 

Among the Greeks the seasons were at first only 
summer and winter (Oepo^ and 'xeifjL(av)y the latter 

Ef rcXof fXBovros 0€p€os. 

Op. et Dies, 661. 
^ Ideier, i. 240. 



ITS EARLIEST STAGES. 117 

including all the rainy and cold portion of the year. 
The winter was then subdivided into the xet/ACDv and 
ea/o, and the summer, less definitely, into 0€po<: and 
oTTcopa. Tacitus says that the Germans knew neither 
the blessings nor the name of autumn, " Autumni 
perinde nomen ac bona ignorantur.*' Yet harvesU 
herbsU is certainly an old German word". 

In the same period in which the sun goes through 
his cycle of positions, the stars also go through a 
cycle of appearances belonging to them ; and these 
perhaps were employed at as early a period as the 
sun in determining the exact length of the year. 
Many of the groups of fixed stars are readily recog- 
nised, as exhibiting always the same configuration ; 
and particular bright stars are singled out as objects 
of attention. These are observed, at particular 
seasons, to appear in the west after sunset ; but it is 
noted that when they do this, they are found nearer 
and nearer to the sun every successive evening, and 
at last disappear in his light. It is observed also, 
that at a certain interval after this, they rise visibly 
before the dawn of day renders the stars invisible ; 
and after they are seen to do this, they rise every 
day at a longer interval before the sun. The risings 
and settings of the stars under these circumstances, 
or under others which are easily recognised, were, in 
countries where the sky is usually clear, employed 
at an early period, to mark the seasons of the year. 

• Ideler, i. 243. 



118 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

Eschylus ' makes Prometheus mention this among 
the benefits of which he, the teacher of arts to the 
earliest race of men, was the communicator. 

Thus, for instance, the rising' of the Pleiades in 
the evening was a mark of the approach of winter* 
The rising of the waters of the Nile in Egypt coin- 
cided with the heliacal rising of Sirius, which the 
Egyptians called Sothis. Even without any arti- 
ficial measure of time or position, it was not diffi- 
cult to carry observations of this kind to such a 
degree of accuracy as to learn from them the num- 
ber of days which compose the year; and to 
fix the precise season from the appearance of the 
stars. 

A knowledge concerning the stars appears toiiave 



^ OvK rjp yap avrois ovre xfiftaros TtKfiap, 
OvT avOtfuofktvs fpos, ovdc Kopwmov 
Otptovs ptfftuov aXX' arep yvtop,rjs ro ira» 
"EirpcLaraoVt €0T€ Ihj axfnv aparoKas cy<o 
Aarponv tbtt^d, ras re tvfrKpvnvi dvcrcif. 

" Ideler (Chronol. i. 242) says that this rising of the Pleiades 
took place at a time of the year which corresponds to our 11th 
May, and the setting to the 20th October, but this does not 
agree with the forty days of their being " concealed," which, 
from the context, must mean, I conceiye, the interval between 
their setting and rising. Pliny, however, says, " Vergiliarum 
exortu cestas incipit, occasu hiems; semeslri spatio intra se 
messes vindemiasque et omnium maturitatem complexa. (H. N. 
xviii. 69.) 

The autumn of the Greeks, dn-oipo, was earlier than our 
autumn, for Homer calls Sirius amfp ^<apu/og, which rose at the 
end of July. 



ITS EABUEST STAGES. 119 

been first cultivated with the last-mentioned view, 
and makes its first appearance in literature with this 
for its object. Thus Hesiod directs the husbandman 
when to reap by the rising, and when to plough by 
the setting of the Pleiades'. In like manner 
Sirius'^ Arcturus*\ the Hyades and Orion**, are 
noticed. 

By such means it was determined that the year 
consisted, at least, nearly, of 365 days. The Egyp- 
tians, as we learn from Herodotus*', claimed the 
honour of this discovery. The {)rie8ts informed 

* nXi/iadttv ArXaycvrwv €7riTtKKofi€vatov» 
Apxto-ff ofiriTov* apoToio bty dvo-ofitvaav. 
'Ai di; roc wieras re koi rffAora T€ir(r€paKOpra 
Kc/Kpvf^oroi, avTis de ireptirXo/ieyov cviovrov 

^(UVOPTCU, 

Op. et Dies, 1. 381. 
'' 1. 413. 

^^ EOr' ay ^i^Kovra ftcra rponat tftKtoio 

Xciftcpi, cicrcXccn; Zfvr ijfiara, di; pa tot atmfp 
ApKTOvpos^ vpoXmmv Upov poov Ojccayoio 
Tlpovrw irofjuilKuvoif fmreXXfrof aKpoKV€<lkuos, 

Op. et Di. 562. 

Evr* ov d'npicay km 2(ipios ts pxtrov f\$if 
Ovpavov, ApKTOvpov d'co'td;; pododcucrvXor ^or. 

607. 

*' avTop €irr)v Hrf 

XJiKffiadts 'Yader re to re a6€vos Qpuovos 
Avvwriv, 

612. 

These methods were employed to a late period, hecause the 
Greek months, being lunar, did not correspond to the seasons. 
Tables of such motions were called n-apaTnfyfMira.-— Ideler, Hist. 
Untersuchungen, p. 209. 



18 



ii. 4. 



120 THE €»tEEK ASTRONOMY. 

him, he says, " that the Egyptians were the fiw*^ 
men who discovered the year, dividing it into twelve: 
equal parts ; and this they asserted that they dis-- 
covered from the stars." Each of these parts or 
months consisted of 30 days, and they added 5 days 
more at the end of the year, " and thus the circle 
of the seasons comes round." It seems, also, that 
the Jews, at an early period, had a similar reckoning 
of time, for the deluge which continued 150 days 
(Gen. vii. 24,) is stated to have lasted from the 17th 
day of the second month (Gren. vii. 11) to the I7th 
day of the seventh month (Gen. viii. 4,) that is, 6 
months of 30 days. 

A year thus settled as a period of a certain num- 
ber of days is called a cit)U year. It is one of the 
earliest discoverable institutions of states possessing 
any germ of civilization ; and one of the earliest 
portions of human systematic knowledge is the dis- 
covery of the length of the civil year, so that it 
should agree with the natural year, or year of the 
seasons. 

Sect 3. — Correction of the CivU Year. (Julian 

Calendar.) 

In reality, by such a mode of reckoning as we 
have described, the circle of the seasons would not 
come round exactly. The real length of the year is 
very nearly 365 days and a quarter. If a year of 
365 days were used, in four years the year would 



ITS EAISLIEST STAGES. 121 

begin a day too socm, when considered with refer- 
ence to the sun and stars ; and in 60 years it would 
begin 16 days too soon, a quantity perceptible to 
the loosest degree of attention. The civil year 
would be found not to c<Hncide with the year of the 
seasons; the beginning of the former wonld take 
place at different periods of the latter; it would 
Wfrnder into various seasons, instead of remaining 
fixed to the same season ; the term year, and any 
number of years, would become ambiguous; some 
correction, at least some comparison, would be 
requisite. 

We do not know by whom the insufficiency of 
the year of 365 days was first discovered^* ; we find 
this knowledge diffiised among all civilized nations, 
and various artifices used in making the correction. 
The method which we employ, and which consists 
in reckoning an additional day at the end of Fe- 
bruary every fourth or leap year, is an example of the 
principle of intercfdoMany by which the correction 
was most commonly made. Methods of intercalar 
tion for the same purpose were found to exist in the 
new world. The Mexicans added 13 days at the 
end of every 52 years. The method of the Greeks 
was more complex ; (by means of the octaeteris or 
cycle of 8 years ;) but it had the additional object 
of accommodating itself to the motions of the 

** Syncellus (Chronographia, p. 123,) says, that according to 
the legend, it was King Aseth who first added the 5 additional 
dajs to 360, for the year, in the eighteenth century B. c. 



122 THE GREEK A8TB0N0HY. 

moon, and therefore niust be treated of hereafter. 
The Egyptians, on the other hand, knowingly per-e 
mitted their civil year to wander, at least so far as 
their religious observances were concerned. " They 
do not wish," says Greminus^', ** the same sacrifices 
of the gods to be made perpetually at the same 
time of the year, but that they should go throv^h 
all the seasons, so that the same feast may happen 
in summer and winter, in spring and autumn." The 
period in which any festival would thus pass through 
all the seasons of the year is 1461 years ; for 1460 
years of 365i days are equal to 1461 years of 365 
days. This period of 1461 years is called the Sothic 
period, from Sothis, the name of the dog-star^ by 
which their y£i;^ year was determined ; and for the 
same reason it is called the canictdar period ^^ 

Other nations did not r^rulate their civil year by 
intercalation at short intervals, but rectified it by a 
reform when this became necessary. The Persians 
are said to have added a month of 30 days every 
120 years. The Roman calendar, at first very rude 
in its structure, was reformed by Nimaa, and was 
directed to be kept in order by the perpetual inter- 
position of the augurs. This, however, was, from 
various causes, not properly done ; and the conse- 
quence was, that the reckoning fell into utter dis- 
order, in which state it was found by Julius Csesar, 
when he became dictator. By the advice of So- 

** Uranol. p. 33. 

^* Censorinus de Die Natali, c. 18. 



ITS EARLIESrr STAGES. 123 

sigenes, he adopted the mode of intercalation of 
one day in 4 years, which we still retain ; and in 
order to correct the derangement which had already 
been produced, he added 90 days to a year of the 
usual length, which thus became what was called 
the year of conftmon* The Julian Calendar, thus 
reformed, came into use, January 1, b. c. 46. 

Sect. 4. — Attempts ai the Fia^ation of the Month. 

The circle of changes through which the moon passes 
in about thirty days, is marked, in the earliest stages 
of language, by a word which implies the space of 
time which one such circle occupies; just as the 
circle of changes of the seasons is designated by the 
word year. The lunar changes are, indeed, more 
obvious to the sense, and strike a more careless per- 
son, than the annual ; the moon, when the sun is 
absent, is almost the sole natural object which attracts 
our notice ; and we look at her with a far more tran- 
quil and agreeable attention than we bestow on any 
other celestial object. Her changes of form and place 
are definite and striking to all eyes ; they are unin- 
terrupted, and the duration of their cycle is so short 
as to require no effort of memory to embrace it. 
Hence it appears to be more easy, and in earlier 
stages of civilization more common, to count time 
by moons than by years. 

The words by which this period of time is desig- 
nated in various languages, seem to refer us to the 



124 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

early history of language. Our word month is con- 
nected with the word moon, and a similar connexion 
is noticeable in the other branches of the Teutonic. 
The Greek word /^v in like manner is related to /xiyvi/, 
which, though not the common word for the moon, 
is found in Homer with that signification. The 
Latin word mensis is probably connected with the 
same group ''• 

The month is not any exact number of days, being 
more than 29 and less than 80. The latter number 
WBB first tried, for men more readily select nmnbers 
possessing some distinction of regularity. It existed 
for a long period in many countries. A very few 
months of 30 days, however, would suffice to derange 
the agreiement between the days of the month and 
the moon's appearance. A little further trial would 
show that months of 29 and 30 days alternately, 
would preserve, for a considerable period, this agree- 
ment. 

The Greeks adopted this calendar, and, in conse- 

*^ Cicero derives this word from the verb to measure; "quia 
mensa spatia conficiunt menses nominantur:" and other etymolo- 
gists, with similar views, comiect the above-mentioned words 
with the Hebrew manah^ to measure, (with which the Arabic 
work alTnanach is connected.) Such a derivation would have 
some analogy with that of annusy &c., noticed above : but if we 
are to attempt to ascend to the earliest condition of language^ 
we must conceive it probable that men would have a name for 
a most conspicuous visible object, the moon, before they would 
have a verb denoting the very abstract and general notion, to 
measure. 



ITS £ARI.I£ST STAGES. 125 

quenc^ considered the days of their month as repre- 
senting the changes of the moon : the last day of 
the month was called eyv ical via, " the old and new," 
as belonging to both the waning and the reappear- 
ing mooni": and their festivals and sacrifices, as 
determined by the calendar, were conceived to be 
necessarily connected with the same periods of the 
cycles of the sun and moon. " The laws and the 
oracles," says Geminus, " which directed that they 
should in sacrifices observe three things, months, 
days, years, were so understood/' With this per- 
suasion, a correct system of intercalation became a 
religious duty. 

The above rule of alternate months of 29 and 30 
days, supposes the length of the months 29 days and 
a hali^ which is not exactly the length of a lunar 
month. Accordingly the months and the moon were 
soon at variance. Aristophanes, in " The Clouds," 
makes the Moon complain of the disorder when 
the calendar was deranged. 

OvK aycLV Ta<; '^/Jbipa^ 
'OuS^v 6p6w, aX\* dvco T€ Koi Kdrto Kvhoiioirav 
^flar aTreCkelv (prjalv dvT'p tou9 0€ov^ kKaarore 
^Hviic ay '^^evaOSxrt heiirvov KamLtotriv oXkoZ^ 
Tri% ioprfj^ fbi) tvxovt€^ Kara Xoyov r&v rip,ep&v. 

Nubes 615—19. 



*^ Aratus says of the moon, in a passage quoted by Geminus, 
p. 33. 

Aif i d*aXXo^ci/ <iyXa irapaKkipov<ra fierama 
Eipiff 6rro<rT€urj iirfvos TrrpircXXcroi ^wf. 



126 THE OREEK ASnUONOMY. 

The Moon by us to jou her greeting sends, 

But bidd us say that she 's an ill-used moon. 

And takes it much amiss that you will still 

Shuffle her days, and turn them topsy turvy; 

So that when gods (who know their feast-days well,) 

By your false -count are sent home supperless. 

They scold and storm at her for your neglect. 

The correction of this inaccuracy, however, was 
not pursued separately, but was combined with 
another object, the securing a correspondence be- 
tween the lunar and solar years, the main purpose of 
all early cycles. 

Sect. 5. — Invention of Lunisalar Years. 

There are 12 complete lunations in a year ; which 
according to the above rule, would make 354 days, 
leaving 12j days of difference between such a lunar 
year and a solar year. It is said, that at an early 
period, this was attempted to be corrected by inter- 
polating a month of 30 days every alternate year ; 
and Herodotus^* relates a conversation of Solon, im- 
plying a still ruder mode of intercalation. This can 
hardly be considered as an advance in the know- 
ledge of the motions of the heavens. 

The first cycle which produced any near corre- 
spondence of the reckoning of the moon and the sun, 
was the Octaeterisj or period of 8 years : 8 years of 

»» B. i. c. 15. 



ITS EARLIEST STAGES. 127 

354 daySy together with 3 months of 30 days each, 
make up 2922 days ; which is exactly the amount of 
8 years of 365 i days each. Hence this period would 
answer its purpose so &r as the above lengths of the 
lunar and solar cycles are exact ; and it might assume 
various forms, according to the manner in which the 
intercalary months were distributed. The customary 
method was to add a thirteenth month at the end of 
the third, fifth, and eighth year of the cycle. This 
period is ascribed to various persons and times ; pro- 
bably different persons proposed different forms of 
it. Dodwell places its introduction in the 59th 
olympiad, or in the 6th century, b. c. : but Ideler 
thinks the astronomical knowledge of the Greeks 
of 'that age was too limited to allow of such a dis- 
covery. 

This cycle, however, was imperfect. The duration 
of 99 lunations is something more than 2922 days ; 
it is more nearly 2923^; hence in 16 years there was 
a deficiency of 3 days, with regard to the motions of 
the moon. This cycle of 16 years {Hecccedecdeteris), 
with 3 interpolated days at the end, was used, it is 
said, to bring the calculation right with regard to 
the moon ; but in this way tlie origin of the year 
was displaced with regard to the sun. After 10 
revolutions of this cycle, or 160 years, the inter- 
polated days would amount to 30, and hence the end 
of the lunar year would be a month in advance of 
the end of the solar. By terminating the lunar year 
at the end of the preceding month, the two years 



128 THE GUBEEK ASHtC^OMY. 

would again be brought into agreciment: and we 
have thus a cycle of 160 years'*. 

This cycle of 160 years, howeyer, was caleulated 
from the cycle of 16 yearsir; and was probably nenner 
used in civil reckoning; which the otfaers^oratleast 
that of 8 years, appear to have been. 

The cycles of 16 and 160 years, were corrections 
of the cycle of 8 years ; and were readily suggested, 
when the leng^ of the solar, and lunar periods be^ 
came known with aoeufacy. But -a much more exact 
cyde, independent of these, was^ djseovered and 
introduced by M^ton", 432 yews b. c. This cycle 
consisted of 19 years, and is so correct iind conver 
nienty that it ia in use among ourselves to this day* 
The time occupied by Id.years^ and by 235 kmatitmsi, 
is very nearly the same; (the former time is less 
than 6940 days by 9^ hourss the latter by 7^ hours.) 
Hence, if the 19 years be divided into 236 months; 
so as to agree with the changes of the moon ; at the 
end of that period the same succession may b^n 
again with great exactness. 

In order that 235 months, of 30 and 29 days> may 
make up 6940 days, we must have 125 of the foimer, 
which were called full mcmths, and 110 of the latter, 
which were termed hoBaw. An artifice was used in 
order to distribute 110 hollow months among 6940 
days. It will be found that there is a hollow month 
for each 63 days nearly. Hence if we reckon 30 



so 



G^minus, Ideler. •' Ideler Hist. Unters. p. 208. 



USSr&atLY ffTAGKB* 129 

^tkys to evei^ iudnth^ but at evety 63d day leap over 
a day in the reckoning; we shall) in the 19 yearg, 
omit 110 days; and this accordingly was done. 
Thus the 3d day of the 3d month, the 6th day of the 
5th mondi) the dth day of the 7th, must be omitted, 
so as to make these months * hollow/ Of the 19 . 
years, sein^Q must consist of 18 months; and it does 
not appear to be known according to what order 
these seven years were selected. Some say they 
were the 3d, 6th, 8th, 11th, 14th, 17th, and 19th; 
others, the 3d, 5th, 8th, 11th, 13th, 16th, and f9th. 
The near coinddence of tfee solar Bikd lunar periods 
in this cycle of 19 years, was undoubtedly a consider- 
able discovery at the time when it was first accom- 
I^shed. It is not easy to trace the way in which such 
a discovery was made at that time ; for we do not 
eve«i know the manner in which men theil recorded 
the agreement or difference between the calendar day 
and the celestial phenomenon whidh ought to cor- 
respond to it. It is most pTobable, that the length 
of the month was obtained with considerable exact- 
ness, by the observation of eclipses, at considerable 
intervals of time from each other ; for eclipses are 
very noticeable phenomena, and must have been 
very soon observed to occur only at new and fall 
moon". 

** Thucyd. vii. 50. *H o-eXi/vi^ ricXcMrcf ^rxr/xovf yo^ ifavp-tXrivoi 

ov<ra. iv. 32. 'Tov r/kiov (KKvtres ri rywrro ircpi yovfirjviav. ii. 28. 

Novfjoipt^ Kara {rtXriVTjv {wnrfp kcu fiopov doxcT elvat yiyvftrBai 

hwarov) 6 ^Xios c^Xittc /*fTa fjsftnjfifipuw koi irakuf€irkrjp<i^t^ yevopitifos 

lirivo€iBrjs K(u aaT€pci>v riv<ov €K<l>av€VTV>v, 

VOL. I. K 



ITS EARLY STAGES. 131 

ill Ptolemy's Almagest, in stating observations of 
eclipses. 

The Metonic and Calippic periods undoubtedly 
imply a very considerable degree of accuracy in the 
knowledge which the astronomers, to whom they are 
due, had of the length of the month ; and the first 
is a very happy invention for bringing the solar and 
hiiiar calendars into agreement. 

The Roman calendar, from which our own is 
derived, appears to have been a much less skilful 
contrivance than the Greek; though scholars are 
not agreed on the subject of its construction, we can 
hardly doubt that months, in this as in other cases, 
were intended originally to have a reference to the 
moon. In whatever manner the solar and lunar mo- 
tions were ii\t;ended to be reconciled, the attempt 
seems altogether to have failed, and to have been 
soon abandoned. The Roman months, both before 
and after the Julian correction, were portions 
of the year, having no reference to full and new 
moons ; and we, having adopted this division of the 
year, have thus, in our common calendar, the traces 
of one of the early attempts of mankind to seize the 
law of the succession of cplestial phenomena, in a 
case where the attempt was a complete failure. 

Considered as a part of the progress of our astro-* 

nomical knowledge, improvements in the calendar 

do not offer many points to our observation, but they 

exhibit a few very important steps. Calendars which, 

'^ng apparently to unscientific ages and nations, 

K 2 



132 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

possess a great degree of accordance with the true 
motions of the sun and moon, like the solar calendar 
of 'the Mexicans, and the lunar calendar of the 
Greeks, contain the only record now extant of dis- 
coveries which must have required a great deal of 
observation, of thought, and probably of time, ^he 
later improvements in calendars, which take place 
when astronomical observation has been attentively 
pursued, are of little consequence to the history of 
science ; for they are generally founded on astrono- 
mical determinations, and are posterior in time, and 
inferior in accuracy, to the knowledge on which they 
depend: still, cycles of correction, which are both short 
and close to exactness, like that of Meton, may per- 
haps be the original form of the knowledge which they 
imply ; and certainly require both accurate facts and 
sagacious arithmetical reasonings. The discovery of 
such a cycle must always have the appearance of a 
happy guess, like other discoveries of laws of nature. 
Beyond this point, the interest of the study of calen- 
dars, as bearing on our subject, ceases : they may be 
considered as belonging rather to art than to science ; 
rather as an application of a part of our knowledge 
to the uses of life, than a means or an evidence of 
its extension. 

Sect. 6. — The Constellatiom. 

Some tendency to consider the stars as formed into 
groups, is inevitable when men begin to attend to 



ITS EARLY STAGES. 138 

them ; but how men were led to the fanciful system 
of names of stars and of constellations, which we 
find to have prevailed in early times, it is very diffi- 
cult to determine. Single stars, and very close 
groups, as the Pleiades, were named in the time of 
Homer and Hesiod, and at a still earlier period, as 
we find in the book of Job". 

Two remarkable circumstances with respect to 
the constellations are, first, that they appear in most 
cases to be arbitrary combinations; the artificial 
figures which are made to include the stars, not 
having any resemblance to their obvious configura- 
tions; and, second, that these figures, in different 
countries, are so far similar, as to imply some com- 
munication. The axbitrary nature of the^e figures 
shows that they were rather the work of the imagi- 
native and mythological tendencies of man, than of 
mere convenience and love of arrangement* "The 
constellations," says an astronomer of our own time**, 
seem to have been almost purposely named and 
delineated to cause as much confusion and iAcon- 

** Job xxxviii. 31. " Canst thou bind the sweet influences of 
Ohima (the Pleiades) or loose the bands of Kesil (Orion)? Canst 
thou bring forth Mazzaroth (Sirius) in his season? or canst 
thou guide Ash or Aisch (Arcturus) with his sons?" 

And ix. 9. " Which maketh Arcturus, Orion and Pleiades, 
and the chamber^ of the south." 

Dupuis, vi. 545, thinks that Aisch was ui£, the goat and kids. 
See Hyde, Ulughbeigh. 

*• Heischel. 



134 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

Tenience as possible. Innumerable snakes t%d»e 
through long and contorted areas of the heavens, 
where no memory can follow them : bears, lions, and 
fishes, large and small, northern and southern, con- 
fuse all nomenclature. A better system of constel- 
lations might have been a material help as an artificial 
memory.*' When men indicate the stars by figures, 
borrowed from obvious resemblances, they are led 
to combinations quite different from the received 
constellations. Thus the common pec^e in our own 
coimtry find a wain or waggon, or a plough, in a por- 
tion of the great bear *^ 

The similarity of the constellations recognised in 
different countries is very remarkable. The Chal- 
dean, the Egyptian, and the Grecian skies have a 
resemblance which cannot be overlooked. Some 
have conceived that this resemblance may be 
traced also in the Indian and Arabic constellations, 
at least in those of the zodiac'*. But while the 
figures are the same, the names and traditions con- 
nected with them are different, according to the 

*^ So also the Greeks. Homer, Od. I. 

ApKTOV fiv KM afia^av eTrLKKrjaiP KuXcovo'tv, 

The northern bear which oft the wain they call. 

Afucros was the traditional name, a/xo^, that suggested bj the 
form. 

■• Dupuis, vi. 548. The Indian zodiac contains, in the place 
of our Capricorn, a ram and a fish, which proves the resem- 
blance without chance of mistake. Bailly, i. p. 157. 



ITS BARLY STAGES. 135 

histories and kx»lities of each country*'; the river 
among the stars which the Greeks called the £ri- 
danusi the Egyptians asserted to be the Nile. Some 
conceive that the signs of the zodiac, or path along 
which the sun and moon pass, had its divisions 
marked by signs which had a reference to the course 
of the seasons, to the motion of the sun, or the 
employments of the husbandman. If we take the 
position of the heavens, which, from the knowledge 
we now possess, we are sure they must have had 
15000 years ago, the i^gnificance of the signs of the 
zodiac, in which the sxm was, as referred to the 
Egyptian year, becomes very marked ^^ and has led 
some to suppose that the zodiac was invented at 
such a period. Others have rejected this as an im- 
probably great antiquity, and have thought it more 
iikely that the constellation assigned to each season 
was that which at that season rose at the beginning 
of the night : thus the balance (which is conceived 
to designate the equality of days and nights) was 
placed among the stars which rose in the evening 
when the spring began : this would fix the origin of 
these signs 2500 years before our era. 

It is clear, as has already been said, that fency, 
and probably superstition, had a share in forming 
the collection of constellations. It is certain 
that, at an early period, superstitious notions were 
associated with the stars". Astrology is of very 

" Dupuis, vi. 549. ' " Laplace, Hist. Astron. p. 8. 

'* Dupuis, vi. 546. 



129 THE QKESBK ASTBONOlfY. 

high antiquity in the Eairt* The ators were supposed 
to influence the character and destiny of man, and 
to be in some way connected with sop^or natuies 
and powers. 

We may, I conceive, look upon the formation of 
the constellations, and the notions thus connected 
with them, as a very early attempt to find a mean- 
ing in the relations of the stars ; and as an utter 
failure. The first effort to associate the appearances 
and motions of the skies by conceptions implying 
unity and connexion, was made in a wrong direc- 
tion, as may very easily be supposed. Instead of 
considering the appearances only with reference to 
space, time, number, in a manner purely rational, a 
number of other elements, imagination, tradition^ 
hope, fear, awe of the supernatural, belief in des- 
tiny, were called into action. Man, young as a phi- 
losopher at l^ast, had yet to learn what notions hid 
successful guesses on these subjects must involve, 
and what they must exclude. At that period, 
nothing could be more natural or excusable than 
this ignorance ; but it is curious to see how long 
and obstinately the belief lingered (if indeed it be 
yet extinct) that the motions of the stars, and the 
dispositions and fortunes of men, may come under 
some common conceptions and laws, by which a 
connexion between the one and the other may be 
established. 

We cannot, therefore, agree with those who con- 
sider astrology in the early ages as " only a de- 



ITS SABLY STAGES. 137 

giraded astronomy, thie abuse of a more ancient 
science'**," It was the first step to astronomy, by 
leading to haUts and means of grouping phenomena ; 
and, after a while, by showing that pictorial and 
mythological relations among the stars had at least 
no very obvious value. From that time, the induc- 
tive process went on steadily in the true rOad, under 
the guidance of . ideas of space, time, and number. 

Sect 7. — The Plamts. 

While men were becoming femiKar with the fixed 
stars, the planets must have attracted their notice. 
Venus, from her brightness, and from her accom- 
panying the sun at no great distance, and thus 
appearing as the morning and evening star, was very 
conspicuous. Pythagoras is said to have maintained 
that the evening and morning star are the same 
body ; which certainly must have been one of the 
earliest discoveries on this subject ; and indeed, we 
can hardly conceive men noticing the stars for a 
year or two without coming to this conclusion. 
Jupiter and Mars, sometimes still brighter than 
Venus, were also very noticeable. Saturn and Mer- 
cury were less so, but in fine climates they and their 
motion would soon be detected by persons observ- 
ant of the heavens. To reduce to any rule the 
movements of these luminaries must have taken 



as 



Dupuis yi. 546. 



138 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

time «ad thought ; probably before this yms doi^e, 
certainly very early, these heavenly bodies were 
brought more peculiarly xmder those views which 
we have noticed as leading to astrology. 

At a time beyond the reach of certain history, 
the planets, along with the sun and moon, had been 
arranged in a certain recognised order by the Egyp- 
tians or some other ancient nation. Probably this 
arrangement had been made according to the slow- 
ness of their motionis among the stars ; for though 
the motion of each is very variable, the gradation of 
their velocities is, on the whole, very manifest ; and 
the different rate of travelling of the different 
planets, and probably other circumstances of differ- 
ence, led, in the ready fancy of early times, to the 
attribution of a peculiar cdiaracter to each luminary. 
Thus Saturn was held to be of a cold and gelid 
nature ; Jupiter, who, from his more rapid motion, 
was supposed to be lower in place, was temperate ; 
Mars, fiery, and the like^^ 

It is not necessary to dwell on the details of these 
speculations, but we may notice a very remarkable 
evidence of their antiquity and generality in the 

*' Achilles Tatius (Uranol. p. 135, 136,) giyes the Grecian 
and Egyptian names of the planets. 





EgyptUn. 


Greek; 




Saturn . 


Ne/iorctts 


Kpovov aaufp 


^Miv&y 


Jupiter . 


• Oo-cpidof 


Atos 


ffkuBuMf 


Mars 


. 'HpaieXeovff 




irvpo€is 


Venus . 




A<l>podvnfs 


i&a<l>opos 


Mercury 


• AiroXX«>vof 


^Epfiou 


mXfimf 



ITS EARLY STAGES. 139 

structtti^ of one of the most femiliar of our mear 
dures of time, the week. This distribution of time 
according to periods of seven days, comes down to 
us, as we learn from the Jewish scriptures, from the 
beginning of man's existence on the earth. The 
same usage is found over all the East ; it existed 
among the Arabians, Assyrians, Egyptians*\ The 
same week is found in India among the Bramins ; it 
has, there also, its days marked by those of the 
heavenly bodies ; and it has been ascertained that 
the same day has, in that country, the name corre- 
sponding with its designation in other nations. 

The notion which led to the usual designations of 
the days of the week is not easily unravelled. The 
days eJM5h correspond to one of the heavenly bodies, 
which were, in the earliest systems of the world, 
conceived to be the following, enumerating them in 
the order of their remoteness from the earth"; 
Saturn, Jupiter, Mars, the Sun, Venus, Mercury, 
the Moon. At a later period, the received systems 
placed these seven luminaries in the seven spheres. 
The knowledge which was implied in this view, and 
the time when it was obtained, we must consider here- 
after. The order in which the names are assigned to 
the days of the week (beginning with Saturday,) is, 
Saturn, the Sun, the Moon, Mars, Mercury, Jupiter, 
Venus ; and various accounts are given of the manner 
in which one of these orders is obtained from the 



a« 



Laplace, Hist. Astron. p. 16. '* Philol. Mus. No. I. 



140 TH£ 6RBEK ASTROm)MV. 

other ; all the methods proceeding upon certain artA- 
traiy arithmetical processes, connected in some way 
with astrological views. It is perhaps not worth our 
while here to examine further the steps of this pro- 
cess ; it would be difficult to determine with certainty 
why the former order of the planets was adopted, and 
how and why the latter was deduced from it. But 
there is something very remarkable in the univer- 
sality of the notions, apparently so fantastic, which 
have produced this result; and we may probably 
consider the week, with Laplace**, as ^' the most 
ancient monument of astronomical knowledge." 
This period has gone on without interruption or 
irregularity from the earliest recorded times to our 
own days, traversing the extent of ages and the 
revolutions of empires; the names of the ancient 
deities which were associated with the stars have 
been replaced by those of the objects of the worship 
of our Teutonic ancestors, according to their views 
of the corr^pondeiM^e of the two mythologies ; and 
the Quakers, in rejecting these names of days, hate 
east aside the most ancient existing relic of astro- 
logical as well as idolatrous superstition. 

Sect 8. — The Cirdes of the Sphere. 

The inventions hitherto noticed, though undoubtedly 
they were steps in astronomical knowledge, can 

^« Hist. Ast. p. It 



ITS EARLY STAGES. 14l 

hardly be considered as purely technical and scien- 
tific speculations ; for the exact reckoning of time 
is one of the wants, even of the least civilized 
nations. But the distribution of the places and 
nootions of the heavenly bodies by means of a celes- 
tial sphere with imaginary lines drawn upon it, is a 
step in speculative astronomy, and was occasioned 
and rendered important by the scientific propensities 
of man. 

It is not easy to say with whom this notion ori- 
ginated. Some parts of it are obvious. The ap- 
pearance of the sky naturally suggests the idea of 
a concave sphere, with the stars fixed on its surface. 
Their motions during any one night, it would be 
readily seen, might be represented by supposing this 
sphere to turn round a pole or axis ; for there is a 
conspicuous star in the heavens which appaa'ently 
stands still; all the others travel round this in 
circles, and keep the same positions with respect to 
each other. This stationary star is every night the 
same, and in the same place ; the other stars also 
have the same relative position ; but their general 
position at the same time of night varies gradually 
from night to night, so as to go through its cycle of 
appearances once a year. All this would obviously 
agree with the supposition that the sky is a concave 
sphere or dome, that the stars have fixed places on 
this sphere, and that it revolves perpetually and 
uniformly about the pole or fixed point. 

But this supposition does not at all explain the 



142 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

way in which the appearances of different nights 
succeed each other. This^ however, may be ex- 
plained, it appears, by supposing the sun also to 
move among the stars on the sur&ce of the concave 
sphere. The sun by his brightness makes the stars 
invisible which are on his side of the heavens ; this 
we can easily believe ; for the moon, when bright, 
also puts out all but the largest stars, and we see 
the stars appearing in the evening, each in its place, 
according to their degree of splendour, as fiEUSt as 
the declining light of day allows them to become 
visible. And as the sun brings day, and his absence 
night, if he move through the circuit of the stars in 
a year, we shall have, in the course of that time, 
every part of the starry sphere in succession pre- 
sented to us as our nocturnal sky. 

This notion, that the susi moves round among the 
stars in a yeaar^ is the basis of astronomy, and a con- 
siderable part of the science is only the develope- 
ment and particularisation of this general concep- 
tion. It is not easy to ascertain either the exact 
method by which the path of the sun among the 
stars was deterpiined, or the author and date of the 
discovery. That there is some difficulty in tracing 
the course of the sun among the stars will be clearly 
seen, when it is considered that no star can ever be 
seen at the same time with the sun. If the whole 
circuit of the sky be divided into twelve parts or 
sig^nsy it is estimated by Autolycus, the oldest 
writer on these subjects whose works remain to 



ITS EARLY STAGES. 143 

us% that the stars in one of these parts are absorbed 
by the solar rays, so that they cannot be seen. Hence 
the stars which are seen nearest to the place of the 
setting and the rising sun in the eyening and in the 
morning, are distant from him by the half of a sign ; 
the evening stars being to the west, and the morn- 
ing stars to the east of him. If the observer had 
previously obtained a knowledge of the places of 
all the principal stars, he might in this way deter- 
mine the position of the sun each night, and thus 
trace his path in a year. 

. In this, or some such way, the sun's path was de- 
termined by the early astronomers of Egypt. Thales, 
who is mentioned as the father of Greek astronomy, 
probably learnt among the Egyptians the results of 
such speculations, and introduced them into his own 
country. His knowledge, indeed, must have been a 
great deal more advanced than that which we are 
now describing, if it be true, as is asserted, that he 
predicted an eclipse. But his having done so is not 
very consistent with what we are told of the steps 
which his successors had still to make. 

The circle of the signs, in which the sun moves 
among the stars, is obliquely situated with regard to 
the circles in which the stars move about the poles. 
Pliny" states that Anaximander% a scholar of 
Thales, was the first person who pointed out this 

'^ Delamb. A. A. p. xiii. *® Lib. ii. c, (viii.) 

'• Plutarch, De Plac. Phil. lib. ii. cap. xii, says Pythagoras 
was the author of this discovery. 



144 THE OREIEK ASTRONOMY. 

obliquity, and thus, as lie says, " opened the gate of 
nature." Certainly the person who first had a clear 
view of the nature of the sun's path in the celestial 
sphere, made that step which led to all the rest ; 
but it is difficult to conceive that the Egyptians and 
Chaldeans had not already advanced so far. 

The diurnal motion of the celestial sphere, and 
the motion of the moon in the circle of the signs, 
gave rise to a mathematical science, the Doctrine of 
the Sphere^ which was one of the earliest branches 
of applied mathematics. A number of technical 
conceptions and terms were soon introduced. The 
sphere of the heavens was conceived to be complete, 
though we see but a part of it ; it was supposed to 
turn about the visible jt?ofe and another pole opposite 
to this, and these poles were connected by an imagi- 
nary ajds. The circle which divided the sphere 
exactly midway between these poles was called the 
equaioT {larffMepivo^.) The two circles parallel to this 
which bounded the sun's path among the stars were 
called tropics {rpoTriKai) because the sun turns back 
again towards the equator when he reaches them. 
The stars which never set are bounded by a circle 
called the Arctic cirde {cup/cTiKo^y from apxro^^ the 
bear, the constellation to which some of the prin- 
cipal stars within that circle belong.) A circle 
about the opposite pole is called antarctic^ and the 
stars which are within it can never rise to us*". The 

*^ The arctic and antarctic circles of modem astronomers are 
difterent from these. 



ITS EAJOJPST STAGES. 145 

ifun's path or ciroje of the signs is called the zodiac^ 
QX circle of animals ; the points where this circle 
ni^ets the equator are the equinoctial points^ the days 
and nights being equal when the sun is in them ; 
title ^titial points ^xe tjiose where the sun's path 
touches the tropica ; his nouotion to the south or to 
the north ceases when he is there» and he appears in 
that respect to stand still. The cplures {KoXovpoi^ 
mutilated) are circlps which pass through the poles 
and through the equinoctial and solstitial points ; 
they have their name because they are only visible 
in part, a portion of them being below the horizon. 
The horizon (opc^eDy) is commonly understood as 
the boundary of the visible earth and heaven. In 
the doctrine of the sphere, this boundary is a great 
circle^ that is, a circle of which the plane passes 
through the centre of the sphere ; and, therefore, an 
entire hemisphere is always above the horizon. The 
term occurs for the first time in the work of Euclid, 
called Phcenomena (^atvofieva), We possess two 
treatises written by Autolycus*^ (about 300 B.C.) 
which trace deductiveh/ the results of the doctrine of 
the sphere. Supposing its diurnal motion to be uni- 
form, in a work entitled Ilepi KivovfMevr)^ S<l>aLpa^, " On 
the Moving Sphere," he demonstrates various pro- 
perties of the diurnal risings, settings, and motions 
of the stars. In another work, Ilepc Eimoktov Kai 
AvGexov, " On Risings and Settings", tadUy assuming 



41 



Delambre, Astron. Ancienne, p. 19. ** lb. p. 25. 

VOL. I. L 



146 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

the sun's motion in his circle to be uniform, he proves 
certain propositions, with regard to the risings and 
settings of the stars, at the same time when the sun 
rises and sets*', or vice versd**; and also their apparent 
risings and settings when they cease to be visible 
after sun-«et, or begin to be visible after sun-rise**. 
Several of the propositions contained in the former 
of these treatises are still necessary to be understood, 
as fundamental parts of astronomy. 

The work of Euclid, just mentioned, is of the same 
kind. Delambre** finds in it evidence that Euclid 
was merely a book-astronomer, who had never ob- 
served the heavens. 

We may here remark the first instance of that 
which we shall find abundantly illustrated in every 
part of the history of science ; that man is prom to 
become a deductive reasoner ; — ^that as soon as he 
obtains principles which can be traced to details by 
logical consequence, he sets about forming a body 
of science, by making a system of such reasonings. 
Geometry has always been a favourite mode of exer- 
cising this propensity : and that science, along with 
Trigonometry, Plane and Spherical, to which the early 
problems of astronomy gave rise, have, up to the 
present day, been a constant field for the exercise of 
mathematical inge]Quity ; a few simple astronomical 
truths being assumed as the basis of the reasoning. 



*' Cosmtcal setting and rising. ** AcronicaL 

** Heliacal *« A. A. p. 53. 



ITS EARLIEST STAGES. 147 

Sect. 9. — The Globular Form of the Earth, 

The establishment of the globular form of the earth 
is an important step in astronomy, for it is the first 
of those convictions, directly opposed to the apparent 
evidence of the senses, which astronomy irresistibly 
proves. To make men believe that up and doum are 
different directions in diflerent places ; that the sea, 
which seems so level, is, in fact, convex ; that the 
earth, which appears to rest on a solid foundation, is, 
in fact, not supported at all; are great triumphs 
both of the power of discovering and the power of 
convincing. We may readily allow this, when we re- 
collect how recently the doctrine of the antipodes^ or 
the existence of inhabitants of the earth, who stand on 
the opposite side of it, with their feet turned towards 
ours, was considered both monstrous and heretical. 

Yet the different positions of the horizon at 
different places, necessarily led the student of spheri- 
cal astronomy toward this notion of the earth as 
a round body. Anaximander*^ is said by some 
to have held the earth to be globular, and to be 
detached or suspended; he is also stated to have 
constructed a sphere, on which were shown the ex- 
tent of land and water. As, however, we do not 
know the arguments upon which he maintained this 
opinion, we cannot judge of its value ; it may have 
been no better founded than a different opinion 

*^ See Brucker, vol. i. p. 486. 

L 2 



148 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

ascribed to him by Laertius, that the earth had the 
shape of a pillar. Probably, the authors of the doc- 
trine of the globular form of the earth were led to 
it, as we have said, by observing the different height 
of the pole at different places. They would find that 
the space which they passed over from north to 
south on the earth, wbs proportional to the change 
of place of the horizon in the celestial sphere ; and 
as the horizon is» at every place, in the direction of 
the earth's apparently level surface, this observation 
would naturally suggest to them the opinion that the 
earth is placed within the celestial sphere, as a small 
globe in the middle of a much larger one. 

We find this doctrine so distinctly insisted on by 
Aristotle, that we may almost look on him as the 
establisher of it*'. " As to the figure of the earth, 
it must necessarily be spherical." This he proves, 
first by the tendency of things, in all places, down- 
wards. He then adds*', " And, moreover, from the 
phenomena according to sense : for if it were not so, 
the eclipses of the moon would not have such sec- 
tions as they have. For in the configurations in the 
course* of a month, the deficient part takes all differ- 
ences ; for it is straight, and concave, and convex ; but 
in eclipses it always has the line of division convex ; 
whjerefore, since the moon is eclipsed in consequence 
of the interposition of the earth, the periphery of 
the earth, having a spherical form, must be the cause 



48 
49 



Arist. de C(b1o« lib. ii. cap. xiv. Casaub. p. 290 F. 
p. 291 O. 



ITS EARLIEST STAGES. 149 

of this. ' And again, by the appearances of the stars, 
it is clear, not only that it is spherical, but that its 
size is not very large : for when we make a small 
removal to the south or the north, the circle of the 
horizon becomes palpably different ; so that the stars 
vertically over us undergo a great change, and are 
not the same to those that travel to the north and 
•to the south. For some stars are seen in Egypt or 
at Cyprus, but are not seen in the countries to the 
north of these ; and the stars that in the north are 
visible while they make a complete circuit, there 
undergo a setting. So that from this it is manifest, 
not only that the form of the earth is round, but also 
that it is a part of not a very large sphere : for other- 
wise the difference would not be so obvious to per- 
sons making so small a change of place. Wherefore 
we may judge that those persons who connect the 
region m the neighbourhood of the pillars of Hercules 
with thai towards Indict and who assert that in this way 
the sea is one, do not assert things very improbable. 
They confirm this conjecture by the elephants, which 
are said to be of the same species (761/09) towards 
each extreme ; as if this circumstance was a conse- 
quence of the conjunction of the extremes. The 
mathematicians, who try to gather from reasoning 
the measure of the circumference, make it amount 
to 400,000 stadia; whence we collect that the earth 
is not only spherical, but is not large compared with 
the magnitude of the other stars.'^ 

When this notion was once suggested, it was de- 



/ 



150 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

fended and confirmed by such arguments as we find 
in later writers: for instance *°, that the tendency of 
all things was to fall to the place of heavy bodies, 
and that this place being the centre of iixe earth, the 
whole earth had no such tendency ; that the inequa- 
lities on the surface were so small as not materially 
to affect the shape of so vast a mass ; that drops of 
water naturally form themselves into figures with a 
convex sur&ce; that the end of the ocean would 
fall if it were not rounded off; that we see ships, 
when they go out to sea, disappearing downwards, 
which shows the surface to be convex. These are 
the arguments still employed in impi^essiiig tlie doc- 
trines of astronomy upon the student of our own 
days ; and thus we find that, even at the early period 
of which we are now speaking, truths had begun to 
accumulate which form a part of our present 
treasures. 

Sect. 10. — The Phases of the Moon. 

When men had formed a steady notion of the moon 
as a solid body, revolving about the earth, they had 
only further to conceive it spherical, and to suppose 
the sun to be beyond the orbit of the moon, and they 
would find that they had obtained an explaoation of 
the vaiying forms whidi the bi^ht part of the moon 
s^ssumes in the course of a month. For the convex 



do 



Pliny, Nat. Hist...ii. lxv. 



ITS EARLIEST STAGES. 151 

side of the orescent-moon, and her ftill edge when 
she is gibbous, are always turned towards the sun. 
And this explanation, once suggested, would be con- 
firmed, the more it was examined. For instance, if 
there be near us a spherical stone, on which the sun 
is shining, and if we place ourselves so that this stone 
and the lAoon are seen in the same direction, (the 
moon appearing just over the top of the stone,) we 
shall find that the visible part of the stone, which is 
then muminated by the sun, is exactly sunUar in form 
to the moon, at whatever period of her changes she 
may be. The stone and the moon being in the same 
position with respect to us, and both being enligh-* 
tened by the sun, the bright parts are the same in 
figure ; the only difference is, that the dark part of 
the moon is usually not visible at all. 

This doctrine is ascribed to Ana^mander. An*, 
totle was aware of it. (Prob. 15.) It could not well 
escape the Chaldeans and Egyptians, if they specu- 
lated- at all about the causes of the appearances in 
the heavens. 

Sect 11. — Eclipses. 

These occurrences, from the earliest times, were 
regarded with a peculiar interest. The notions of 
superhuman influences and relations, which, as we 
have seen, were associated, from the earliest times, 
with the luminaries of the sky, made men look with 
alarm at any sudden and striking change in those 



152 THE OREEK ASTTRONOaiY. 

objects ; and as the constant and steady comrse of 
the celestial revolutions was contemplated with a 
feeling of admiration and awe, any marked inter- 
ruption iand deviation in this course, was regarded 
with surprise and terror. This appears to be the 
case with all nations at an early period of their 
civilization. 

This impression would cause eclipses to be noted 
and remembered ; and accordingly we find that the 
records of eclipses are the earliest astronomical in- 
formation which we possess. When men had dis- 
covered some of the laws of succession of other 
astronomical phenomena, for instance, of the usual 
appearances of the moon and sun, it might then 
occur to them that these unusual appearances also 
might probably be governed by some rule. 

The search after this rule was successful at an 
early period. The Chaldeans were able to predict 
eclipses of the moon. This they did, probably, by 
means of their cycle of 223 months, or about 18 
years ; for at the end of this time, the eclipses of the 
moon begin to return, at the same intervals and in 
the same order as at the beginning^'. Probably this 
was the first instance of the prediction of peculiar 
astronomical phenomena. The Chinese have, indeed, 
a legend, in which it is related that a solar eclipse 
happened in the reign of Tchong-kang, above 2000 

'^^ The eclipses of the sun are more difficult to calculate; since 
they depend upon the place of the spectator on the earth. 



ITS EARLIEST STAGES. 153 

years before Christ, and that the emperor was so 
much irritated against two great officers of state, who 
had neglected to predict this eclipse, that he put 
them to death. But this cannot be accepted as a 
real event: for during the next ten centuries, we 
find no single observation, or fact, connected with 
astronomy, in the Chinese histories ; and their astro- 
nomy has never advanced beyond a very rude and 
imperfect condition. 

We can only conjecture the mode in which the 
Chaldeans discovered their period of 18 years ; and 
we may make very different suppositions with regard 
to the degree of science by which they were led to 
it. We may suppose, with Delambre**, that they 
carefully recorded the eclipses which happened, and 
then, by the inspection of their registers, discovered 
that those of the moon recurred after a certain period. 
Or we may suppose, with other authors, that they 
sedulously determined the motions of the moon, and 
having obtained these with considerable accuracy, 
sought and found a period which should include 
cycles of these motions. This latter mode of pro- 
ceeding would imply a considerable degree of 
knowledga 

It appears probable rather that such a period was 
discovered by noticing the recurrence of eclipses, than 
by studying the moon's motions. After 6585 j days, 
or 223 lunations, the same eclipses nearly will recur.. 



ss 



A. A.; p. 212. 



154 THE OBBEK A8I1KXNOMY. 

It is not contested that the Chaldeans were ac* 
qiudnted with this period, which thej called Saras ; 
or that they calculated eclipses hj means of it. 

Sect. 12. — Sequel to the Early Stages of Astrofiwmy. 

Every stage of science has its train of practical ap« 
pUcations and systematic inferences, arising both 
from the demands of convenience and curiosity, and 
from the pleasure, which, as we have abeady said, 
ingenious and active-minded men feel in exercising 
the process of deduction. The earliest condition of 
astronomy in which it can be looked upon as a 
science,* exhibits several examples of such applica- 
tions and inferences, of which we may mention a 
few. 

Prediction of Edipses. — ^The cycles which served 
to keep in order the calendar of the early nations of 
antiquity, in some instances enabled them, also, as 
has just been stated, to predict eclipses ; and this 
application of knowledge necessarily excited great 
notice. 

Terrestrial Zones. — The globular form of the 
earth being assented to, the doctrine of the sphere 
was applied to the earth as well as the heavens; 
and its surface was divided by various imaginary 
circles ; among the re&rt;, the eqmktor, the tropics, and 
circles at the same distance from the poles as the 
tropics are from the equator. One of the curious 
consequences of this division was the assumption. 



ITS EARLIEST STAeEB. 165 

that there must be some marked difference in the 
stripes or zones into which the earth's surface was thus 
divided. In going to the south, men found countries 
hotter and hotter, in going to the north, colder and 
colder; and it was supposed that the space between 
the tropical circles must be uninhabitable from heat, 
and that within the polar circles, again, uninhabitable 
from cold. This fancy was, as we now know, en- 
tirely unfounded. But the principle of the globular 
form of the earth, when dealt with by means of 
spherical geometry,, led to many true and important 
propositions concerning the lengths of days and nights 
at (tiflerent places. 

Cfnamonick.'-^ Another important result of the 
doctrine of the sphere was Cfnomanick or DiaUing. 
Anaximenes is said by Pliny to have first taught 
this art in Greece ; and both he and Anaximander 
are reported to have erected the first dial at Lace^ 
demon. 

Mmswre of the Sun's Distanoe. — ^The explanation 
of the phases of the moon led to no result so re^ 
markable as the attempt of Aristarchus of Samos to 
obtain from this doctrine a measure of the distance 
of the sun as compared with that of the moon. If 
the moon was a perfectly smooth sphere, when she 
was exactly midway between the new and fiiU in 
position (that is a quadrant from the sun) she would 
be somewhat more than a half moon ; and the place 
when she was dichotomised^ that is, was an exact semi- 
circle, the bright part being bounded by a straight 



156 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

line, would depend upon the sun's distance from the 
earth. Aristarchus endeavoured to fix the exact 
place of this dichotomy ; but the irregularity of the 
edge which bounds the bright part of the sun, and 
the diflSiculty of measuring with accuracy, by means 
then in use, either the precise time, when the boun- 
dary was most nearly a straight line or the exact dis- 
tance of the moon from the sun at that time, rendered 
his conclusion £alse and valueless. He collected that 
the sun is at 18 times the distance of the moon 
from us 4 we now know that be is at 400 times the 
moon's distance. 

It would be easy to dwell longer on subjects of 
this kind ; but we have already perhaps entered too 
much into detail. We have been t^npted to do 
this by the interest which the mathematical spirit of 
the Greeks gave to the earliest astron(Hnical dis- 
coveries, when these were the subjects of their rear 
sonings : but we must now proceed to contemplate 
them engaged in a worthier employment, in adding 
to these discoveries. 



16 



ly 



CHAPTER II. 

Prelude to the Inductive Epoch op 

HiPPABCHUS. 

Without pretending that we have exhausted the 
consequences of the elementary discoveries which 
we have enumerated, we now proceed to consider 
the nature and circumstances of the next great dis- 
covery which makes an epoch in the history of 
astronomy ; and this we shall find to be the theory 
of epicycles and eccentrics. Before, however, we 
relate the establishment of this theory, we must, 
according to the general plan we have marked out, 
notice some of the conjectures and attempts by which 
it was preceded, and the growing acquaintance with 
facts, which made the want of such an explanation 
felt. 

In the steps previously made in astronomical 
knowledge, no ingenuity had been required, to devise 
the view which was adopted. The motions of the 
stars and sun were most naturally and almost irre- 
sistibly conceived as the results of motion in a 
revolving sphere ; the indications of position which 
we obtain from different places on the earth's surface, 
when clearly combined, obviously present a globular 
shape. In these cases the first conjectures, the sup- 
position of the simplest form, of the most unifonn 



♦"^w 



168 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

motion, required no after-correetion. But this mani- 
fest simplicity, this easy and obvious explanation, did 
not apply to the movement of all the heavenly bodies. 
The planets, the " wandering stars," could not be so 
easily understood; the motion of each, as Cicero says, 
" undergoing very remarkable changes in its course, 
going before and behind, quicker and slower, appearing 
in the evening, but gradually lost there, and emerging 
again in the morning ^" A continued attention to 
these stars would, however, detect a kind of intricate 
regularity in their motions, which might naturally 
be described as ^^a dance." The Chaldeans are 
stated by Diodoru8^ to have observed assiduously 
the risings and sitings of the plants, from the top 
of the temple of Belus. By doing this, they would 
find the times in which the forwards and backwards 
movements of Saturn, Jupiter, and Mars recur ; and 
also the time in which they come round to the same 
part of the heavens ^ Venus and Mercury never 
recede far from the sun, and the intervals which 
elapse while either of them leaves its greatest dis- 
tance from the sun and returns again to the 



* Cic. de Nat. D. lib. 2. p. 460. *' Ea qu« Saturni stella 
dicitur, ^Muywyque a Gneds nominatur, quiB a terra abest plaii- 
mum, XXX fere aimis cursum suum conficit ; in q-uo cursu multa 
mirabiliter efiiciens, turn antecedendo, turn retardando, turn yes- 
pertinis temporibus delitescendo, turn matutinis se rursum 
aperiendo, sibU imnmtat sempitemis sadculonun »tatibus, qtam 
eadem iisdem temponbus efficiat." And so of the other planets. 

• Del. A. A. ; p. 4; * Hin. H. N. ii. p, 204. 



PRELUDE TO THE EPOCH OF HIPPARCHUS. 159 

greatest distance on the sasne side, would easily be 
observed. 

Probably the manner in which the motions of the 
planets were originally reduced to rule was something 
like the following : — In about 30 of our years, Sa- 
turn goes 29 times through his emomalyy that is, the 
succession of varied motions by which he sometimes 
goes forwards and sometimes backwards among the 
stars. During this time, he goes once round the 
heavens, and returns nearly to the same place. 

Perhaps the eastern nations contented themselves 
with thus referring these motions to cycles of time, 
so as to determine their recurrence. Something of 
this kind was done at an early period, as we have 
seen. 

But the Greeks soon attempted to frame to them-- 
selves a sensible image of the mechani^ by which 
these complex motions were produced : nor did they 
find this difficult. Venus, for instance, who, upon the 
whole, moves from west to east among the stars, is 
seen, at certain intervals, to return or move retrograde 
a short way back from east to west, then to become 
for a short time stationary, then to turn again and 
resiune her direct motion westward, and so on. Now 
this can be explained by supposing that she is placed 

ft 

in the rim of a wheel, which is turned edgeways to 
us, and of which the centre turns round in the 
heavens from west to ea^t, while the wheel, carrying 
the planet in its motion, moves round its own centre- 
In this way the motion of the wheel about its centre. 



160 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

would, in some situations, counterbalance the general 
motion of the centre, and make the planet retrograde^ 
while, on the whole, the westerly motion would pre- 
yail. Just as if we suppose that a person, holdin&f a 
lamp in his haad in the dark, and at a distance, so 
that the lamp alone is visible, should run on turning 
himself round ; we should see the light sometimes 
stationary, sometimes retrograde, but on the whole 
progressive. 

A mechanism of this kind was imagined for each 
of the planets, and the wheels of which we have 
spoken were, in the end, called epicycles. 

The application of such mechanism to the planets 
appears to have arisen in Greece about the time of 
Aristotle. In the works of Plato we find a strong 
taste for this kind of mechanical speculation. In 
the tenth book of the " Polity," we have the apologue 
of Alcinus the Pamphylian, who, being supposed to 
be killed in battle, revived when he was placed on 
the funeral pyre, and related what he had seen 
during his trance. Among other revelations, he 
beheld the machinery by which all the celestial 
bodies revolve. The axis of these revolutions is the 
adamantine distafi^ which Destiny holds between her 
knees; on this are fixed, by means of diflferent 
sockets, flat rings, by which the planets are carried. 
The order and magnitude of these spindles are mi- 
nutely detailed. Also, in the "Epilogue to the 
Laws" (Epinomis), he again describes the various 
movements of the sky, so as to show a distinct 



PRELUDE TO THE EPOCH OF HIPPARCHUS. 161 

acquaintance with the general character of the 
planetary motions : and, after speaking of the Egyp- 
tians and Syrians as the original cultivators of such 
knowledge, he adds some very remarkable exhorta- 
tions to Ms countrymen to prosecute the subject. 
" Whatever we Greeks,** he says, " receive from the 
barbarians, we improve and perfect ; there is good 
hope and promise, therefore, that Greeks will carry 
this knowledge far beyond that which was introduced 
from abroad." To this task, however, he looks with 
a due appreciation of the qualities and preparation 
which it requires. " An astronomer must be,'* he 
says, " the wisest of men ; his mind must be duly dis- 
ciplined in youth ; especially is mathematical study 
necessary ; both an acquaintance with the doctrine 
of number, and also with that other branch of matlie- 
matics, which, closely connected as it is with the 
science of the heavens^ we very absurdly call geometry^ 
tbe measurement of the earth*' T 

These anticipations were very remarkably verified 
in the subsequent career of the Greek astro- 
nomy. 

The theory, once suggested, probably made rapid 
progress. Simplicius* relates, that Eudoxus of 
Cnidus, introduced the hypothesis of revolving circles 
or spheres.. Calippus of Cyzicus, having visite4 
Polemarchus, an > intimate friend of Eudoxus, they 
went together to Athens, and communicated to Aris-t 

^ EpiAomis, pp. 988, 990. 

* Lib. ii. de Coelo. BuUialdus, p. 18. 

VOL. I. M 



162 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

totle the invention of Eudoxus, and with his help 
improved and corrected it. 

Probably at first this hypothesis was applied only 
to account for the general phenomena of the pro- 
gressions, retrogradations, and stations of the planet ; 
but it was soon found that the motions of the sun 
and moon, and the circular motions of the planets, 
which the hypothesis supposed, had anomalies or irre- 
gularities, which made a further extension of the 
hypothesis necessary. 

The defect of uniformity in these motions of the 
sun and moon, though less apparent than in the 
planets, is easily detected, as soon as men endeavour 
to obtain any accuracy in their observations. We 
have already stated (Chap. I.) that the Chaldeans 
were in possession of a period of about 18 years, 
which they used in the calculation of eclipses, and 
which might have been discovered by close observa- 
tion of the moon's motions ; although it was probably 
rather hit upon by noting the recurrence of eclipses. 
The moon moves in a manner which is not reducible 
to regularity without considerable care and time. 
If we trace her path among the stars, we find that, 
like the path of the sun, it is oblique to the equator, 
but it does not, like that of the sun, pass over the 
same stars in successive revolutions. Thus its lati^ 
tvde^ or distance from the equator, has ^ cycle different 
from its revolution among the stars ; and its nodes^ 
or the points where it cuts the equator, are per- 
petually changing their position. In addition to this, 
the moon's motion in her own path is not uniform ; in 



PRELUDE TO THE EPOCH OP mPPARCHUS. 169 

the course of eaeh lunation, she moves alternately 
slower and quicker, passing gradually through the 
intermediate degrees of velocity ; and goes through 
the cycle of these changes in something less than a 
month: this is called a revolution of anomaly. 
When the moon has gone through a complete 
number of revolutions of anomaly, and has, in the 
same time, returned to the same position with regard 
to the sun, and also with regard to her nodes, her 
motions with respect to the sun will be the same as 
at the first, and all the circumstances on which lunar 
eclipses depend being the same, the eclipses will 
occur in the same order. In 0586J days there are 
289 revolutions of anomaly, 241 revolutions with 
regard to one of the nodes, and, as we have said, 
223 lunations or revolutions with regard to the sun. 
Hence this period will bring about a succession of 
the same lunar eclipses. 

If the Chaldeans observed the moon's motion 
among the stars with any considerable accuracy, so 
as to detect this period by that means, they could 
hardly avoid discovering the anomaly or unequal 
motion of the moon ; for in every revolution, her 
daily progression in the heavens varies from about 
22 to 26 times her own diameter. But there is not. 
In the existence of this period, any evidence that 
they had measured the amount of this variation, 
and Delambre* is probably right in attributing all 
such observations to the Greeks. 

• A. A. i. 212. 

M 2 



164 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

The sun's motion would also be seen to be irre- 
gular as soon as men had any exact mode of deter- 
mining the lengths of the four seasons, by means of 
the passage of the sun through the equinoctial and 
solstitial points. For spring, summer, autumn, and 
winter, which would each consist of an equal num- 
ber of days if the motions were uniform, are, in fiu3t, 
found to be unequal in length. 

It was not very difficult to see that the mechanism 
of epicycles might be applied so as to explain irre- 
gularities of this kind. A wheel travelling round 
the earth, while it revolved upon its centre, might 
produce the effect of making the sun or moon fixed 
in its rim go sometimes faster and sometimes slower 
in appearance, just in the same way as the same 
suppositions would account for a planet going some- 
times forwards and sometimes backwards : the epi- 
cycles of the sun and moon would, for this purpose, 
be less than those of the planets. Accordingly, it 
is probable that, at the time of Plato and Aristotle, 
philosophers were already endeavouring to apply the 
hypothesis to these cases, though it does not appear 
that any one fully succeeded before Hipparchus. 

The problem which was thus present to the minds 
of astronomers, and which Plato is said to have pro- 
posed to them in a distinct form, was, " To reconcile 
the celestial phenomena by the combination of 
equable circular motions." That the circular mo- 
tions should likewise be equable, was a condition, 
which, if it had been merely tried at first, as the 



PRELUDE TO THE EPOCH OF HIPPARCHUS. 165 

most simple and definite conjecture, would have 
deserved praise. But this condition, which is, in 
reality, inconsistent with nature, was, in the sequel, 
adhered to with a pertinacity which introduced end- 
less complexity into the system. The history of 
this assumption is one of the most marked in- 
stances of that love of simplicity and symmetry, 
which is the source of all general truths, though it 
so often produces and perpetuates error. At pre- 
sent we can easily see how fancifully the notion of 
simplicity and perfection was interpreted, in the 
arguments by which the opinion was defended, that 
the real motions of the heavenly bodies must be cir- 
cular and uniform. The Pythagoreans, as well as 
the Platonists, maintained this dogma. According 
to Geminus, " They supposed the motions of the sun, 
and the moon, and the five planets, to be circular and 
equable : for they would not allow of such disorder 
among divine and eternal things, as that they should 
sometimes move quicker, and sometimes slower, and 
sometimes stand still; for no one would tolerate 
such anomaly in the movements, even of a man, who 
was decent and orderly. The occasions of life, how- 
ever, are often reasons for men going quicker or 
slower, but in the incorruptible nature of the stars, 
it is not possible that any cause can be alleged of 
quickness and slowness. Whereupon they pro- 
pounded this question, how the phenomena might be 
represented by equable and circular motions." 

These conjectures and assumptions led naturally 



166 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

to the establishment of the various parts of the 
theory of epicycles. It is probable that this theory 
was adopted tnth respect to the planets at or before 
the time of Plato. And Aristotle gives us an ac- 
count of the system thus devised ^ "Eudoxus," 
he says, "attributed four spheres to each planet: 
the first revolved with the fixed stars (and this pro- 
duced the diurnal motion); the second gave it a 
motion along the eclij)tic (the mean motion in 
longitude); the third had its axis perpendicular' to 
the ecliptic (and this gave the inequality of each 
planetary motion); the fourth produced the oblique 
motion transverse to this (the motion in latitude.)" 
He is also said to have attributed a motion in lati- 
tude and a corresponding sphere to the sun as well 
as to the moon, of which it is difficult to understand 
the meaning, if Aristotle has reported rightly of the 
theory ; for it would be absurd to ascribe to Eudoxus 
a knowledge of the motions by which the sun de- 
viates from the ecliptic. Calippus conceived that 
two additional spheres must be given to the sun and 
to the moon, in order to explain the phenomena : 
probably he was aware of the inequalities of the 
motions of these luminaries. He also proposed an 
additional sphere for each planet, to account, we may 

^ Metaph. xi. 8. 

® Aristotle says " has its poles in the ecliptic," hut this must 
he a mistake of his. He professes merely to receive these 
opinions flfom the professed astronomers "ck rrjs oiKttorarris 



PRELUDE TO THE EPOCH OF HIPPARCHUS. 167 

suppose, for the results of the eccentricity of the 
orbits. 

The hypothesis, in this form, does not appear to 
have been reduced to measure, and was, moreover, 
unnecessarily complex. The resolution of the 
oblique motion of the moon into two separate mo- 
tions, by Eudoxus, was not the simplest way of 
conceiving it ; and Calippus imagined the connexion 
of these spheres in some way which made it neces- 
sary nearly to double their number ; in this manner 
his system had no less than 55 spheres. 

Such was the progress which the idea of the hypo- 
thesis of epicycles had made in men's minds, pre- 
viously to the establishment of the theory by Hip- 
parchus. There had also been a preparation for 
this step, on the other side, by the collection of 
facts. We know that observations of the eclipses 
of the moon were made by the Chaldeans 367 
B.C. at Babylon, and were known to the Greeks; 
for Hipparchus and Ptolemy found their theory of 
the moon on these observations. Perhaps we can- 
not consider, as equally certain, the story that, at the 
time of Alexander's conquest, they had a series of 
observations, which went back 1903 years, and 
which Aristotle caused Callisthenes to bring to him 
in Greece. All the Greek observations, which are of 
any value, begin with the school of Alexandria. 
Aristyllus and Timocharis appear, by the citations 
of Hipparchus, to have observed the places of stars, 
and planets, and the times of the solstices, at various 



168 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

periods from b. c. 295 to b. c. 269. Without their 
observations, indeed, it would not have been easy for 
him to establish either the theory of the sun or the 
precession of the equinoxes. In order that observa- 
tions at distant intervals may be compared with each 
other, they must be referred to some common era. 
The Chaldeans dated by the era of Nabonassar, 
which commenced 749 B. c. The Greek observations 
were referred to the Calippic periods of 76 years, 
of which the first began 331 B. c. These are the 
dates used by Hipparchus and Ptolemy. 



169 



CHAPTER III. 

Inductive Epoch of Hipparchus. 



Sect, 1. — Establishment of the Theory of Epicycles 

and Eccentrics, 

Although, as we have already seen, the idea of 
epicycles had been suggested, the problem of its 
general application proposed, at the time of Plato, 
and the solutions offered by his followers, we still 
consider Hipparchus as the real discoverer and 
founder of that theory, inasmuch as he not only 
guessed that it mighty but showed that it musty 
account for the phenomena, both as to their nature 
and as to their quantity. The assertion that " he 
only discovers who proves," is just ; not only because, 
until a theory is proved to be the true one, it has no 
pre-eminence over the numerous other guesses 
among which it circulates, and above which the 
proof alone elevates it; but also because he who 
takes hold of the theory so as to apply calculation 
to it, possesses it with a distinctness of conception 
which makes it peculiarly his. 

In order to establish the theory of epicycles, it 
was necessary to assign the magnitudes, distances, 
and positions of the circles or spheres in which the 



170 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

heavenly bodies were moved, in such a manner as to 
account for their apparently irregular motions. We 
may best understand what was the problem to be 
solved by calling to mind what we now know to be 
the real motions of the heavens. The true motion 
of the earth round the sun, and therefore the appa- 
rent annual motion of the sun, is performed, not in 
a circle of which the earth is the centre, but' in an 
ellipse or oval, the earth being nearer to one end 
than to the other; and the motion is most rapid 
when the sun is at the nearer end of this oval. But 
instead of an oval, we may suppose the sun to move 
uniformly in a circle, the earth being now not in 
the centre, but nearer to one side ; for on this sup- 
position, the sun will appear to move most quickly 
when he is nearest to the earth, or in his perigee, as 
that point is called. Such an orbit is called an 
eccentric, and the distance of the earth from the 
centre of the circle is called the eccentricity. It may 
easily be shown by geometrical reasoning, that the 
inequality of apparent motion so produced, is exactly 
the same in detail, as the inequality which follows 
from the hypothesis of a small epicycle, turning uni- 
formly on its axis, and carrying the sun in its circum- 
ference, while the centre of this epicycle moves 
uniformly in a circle of which the earth is the centre. 
This identity of the results of the hjrpothesis of the 
eccentric and the epicycle is proved by Ptolemy in 
the third book of the " Almagest." 
The Sun's Eccentric. — When Hipparchus had clearly 



INDUCTIVE EPOCH OF HIPPARCHUS. 171 

conceived these hypotheses, as possible ways of ac- 
counting for the sun's motion, the task which he 
had to perform, in order to show that they deserved 
to be adopted, was to assign a place to the perigee^ a 
magnitude to the eccentricity^ and an epoch at which 
the sun was at the perigee ; and to show that, in this 
way, he had produced a true representation of the 
motions of the sun. This, accordingly, he did ; and 
having thus determined, with considerable exactness, 
both the law of the solar irregularities, and the num- 
bers on which their amount depends, he was able to 
assign the motions and places of the sun for any 
moment of future time with corresponding exact- 
ness ; he was able, in short, to construct Solar TaJbks^ 
by means of which the sun's place with respect to 
the stars could be correctly found at any time. 
These tables (as they are given by Ptolemy',) give 
the anomaly^ or inequality of the sun's motion ; and 
this they exhibit by means of the prosthapheresis, the 
quantity which, at any distance of the sun from the 
apogee^ it is requisite to add to or subtract from the 
arc, which he would have described if his motion 
had been equable. 

The reader might perhaps expect that the calcu- 
lations which thus exhibited the motions of the sun 
for an indefinite future period must depend upon a 
considerable number of observations made at all 
seasons of the year. That, however, was not the 

^ Syntax. 1. iii. 



172 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

case ; and the genius of the discoverer appeared, as 
it usually does appear, in his perceiving how small a 
number of fieu^ts, rightly considered, were sufficient 
to test the theory. The number of days contained 
in two seasons of the year sufficed for this purpose 
to Hipparchus. "Having ascertained," says Ptolemy, 
" that the time from the vernal equinox to the sum- 
mer tropic is 94i days, and the time from the sum- 
mer tropic to the autumnal equinox 92 i days, from 
these phenomena alone he demonstrates that the 
straight line joining the centre of the sun's eccentric 
path with the centre of the zodiac (the spectator's 
eye) is nearly the 24th part of the radius of the ec- 
centric path ; and that its apogee precedes the sum- 
mer solstice by 24i degrees nearly, the zodiac 
containing 360." 

The exactness of the Solar Tables, or Cavwn, which 
was founded on these data, was manifested, not only 
by the coincidence of the sun's calculated place 
with such observations as the Greek astronomers of 
this period were able to make, (which were indeed 
very rude,) but by its enabling them to calculate 
solar and lunar eclipses; phenomena which are a 
very precise and severe trial of the accuracy of such 
tables, inasmuch as a very minute change in the 
apparent place of the sun or moon would completely 
alter the obvious features of the eclipse. Though 
the tables of this period were by no means perfect, 
they bore with tolerable credit this trying and 
perpetually recurring test; and thus proved the 



INDUCTIVE EPOCH OF HIPPARCHUS. 173 

soundness of the theory on which the tables were 
calculated. 

The MoovCs Eccentric* — The moon's motions have 
many irregularities ; but when the hypothesis of an 
eccentric or an epicycle had sufficed in the case of 
the sun, it was natural to try to explain, in the same 
way, the motions of the moon ; and it was shown 
by Hipparchus that such hypotheses would account 
for the more obvious anomalies. It is not very easy 
to describe the several ways in which these hypo- 
theses were applied, for it is, in truth, very difficult to 
explain in words even the mere facts of the moon's 
motion. If she were to leave a visible bright line 
behind her in the heavens, wherever she moved, 
the path thus exhibited would be of an extremely 
complex nature ; the circle of each revolution slip- 
ping away from the preceding, and the traces of 
successive revolutions forming a sort of band of net- 
work running round the middle of the sky*. In 
each revolution, the motion in longitude is affected 
by an anomaly of the same nature as the sun's 
anomaly already spoken of; but besides this, the 
path of the moon deviates from the ecliptic to the 
north and to the south of the ecliptic, and thus she 
has a motion in latitude. This motion in latitude is 
sufficiently known if we knew the period of its 
restoration^ that is, the time which the moon occu- 

■ The reader will find an attempt to make the nature of this 
path generally intelligible in the Companion to the British 
Almanadk for 1834. 



174 THE GREEK ASTRONOBTSr. 

pies in moving from any latitude till she is restored 

• 

to the same latitude; as, for instance, from the 
ecliptic on one side of the heavens to the ecliptic on 
the same side of the heavens again. But it is found 
that the period of the restoration of the latitude is 
not the same as the period of the restoration of the 
longitude, that is, as the period of the moon's revo- 
lution among the stars ; and thus the moon describes 
a different path among the stars in every successive 
revolution, and her path, as well as her velocity, is 
constantly variable. 

Hipparchus, however, reduced the motions of the 
moon to rule and to Tables, as he did those of the 
sun, and in the same manner. He determined, with 
much greater accuracy than any preceding astrono- 
mer, the mean or supposed equable motions of the 
moon in longitude and in latitude; and he then 
represented the anomaly of the motion in longitude 
by means of an eccentric, in the same manner as he 
had done for the sun. 

But here there occurred still an additional change, 
besides those of which we have spoken. The apogee 
of the sun was always in the same place in the 
heavens ; or at least so nearly so, that Ptolemy could 
detect no error in the place assigned to it by Hip- 
parchus 250 years before. But the apogee of the 
moon was found to have a motion among the stars. 
It had been observed before the time of Hipparchus, 
that in 6585^ days, there are 241 revolutions of the 
moon with regard to the stars, but only 239 revolu- 



INDUCTIVE EPOCH OF HIPPARCHUS. 175 

tions with regard to the anomaly. This difference 
could be suitably represented by supposing the 
eccentric, in which the moon moves, to have itselt 
an angular motion, perpetually carrying its apogee 
in the same direction in which the moon travels ; 
but this supposition being made, it was necessary to 
determine, not only the eccentricity of the orbit, and 
place of the apogee at a certain time, but also the 
rate of motion of the apogee itself, in order to form 
tables of the moon. 

This task, as we have said, Hipparchus executed ; 
and in this instance, as in the problem of the reduc- 
tion of the sun's motion to tables, the data which he 
found it necessary to employ were very few. He 
deduced all his conclusions from six eclipses of the 
moon'. Three of these, the records of which were 
brought from Babylon, where a register of such oc- 
currences was kept, happened in the 366th and 
367th years from the era of Nabonassar, and enabled 
Hipparchus to determine the eccentricity and apogee 
of the moon's orbit at that time. The three others 
were observed at Alexandria, in the 547th year of 
Nabonassar, which gave him another position of the 
orbit at an interval of 180 years ; and he thus be- 
came acquainted with the motion of the orbit itself 
as well as its form*. 

The moon's motions are really affected by several 

• Ptol. Syn. iv. 10. 

* Ptolemy uses the hypothesis of an epicycle for the moon's 
first inequality: hut Hipparchus employs the eccentric. 



176 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

other inequalities, of very considerable amount, 
besides those which were thus considered by Hip- 
parchus; but the lunar p^aths, constructed on the 
above data, possessed a considerable degree of cor- 
rectness, and especially when applied, as they were 
principally, to the calculation of eclipses; for the 
greatest of the additional irregularities which we 
have mentioned disappear at new and full moon. 

The numerical explanation of the motions of the 
sun and moon, by means of the hypothesis of eccen- 
trics, and the consequent construction of tables, was 
one of the great achievements of Hipparchus. The 
generkl explanation of the motions of the planets, 
by means of the hypothesis of epicycles, was in 
circulation previously, as we have seen. The mo- 
tions of the planets, in their epicycles, are, in reality, 
ajSected by anomalies of the same kind as those 
which render it necessary to introduce eccentrics in 
the cases of the sun and moon. 

Hipparchus determined, with great exactness, the 
mean motions of the planets ; but he was not able, 
from want of data, to explain the planetary irregu- 
larities by means of eccentrics. The whole mass of 
good observations of the planets which he received 
from preceding ages, did not contain so many, says 
Ptolemy, as those which he has transmitted to us of 
his own. " Hence* it was," he adds, " that while he 
laboured, in the most assiduous manner, to represent 

* Synt. ix. 2. 



INDUCTIVE EPOCH OF HIPPARCHUS. 177 

the motions of the sun and moon by means of 
equable circular motions; with respect to the 
planets, so far as his works show, he did not even 
make the attempt, but merely put the extant obser- 
vations in order, added to them himself more than 
the whole of what he received from preceding ages, 
and showed the insufficiency of the hjrpothesis 
current among astronomers to explain the pheno- 
mena." It appears, that preceding mathematicians 
had already pretended to construct "a perpetual 
canon," that is, tables which should give the places 
of the planets at any future time ; but these, being 
constructed without regard to the eccentricity of the 
orbits, must have been very erroneous. 

Ptolemy declares, with great reason, that Hippar- 
chus showed his usual love of truth, and his right 
sense of the responsibility of his task, in leaving this 
part of it to future ages. The theories of the sun 
and moon, which we have already described, consti- 
tute him a great astronomical discoverer, and justify 
the reputation he has always possessed. There is, 
indeed, no philosopher who is so uniformly spoken 
of in terms of admiration. Ptolemy, to whom we owe 
our principal knowledge of him, perpetually couples 
with his name epithets of praise : he is not only an 
excellent and carefiil observer, but " a" most truth- 
loving and labour-loving person," one who had shown 
extraordinary sagacity and remarkable desire of truth 

• Synt. ix. 2. 
VOL. I. N 



178 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

in every part of science." Pliny, after mentioning 
him and Thales, breaks out into one of his passages 
of declamatory vehemence ; " Great men ! elevated 
above the common standard of human nature, by 
discovering the laws which celestial occurrences 
obey, and by freeing the wretched mind of man 
from the fears which eclipses inspired. — Hail to you 
and to your genius, interpreters of heaven, worthy 
recipients of the laws of the universe, authors of 
principles which connect gods and men !" Modem 
writers have spoken of Hipparchus with the same 
admiration ; and even the exact but severe historian 
of astronomy, Delambre, who bestows his praise so 
sparingly, and his sarcasm so generally ; — ^who says^ 
that it is unfortunate for the memory of Aristarchus 
that his work has come to us entire, and who cannot 
refer" to the statement of an eclipse rightly predicted 
by Halicon of Cyzicus without adding, that if the story 
be true, Halicon was more lucky than prudent ;— 
loses all his bitterness when he comes to Hipparchus*. 
" In Hipparchus," says he, " we find one of the most 
extraordinary men of antiquity ; the 'oery greaJbesU in 
the sciences which require a combination of observa- 
tion with geometry." Delambre adds, apparently 
in the wish to reconcile this eulogium with the de- 
preciating manner in which he habitually speaks of 
all astronomers whose observations are inexact, ^^ a 
long period and the continued efforts of many indus- 

^ i. 75. « i. 17- ' i. 186. 



INDUCTIVE EPOCH OF HIPPARCHUS. 179 

trious men are requisite to produce good instru- 
ments, but energy and assiduity depend on the man 
himself." 

Hipparchus was the author of other great dis- 
coveries and improvements in astronomy, besides 
the establishment of the doctrine of eccentrics and 
epicycles; but this, being the greatest advance in 
the theory of the celestial motions which was made 
by the ancients, must be the leading subject of our 
attention in the present work ; our object being to 
discover in what the progress of real theoretical 
knowledge consists, and under what circumstances 
it has gone on. 

Sect 2. — Estimate of the Value of the Theory of 

Eccentrics and Epicycles. 

It may be useful here to explain the value of the 
theoretical step which Hipparchus thus made ; and 
the more so, as there are, perhaps, opinions in 
popular circulation, which might lead men to think 
lightly of the merit of introducing or establishing 
the doctrine of epicycles. For, in the first place, 
this doctrine is now acknowledged to be false ; and 
some of the greatest men in the more modern his- 
tory of astronomy owe the brightest part of their 
fame to their having been instrumental in over- 
turning this hypothesis. And, moreover, in the 
next place, the theory is not only false, but ex- 
tremely perplexed and entangled, so that it is usually 

N 2 



180 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

conceived as a mass of arbitrary and absurd compli- 
cation. Most persons are familiar with passages in 
which it is thus spoken of '°. 

He his fabric of the heavens 

Hath left to their disputes, perhaps to more 
His laughter at their quaint opinions wide ; 
Hereafter when thej come to model heaven 
And calculate the stars, how will they wield 
The mighty frame ! how build, unbuild, contrive, 
To save appearances! how gird the sphere 
With centric and eccentric scribbled o'er, 
Cycle in epicycle, orb in orb! 

And every one will recollect the celebrated saying 
of Alphonso X., king of Castile ^^ when this com- 
plex system was explained to him; that "if God 
had consulted him at the creation, the universe 
should have been on a better and simpler plan." 
In addition to this, the system is represented as 
involving an extravagant conception of the nature 
of the orbs which it introduces ; — ^that they are crys- 
talline spheres, and that the vast spaces which inter- 
vene between the celestial luminaries are a solid mass, 
formed by the fitting together of many masses per- 
petually in motion; an imagination which is pre- 
sumed to be incredible and monstrous. 

We must endeavour to correct or remove these 
prejudices, not only in order that we may do justice 
to the Hipparchian, or, as it is usually called, Ptole- 
maic system of astronomy, and to its founder ; but 

^•P. L. viii. ^^ A.D. 1252. 



INDUCTIVE EPOCH OF HIPPAKCHUS. 181 

for another reason, much more important to the pur- 
pose of this work ; namely, that we may see how 
theories may be highly estimable, though they 
contain false representations of the real state of 
things, and may be extremely useful, though they 
involve unnecessary complexity. In the advance of 
knowledge, the value of the true part of a theory 
may much outweigh the accompanying error, and 
the use of a rule may be little impaired by its want of 
simplicity. The first steps of our progress do not 
lose their importance because they are not the last ; 
and the outset of the journey may require no less 
vigour and activity than its close. 

That which is true in the Hipparchian theory, and 
which no succeeding discoveries have deprived of its 
value, is the resolution of the apparent motions of 
the heavenly bodies into an assemblage of circular 
motions. The test of the truth and reality of this 
resolution is, that it leads to the construction of 
theoretical tables of the motions of the luminaries, 
by which their places are given at any time, agreeing 
nearly with their places as actually observed. The 
assumption that these circular motions, thus intro- 
duced, are all exactly uniform, is the fundamental 
principle of the whole process. This assumption is, 
it may be said, false ; and we have seen how fantastic 
some of the arguments were, which were originally 
urged in its favour. But some assumption is neces- 
sary, in order that the motions, at different points 
of a revolution may be somewhat connected, that is, 



182 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

in order that we may have any theory of the motions ; 
and no assumption more simple than the one now 
mentioned can be selected. The merit of the theory is 
this ; — that obtaining the amount of the eccentricity, 
the place of the apogee, and, it may be, other elements, 
from a fm observations, it deduces from these, 
results agreeing with a// observations, however nume- 
rous and distant. To express an inequality by means 
of an epicycle, implies not only that there is an in- 
equality, but further ; — that the inequality is at its 
greatest value at a certain known place ; — diminishes 
in proceeding from that place by a known law ; — 
continues its diminution for a known portion of 
the revolution of the luminary; — then increases 
again ; and so on : that is, the introduction of the 
epicycle represents the inequality of motion, as com- 
pletely as it can be represented with respect to its 
quantity. 

We may further illustrate this, by remarking that 
such a resolution of the unequal motions of the hear 
venly bodies into equable circular motions, is, in fact, 
equivalent to the most recent and improved processes 
by which modem astronomers deal with such motions. 
Their universal method is to resolve all unequal 
motions into a series of terms^ or expressions of par- 
tial motions; and these terms involve sines and 
cosines^ that is, certain technical modes of measuring 
circular motion, the circular motion having some 
constant relation to the time. And thus the pro- 
blem of the resolution of the celestial motions into 



INDUCTIVE EPOCH OF HIPPARCHUS. 183 

equable circular ones, which was propounded above 
two thousand years ago in the school of Plato, is 
still the great object of the study of modem astro- 
nomers, whether observers or calculators. 

That Hipparchus should have succeeded in the 
first great steps of this resolution for the sun and 
moon, and should have seen its applicability in other 
cases, is a circumstance which gives him one of the 
most distinguished places in the roll of great astro- 
nomers. As to the charges or the sneers against 
the complexity of his system, to which we have 
referred, it is easy to see that they are of no force. 
As a system of calculation, his is not only good, but, 
as we have just said, in many cases no better has 
yet been discovered. If, when the actual motions 
of the heavens are calculated in the best possible 
way, the process is complex and difficult, and if we 
are discontented at this, nature, and not the astrono- 
mer, must be the object of our displeasure. This 
plea of the astronomers must be allowed to be 
reasonable. "We must not be repelled," says 
Ptolemy'*, "by the complexity of the hypotheses, 
but explain the phenomena as well as we can. If 
the hypotheses satisfy each apparent inequality 
separately, the combination of them will represent 
the truth ; and why should it appear wonderful to 
any that such a complexity should exist in the 
heavens, when we know nothing of their nature 



IS 



Synt. xiii. 2. 



184 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

which entitles us to suppose that any inconsistency 
will result ?" 

But it may be said, we now know that the mo- 
tions are more simple than they were thus repre- 
sented, and that the theory of epicycles was false, 
as a conception of the real construction of the 
heavens. And to this we may reply, that it does 
not appear that the best astronomers of antiquity 
conceived the cycles and epicycles to have a material 
existence. Though the dogmatic philosophers, as 
Aristotle, appear to have taught that the celestial 
spheres were real solid bodies, they are spoken of by 
Ptolemy as imaginary'^; and it is clear, from his 
proof of the identity of the results of the hypothesis 
of an eccentric and an epicycle, that they are in- 
tended to pass for no more than geometrical concep- 
tions, in which view they are true representations 
of the apparent motions. 

It is true, that the real motions of the heavenly 
bodies are simpler than the apparent motions ; and 
that we, who are in the habit of representing to our 
minds their real arrangement, become impatient of 
the seeming confusion and disorder of the ancient 
hypotheses. But this real arrangement never could 
have been detected by philosophers, if the apparent 
motions had not been strictly examined and success- 
fiiUy analyzed. How far the connexion between the 
facts and the true theory is from being obvious or 



18 



Synt. iii. 3. 



INDUCTIVE EPOCH t)F HIPPARCHUS. 185 

easily traced, any one may satisfy himself by en- 
deavouring, from a general conception of the moon's 
real motions, to discover the rules which regulate 
the occurrences of eclipses ; or even to explain to a 
learner, of what nature the apparent motions of the 
moon among the stars will be. 

The unquestionable evidence of the merit and 
value of the theory of epicycles is to be found in 
this circumstance ; — ^that it served to embody all the 
most exact knowledge then extant, to direct astro- 
nomers to the proper methods of making it more 
exact and complete, to point out new objects of 
attention and research ; and that, after doing this at 
first, it was also able to take in, and preserve, all the 
new results of the active and persevering labours of 
a long series of Greek, Latin, Arabian, and modem 
European astronomers, till a new theory arose which 
could discharge this ofBce. It may, perhaps, surprise 
some readers to be told, that the author of this next 
great step in astronomical theory, Copernicus, adopted 
the theory of epicycles ; that is, he employed that 
which we have spoken of as its really valuable charac- 
teristic. " We ^* must confess," he says, " that the 
celestial motions are circular, or compounded of 
several circles, since their inequalities observe a 
fixed law and recur in value at certain intervals, which 
could not be, except they were circular ; for a circle 
alone can make that which has been, recur again." 

^* Copernicus. De Rev. 1. i, c. 4. 



186 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

In this sense, therefore, the Hipparchian theory 
was a real and indestructible truth, which was not 
rejected, and replaced by different truths, but adopted 
and incorporated into every succeeding astronomical 
theory ; and which can never cease to be one of the 
most important and fundamental parts of our astro- 
nomical knowledge. 

A moment's reflection will show that, in the 
events just spoken of, the introduction and esta- 
^ blishment of the theory of epicycles, those characte- 
ristics were strictly exemplified, which we have 
asserted to be the conditions of every real advance 
in progressive science; namely, the application of 
distinct and appropriate ideas to a real series of 
facts. The distinctness of the geometrical concep- 
tions which enabled Hipparchus to assign the orbits 
of the sun and moon, requires no illustration ; and 
we have just explained how these ideas combined 
into a connected whole the various motions and 
places of those luminaries. To make this step in 
astronomy, required diligence and care exerted in 
collecting observations, mathematical clearness and 
steadiness of view exercised in seeing and showing 
that the theory was a successful analysis of the 
observations. 

Sect. 3. — Discacery of the Precession of the 

Equinoxes. 

The same qualities which we trace in the researches 
of Hipparchus already examined, — diligence in col- 



INDUCTIVE EPOCH OF HIPPARCHUS. 187 

lecting observations, and clearness of idea in repre- 
senting them, — appear also in other discoveries of his, 
which we must not pass unnoticed. The precession 
of the equinoxes, in particular, is one of the most 
important of these discoveries. 

The circumstance here brought into notice was a 
change of longitude of the fixed stars. The longi- 
tudes of the heavenly bodies being measured from the 
point where the sun's annual path cuts the equator, 
will change if that path changes. Whether this hap- 
pens, however, is not very easy to decide ; for the sun's 
path among the stars is made out, not by merely look- 
ing at the heavens, but by a series of inferences from 
ether observable facts. Hipparchus used for this pur- 
pose eclipses of the moon ; for these, being exactly 
opposite to the sun, afford data in marking out his 
path. By comparing the eclipses of his own time with 
those observed at an earlier period by Timocharis. 
he found that the bright star, Spica Virginis, was six 
degrees from the equinoctial point in his own time, 
and had been eight degrees distant from the same 
point at an earlier epoch. The suspicion was thus 
suggested, that the longitudes of all the stars increase 
perpetually ; but Hipparchus had too truly philoso- 
phical a spirit to take this for granted. He examined 
the places of Regulus, and those of other stars, 
as he had done those of Spica; and he found, in 
all these instances, a change of place which could 
be explained by a certain alteration of position in 
the circles to which the stars are referred, which 



188 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

alteration is described as the Precession of the 
Equinoxes. 

The distinctness with which Hipparchus conceived 
this change of relation in the heavens, is manifested 
by the question which, as we are told by Ptolemy, 
he examined and decided ; — ^that this motion of the 
heavens takes place about the poles of the ecliptic 
and not of the equator. The care with which he 
collected this motion from the stars themselves, may 
be judged of from this, that having made his first 
observations for this purpose on Spica and Regulus, 
zodiacal stars, his first suspicion was that the stars of 
the zodiac alone changed their longitude. The idea 
of the nature of the motion, and the evidence of its 
existence, the two conditions of a discovery, were 
also fiilly brought into view. The scale of the facts 
which Hipparchus was thus able to reduce to law, 
may be in some measure judged of, by recollecting 
that the precession, from his time to ours, has only 
carried the stars through one sign of the zodiac; 
and that» to complete one revolution of the sky by 
the motion thus discovered, would require a period of 
25,000 years. Thus this discovery connected the 
various aspects of the heavens at the most remote 
periods of human history; and, accordingly, the 
novel and ingenious views which Newton published 
in his chronology, are founded on this single astro- 
nomical fact, of the precession of the equinoxes. 

The two discoveries which have been described, 
the mode of constructing solar and lunar tables, and 



INDUCTIVE EPOCH OF HIPPARCHUS. 189 

the precession, were advances of the greatest im- 
portance in astronomy, not only in themselves, but 
in the new objects and undertakings which they 
suggested to astronomers. The one detected a con- 
stant law and order in the midst of perpetual change 
and apparent disorder ; the other disclosed mutation 
and movement perpetually operating where every- 
thing had been supposed fixed and stationary. Such 
discoveries were well adapted to call up many 
questionings in the minds of speculative men ; for, 
after this, nothing could be supposed constant till it 
had been ascertained to be so by close examina- 
tion ; and no apparent complexity or confusion could 
justify the philosopher in turning away in despair 
from the task of simplification. To answer the 
inquiries thus suggested, new methods of observing 
the facts were requisite, more exact and uniform 
than those hitherto employed. Moreover the dis- 
coveries which were made, and others which could 
not fail to follow in their train, led to many conse- 
quences, required to be reasoned upon, systematized, 
completed, enlarged. In short, the epoch of indtection 
led, as we have stated that such epochs must always 
lead, to a period of developement, of verification, appli-- 
catioUf and ewtefision. 



190 



CHAPTER lY. 



Sequel to the Inductive Epoch of Hipparchus. 



Sect. 1. — Researches which verified the Theorjf. 

The discovery of the leading laws of the solar and 
lunar motions, and the detection of the precession, 
may be considered as the great positive steps in the 
Hipparchian astronomy; — ^the parent discoveries, from 
which many minor improvements proceeded. The 
task of preserving the collateral and consequent re- 
searches which now offered themselves, — of bringing 
the other parts of astronomy up to the level of its 
most improved portions, — ^was prosecuted by a suc- 
cession of zealous observers and calculators, first, in 
the school of Alexandria, and afterwards in other 
parts of the world. We must notice the various 
labours of this series of astronomers ; but we shall 
do so very briefly ; for the ulterior developement of 
doctrines once established, is not so important an 
object of contemplation for our present purpose, as 
the first conception and proof of those fundamental 
truths on which systematic doctrines are founded. 
Yet periods of verification, as well as epochs of 
induction, deserve to be attended to ; and they can 



SEQUEL TO THE EPOCH OF HIPPARCHUS. 191 

nowhere be studied with so much advantage as in 
the history of astronomy. 

In truth, however, Hipparchus did not leave to 
his successors the task of pursuing into detail those 
views of the heavens to which his discoveries led 
him. He examined with scrupulous care almost 
every part of the subject. We must briefly mention 
some of the principal points which were thus settled 
by him. 

The verification of the laws of the changes which 
he assigned to the skies, impUed that the condition 
of the heavens was constant, except so far as it was 
affected by those changes. Thus, the doctrine that 
the changes of position of the stars were rightly 
represented by t)ie precession of the equinoxes, 
supposed that the stars were fixed with regard to 
each other; and the doctrine that the unequal 
number of days, in certain subdivisions of months 
and years, was acfequately explained by the theory 
of epicycles, asstfmed that years and days were 
always of constatit iiengths. But Hipparchus was 
not content with assi^ing these bases of his theory, 
he endeavoured to prove them. 

1. Fixity of tke Stars. The question necessarily 
arose after the discovery of the precession, even if 
such a question had never suggested itself before, 
whether the stars which were called fixed, and to 
which the motions of the other luminaries are re- 
ferred, do really retain constantly the same relative 
position. In ord^r to determine this fundamental 



192 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

question, Hipparchus undertook to constract a Map 
of the heavens ; for though the result of his survey 
was expressed in words, we may give this name to 
his Catalogue of the positions of the most conspi- 
cuous stars. These positions are described by means 
of alineaiions ; that is, three or more such stars are 
selected as can be touched by an apparent straight 
line drawn in the heavens. Thus Hipparchus ob- 
served that the southern claw of Cancer, the bright 
star in the same constellation which precedes the 
head of the Hydra, and the bright star Procyon, 
were nearly in the same line. Ptolemy quotes this 
and many other of the configurations which Hip- 
parchus had noted, in order to show that the 
positions of the stars had not changed in the 
intermediate time ; a truth which the catalogue of 
Hipparchus thus gave astronomers the means of 
ascertaining. It contained 1080 stars. 

The construction of this catalogue of the stars by 
Hipparchus is an event of great celebrity in the 
history of astronomy. Pliny \ who speaks of it with 
admiration as a wonderful and superhuman task 
(" ausus rem etiam Deo improbam, annumerare pos- 
teris Stellas") asserts the undertaking to have been 
suggested by a remarkable astronomical event, the 
appearance of a new star ; " novam stellam et aliam 
in aevo suo genitam deprehendit ; ejusque motu, qua 
die fulsit, ad dubitationem est adductus anne hoc 

* lib. ii. (xxyi.) 



SEQUEL TO THE EPOCH OF HIPPARCHUS. 193 

ssepius fieret, moverenturque et ese quas putamus 
affixas." There is nothing inherently improbable in 
this tradition, but we may observe, with Delambre% 
that we are not informed whether this new star 
remained in the sky or soon disappeared again. 
Ptolemy makes no mention of the star or the story ; 
and his catalogue contains no bright star which is 
not found in the <* Catasterisms" of Eratosthenes. 
These Catasterisms were an enumeration of 475 of 
the principal stars» according to the constellations in 
which they are; and were published about sixty 
years before Hipparehus. 

2. Constant Length of Ymrs. — Hipparehus also 
attempted to ascertain whether successive years are 
all of the same length ; and though, with his scru- 
pulous love of accuracy", he does not appear to have 
thought himself justified in asserting that the years 
Were always exactly equal, he showed, both by ob- 
servations of the time when the sun passed the 
equinoxes, and by eclipses, that the difference of 
successive y^rs, if there were any difference, must 
be extremely slight. ~ The observations of succeeding 
astronomers, and especially of Ptolemy, confirmed 
this opinion, and proved, with certainty, that there 
is no progressive increase or diminution in the durar 
tion of the year. 

3. CcThstant Length of Days. JEquation ofTime*'-^ 
The eqiiality of days was more difficult to ascertain 
than that of years ; for the year is measured, as on 

■ A. A. i. 290. . • Ptolem. Synt. iii. 2. 

VOL. I. O 



194 THS GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

a natural scale, by the number of days which it 
contains ; but the day can be subdivided into hours 
only by artificial means; and the medbanical skill 
of the ancients did not enable them to attain any 
conriderable accuracy in the measure of such por- 
tions of time ; though clepsydras and similar instru<« 
ments were used by astronomers. The equality of 
days could only be proved, therefore, by the cons&« 
quences of such a supposition ; and in this manner 
it appears to have been assumed, as the ftict really 
is, that the apparent revolution of the stars is acoUf^ 
rately uniform, never becoming either quicker or 
slower. It followed as a consequence of this, that 
the solar days (or rather the nycthemerSf compounded 
of a night and a day,) would be unequal, in conse* 
quence of tiie sun's unequal motion, thus giving rise 
to what we now call the equaiUon of time ;«^the in* 
terval by which the time, as marked on a dial, is 
before or after the time, as indicated by the accurate 
time-pieces which modem skill can produce. This 
inequality was fully taken account of by the anci^at 
astronomers, which was in fact assuming the equa^- 
lity of the sidereal days. 

Sect 2. — Researches which did not verify the Theory. 

Some of the researches of Hipparchus and his fol- 
lowers fell upon the weak parts of his theory ; and 
if the observations had been sufficiently exact, must 
have led to its being corrected or rented. 

Among these we may notice the researches which 



SEQUEL TO THE EPOCH OF HIPPABCHUS. 106 

vrere made oonceming the ParaUaa? of the heayenly 
bodies, that is^ their apparent displacement by the 
alteration of position of the observer from one part of 
the earth's sur&ce to the other. This subject is 
treated of at length by Ptolemy ; and there can be 
no doubt that it was well examined by Hipparchus, 
who inyented a paraUacHc dnstrumerU for that pur^ 
pose. The idea of parallax, as a geometrical pos« 
sibility, was indeed too obvious to be overlooked at 
any time ; and in the period of establishment of the 
doctrine of the sphere, it must have appeared 
strange, that every place on the earth's surface might 
aUke be considered as the centre of the celestial 
motions* But if this vras true with respect to tihe 
motions of the fixed stars, was it also true with 
regard to those of the sun and moon ? The displace* 
ment of the sun by parallax is so small that the best 
observers among the ancients could never be sure 
of its existence : but with respect to the moon, the 
case is different. She may be displaced by this 
cause to the amount of twice her own breadth, a 
quantity easily noticed by the rudest process of in* 
Btrumental observation. The law of the displace* 
ment thus produced is easily obtained by theory, the 
globular form of the earth being supposed known ; 
but the amount of the displacement depends upon 
the distance of the moon from the earth, and requires 
at least one good observation to determine it. Pto- 
lemy has given a table of the effects of parallax, 
calculated according to the apparent altitude of the 

o 2 



196 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

moon, assuming certain supposed distances; these 
distances, however, do not follow the real law of the 
moon's distances, in consequence of their being 
founded upon the hypothesis of the eccentric and 
epicycle. 

In &ct this hypothesis, though a very close repre^ 
sentation of the truth, so &r as the positions of the 
luminaries sure concerned, £sdls altogether when we 
apply it to their distances. The radius of the epi- 
cycle, or the eccentricity of the eccentric, are deter-i 
mined so as to satisfy the observations of the 
apparent motions of the bodies : but, inasmuch as 
the hypothetical motions are different altogether 
from the ireal motions, the hypothesis does not, at 
the same time, satisfy the observations of the di&r 
tances of the bodies, if we are able to make any such 
observations. 

Parallax is one method by which the distances of 
the moon, at different times, may be compared ; her 
apparent diameters afford another method. Neither 
of these modes, however, is easily capable of such 
accuracy as to overturn at once the hypothesis of 
epicycles ; and, accordingly, the hypothesis continued 
to be entertained in spite of such measures; the 
measures being in some degree falsified in conse- 
quence of the reigning opinion. In fact, however, 
the imperfection of the methods of measuring pa- 
rallax and magnitude, which. were in use at this 
period, was such, that the results could not lead to 
any degree of conviction deserving to be set in op- 



SEQUEL TO THE EPOCH OF HIPPARCHUS, 19/ 

position to a theory which was so satisfactory with 
regard to the more certain observations. 

The eccentricity, or the radius of the epicycle, 
which would satisfy the inequality of the motions of 
the moon, would, in fact, double the inequality of 
the distances. The eccentricity of the moon's orbit 
is determined by Ptolemy as ^ of the radius of the 
orbit ; but its real amount is only half as great ; this 
difference is a necessary consequence of the sup- 
position of uniform circular motions, on which the 
epicyclic hypothesis proceeds. 

We see, therefore, that this part of the Hippar* 
chian theoiy carries in itself the germ of its own 
destruction. As soon as the art of celestial measure- 
ment was so far perfected, that astronomers could 
be sure of the apparent diameter of the moon within 
Jjj or ij of the whole, the inconsistency of the theory 
with itself would become manifest. We shall see, 
hereafter, the way in which this inconsistency 
operated ; in reality, a very long period elapsed before 
the methods of observing were sufficiently good to 
bring it clearly into view. 

Sect. 3. — Methods of Observation of the Cheek 

Astronomers. 

We must now say a word concerning the methods 
above spoken of. Since one of the most important 
tasks of a period of verification, is to ascertain with 
accuracy the magnitude of the quantities which enter, 
as elements, into .the theory which signalizes the 



198 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

period ; the improTement of instruments, and me- 
thods of observing and experimenting, are principal 
features in such periods. We shall, therefore, men- 
tion some of the facts which bear upon this point. 

The estimation of distances among the stars by 
the eye, is an extremely inexact process. In some 
of the ancient observations, however, this appears to 
be the method employed : and stars are described as 
being a cubit or tivo cubits from other stars. We 
may form some notion of the scale of this kind of 
measurement, from what Cleomedes remarks*, that 
the sun appears to be about a foot broad ; an opinion 
which he conftites at length. 

A method of determining the positions of the 
stars, susceptible of a little more exactness that the 
former, is the use of allneations, already noticed in 
speaking of Hipparchus's catalogue. Thus, a straight 
line passing through two stars of the Great Bear 
passes also through the pole-star: this is, indeed, 
even now a method usually employed to enable us 
readily to fix on the pole-star ; and the two stars, 
fi and a of Ursa Major, are hence often called " the 
pointers." 

But nothing like accurate measurements of any 
portions of the sky were obtained, till astronomers 
adopted the method of making visual coincidences 
of the objects with the instruments, either by means 
of shadoujs or of sights. 

Probably the oldest and most obvious measure- 

* Del. ^. A. i. 222. 



SEQUEL TO THE EPOCH OP HIPPARCHUS. 199 

ments of the poBitions of the heavenly bodies were 
those in which the elevation of the sun was detennined 
by comparing the length of the shadow of an up- 
right staff or gnomon^ with the length of the staff 
itself. ^^It appears \ from a memoir of Gautil, first 
printed in the Connaissance des Temps for 1809, that, 
at the lower town of Loyang, now called Hon«an- 
fou, Tchon-kong found the length of the shadow of 
the gnomon, at the summer solstice, equal to one 
foot and a half, the gnomon itself being eight feet 
in length." This was about 1100 B. o. The Greeks, 
at an early period, used the same method. Strabo 
says' that ^^ Byzantium and Marseilles are on the 
same parallel of latitude, because the shadows at 
those places have the same proportion to the gnomon, 
according to the statement of Hipparchus, who fol- 
lows Pytheas." 

But the relations of position which astronomy 
considers, are, for the most part, angular distances ; 
and these are most simply expressed by the inter- 
cepted portion of a circumference described about 
the angular point. The use of the gnomon might 
lead to the determination of the angle by the gra- 
phical methods of geometry; but the numerical 
expression of the circumference required some pro- 
gress in trigonometry ; for instance, a table of the 
tangents of angles. 

Instruments were soon invented for measuring 
angles, by means of circles, which had a border, or limb^ 

* lib. U. K. Hist. A«t. p. 5. • Del. A. A. i. 257. 



200 THE GBEBK ASTRONOMY. 

divided into equal parts. The whole circumference 
was divided into 360 degrees : perhaps because the 
circles, first so divided, were those which represented 
the sun's annual path ; one auch degree would be 
the sun's daily advance, more nearly than any other 
convenient aliquot part which could be taken. The 
position of the sun was determined by means of the 
shadow of one part of the instrument upon the other. 
The most ancient instrument of this kind appears to 
be the Hemisphere of Berosus. A hollow hemisphere 
was placed with its rim horizontal, and a style was 
erected in such a manner that the extremity of the 
style was exactly at the centre of the sphere. The 
shadow of this extremity, on the concave sur&ce, 
had the same position with regard to the lowest 
point of the sphere which the sun had with regard 
to the highest point of the heavens. But this instru- 
ment was in fact used rather for dividing the day 
into portions of time than for determining position. 

Eratosthenes' observed the amount of the oblir 
quity of the sun's path to the equator ; we are not 
informed what instruments he used for this purpose : 
but he is said to have obtained, from the munificence 
of Ptolemy Euergetes, two Armils, or instruments 
composed of circles, which were placed in the portico 
at Alexandria, and long used for observations. If a 
circular rim were placed so as to coincide with the 
direction of the equator, the inner concave edge 
would be enlightened by the sun's rays which came 

^ Delambre, A. A« i. 86. 



SEQUEL TO THE EPOCH OF HIPPARCHUS. 201 

under the front edge, wken the sun was south of the 
equator, and by the rays which came over the front 
edge, when the sun was north of the equator : the 
moment of the transition would be the time of the 
equinox. Such an instrument appears to be referred 
to by Hipparchus, as quoted by Ptolemy*. " The 
circle of copper, which stands at Alexandria in what 
is called the Square Porch, appears to mark, as the 
day of the equinox, that on which the concave sur- 
iace begins to be enlightened from the other side." 
Such an instrument was called an equinoctial armil. 

A solstitial armil is described by Ptolemy, con- 
sisting of two circular rims, one sliding round within 
the other, and the inner one frimished with two pegs 
standing out from its surface, and diametrically op- 
posite to each other. These circles being fixed in 
the plane of the meridian, and the inner one 
turned, till, at noon, the shadow of the peg in front 
falls upon the peg behind, the position of the sun at 
noon would be determined by the degrees on the 
outer circle. 

In calculation, the degree was conceived to be 
divided into 60 minutes^ the minute into 60 seconds^ 
and so on. But in practice it was impossible to 
divide the limb of the instrument into parts so small. 
The armils of Alexandria were divided into no parts 
smaller than sixths of degrees, or divisions of 10 
minutes. 

The angles, observed by means of these divisions, 

» Ptol. Synt. iii. 2. 



202 THE GREEK AETTRONOMY. 

were expressed as a fraction of the cireumference. 
Thus Eratosthenes stated the interval between the 
tropics to be fe of the circumference'. 

It was soon remarked that the whole circum- 
ference of the circle was not wanted for such obser- 
vations. Ptolemy^* says, that he found it more 
convenient to observe altitudes by means of a square 
flat piece of stone or wood, vnth. a quadrant of a 
circle described on one of its flat faces, about a 
centre near one of the angles. A peg was placed at 
the centre, and one of the extreme radii of the 
quadrant being perpendicular to the horison, the ele- 
vation of the sun above the horizon was determined 
by observing the point of the arc of the quadrant 
on which the shadow of the peg fell. 

As the necessity of accuracy in the observations 
was more and more felt, various adjustments of such 
instruments were practised. They were placed in 
the meridian by means of a meridian line^ drawn by 
astronomical methods on the floor on which they 
stood. The plane of the instrument was made 
vertical by means of a plumb-line: the bounding 
radius, from which angles were measured, was also 
adjusted by the flumb line^\ 

• Delambre, A. A. i. 87. It is probable that his obserration 

gave him 47| degrees.^^ The fraction gj = M = 1^? = ^^^ 

which is very nearly -- 

^« Syiit. i. 1. 

" The curvature of the plane of the circle, by warping, was 
noticed. Ptol. iii. 2. p. 155, observes that his equatorial circle 



SEQUEL TO THE EPOCH OP HIPPARCHUS. 203 

In this maimer, the places of the sun and of the 
moon could be observed by means of the shadows 
which they cast. In order to observe the stars", the 
observer looked along the face of the circle of the 
armil, so as to see its two edges apparently brought 
together, and the star apparently touching them*'. 

It was afterwards found important to ascertain 
the position of the sun with regard to the ecliptic : 
and, for this purpose, an instrument, called an Astro-' 
labe^ was invented, of which we have a description 
in Ptolemy**. This also consisted of circular rims, 
moveable within one another, or about poles ; and 
contained circles which were to be brought into the 
position of the ecliptic, and of a plane passing through 
the sun and the poles of the ecliptic. The position 
of the moon with regard to the ecliptic, and its 
position in longitude with regard to the sun or a 
star, were thus determined. 

The astrolabe continued long in use, but not so 
long as the quadrant described by Ptolemy ; which, 
in a larger form, is the mural quadrant^ and has been 
used up to the most recent times. 

It may be considered surprising**, that Hipparchus, 
after having observed, for some time, right ascensions 

was illuminated on the hollow side twice in the same day. (He 
did not know that this might arise from refraction.) 

** Delamb. A. A. i. 185. 

*^ Ptol. Sjnt. i. 1. Qawep KeKoXXjjfitvos afA<j>iTtp<us avraif reus 
eirifficivfuus 6 acTrfp €v ry Bi axrrav eniTTtbtj^ fitoTrrruiyTat. 

** Synt. Y. 1. '' Del. A. A. 181. 



204 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

and declinations, quitted equatorial armils for the 
astrolabe, which immediately refers the stars to the 
ecliptic. He probably did this because, after the 
discovery of precession, he found the latitudes con- 
stant, and wanted to know the motion in longitude. 

To the above instruments, may be added the 
dioptra and the parallactic instrument of Hipparchus, 
and Ptolemy. In the latter, the distance of a star 
from the zenith was observed by looking through two 
sights fixed in a rule, this being annexed to another 
rule, which was kept in a vertical position by a 
plumb-line; and the angle between the two rules 
was measured. 

The following example of an observation, taken 
from Ptolemy, may seem to show the form in which 
the results of the instruments, just described, were 
usually stated**. 

" In the 2nd year of Antoninus, the 9th day of 
Pharmouthi, the sun being near setting, the last 
division of Taurus being on the meridian (that is, 
5i equinoctial hours after noon), the moon was in 
3 degrees of Pisces, by her distance from the sun 
(which was 92 degrees, 8 minutes) ; and half an hour 
after, the sun being set, and the quarter of Gemini on 
the meridian, Regulus appeared, by the other circle 
of the astrolabe, 57i degrees more forwards than the 
moon in longitude." From these data the longitude 
of Regulus is calculated. 

" Del. A. A. ii. 248. 



SEQUEL TO THE EPOCH OP HIPPARCHUS. 205 

From what has been said respecting the observa- 
tions of the Alexandrian astrcmomers, it will have 
been seen that their instrumental observations could 
not be depended on for any close accuracy. This 
defect, after the general reception of the Hipparchiaii 
theory, operated very unfavourably on the progress 
of the science. If they could have traced the moon's 
place distinctly from day to day, they must soon 
have discovered all the inequalities which were 
known to Tycho Brahe; and if they could have 
measured her parallax or her diameter with any 
considerable accuracy, they must have obtained a 
confutation of the epicycloidal form of her orbit. 
By the badness of their observations, and the imper- 
fect agreement of these with calculation, they not only 
were prevented making such steps, but were led to 
receive the theory with a servile assent and an 
indistinct apprehension, instead of that rational con- 
viction and intuitive clearness which would have 
given a progressive impulse to their knowledge. 

Sect. 4. — Period from Ilipparchus to Ptolemy. 

We have now to speak of the cultivators of astro- 
nomy from the time of Hipparchus to that of 
Ptolemy, the next great name which occurs in the 
history of this science ; though even he holds place 
only among those who verified, developed, and, in 
some points, materially extended the theory of Hip- 
parchus. The astronomers who lived in the inter- 



206 THE GSEEK A8IB0N0MT. 



timei indeed, did little, eyen in this way ; 
though it might haye been supposed that their 
studies were carried on imder consideiable adyan- 
tages, inasmnch as they all enjoyed the liberal 
patronage of the kings of Egypt '^ The ^diyine 
school of Alexandria," as it is called by Synesius, in 
the fourth century, appears to haye produced few 
persons capable of canying forwards, or eyen of yen- 
fying, the labours of its great astronomical teacher. 
The mathematicians of the school wrote much, and 
apparently they obseryed sometimes ; but their obs^r^ 
yations are of little yalue : and their books are expo* 
sitions of the theory and its geometrical consequences^ 
without any attempt to compare it with obseryation. 
For instance, it does not appear that any one yerified 
the remarkable discoyery of the precession, till the 
time of Ptolemy, 250 years after ; nor does the state- 
ment of this motion of the heayens appear in the 
treatises of the intermediate writers; nor does Ptolemy 
quote a single obseryation of any person made in this 
long interval of time ; while his references to those of 
Hipparchus are perpetual ; and to those of Aristyllus 
and Timocharis, and of others, as Conon, who pre- 
ceded Hipparchus^ are not unfrequent« « 

This Alexandrian period, so inactiye and barren 
in the history of science, was prosperous, civilized, 
and literary ; and many of the works which belong 
to it are come down to us^ though those of Hippar- 

'^ Delamb. A. A. ii. 240. 



SEQUEL TO THE EPOCH OF HIPPARCHUS. 207 

chus are lost. We have the " Uranologion" of 
Geminus^% a systematio treatise on astronomy, ex- 
pounding correctly the Hipparchian theories and 
their consequences, and containing a good account 
of the use of the various cycles^ which ended in the 
adoption of the Calippic period. We have likewise 
"The Circular Theory of the Celestial Bodies" of 
Cleomedes ^% of which the principal part is a developed 
ment of the doctrine of the sphere, including the 
consequences of the globular form of the earth. We 
have also another work on " Spherics" by Theodosius 
of Bithynia'^ which contains some of the most import 
taut propositions of the subject, and has been used 
as a book of instruction even in modem times. 
Another writer on the same Subject is Menelaus* 
who lived somewhat later, and whose three books 
on Spherics still remain. 

One of the most important kinds of deduction 
from a geometrical theory, such as that of the doctrine 
of the sphere, or that of epicycles, is the calculation 
of its numerical results in particular cases. With 
regard to the latter theory, this was done in the con- 
struction of solar and lunar tables, as we have already 
seen ; and this process required the formation of a 
trigonametfy^ or system of rules for calculating the 
relations between the sides and angles of triangles. 
Such a science had been formed by Hipparchus, who 
appears to be the author of every great step in 

^''B.c.70. ^•b.c. 60. "b.c. 50. 



208 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

ancient astronomy'^ He wrote a work in twelve 
books, " On the Construction of the Tables of Chords 
of Arcs ;" such a table being the means by which the 
Greeks solved their triangles. The doctrine of the 
sphere required, in like manner, a spherical trigoruh 
metrj/y in order to enable mathematicians to calculate 
its results ; and this branch of science also appears to 
have been formed by Hipparchus*', who gives results 
that imply the possession of such a method. Hyp- 
sicles, who was a contemporary of Ptolemy, also 
made some attempts at the solution of such pro- 
blems : but it is extraordinary that the writers whom 
we have mentioned as coming after Hipparchus, 
Theodosius, Cleomedes, and Menelaus, do not even - 
mention the calculation of triangles", either plane or 
spherical ; though the latter writer'* is said to have 
written on " the Table of Chords," a work which is 
now lost. 

We shall see, hereafter, how prevalent a disposi- 
tion in literary ages is that which induces authors to 
become commentators. This tendency showed itself 
at an early period in the school of Alexandria. 
Aratus", who lived 270 b. c. at the court of Anti- 
gonus, king of Macedonia, described the celestial 
constellations in two poems, entitled " Phsenomena," 
and " Prognostics." These poems were little more 
than a versification of the treatise of Eudoxus on the 
acronycal and heliacal risings and settings of the 

«^ Delamb. A. A. ii. 37- " A. A. i. 117. 

" A. A. i. 249. " A. A. ii. 37. " A. A. i. 74. 



SEQUEL TO THE EPOCH OF HIPPARCHUS. 209 

stars. The work was the subject of a comment by 
Hipparchus, who perhaps found this the easiest way of 
giving connexion and circulation to his knowledge. 
Three Latin translations of this poem gave the 
Romans the means of becoming acquainted with it : 
the first is by Cicero, of which we have numerous 
fragments extant** ; Germanicus Caesar, one of the 
sons-in-law of Augustus, also translated the poem, 
and this translation remains, almost entire. Finally, 
we have a complete translation by Avienus■^ The 
." Astronomica" of Manilius, the " Poeticon Astrono- 
micon'* of Hyginus, both belonging to the time of 
Augustus, are, like the work of Aratus, poems which 
combine mythological ornament with elementary 
astronomical exposition ; but have no value in the 
history of science. We may pass nearly the same 
judgment upon the explanations and declamations 
of Cicero, Seneca, and Pliny, for they do not aipprize 
us of any additions to astronomical knowledge ; and 
they do not always indicate a very clear apprehen- 
sion of the doctrines which the writers adopt. 

Perhaps the most remarkable feature in the two 
last-named writers, is the declamatory expression of 
their admiration for the discoverers of physical 
knowledge ; and in one of them, Seneca, the per- 
suasion of a boundless progress in science to which 

■' Two copies of this translation, illustrated by drawings of 
different ages, one set Roman, and the other Saxon, according 
to Mr. Ottlej, are described in the Archceologia^ vol. 18. 

" Mont. i. 221. 

VOL. I. P 



210 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

man was destined* Though this belief was no more 
than a vague and arbitrary conjecture, it suggested 
other coiyectures in detail, some of which, having 
been verified, have attracted much notice. For 
instance, in speaking of comets '% Seneca says^ 
**The time wiU come when those things which are 
now hidden shall be brought to light by time and 
persevering diligence. Our posterity will wonder 
that we should be ignorant of what is so obvious." 
The motions of the planets, he adds, complex and 
seemingly confused, have been reduced to rule ; and 
some one will come hereafter, who will reveal to us 
the paths of comets. Such convictions and conjec- 
tures are not to be admired for their wisdom ; for 
Seneca was led rather by enthusiasm, than by any 
solid reasons, to entertain this opinion ; nor, again, 
are they to be considered as merely lucky guesses, 
implying no merit : they are remarkable as showing 
how the persuasion of the universality of law, and the 
belief of the probability of its discovery by man, 
grow up in men's minds, when speculative know- 
ledge becomes a prominent object of attention. 

An important practical application of astronomical 
knowledge was made by Julius Csesar, in his correco 
tion of the calendar, which we have already noticed : 
and this^ was strictly due to the Alexandrian school, 
for Sosigenes, an astronomer, came from Egypt to 
Rome for the purpose. 



88 



Seneca. Qu. N. vii. 25. 



211 



Sect. 5. — Measures of the Earth. 

There were, as we have said, few attempts made, at 
the period of which we are speaking, to improve the 
accuracy of any of the determinations of the early 
Alexandrian astronomers. One question naturally 
excited much attention at all times, the magnitude 
of the earth, its figure being universally acknow* 
ledged to be a globe. The Chaldeans, at an earlier 
period, had asserted that a man, walking without 
stopping, might go round the circuit of the earth in 
a year ; but this might be a mere fitncy, or a mere 
guess. The attempt of Eratosthenes to decide this 
question went upon principles entirely correct. Syene 
was situated on the tropic ; for there, on the day 
of the solstice, at noon, objects cast no shadow ; and 
a well waa enlightened to the bottom by the sun's 
rays. At Alexandria, on the same day, the sun 
was, at noon, distant from the zenith by a fiftieth 
part of the circumference. These two cities were 
north and south from each other; and the distance 
had been determined, by the royal overseers of the 
roads, to be 5000 stadia. This gave a circumference 
of 250,000 stadia to the earth, and a radius of about 
40,000. Aristotle" says that the mathematicians 
make the circumference 400,000 stadia. Hippar^ 
ehus conceived that the measure of Eratosthenes 

■• De Ccelo. ii. ad fin. 

P 2 






':-'<■: [. Ci: -. j:. me meri; 



■. -^nrrr - 



SEQUEL TO THE EPOCH OF HIPPARCHUS. 213 

to remove all doubt concerning the scale of this 
measure, we are informed that the cubit is that 
called the black cubit, which consists of 27 inches, 
each inch being the thickness of six grains of barley. 

Sect 6. — Ptolemy's Discovery of Evection. 

By referring, in this place, to the last-mentioned 
measure of the earth, we include the labours of the 
Arabian as well as the Alexandrian astronomers, in 
the period of mere detail, which forms the sequel to 
the great astronomical revolution of the Hipparchian 
epoch. And this period of verification is rightly 
extended to those later times ; not merely because 
astronomers were then still employed in determining 
the magnitude of the earth, and the amount of other 
elements of the theory ; for those are their employ- 
ments to the present day; but because no great 
intervening discovery marks a new epoch, and begins 
a new period ; — because no great revolution in the 
theory added to the objects of investigation, or 
presented them in a new point of view. This being 
the case, it will be more instructive for our purpose 
to consider the general character and broad intellec- 
tual features of this period, than to offer a useless 
catalogue of obscure and worthless writers, and of 
opinions either borrowed or unsound. But before 
we do this, there is one writer whom we cannot 
leave undistinguished in the crowd ; since his name 
is more celebrated even than that of Hipparchus ; 



214 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

his works contain ninety-nine hundredths of what 
we know of the Greek astronomy ; and though he 
was not the author of a new theory, he made some 
very remarkable steps in the verification, correction, 
and extension of the theory which he received. I 
speak of Ptolemy, whose work, " The Mathematical 
Construction" (of the heavens) contains a complete 
exposition of the state of astronomy in his time, the 
reigns of Adrian and Antonine. This book is &mi- 
liarly known to us by a term which contains the 
record of our having received our first knowledge of 
it from the Arabic writers. The " Megiste Syntaxis," 
or great construction, gave rise, among them, to the 
title Al Magisth or Almagest, by which the work is 
commonly described. As a mathematical exposi- 
tion of the theory of epicycles and eccentrics, of the 
observations and calculations which were employed 
in Order to apply this theory to the sun, moon, and 
planets, and of the other calculations which are 
requisite, in order to deduce the consequences of 
this theory, the work is a splendid and lasting monu- 
ment of diligence, skill and judgment. Indeed, all 
the other astronomical works of the ancients hardly 
add anything whatever to the information we obtain 
jfrom the Almagest ; and the knowledge which the 
student possesses of the ancient astronomy must 
depend mainly upon his acquaintance with Ptolemy. 
Among other merits, Ptolemy has that of giving us 
a very copious account of the manner in which 
Hipparchus established the main points of his 



SEQUEL TO THE EPOCH OF HIPPARCHUS. 215 

theories; an account the more agreeable, in con- 
sequence of the admiration and enthusiasm with 
which this author everywhere speaks of the great 
master of the astronomical school. 

In our present survey of the writings of Ptolemy, 
we are concerned less with his exposition of what 
had been done before him, than with his own ori- 
ginal labours. In most of the branches of the 
subject, he gave additional exactness to what Hip^ 
parchus had done ; but our main business, at pre- 
sent, is with those parts of the Almagest which 
contain new steps in the application of the Hippar- 
chian hypothesis; there are two such cases, both 
very remarkable, — ^that of the moon's evection^ and 
that of the planetary motions. 

The law of the moon's anomaly, that is, of the 
leading and obvious inequality of her motion, could 
be represented, as we have seen, either by an eccen- 
tric or an epicycle ; and the amount of this inequality 
had been collected by observations of eclipses. But 
though the hypothesis of an epicycle, for instance, 
would bring the moon to her proper place, so far as 
eclipses could show it, that is, at new and full moon, 
this hypothesis did not rightly represent her motions 
at other points of her course. This appeared, when 
Ptolemy set about measuring her distances from the 
sun at diiferent times. "These," he'* says, "some- 
times agreed and sometimes disagreed." But by 
further attention to the facts, a rule was detected 

'^ Synt. T. 2. 



216 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

in these differences. "As my knowledge became 
more complete and more connected, so as to show 
the order of this new inequality, I perceived that 
this difference was small, or nothing, at new and full 
moon ; and that at both the dichotomies (when the 
moon is half illuminated,) it was small, or nothing, 
if the moon was at the apogee or perigee of the 
epicycle, and was greatest when she was in the 
middle of the interval, and therefore when the first 
inequality was greatest also." He then adds some 
further remarks on the circumstances according to 
which the moon's place, as affected by this new 
inequality, is before or behind the place, as given by 
the epicyclical hypothesis. 

Such is the announcement of the celebrated 
discovery of the moon's second inequality, after- 
wards called (by BuUialdus) the evection. Ptolemy 
soon proceeded to represent this inequality by a 
combination of circular motions, uniting, for this 
purpose, the hypothesis of an epicycle, already 
employed to explain the first inequality, with the 
hypothesis of an eccentric, in the circumference of 
which the centre of the epicycle was supposed to 
move. The mode of combining these was some- 
what complex; more complex we may, perhaps, 
say, -than was absolutely requisite '° ; the apogee of 

" If Ptolemy had used the hypothesis of an eccentric instead 
of an epicycle for the first inequality of the moon, an epicycle 
would hare represented the second inequality more simply than 
his method did. 



SEQUEL TO THE EPOCH OF HIPPARCHUS. 217 

the eccentric moved backwards, or contrary to the 
order of the signs, and the centre of the epicyle 
moved forwards nearly twice as fast upon the cir- 
cumference of the eccentric, so as to reach a place 
nearly, but not exactly, the same, as if it had moved 
in a concentric instead of an eccentric path. Thus 
the centre of the epicycle went twice round the 
eccentric in the course of one month : and in this 
manner it satisfied the condition ' that it should 
vanish at new and full moon, and be greatest when 
the moon was in the quarters of her monthly 
course. 

The discovery of the evection, and the reduction 
of it to the epicyclical theory, was, for several rea- 
sons, an important step in astronomy ; some of these 
reasons may be stated. 

1. It obviously suggested, or confirmed, the suspi- 
cion that the motions of the heavenly bodies might 
be subject to many inequalities ; — ^that when one set 
of anomalies had been discovered and reduced to 
rule, another set might come into view ; — ^that the 
discovery of a rule was a step to the discovery of 
deviations from the rule, which would require to be 
expressed in other rules; — ^that in the application 
of theory to observation, we find, not only the sMed 
phenomena^ for which the theory does account, but 
also residual phenomena^ which remain unaccounted 
for, and stand out beyond the calculation ;— that 
thus nature is not simple and regular, according to 
the simplicity and regularity of our hypothesis, but 



218 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

leads us forwards to apparent complexity, and to an 
accumulation of rules and relations. A fact like the 
evection, explained by an hypothesis like Ptolemy's, 
tended altogether to discourage any disposition to 
guess at the laws of nature from mere ideal views, 
or from a few phenomena. 

2. The discovery of evection had an importance 
which did not come into view till long afterwards, 
in being the first of a numerous series of inequalities 
of the moon, which result from the disturbing force 
of the sun. These inequalities were successively 
discovered ; and led finally to the establishment of 
the law of imiversal gravitation. The moon's first 
inequality arises from a different cause ; — ^from the 
same cause as the inequality of the sun's motion ;— • 
from the motion in an ellipse, so £eir as the central 
attraction is undisturbed by any other. This first 
inequality is called the elliptic inequality, or, more 
usually, the eqtiation of the centre. All the planets 
have such inequalities, but the evection is peculiar 
to the moon. The discovery of other inequalities of 
the moon's motion, the variation and annual equa- 
tion, made an immediate sequel in the order of 
the subject to the discoveries of Ptolemy, although 
separated by a long interval of time ; for these dis- 
coveries were only made by Tycho Brahe in the 
sixteenth century. The imperfection of astrono- 
mical instruments was the great cause of this long 
delay. 

3. The epicyclical hypothesis was found capable 



SEQUEL TO THE EPOCH OF HIPPARCHUS. 219 

of accommodating itself to such new discoveries. 
These new inequalities could be represented by new 
combinations of eccentrics and epicycles: all the 
real and imaginary discoveries of astronomers, up to 
Copernicus, were actually embodied in these hypo- 
theses ; Copernicus, as we have seen, did not reject 
such hypotheses ; the lunar inequalities which Tycho 
detected might have been similarly exhibited ; and 
even Newton'* represents the motion of the moon's 
apogee by means of an epicyle. As a mode of 
expressing the law of the irregularity, and of calcu- 
lating its results in particular cases, the epicyclical 
theory was capable of continuing to render great 
service to astronomy, however extensive the pro- 
gress of the science might be. It was, in fact, as we 
have already said, the modem process of representing 
the motion by means of a series of circular functions. 
4. But though the doctrine of eccentrics and 
epicycles was thus admissible as an hypothesis, and 
convenient as a means of expressing the laws of the 
heavenly motions, the successive occasions on which 
it was called into use, gave no countenance to it as a 
theory ; that is, as a true view of the nature of these 
motions, and their causes. By the steps of the pro- 
gress of this hypothesis, it became more and more com- 
plex, instead of becoming more simple ; which, as we 
shall see, the true theory did. The notions concerning 
the position and connexion of the heavenly bodies. 



84 



Principia, lib. iii. prop. xxxr. 



220 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

which were suggested by one set of phenomena, were 
not confirmed by the indications of another set of 
phenomena ; for instance, those relations of the epi- 
cycles which were adopted to account for the mo- 
tions of the heavenly bodies, were not found to fall 
in with the consequences of their apparent dia- 
meters and parallaxes. In reality, as we have said, 
if the relative distances of the sun and moon at dif- 
ferent times could have been accurately determined, 
the theory of epicycles must have been forthwith 
overturned. The insecurity of such measurements 
alone maintained the theory to later times. 

Sect 7. — Conclusion of the History of Greek 

Astronomy. 

I might now proceed to give an account of Pto- 
lemy's other great step, the determination of the 
planetaiy orbits ; but as this, though in itself very 
curious, would not illustrate any point beyond those 
already noticed, I shall refer to it very briefly. The 
planets all move in ellipses about the sun, as the 
moon moves about the earth ; and as the sun appa- 
rently moves about the earth. They will therefore 
each have an elliptic inequality or equation of the 
centre, for the same reason that the sun and moon 
have such inequalities. And this inequality may be 
represented, in the cases of the planets, just as in the 
other two, by means of an eccentric ; the epicycle, 
it will be recollected, had alreadv been used in order 



SEQUEL TO THE EPOCH OF HIPPARCHUS- 221 

to represent the more obvious changes of the plane- 
tary motions. To determine the amount of the ec- 
centricities and the places of the apogees of the 
planetary orbits, was the task which Ptolemy under- 
took; Hipparchus, as we have seen, having been 
destitute of the observations which such a process 
required. The determination of the eccentricities 
in these cases involved some peculiarities which 
might not at first sight occur to the reader. The 
elliptical motion of the planets takes place about 
the sun ; but Ptolemy considered their movements as 
altogether independent of the sun, and referred them 
to the earth alone ; and thus the apparent eccentrici- 
ties which he had to account for, were the compoimd 
result of the eccentricity of the earth's orbit, and of 
the proper eccentricity of the orbit of the planet. 
He explained this result by the received mechanism 
of an eccentric deferent, carrying an epicycle ; but 
the motion in the deferent is uniform, not about the 
centre of the circle, but about another point, the 
equanl. Without going further into detail, it may 
be sufficient to state that, by a combination of ec- 
centrics and epicycles, he did account for the lead- 
ing features of these motions; and by using his 
own observations, compared with more aiicient ones, 
(for instance, those of Timocharis for Venus,) he was 
able to determine the dimensions and positions of 
the orbits. 

I shall here close my account of the astronomical 
progress of the Greek school. My purpose is only 



222 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

• 

to illustrate the principles on which the progress of 
science depends, and therefore I have not at all pre- 
tended to touch upon every part of the subject. Some 
portions of the ancient theories, as for instance, the 
mode of accounting for the motions of the moon 
and planets in latitude, are sufficiently analogous to 
what has been explained, not to require any more 
especial notice. Other parts of the Greek astrono- 
mical knowledge, as, for instance, their acquaintance 
with refraction, did not assume any clear or definite 
form, and can only be considered as the prelude to 
modem discoveries on the same subject. And before 
we can with propriety pass on to these, there is a 
long and remarkable, though unproductive interval, 
of which some account must be given. 

Sect. 8. — Arabian Astronomy. 

The interval to which I have just alluded may be 
considered as extending from Ptolemy to Coper- 
nicus; we have no advance in Greek astronomy 
after the former ; no signs of a revival of the power 
of discovery till the latter. During this interval of 
1350 years*', the principal cultivators of astronomy 
were the Arabians, who adopted this science from 
the Grcebi whom they conquered, and from whom 
the conquerors of western Europe again received 
back their treasure, when the love of science and 

^ Ptolemy died about a.i>. 150. C^opemicus was liTing a.d. 
1500. 



SEQUEL TO THE EPOCH OF HIPPARCHUS. 223 

the capacity for it had been awakened in their 
minds. In the intervening time, the precious de- 
posit had undergone little change. The Arab astro** 
nomer had been the scrupulous but unprofitable 
servant, who kept his talent without apparent danger 
of loss, but also without prospect of increase. There 
is little in Arabic literature which bears upon the 
progress of astronomy ; but as the little that there is 
must be considered as a sequel to the Greek science, 
I shall notice one or two points before I treat of the 
stationary period in general. 

When the sceptre of western Asia had passed 
into the hands of the Abasside caliphs'^, Bagdad, 
" the city of peace," rose to splendour and refine- 
ment, and became the metropolis of science under 
the successor^ of Almansor the Victorious, as Alexan- 
dria had been under the successors of Alexander the 
Great. Astronomy attracted peculiarly the favour of 
the powerful as well as the learned ; and almost aU 
the culture which was bestowed upon the science, 
appears to have had its source in the patronage, 
often in the personal studies, of Saracen princes. 
Under such encouragement, much was done, in those 
scientific labours which money and rank can com- 
mand. Translations of Greek works were made, large 
instruments were erected, observers were main- 
tained ; and accordingly as observation showed the 
defects and imperfection of the extant tables of the 

^ Gibbon X. 31. 



224 THE GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

celestial motions, new ones were constructed. Thus 
under Almansor, the Grecian works of science were 
collected from all quarters, and many of them trans- 
lated into Arabic''. The translation of the ** Megiste 
Syntaxis" of Ptolemy, which thus became the Al- 
magest, is ascribed to Isaac ben Homain in this reign. 

The greatest of the Arabian astronomers comes 
half a century later. This is Albategnius, as he 
is commonly called ; or more exactly, Muhammed 
ben Geber Albatani, the last appellation indicating 
that he was bom at Batan, a city of Mesopotamia'^". 
He wa. a Syrian prince, whose residence was at 
Aracte or Racha in Mesopotamia ; a part of his ob- 
servations were made at Antioch. His work still 
remains to us in Latin. " After having read," he 
says, « the Syntaxis of Ptolemy, and learnt the 
methods of calculation employed by the Greeks, his 
observations led him to conceive that some improve- 
ments might be made in their results. He found it 
necessary to add to Ptolemy's observations, as Pto- 
lemy had added to those of Abrachis" (Hipparchus). 
He then published tables of the motions of the sun, 
moon, and planets, which long maintained a high 
reputation. 

These, however, did not prevent the publication 
of others. Under the Caliph Hakem (about a.d. 
1000,) Ebn lounis published tables of the sun, 
moon, and planets, which were hence called the 

'^ Gibbon,, x. 36. •* Del., Astronomie du Moyen Age, 4. 



SEQUEL TO THE EPOCH OP HIPPARCHUS. 225 

Hakemite tables. Not long after, Arzachel of 
Toledo published the Tohtan tables. In the 13th 
century, Nasir Eddin published tables of the stars, 
dedicated to Ilchan, a Tartar prince, and hence 
termed the Ihhanic tables. Two centuries later, 
Ulugh Beigh, the grandson of Tamerlane, and prince 
of the countries beyond the Oxus, was a zealous 
practical astronomer; and his tables, which were 
published by Hyde in 1665, are referred to as im- 
portant authority by modern astronomers. The 
series of astronomical tables which we have thus 
noticed, in which, however, many are omitted, leads 
us to the Alphondne tables, which were put forth in 
1488, and in succeeding years, under the auspices 
of Alphonso, king of Castile ; and thus brings us to 
the verge of modern astronomy. 

For all these tables, the Ptolemaic hypotheses 
were employed; and, for the most part, without 
alteration. The Arabs sometimes felt the extreme 
complexity and difficulty of the doctrine which they 
studied ; but their minds did iiot possess that kind 
of invention and energy by which the philosophers 
of Europe, at a later period, won their way into a 
simpler and better system. 

Thus Alpetragius states, in the outset of his 
" Planetarum Theorica," that he was at first asto- 
nished and stupified with this complexity, but that 
afterwards " God was pleased to open to him the 
occult secret in the theory of his orbs, and to make 
known to him the truth of their essence, and the rec- 

VOL. I. Q 



226 THE GREEK ASTJEtONOMY. 

titude of the quality of their motion." His system 
consists, according to Delambre", in attributing to 
the planets a spiral motion from east to west, an 
idea already refuted by Ptolemy. Geber of Seville 
criticizes Ptolemy very severely *^ but without intro- 
ducing any essential alteration into his system. The 
Arabian observations are in many cases valuable; 
both because they were made with more skill and 
with better instruments than those of the Greeks ; 
and also because they illustrate the permanence or 
variability of important elements, such as the obli- 
quity of the ecliptic and the inclination of the 
moon's orbit. 

We must, however, notice one or two peculiar 
Arabian doctrines. The most important of these is 
the discovery of. the motion of the sun's apogee by 
Albategnius. He found the apogee to be in longi- 
tude 82 degreQS ; Ptolemy had placed it in longi- 
tude 66 degrees. The difference of 17 degrees was 
beyond all limit of probable error of calculation, 
though the process is not capable of great precision ; 
and the inference of the motion of the apogee was 
so obvious, that we cannot agree with Delambre, in 
doubting or extenuating the claim of Albategnius 
to this discovery, on the ground of his not having 
expressly stated it. 

In detecting this motion, the Arabian astronomers 
reasoned rightly from facts well observed ; they were 

" Delambre, M. A. p. 7- *• M. A. p. 180, &c. 



SEQUEL TO THE EPOCH OP HIPPARCHUS. 227 

not always so fortunate. Arzachel, in the 11th cen- 
tury, found the apogee of the sun to be less advanced 
than Albategnius had found it, by some degrees ; he 
inferred that it had receded in the intermediate 
time ; but we now know, from an acquaintance with 
its real rate of moving, that the true inference 
would have been, that Albategnius, whose method 
was less trustworthy than that of Arzachel, had 
made an error to the amount of the difference thus 
arising. A curious, but utterly false hypothesis was 
founded on observations thus erroneously appre* 
ciated ; namely, the trepidation of the jiwed $twrs. 
Arzachel conceived that a uniform precession of 
the equinoctial points would not account for the 
apparent changes of position of the stars, and 
that for this purpose, it was necessary to conceive 
two circles of about 8 degrees radius described 
round the equinoctial points of the immoveable 
sphere, and to suppose the first points of Aries and 
Libra to describe the circumferences of these circles 
in about 800 years. This would produce, at one 
time a progression, and at another a regression, of the 
apparent equinoxes, and would moreover change the 
latitudes of the stars. Such a motion is entirely 
visionary; but the doctrine made a sect among 
astronomers, and was adopted in the first edition 
of the Alphonsine Tables, though afterwards re- 
jected. 

An important exception to the general unprogres- 
sive character of Arabian science has been pointed 

Q2 



228 THE GBEEK ASTRONOMY. 

out recently by M. Sedillot**. It appears that 
Mohammed-Aboul We&ral-Bouzdjani, an Arabian 
astronomer of the tenth century, who resided at Cairo, 
and observed at Bagdad in 975, discoyered a third 
inequality of the moon, in addition to the two ex- 
pounded by Ptolemy, the equation of the centre, 
and the evection. This third inequality, the vanar- 
Hon, is usually supposed to have been discovered by 
Tycho Brahe, six centuries later. It is an inequality 
of the moon's motion, in virtue of which she moves 
quickest when she is at new or full, and slowest at 
the first and third quarter ; in consequence of this, 
from the first quarter to the full, she is behind her 
mean place ; at the fall, she does not differ from her 
mean place ; from the full to the third quarter, she 
is before her true place ; and so on ; and the greatest 
effect of the inequaUty is in the octants, or points 
half-way between the four quarters. In an Almagest 
of Aboul Wefa, a part of which exists in the Royal 
Library at Paris, after describing the two inequalities 
of the moon, he has a Section ix., " Of the Third 
Anomaly of the Moon called Muhazal or Prosnetms.'^ 
He there says, that taking cases when the moon was 
in apogee or perigee, and when, consequently, the 
effect of the two first inequalities vanishes, he found, 
^ observation of the moon, when she was nearly in 
trine and in sea^tik with the sun, that she was a degree 

** Sedillot. Nouvelles Rech. sur I'Hist. de TAstion. chez 
les Arabes. Nouveau Journal Asiatique. 18S6. 



SEQUEL TO THE EPOCH OP HIPPARCHUS, 229 

and a quarter from her calculated place. "And 
hence," he adds, "I perceived that this anomaly 
exists independently of the two first : and this can 
only take place by a declination of the diameter of 
the epicycle with respect to the centre of the 
zodiac." 

We may remark that we have here this inequality 
of the moon made out in a really philosophical 
manner ; a residual quantity in the moon's longitude 
being detected by observation, and the cases in 
which it occurs selected and grouped by an inductive 
effort of the mind. The advance is not great ; for 
Aboul Wefa appears only to have detected the 
existence, and not to have fixed the law or the 
exact quantity of the inequality ; but still it places 
the scientific capacity of the Arabs in a more favour- 
able point of view than any circumstance with which 
we were previously acquainted. 

But this discovery of Aboul Wefa appears to have 
excited bo notice among his contemporaries and 
followers ; at least it had been long quite forgotten 
when Tycho Brache rediscovered the same lunar 
inequality. We can hardly help looking upon this 
circumstance as an evidence of the servility of 
intellect of the Arabian period. The learned Ara- 
bians were so little in the habit of considering science 
as progressive, and looking with pride and confidence 
at examples of its progress, that they had not the 
courage to believe in a discovery which they them- 
selves had made, and were dragged back by the 



230 TH£ GREEK ASTRONOMY. 

chain of authority, even when they had advanced 
beyond their Greek masters. 

As the Arabians took the vj^hole of their theory 
(with such slight exceptions as we have been 
noticing) from the Greeks, they took from them also 
the mathematical processes by which the conse- 
quences of the theory were obtained. Arithmetic 
and trigonometry, two main branches of these pro- 
cesses, received considerable improvements at their 
hands. In the former, especially, they rendered a 
service to the world which it is difficult to estimate 
too highly, in abolishing the cumbrous sexagesimal 
arithmetic of the Greeks, and introducing the nota* 
tion by means of the digits 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8, 9, 0, 
which we now employ**. These numerals appear to 
be of Indian origin, as is acknowledged by the Arabs 
themselves ; and thus form no exception to the steri-- 
lity of the Arabian genius as to great scientific 
inventions. Another improvement, of a subordinate 
kind, but of great utility, was Arabian, being made 
by Albategnius. He introduced into calculation the 
sine^ or half-chord of the double arc, instead of the 
chord of the arc itself^ which had been employed by 
the Greek astronomers. There have been various 
corjectures concerning the origin of the word dm; 
the most probable appears to be that sinus is the 
Latin translation of the Arabic word giJ)^ which 
signifies a fold, the two halves of the chord being 
conceived to be folded together. 

" Mont. i. 376. 



SEQUEL TO THE EPOCH OP HIPPARCHUS. 231 

The great obligation which science owes to the 
Arabians, is to have preserved it during a period of 
darkness and desolation, so that Europe might 
receive it back again when the evil days were past. 
We shall see hereafter how differently the European 
intellect dealt with this hereditary treasure when 
once recovered. 

Before quitting the subject, we may observe that 
Astronomy brought back, from her sojourn among 
the Arabs, a few terms which may still be perceived 
in her phraseology. Such are the zenith^ and the 
opposite imaginary point, the nadir ; — ^the circles of 
the sphere termed (dmacantars and azimvtii circles. 
The alidad of an instrument is its index, which pos- 
sesses an angular motion. Some of the stars still 
retain their Arabic names ; Aldebaran^ Rigel, Fomain 
haul ; many others were known by such appellations 
a little while ago. Perhaps the word almanac is the 
most familiar vestige of the Arabic period of 
astronomy**. 

*' It is not to my purpose to note any eflforts of the intellec- 
tual faculties among other nations, which may hare taken place 
independently of the great system of progressive European 
culture, &om which all our existing science is derived. Other- 
wise I might speak of the astronomy of some of the Orientals, 
for example, the Chinese, who are said, by Montucla (i. 465) 
to have discovered the first equation of the moon, and the 
proper motion of the fixed stars (the precession), in the third 
century of our era. The Greeks had made these discoveries 
500 years earlier. 



BOOK IV. 



HISTORY 



OP 



PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES ; 



OR, 



VIEW OF THE STATIONARY PERIOD OF 
INDUCTIVE SCIENCE. ' 



In vain, in vain ! the all-coniposing liour 
Besistless falls . • . • 

As one by one, at dread Medea's strain, 
The sickening stars fade off th' ethereal plain; 
As Argus' eyes, by Hermes' wand opprest. 
Closed one by one to everlasting rest ; 
Thus at her felt approach and secret might, 
Art after art goes out, and aU is night. 
See skulking Truth to her old cavern fled, 
Mountains of casuistry heaped on her head ; 
Philosophy, that reached the heavens before. 
Shrinks to her hidden cause, and is no more. 
Physic of Metaphysic begs defence, 
And Metaphysic calls for aid to Sense : 
See Mystery to Mathematics fly ! 
In vain ! they gaze, turn giddy, rave^ and die. 

Dundady b. iv. 



INTRODUCTION. 



We have now to consider more especially a long and 
barren period, which intervened between the scien- 
tific activity of ancient Greece, and that of modem 
Europe; and which we may, therefore, call the 
Stationary Period of Science. It would be to no 
purpose to enumerate the various forms in which, 
during these times, men reproduced the discoveries 
of the inventive ages : or to trace in them the small 
successes of art, void of any principle of genuine 
philosophy. Our object requires rather that we 
should point out the general and distinguishing 
features of the intellect and habits of those times. 
We must endeavour to delineate the character of 
the Stationary Period, and, as far as possible, to 
analyse its defects and errors; and thus to obtain 
some knowledge of the causes of its barrenness and 
darkness. 

We have already stated, that real scientific pro- 
gress requires distinct general ideas, applied to many 
special and certain facts. In the period of which 
we now have to speak, men's ideas were obscured, 
their disposition to bring their general views into 
accordance with facts was enfeebled. They were 
thus led to employ themselves unprofitably, among 



236 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

indistinct and unreal notions. And the evil of 
these tendencies was further inflamed, by moral 
peculiarities in the character of those times ; — by an 
abjectness of thought on the one hand, which could 
not help looking towards some intellectual superior ; 
and by an impatience of dissent on the other. To 
this must be added an enthusiastic temper, which, 
when introduced into speculation, tends to subject 
the mind's operations to ideas altogether distorted 
and delusive. 

These characteristics of the stationary period, its 
obscurity of thought, its servility, its intolerant dis- 
position, and its enthusiastic temper, will be treated 
of in the four following chapters, on the Indistinct- 
ness of Ideas, the Commentatorial Spirit, the Dog- 
matism, and the Mysticism of the Middle Ages. 



237 



CHAPTER I. 

On the Indistinctness of Ideas of the 

Middle Ages. 

That firm and entire possession of certain clear 
and distinct general ideas which is necessary to 
sound science, was the character of the minds of 
those of the ancients who created the several sciences 
which arose among them. It was indispensable, that 
such inventors should have a luminous and stead- 
fast apprehension of certain general relations, such as 
those of space or number, of order and cause ; and 
should be able to apply these notions with perfect 
readiness and precision to special facts and cases. 
It is necessary that such scientific notions should be 
more definite and precise than those which common 
language conveys ; but even in this state of unusual 
clearness, they must be so familiar to the philoso- 
pher, that they are the language in which he thinks. 
And the discoverer is thus led to doctrines which 
other men adopt and follow out, in proportion as 
they seize the fundamental ideas, and become ac- 
quainted with the leading facts. Thus Hipparchus, 
conceiving clearly the motions and combinations of 
motion which enter into his theory, saw that the 
relative lengths of the seasons were sufficient data 



238 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

for detennining the form of the sun's orbit ; thus Ar- 
chimedes, possessing a steady notion of mechanical 
pressure, was able, not only to deduce the properties 
of the lever and of the centre of gravity, but also to 
see the truth of those principles respecting the dis- 
tribution of pressure in fluids, on which the science 
of hydrostatics depends. 

With such distinct ideas, the inductive sciences rise 
and flourish ; with the decay and loss of such distinct 
ideas, these sciences become stationary, languid, and 
retrograde. When men merely repeat the terms of 
science, without attaching to them any clear con** 
ceptions ; — ^when their apprehensions become vague 
and dim ; — ^when they assent to scientific doctrines 
as a matter of tradition, rather than of conviction, 
on trust rather than on sight; — ^when science is 
considered as a collection of opinions, rather than 
a record of laws by which thft universe is really 
governed; — ^it must inevitably happen, that men 
will lose their hold on the truths which the great 
discoverers who preceded them have brought to 
light. They are not able to push forwards the 
truths on which they lay so feeble and irresolute 
a hand; probably they cannot even prevent their 
sliding back towards the obscurity from which they 
had been drawn, or from being lost altogether. 
Such indistinctness and vacillation of thought ap- 
pear to have prevailed in the stationary period, and 
to be, in fiact, intimately connected vrith its sta- 
tionary character. I shall point out some indica- 



INDISTINCTNESS OF IDEAS. 289 

tions of the intellectual peculiarity of which I 
speak. 

1. Collections of Opinions.^'^The fact, that mere 
Collections of the opinions of physical philosophers 
came to hold a prominent place in literature, already 
indicated a tendency to an indistinct and wandering 
apprehension of such opinions. I speak of such 
works as Plutarch's five Books " on the Opinions of 
Philosophers," or the physical opinions which Dio- 
genes LaCrtius gives in his " Lives of the Philoso- 
phers." At an earlier period still, books of this 
kind appear; as for instance, a large portion of 
Pliny's Natural History, a work which has very 
appropriately been called the Encyclopsedia of Anti- 
qlyf e™a Ari,t«tle Mmself i. um,i in the luAit 
of enumerating the opinions of those who had 
preceded him. To present such statements as an 
important part of physical philosophy, shows an 
erroneous and loose apprehension of the nature 
of such philosophy; for the only proof of which 
its doctrines admit, is the possibility of appljring 
the general theory to each particular case. The 
authority of great men, which in moml and prac- 
tical matters may or must have its weight, is here 
of no force; and the technical precision of ideas 
which the terms of a sound physical theory usually 
demand, renders a mere statement of the doctrines 
very imperfectly intelligible to readers femiliar with 
common notions only. To dwell upon such col- 
lections of opinions, therefore, implies, and pro- 



240 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

duces, in writers and readers, an obscure and inade- 
quate apprehension of the fall meaning of the 
doctrines thus collected; if there be among them 
any which really possess that clearness, solidity, and 
reality, which make them important in the history 
of science. Such diversities of opinion convey no 
truth ; such a multiplicity of statements of what has 
been said, in no degree teaches us what is ; such 
accumulations of indistinct notions, however vast 
and varied, do not make up one distinct idea. On 
the contrary, the habit of dwelling upon the verbal 
expressions of the views of other persons, and of 
being content with such an apprehension of doo^ 
trines as a transient notice can give us, is fatal to 
firm and clear thought: it indicates wavering and 
feeble conceptions, which are inconsistent with 
sound physical speculation. 

We may, therefore, consider the prevalence of 
Collections of the kind just referred to, as indicating 
a deficiency of philosophical talent in the ages now 
under review. As evidence of the same character, 
we may add the long train of publishers of Abstracts, 
Epitomes, Bibliographical Notices, and similar wri-. 
ters. All such writers are worthless for all purposes 
of science, and their labouiis may be considered as 
dead works; they have in them no principle of 
philosophical vitality; they draw their origin and 
nutriment from the death of true physical know- 
ledge ; and resemble the swarms of insects that are 
bom from the perishing carcass of some nobler animal. 



INDISTINCTNESS OF IDEAS. 241 

2. Indistinctness of Ideas in Mechanics. — ^But the 
indistinctness of thought which is so fatal a feature 
in the intellect of the stationary period, may be traced 
more directly in the works, even of the best authors, 
of those times. We find that they did not retain 
steadily the ideas on which the scientific success of the 
previous period had depended. For instance, it is a 
remarkable circumstance in the history of the science 
of mechanics, that it did not make any advance from 
the time of Archimedes to that of Stevinus and 
Galileo. Archimedes had established the doctrine 
of the lever ; several persons tried, in the interme- 
diate time, to prove the property of the inclined 
plane, and none of them succeeded. But let us 
look to the attempts ; for example, that of Pappus, 
in the eighth book of his Mathematical Collections, 
and we may see the reason of the failure. His 
problem shows, in the very terms in which it is 
propounded, the want of a clear apprehiensioh of the 
subject. " Having given the power which will draw 
a given weight along a horizontal plane, to find the 
additional power which will draw the same weight 
along a given inclined plane." This is proposed 
without previously defining how powers, producing 
such effects, are to be measured ; and as if the rate 
at which the body were drawn, and the nature of 
the surface of the plane, were of no consequence. 
The proper elementary problem is, to find the force 
which will support a body on an inclined plane ; and 
no doubt the solution of Pappus has more reference 

VOL. I. R 



242 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

to this problem than to his own. His reasoning is, 
however, totally at yariance with mechanical ideas 
on any view of the problem. He supposes the 
weight to be formed into a sphere ; and this sphere 
beiilg placed in contact with the inclined plane, he 
assumes that the effect will be the same as if the 
weight [were supported on a horizontal levw, the 
fulcrum being the point of contact of the sphere 
with the plane, and the power acting at the circum- 
ference of the sphere. Such an assumption implies 
an entire absence of those distinct ideas of mechar- 
nical pressure, on which our perception of the 
identity or diflference of different modes of action 
must depend ; — of those ideas by the help of which 
Archimedes had been able to demonst^rate the preop- 
tics of the lever, and Stevinus afterwards discovered 
the true solution of the problem of the inclined plane. 
The motive to Pappus's assumption was probably his 
perceiving that the additional power, which he thus 
obtained, vanished when the plane became horizontal, 
and increased as the inclination became greater. Thus 
his conceptions were vague ; he had no grounds of 
rational conviction, and he tried a conjecture. This 
is not the way to real knowledge. 

Pappus (who lived about A. D. 400) was one of the 
best mathematicians of the Alexandrian school; 
and, on subjects where his ideas were so indistinct, 
it is not likely that any much clearer were to be 
found in the minds of his contemporaries. Accord- 
ingly, on all subjects of speculative mechanics, there 



INDISTINCTNESS OF IDEAS. 243 

appears to have been an entire confusion and obscu* 
rity of thought till modem times. Men's minds 
were busy in endeavouring to systematize the dis- 
tinctions and subtleties of the Aristotelian school, 
concerning motion and power; and, being thus 
employed among doctrines in which there was 
involved no definite signification, capable of real 
exemplification, they, of course, could not acquire 
sound physical knowledge. We have already 
seen that the physical opinions of Aristotle, even 
as they came from him, had no proper scientific 
precision. His followers, in their endeavours to 
perfect and develop his statements, never attempted 
to introduce clearer ideas than those of their master ; 
and as they never referred, in any steady manner, to 
fiicts, the vagueness of their notions was not cor- 
rected by any collision with observation. The 
physical doctrines which they extracted from Aris- 
totle were, in the course of time, built up into a 
regular system; and though these doctrines could 
not be followed into a practical application without 
introducing distinctions and changes, such as de- 
prived the terms of all steady meaning, the dogmas 
continued to be repeated, till the world was per- 
suaded that they were self-evident ; and when, at a 
later period, experimental philosophers, such as 
Galileo and Boyle, ventured to contradict these 
current maxims, their new principles sounded in 
men's ears as strange as they now sound familiar. 
Thus Boyle promulgated his opinions on the me- 



244 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

chanics of fluids, as '* Hydrostatical Paradowes^ 
proved and illustrated by experiments." And 
the opinions which he there opposes, are those 
which the Aristotelian philosophers habitually pro- 
pounded as certain and indisputable; such, for 
instance, as thiat " in fluids the upper parts do not 
gravitate on the lower;" that "a lighter fluid will 
not gravitate on a heavier ;" that " levity is a posi- 
tive quality of bodies as well as gravity." So long 
as these assertions were left uncontested and un- 
tried, men heard and repeated them, without per- 
ceiving the incongruities which they involved : and 
thus they long evaded refutation amid the vague 
notions and undoubting habits of the stationary 
period. But when the controversies of Galileo's 
time had made men think with more acuteness and 
steadiness, it was discovered that many of these 
doctrines were inconsistent with themselves, as well 
as with experiment. We have an example of the 
confusion of thought to which the Aristotelians were 
liable, in their doctrine concerning felling bodies. 
" Heavy bodies," said they, " must fall quicker than 
light ones ; for weight is the cause of their fall, and 
the weight of the greater bodies is greater." They 
did not perceive that, if they considered the ,weight 
of the body as a power acting to produce motion, 
they must consider the body itself as offering a 
resistance to motion; and that the effect must 
depend on the proportion of the power to the resist- 
ance ; in short, they had no clear idea of accelerating 



INDISTINCTNESS OF IDEAS. 245 

force. This defect runs through all their mecha- 
nical speculations, and renders them, entirely value- 
less. 

We may exemplify the same confusion of thought 
on mechanical subjects in writers of a less technical 
character. Thus, if men had had any distinct idea 
of mechanical action, they could not . have ac- 
cepted for a moment the fable of the Echineis or 
Remora, a little fish which was said to be able to 
stop a large ship merely by sticking to it. Lucan* 
refers to this legend in a poetical manner, and 
notices this creature only in bringing together a 
collection of monstrosities; but Pliny relates the 
tale gravely, and moralizes upon it. after his manner. 
" What," he cries s " is more violent than the sea 
and the Winds ? what, a greater work of art than a 
ship? Yet one little fish (the Echineis) can hold 
back all th^se when they all strain the same way. 
. The winds may blow, the waves may rage ; but this 
small creature controls their fiiry, and stops a vessel, 

• 

' Lucan is describing one of the poetical compounds intro- 
duced in incantations. 

Hue quicquid foetu genuit Natura sinistro 
Miscetur: non spuma canum quibus unda timori est, 
Viscera non Ijncis, non duree nodus hyanee 
Defuit, et cervi pasti serpente medullaB; 
Non puppes retinens. Euro tendente audentes 
In medilB Echineis aqois, oculique draconum. 

Etc. Pharsaliaj iy. 670. 

" Plin. Hist. N. xxxii. 1. 



246 PHYSICAL SaENCE IN THS MIDDLE AGES. 

when chainai and anchors would not hold it: and 
this it does, not by hard labour, but merely by ad- 
hering to it. Alas, for human vanity ! when the 
turretted ships which man has built, that he may 
fight from castle^walls, at sea as well as at land^ are 
held captive and motionless by a fish a foot and a 
half long. Such a fish is said to have stopt the 
admiral's ship at the battle of Actium, and eom- 
pelled Antony to go into another. And in our own 
memory, one of these animals held fast the ship 
Caius, the emperor, when he was sailing from 
Astura to Antium. The stopping of this ship, when 
all the rest of the fleet went on, caused surprise ; 
but this did not last long, for some of the men 
jumped into the water to look for the fish, and found 
it sticking to the rudder ; they showedlt to Caius, 
who was indignant that this animal should inter- 
pose its prohibition to his progress, when im« 
pelled by four hundred rowers. It was like a 
slug ; and had no power, after it was taken into the 
ship." 

A very little advance in the power of thinking 
clearly on the force which is exerted in pulling, would 
have enabled the Romans to see^ that the ship and 
its rowers must pull the adhering fish by the hold 
the oars had upon the water ; and that, except the 
fish had a hold equally strong on some external 
body, it could not resist this force. 

3. Indistinctness of Ideas shown in Architecture. — 



INDISTINCTNESS OP IDEAS. 247 

Perhaps it may serve to illustrate still further the ex- 
tent to which, under the Roman empire, men's notions 
of mechanical relations became faint, wavered, and 
disappeared, if we observe the change which took 
place in architecture. All architecture, to possess 
genuine beauty, must be mechanically consistent. 
The decorative members must represent a structure 
which has in it a principle of support and stability. 
Thus the Grecian colonnade was a straight hori- 
zontal beam, resting on vertical props; and their 
pediment imitate^ a frame like a roof, where oppo-- 
sitely-inclined beams support each other. These 
forms of building were, therefore, proper models of 
art, because they implied supporting forces. But 
to be content with colonnades and pediments, which, 
thou^ they imitated the forms of the Grecian, 
were destitute of their mechanical truth, belonged 
to the decline of art; and showed that men had 
lost the idea of force, and retained only that of 
shape. Yet this was what the architects of the 
empire did. Under their hands, the pediment was 
severed at its vertex, or divided into sepawtte halves, 
so that it was no longer a mechanical possibility. 
The entablature no longer lay straight from pillar to 
pillar, but, projecting over each column, turned back 
to the wall, and adhered to it in the intervening- 
space. The splendid remains of Palmyra, Balbec, 
Petra, exhibit endless examples of this kind of 
perverse inventiveness ; and show us, very instruc- 
tively, how the decay of art and of science alike go 



248 FHTSICAI. 8CIENC& IN THE UDDLE AGES. 

along with this indistinctness of ideas which we are 
endeayoming to explain. 

4. Indistinctness of Ideas in Astronomy. — ^Retnm- 
ing to the sciences, it may be supposed, at first sight, 
that, with regard to astronomy, we have not the 
same ground for charging the stationary period with 
indistinctness of ideas on that subject, since they 
were able to acquire and verify, and, in some mea- 
sure, to apply, the doctrines previously estaUifibed. 
And, undoubtedly, it must be confessed that men's 
notions of the relations of space and number are 
never very indistinct. It appears to be unpossible for 
these chains of elementary perception ever to be 
much entangled. The later Greeks, the Arabians, 
and the earliest modem astronomers, must have 
conceived the hypotheses of the Ptolemaic system 
in a tolerably complete degree. And yet, we may 
assert, that, during the stationary period, men did 
not possess the notions, even of space and number, 
in that vivid and vigorous manner which enables 
them to discover new truths. If they had perceived 
distinctly that the astronomical theorist had merely 
to do with relative motions, they must have been led 
to see the possibility, at least, of the Copemican 
system ; as the Greeks, at an earlier period, had 
already perceived it. We find no trace of this. 
Indeed the mode in which the Arabian mathema- 
ticians present the solutions of their problems, does 
not indicate that clear apprehension of the relations 
of space, and that delight in the contemplation of 



INDISTINCTNESS OF IDEAS. 249 

them, which the Greek geometrical speculations 
imply. The Arabs are in the habit of giving con- 
clusions without demonstrations, precepts without 
the investigations by which they are obtained ; as 
if their main object were practical rather than 
speculative, — ^the calculation of results rather than 
the exposition of theory. Delambre* has been 
obliged to exercise great ingenuity, in order to dis- 
cover the method in which Ibn lounis proved his 
solution of certain difficult problems. 

5. Indistinctmss of Ideas shown by Sc€ptics.^^The 
same unsteadiness of ideas which prevents men from 
obtaining clear views, and steady and just convic- 
tions, on special subjects, may lead them to despair 
of or deny the possibility of acquiring certainty at 
all, and may thus make them sceptics with regard 
to all knowledge. Such sceptics are themselves 
men of indistinct views, for they could not other- 
wise avoid assenting to the demonstrated truths of 
science ; and, so far as they may be taken as speci- 
mens of their contemporaries, they prove that indis- 
tinct ideas prevail in the age in which they appear. 
In the stationary period, moreover, the indefinite 
speculations and unprofitable subtleties of the schools 
might further impel a man of bold and acute mind 
to this universal scepticism, because they oiSered 
nothing which could fix or satisfy him. And thus 
the sceptical spirit may deserve our notice as indica- 

« 

* Delamb. M. A. p. 125-8. 



250 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

tions of the defects of that system of doctrine which 
was too feeble in demonstration to control such 
resistance. 

The most remarkable of these philosophical scep- 
tics is Sextus Empiricus ; so called, from his belongs 
ing to that medical sect which was termed the emfi" 
ricalf in contradistinction to the rational and metiuh 
diced sects. His works contain a series of treatises, 
directed against all the divisions of the science of 
his time. He has chapters against the Geometers, 
against the Arithmeticians, against the Astrologers, 
against the Musicians, as well as against Gramma* 
rians. Rhetoricians and Logicians ; and, in short, as a 
modem writer haa said, his scepticism is employed 
as a sort of frame-work which embraces an encyclo-* 
pedical view of human knowledge. It must be 
stated, however, that his objections are rather to the 
metaphysics, than to the details of the sciences ; he 
rather denies the possibility of speculative truth in 
general, than the experimental truths which had 
been then obtained. Thus his objections to geo- 
metry and arithmetic are founded on abstract cavils 
concerning the nature of points, letters, unities, &c. 
And when he comes to speak against astrology, he 
says, ^^ I am not going to consider that perfect 
science which rests upon geometry and arithmetic ; 
for I have already shown the weakness of those 
sciences; nor that fitculty of prediction (of 
the motions of the heavens) which belongs to 
the pupils of Eudoxus, and Hipparchus, and the 



INDISTINCTNESS OF IDEAS. 251 

rest, which some call astronomy; for that is an 
observation of phenomena, like a^culture or navi- 
gation ; but against the art of prediction from the 
time of birth, which the Chaldeans exercise." Sex- 
tus, therefore, though a sceptic by profession, was 
not insensible to the difference between experimen- 
tal knowledge and mystical dogmas, though the 
f&rmer had nothing which excited his admiration. 

The early writers of the Christian church deemed 
lightly of the philosophy of their pagan antagonists ; 
but this was on different grounds, as we shall here- 
after see. The spirit of bold examination and denial 
of authority appears to be still more uncongenial to the 
Mohammedan temper of thought ; yet one remark- 
able sceptic with regard to philosophy can be pointed 
out among the Saracen writers. This is Algazel, or 
Algezeli, who was a celebrated teacher at Bagdad in 
the eleventh century, and who declared himself the 
enemy, not only of the mixed peripatetic and Pla- 
tonic philosophy of his time, but of Aristotle him- 
self. His work, entitled " The Destructions of the 
Philosophers," is known to us by the refutation of 
it which Avicenna published, under the title of 
<< Destruction of AlgaeeFs Destructions of the Phi« 
lo60phers\" It appears that he contested the fimda^ 
mental principles of the Platonic and Aristotelian 
sohools, and denied the possibility of a known con« 
nexion between cause and efifect; thus making a 
prelude to the celebrated argumentation of Hume« 

* Degerando, Hist. Comp. des Syst. iy. 124. 



252 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES, 

In his work " On the Opinions of the Philosophers," 
he examined those opinions in particular which refer 
to the principles of the physical sciences. We can- 
not doubt that his objections, so far as they attacked 
the really-estabUshed truths of astronomy and othw 
sciences, must have implied confusion of apprehen- 
sion both in him and in those whom he persuaded. 

6. Neglect of Physical Redsoning in Christendom.^^ 
If the Arabians, who, during the ages of which we 
are speaking, were the most eminent cultivators of 
science, entertained only such comparatively feeble 
and servile notions of its doctrines, it will easily be 
supposed, that in the Christendom of that period, 
where physical knowledge was comparatively negr 
lected, there was still less distinctness. and vividness 
in the prevalent idea^i on such subjects. Indeed, 
during a considerable period of the history of the 
Christian church, and by many of its principal autho- 
rities, the study of natural philosophy was not only 
disregarded but discommended. The great practical 
doctrines which were presented to men's minds, ,and 
the serious tasks, of the regulation of the will and 
afiections, which religion impressed upon them, 
made inquiries of mere curiosity seem to be a repre- 
hensible misapplication of human powers ; . and many 
of the fathers of the church revived, in a still , more 
peremptory form, the opiniou of Socrates, that the 
only valuable philosophy is that which teaches us 
our moral duties and religious hopes*. Thus Euse- 

' Brucker iii. 317- 



INDISTINCTNESS OF IDEAS. 253 

bius says', " It is not through ignorance of the things 
admired by them, but through contempt of their 
useless labour, that we think little of these matters, 
turning our souls to the exercise of better things." 
When the thoughts were thus intentionally averted 
from those ideas which natural philosophy involves, 
the ideas inevitably became very indistinct in their 
minds; and they could not conceive that any other 
persons could find, on such subjects, grounds of clear 
conviction and certainty. They held the whole of 
their philosophy to be, as Lactantius^ asserts it to be, 
" empty and false." " To search," says he, " for the 
causes of natural things ; to inquire whether the 
sun be as large as he seems, whether the moon is 
convex or concave, whether the stars are fixed in the 
sky or float freely in the air ; of what size and of what 
material are the heavens ; whether they be at rest or 
in motion ; what is the magnitude of the earth ; on 
what foundations it is suspended and balanced ; — ^to 
dispute and conjecture on such matters, is just as if 
we chose to discuss what we think of a city in a 
remote country, of which we never heard but the 
name." It is impossible to express more forcibly 
that absence of any definite notions on physical sub- 
jects which led to this tone of thought. 

7. Question of Aniipodes.--^With such habits of 
thought, we are not to be surprised if the relations 
resulting from the best established theories were 

• Praep. Ev. xy. 61. ^ I. iii. init. 



254 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

apprehended in an imperfect and incongruous man- 
ner. We have some remarkable examples of this ; 
and a very noted one, in the celebrated question of 
the existence of Antipodes^ or persons inhabiting the 
opposite side of the globe of the earth, and conse- 
quently having the soles of their feet directly op- 
posed to ours. The doctrine of the globular form 
of the earth results, as we have seen, by a geome- 
trical necessity, from a clear conception of the vari- 
ous points of knowledge which we obtain, bearing 
upon that subject ; this doctrine was held distinctly 
by the Greeks ; it was adopted by all astronomers, 
Arabian and European, who followed them; and 
was, in feet, an inevitable part of every system of 
astronomy which gave a possible and intelligible 
representation of phenomena. But those who did 
not call before their minds any distinct representa- 
tion at all, and who referred the whole question to 
other relations than those of space, might still deny 
this doctrine ; and they did so. The existence of 
inhabitants on the opposite side of the terraqueous 
globe, was a fact of which experience alone could 
teach the truth or falsehood ; but the religious rela- 
tions, which extend alike to all mankind, were sup- 
posed to give the Christian philosopher grounds for 
deciding against the possibility of such a race of 
men. Lactantius" in the fourth century, argues this 
matter, in a way very illustrative of that impatience 

« 1. iii. 23. 



INDISTINCTNESS OF IDEAS. 265 

of such speculations, and consequent confusion of 
thought which we have mentioned. " Is it possible," 
he says, ^^ that men can be so absurd as to believe 
that the crops and trees on the other side of the 
earth hang downwards, and that men there have 
their feet higher than their heads ? If you ask of 
them how they defend these monstrosities? — ^how 
things do not fall away from the earth on that side ? 
they reply, that the nature of things is such that 
heavy bodies tend towards the centre, like the spokes 
of a wheel, while light bodies, as clouds, smoke, fire, 
tend from the centre towards the heavens on all 
sides. Now I am really at a loss what to say of 
those who, when they have once gone wrong, steadily 
persevere in their folly, and defend one absurd opi- 
nion by another." It is obvious that so long as the 
writer reftised to admit into his thoughts the funda* 
mental conception of their theory, he must needs be 
at a loss what to say to their arguments, without 
being on that account in any degree convinced of 
their doctrines. In the sixth century, indeed, in the 
reign of Justinian, we find a writer (Cosmas Indico- 
pleustes*) who does not rest in this obscurity of 
representation ; but in this case, the distinctness of 
his pictures only serves to show his want of any 
clear conception as to what suppositions would ex- 
plain the phenomena. He describes the earth as an 

• Montfaucon, Collectio Nova Patrum, t. ii. p. 113. Cosmas 
Indicopleustes. Christianorum Opiniones de Mundo, sire To- 
pographia Christiana. 



266 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

oblong floor, surrounded by upright walls, and 
covered by a vault, below which the heavenly bodies 
perform their revolutions, going round a certain high 
mountain, which occupies the northern parts of the 
earth, and makes night by intercepting the light of 
the sun. In Augustin** (who flourished a.d. 400) the 
opinion is treated on other grounds ; and without de- 
nying the globular form of the earth, it is asserted that 
there are no inhabitants on the opposite side, because 
no such race is recorded by Scripture amons: the de- 
scendants of Adam. Considexutions of the same 
kind operated in the well-known instance of Virgil, 
bishop of Salzburg, in the eighth century. When 
he was reported to Bonifece, archbishop of Mentz, 
as holding the existence of Antipodes, the prelate 
was shocked at the assumption, as it seemed to him, 
of a world of human beings, out of the reach of the 
conditions of salvation; and application was made 
to Pope Zachary for a censure of the holder of this 
dangerous doctrine. It does not however appear 
that this led to any severity ; and the story of the 
deposition of Virgil from his bishopric, which is 
circulated by Kepler and by more modem writers, 
is undoubtedly altogether felse. The same scruples 
continued to prevail among Christian writers to a 
later period ; and Tostatus * * notes the opinion of the 
rotundity of the earth as an unsafe doctrine, only a 
few years before Columbus visited the other hemi- 
sphere. 

'^ Civ. D. xvi. 9. '' Montfauc. Patr. t. ii. 



INDISTINCTNESS OP IDEAS. 257 

8. Intellectual Condition of the Meliffiotcs Orders. — 
It must be recollected, however, that though these 
were the views and tenets of many religious writers, 
and though they may be taken as indications of the 
prevalent and characteristic temper of the times of 
which we speafc, they never were universal. Such 
a confusion of thought affects the minds of many 
persons, even in the most enlightened times ; and in 
what we call the dark ages, though clear views on such 
subjects might be more rare, those who gave their 
minds to science, entertained the true opinion of the 
figure of the earth. Thus Boethius*' (in the sixth 
century) urges the smallness of the globe of the 
earth, compared with the heavens, as a reason to 
repress our love of glory. This work, it will be 
recollected, was translated into the Anglo-Saxon by 
our own Alfred. It was also commented on by 
Bede, \dio, in what he says on this passage, assents 
to the doctrine, and shows an acquaintance with 
Ptolemy and his commentators, both Arabian and 
Greek. Gerbert, in the tenth century, went from 
France to Spain to study astronomy with the Ara- 
bians, and soon surpassed his masters. He is re- 
ported to have &bricated clocks, and an astrolabe of 
peculiar construction. Gerbert afterwards, (in the 
last year of the first thousand from the birth of 
Christ,) became pope, by the name of Sylvester II. 
Among other cultivators of the sciences, some of 



la 



Boetliius, Cons. ii. pr. 7» 
VOL. I. S 



258 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

whom, from their proficiency, must have possessed 
with considerable clearness and steadiness the ele- 
mentary ideas on which it depends, we may here 
mention, after Montncla'*, Adelbold, whose work 
On the Sphere was addressed to Pope Sylvester, 
and whose geometrical reasonings are, according to 
Montucla^\ vague and chimerical; Hermann Con-» 
tractus, a monk of St. Gall, who, in 1050, published 
astronomical works; William of Hirsaugen, who 
followed this example in 1080 ; Robert of Lorraine, 
who was made Bishop of Hereford by William the 
Conqueror, in consequence of his astronomical know-f 
ledge. In the next century, Adelhard Goth, an 
Englishman, travelled among the Arabs for pur- 
poses of study, as Gerbert had done in the preceding 
age; and on his return, translated the Elements 
of Euclid, which he had brought from Spain or 
Egypt. Robert Grostete, Bishop of Lincoln, was 
the author of an epitome on the Sphere ; Roger 
Bacon, in his youth the contemporary of Robert 
and his brother Adam Marsh, praises very highly 
their knowledge in mathematics. 

" And here," says the French historian of mathe- 
matics, whom I have followed in the preceding rela- 
tion, ^^ it is impos^ibl^ pot to reflect that all those men 

who, if they did not augment the treasure of the 
scieuces, at least served to transmit it, were monks, or 
had been such originally. Convents were, during 

" Mont. i. 602. " Mont. i. 503. 



INDISTINCTNESS OF IDEAS. 259 

these stormy ages, the asylum of sciences and letters. 
Without these religious men, who, in the silence of 
their monasteries, occupied themselves in trans- 
cribing, in studying, and in imitating the works of 
the ancients, well or ill, those works would have 
perished ; perhaps not one of them would have come 
down to us. The thread which connects us with 
the Greeks and Romans would have been snapt 
asunder ; the precious productions of ancient litera* 
ture would no more exist for us, than the works, if 
there were any, published before the catastrophe 
which annihilated that highly scientific nation, 
which, according to Bailly, existed in remote ages 
in the centre of Tartary, or at the roots of Cau-i 
casus. In the sciences we should have had all to 
create ; and at the moment when the human mind 
i^ould have emerged from its stupor and shaken oiF 
its slumbers, we should have been no more advanced 
than the Greeks were after the taking of Troy." 
He adds, that this consideration inspires feelings 
towards the religious orders very different ftom those 
which, when he wrote, were prevalent among his 
countrymen. 

Except so far as their religious opinions inter- 
fered, it was natural that men who lived a life of 
quiet and study, and were necessarily in a great 
measure removed from the absorbing and blinding 
interests with which practical life occupies the 
thoughts, should cultivate science more successfully 

s 2 



260 PHYSICAL SCIENCE OF THE MIDDLE AGES. 

than others, precisely because their ideas on specu- 
lative subjects had time and opportunity to become 
clear and steady. The studies which were cultivated 
under the name of the Seven Liberal Arts neces- 
sarily tended to fiivour this effect. The Trivium'\ 
indeed, which consisted of Grammar, Logic, and 
Rhetoric, had no direct bearing upon those ideas 
with which physical science is concerned ; but the 
Quadriviunij Music, Arithmetic, Geometry, Astro- 
nomy, could not be pursued with any attention, 
without a corresponding improvement of the mind 
for purposes of sound knowledge ^*. 

9. Popular Opinions. — ^That, even in the best in- 
tellects, something was wanting to fit them for 
scientific progress and discovery, is obvious from 
the fact that science was so long absolutely sta- 
tionary. And I have endeavoured to show that one 
part of this deficiency was the requisite clearness 
and vigour of the fundamental scientific ideas. If 
these were wanting, even in the most powerful and 
most cultivated minds, we may easily conceive that 
still greater confusion and obscurity prevailed in the 
common class of mankind. They actually adopted 

»» Brack, iii. 597. 

*' Roger Bacon, in his Specula Mathematica, cap. i., says, 
^^Harum scientiarum porta et clavis est mathematica, quam 
sancti a principio mundi inyenerunt, etc. Cajus negligentia 
jam per triginta vel quadraginia annos destruxit totum 
studium Latinorum." I do not know on what occasion this 
neglect took place. 



INDISTINCTNESS OP IDEAS. 261 

the belief, however crude and inconsistent, that the 
fonn of the earth and heavens really is what at any 
place it appears to be ; that the earth is flat, and the 
waters of the sky sustained above a material floor, 
through which in showers they descend. Yet the 
true doctrines of astronomy appear to have had 
some popular circulation. For instance, a French 
poem of the time of Edward the Second, " called 
" Ymage du Monde," contains a metrical account of 
the earth and heavens, according to the Ptolemaic 
views ; and in a manuscript of this poem, preserved 
in the library of the University of Cambridge, there 
are representations, in accordance with the text, of 
a spherical earth, with men standing upright upon 
it on every side: and by way of illustrating the 
tendency of all things to the centre, perforations of 
the earth, entirely through its mass, are described 
and depicted; and figures are exhibited dropping 
balls down each of these holes, so as to meet in the 
interior. And, as bearing upon the perplexity 
which attends the motions bf wp and dmim^ when 
applied to the globular earth, and the change of the 
direction of gravity which would occur in passing 
the centre, the readers of Dante will recollect the 
extraordinary manner in which the poet and his 
guide emerge from the bottom of the abyss ; and the 
explanation which Virgil imparts to him of what he 
there sees. After they have crept through the aper- 
ture in which Lucifer is placed, the poet says. 



262 PHYSICAL 8CIEKCE OF THE MIDDLE AGES. 

lo lerai gli occhi e credetti yedere 
Ludfero com' io 1* area lasciato, 
E yidili le gambe in su tenere. 

" Quest! come e fitto 

Ei sottasopra?* .... 

" Quando mi yolsi, ta passast' il punto 
Al qual 8i traggon d' ogni parte i pesi." 

Inferno^ xxxiy. 

I raised mine eyes, 

Belieying that I Lucifer should see 
Where he was lately left, but law him now 
With legs held upward 

"'How standeth he in posture thus reversed T 



^ Thou wast on the other side so long as I 

Descended ; when I turned, thou didst o'erpass 

That point to which from every part is dragged 

All heayy substance." 

Cart. 

This is more philosophical than Milton's repre- 
sentation, in ft more scientific age, of Uriel sliding 
to the earth on a sun-beam, and sliding back again 
when the sun had sunk below the horizon. 

Uriel to his charge 

Betumed on that bright beam whose point now raised, 
Bore him slope downward to the sun, now fallen 
Beneath the Azores. 

P. L. b. ir. 

The philosophical notions of up and down are too 
much at variance with the obvious suggestions of 
our senses, to be held steadily and Justly by minds 
undisciplined in science. Perhaps it was some mis- 



INDISTINCTNESS OF IDEAS. 263 

understood statement of the curved surface of the 
ocean, which gave rise to the tradition of there 
being a part of the sea directly oveY the earth, from 
which at times an object has been known to fall, or 
an anchor to be let down. Even such whimsical 
famjies are not without instruction, and may serve to 
show the reader what that vagueness and obscurity 
of ideas is, of which I have been endeavouring to 
trace the prevalence in the dark ages. 

We now proceed to another of the features which 
appears to me to mark, in a very prominent manner, 
the character of the stationary period. 



264 



CHAPTER II. 

The Commentatorial Spirit of the 

Middle Ages. 

We have already noticed, that, after the first great 
achievements of the founders of sound speculation, 
in the different departments of human knowledge, 
had attracted the interest and admiration which 
those who became acquainted with them could not 
but give to them, there appeared a disposition among 
men to lean on the authority of some of these 
teachers ; — ^to study the opinions of others as the only 
mode of forming th§ir own ; — ^to read nature through 
books ; — ^to attend to what had been already thought 
and said, rather than to what really is and happens. 
This tendency of men's minds requires our particular 
consideration. Its manifestations were very im- 
portant, and highly characteristic of the stationary 
period ; it gave, in a great degree, a peculiar bias 
and direction to the intellectual activity of many 
centuries ; and the kind of labour with which specu- 
lative men were occupied in consequence of this bias, 
took the place of that examination of realities which 
must be their employment, in order that real know- 
ledge may make any decided progress. 

In some subjects, indeed, as, for instance, in the 
domains of morals, poetry, and the arts which aim 



THE COMMENTATORIAL SPIRIT. 265 

at beauty, this opposition between the study of 
former opinion and present reality, may not be so 
distinct ; inasmuch as it may be said by some, that, 
in these subjects^ opinions are realities; that the 
thoughts and feelings which prevail in mgn's minds 
are the material of our workmanship, the particulars 
from which we are to generalize, the instruments, 
which we are to use ; and that, therefore, to reject 
the study of antiquity, or even its authority, would 
be to show ourselves ignorant of the extent and 
mutual bearing of the elements with which we have 
to deal ;— would be to cut asunder that which we 
ought to unite into a vital whole. Yet even in the 
provinces of history and poetry, the poverty and 
servility of men's minds during the middle ages, are 
shown by indications so strong as to be truly re- 
markable ; for instance, in the efforts of the anti- 
quarians of almost every European country to assi- 
milate the early history of their own state to the 
poet's account of the foundation of Rome, by bringing 
from the sack of Troy, Brutus to England, Bavo 
to Flanders, and so on. But however this may be, 
our first business at present is, to trace the varying 
spirit of the physical philosophy of different ages ; 
trusting that, hereafter, this prefatory study will 
enable us to throw some light upon the other parts 
of philosophy. And in physics the case undoubt- 
edly was, that the labour of observation, which is 
one of the two great elements of the progress of 
knowledge, was in a great measure superseded by 



266 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

the collection, the analysis, the explanation, of pre- 
vious authors and opinions; experimenters were 
replaced by commentators ; criticism took the place 
of induction; and instead of great discoverers we 
had learned men. 

1. Natural Bms to Anihority. — It is very easy to 
see that, in such a bias of men's studies, there is 
something very natural ; however strained and tech- 
nical this erudition may have been, at least the 
propensities on which it depends are very general, 
and are easily seen. Deference to the authority of 
thoughtful and sagacious men, a disposition which 
we neither reject nor think we ought to reject, in 
practical matters, naturally clings to us, even in 
speculation. It is a satisfaction to us to suppose 
that there are, or have been, minds of transcendent 
powers, of wide and wise views, superior to the 
common errors and blindnesses of our nature. The 
pleasure of admiration, and the repose of confidence, 
are inducements to such a belief There are also other 
reasons why we willingly believe that there are in 
philosophy great teachers, so profound and sagacious, 
that, in order to arrive at truth, we have only to learn 
their thoughts, to understand their writings. There 
is a peculiar interest which men feel ia dealing with 
the thoughts of their fellow-meir, rather than with 
brute matter. Matter feels and excites no sympa- 
thies ; in seeking for mere laws of nature, there is 
nothing of mental intercourse with the great spirits 
of the past, as there is in studying Aristotle or Plato. 



THE COMMENTATORIAL SPIRIT. 267 

Moreover, a large portion of this employment is of 
a kind the most agreeable to most speculative 
minds, consisting in tracing the consequences of 
assumed principles : it is deductive like geometry ; 
and the principles of the teachers being known, and 
being undisputed, the deduction and application of 
their results is an obvious, self-satisfying, and iner^ 
haustible exercise of ingenuity. 

These causes, and probably others, make criticism 
and commentation flourish, when invention begins 
to fail, oppressed and bewildered by the acquisitions 
it has already made ; and when the vigour and hope 
of men's minds are enfeebled by civil and political 
changes. Accordingly S the Alexandrian school was 
eminently characterized by a spirit of erudition, of 
literary criticism, of interpretation, of imitation. 
These practices, which reigned first in their full 
vigour in the Museum, are likely to be, at all times, 
the leading propensities of similar academical insti- 
tutions. 

How natural it is to select a great writer as 
a paramount authority, and to ascribe to him ex- 
traordinary profiindity and sagacity, we may see, 
in the manner in which the Greeks looked upon 
Homer ; and the fancy which detected in his poems 
traces of the origin of all arts and sciences, has, as 
we know, found favour even in modem times. To 
pass over earlier instances of this feeling, we may 

* Degerando. Hist, des Syst. de Philos. iii. p. 134. 



268 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

observe, that Strabo begins his Geography by saying 
that he agrees with Hipparchus, who had declared 
Homer to be the first author of our geographical 
knowledge : and he does not confine the application 
of this assertion to the various and curious topogra- 
phical information which the Iliad and Odyssey 
contain, concerning the countries surrounding the 
Mediterranean ; but in phrases which, to most per- 
sons, might appear the mere play of a poetical fancy, 
or a casual selection of circumstances, he finds unques- 
tionable evidence of a correct knowledge of general 
geographical truths. Thus*, when Homer speaks of 
the sun "rising from the soft and deep-flowing 
ocean," of his " splendid blaze plimging in the ocean;" 
of the northern constellation 

"Alone imwashen by the ocean ware;** 

and of Jupiter " who goes to the ocean to feast with 
the blameless Ethiopians ;" Strabo is satisfied from 
these passages that Homer knew the dry land to be 
surrounded with water: and he reasons in like 
manner with respect to other points of geography. 

2. Character of Commentators. — ThiB spirit of 
commentation, as has already been suggested, turns 
to questions of taste, of metaphysics, of morals, v^dth 
far more avidity than to physics. Accordingly, 
critics and grammarians were peculiarly the growth 
of this school ; and, though the commentators some- 
times chose works of mathematical or physical 

• Strabo. i. p. 5. 



THE COMMENTATORIAL SPIRIT. 269 

science for their subject (as Proclus, who commented 
on Euclid's Geometry, and Simplicius, on Aris- 
totle's Physics,) these commentaries were, in fact, 
rather metaphysical than mathematical. It does not 
appear that the commentators have, in any instance, 
illustrated the author by bringing his assertions of 
facts to the test of experiment. Thus, when Sim- 
plicius comments on the passage concerning a 
vacuum, which we formerly adduced, he notices the 
argument which went upon the assertion, that a 
vessel full of ashes would contain as much water as 
an empty vessel ; and he mentions various opinions 
of different authors, but no trial of the fact. Eu- 
demus had said, that the ashes contained something 
hot, as quicklime does, and that by means of this, a 
part of the water was evaporated ; others supposed 
the water to be condensed, and so on'. 

The commentator's professed object is to explain, 
to enforce, to illustrate. He endeavours to adapt 
the work on which he employs himself to the state 
of information and of opinion in his own time ; to 
elucidate obscurities and technicalities; to supply 
steps omitted in the reasoning; but he does not 
seek to obtain additional truths or new generaliza- 
tions. He undertakes only to give what is virtually 
contained in his author; to develope, but not to 
create. He is a cultivator of the thoughts of others : 
his labour is not spent on a field of his own ; he 
ploughs but to enrich the granary of another man. 

' Simplicius, p. 170. 



270 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

Thus he does not work as a freeman, but as one 
in a serrile condition ; or rather his is a menial, 
and not a productiye service : his office is to adorn 
the appearance of his master, not to increase his 
wealth. 

Yet though the commentator^s employment is 
thus subordinate and dependent, he is easily led to 
attribute to it the greatest importance and dignity. 
To elucidate good books is» indeed, a useful task ; 
and when those who undertake this work execute 
it well, it would be most unreasonable to find fault 
with them for not doing more. But the critic, long 
and earnestly employed on one author, may easily 
underrate the relative value of other kinds of mental 
exertion. He may ascribe too large dimensions to 
that which occupies the whole of his own field of 
vision. Thus he may come to consider such study 
as the highest aim, and best evidence of human 
genius. To understand Aristotle, or Plato, may 
appear to him to comprise all that is possible of 
profundity and acuteness. And when he has 
travelled over a portion of their domain, and satisfied 
himself that of this he too is master, he may look 
with complacency at the circuit he has made, and 
speak of it as a labour of vast effort and difficulty. 
We may quote, as an expression of this temper, 
the language of Sir Henry Savile, in concluding 
a course of lectures on Euclid, delivered at Oxford*. 

* Exolvi per Dei gratiam, Domini auditores, promissum ; 
liberayi fidem meam; expHcayi pro meo modulo, definitiones, 



THE COMMENTATORIAL SPIRIT. 271 

« By the grace of God, gentlemen hearers, I have 
performed my promise ; I have redeemed my pledge. 
I have explained, according to my ability, the defi- 
nitions, postulates, axioms, and first eight proposi-> 
tions of the Elements of Euclid. Here, sinking 
under the weight of years, I lay down my art and 
my instruments." 

We here speak of the peculiar province of the 
commentator ; for undoubtedly, in many instances, 
a comment on a received author has been made the 
vehicle of conveying systems and doctrines entirely 
different from those of the author himself; as, for 
instance, when the New Platonists wrote, taking 
Plato for their text. The labours of learned men 
in the stationary period, which came under this 
description, belong to another class. 

3. Greek Commentators on Aristotle. — ^The com-« 
mentators or disciples of the great philosophers did 
not assume at once their servile character. At first 
their object was to supply and correct, as well as to 
explain their teacher. Thus among the earlier com- 
mentators of Aristotle, Theophrastus invented five 
moods of syllogism in the first figure, in addition to 
the four invented by Aristotle, and stated with 
additional accuracy the rules of hypothetical syllo- 
gisms. He also, not only collected much informa- 
tion concerning animals, and natural events, which 

petitiones, communes sententias, et octo priores propositiones 
Elementorum Euclidis. Hie, annis essus, cyclos artemque 
repoDO. 



272 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

Aristotle had omitted, but often differed wiiii his 
master ; as, for instance, oonceming Hie saltness of 
the sea : this, which the Stagirite attributed to the 
effect of the evaporation produced by the sun's rays, 
was ascribed by Theophrastus to beds of salt at the 
bottom. Porphyry*, who flourished in the third 
century, wrote a book on the PredicaiieSf which was 
found to be so suitable a complement to the Predi- 
caments or Categories of Aristotle, that it was usually 
prefixed to that treatise ; and the two have been used 
as an elementary work together, up to modem times. 
The Predicables are the five steps which the gradations 
of generality and particularity introduce; — -gemtSi 
spedes^ differmcey indimdncd^ accident; — ^the Categories 
are the ten heads under which assertions or predi- 
cations may be arranged ; — ^namely, substance^ qwm-- 
iHtyy relation^ qtiality, place^ time^ position^ habity action^ 
passion. 

At a later period, the Aristotelian commentators 
became more servile, and followed the author step 
by step, explaining, according to their views, his 
expressions and doctrines; often, indeed, with ex- 
treme prolixity, expanding his clauses into sentences, 
and his sentences into paragraphs. Alexander 
Aphrodisiensis, who lived at the end of the second 
century, is of this class ; " sometimes usefal," as one 
of the recent editors of Aristotle says'; " but by the 
prolixity of his interpretation, by his perverse itch 

* Buhle, Arist. i. 284. « Bulile, i. 288. 



THE COMMENTATORIAL SPIRIT. 273 

for liimself discussing the argument expounded by 
Aristotle, for defending his opinions, and for refuting 
or reconciling those of others, he rather obscures 
than enlightens." At various times, also, some of 
the commentators, and especially those of the Alex- 
andrian school, endeavoured to reconcile, or combined 
without reconciling, opposing doctrines of the great 
philosophers of the earlier times. Simplicius, for 
instance, and, indeed, a great number of the Alex- 
andrian philosophers ^ as Alexander, Ammonius, and 
others, employed themselves in the futile task of 
reconciling the doctrines of the Pythagoreans, of the 
Eleatics, of Plato, and of the Stoics, with those of 
Aristotle. Boethius* entertained the design of 
translating into Latin the whole of Aristotle's and 
Plato's works, and of showing their agreement ; a 
gigantic plan, which he never executed. Others 
employed themselves in disentangling the confusion 
which such attempts produced, as John the Gramma- 
rian, surnamed Philoponus, "the labour-loving;" who, 
towards the end of the seventh century, maintained 
that Aristotle was entirely misunderstood by Por- 
phyry and Proclus ', who had pretended to incorporate 
his doctrines into those of the New Platonic school, or 
even to reconcile him with Plato himselfon the subject 
of ideas. Others, again, wrote epitomes, compounds, 
abstracts; and endeavoured to throw the works 
of the philosopher into some simpler and more 

"^ BuHle, i. 311. • Degerando. Hist, des Syst. iv. 100. 

. • lb. iv. 155. 
VOL. I. T 



274 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

obviously regillal* fomi, as John of DaHiascud^ in the 
middle of the eighth century, who made abstracts of 
some of Aristotle's works, and introduced the study 
of the author into theological education. These two 
tmters lived under the patronage of the Arabs J the 
former was favoured by Amrou, the conqueror of 
Egypt ; the latter was at first secretary to the Caliph, 
but afterwards withdrew to a monastery ^•. 

At this period the Arabs became the fosterei*s alid 
patrons of philosophy rather than the Greeks. Jus- 
tinian had, by an edict, closed the school of Athens^ 
the last of the schools of heathen philosophy. Ledj 
the Isaurian, who was a zealous Iconoclast^ abolished 
also the schools where general knowledge had been 
taught, in combination with Christianity^*; yet the 
line of the Aristotelian commentators was continued^ 
though feebly, to the later ages of the Greek empire^ 
Anna Comnena^' mentions a Eiistratus who em- 
ployed himself upon the dialectic aiid moral treatises, 
and whom she does not hesitate to elevate above 
the Stoics and Platonists, for his talent in philoso- 
phical discussions. Nicephorus Blemmydes wrote 
logical and physical epitomes for the use of John 
t)ucasj George Pachymeus composed an epitome 
of the philosophy of Aristotle, and a compend* of 
his logic : Theodore Metochytes, who was famous in 
his time alike for his eloquence and his learning, 
has left a paraphrase of the books of Aristotle on 

'' Beg. iv. 150. '' lb. iv. 163 ^» lb. 167. 



THE COMMENTATORIAL SPIRIT. 275 

Physics, on the Soul, the Heavens'*, &c. Fabricius 
states that this writer has a chapter, the object of 
which is to prove, that all philosophers, and Aristotle 
and Plato in particular, have disdained the authority 
of their predecessors. He could hardly help re- 
marking, in how different a spirit philosophy had 
been pursued since their time. 

8. Greek Commentators of Plato and others. — I 
have spoken principally of the commentators of 
Aristotle, for he was the great subject of the com- 
mentators proper ; and though the name of his rival, 
Plato, was graced by a list of attendants hardly less 
numerous, these, the Neoplatonists, as they are 
called, had introduced new elements into the doc- 
trines of their nominal master, to such an extent 
that they must be placed in a different class. We 
may observe here however, how, in this school as 
in the Peripatetic, the race of commentators multi- 
plied itself Porphyry, who commented on Aristotle, 
was commented on by Ammonius ; Plotinus's En- 
neads were commented on by Proclus and Dexippus. 
Psellus^* the elder was a paraphrast of Aristotle; 
Psellus the younger, in the eleventh century, at- 
tempted to restore the New Platonic school. The 
former of these two writers had for his pupils two 
men, the emperor Leo, sumamed the Philosopher, 
and Photius the patriarch, who exerted themselves 
to restore the study of literature at Constantinople. 



18 



Deg. ir. 168. " lb. ir. 169. 

T 2 



276 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

We still possess the Collection of Extracts of Photius, 
which, like that of Stobseus and others, shows the 
tendency of the age to compilation, abstracts, and 
epitomes, — ^the extinction of philosophical vitality. 

4. Arabian Commentators of Aristotle.— The reader 
might perhaps have expected, that when the philo- 
sophy of the Greeks was carried among a new race 
of intellects, of a different national character and 
condition, the chain of this servile tradition would 
have been broken ; that some new thoughts would 
have started forth ; that some new direction, some 
new impulse, would have been given to the search 
for truth. It might have been anticipated that we 
should have had schools among the Arabians which 
should rival the Peripatetic, Academic and Stoic 
among the Greeks ; — ^that they would preoccupy the 
ground on which Copernicus and Galileo, Lavoisier 
and Linnaeus, won their fame; — ^that they would 
make the next great steps in the progressive sciences. 
Nothing of this, however, happened. The Arabians 
cannot claim, in science or philosophy, any really 
great names; they produced no men and no dis- 
coveries which have materially influenced the course 
and destinies of human knowledge; they tamely 
adopted the intellectual servitude of the nation 
which they conquered by their arms ; they joined 
themselves at once to the string of slaves who were 
dragging the car of Aristotle and Plotinus. Nor, 
perhaps, on a little further reflection, shall we be 
surprised at this want of vigour and productive 



THE COMMENTATORIAL SPIRIT. 277 

power, in this period of apparent natural youth. 
The Arabs had not been duly prepared rightly to 
enjoy and use the treasures of which they thus 
became possessed. They had, like most uncivilized 
nations, been passionately fond of their indigenous 
poetry; their imagination had been awakened, but 
their rational powers and speculative tendencies 
were still torpid. They received the Greek philo- 
sophy without having passed through those grada- 
tions of ardent curiosity and keen research, of ob- 
scurity brightening into clearness, of doubt succeeded 
by the joy of discovery, by which the Greeks had 
had their minds enlarged and exercised. Nor had 
the Arabs ever enjoyed, as the Greeks had, the in- 
dividual consciousness, the independent volition, the 
intellectual freedom, arising from the freedom of poli- 
tical institutions. They had not felt the contagious 
mental activity of a small city ; the elation arising 
from the general sympathy in an admiration of specu- 
lative pursuits dijffused through an intelligent and 
acute audience ; in short, they had not had a national 
education such as fitted them to be disciples of Plato 
and Hipparchus. Hence, their new literary wealth 
rather encumbered and enslaved, than enriched and 
strengthened them : in their want of taste for intel- 
lectual freedom, they were glad to give themselves 
up to the guidance of Aristotle and other dogmatists. 
Their military habits had accustomed them to look 
to a leader ; their reverence for the book of their 
law had prepared them to accept a philosophical 



278 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

Koran also. Thus the Arabians, though they never 
translated the Greek poetry, translated, and merely 
translated, the Greek philosophy ; they followed the 
Greek philosophers without deviation, or, at least, 
without any philosophical deviations. They became 
for the most part Aristotelians ; — studied not only 
Aristotle, but the commentators of Aristotle ; and 
themselves swelled the vast and unprofitable herd* 

The philosophical works of Aristotle had, in some 
measure, made their way in the east, before the 
growth of the Saracen power. In the sixth century, 
a Syrian, Uranus'*, encouraged by the love of philo^ 
JKjphy manifested by Cosroes, had translated some 
of the writings of the Stagirite; about the same 
time, Sergius had given some translations in Syriac. 
In the seventh century, Jacob of Edessa translated 
into this language the Dialectics, and added Notes to 
the work. Such labours became numerous; and 
the first Arabic translations of Aristotle were formed 
upon these Persian or Syriac texts ; in this succession 
of transfusions, some mistakes must inevitably have 
been introduced. 

The Arabian interpreters of Aristotle, like a large 
portion of the Alexandrian ones, gave to the philo- 
sopher a tinge of opinions borrowed from another 
source, which I shall have to speak of under the 
name of mysticism. But they are, for the most 
part, sufficiently strong examples of the peculiar 

'' Deg. iv. 196. 



THE COMMBNTATORIAI4 SPIRIT. 279 

spirit of compientatiou, to make it fitting to notice 
thPW here. At the head of them stands '• Alkindi, 
who 9;ppears to have lived at the court of Almamon, 
and who wrote commentaries on the Organon of 
Aristotle. But Alfarabi was the glory of the school 
of Bagdad ; his knowledge included mathematics, 
aatrojiomy, medicine and philosophy. Born in an 
elevated rank, and possessed of a rich patrimony, he 
led an austere life, and devoted himself altogether 
to study and meditation. He employed himself 
particularly in unfolding the import of Aristotle's 
treatise on the Soul, Avicenna'^ (Ebn Sina) was at 
once the Hippocrates and the Aristotle of the Arar 
bians; and certainly the most extraordinary man 
that the nation produced. In the course of an un-r 
fortunate and stormy life, occupied by politics and 
by pleasures, he produced works which \vere long 
revered as a sort of code of science. In particular, 
his writings on medicine, though they contain little 
besides a compilation of Hippocrates and Galen, took 
the place of both, even in the universities of Europe ; 
and were studied as models at Paris and Montpellier, 
till the end of the seventeenth century, at which 
period they fell into an almost complete oblivion. 
Avieenna is conceived, by some modem writers '^ to 
have shown some power of original thinking in his 
representations of the Aristotelian Logic and Meta- 

»• Deg. It. 187. '^ lb. iv. 205. 

^« lb. ir. 206. 



280 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

physics. Averroes (Ebn Roshd) of Cordova, was 
the most illustrious of the Spanish Aristotelians, and 
became the guide of the schoolmen'*, being placed 
by them on a level with Aristotle himself, or above 
him. He translated Aristotle from the first Syriac 
version, not being able to read the Greek text. He 
aspired to, and retained for centuries, the title of 
the Commenkttor ; and he deserves this title by the 
servility with which he maintains that Aristotle*' 
carried the sciences to the highest possible degree, 
measured their whole extent, and fixed their ulti- 
mate and permanent boundaries ; although his works 
are conceived to exhibit a trace of the New Plato- 
nism. Some of his writings are directed against 
an Arabian sceptic, of the name of Algazel, whom 
we have already noticed. 

When the schoolmen had adopted the supremacy 
of Aristotle to the extent in which Averroes main- 
tained it, their philosophy went further than a 
system of mere commentation, and became a system 
of dogmatism ; we must, therefore, in another chap- 
ter, say a few words more of the Aristotelians in 
this point of view, before we proceed to the revival 
of science ; but we must previously consider some 
other features in the character of the Stationary 
Period. 

*• Deg. iy. 247. Ayerroes died a. d. 1206. " Deg. iy. 248. 



281 



CHAPTER HI. 

Op the Mysticism of the Middle Ages. 

It has been already several times hinted, that a new 
and peculiar element was introduced into the Greek 
philosophy which occupied the attention of the 
Alexandrian school ; and that this element tinged a 
large portion of the speculations of succeeding ages. 
We may speak of this peculiar element as mysticism ; 
for, from the notion usually conveyed by this term, 
the reader will easily apprehend the general cha- 
racter of the tendency now spoken of; and espe- 
cially when he sees its effect pointed out in various 
subjects. Thus, instead of referring the events of 
the external world to space and time, to sensible 
connexion and causation, men attempted to reduce 
such occurrences under spiritual and supersensual 
relations and dependencies ; they referred them to 
superior intelligences, to theological conditions, to 
past and ftiture events in the moral world, to states 
of mind and feelings, to the creatures of an imagi- 
nary mythology or demonology. And thus their 
physical science became magic, their astronomy be- 
came astrology, the study of the composition of 
bodies became alchemy, mathematics became the 
contemplation of the spiritual relations of number 
and figure, and philosophy became theosophy. 



282 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

The examination of this feature in the history of the 
human mind is important for us^ in consequence of its 
influence upon the employments and the thoughts 
of the tunes now under our notice. This tendency 
materially affected both men's speculations and 
their labours in the pursuit of knowledge. By its 
direct operation, it gave rise to the newer Platonic 
philosophy among the Greeks, and to corresponding 
doctrines among the Arabians ; and by calling into 
a prominent place astrology, alchemy, and magic, it 
long occupied most of the real observers of the 
material world. In this manner it delayed and im- 
peded the progress of true science ; for we shall see 
reason to believe that human knowledge lost more 
by the perversion of men's minds and the misdireo- 
tion of their efforts, than it gained by any increase of 
zeal arising from the peculiar hopes and objects of 
the mystics. 

It is not to our purpose to attempt any general 
view of the progress and fortunes of the various forms 
of mystical philosophy ; but only to exhibit some of 
its characters, in so far as they illustrate those ten- 
dencies of thought which accompanied the retrogra- 
dation of inductive science. And of these, the lead- 
ing feature which demands our notice is that already 
alluded to ; namely, the practice of referring things 
and events, not to clear and distinct relations, obvi- 
ously applicable to such cases ;-r-not to general rules 
capable of direct verification ; but to notions vague, 
distant, and vast, which we cannot bring into con- 



THEIB MYSTICISM. 283 

taet with facts, because they belong to a different 
region from the facts ; as when we connect natural 
events with moral or historical causes, or seek spiri- 
tual meanings in the properties of number and 
figure. Thus the character of mysticism is, that it 
refers particulars, not to generalizations homogeneous 
and immediate, but to such as are heterogeneous and 
remote ; to which we must add, that the process of 
this reference is not a calm act of the intellect, but 
is accompanied with a glow of enthusiastic feeling, 
1. Neophionic Theosophy. — The Newer Plor 
tonism is the first example of this mystical philo- 
sophy which I shall consider. The main points 
which here require our notice are, the doctrine of an 
intellectual world resulting from the act of the 
Divine Mind, as the only reality ; and the aspiration 
after the union of the human soul with this Divine 
Mind, as the object of human existence. The 
*' ideas" of Plato were forms of our knowledge ; 
but among the Neoplatonists they became really 
existing, indeed the only really existing, objects; 
and the inaccessible scheme of the universe which 
these ideas constitute, was offered as the great sub- 
ject of philosophical contemplation. The desire of 
the human mind to approach towards its Creator 
and Preserver, and to obtain a spiritual access to Him, 
leads to an employment of the thoughts which is well 
worth the notice of the religious philosopher ; but 
such an effort, even when founded on revelation and 
well regulated, is not a means of advance in physics : 



284 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

and when it is the mere result of natural enthu- 
siasm, it may easily obtain such a place in men's 
minds as to unfit them for the successful prosecution 
of natural philosophy. The temper, therefore, which 
introduces such supernatural communion into the 
general course of its speculations, may be properly 
treated as mystical, and as one of the causes of the 
decline of science in the Stationary Period. The 
Neoplatonic philosophy requires our notice as one 
of the most remarkable forms of this mysticism. 

Though Ammonius Saccas, who flourished at the 
end of the second century, is looked upon as the 
beginner of the Neoplatonists, his disciple Plo- 
tinus is, in reality, the great founder of the school, 
both by his works, which still remain to us, and by 
the enthusiasm which his character and manners in- 
spired among his followers. He lived a life of medi- 
tation, gentleness, and self-denial, and died in the 
second year of the reign of Claudius (a. d. 270.) 
His disciple, Porphyry, has given us a Life of him, 
from which we may see how well his habitual man- 
ners were suited to make his doctrines impressive. 
" Plotinus, the philosopher of our time," Porphyry 
thus begins his biography, " appeared like a person 
ashamed that he was in the body. In consequence 
of this disposition, he could not bear to talk con- 
cerning his family, or his parents, or his country. 
He would not allow himself to be represented by a 
painter or statuary ; and once^ when AureUus en- 
treated him to permit a likeness of him to be taken, 



THEIR MYSTICISM. 285 

he said, * Is it not enough for us to carry this image 
in which nature has enclosed us, but we must also try 
to leave a more durable image of this image, as if it 
were so great a sight V And he retained the same 
temper to the last. When he was dying, he said, 
* I am trying to bring the divinity which is in us to 
the divinity which is in the universe.' " He was 
looked upon by his successors with extraordinary 
admiration and reverence ; and his disciple Porphyry 
collected from his lips, or from fragmental notes, the 
six Enneads of his doctrines (that is, parts each 
consisting of nhie books,) which he arranged and 
annotated. 

We have no difficulty in finding in this remark- 
able work examples of mystical speculation. Besides 
the general tendency of the doctrines, the intelli- 
gible world of realities or essences corresponds to 
the world of sense ^ in the classes of things which it 
includes. To the intelligible world, man's mind 
ascends, by a triple road which Plotinus figuratively 
calls that of the musician, the lover, the philo- 
sopher*. The activity of the human soul is identi- 
fied by analogy with the motion of the heavens. 
" This activity is about a middle point, and thus 
it is circular ; but a middle point is not the same in 
body and in the soul ; in that, the middle point is 
local, in this, it is that on which the rest depends. 
There is, however, an analogy ; for as in one case, so 
in the other, there must be a middle point, and as 

^ vi Ennead iii. 1. ' ii E. ii. 2. 



286 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

the sphere revolres about its centre, the soul 
revolves about God through its affections^'* 

The conclusion of the work is", as might be sup- 
posed, upon the approach to, union with, and fruition 
of God. The author refers again to the analogy 
between the movements of the soul and those of 
the heavens. " We move round him like a choral 
dance; even when we look from him we revolve 
about him ; we do not always look at him, but when 
we do, we have satisfaction and rest, and the har- 
mony which belongs to that divine movement. In 
this movement, the mind beholds the fountain of 
life, the fountain of mind, the origin of being, the 
cause of good, the root of the soul*." ** There will 
be a time when this vision shall be continual ; the 
mind being no more interrupted, nor suflfering any 
perturbation from the body. Yet that which be- 
holds is not that which is disturbed ; and when this 
vision becomes dim, it does not obscure the know- 
ledge which resides in demonstration, and faith, and 
reasoning ; but the vision itself is not reason, but 
greater than reason, and before reason*." 

The fifth book of the third Ennead, has for its 
isubject the Daemon which belongs to each man. It 
is entitled " Concerning Love ;" and the doctrine ap- 
pears to be, that the love, or common source of the 
passions which is in each man's mind, is " the daemon 
which they say accompanies each man*." These 

« vi Enn. ix. 8. * lb. 9. ' lb. 10. 

' Ficinus, Comm. in y. Enn. iii. 



THEIR MYSTICISM. 287 

deemons were, however, (at least by later writers,) in- 
vested with a visible aspect and with a personal cha- 
i*aeter, including a resemblance of human passions and 
inbtives. It is curious thus to see an untenable and 
visionary generalization falling back into the domain 
of the senses and the fancy, after a vain attempt to 
support itself in the region of the reason. This ima- 
gination soon produced pretensions to the power of 
Inaking these daemons or genii visible ; and the Trea- 
tise on the Mysteries of the Egyptians, which is attri- 
buted to lamblichus, gives an account of the secret 
Ceremonies, the mysterious words, the sacrifices and 
expiations, by which this was to be done. 

It is unnecessary for us to dwell on the progress 
of this school; to point out the growth of the 
theurgy which thus arose; or to describe the at- 
tempts to claim a high antiquity for this system^ 
knd to make Orpheus, the poet, the first promulgator 
of its doctrines. The system, like all mystical sys*- 
terns, assumed the character rather of a religion than 
of a theory. The opinions of its disciples materially 
influenced their lives. It gave the world the spec- 
tacle of an austere morality, a devotional exaltation, 
combined With the grossest superstitions of Paganism. 
The successors of lamblichus appeared rather to 
hold a priesthood, than the chair of a philoso- 
phical schools They were persecuted by Constan- 
tino and Constantius, as opponents of Christianity. 

' Deg. iii. 407. 



288 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

Sopater, a Syrian philosopher of this school, was 
beheaded by the former emperor, on a charge that 
he had bound the winds by the power of magic'. 
But Julian, who shortly after succeeded to the 
purple, embraced with ardour the opinions of lam- 
blichus. Proclus (who died A. D. 487,) was one of the 
greatest of the teachers of this school"; and was, 
both in his Ufe and doctrines, a worthy successor of 
Plotinus, Porphyry, and lamblichus. We possess a 
biography, or rather a panegyric of him, by his dis- 
ciple Marinus, in which he is exhibited as a repre- 
sentation of the ideal perfection of the philosophic 
character, according to the views of the Neopla^ 
tonists. His virtues are arranged as physical, 
moral, purificatory, theoretic, and theurgic. Even 
in his boyhood, Apollo and Minerva visited him in 
his dreams : he studied oratory at Alexandria, but it 
was at Athens that Plutarch and Lysianus initiated 
him in the mysteries of the New Platonists. He 
received a kind of consecration at the hands of the 
daughter of Plutarch, the celebrated Asclepigenia, 
who introduced him to the traditions of the Chal- 
deans, and the practices of theurgy; he was also 
admitted to the mysteries of Eleusis. He became 
celebrated for his knowledge and eloquence; but 
especially for his skill in the supernatural arts which 
were connected with the doctrines of his sect. He 
appears before us rather as a hierophant than a 
philosopher. A large portion of his life was spent in 

• Gibbon, iii. 352. • beg. iii. 419. 



THEIR MYSTICISM. 289 

evocations, purifications, fiistings, prayers, hjnmns, in- 
tercourse with apparitions, and with the gods, and in 
the celebration of the festivals of Paganism, especially 
those which were held in honour of the Mother of the 
Gods. His religious admiration extended to all forms 
of mythology. The philosopher, said he, is not the 
priest of a single religion, but of all the religions in 
the world. Accordingly, he composed hymns in 
honour of all the divinities of Greece, Rome, Egypt, 
Arabia ; — ^Christianity alone was excluded from his 
favour. 

2. Mystical Aritiimetic. — It is unnecessary further 
to exemplify, from Proclus, the general mystical 
character of the school and time to which he be- 
longed; but we may notice more specially one of the 
forms of this mysticism, which very frequently offers 
itself to our notice, especially in him ; and which we 
may call mystical arithmetic. Like all the kinds of 
mysticism, this consists in the attempt to connect 
our conceptions of external objects by general and 
inappropriate notions of goodness, perfection, and 
relation to the divine essence and government; in- 
stead of referring such conceptions to those appro- 
priate ideas, which, by diie attention, become per- 
fectly distinct, and capable of being positively ap- 
plied and verified. The ^subject which is thus dealt 
with, in the doctrines of which we now speak, is 
number; a notion which tempts men into these 
visionary speculations qjore naturally than any 
other. For number is really applicable to moral 

VOL. I. u 



290 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

notions, — ^to emotions and feelings, and to their ob- 
jects, — as well as to the things of the material world. 
Moreover, by the discovery of the principle of musical 
concords, it had been found, probably most unex- 
pectedly, that numerical relations were closely con- 
nected with sounds which could hardly be distin- 
guished f5pom the expression of thought and feeling ; 
and a suspicion might easily arise, that the universe, 
both of matter and of thought, might contain many 
general and abstract truths of some analogous kind. 
The relations of number have so wide a bearing, that 
the ramifications of such a suspicion could not easily 
be exhausted, when men were willing to follow 
them into darkness and vagueness; which it is 
precisely the mystical tendency to do. Accord- 
ingly, this kind of speculation appeared very early, 
and showed itself first among the Pythagoreans, 
as we might have expected, from the attention 
which they gave to the theory of harmony: and 
this, as well as some other of the doctrines of 
the Pythagorean philosophy, was adopted by the 
later Platonists, and, indeed, by Plato himself, whose 
speculations concerning number have decidedly a 
mystical character. The mere mathematical propor- 
tions of numbers,-^s odd and even, perfect and im- 
peri^ect, abundant and defective,--.were, by a willing 
submission to an enthusiastic bias, connected with 
the notions of good and beauty, which the terms 
suggested ; and principles^resulting from such a con- 
nexion were woven into a wide and complex system. 



THEIR MYSTICIgM. 291 

It is not necessary to dwell long on this subject; the 
mere titles of the works which treated of it show its 
nature. Archytas** is said to have written a treatise 
on the number ten: Telauge, the daughter of Pytha- 
goras, wrote on the number four. This number, 
indeed, which was known by the name of the 7V- 
tractys, was very celebrated in the school of Pytha- 
goras. It is mentioned in the " Golden Verses," 

« 

which are ascribed to him: the pupil is conjured to 
be virtuous, 

Nai jxib Tov afierepa '^^v'x^a irapahovra T€rpa)(rvv 
Ilarfav Aevvdov (jyvaeat)^ 

By him who stampt The Four upon the mind, 
The Four^ the fount of nature's endless stream. 

In Plato's works, we have evidences of a similar 
belief in religious relations of number ; and in the 
New Platonists, this doctrine was established as a 
system. Proclus, of whom we have been speaking, 
founds his philosophy, in a great measure, on the 
relation of unity and multiple ; from this, he is led 
to represent the causality of the Divine Mind by 
three triads of abstractions ; and in the developement 
of one part of this system, the number seven is 
introduced * *. " The intelligible and intellectual gods 
produce all things triadically; for the monads in 
these are divided according to number; and what 
the monad was in the former, the number is in the 
latter. And the intellectual gods produce all things 

** Mont. ii. 123. " Procl. v. 3., Taylors Translation. 

U 2 



292 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

• 

hebdomically ; for they evolve the intelligible, and 
at the same time intellectual triads, into intellectual 
hebdomads, and expand their contracted powers into 
intellectual variety." Seven is what is called by 
arithmeticians a prime number, that is, it cannot 
be produced by the multiplication of other numbers. 
In the language of the New Platonists, the number 
seven is said to be a virgin, and without a mother, 
and it is therefore sacred to Minerva. The number 
six is a perfect number, and is consecrated to Venus. 
The relations of space were dealt with in like 
manner, the geometrical properties being associated 
with such physical and metaphysical notions as 
vague thought and lively feeling could anyhow 
connect with them. We may consider, as an ex- 
ample of this^', Plato's opinion concerning the par- 
ticles of the four elements. He gave to each kind 
of particle one of the five regular solids, about which 
the geometrical speculations of himself and his 
pupils had been employed. The particles of fire 
were pyramids, because they are sharp, and tend 
upwards ; those of earth are cubes, because they are 
stable, and fill space ; the particles of air are octahe- 
dral, as most nearly resembling those of fire ; those 
of water are icositetrahedron, as most nearly spheri- 
cal. The dodecahedron is the figure of the element 
of the heavens, and shows its influence in other 
things, as in the twelve signs of the zodiac; we see 



i« 



Stanley, Hist. Phil. 



THEIR MYSTICISM. 293 

how loosely space and number are combined or 
confounded by these mystical visionaries. 

These numerical dreams of ancient philosophers 
have been imitated by modern writers ; for instance, 
by Peter Bungo and Kircher, who have written De 
Mysteriis Numerorum. Bungo treats of the mysti- 
cal properties of each of the numbers in order, at 
great length. And such speculations have influenced 
astronomical theories. In the first edition of the 
Alphonsine tables^', the precession was represented 
by making the first point of Aries move, in a period 
of 7000 years, through a circle of* which the radius 
was 18 degrees, while the circle moved round the 
ecliptic in 49,000 years ; and these numbers, 7000 
and 49,000, were chosen probably by Jewish calr 
culators, or with reference to Judaical Sabbatarian 
notions. 

3. Astrology. — Of all the forms which mysticism 
assumed, none was cultivated more assiduously 
than astrology. Although this art prevailed most 
universally and powerfully during the stationary 
period, its existence, even as a detailed technical 
system, goes back to a very early period. It pro- 
bably had its origin in the East ; it is universally 
ascribed to the Babylonians and Chaldeans; the 
name Chaldean was, at Rome, synonymous with 
mathematictis^ or astrologer ; and we read repeatedly 
that this class of persons were expelled from Italy 

^^ Montucla, i. 511. 



294 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

by a decree of the senate, both during the times of 
the republic and of the empire^*. The recurrence 
of this act of legislation shows that it was not effec- 
tual ; " It is a class of men," says Tacitus, " which, 
in our city, will always be prohibited, and will alM'ays 
exist." In Greece, it does not appear that the state 
showed any hostility to the professors of this art. 
They undertook, it would seem, then, as at a later 
period, to determine the course of a man's character 
and life from the configuration of the stars at the 
moment of his birth. We do not possess any of 
the speculations of the earlier astrologers ; and we 
cannot therefore be certain that the feelings which 
operated in men's minds when the art had its birth, 
agreed with the views on which it was afterwards 
defended, when it became a matter of controversy. 
But it appears probable, that, though it was at later 
periods supported by physical analogies, it was ori- 
ginally suggested by mythological belief. The Greeks 
spoke of the influences or effliuves {airoppota^;) which 
proceeded from the stars ; but the Chaldeans had 
probably thought rather of the powers which they 
exercised as deities. In whatever manner the sun, 
moon, and planets came to be identified with gods 
and goddesses, it is clear that the characters ascribed 
to these gods and goddesses regulate the virtues 
and powers of the stars which bear their names. 
This association, so manifestly visionary, was retained, 

** Tacit. Ann. ii. 32. xii. 52. Hist. I. 22, II. 62. 



THEIR MYSTICISM. 295 

amplified, and pursued, in an enthusiastic spirit, 
instead of being rejected for « more distinct and 
substantial connexions ; and a pretended science 
was thus formed, which bears the obvious stamp 
mysticism. 

That common sense of mankind which teaches 
them that theoretical opinions are to be calmly tried 
by their consequences and their accordance with 
facts, appears to have counteracted the prevalence 
of astrology in the better times of the human mind. 
Eudoxus, as we are informed by Cicero^*, rejected the 
pretensions of the Chaldeans; and Cicero himself 
reasons against them with arguments as sensible and 
intelligent as could be adduced by a writer of the pre- 
sent day ; such as the different fortunes and charac- 
ters of persons born at the same time ; and the failure 
of their predictions, in the case of Pompey, Crassus, 
Caesar, to whom they had foretold glorious old age 
and peaceful death. He also employs an argument 
which the reader would perhaps not expect from 
him ; — the very great remoteness of the planets as 
compared with the distance of the moon. ** What 
contagion can reach us," he asks, " from a distance 
almost infinite ?" 

Pliny argues on the same side, and with some of 
the same arguments ^•. " Homer," he says, " tells 
us that Hector and Polydamas Were born the same 
night ; — ^men of such different fortune. And every 

" Cic. de Dir. ii. 42. '' Hist. Nat. vii. 49. 



296 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

hour, in every part of the world, are bom lords and 
slaves, kings and beggars." 

The impression made by these arguments is 
marked in an anecdote told concerning Publius 
Nigidius Figulus, a Roman of the time of Julius 
Caesar, whom Lucan mentions as a celebrated astro- 
loger. It is said, that when an opponent of the art 
urged as an objection the different fetes of persons 
bom in two successive instants, Nigidius bade him 
make two contiguous marks on a potter's wheel, 
which was revolving rapidly near them. On stop- 
ping the wheel, the two marks were found to be 
really far removed from each other ; and Nigidius is 
said to have received the name of Figulus (the 
potter), in remembrance of this story. His argu- 
ment, says St. Augustine, who gives us the narra- 
tive, was as fragile as the ware which the wheel 
manufactured. 

As the darkening times of the Roman empire 
advanced, even the stronger minds seem to have lost 
the clear energy which was requisite to throw off 
this delusion. Seneca appears to take the influence 
of the planets for granted ; and even Tacitus*^ seems 
to hesitate. " For my own part," says he, " I doubt ; 
but certainly the majority of mankind cannot be 
weaned from the opinion, that, at the birth of each 
man, his future destiny is fixed ; though some things 
may fall out differently from their predictions, by 

'"^ Ann. vi. 22. 



THEIR MYSTICISM. 297 

the ignorance of those who profess the art ; and that 
thus the art is unjustly blamed, confirmed as it is by 
noted examples in all ages." The occasion which 
gives rise to these reflections of the historian is the 
mention of Thrasyllus, the favourite astrologer of 
the Emperor Tiberius, whose skill is exemplified in 
the following narrative. Those who were brought 
to Tiberius on any important matter, were admitted 
to an interview in an apartment situated on a lofty 
cliff in the island of Caprese. They reached this place 
by a narrow path, accompanied by a single freedman 
of great bodily strength ; and on their return, if the 
emperor had conceived any doubts of their trust- 
worthiness, a single blow buried the secret and its 
victim in the ocean below. After Thrasyllus had, 
in this retreat, stated the results of his art as they 
concerned the emperor, Tiberius asked him whether 
he had calculated how long he himself had to live. 
The astrologer examined the aspect of the stars, and 
while he did this, as the narrative states, showed 
hesitation, alarm, increasing terror, and at last de- 
clared that, " the present hour was for him critical, 
perhaps fatal." Tiberius embraced him, and told 
him " he was right in supposing he had been in 
danger, but that he should escape it ;" and made 
him thenceforth his confidential counsellor. 

The belief in the power of astrological prediction 
which thus obtained dominion over the minds of 
men of literary cultivation and of practical energy, 
naturally had a more complete sway among the spe- 



298 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

culatlve but unstable minds of the later philosophi- 
cal schools of Alexandria, Athens, and Rome. We 
have a treatise on astrology by Proclus, which will 
serve to exemplify the mystical principle in this 
form. It appears as a commentary on a work on 
the same subject called " Tetrabiblos," ascribed to 
Ptolemy ; though we may reasonably doubt whether 
the author of the " Megale Syntaxis" was also the 
writer of the astrological work. A few notices of 
the commentary of Proclus will suffice '^ The 
science is defended by urging hotv powerful we 
know the physical effects of the heavenly bodies to 
be. " The sun regulates all things on earth ; — ^the 
birth of animals, the growth of fruits, the flowing 
of waters, the change of health, according to the 
seasons ; he produces heat, moisture, dryness, cold, 
according to his approach to our zenith. The moon, 
which is the nearest of all bodies to the earth, gives 
out much influence ; and all things, animate and in- 
animate, sympathize with her ; rivers increase and 
diminish according to her light ; the advance of the 
sea, and its recess, are regulated by her rising and 
setting ; and along with her, fruits and animals wax 
and wane, either wholly or in part." It is easy to 
see that by pursuing this train of associations (some 
real and some imaginary) very vaguely an^ very 
enthusiastically, the connexions which astrology 
supposes would receive a kind of countenance. 
Proclus then proceeds to state ^' the doctrines of the* 

" L 2- '' I. 4. 



t I' »f f '• • w 



Irr 



THEIR MYSTICISM. 299 

f 

science. " The sun," he says, " is productive of 
heat and dryness; this power is moderate in its 
nature, but is more sensible than that of the other 
luminaries, from his magnitude, and from the change 
of seasons. The nature of the moon is for the most 
part moist ; for being the nearest to the earth, she 
receives the vapours which rise from moist bodies, 
and thus she causes bodies to soften and rot. But 
by the illumination she receives from the sun, she 
partakes in a moderate degree of heat. Saturn is 
cold and dry, being most distant both from the heat- 
ing power of the sun, and the moist vapours of the 
eaitb. -His cold, however, is most prevalent, his 
dryness is more moderate. Both he and the rest 
receive addi'tional powers from the configurations 
which they make with respect to the sun and moon." 
In jij^e same manner it is remarked that Mars is dry 
mid caustic, from his fiery nature, which, indeed, his 
colour shows. Jupiter is well compounded of warm 
and moist, as is Venus. Mercury is variable in his 
character. From these notions were derived others 
concerning the beneficial or malefic effect of these 
stars. Heat and moisture are generative and crea- 
tive elements ; hence the ancients, says Proclus, 
deemed Jupiter, and Venus, and the moon, to have 
a good power ; Saturn and Mercury, on the other 
hand, had an evil nature. 

Other distinctions of the character of the stars 
are enumerated, equally visionary, and suggested by 
the most fanciful connexions. Some are masculine, 



300 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

and some feminine : the moon and Venus are of 
the latter kind ; this appears to be merely a mytho- 
logical or etymological association. Some are diurnal, 
some nocturnal; the moon and Venus are of the 
latter kind, the sun and Jupiter of the former; 
Saturn and Mars are both. 

The fixed stars, also, and especially those of the 
zodiac, had especial influences and subjects assigned 
to them. In particular, each sign was supposed to 
preside over a particular part of the body; thus 
Aries had the head assigned to it, Taurus the neck, 
and so on. 

The most important part of the sky in the astro- 
loger's consideration, was that sign of the zodiac 
which rose at the moment of the child^s birth ; this 
was, properly speaking, the horoscope, the ascendant^ 
or the first home ; the whole circuit of the heavens 
being divided into twelve houses, in which life and 
death, marriage and children, riches and honours, 
friends and enemies were distributed. 

We need not attempt to trace the progress of 
this science. It prevailed extensively among the 
Arabians, as we might expect from the character of 
that nation. Albumasar, of Balkh in Khorasan, 
who fl,ourished in the. ninth century, who was one of 
their greatest astronomers, was also a great astro- 
loger ; and his work on the latter subject, " De 
Magnis Coiyunctionibus, Annorum Bevolutionibus 
ac eorum Perfectionibus," was long celebrated in 
Europe. Aboazen Haly (the writer of a treatise 



THEIR MYSTICISM. 301 

De Judiciis Astronom.) who lived in Spain in the 
thirteenth century, was one of the classical authors 
on this subject. 

It will easily be supposed that when this apoteles- 
matic or Judicial astrology obtained firm possession of 
men's minds, it would be pursued into innumerable 
subtle distinctions and extravagant conceits; and 
the more so, as experience could offer little or no 
check to such exercises of fancy and subtlety. For 
the correction of rules of astrological divination by 
comparison with known events, though pretended to 
by many professors of the art, was far too vague and 
fallible a guidance to be of any real advantage. 
Even in what has been called natural astrology, the 
dependence of the weather on the heavenly bodies, 
it is easy to see what a vast accumulation of well- 
observed facts is requisite to establish any true rule; 
and it is well known how long, in spite of facts, 
false and groundless rules (as the dependence of the 
weather on the moon) may keep their hold on men's 
minds. When the facts are so loose and many-sided 
as human characters, passions, and happiness, it was 
hardly to be expected that even the most powerfiil 
minds should be able to find a footing suflBiciently 
firm, to enable them to resist the impression of a 
theory constructed of sweeping and bold assertions, 
and filled out into a complete system of details. 
Accordingly, the connexion of the stars with human 
persons and actions was, for a long period, undis- 
puted. The vague, obscure, and heterogenous cha- 



302 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

racter of such a connexion, and its unfitness for any 
reallj scientific reasoning, could, of course, never be 
got rid of: and the bewildering feeUng of earnest- 
ness and solemnity, with which the connexion of the 
heavens with man was contemplated, never died 
away. In other respects, however, the astrologers 
fell into a servile commentatorial spirit; and em* 
ployed themselves in annotating and illustrating the 
works of their predecessors to a considerable extent, 
before the revival of true science. 

It may be mentioned, that astrology has long been, 
and probably is, an art held in great esteem and 
admiration among other eastern nations besides the 
Mohammedans : for instance, the Jews, the Indians, 
the Siamese, and the Chinese. The prevalence of 
vague, visionary, and barren notions among these 
nations, cannot surprise us ; for we have no evidence 
from them, as from Europeans w6 have, that they 
are capable, on subjects of physical speculation, of 
originating sound and rational general principles. 
The arts may have had their birth in all parts of the 
globe ; but it is only Europe, at particular favoured 
periods of its history, which has ever produced 
sciences. 

We are, however, now speaking of a long period, 
during which this productive energy was interrupted 
and suspended. During this period Europe de- 
scended, in intellectual character, to the level at 
which the other parts of the world have always stood. 
Her science wfis then a mixture of art and mysticism ; 



THEIR MYSTICISM. 803 

we have considered several forms of this mysticism, 
but there are two others which must not pass 
unnoticed, alchemy and magic. 

We may observe, before we proceed, that the 
deep and settled influence which astrology had ob- 
tained among men, appears perhaps most strongly 
in the circumstance, that the most vigorous and 
clear-sighted minds which were concerned in the 
revival of science, did not, for a long period* shake 
off the persuasion, that there was, in this art, some 
element of truth. Roger Bacon, Cardan, Kepler, 
Brahe, Francis Bacon, are examples of this. These, 
or most of them, rejected all the more obvious and 
extravagant fallacies with which the subject had 
been loaded ; but still conceived that some real and 
valuable truth remained when all these were re- 
moved. Thus Campanella", whom we shall have to 
speak of as one of the first opponents of Aristotle, 
wrote an " Astrology purified from all the Supersti- 
tions of the Jews and Arabians, and treated physio- 
logically." 

4. Alchemy. — Like other kinds of mysticism, 
alchemy seems to have grown out of the notions of 
moral, personal, and mythological qualities, which 
men associated with terms, of which the primary 
application was to physical properties. This is the 
form in which the subject is presented to us in the 
earliest writings which we possess on the subject of 

■^ Bacon, De Aug. ill. 4. 



304 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN TH& MIDDLE AGES. 

chemistry ; — thos^ of G^er" of S^^yiUe, wixp-i^ -SHp- 
posed to have lived in the eighth, or .pi^th, qcfatjiry. 
The very titles of Giber's wprks shaw the iiQ^^cffia 
on which his pretended SQience prweetdpi . T3iey -arex 
«0f the. Search of Perfpctigji ;" "Of .tllft.^^i^f 
Perfection, pr of the Perfect Magistery ; ' ," Of .^^ 
Invention of Verity, or Perfp^tion,". The basis, <rf 
this phraseology is the distinction of me^Qjis>in^Q more, 
or less perfect ; gold being the mo«t p^rfqct, aa;be{Qg 
the most, valuable, most beautiful, most purei.i!!)j5st 
durable ; silver the next ; and so on. The " S^soreh 
of Perfeption," was, therefore^ tlie at|;eq[ipt;to.cpn^i^^ 
other metals into gold; and doctrines, were a^Qpted 
\f hich repifesented the metids as aU coinpoupded of. 
the ^am^ elementSi so that this w^ts theoretiiCaHy 
po^iWe.. But the myst^ic^ trwjs of. asscfciation w€a«- 
pursued, loiuch j&iri^er. than this ; gpld a^d silveiJ were 
hpld to be the most n^Aie of metals ^ gold was th^ 
king, and silver their /quieen. My thcJogical . associa- 
tipns w^e wUbii^ siid pf Ibeiie'feiideB^ a« had. been 
dpne in. astrology.. Gqld.MlasBpl, the sun; tilvenwas. 
Luna, the m(>on ; jeoppeor, iron^ tint,, load, were assigned 
to Venusi M^rs^Juipiter^i Satujrn. The processes of 
mixture and heat were spoken of a$ personal aetions 
and relations, struggles and victpriqs. iSome ele*- 
ments were conquerors, som^e . conquered ; there. «x<^ 
isted preparations which possessed the power of 
changing the whole of a body into a substance of 

•^ Thoflnaons Hist, of Chem. i. II7. 



THEIR MYSTICISM. 805 

another kind : these were called magisterie$*\ When 
gold and quicksilver are combined, the king and the 
queen are married, to produce children of their own 
kind. It will easily be conceived, that when chemi« 
cal operations were described in phraseology of this 
sort, the enthusiasm of the fancy would be added to 
that of the hopes, and observation would not be per- 
mitted to correct the delusion, or to suggest sounder 
and more rational views. 

The exaggeration of the vague notion of perfec 
tion and power in the object of the alchemist's 
search, was carried further still. The same prepa- 
ration which possessed the faculty of turning baser 
jnetals into gold, was imagined to be also a universal 
medicine, to have the gift, of curing or preventing 
diseases, prolonging life, producing bodily strength 
and beauty: the philosopAers^ stone was finally in- 
vested with every desirable efficacy which the fimcy 
of the " philosophers" could devise. 

It has been usual to say that alchemy was the 
mother of chemistry; and that men would never 
have made the experiments on which the real sci- 
ence is founded, if they had not been animated by 
the hopes and the energy which the delusive art 
inspired. To judge whether this is truly said, we 
must be able to estimate the degree of interest 
which men feel in purely speculative truth, and in 
the real and substantial improvement of art to 

** Boyle. Thomson's Hist. Ch. i. 25. Carolus Musitanus. 
VOL. I. X 



806 PHYSICAL SOIENCB IN THE KIDDLE AGES. 

which it leads. Since the fell of alchemy, and thc^ 
progress of real chemistry, these motiyes have be^i 
powerfid enough to engage in the study of the science» 
a body fitr larger than the alchemists ever were^ and 
no less zealous. There is no apparent reason why tiie 
result should not have been the same, if the progress 
of true science had begun sooner. Astronomy was 
long cultivated without the bribe of astrology. But, 
perhaps, we may justly say this ;~*>that, in the station* 
aiy period, men's minds were so far enfeebled and 
degraded, that pure speculative truth had not its ftill 
effect upon them ; and the mystical pursuits in which 
some dim and disfigured images of truth were sought 
with avidity, were among the provisions by which the 
human soul, even when sunk below its best con- 
dition, is perpetually directed to something above the 
mere objects of sense and appetite ^^-^-Or contrivance 
of compensation, as it were, in the intellectual and 
spiritual constitution of man. 

5. illf<z^f(;.«— Magical arts, so &r as they were be- 
lieved in by those who professed to practise them, 
and so &r as they have a bearing in science, stand 
on the same footing as astrology; and, indeed, a 
close alliance has generally been maintained between 
the two pursuits. Incapacity and indisposition to 
perceive natural and philosophical causation, an en- 
thusiastic imagination, and such a faith as can devise 
and maintain supernatural and i^lritual connexion)^ 
are the elements of this, as of other forms of mysti- 
cism. And thus that temper which led men to aim 



THBim MYSTICISM. 80? 

at the magician's supposed authority over the ele- 
ments, is an additional exemplification of those habits 
of thought which prevented the progress of real 
science, and the acquisition of that command over 
nature which is founded on science, during the iU'^ 
terval now before us. 

But there is another aspect under which the 
opinions connected with this pursuit may serve to 
illustrate the mental character of the stationary 
period* 

The tendency, during the middle ages, to attribute 
the character of magician to almost all persons emi* 
nent for great speculative or practical knowledge, is 
a feature of those times, which shows how extensive 
and complete was the inability to apprehend the 
nature of real science. In cultivated and enligh« 
tei^ed periods, such bb those of ancient Greece, or 
modem Europe, knowledge is wished for and ad* 
mired, even by those who least possess it: but in 
dark and degraded periods, superior knowledge is 
a butt for hatred and fear. In the one case, men's 
eyes are open; their thoughts are clear; and,how- 
eveif high the philosopher may be raised above the 
multitude, they can catch glimpses of the interven- 
ing path, and see that it is open to all, and that 
elevation is the reward of energy and labour. In 
the other case, the crowd are not only ignorant, but 
spiritless ; they have lost the pleasure in knowledge, 
the appetite for it, and the feeling of dignity which 
it gives : there is no sympathy which connects them 

X2 



308 PHYSICAL SC3ENCS IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

with the learned man: they see him above them^ 
but know not how he is raised or supported : he 
beoomes an olject of aversion and envy, of vague 
susjHcion and terror ; and these emotions are emr- 
bodied and confirmed by association with the &ncies 
and dogmas of superstition. To consider sup^or 
knowledge as magic, and magic bb a detestable and 
criminal employment, was the form which these 
feelings of dislike assumed ; and at one period in 
the history of Europe, almost every one who had 
gained any eminent literary &me, was spoken of as 
a magician. Naudseus, a learned Frenchman, in the 
seventeenth century, wrote " An Apology for all the 
Wise Men who have been unjustly reported Ma- 
gicians, from the Creation to the present Age." 
The list of persons whom he thus thinks it necessary 
to protect, are of various classes and ages. Alkindi, 
Geber, Artephius, Thebit, Baymund Lully, Arnold 
de Villa Nova, Peter of Apono, and Paracelsus, had 
incurred the black suspicion as physicians or alche- 
mists* Thomas Aquinas, Roger Bacon, Michael 
Scot, Picus of Mirandula, and Trithemius, had nat 
escaped it, though ministers of religion. Ev^i dig- 
nitaries, such as Robert Grosteste, bishop of Lincohi, 
Albertus Magnus, bishop of Ratisbon, Popes Syl- 
vester the Second, and Gregory the Seventh, had 
been involved in the wide calumny. In the same 
way in which the vulgar confounded the eminent 
learning and knowledge which had appeared in recent 
times, with skill in dark and supernatural arts, they 



THfilR MYSTICISM. 809 

converted into wizards all the best-known names in 
the rolls of fame; as Aristotle, Solomon, Joseph, 
Pythagoras ; and, finally, the poet Virgil was a power- 
fill and skilful necromancer, and this fancy was ex- 
emplified by many strange stories of his achievements 
and practices. 

The various results of the tendency of the human 
mind to mysticism, which we have here noticed, form 
promliient features in the intellectual character of 
the world, for a long course of centuries. The 
theosophy and theurgy of the Neoplatonists, the 
mystical arithmetic of the Pythagoreans and their 
successors, the predictions pf the astrologers, the 
pretences of alchemy and magic, represent, not un- 
fairly, the general character and disposition of men's 
thoughts, with reference to philosophy and science. 
That there were stronger minds, which threw off in 
a greater or less degree this train of delusive and 
unsubstantial ideas, is true ; as, on the other hand, 
mysticism, among the vulgar or the foolish, often 
went to an extent of extravagance and superstition, 
of which I have not attempted to convey any con- 
ception. The lesson which the preceding survey 
teaches us is, that during the stationary period, 
mysticism, in its various forms, was a leading cha- 
racter, both of the common mind, and of the specu- 
lations of the most intelligent and profound reasoners; 
and that this mysticism was the opposite of that 
habit of thought which we have stated science to 
require; namely, clear ideas, distinctly employed to 



SIQ PHYSICAL SCIENCB IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

conneot weU-«scertained facts ; inadmuch asrthe ideas 
in which it dealt were vague and unstable, and the 
temper in which they were contemplated was an 
urgent and aspiring enthu8ia«n» which could not 
submit to a calm conference with experience upon 
even terms. The fervour of thought in some degree 
supplied the place of reason in producing belief; 
but opinions so obtained had no enduring value; 
they did not exhibit a permanent record of old truths^ 
nor a firm foundation for new. Experience collected 
her stores in vain, or ceased to collect them, when 
she had only to pour them into the flimsy folds of 
the lap of mysticism ; who was, in truth, so much 
absorbed in looking for the l3*easures which were to 
&11 from the skies, that she heeded little how scan<- 
tily she obtained, or how loosely she held, such riches 
as might be found near her. 



311 



CHAPTER IV. 

Of the Dogmatssim of the Stationary Period. 

In speaking of the character of the age of commen* 
tator^, we noticed principally the ingenious servility 
which it displays ;**^the acuteness with which it finda 
ground for speculation in the expression of other 
men's thoughts ;-^the want of all vigour and fertility 
in acquiring any real and new truths* Such wa3 
the character of the reasoners of the stationary 
period from the first; hut, at a later day^ this 
character, from various causes, was modified hy new 
features. The servility which had yielded itself to 
the yoke, insisted upon forcing it on the necks of 
others; the subtlety which foimd all the truth it 
needed in certain accredited writings, resolved that 
no one should find there, or in any other region, any 
other truths ; speculative men became tyrants with- 
out ceasing to be slaves ; to their character of com- 
mentators they added that of dogmatists. 

1. Origin of the Scholastic Philosophj/. — ^The causes 
of this change have. been very happily analysed and 
described by several modern writers \ The general 
nature of the process may be briefly stated to have 
been the following. 

* Dr. Hampden, in the Life of Thomas Aquinas, in the Encyc. 
Metrop. Degerando, Hist. Compar^e, vol. iv. Also Tennemann, 
Hist, of Phil. vol. viii. Introduction. 



312 WmSIVAL 80IENQB IH THE MIDDLE AQtEM. 

The tendeEcies of the later times of the Boman 
raapire to a ocMiimeiitiiig literatofe, and a seoond* 
hand phQosophy, have ahready been noticed. The 
loss of the dignity of political fireedom, tiie want of the 
chearfulness of advancing proq)eiity^ and tibie substi- 
tution of the unphilosophical Latin language fw the 
delicate intellectual mediianism of the Greek ; fixed 
and augmented the preTalent feebleness and barren* 
ness of intellect. Men forgot, or feared, to consult 
tiature^ to seek for hew truths, to do what the great 
discoiFerers of other times had done; they weid 
content to consult libraries, to study and defend 
old (^pinions, to talk of what great geniuses had said. 
They sought their philos<^hy in accredited treatise^ 
iuid dared not question such doctrines as they there 
found. 

The character of the philosophy to which they 
were thus led, was determined by this want of 
courage and originality. There are Tarious anta- 
gonist principles of opinion, which seem alike tb 
baye their root in tiie intellectual constitution of 
man, and whidi are maintained and developed by 
opposing sects^ when the intellect is in vigorous 
action. Such principles are, for instance^— -*th6 
claims of authority and of reason to our assent ;-^ 
the source of our knowledge in experience or in 
ideas ; — ^the superiority of a mystical or of a sceptical 
turn of thought. Such oppositions of doctrine were 
found in writers of the greatest fame ; and two of 
those, who most occupied the attention of students. 



DOGMATISM OF TBE aTATTONABY PESEtlOD* SIS 



Plato and Aristotle, vmre, on several points of this 
nature^ very diverse from each other in their ten- 
dency. The attempt to reconcile these philosophers 
by BoSthins and others, we have already noticed ; 
and the attempt was so far successful, that it 1^ on 
men's minds the belief in the possibility of a great 
philosophical system which should be based on these 
writers, and have a claim to the assent of all sobw 
speculators. 

But, in the mean time, the Christian religion had 
become the leading subject of men's thoughts; and 
divines had put forward its claims to be, not merely 
the guide of men's lives, and the means of reconciling 
them to their heavenly Master; but also to be a 
philosophy in the widest sense in which the term had 
been used ; — a consistent speculative view of man's 
condition and nature, and of the world in whidh he 
is placed. 

These daims had been acknowledged; and, un- 
fortunately, from the intellectual condition of the 
times,^th no due apprehenrion (rf the necessaiy 
ministry of observation, and rewon dealing with 
observation, by which alone such a system can be em- 
bodied. It was held, without any regulating principle, 
that the philosophy which had been bequeathed to the 
world by the great geniuses of heathen antiquity, and 
the philosophy which was deduced fit)m, and implied 
by, the revelations made by God to man, must be 
identical ; and therefore, that theology is the only true 
philosophy. Indeed, the Neoplatonists had already 



814 PHYSICAL SCISNCB IN THE MIDDLE AGES, 

arriyed, by other roads, at the same conviction. John 
Scot £rigena» in the reign of Alfred, and consequently 
before the existence of the scholastic philosophy, 
properly so called, had reasserted this doctrine*. 
Anselm, in the deyenth century, a^n brought it 
forward'; and Bernard de Chartres, in the thirteenth\ 

This view was confirmed by the opinion which 
prevailed, concerning the nature of philosophical 
truth ; a view supported by the theory of Plato, the 
practice of Aristotle, and the general propensities of 
the human mind: I mean, the opinion that all 
science may be obtained by the use of reasoning 
alone ;«~that by analysing and combining the notions 
which common language brings before us, we may 
learn all that we can know. Thus logic came to 
include the whole of science ; and accordingly this 
Abdard expressly maintained'. I have already ex* 
plained, in some measure, the fallacy of this belief, 
which ooninsts, as has been well said% ^ in mistaking 
the universality of the theory of language for the 
generalisation of ftcts*" But on all accounts this 
opinion is readily accepted ; and it led at once to the 
conclusion, that the theological philosophy which we 
have described, is complete as well as tru& 

Thus a universal science was established, with the 
authority of a religious creed. Its universality rested 
on erroneous views of the relation of words and 
truths ; its pretensions as a science were, admitted 

*Deg.iY.351. »Ib.iY.388. * lb. iv. 418. 

* lb. iv. 407. • Enc. Met. 807. 



DOGMATISM OF THE STATIONARY PERIODt 815 

by the servile temper of men's intellects ; and its 
religious authority was assigned it, by making all 
truth part of religion. And as religion claimed 
assent within her own jurisdiction under the most 
solemn and imperative sanctions, philosophy shared 
in her imperial power, and dissent from their doctrines 
was no longer blameless or allowable. Error became 
wicked, dissent became heresy; to reject the re* 
ceived human doctrines, was nearly the same as to 
doubt the Divine declarations. The Scholastic PhU 
lasophy claimed the assent of all believers* 

The external form, the details, and the text o( 
this philosophy, were taken, in a great measure, 
from Aristotle; though, in the spirit, the general 
notions, and the style of interpretation, Plato and the 
Platonists had no inconsiderable share. Various 
causes contributed to the elevation of Aristotle to 
this distinction. His logic had early been adopted 
as an instrument of theological disputation ; and his 
spirit of systematieation, of subtle distinction, and 
of analysis of words, as well as the disposition to 
argumentation, afforded the most natural and gratefid 
employment to the commentating propensities; 
Those principles which we formerly noted as the 
leading points of his physical philosophy, were s^ 
lected and adopted; and these, presented in a moat 
technical form, and applied in a systematic manner, 
constitute a large portion of the philosophy of which 
we now speak, so far as it pretends to deal with 
physics. 



016 PHYSICAL mmm m the mm^E miss. 

2. SchclasHe I)ogm(zs.^^But before the oomplete 
ascendency of Aristotle was thus established, 
when sometWng of an intellectual waking took 
place after the darkness and sleep of the nintl^ 
and tenth centuries, the Platonic doctrines seem 
to have had, at first, a strong attraefcion for 
men's minds, as better falling in with the n^ystical 
speculations and contemplative piety which belong 
to the times. John Scot Erigena^ may be looked 
upon as the reviver of the New Platonism in the 
tenth century. Towards the end of the deventh, 
Peter Damien% in Italy, reproduced, involved in a 
theological discussion, some Neoplatonic ideas. Ooder- 
froy* also, censor of St. Victor, has left a treatise, 
entitled Microcosmus ; this is founded on a mystical 
analogy, often afterwards again brought forward, 
between man and the universe. ** Philosophers and 
theologians,*' says the writer, *^ agree in considering 
man as a little world ; and as the world is composed 
k>f four elements, man is endowed with four foculties, 
the senses, the imagination, reason, and understand- 
ing.*' Bernard of Chartres*^ in his Megascosmus 
iand Microcosnms, took up the same notions; Hugo, 
abbot of St. Victor, made a contemplative life the 
•main point and crown of his philosophy; and is said 
to have been the first of the scholastic writers who 
made psycholo^ his special study**. He says the 
Acuities of the mind are " the senses, the imaginar 

'Deg. iv. 35. »Ib. iv. 367. » lb. iy. 413 

'' lb. iv. 419. '' lb. iy. 415. 



DOGKATISM OP THE STATIONARY PERIOD* 317 

tion» the reason, the memory, the undearstanding, 
and the intelligence." 

Physics does not originally and properly form any 
prominent part of the scholastic philosophy, which 
consists mainly of a series of questions and determi- 
nations upon the various points of a certain technical 
divinity^ Of this kind is the "Book of Sentences" 
of Peter the Lombard (bishop of Paris), who is, on 
that account, usually called "Magister Senten« 
tiarum ;" a work which was published in the twelfth 
century, and was long the text and standard of such 
discussions. The questions are decided by the 
authority of Scripture and of the Fathers of the 
Church ; and are divided into four Books, of which 
the first contains questions concealing God and the 
doctrine of the Trinity in particular ; the second is 
concerning the creation ; the third, concerning Christ 
and the Christian religion ; and. the fourth treats of 
religious and moral duties. In the second Book, s^ 
in. many of the writers of this time^ the nature of 
angels is considered in detail, and the order? of^their 
hierarchy, of which there weue held, to be nine. 
The: physical discussions enter only a^ bearing uppn 
the revealed history of the creation^ and cannot be 
taken as a specimen of the work ; but I may observe, 
that in speaking of the division of the waters above 
the firmament from the waters under the firmament, 
he gives one opinion, that of Bede, that the former 
waters are the solid crystalline heavens in which the 
stars are fixed ^*, "for crystal, which is so hard and 

^' Lib. ii. Distinct, sir. 



318 PHYSICAL 8CIEN0E IN THE HIDraJS A018. 

transpai^nt, is made of water.'' But he mentions also 
the opinion of St. Augustine, and adds that the waters 
above the heavens are there in a state of vapour 
(vaporaliter) and in minute drops ; ^' if» then^ water 
can, as we see in clouds, be so minutelj divided tiiat 
it may be thus supported as vapour on air, which is 
naturally lighter than water ; why may we not be- 
lieve that it floats above that lighter celestial element 
in still minuter drops and still lighter vapours ? But 
in whatever manner the waters are there, we do not 
doubt that they are there." 

The celebrated •* Summa Theologise" of Thomafir 
Aquinas is a woric of the same kind ; and anything 
which has a physical bearing forms an equally small 
part of it. Thus, of the 512 Questions of the 
gumma, there is only one (Part I., Quest- 116) "on 
corporeal action," or on any part of the material 
world; though there are several concerning the 
celestial hierarchies, as " on the act of angels," ** on 
the speaking of angels," " on the subordination of 
angels," " on guardian angels," and the like. This, of 
course, would not be remarkable in a treatise on 
theology, except this theology were intended to 
constitute the whole of philosophy. 

We may observe, that in this work, though Plato, 
Avecibron, and many other heathen as well as Ohris- 
tian phflosophers, are adduced as authority, Aristotle 
is referred to in a peculiar manner as " the philoso- 
pher." This is noticed by John of Salisbuiy, ai^ 
attracting attention in his time; (he died a. P. 



DOGMATISM OF THE GPTATIONARY PIBRIOD; 319 

1 182.) *' The various masters of Dialectic,'* says he *% 
'* shine, each Mith his peculiar mei}t; but all are 
proud to worship the footsteps of Aristotle; so 
much so, indeed, that the name of phthMpker^ which 
belongs to them all, has been pre-eminently appro« 
priated to him. He is called the philosopher aut(h 
nomatice^ that is, by excellence." 

The Question oonceming Corporeal Action, in 
Aquinas, is divided into six Articles ; and the oonclu* 
sion delivered upon the first, is ^\ that *^ Body being 
compounded of power and act, is active as well as pas^ 
sive.'' Against this it is urged, that quantity is an 
attribute of body, and that quantity prevents action ; 
that this appears in fact, since a larger body is more 
difficult to move. The author replies, that " quan«< 
tity does not prevent corporeal form from action 
altogether, but prevents it from being a universal 
agent inasmuch as the form is individualized, which, 
in matter subject to quantity, it is. Moreover, the 
illustration deduced from the ponderousness of bodies 
is not to the purpose ; first, because the addition of 
quantity is hot the cause of gravity, as is proved in the 
fourth book, De Ccelo and De Mundo" (we see that 
he quotes familiarly the physical treatises of Aris-» 
totle); ^^ second, because it is false that ponderous- 
ness makes motion slower; on the contrary, in 
proportion as anything is heavier, the more does it 
move with its proper motion ; thirdly, because action 



18 



Metalogicus, lib. ii. cap. 16. ^* Summee, P. i. Q. 115. Art. 1. 



320 PHY0ICAX. .905)109 IN. fTH^ .mpmjir A8K8. 

does not take place by loe^ .mot]iOii>(M..D0iiioeritu0 
aaserted ; but by tbj% th^ i^m^buig !» diMvuftiam 
power into act." . , ? ; :' ./p.; 

It does not belong to 0X^ piirpoig^ to ;a>n0id^ 
dither the theologieal -or. tbei m^jiixymeel dMf rines 
wludx form so large a portim of tb^ tceCtlBes/«{<lhe 
schoolmen. Pedxaps it 9iay : b^ioiift^r . sappefby tlu^t 
some light is thrown on, ^omp.tofihe/qp^ptiom nMsk 
have occupied metaphysiQiaASe io nil ages^ .by \thftt 
examination of the bistoiiy of the j^xogtoBm^.^mifxe^ 
in which we are now eugage4; but.tUl W€|. aco'^ble 
to analyse the leading controversies pf this jkpu^ it 
would be of. little serviice to speak of jthem ip 4etaU. 
It may be noticed5 bowe veri that nia^y q£, t}x» mj[>st 
prominent of them rpfej: to . tlti^ groat que^n,-^ 
<* What is the . relati w between aetu^ ^if^g^ '^^ 
general te;rnp^s?'' Perhaps in. mpdejr^ tUuc^ tbe 
actual things would ,be more epnimonly taken a^.tbe 
point to start from ; mi men wou)ld; beg^ by eon-* 
sidering how classes apid univ W9^ ape pbtained fron; 
individuals. Bu,t the sc^OQtlm^« fpundii^g tl^^ic 
speculations on the recedved mpdefii of ppni^denng 
such subjects, to which both iVristotle and Platp had 
contributed, travelled in the pppoi^ite dire^tion^ and 
endeavoured to discover how individuals were de-; 
duced from genera and species; — ^what was ^Uhe 
principle of individuation." This was variously 
stated by different reasoners. Thus Bonaventura** 



15 



Deg. ir. 673. 



150»»rA*tl8ll'^F TH* BTAtlONARY PERIOD. 321 

mhre» %h6 diifiettlty fe^rthe aid tf the AristotcHan 
distHbotkm of -mattei^ and form. The individual 
derives from the form the property of being some-^ 
Mng^'tBOid fttnn th^ matter the property of being 
that pofttihuhr Jhinq. ' Duiis Seotus'*, the great ad- 
ve^stery of Thomai^ Aqninas in theology, placed the 
{Mriliciple of individuation in ^^ a certain positive de- 
tenhiniiig entity,'- which his school called Hacceityt 
or thkne^s. *' Tliitti' Peter is an individual, because 
his kMumity is combined with Petreity.*" The force 
of abstract terms is a curious question, and some 
remarkable experiments in their use had been made 
by the Latin Aristotelians before this time. In the 
same way in which we talk of the quaniiit/ and qiuditg 
of a thing, they spoke of its quiddity^\ 

We may consider the teign of mere disputation 
as fully established at the time of which we are now 
speaking; and the only kind of philosophy hence- 
forth studied was one in which no sound physical 
science had or could have a place. The wavering 
abstractions, indistinct generalisations, and loose 
classifications of common language, which we have 
already noted as the fountain of the physics of the 
Greek schools of philosophy, were also the only 
source from which the schoolmen of the middle ages 
drew their views, or rather their arguments: and 
though these notional and verbal relations were in- 
vested with a most complex and pedantic techni- 

»« Deg. iy. 523. /^ lb. iv. 404. 

VOL. I. Y 



322 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

cality, they did not, on that account, become at all 
more precise as notions, or most likely to lead to a 
single real truth. Instead of acquiring distinct ideas, 
they multiplied abstract terms ; instead of real gene^ 
ralisations, they had recourse to verbal distinctions. 
The whole course of their employments tended to 
make them, not only ignorant of physical truth, but 
incapable of conceiving its nature. 

Having thus taken upon themselves the task of 
raising and discussing questions by means of abstract 
terms, verbal distinctions, and logical rules alone, 
there was no tendency in their activity to come to 
an end, as there was no progress. The same ques- 
tions, the same answers, the same difficulties, the 
same solutions, the same verbal subtleties, — sought 
for, admired, cavilled at, abandoned, reproduced, and 
again admired, — ^might recur without limit. John of 
Salisbury** observes of the Parisian teachers, that, 
after several years' absence he found them not a 
step advanced, and still employed in urging and 
parrying the same arguments ; and this, as Mr. Hal- 

• 

^' He stadied logic at Paris, at St. Geneyiere, and then left 
them. ^^ Duodecennium mihi elapsitm est dirersis studiis oc*- 
cupatum. Jucundmn itaque yisum est yeteres qnos TeUqueram, 
et quos adhuc Dialectica detinebat in monte, (Sanctse GenoTe£e) 
revisere socios, conferre cum eis super ambiguitatibus pristinis ; 
ut nostrum invicem collatione mutua commetiremur profectum. 
Inventi sunt, qui fuerant et ubi; neque enim ad palmam risi 
sunt processisse ad qussstiones pristinas diiimendas, neque pro- 
positiunculam unam adjeceiant. Quibus uigebant stimulis 
eisdem et ipsi urgebantur." &c. Metalogicus^ Kb. li. cap. 10. 



DOGMATISM OF THE STATIONARY PERIOD* 823 

lam remarks '% ^^ was equally applicable to the period 
of centuries." The same knots were tied and un- 
tied ; the same clouds were formed and dissipated. 
The poet's censure of " the Sons of Aristotle," is as 
just as happily expressed : — 

They stand 
Locked up together hand in hand ; 
Eyery one leads as he is led, 
The same bare path they tread, 
And dance like Fairies a fantastic round, 
But neither change their motion nor their ground. 

It will, therefore, be unnecessary to go into any 
detail respecting the history of the school philosophy 
pf the thirteenth, fourteenth, and fifteenth centuries. 
We may suppose it to have been, during the interme- 
diate time, such as it was at first and at last. An 
occasion to consider its later days will be brought 
before us by the course of our subject. But, even 
during the most entire ascendency of the scholastic 
doctrines, the elements of change were at work. 
While the doctors and the philosophers received all 
the ostensible homage of men, a doctrine and a phi- 
losophy of another kind were gradually forming : the 
practical instincts of man, their impatience of tyranny, 
the progress of the useful arts, the promises of alchemy, 
were all disposing men to reject the authority and 
deny the pretensions of the received philosophical 
creed. Two antagonist forms of opinion were in 
existence, which for some time went on detached, 

»• Middle Ages, iii. 537- 

y 2 



324 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES^ 

and almost independent of each other ; but, finally, 
these came into conflict, at the time of Galileo; and 
the war speedily extended to every part of civilized 
£urope. 

3. Scholastic Physics. — ^It is difficult to give briefly 
any appropriate examples of the nature of the Aris- 
totelian physics which are to be found in the works 
of this time. As the gravity of bodies was one of 
the first subjects of dispute when the struggle of the 
rival methods began, we may notice the mode in 
which it was treated ". " Zabarella maintains that 
the proximate cause of the motioxi of elements is 
atxeform, in the Aristotelian sense of the term : but 
to this sentence we," says Keckerman, "cannot 
agree; for in all other things the form is the proxi- 
mate cause, not of the ad, but of the power or faculty 
from which the act flows. Thus in man, the rational 
soul is not the cause of the act of laughing, but of 
the risible faculty or power." Keckerman*s system 
was at one time a work of considerable authority : 
it was published in 1614. By comparing and 
systematising what he finds in Aristotle, he is led 
to state his results in the form of definitions . and 
theorems. Thus, " gravity is a motive quality, arising 
from cold, density, and bulk, by which the elements 
are carried downwards." " Water is the lower in- 
termediate element, cold and moist." The first 
theorem concerning water is, " The moistness of 

»* Keckerman, p. 1428. 



DOGMATISM OP THE STATIONARY PERIOD. 325 

water is controlled by its coldness, so that it is less 
than the moistness of the air ; though, according to 
the sense of the vulgar, water appears to moisten 
more than air." It is obvious that the two proper- 
ties of fluids, to have their parts easily moved, and 
to wet other bodies, are here confounded. I may, 
as a concluding specimen of this kind, mention those 
propositions or maxims concerning fluids, which were 
so firmly established, that, when Boyle propounded 
the true mechanical principles of fluid action, he 
was obliged to state his opinions as " hydrostatical 
'paradowesr Theise were, — ^that fluids do not gravi- 
tate in proprio loco ; that is, that water has no gravity 
in or on water, since it is in its own place ; that air 
has no gravity on water, since it is above water, 
which is its proper place ; that earth in water tends 
to descend, since its place is below water ; — ^that the 
water rises in a pump or siphon, because nature 
abhors a vacuum ; — ^that some bodies have a positive 
levity in others, as oil in water ; and the like. 

4. Authority of Aristotle among the Schoolmen. — > 
The authority of Aristotle, and the practice of mak- 
ing him the text and basis of the system, especially 
as it regarded physics, prevailed during the period 
of which we speak. This authority was not, how- 
ever, without its fluctuations. Launoy has traced 
one part of its history, in a book " On the various 
Fortune of Aristotle in the University of Paris." 
The most material turns of this fortune depend on 
the bearing which the works of Aristotle were sup- 



326 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

posed to have upon theology. Several of Aristotle's 
works, and more especially his metaphysical writings, 
had heen translated into Latin, and were explained in 
the schools of the University of Paris, as early as the 
beginning of the thirteenth century**. At a council 
held at Paris in 1209, they were prohibited, as having 
given occasion to the heresy of Almeric (or Amauri), 
and because "they might give occasion to other 
heresies not yet invented." The Logic of Aristotle 
recovered its credit some years after this, and was 
publicly taught in the University of Paris, in the 
year 1215 ; but the Natural Philosophy and Meta- 
physics were prohibited by a decree of Gregory the 
Ninth, in 1231. The emperor, Frederic the Second, 
employed a number of learned men to translate into 
Latin, from the Greek and Arabic, certain books of 
Aristotle, and of other ancient sages ; and we have 
a letter of Peter de Vineis, in which they are recom- 
mended to the attention of the University of Bo- 
logna: probably the same recommendation was 
addressed to other Universities. Both Albertus 
Magnus and Thomas Aquinas wrote commentaries 
on Aristotlelb works ; and as this was done soon 
after the decree of Gregory the Ninth, Launoy is 
much perplexed to reconcile the fact with the ortho- 
doxy of the two doctors- Campanella, who was one 
of the first to cast off the authority of Aristotle, 
says, " We are by no means to think that St. Thomas 

** Mosheinii iii. 167- 



DOGMATISM OF THE STATIONARY PERIOD. 327 

aristotdized ; he only expounded Aristotle, that he 
might correct his errors ; and I should conceive he 
did this with the license of the Pope." This state- 
ment, however, by no means gives a just view of 
the nature of Albertus's and Aquinas's commentaries. 
Both have followed their author with profound de- 
ference ". For instance, Aquinas " attempts to defend 
Aristotle's assertion, that if there were no resistance, 
a body would move through a space in no time ; and 
the same defence is given by Scotus. 

We may imagine the extent of authority and 
admiration which Aristotle would attain, when thus 
countenanced, both by the powerful and the learned. 
In universities, no degree could be taken without a 
knowledge of the philosopher. In 1452, Cardinal 
Totaril established this rule in the University of 
Paris". When Ramus, in 1543, published an attack 
upon Aristotle, it was repelled by the power of the 
court, and the severity of the law. Francis the 
First published an edict, in which he states that he 
had appointed certain judges, who had been of 
opinion", " que le dit Ramus avoit ete temeraire 
an'ogant et impudent ; et que parcequ'en son livre des 
animadversions il reprenait Aristotle, estait evidem- 
ment connue et manifesto son ignorance.'^ The 
books are then declared to be suppressed. It was 
often a complaint of pious men, that theology was 
corrupted by the influence of Aristotle and his com- 



8S 



Dcg. N. 475. " F. Piccolomini, ii. 835. 

»* Launoy, p. 108, 128. " Launoy, p. 132. 



328 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE HIDPLE AGES. 

mentator&k Petrarch says*% that one of. the Italian 
learned men conversing ^'it)i him» ^iter e^^pressing 
much contempt for the apostles and jhtbers, ex- 
claimed, ^^Utinam tu Averroen pati .posses» ut 
videres quanto ille tuis his nugatoribns major ^t!"" 

When the revival of letters began to take pfeyee, 
and a number of men of ardent and elegant minds, 
susceptible to the impressions of beauty of style and 
dignity of thought, were brought in cont^t Mith 
Greek literature, Plato had naturally greater charms 
for them. A powerful school of Platonists i(not 
Neoplatonists) was formed . in Italy, including some 
of the principal scholars and men of genius of the 
time ; as Picus of Mirandula in the middle, Marsir 
lius Ficinus at the end, of the fifteenth century. At 
pne time, it appeared as if the ascendency of Aria* 
totle was about to be overturned ; but, in physics at 
least, his authority passed unshaken through this 
trial. It was not by disputation that Aristotle could 
be overthrown ; and the Platonists were not persona 
whose doctrines led th^m to use the only decisive 
method in such cases, the observation and unfettei^ed 
interpretation of facts* 

The history of their controversies, therefore^ does 
not belong to our design. For like reasons we do 
not here speak of other authors, who opposed tho 
scholastic philosophy on general theoretical grounds 
of various kinds. Such examples of insurrection 
against the dogmatism which we have been review* 

»• Halhun, M. A., in. 536. 



DOOMAtrSM OF THE STATIONARY PERIOD. 329 

ing, are extremely interesting events in the history 
of the philosophy of science. Bnt, in the present 
work, we are to confine ourselves to the history of 
science itself; in the hope that we may thus be able 
hereafter, to throw a steadier light iipon that philo- 
sophy by which the succession of stationary and 
progressive periods which we are here tracing, may 
be in some measure explained. We are now to 
close our accotmt of the stationary period, and to 
enter upon the great subject of the progress of physi- 
cal science in modem times. 

5. Subjects omitted. Civil Law. Medicine. — My 
object has been to make my way, as rapidly as pos- 
sible, to this period of progress ; and in doing this, I 
have had to pass over a long and barren tract, where 
almost all traces of the right road disappear. In 
exploring this region, it is not without some difficulty 
that he who is travelling with objects such as mine, 
continues a steady progress in the proper direction ; 
for many curious and attractive subjects of research 
come in his way: he crosses the track of many a 
controversy, which in its time divided the world of 
speculators, and of which the results may be traced, 
even now, in the conduct of moral, or political, or 
metaphysical discussions ; or in the common associa- 
tions of thought, arid forms of language. The wars 
of the Nominalists and Realists ; the disputes con- 
cerning the foundations of morals, and the motives 
of human actions ; the controversies concerning pre- 
destination, free will, grace, and the many other 



330 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

points of metaphysical divinity; the influence of 
theology and metaphysics upon each other, and upon 
other subjects of human curiosity; the effects of 
opinion upon politics, and of political condition upon 
opinion ; the influence of literature and philosophy 
upon each other, and upon society ; and many other 
subjects ; — ^might be well worth examination, if our 
hope of success did . not reside in pursuing, steadily 
and directly, those inquiries in which we can look 
for a definite and certain reply. We must even 
neglect two of the leading studies of those times, 
which occupied much of men's time and thoughts, 
and had a very great influence on society ; the one 
dealing with notions, the other with things; the 
one employed about moral rules, the other about 
material causes, but both for practical ends ; I mean, 
the study of the Civil Law, and of Medicine. The 
second of these studies will hereafter come before 
us, as one of the principal occasions which led to the 
cultivation of chemistry ; but, in itself, its progress 
is of too complex and indefinite a nature to be ad- 
vantageously compared with that of the more exact 
sciences. The Roman Law is held, by its admirers, 
to be a system of deductive science, as exact as the 
mathematical sciences themselves ; and it may, there- 
fore, be useful to consider it, if we should, in the 
sequel, have to examine how feir there can exist an 
analogy between moral and physical science. But, 
after a few more words on the middle ages, we must 
return to oujp task of tracing the progress of the latter. 



831 



CHAPTER V. 

Progress of the Arts in the Middle Ages. 

1. Art and Science. — ^I shall, before I resume the 
history of science, say a few words on the subject 
described in the title of this chapter, both because 
I might otherwise be accused of doing injustice to 
the period now treated of; and also, because we shall 
thus have, brought under our notice, some circum- 
stances which were important as the harbingers of 
the revival of progressive knowledge. 

The accusation of injustice to the state of science 
in the middle ages, if we were to terminate our 
survey of them with what has hitherto been said, 
might be urged from obvious topics. How do we 
recognise, it might be asked, in a picture of mere 
confusion and mysticism of thought, of servility and 
dogmatism of character, the powers and acquirements 
to which we owe so many of the most important in- 
ventions which we now enjoy ? Parchment and paper, 
printing and engraving, improved glass and steel, 
gunpowJler, clocks, telescopes, the mariner's compass, 
the reformed calendar, the decimal notation, algebra, 
trigonometry, chemistry, counterpoint, which was 
equivalent to a new creation of music ; — ^these are 
all possessions which we inherit from that which has 
been so disparagingly termed the stationary period. 



»■• 



■*>*, 



332 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

Above all, let us look at the monuments of arehi- 
tectnre of this period; — ^the admiration and the 
despair of modem architects, not onlj for their 
beauty, but for the skill disclosed in their construc- 
tion. With all these evidences before us, how can 
we avoid allowing that the masters of the middle 
ages not only made some small progress in astronomy, 
which has, grudgingly as it would seem, been ad- 
mitted in a former Book ; but also that they were 
no small proficients in other sciences, in optics, in 
harmonics, in physics, and, above all, in mechanics ? 

If, it may be added, we are allowed in the present 
day, to refer to the perfection of our arts as evidence 
c^ the advanced state of our physical philosophy ; — ^if 
our steam-engines, our gas-illumination, our build- 
ings, our navigation, our manufiictures, are cited as 
triumphs of science; — shall not prior inventions, made 
under fer heavier disadvantages, — shall not greater 
works, produced in an earlier state of knowledge, 
also be admitted as witnesses that the middle ages 
had their share, and not a small or doubtfol one, of 
science? 

To these questions I answer, by distinguishing 
between art, and science in that sense of general 
inductive systematic truth, which it bearff in this 
work. To separate and compare, with precision, 
these two processes, belongs to the philosophy of 
induction; and the attempt must be reserved for 
another place : but the leading differences are suf- 
ficiently obvious. Art is practical, science is specu- 



^ 



PROGJtESS OF TKB ARTS* 333 

lative : the fonner i^ seen in doing ; the latter rests 
in the contemplation of what is known. The art of 
the builder appears in his edifice, though he may 
never have meditated on the abstract propositions 
on which its stability and strength depends. The 
science of the mathematical mechanician consists in 
his seeing that, under certain conditions, bodies must 
sustain ^ch other^s pressure, though he may neyer 
haVQ applied his knowledge in a single easa 

Npw the remark which. I have to make is this :-^ 
in all cases the arts are prior to the related acienoes. 
Art is the parent, not the progeny, of science ; the 
realization of principles in practice forms part of 
the pi^elude, as well as of the sequBl, of theoretical 
discoyeiy. And thus the inventions of the middle 
ages, which have been above eniunerated, though at 
the present day they may be portions of our sciencess 
are no evidence that the sciences th^ existed ; but 
only that those powers of practical obs^vation and 
practical skill were ^t work, which prepare, the way 
fo;* theoretic^ views and sci^ntifio discoveries* 

It may be urged, that the great works of art do 
virtiially take for granted principles of science ; and 
that, therefore, it is unreasonable to deny science to 
great artists. It may be said^ that the. grand struct 
tures of Cologne, or Amiens, or Canterbury, could 
not have been erected without a profound knowledge 
of mechanical principles. 

To this we reply, that ^uck knowledge is rnani^ 
festly not of the nt^ture.pf that which we call science^ 



334 PHYSICAL SCIEMrCE IN THB MIDDLE AGES. 

If the beautiful and skilful structures of the middle 
ages prove that mechanics then existed as a science, 
mechanics must have existed as a science also among 
the builder? of the Cyclopean walls of Greece and 
Italy, or of our own Stonehenge ; for the masses which 
are there piled on each other, could not be raised 
without considerable mechanical skill. But we may 
go much further. The actions of every man who 
raises and balances weights, or walks along a pole, take 
for granted the laws of equilibrium ; and even animals 
constantly avail themselves of such principles. Are 
these, then, acquainted with mechanics as a science ? 
Again, if actions which are performed by taking 
advantage of mechanical properties prove a know- 
ledge of the science of mechanics, they must also 
be allowed to prove a knowledge of the science of 
geometry, when they proceed on geometrical pro- 
perties. But the most familiar actions of men and 
animals do this. The Epicureans held, as Proclus 
informs us, that even asses knew that two sides of a 
triangle are greater than the third. They may be said 
to have a practical knowledge of this ; but they have 
not, therefore, a science of geometry. And in like 
manner among men, if we consider the matter strictly, 
a practical assimiption of a principle does not imply a 
speculative knowledge of it. 

We may, in another way also, show how inadmissi- 
ble are the works of the master artists of the middle 
ages into the series of events which mark the advance 
of science. The following maxim is applicable to a 



PROGRESS OF THE ARTS. 835 

histoTy, such as we are here endeavouring to write. 
We are employed in tracing the progress of such 
general principles as constitute each of the sciences 
which we are reviewing ; and no fitcts or subordinate 
truths belong to our scheme, except so fer as they 
lead to or are included in these higher principles ; 
nor are they important to us, any further than as they 
prove such principles. Now with regard to such pro- 
cesses of aH as those which we have referred to, as 
the inventions of the middle ages, let us ask, what 
principle each of them illustrates ? What chemical 
doctrine rests for its support on the phenomena of 
gunpowder, or glass, or steel ? What new harmoni- 
cal truth was illustrated in the Gregorian chant? 
What mechanical principle unknown to Archimedes 
was displayed in the printing-press ? The practical 
value and use, the ingenuity and skill of these in- 
ventions is not questioned ; but what is their place 
in the history of speculative knowledge ? Even in 
those cases in which they enter into such a history, 
how minute a figure do they make ! how great is 
the contrast between their practical and theoretical 
importance ! They may have changed the face of 
the world ; but in the history of the principles of 
the sciences to which they belong, they may be 
omitted without being missed. 

As to that part of the objection which was stated 
by asking, why, if the arts of our age prove its scien- 
tific eminence, the arts of the middle ages should 
not be received as proof of theirs ; we must reply 



836 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

to it, by giving up some of the pretensions which 
are often put forwards on behalf of the science of 
our times. The perfection of the mechanical and 
other arts among us proves the advanced condition 
of our sciences, only in so far as these arts have 
b«o pe*o^ b/u.e .pplictioa of some great 
scientific truth, with a clear insight into its nature* 
The greatest improvement of the steam-engine was 
due to the steady apprehension of an atmological 
doctrine by Watt ; but what distinct theoretical prin- 
ciple is illustrated by the beautiful manufactures of 
porcelain, or steel, or glass ? A chemical view of 
these compounds, which would explain the condi- 
tions of success and &ilure in their manufacture, 
would be of great value in art ; and it would 
also be a novelty in chemical theory; so little 
is the present condition of those processes a 
triumph of science shedding intellectual glory on 
our age. And the same might be said of many, 
or of most, of the processes of the arts as now prac 
tised. 

2. Arabian Science. — Having, I trust, established 
the view I have stated, respecting the relation of art 
and science, we shall be able very rapidly to dispose 
of a number of subjects which otherwise might 
seem to require a detailed notice. Though this dis- 
tinction has been recognised by others, it has hardly 
been rigorously adhered to, in consequence of the 
indistinct notion of science which has commonly 
prevailed. Thus Gibbon, in speaking of the know- 



< FSt06BXfi» OP THE ARTB. 337 

l^iAge-of tfaa period ^ no^- under (mr -notice^ says\ 
<^Muelt useful experience had been acquired in th6 
ptoactiee^ofr aits and manufa<^ures ; bui the scieike 
o£' eheaasttytmB^ its^ JOrigin ' ajid^ improvement to 
the;* indourtrjr <xP the iSafrac^s. . They,** he adds, 
^^ first iniieiited and'iiiaided'the alembic for the puiv^ 
poses iof distiUation^ :4malysed the' substances of the 
three kiogdems jof nfltute, tried the . distlncrtronr and 
aflinitieenof' aloatis and acid$, and converted the 
poiso|i6usi tsadfieat^lS'into BOfbmidt salutary medidnes;^' 
The fotcmaiion and realisation of the notions of cmoh^ 
lyms and oS. affimtjfy were important steps in ehe-»: 
mioid science^ n^hicfa, as Ishali^hereafter endeavour 
to diow^ it.TemainJad for the chemists of Eurk)pe to 
nid.ke«t a much later period. If the Arabis(ns ^d* 
dffioie this^ thej might* with justice have been eblled- 
the Btttiiors {Of the science' of chemistry; but^ no' 
doctrineai cto be« ■ adduced^ firom their works wMeh • 
give: .them any title tP' this ^^nii^ntdistinctionv 
Their, claims aror dissipated atrtmce. by the application' 
of the maxim above stated. What analysis of theirs' 
tended(tQf«[St9)bliidi iaiQ^irectived primdpleof cheniis- 
tiy? H^^ikrfitrueido^ineoaaG^imig the differences 
and affinities ctf acids and bjHaUis: did they teach ? We 
need not wonder if Gifobon,wbo^e views of the boun- 
daries of scientific chemistry » were probably very wide 
and indistinct, could include the arts of tiie Arabians 
within its domain; but they* cannot pass the frontier of 
science if philosophitcallydefined, and steadily guarded. 

' * Decline and Fall, vdl. x. p: 43. 

VOL. I. Z 



338 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

The judgment which we are thus led to form 
respecting the chemical knowledge of the middle 
ages, and of the Arabians in particular, may serve 
to measure the condition of science in other depart- 
ments ; for chemistry has justly been considered one 
of their strongest points. In botany, anatomy, 
zoology, optics, acoustics, we have still the same 
observation to make, that the steps in science which, 
in the order of progress, next followed what the 
Greeks- had done, were left for the Europeans of the 
sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. The merits 
and advances of the Arabian philosophers in astro- 
nomy and pure mathematics, we have already 

3. Experimental Philosophy of the Arabians.''^ 
The estimate to which we have thus been led, of 
the scientific merits of the learned men of the 
middle ages, is much less exalted than that which 
has been formed by many writers ; and, among the 
rest, by some of our own time. But I am persuaded 
that any attempt to answer the questions just asked, 
will expose the imtenable nature of the higher 
claims which have been advanced in favour of the 
Arabians. We can deliver no just decision, except 
we will consent to use the terms of science in a 
strict and precise sense': and if we do this, we shall 

* If I might take the liberty of criticising an author who has 
given a very interesting view of the period in question (Maho- 
metanism Unveiled^ by the Rev. Charles Forster, 1829), I would 
remark, that in his work this caution is perhaps too little ob- 



JPEOGRSSS OF THE ABTS. 339 

find little, » either in the particular discoveries or 
general methods of the Arabians, which is important 
in the history o^ the inductive sciences. 

The credit due to the Arabians for improvements 
in the general methods of philosophising, is a more 
difficult question ; and cannot be discussed at length 
by us, till we examine the history of such methods 
in the abstract, which, in the present work, it is not 
our intention to do. But we may observe, that we 
cannot agree with those who rank their merits high 
in this respect. We have already seen, that their 
minds were completely devoured by the worst habits 
of the stationary period,-^mysticism and commenta« 
tion. They followed their Greek leaders, for the 
most part, with abject servility, and with only that 
kind of acuteness and independent speculation which 
the commentator's vocation implies. And in their 
choice of the standard subjects of their studies, they 
fixed upon those works, the Physics of Aristotle, 
which have never promoted the progress of science^ 

served. Thus, lie says, in speaking of Alhazen (vol. ii. p. 270), 
^'the theory of the telescope maj be found in the work of this 
astronomer;" and of another, ^^ the uses of magnifjing glasses 
and telescopes, and the principle of their construction, are ex- 
plained in the great work of (Roger) Bacon, with a truth and 
clearness which hare commanded universal admiration." Such 
phrases would he much too strong, even if used respecting the 
optical doctrines of Kepler, which were yet incomparably more 
true and clear than those of Bacon. To employ such language, 
in such cases, is to deprive such terms as theory and principles 
of all meaning. 

Z 2 



340 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

except so far as they incited men to refutp them ; an 
effect which they never produced on the Arabians. 
That the Arabian astronomers made some advances 
beyond the Greeks, we have already stated: the 
two great instances are, the discovery of the motion 
of the sun's apogee by Albategnius, and the dis- 
covery (recently brought to light) of the existence 
of the moon's second inequality, by Aboul Wefiu 
But we cannot but observe in how different a 
manner they treated these discoveries, from that with 
which Hipparchus or Ptolemy would have done. The 
variation of the moon, in particular, instead of being 
incorporated into the system by means of an epicycle, 
as Ptolemy had done with the evection, was allowed, 
almost immediately, so &r as we can judge, to fall 
into neglect and oblivion : so little were the learned 
Arabians prepared to take their lessons from obser- 
vation as well as books. That in many subjects 
they made experiments, may easily be allowed: 
there neyer was a period of the earth's history, and 
least of all a period of commerce and manu&ctures, 
luxury and art, medicine and engineering, in which 
were not going on innumerable processes, which 
may be termed experiments; and, in addition to 
these, the Arabians adopted the pursuit of alchemy, 
and the love of exotic plants and animals. But 
they seem to have been so far from being, as has 
been ipaintained", a people whose "experimental 

' Mahometanism Unveiled, ii. 271. 



PROGRESS OF THE ARTS. 341 

intellect" fitted them to form sciences which the 
"abstract intellect" of the Greeks failed in pro- 
ducing, that the case appears rather to be, that 
several of the sciences which the Greeks had founded, 
were never even comprehended by the Arabians. 
I do not know any evidence that these pupils ever 
attained to understand the real principles of me- 
chanics, hydrostatics, and harmonics, which their 
masters had established. At any rate, when these 
sciences again became progressive, Europe had to 
start where Europe had stopped. There is no Ara- 
bian name which any one has thought of interposing 
between Archimedes the ancient, aiid Stevinus and 
Galileo the modems. 

4. Roger Bacon. — ^There is one writer of the 
middle ages, on whom much stress has been laid, 
and who was certainly a most remarkable person. 
Roger Bacon's works are not only so far beyond his 
age in the knowledge which they contain, but so 
different from the temper of the times, in his asser- 
tion of the supremacy of experiment, and in his 
contemplation of the future progress of knowledge, 
that it is difficult to conceive how such a character 
could then exist. That he received much of his 
knowledge from Arabic vmters, there can be no 
doubt ; for they were in his time the repositories of 
all traditionary knowledge. But that he derived 
from them his disposition to shake off the authority 
of Aristotle, to maintain the importance of experi- 
ment, and to look upon knowledge as in its infancy. 



342 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

I cannot believe, because I have not myself hit 
upon, nor seen quoted by others, any passages in 
which Arabian writers express such views. On the 
other hand, we do find in European writers, in the 
authors of Greece and Rome, the solid sense, the 
bold and hopeful spirit, which suggest such impres- 
sions. We have already seen that Aristotle asserts, 
as distinctly as words can express, that all know- 
ledge must depend on observation, and that science 
must be collected from fistcts by induction. We 
have seen, too, that the Roman writers, and Seneca 
in particular, speak with an enthusiastic confidence 
of the progress which science must make in the 
course of ages. When Roger Bacon holds similar 
language in the thirteenth century, the resemblance 
is probably rather a sympathy of character, than a 
matter of direct derivation ; but I know of nothing 
which proves even so much of connexion with 
Arabian philosophers. 

A good deal has been said of late^ of the coin- 
cidences between his views, and those of his great 
namesake in later times, Francis Bacon \ The re- 
semblances consist mainly in such points as I have 
just noticed ; and we cannot but acknowledge, that 
many of the expressions of the Franciscan fifiar 
remind us of the large thoughts and lofty phrases 
of the philosophical chancellor. How f^r the one 
can be considered as having anticipated the method 

* Hallam's Middle Ages, iii. 539. Forster's Mahom. U. ii. 
313. 



PROGRESS OP THE ARTS. 343 

of the other, we shall examine more advantageously, 
when we oome to consider what the character and 
effect of Francis Bacon's works really are. 

5. Architecture of the Middle Ages. — But though 
we are thus compelled to disallow several of the 
claims which have been put forwards in support of 
the scientific character of the middle ages, there are 
two points in which we may, I conceive, really trace 
the progress of scientific ideas among them; and 
which, therefore, may be considered as the prelude 
to the period of discovery. I mean their practical 
architecture, and their architectural treatises. 

In a previous chapter of this book, we have en- 
deavoured to explain how the indistinctness of ideas, 
which attended the decline of the Roman empire, 
appears in the forms of their architecture ; — ^in the 
disregard, which the decorative construction exhibits, 
of the necessary mechanical conditions of support. 
The original scheme of Greek ornamental architec- 
ture, had been horizontal masses resting on vertical 
columns; when the arch was introduced by the 
Romans, it was concealed, or kept in state of sub- 
ordination ; and the lateral support which it required 
was supplied latently, masked by some artifice. But 
the struggle between the mechanical and the deco- 
rative construction*, ended in the complete disorga- 
nisation of the classical style. The inconsistencies 
and extravagancies, of which we have noticed the 

* See Mr. Willis's admirable Remarks on the Architecture cf 
the Middle Ages^ chap. ii. 



344 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

the occurrence, were results and indications of the 
fall of good architecture. The elements of the 
ancient system had lost all principle of connexion 
and regard to rule. Building became not only a 
mere art, but an art exercised by masters without 
skill, or feeling for real beauty. 

When, after this deep decline, architecture rose 
again, as it did in the twelfth and succeeding cen- 
turies, in the exquisitely beautiftil and skilful forms 
of the Gothic style, what was the nature of the 
change which had taken place, so far as it bears upon 
the progress of science ? It was this : — ^the idea of 
true mechanical relations in an edifice had been 
revived in men's minds, as far as was requisite for 
the purposes of art and beauty : and this, though a 
very different thing from the possession of the idea 
as an element of speculative science, was the proper 
preparation for that acquisition. The notion of 
support and stability in the decorative construction 
again became conspicuous and universal in the forms 
of building. The eye which, looking for beauty in 
definite and significant relations of parts, is never 
satisfied except the weights appear to be duly sup- 
ported', was again gratified. Architecture threw off 
its barbarous characters : a new decorative construc- 
tion was matured, not thwarting and controlling, but 
assisting and harmonizing with the mechanical con- 

• Willis, p. 15 — 21. I have throughout this description of 
the formation of the Gothic style ayailed myself of Mr. Willis's 
well-chosen expressions. 



PROGRESS OF THE ARTS. 345 

struction. All the ornamental parts were made to 
enter into the apparent construction. Every mem- 
ber, almost every moulding, became a sustainer of 
weight; and by the multiplicity of props assisting 
each other, and the consequent subdivision of weight, 
the eye was satisfied of the stability of the structure, 
notwithstanding the curiously-slender forms of the 
separate parts. The arch and the vault, no longer 
trammelled by an incompatible system of decoration, 
but favoured by more tractable forms, were only 
limited by the skill of the builders. Everything 
showed that, practically at least, men possessed and 
applied, with steadiness and pleasure, the idea of 
mechanical pressure and support. 

The possession of this idea, as a principle of art, 
led, in the course of time, to its speculative deve- 
lopement as the foundation of a science ; and thus 
architecture prepared the way for mechanics. But 
this advance required several centuries. The in- 
terval between the admirable cathedrals of Salisbury, 
Amiens, Cologne, and the mechanical treatises of 
Stevinus, is not less than three hundred years. 
During this time, men were advancing towards 
science, but in the meantime, and perhaps from 
the very beginning of the time, art had begun to 
decline. The buildings of the fifteenth century, 
erected when the principles of mechanical support 
were just on the verge of being enunciated in general 
terms, exhibit those principles with a far less im- 
pressive simplicity and elegance than those of the 



349 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

thirteenth. We inay hereafter inquire whether we 
find my other examples to countenance the belief, 
that the formation of science igf commonly accon^-* 
panied by the decline of art 

The leading principle of the style of the Gothic 
edifices was, not merely that the weights were sup- 
ported, but that they were seen to be so ; and that 
not only the mechanical relations of the larger 
masses, but of the smaller members also, were dis- 
played. Hence we cannot admit as an origin or 
anticipation of the Gothic, a style in which this 
principle is not manifested. I do not see, in any of 
the representations of the early Arabic buildings, 
that distribution of weights to supports, and that 
mechanical consistency of parts, which elevates them 
above the character of barbarous architecture. Their 
masses are broken into innumerable members, with'- 
out subordination or meaning, and suggested appa- 
rently by caprice and the love of the marvellous. 
<^In the construction of their mosques, it was a 
favourite artifice of the Arabs to sustain immense 
and ponderous masses of stone by the support of 
pillars so slender, that the incumbent weight seeined, 
as it were, suspended in the air by an invisible 
hand^" This pleasure in the contemplation of ap- 
parent impossibilities is a very general disposition 
among mankind ; but it appears to belong to the 
infancy, rather than the maturity pf intellect The 

'^ Mahometemism XJnveiled^ ii* 255, 



PROGRESS OF THE ARTS, 347 

pleasure in the contemplation of what is clear, the 
craving for a thorough insight into the reasons of 
things, which marks the European mind, is the 
temper which leads to science. 

6, TreoHsm on Architecture* — No one who has 
attended to the architecture which prevailed in 
England) France, and Germany, from the twelfth to 
the fifteenth century, so far as to comprehend its 
beauty, harmony, consistency, and uniformity, even 
in the minutest parts and most obscure relations, 
can look upon it otherwise than as a remarkably 
connected and definite artificial system. Nor can 
we doubt that it was exercised by a class of artists 
who formed themselves by laborious study and prac- 
tice, and by communication with each other. There 
must have been bodies of masters and of scholars, 
discipline, traditions, precepts of art. How these 
associated artists diffused themselves over Europe, 
and whether history enables us to trace them in a 
distinct form, I shall not here discuss. But the 
existence of a course of instruction, and of a body of 
rules of practice, is proved beyond dispute by the 
great series of European cathedrals and churches, so 
nearly identical in their general arrangements, and 
in their particular details. The question then occurs, 
have these rules and this system of instruction any- 
where been committed to writing? Can we, by 
such evidence, trace the progress of the scientific 
idea, of which we see the working in these 
buildings ? 



348 PHYSICAL SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

We are not to be surprised, if, during the most 
flourishing and vigorous period of the art of the 
middle ages, we find none of its precepts in books. 
Art has, in all ages and countries, been taught and 
transmitted by practice and verbal tradition, not by 
writing. It is only in our own times, that the 
thought occurs as fstmiliar, of committing to books 
what we wish to preserve and convey. And, even 
in our own times, most of the arts are learned far 
more by practice, and by intercourse with practi- 
tioners, than by reading. Such is the case, not only 
with manufectures and handicrafts, but with the fine 
arts, with engineering, and even yet, Avith that art, 
building, of which we are now speaking. 

We are not, therefore, to wonder, if we have no 
treatises on architecture belonging to the great 
period of the Gothic masters ; — or if it appears to 
have required some other incitement and some other 
help, besides their own possession of their practical 
skill, to lead them to shape into a literary form the 
precepts of the art which they knew so well how to 
exercise: — or if, when they did write on such subjects^ 
they seem, instead of delivering their own sound 
practical principles, to satisfy themselves with pur- 
suing some of the frivolous notions and speculations 
which were then current in the world of letters* 

Such appears to be the case. The earliest treatises 
on architecture come before us under the form which 
the commentatorial spirit of the middle ages inspired. 
They are translations of Vitruvius, with annotations. 



PROGRESS OF THE ARTS. 349 

In some of these, particularly that of Cesare Cesa- 
riano, published at Como, in 1521, we see, in a very 
curious manner, how the habit of assuming that, in 
every department of literature, the ancients must 
needs be their masters, led these writers to subordi- 
nate the members of their own architecture to the 
precepts of the Roman author. We have Gothic 
shafts, mouldings, and arrangements, given as paral- 
lelisms to others, which profess to represent the 
Roman style, but which are, in fact, examples of 
that mixed manner which is called the style of the 
cinqtie cento by the Italians, of the renaissance by the 
French, and which is commonly included in our 
Elizabethan. But in the early architectural works, 
besides the superstitions and mistaken erudition 
which thus choked the growth of real architectural 
doctrines, another of the peculiar elements of the 
middle ages comes into view ; — ^its mysticism. The 
dimensions and positions of the various parts of 
edifices and of their members, are determined by 
drawing triangles, squares, circles, and other figures, 
in such a manner as to bound them : and to these 
geometrical figures were assigned many abstruse 
significations. The plan and the front of the Cathe- 
dral at Milan are thus represented in Cesariano's 
work, bounded and subdivided by various equilateral 
triangles ; and it is easy to see, in the earnestness 
with which he points out these relations, the evi- 
dence of a fanciful and mystical turn of thought ^ 

^ The plan which he has given, fol. 14, he has entitled 
^' Ichnographia Fundamenti sacrse ^dis baricephalae, Oermanico 



360 PHYSICAL SCIENCfi IN THE MIDDLE AGES. 

We thus find eradition and mysticism take the 
place of much of that developement of the architec- 
tural principles of the middle ages which would be 
so interesting to us. Still, however, these works 
are by uo means without their value. Indeed many 
of the arts appear to flourish not at all the worse, for 
being treated in a manner somewhat mystical ; and 
it may easily be, that the relations of geometrical 
figures, for which fantastical reasons are given, may 
really involve principles of beauty or stability. But 
independently of this, we find, in the best works of 
the architects of all ages (including engineers), evi- 
dence that the true idea of mechanical pressure exists 
among them more distinctly than among men in 
general, although it may not be developed in a 
scientific form. This ' is true up to our own time, 
and these arts could not be successfully exercised 
if it were not so. Hence the writings of architects 
and engineers during the middle ages do really form 
a prelude to the writers on scientific mechanics. 
Vitruvius, in his Architecture^ and Julius Frontinus, 
who, under Vespasian, wrote On Aqueducts^ of 
which he was superintendent, have transmitted to 

more, a Trigono ac Pariquadrato perstructa, uti etiam ea quad 
nunc Milani videtur." 

The work of Cesariano was translated into German by 
Gualter Eirius, and published at Nuremberg, in 1548, under 
the title of Yitruyius Teutsch, with copies of the Italian dia- 
grams. A few years ago, in an article in the Wiener Jahr- 
biicher (Oct. — Dec, 1821), the reviewer maintained, on the 
authority of the diagrams in Rivius's book, that Gothic archi- 
tecture had its origin in Germany, and not in England. 



PROGRESS OF THE ARTS. 351 

US the principal part of What we know respecting 
the practical mechanics and hydraulics of the Ro- 
mal In modem time, the series is resumed. 
The early writers on architecture are also writers on 
engineering, and often on hydrostatics: for ex- 
ample, Leonardo da Vinci wrote on the equilibrium 
of water. And thus we are led up to Stevinus of 
Bruges, who was engineer to Prince Maurice of 
Nassau, and inspector of the dykes in Holland; 
and in whose work, on the processes of his art, is 
contained the first clear modem statement of the 
scientific principles of hydrostatics. 

Having thus explained both the obstacles and the 
prospects which the middle ages offered to the 
progress of science, I now proceed to the history of 
the progress, when it was once again resumed. 



BOOK V. 



HISTORY 



OF 



FORMAL ASTRONOMY 



AFTER THE STATIONARY PERIOD. 



VOL. I. 2 A 



• • • Cjclopum edncta caminifl 

MfBDia conqdcio, atqne adverBO fomice portas. 

Hia demum exactis, perfecto mnnere Diysd, 
Devenere looos Isetos et amflena yireta 
Fortimatonim nemomm sedesqne beatas. 
TsjTgioT hie campos sether et lumine vestit 
Fmpureo : solemque sauni, sua sidera noront. 

Virgil, JEn. vL 630. 



They leave at length the nether gloom, and stand 

Before the portals of a better land : 

To happier plains they come, and £Edrer groves, 

The seats of those whom heaven, benignant, loves ; 

A brighter day, a bhier ether, spreads 

Its lucid depths above their fsivonred heads ; 

And, pniged from mists that veil our earthly skies. 

Shine sons and stars unseen by mortal eyes. 



Introduction. 

Of Formal and Physical AstroMmy. 

We have thus rapidly traced the causes of the ahnost 
complete blank which the history of physical science 
offers, from the decline of the Roman empire, for a 
thousand years. Along with the breaking up of the 
ancient forms of society, were broken up the ancient 
energy of thinking, the clearness of idea, and steadi- 
ness of intellectual action. This mental declension 
produced a senile admiration for the genius of the 
better times, and thus, the spirit of commentation : 
Christianity established the clain) of truth to govern 
the world; and this principle, misinterpreted and 
combined with the ignorance and servility of the 
times, gave rise to the dogmatic system : and the 
love of speculation, finding no secure and permitted 
path on solid ground, went off into the regions of 
mysticism. 

The causes which produced the inertness and 
blindness of the stationary period of human know- 
ledge, began at last to yield to the influence of the 
principles which tended to progression. The indis- 
tinctness of thought, which was the original feature 
in the decline of sound knowledge, was in a measure 
remedied by the steady cultivation of pure mathe- 
matics and astronomy, and by the progress of inven- 

2 A 2 



356 INTRODUCTION. 

tions in the arts, which call out and fix the distinct- 
ness of our conceptions of the relations of natural 
phenomena. As men's minds became clear, they 
became less servile : the perception of the nature of 
truth drew men away from controversies about mere 
opinion ; when they saw distinctly the relations of 
things^ they ceased to give their whole attention to 
what had been said concerning them ; and thus, as 
science rose into view, the spirit of commentation 
lost its sway. And when men came to feel what it 
was to think for themselves on subjects of science, 
they soon rebelled against the right of others to im- 
pose opinions upon them. When they threw off 
their blind admiration for the ancients, they were 
disposed to cast away also their passive obedience to 
the ancient system of doctrines. When they were 
no longer inspired by the spirit of commentation, 
they were no longer submissive to the dogmatism of 
the schools. When they began to feel that they 
could discover truths, they felt also a persuasion of a 
right and a growing will so to do. 

Thus the revived clearness of ideas, which made 
its appearance at the revival of letters, brought on a 
struggle with the authority, intellectual and civil, of 
the established schools of philosophy. This clearness 
of idea showed itself, in the first instance, in astro- 
nomy, and was embodied in the system of Copernicus ; 
but the contest did not come to a crisis till a century 
later, in the time of Galileo and other disciples of 
the new doctrine. It is oui: present business to trace 



INTRODUCTION. 357 

the principles of this series of events in the history 
of philosophy. 

I do not profess to write a history of astronomy, 
any further than is necessary in order to exhibit the 
principles on which the progression of science pro- 
ceeds ; and, therefore, I neglect subordinate persons 
and occurrences, in order to bring into view the 
leading features of great changes. Now in the in- 
troduction of the Copernican system into general 
acceptation, two leading views operated upon men's 
minds ; the consideration of the system as exhibiting 
the apparent motions of the universe, and the consi- 
deration of this system with reference to its causes ; — 
the formal SLiid the phj/sical ss]^ect of the theory ; — ^the 
relations of space and time, and the relations of force 
and matter. These two divisions of the subject were 
at first not clearly separated ; and, indeed, the second 
was long mixed, in a manner very dim and obscure, 
with the first, without appearing as a distinct subject 
of attention ; but at last it was extricated and treated 
in a manner suitable to its nature. The views of 
Copernicus rested mainly on the formal conditions of 
the universe, the relations of space and time ; but 
Kepler, Galileo, and others, were led, by controversies 
and other causes, to give a gradually increasing 
attention to the physical relations of the heavenly 
bodies ; an impulse was given to the study of me- 
chanics, (the doctrine of motion,) which became very 
soon an important and extensive science ; and in no 
long period, the discoveries of Kepler, suggested by 



358 INTRODUCTION. 

a vague but intense belief in the physical connexion 
of the paxts of the universe, led to the decisive and 
sublime generalizations of Newton. 

The distinction of formal and physical astronomy 
thus becomes necessary, in order to treat clearly of 
the discussions which the propounding of the Coper- 
nican theory occasioned. But it may be observed 
that, besides this great change, astronomy made very 
great advances in the same path which we have 
already been tracing, namely, the determination of 
the quantities and lavrs of the celestial motions, in so 
far as they were exhibited by the ancient theories, or 
might be represented by obvious modifications of 
those theories. I speak of new inequalities, new 
phenomena, such as Copernicus, Galileo, and Tycho 
Brahe discovered. As, however, these were very 
soon referred to the Copemican rather than the 
Ptolemaic hypothesis, they may be considered as 
developements rather of the new than of the old 
theory ; and I shall, therefore, treat of them, agree- 
ably to the plan of the former part, as the sequel of 
the Copemican induction. 



859 



CHAPTER I. 



Prelude to the Inductive Epoch of 

Copernicus. 

The doctrine of Copernicus, that the sun is the true 
centre of the celestial motions, depends primarily 
upon the consideration that such a supposition ex- 
plains very simply and completely all the obvious 
appearances of the heavens. In order to see that it 
does this, nothing more is requisite than a distinct 
conception of the nature of relative motion, and a 
knowledge of the principal astronomical phenomena. 
There was, therefore, no reason why such a doctrine 
might not be discovered^ that is, suggested as a theory 
plausible at first sight, long before the time of 
Copernicus; or rather, it was inevitable that this 
guess, among others, should be propounded as a solu- 
tion of the appearances of the heavens. We are 
not, therefore, to be surprised if we find, in the 
earliest times of astronomy, and at various succeed- 
ing periods, such a system spoken of by astronomers, 
and maintained by some as true, though rejected by 
the majority, and by the principal writers. 

When we look back at such a difference of opi- 
nion, having in our minds, as we unavoidably have. 



360 HISTORY OF FORMAL ASTRONOMY. 

the clear and irresistible considerations by which 
the Copemican doctrine is established for us, it is 
difficult for us not to attribute superior sagacity and 
candour to those who held that side of the question, 
and to imagine those who clung to the Ptolemaic 
hypothesis to have been blind and prejudiced ;— in- 
capable of seeing the beauty of simplicity and sym- 
metry, or indisposed to resign established errors, 
and to accept novel and comprehensive truths. Yet 
in judging thus, we are probably ourselves influenced 
by the prejudices of the knowledge and received opi- 
nions of our own times. For is it, in reality, clear 
that, before the time of Copernicus, the heliocentric 
theory (that which places the centre of the celestial 
motions in the sun,) had a claim to assent so de- 
cidedly superior to the geocentric theory, which 
places the earth in the centre ? What is the basis 
of the heliocentric theory ? — ^That the relative mo- 
tions are the same^ on that and on the other suppo- 
sition. So fer, therefore, the two hypotheses are 
exactly on the same footing. But, it is urged, on 
the heliocentric side we have the advantage of sim- 
plicity : — ^true ; but we have, on the other, the testi- 
mony of our senses ; that is, the geocentric doctrine 
is the obvious and spontaneous interpretation of the 
appearances. Both these arguments, simplicity on 
the one side, and obviousness on the other, are 
vague, and we may venture to say, both indecisive. 
We cannot establish any strong preponderance of 
probability in favour of the former doctrine, without 



PRELUDE TO THE EPOCH OF COPERNICUS. 361 

going much further into the arguments of the 
question. 

Nor, when we speak of the superior simplicity of 
the Copemican theory, must we forget, that though 
this theory has undoubtedly, in this respect, a great 
advantage over the Ptolemaic, yet that the Coper- 
nican system itself is very complex, when it under- 
takes to account, as the Ptolemaic did, for the 
inequalities of the motions of the sun, moon, and 
planets; and that, in the hands of Copernicus, it 
retained a large share of the eccentrics and epicyles 
of its predecessor, and, in some parts, with increased 
machinery. The heliocentric theory, without these 
appendages, would not approach the Ptolemaic, in 
the accurate explanation of facts ; and as those who 
placed the sun in the centre had never, till the time 
of Copernicus, shown how the inequalities were to 
be explained on that supposition, we may assert that 
after the promulgation of the theory of eccentrics 
and epicycles on the geocentric hypothesis, there 
was no published heliocentric theory which could 
bear a comparison with it. 

It is true, that all the contrivances of epicycles, and 
the like, by which the geocentric hjrpothesis was made 
to represent the phenomena, were susceptible of an 
easy adaptation to a heliocentric method, when a 
good mathematician had once proposed to himself the 
problem; and this was precisely what Copernicus 
undertook and executed. But, till the appearance 
of his work, the heliocentric system had never come 



362 HISTORY OF FORMAL ASTRONOMY. 

before the world except as a hasty and imperfect 
hypothesis; which bore a favourable comparison 
with the phenomena, so long as their general features 
only were known ; but which had been completely 
thrown into the shade by the labour and intelligence 
bestowed upon the Hipparchian or Ptolemaic theories 
by a long series of great astronomers of all countries. 

But, though the astronomers who, before Coper- 
nicus, held the heliocentric opinion, cannot, on any 
good grounds, be considered as much more enlight*- 
ened than their opponents, it is curious to trace the 
early and repeated manifestations of this view of the 
universe. Its distinct assertion among the Greeks is 
an evidence of the clearness of their thoughts, and 
the vigour of their minds ; and it is a proof of the 
feebleness and servility of intellect in the stationary 
period, that, till the period of Copernicus, no one 
was found to try the fortune of this hypothesis, 
modified according to the improved astronomical 
knowledge of the time. 

The most ancient of the Greek philosophers to 
whom the ancients ascribe the heliocentric doctrine, 
is Pythagoras ; but Diogenes Laertius makes Philo- 
laus, one of the followers of Pythagoras, the first 
author of this doctrine. We learn from Archimedes, 
that it was held by his contemporary, Aristarchus. 
" Aristarchus of Samos," says he \ " makes this sup- 
position, — ^that the fixed stars and the sun remain at 

^ Archim Arenarius. 



PRELUDE TO THE EPOCH OF COPERNICUS. 363 

rest, and that the earth revolves round the sun in a 
circle." Plutarch* asserts that this, which was only 
a hypothesis in the hands of Aristarchus, was proved 
by Seleucus ; but we may venture to say that, • at 
that time, no such proof was possible. Aristotle 
had recognised the existence of this doctrine by 
arguing against it. " All things," says he', " tend to 
the centre of the earth, and rest there, and there- 
fore the whole mass of the earth cannot rest except 
there." Ptolemy had in like manner argued against 
the diurnal motion of the earth : such a revolution 
would, he urged, disperse into surrounding space all 
the loose parts of the earth. Yet he allowed that 
such a supposition would facilitate the explanation 
of some phenomena. Cicero appears to make Mer- 
cury and Venus revolve about the sun, as does Mar- 
tianus Capella at a later period ; and Seneca says*, 
it is a worthy subject of contemplation, whether the 
earth be at rest or in motion : but at this period, as 
we may see from Seneca himself, that habit of in- 
tellect which was requisite for the solution of such 
a question, had been succeeded by indistinct views, 
and rhetorical forms of speech. If there were any 
good mathematicians and good observers at this 
period, they were employed in cultivating and veri- 
fying the Hipparchian theory. 

Next to the Greeks, the Indians appear to have 

* Quest. Plat. Delamb. A. A. vi. 
' Copemic. i. 7* * Quest. Nat. vii. 2. 



364 HISTORY OF FORMAL ASTRONOMY. 

possessed that original vigour and clearness of 
thought, from which true science springs. It is 
remarkable that the Indians, also, had their heliocen- 
trie theorists. Ar7abatta^ (a.d. 1322), and other 
astronomers of that country, are said to have advo- 
cated the doctrine of the earth's revolution on its 
axis ; which opinion, however, was rejected by sub- 
sequent philosophers among the Hindoos. 

Some jmters have thought that the heliocentric 
doctrine was derived by Pythagoras and other Euro- 
pean philosophers, from some of the oriental nations. 
This opinion, however, will appear to have little 
weight, if we consider that the heliocentric hypothesis, 
in the only shape in which the ancients knew it, was 
too obvious to require much teaching; that it did 
not and could not, so far as we know, receive any 
additional strength from anything which the oriental 
nations could teach ; and that each astronomer was 
induced to adopt or reject it, not by any informa- 
tion which a master could give him, but by his love 
of geometrical simplicity on the one hand, or the 
prejudices of sense on the other. Real science, de- 
pending on a clear view of the relation of phenomena 
to general theoretical ideas, cannot be communicated 
in the way of secret and exclusive traditions, like 
the mysteries of certain arts and crafts. If the 
philosopher do not see that the theory is true, he is 
little the better for having heard or read the words 
which assert its truth. 

*Lib. U. K. Hist. Ast. p. 11. 



PRELUDE TO THE EPOCH OF COPERNICUS. 365 

It is impossible, therefore, to assent to those views 
which would discover in the heliocentric doctrines 
of the ancients, traces of a more profound astronomy 
than any which they have transmitted to us. Those 
doctrines were merely the plausible conjectures of men 
with sound geometrical notions ; but they were never 
extended so as to embrace the details of the existing 
astronomical knowledge ; and perhaps we may say, 
that the analysis of the phenomena into the arrange- 
ments of the Ptolemaic system, was so much more 
obvious than any other, that it must necessarily 
come first, iii order to form an introduction to the 
Copemican. 

The true foundation of the heliocentric theory for 
the ancients, was, as we have intimated, its perfect 
geometrical consistency with the general features of 
the phenomena, and its simplicity. But it was 
unlikely that the human mind would be content to 
consider the subject under this strict and limited 
aspect alone. In its eagerness for wide speculative 
views, it naturally looked out for other and vaguer 
principles of connexion and relation. Thus, as it 
had been urged in favour of the geocentric doctrine 
that the heaviest body must be in the centre, it was 
maintained, as a leading recommendation of the 
opposite opinion, that it placed the fire, the noblest 
element, in the centre of the universe. The autho- 
rity of mythological ideas was called in on both sides 
to support these views. Numa, as Plutarch* in- 

* De Facie in Orbe Lunae. 6. 



366 HISTORY OF FOBMAL ASTRONOMY. 

fonns us, btiilt a circular temple over the ever-burn- 
ing fire of Vesta ; typifying, not the earth, but the 
universe, which, according to the Pythagoreans, has 
the fire seated at its centre. The same writer, in 
another of his works, makes one of his interlocutors 
say, "Only, my Mend, do not bring me before a 
court of law on a charge of impiety ; as Cleanthes 
said, that Aristarchus the Samian ought to be tried 
for impiety, because he removed the homestead of 
the universe." This, however, seems to have been 
intended as a pleasantry. 

The prevalent physical views, and the opinions con- 
cerning the causes of the motions of the parts of the 
universe, were scarcely more definite than those con- 
cerning the relations of the four elements, till Galileo 
had founded the true doctrine of motion. Though, 
therefore, arguments on this part of the subject were 
the most important part of the controversy after 
Copernicus, the force of such arguments was at his 
time almost balanced. Even if more had been 
known on such subjects, the arguments would not 
have been conclusive : for instance, the vast mass of 
the heavens, which is urged as a reason why the 
heavens do not move round the earth, would not 
make such a motion impossible ; and, on the other 
hand, the motions of bodies at the earth's surface, 
which were alleged as inconsistent with its motion, 
did not really disprove such an opinion. But ac- 
cording to the state of the science of motion before 
Copernicus, all reasonings from such principles were 
utterly vague and obscure. 



PRELUDE TO THE EPOCH OF COPERNICUS. 367 

We must not omit to mention a modem who 
preceded Copernicus, in the assertion at least of the 
heliocentric doctrine. This was Nicholas de Cusa, 
a cardinal and bishop, who, in the first half of the 
fifteenth century, was very eminent as a divine and 
mathematician; and who in a work, ^^De Docta 
Ignorantia," propounded the doctrine of the motion 
of the earth ; more, however, as a paradox than as 
a reality. We cannot consider this as any anticipa- 
tion of a profound and consistent view of the truth. 

We shall now examine further the promulgation 
of the heliocentric system by Copernicus, and its 
consequences. 



368 



CHAPTER II. 

Induction op Copernicus. — ^The Heliocentric 
Theory asserted on formal grounds. 

It will be recollected that ihe formal are opposed to 
the physical grounds of a theory ; the fonner tenn 
indicating that it gives a satisfectory account of the 
relations of the phenomena in space and time, that 
is, of the motions themselves; while the latter 
expression implies further that we refer to the causes 
of the motions, the laws of force and matter. The 
strongest of the considerations by which Copernicus 
was led to invent and adopt his system of the universe 
were of the former kind. He was dissatisfied, he says, 
in his preface addressed to the Pope, with the want of 
symmetry in the eccentric theory, as it prevailed in 
his days ; and weary of the uncertainty of the mathe- 
matical traditions. He then sought through all the 
works of philosophers, whether any had held opinions 
concerning the motions of the world, different from 
those received in the established mathematical 
schools. He found, in ancient authors, accounts of 
Philolaus and others, who had asserted the motion 
of the earth. " Then," he adds, " I, too, began to 
meditate concerning the motion of the earth : and 
though it appeared an absurd opinion, yet since I 



INDUCTION OP COPERNICUS. 369 

knew that, in previous times, others had been allowed 
the privilege of feigning what circles they chose, in 
order to explain the phenomena, I conceived that I 
also might take the liberty of trying whether, on the 
supposition of the earth's motion, it was possible to 
find better explanations than the ancient ones, of 
the revolutions of the celestial orbs. 

" Having then assumed the motions of the earth, 
which are hereafter explained, by laborious and long 
observation I at length found, that if the motions of 
the other planets be compared with the revolution 
of the earth, not only their phenomena follow from 
the suppositions, but also that the several orbs, and 
the whole system, are so connected in order and 
magnitude, that no one part can be transposed with- 
out disturbing the rest, and introducing confusion 
into the whole universe." 

Thus the satisfactory explanation of the apparent 
motions of the planets, and the simplicity and sym- 
metry of the system, were the grounds on which 
Copernicus adopted his theory ; as the craving for 
these qualities was the feeling which led him to seek 
for a new theory. It is manifest that in this, as in 
other cases of discovery, a clear and steady possession 
of abstract ideas, and an aptitude in comprehending 
real facts under these general conceptions, must have 
been leading characters in the discoverer's mind. 
He must have had a good geometrical head, and 
great astronomical knowledge. He must have seen, 
with peculiar distinctness, the consequences which 

VOL. I. 2 B 



370 HISTORY OF FORMAL ASTRONOMY. 

flowed from his suppositions as to the relations of 
space and time, — the apparent motions which re- 
sulted from the assumed real ones; and he must 
also have known well all the irregularities of the 
apparent motions for which he had to account. We 
find indications of these qualities in his expressions. 
A steady and calm contemplation of the theory is 
what he asks for, as the main requisite to its recep- 
tion. If you suppose the earth to revolve and the 
heaven to be at rest, you will find, he says, ** si serio 
animcdverlas^^ if you think steadily, that the apparent 
diurnal motion will follow. And after alleging his 
reasons for his system, he says^ " We are, therefore, 
not ashamed to confess, that the whole of the space 
within the orbit of the moon, along with the centre 
of the earth, moves round the sun in a year among 
the other planets ; the magnitude of the world being 
so great, that the distance of the earth from the sun 
has no apparent magnitude when compared with the 
sphere of the fixed stars." "All which things, 
though they be diflSicult and almost inconceivable, 
and against the opinion of the majority, yet, in the 
sequel, by God's favour, we will make clearer than 
the sun, at least to those who are not ignorant of 
mathematics." 

It will easily be understood, that since the ancient 
geocentric hypothesis ascribed to the planets those 
motions which were apparent only, and which really 

' De Ber. p. 9. 



INDUCTION OP COPERNICUS. 871 

arose from the motion of the earth round the sim in 
the new hypothesis, the latter must much simplify the 
planetary theory. Kepler' enumerates eleven motions 
of the Ptolemaic system, which are at once extermi- 
nated and rendered unnecessary by the new system. 
Still, as the real motions, both of the earth and the 
planets, are unequable, it was requisite to have some 
mode of representing these inequalities ; and, accord- 
ingly, the ancient theory of eccentrics and epicycles 
was retained, so far as was requisite for this purpose. 
The planets revolved round the sun by means of a 
deferent, and a great and small epicycle ; or else by 
means of an eccentric and epicycle, modified from 
Ptolemy's, for reasons which we shall shortly men- 
tion. This mode of repr^enting the motions of the 
planets continued in use, till it was expelled by the 
discoveries of Kepler. 

Besides the daily rotation of the earth on its axis, 
and its annual circuit about the sun, Copernicus 
attributed to the axis a " motion of declination," by 
which, during the whole annual revolution, the pole 
was constantly directed towards the same part of 
the heavens. This constancy in the absolute direc- 
tion of the axis, or its moving parallel to itself, may 
be more correctly viewed as not indicating any 
separate motion. The axis continues in the same 
direction, because there is nothing to make it change 
its direction ; just as a straw, lying on the surface of 

■ Myst. Cosm. cap. 1. 

2 B 2 



372 HISTORY OF FORKAL ASTRONOMY. 

a cup of water, continues to point nearly in the same 
direction when the cup is carried round a room. 
And this wa« noticed by Copemicus's adherent, 
Rothman', a few years after the publication of the 
work De Revolutionibus. " There is no occasion," 
he says, in a letter to Tycho Brahe, " for the triple 
motion of the earth : the annual and diurnal motions 
suffice." This error of Copernicus, if it be looked 
upon as an error, arose from his referring the position 
of the axis to a limited space, which he conceived 
to be carried round the sun along with the earth, 
instead of referring it to . fixed or absolute space. 
When, in a planetarium, the earth is carried round 
the sun by being fastened to a material radius, it is 
requisite to give a motion to the axis by additional 
machinery, in order to enable it to preserve its paral- 
lelism. A similar confusion of geometrical concep- 
tion, produced by a double reference to absolute 
space and to the centre of revolution, often leads 
persons to dispute whether the moon, which revolves 
about the earth, always turning to it the same face, 
revolves about her axis or no. 

It is also to be noticed that the precession of the 
equinoxes made it necessary to suppose the axis of 
the earth to be not exactly parallel to itself, but to 
deviate from that position by a slight annual diflFer- 
ence. Copernicus erroneously supposes the preces- 
sion to be unequable ; and his method of explaining 

• Tycho. Epist. i. p. 184, a. d. 1590. 



INDUCTION OP COPERNICUS. 373 

this change, which is simpler than that of the 
ancients, becomes more simple still, when applied to 
the true state of the facts. 

The tendencies of our speculative nature, which 
carry us onwards in pursuit of symmetry and rule, 
and which thus produced the theory of Copernicus, 
as they produce all theories, perpetually show their 
vigour by overshooting their mark. They obtain 
something by aiming at much more. They detect 
the order and connexion which exist, by imagining 
relations of order and connexion which have no 
existence. Real discoveries are thus mixed with 
baseless assumptions ; profound sagacity is combined 
with fanciful conjecture; not rarely, or in peculiar 
instances, but commonly, and in most cases; pro- 
bably in all, if we could read the thoughts of the 
discoverers as we read the books of Kepler. To try 
wrong guesses is apparently the only way to hit upon 
right ones. The character of the true philosopher 
is, not that he never conjectures hazardously, but that 
his conjectures are clearly conceived and brought 
into rigid contact with facts. He sees and compares 
distinctly the ideas and the things, — ^the relations of 
his notions to each other and to phenomena. Under 
these conditions it is not only excusable, but ne- 
cessary for him, to snatch at every semblance of 
general rule; — ^to try all promising forms of simplicity 
and symmetry. 

Copernicus is not exempt from giving us, in his 
work, an example of this character of the inventive 



874 HISTOEY OP FORMAL ASTRONOMY. 

spirit. The axiom that the celestial motions must 
be circular and uniform, appeared to him to have 
strong claims ; and his theory of the inequalities of 
the planetary motions is fashioned upon it. His 
great desire was to apply it more rigidly than 
Ptolemy had done. The time did not come for 
rejecting the ajdom, till the observations of Tycho 
Brahe and the calculations of Kepler had been 
made. 

I shall not attempt to explain, in detail, Copemi- 
cus's system of the planetary inequalities. He 
retained epicycles and eccentrics, altering their 
centres of motion; that is, he retained what was 
true in the old system, translating it into his own. 
The peculiarities of his method consisted in making 
such a combination of epicycles as to supply the 
place of the equant, and to make all the motions 
equable about the centres of motion. This device 
was admired for a time, till Kepler's elliptic theory 
expelled it, with all other forms of the theory of epi- 
cycles : but we must observe that Copernicus was 
aware of some of the discrepancies which belonged to 
that theoryas it had, up to that time, been propounded. 
In the case of Mercury, which is more eccentric than 
the other planets, he makes suppositions which are 
complex indeed, but which show his perception of 
the imperfection of the common theory; and he 
proposes a new theory of the moon, for the very 
reason which did at last overturn the doctrine of 
epicycles, namely, that the ratio of their distances 



INDUCTION OF COPEBNICUS. 375 

from the earth at diiferent times was inconsistent 
with the circular hypothesis*. 

It is obvious, that, along with his mathematical 
clearness of view, and his astronomical knowledge, 
Copernicus must have had great intellectual bold- 
ness and vigour, to conceive and fiiUy develope a 
theory so different as his .was, from all received doc- 
trines. His pupil and expositor, Rheticus, says to 
Schener, " I beg you to have this opinion concern- 
ing that learned man, my Preceptor ; that he was an 
ardent admirer and follower of Ptolemy ; but when 
he was compelled by phenomena and demonstration, 
he thought he did well to aim at the same mark at 
which Ptolemy had aimed, though with a bow and 
shafts of a very different material from his. We 
must recollect what Ptolemy says, Ael KiKevBipov 

elvat T§ yyoifitj rov fiiWovra <f>iXo(TO<f>€2v» * He who IS 

to follow philosophy must be a freeman in mind.' " 
Rheticus then goes on to defend his master from the 
charge of disrespect to the ancients : ^ That tem- 
per," he says, " is alien from the disposition of every 
good man, and most especially from the spirit of 
philosophy, and from no one more utterly than from 
my Preceptor. He was very far from rashly reject- 
ing the opinions of ancient philosophers, except for 
weighty reasons and irresistible fiusts, through any 
love of novelty. His years, his gravity of character, 
his excellent learning, his magnanimity and noble* 

* De Rev. iv, c, 2. 



376 HISTORY OF FORMAL ASTRONOMY. 

ness of spirit, are very fiur £5pom haying any liability 
to such a temper, which belongs either to youth, or 
to ardent and light tempers, or to those r&v iieya 
<l>povovvTcifv iirl Oetopia fiixp^y ^ who think much of them- 
selves and know little,' as Aristotle says/' Undoubt- 
edly this deference for the great men of the past, 
joined with the talent of seizing the spirit of their 
methods when the letter of their theories is no 
longer tenable, is the true mental constitution of 
discoverers. 

Besides the intellectual energy which was requi- 
site in order to construct a system of doctrines so 
novel as those of Copernicus, some courage was 
necessary to the publication of such opinions; certain, 
as they were, to be met, to a great extent, by rejec- 
tion and dispute, and perhaps by charges of heresy 
and mischievous tendency. This last danger, how- 
ever, must not be judged so great as we might infer 
from the angry controversies and acts of authority 
which occurred in Galileo's time. The dogmatism 
of the stationary period, which identified the cause 
of philosophical and religious truth, had not yet dis- 
tinctly felt itself attacked by the advance of phy- 
sical knowledge; and therefore had not begun to 
look with alarm on such movements. Still, the 
claims of Scripture and of ecclesiastical authority 
were asserted as paramount on all subjects ; and it 
was obvious that many persons would be disquieted 
or offended, with the new interpretation of many 
scriptural expressions, which the true theory would 



INDUCTION OF COPERNICUS. 377 

make necessary. This evil Copernicus appears to 
have foreseen ; and this and other causes long with- 
held him from publication. He was himself an 
ecclesiastic ; and, perhaps by the patronage of his 
maternal uncle, was prebendary of the church of 
St. John at Thorn, and a canon of the church of 
Frawenturg, in the diocese of Ermeland*. He was 
a student at Bologna, a professor of mathematics at 
Rome in the year 1500, and afterwards pursued his 
studies and observations at Fruemburg, at the mouth 
of the Vistula*. His discovery of his system must 
have occurred before 1607, for in 1543 he informs 
Pope Paulus the Third, in his dedication, that he had 
kept his book by him for four times the nine years 
recommended by Horace, and then only published it 
at the earnest entreaty of his friend Cardinal Schom- 
berg, whose letter is prefixed to the work. "Though 
I know," he says, " that the thoughts of a philosopher 
do not depend on the judgment of the many, his 
study being to seek out truth in all things as far as 
that is permitted by God to human reason: yet 
when I considered," he adds, " how absurd my doc- 
trine would appear, I long hesitated whether I should 
publish my book, or whether it were not better to 
follow the example of the Pythagoreans and others, 
who delivered their doctrines only by tradition and 
to friends." It will be observed that he speaks here 
of the opposition of the established school of astro- 

^ Rheticus, Nar. p. 94. ' Riccioli. 



378 HISTORY OF FORMAL ASTRONOMY. 

nomerSy not of divines. The latter, indeed, he 
appears to consider as a less formidable danger. " If 
perchance," he says at the end of his preface, " there 
be fmraioXoyoii vain babblers, who knowing nothing 
of mathematics, yet assume the right of judging on 
account of some place of Scripture perversely 
wrested to their purpose, and who blame and attack 
my undertaking ; I heed them not, and look upon 
their judgments as rash and contemptible," He 
then goes on to show that the globular figure of the 
earth (which was, of course, an undisputed point 
among astronomers,) had been opposed on similar 
grounds by Lactantius, who, though a writer of credit 
in other respects, had spoken very childishly in that. 
In another epistle prefixed to the work (apparently 
from another hand, and asserted by Kepler^ to be by 
Andreas Osiander), the reader is reminded that the 
hjrpotheses of astronomers are not necessarily as- 
serted to be true, by those who propose them, but 
only to be a way of representing facts. This salvo, 
indeed, appears to be still the orthodox Catholic 
mode of avoiding the supposed theological diflicul- 
ties which are involved in admitting the motion of 
the earth ; for it is the language used by the Jesuit 
editors of Newton. They prefix to the third book 
of the " Principia" a declaration that they admit the 
motion of the earth only as a hypothesis, professing 
to obey the decrees of the popes against the motion 

' See the motto to Kepler's De Stella Martis. 



INDUCTION OP COPEBNICUS. 370 

of the earth : — ^^ Latis a summis pontificibus contra 
telluris motum decretis nos obsequi profitemur." We 
may observe that, in the time of Copernicus, when 
the motion of the earth had not been connected 
with the physical laws of matter and motion, it 
could not be considered so distinctly real as in after 
times. 

The delay of the publication of Copemicus's work 
brought it to the end of his life : he died in the 
year 1543, in which it was published ^ His system 
was, however, to a certain extent, promulgated, and 
his fame diffused before that time. Cardinal Schom- 
berg, in his letter of 1536, which has been already 
mentioned, says, " Some years ago, when I heard 
tidings of your merit by the constant report of all 
persons, my affection for you was augmented, and 
I congratulated the men of our time, among whom 
you flourish in so much honour. For I had under- 
stood that you were not only acquainted with the 
discoveries of ancient mathematicians, but also had 
formed a new system of the world, in which you 
teach that the earth moves, the sun occupies the 
lowest, and consequently, the middle place, the 
sphere of the fixed stars remains immoveable and 
fixed." He then proceeds to entreat him earnestly 
to publish his work. The book appears to have been 
written in 1539', and is stated to have been sent in 
1540 by Achilles P. Gessarus of Feldkirch to Dr. 

^ De Revolutionibus Siderura. • Maestlin. 



380 HISTORY OF FORMAL ASTRONOMY. 

Vogelinus of Constance, as a palingenesis, or new 
birth of astronomy. At the end of the De Revo- 
lutionibus is the " Narratio" of Rheticus, already 
quoted. Rheticus, it appears, went to Copernicus 
for the purpose of studying his theory, and spealcs 
of his " Preceptor" with strong admiration, as we 
have seen. " He appears to me," says he, " more to 
resemble Ptolemy than any other astronomer." This, 
it must be recollected, was selecting the highest 
known subject of comparison. 



881 



CHAPTER III. 

Sequel to Copernicus. — ^The Reception and Db- 
velopement op the copernican theory. 



Sect 1. — First Reception of the Copemican Theory. 

The theories of Copernicus made their way among 
astronomers, in the manner in which true theories 
always obtain the assent of competent judges. They 
led to the construction of tables of the motion of the 
sun, moon, and planets, as the theories of Hippar- 
chus and Ptolemy had done ; and the verification of 
these doctrines was to be looked for, from the agree- 
ment of these tables with observation, through a 
sufficient course of time. The work " De Revolu- 
tionibus" contains such tables. In 1551 Beinhold 
improved and republished tables founded on the 
principles of Copernicus. " We owe," he says in his 
preface, "great obligations to Copernicus, both for 
his laborious observations, and for restoring the doc- 
trine of the Motions. But though his geometry is 
perfect, the good old man appears to have been, at 
times, careless in his numerical calculations. I have, 
therefore, recalculated the whole, from a comparison 
of his observations with those of Ptolemy and others, 
following nothing but the general plan of Copemi- 



382 HISTORY OF FORMAL ASTRONOMY. 

cus's demonstrations." These Prutenic tables were 
republished in 1571 and 1585, and continued in re- 
pute for some time ; till superseded by the Rudolph- 
ine tables of Kepler in 1627. The name Pru- 
tenic, or Prussian, may be considered as a tribute 
to the feme of Copernicus, for it shows that his dis- 
coveries had inspired his countrymen with the ambi- 
tion of claiming a place in the literary community of 
Europe. In something of the same spirit, Rheticus 
wrote an " Encomium Borussise," which was published 
along with his " Narratio." 

The tables founded upon the Copemican system 
were, at first, much more generally adopted than the 
heliocentric doctrine on which they were founded. 
Thus Magin published at Venice, in 1587, " New 
Theories of the Celestial Orbits, agreeing with the 
Observations of Nicholas Copernicus." But in the 
preface, after praising Copernicus, he says, " Since, 
however, he, either for the sake of showing his talents, 
or induced by his own reasons, has revived the opinion 
of Nicetas, Aristarchus, and others, concerning the 
motion of the earth, and has disturbed the established 
constitution of the world, which was a reason why 
many rejected, or received with dislike, his hypothe- 
ses, I have thought it worth while, that, rejecting the 
suppositions of Copernicus, I should accommodate 
other causes to his observations, and to the Prutenic 
tables." 

This doctrine, however, was, as we have shown, 
received with fevour by many persons, even before 



SEQUEL TO COPERNICUS. 888 

its general publication. We have already seen the 
enthusiasm with which Rheticus, who was his pupil 
in the latter years of his life, speaks of him. " Thus," 
says he, " God has given to my excellent preceptor 
a reign without end ; which may he vouchsafe to 
guide, govern, and increase, to the restoration of 
astronomical truth. Amen." 

Of the immediate converts of the Copemican 
system, who adopted it before the controversy on the 
subject had attracted attention, I shall only add 
Maestlin, and his pupil, Kepler. Maestlin published 
in 1588 an " Epitome Astronomiae," in which the 
immobility of the earth is asserted ; but in 1596 he 
edited Kepler's " Mysterium Cosmographicum," and 
the " Narratio" of Rheticus ; and in an epistle of his 
own, which he inserts, he defends the Copemican 
system by those physical reasonings which we shall 
shortly have to mention, as the usual arguments in 
this dispute. Kepler himself, in the outset of the 
work just named, says, " When I was at Tiibingen, 
attending to Michael Maestlin, being disturbed by 
the manifold inconveniences of the usual opinion 
concerning the world, I was so delighted with Coper- 
nicus, of whom he made great mention in his lec- 
tures, that I not only defended his opinions in our 
disputations of the candidates, but wrote a thesis 
concerning the First Motion which is produced by 
the revolution of the earth." This must have been 
in 1590. 

The differences of opinion respecting the Copemi- 



384 HISTORY OF FORMAL ASTRONOMY. 

can system, of which we thus see traces, led to a 
controversy of some length and extent. This con- 
troversy turned principally upon physical considera- 
tions, which were much more distinctly dealt with 
by Kepler, and others of the followers of Copernicus, 
than they had been by the discoverer himself. I 
shall, therefore, give a separate consideration to this 
part of the subject. It may be proper, however, in 
the first place, to make a few observations on the 
progress of the doctrine, independently of these phy- 
sical speculations. 

Sect. 2. — Diffusion of the Copemican Theory. 

The diffusion of the Copemican opinions in the 
world did not take place rapidly at first. Indeed, it 
was necessarily some time before the progress of 
observation, and of theoretical mechanics, gave the 
heliocentric doctrine that superiority in argument, 
which now makes us wonder that men should have 
hesitated when it was presented to them. Yet there 
were some speculators of this kind, who were at- 
tracted at once by the enlarged views of the universe 
which it opened to them. Among these was the 
unfortunate Giordano Bruno of Nola, who was burnt 
as a heretic at Rome in 1600. The heresies which 
led to his unhappy fate were, however, not his astro- 
nomical opinions, but a work which he published in 
England, and dedicated to Sir Philip Sydney, under 
the title of " Spaccio della Bestia Trionfante," 



SEQUEL TO COPERNICUS. 385 

and which is understood to contain a bitter satire of 
the Catholic religion and the papal government. 
Montucla conceives that, by his rashness in visiting 
Italy after putting forth such a work, he compelled 
the government to act against him. Bruno em- 
braced the Copernican opinions at an early period, 
and connected with them the belief in innumerable 
worlds besides that which we inhabit ; as also cer- 
tain metaphysical or theological doctrines, which he 
called the Nolan philosophy. In 1591 he published 
*' De innumerabilibus Mundis et infigurabili, sen de 
Universe et Mundis," in which he maintains that 
each star is a sun, about which revolve planets like 
our earth ; but this opinion is mixed up with a large 
mass of baseless verbal speculations. 

Giordano Bruno is a disciple of Copernicus on 
whom we may look with peculiar interest, since he 
probably had a considerable share in introducing the 
new opinions into England \ He visited this coun- 
try in the reign of Queen Elizabeth, and speaks of 
her and of her councillors in terms of praise, which 
appear to show that his book was intended for 
English readers ; though he describes the mob which 
was usually to be met with in the streets of London, 
with expressions of great disgust : '^ Una plebe la 
quale in essere irrespettevole, incivile, rozza, rustica, 
selvatica, et male allevata, non cede ad altra che 

^ See Burton's Anat. Mel., Pref. '' Some prodigious tenet or 
paradox of the earth's motion," &c. *' Bruno," &c. 

VOL. I. 2 C 



886 HISTOKY OF FOBHAL ASTBONOMT. 

pasoev possa la terra nel suo Beno'." The work 
to which I refer is '^La Cena de le Cenere/' 
and narrates what took place at a eupper held on 
the evening of Ash Wednesday (about 1588, see 
p. 146)9 at the house of Sir Fulk Greville, in order 
to give " H Nolano" an opportunity of defending his 
peculiar opinions. His principal antagonists are two 
*< Dottori d' Oxonia," whom Bruno calls Nundinio and 
Torquato. The subject is not treated in any very 
masterly manner on either side ; but the author makes 
himself have greatly the advantage not only in argu- 
ment, but in temper and courtesy : and in support of 
bis representations of *^ pedantesca» ostinatissima 
ignoranza et presumdone, mista con una rustica inci- 
vilita, che farebbe prevaricar la pazienza di Giobbe," 
in his opponents, he refers to a public disputation 
which he had held at Oxford with these doctors of 
theology, in presence of Prince Alasco, and many of 
the English nobility". 

Among the evidences of the diificulties which still 
lay in the way of the reception of the Copemican 
system, we may notice Bacon, who, as is well known, 
constantly refused his assent to it. It is to be ob- 
served, however, that he does not reject the opinion 
of thd earth's motion in so peremptory and dogmatical 
a manner as he is sometimes accused of doing: 
thus in the '^Thema Cceli" he says, "The earth, 
then, being supposed to be at rest (for that now 

• Opere di Giordano Bruno, vol. 1. p. 146. ■ voL I. p. 179- 



SEQUEL TO OOPERNICUS. 387 

appears to us the mor^ true opinion)." And in his 
tract *• On the Cause of the Tides," he says, -« If the 
tide of the sea be the extreme and dimished limit ef 
the diurnal motion of the heavens, it will follow that 
the earth is immovable ; or at least that it moves 
with a much slower motion than the water." In 
the ♦•Descriptio Globi Intelleotualis" he gives his 
reasons for not accepting the heliocentric theory. 
" In the system of Copernicus there are many and 
grave difficulties: for the threefold motion with 
which he encumbers the earth is a serious incon- 
venience ; and the separation of the sun from the 
planets, with which he has so many affections ip 
common, is likewise a harsh step: and the intro- 
duction of so many immovable bodies into nature, as 
when he makes the sun and the stars immovable, the 
bodies which are peculiarly lucid and radiant ; and 
his making the moon adhere to the earth in a sort 
of epicycle; and some other things which he as* 
sumes, are proceedings which mark a man who 
thinks nothing of introducing fictions of any kind 
into nature, provided his calculations turn out well." 
We have already explained that, in attributing three 
motions to the earth, Copernicus had presented his 
system encumbered with a complexity not really 
belonging to it. But it will be seen shortly, that 
Bacon's fundamental objection to this system'was his 
wish for a system which could be supported by sound 
physical considerations ; and it must be allowed, that 
at the period of which we are speaking, this had not yet 

2 c 2 



388 HifirroRY of formal asttronomt. 

been done in feyour of the Copermcan hypothesis. 
We maj add, however, that it is not quite clear that 
Bacon was in full possession of the details of the 
astronomical systems which that of Copernicus was 
intended to supersede ; and that thus he, perhaps, did 
not see how much less harsh were these fictions^ as he 
called them, than those which were the inevitable 
alternatives. Perhaps he might even be liable to a 
little of that indistinctness, with respect to strictly 
geometrical conceptions, which we have remarked in 
Aristotle. We can hardly otherwise account for his 
not seeing any use in resolving the apparently irre- 
gular motion of a planet into separate regular mo- 
tions. Yet he speaks slightingly of this important 
step*. " The motion of planets, which is constantly 
talked of as the motion of regression, or renitency, 
from west to east, and which is ascribed to the 
planets as a proper motion, is not true; but only 
arises from appearance, from the greater advance 
of the starry heavens towards the west, by which 
the planets are left behind to the east." Un- 
doubtedly those who spoke of such a motion of 
regression, were aware of this ; but they saw how 
the motion was simplified by this way of conceiving 
it, which Bacon seems not to have seen. Though, 
therefore, we may admire Bacon for the stedfastness 
with which he looked forwards to physical astronomy 
as the great and proper object of philosophical inte- 
rest, we cannot give him credit for seeing the ftdl 

* Thema CoeH, p. 246. 



SEQUEL TO COPERNICUS. 389 

value and meaning of what had been done, up to his 
time, in Formal Astronomy. 

Bacon's contemporary, Gilbert, whom he fre- 
quently praises as a philosopher, was much more 
disposed to adopt the Copemican opinions, though 
even he does not appear to have made up his mind 
to assent to the whole of the system. In his work, 
" De Magneta," (printed 1600,) he gives the prin- 
cipal arguments in favour of the Copernican system, 
and decides that the earth revolves on its axis*. He 
connects this opinion with his magnetic doctrines ; 
and especially endeavours by that means to account 
for the precession of the equinoxes; But he does 
not seem to have been equally confident of its 
annual motion. In a posthumous work, published 
in 1651, (" De Mundo Nostro Sublunari Philosophia 
Nova,") he appears to hesitate between the systems 
of Tycho and Copernicus*. Indeed, it is probable 
that at this period many persons were in a state of 
doubt on such subjects. Milton, at a period some<- 
what later, appears to have been still undecided. 
In the opening of the eighth book of the Paradise 
Lost, he makes Adam state the difficulties of the 
Ptolemaic hypothesis, to which the archangel Ra- 
phael opposes the usual answers; but afterwards 
suggests to his pupil the newer system : 

. . . . What if seyenth to these 

The planet earth, so stedfast though she seem, 

Insensihly three different motions move ? 

P. L. b. Till. 

* Lib. vi. cap. 3, 4. • Lib. ii. cap. 20. 



S90 HISTOBT OF FORMAL A8TB0N0MY. 

Milton's leaning) however, seems to have been for 
the new system; we can hardlj believe that he 
would otherwise have conceived so distinctly, tad 
described with such obvious pleasure, the motion of 
the earth : 

Or she from west her silent course advance 
With hio£fetlftite pace, that spinning sleeps 
On her soft axle, while she paces ey^H, 
And bears thee soft with the smooth air along. 

P. L. b. viii. 

Perhaps the works of the celebrated Bishop Wil- 
kins tended more than any others to the difl^lsion of 
the Copemican system in England, since even their 
extravagancies drew a stronger attention to them. 
In 1638, when he was only twenty-four years old, he 
published a book entitled " The Discovery of a New 
World ; or, a Discourse tending to prove that it is 
probable there may be another habitable World in 
the Moon ; with a Discourse concerning the possi- 
hUity of a passage thither" The latter part of his 
subject was, of course, an obvious mark for the 
sneers and witticisms of critics. Two years after- 
wards, in 1640, appeared his " Discourse concerning 
a new Planet ; tending to prove that it is probable 
our Earth is one of the Planets :" in which he urged 
the reasons in favour of the heliocentric system ; and 
explained away the opposite arguments, especially 
those drawn from the supposed declarations of Scrip- 
ture* Probably a good deal was done for the esta- 



SEQUEL TO COPERNICUS4 391 

blishment of those opinions by Thomas Salusbury, 
who was a wann admii^er of Galileo, and published, 
in 1661^ a translation of several of his works bearing 
upon this subject. The mathematicians of this 
coimtry, in the seventeenth century, as Napier and 
Briggs, Horrox and Crabtree, Oughtred and Ward, 
Wallis and Wren, were probably all decided Coper- 
nicans. Kepler dedicates one of his works to 
Napier, and Ward invented an approximate method 
of solving Kepler's problem, still known as "the 
simpld elliptical hypothesis." Horrox wrote, and 
wrote well, in defence of the Copemican opinion, in 
his " Keplerian Astronomy defended and promoted," 
composed (in Latin) probably about 1636, but not 
published till 1678, the author having died at the 
age of twenty-two, and his papers having been lost. 
But Salusbury's work was calculated for another 
circle of readers. " The book," he says in the intro- 
ductory address, "being, for subject and design, 
intended chiefly for gentlemen, I have been as care- 
less of using a studied pedantry in my style, as 
careful in contriving a pleasant and beautifiil im- 
pression." In order, however, to judge of the 
advantage under which the Copernican system now 
came forwards, we must consider the additional 
evidence for it which was brought to light by 
Galileo's astronomical discoveries. 



392 HISTORY OF FORMAL ASTRONOMY. 



Sect. 3.— -7%^ Hdiocenbric ITieorjf confirmed hy Facts. 
GaWeds Astronomical Discoveries. 

The long interval which elapsed between the last 
great discoveries made by the ancients and the first 
made by the modems, had afforded ample time for 
the developement of all the important consequences 
of the ancient doctrines. But when the human 
mind had been thoroughly roused again into acti- 
vity, this was no longer the course of events. Dis- 
coveries crowded on each other ; one wide field of 
speculation was only just opened up, when a richer 
promise tempted the labourers away into another 
quarter. Hence the history of this period contains 
the beginnings of many sciences, but exhibits none 
fully worked out into a complete or final form. Thus 
statics, soon after its revival, was eclipsed and over- 
laid by dynamics ; and the Copernican system, con- 
sidered merely with reference to the views of its 
author, was absorbed in the commanding interest of 
physical astronomy. 

Still, advances were made which had an important 
bearing on the heliocentric theory, in other ways than 
by throwing light upon its physical principles. I speak 
of the new views of the heavens which the telescope 
gave ; the visible inequalities of, the moon's surface ; 
the moon-like phases of the planet Venus ; the dis- 
covery of the satellites of Jupiter, and of the ring of 



SEQUEL TO COPERNICUS. 393 

Saturn. These discoveries excited at the time the 
strongest interest ; both from the novelty and beauty 
of the objects they presented to the sense ; from the 
way in which they seemed to gratify man's curiosity 
with regard to the remote parts of the universe ; and 
also from that of which we have here to speak, their 
bearing upon the conflict of the old and the new 
philosophy, the heliocentric and geocentric theories. 
It may be true, as Lagrange and Montucla say, that 
the laws which Galileo discovered in mechanics 
implied a profounder genius than the novelties he 
detected in the sky: but the latter naturally attracted 
the greater share of the attention of the world, and 
were matter of keener discussion. 

It is not to our purpose to speak here of the details 
and occasion of the invention of the telescope ; it is 
well known that Galileo constructed his about 1609, 
and proceeded immediately to apply it to the heavens. 
The discovery of the satellites of Jupiter was almost 
immediately the reward of this activity : and these 
were announced in his Nuncius Sidereus, published 
at Venice in 1610. The title of this work will best 
convey an idea of the claim it made to public notice : 
" The Sidereal Messenger^ annoimcing great and very 
wonderful spectacles, and oflering them to the con- 
sideration of every one, but especially of philosophers 
and astronomers; which have been observed by 
Galileo Galilei, &c. &c., by the assistance of a per- 
spective glass lately invented by him; namely, in 
the face of the moon, in innumerable fixed stars 



394 Hi&rroitT of fobmal AflrniONOMY. 

in the milkjr way^ in nebulous stafs, but especiallj 
in foul* planets which reyolte round Jupiter at Ai$* 
ferent intervals and periods with a wonderful cele-^ 
litf; which, hitherto not known to any one^ the 
author has recently been the first to detect, and has 
decreed to call the Medicean stars'^ 

The interest this discovery excited was intense: 
and men were at this period so little habituated to 
accommodate their convictions on matters of science 
to newly-observed facts, that several of " the paper-' 
philosophers," as Galileo termed them, appear to have 
thought they could get rid of these new objects by 
writing books against them. The effect which the 
discovery had . upon the reception of the Copemican 
system was immediately very considerable* It 
showed that the real universe was very different 
from that which ancient philosophers had imagined, 
and suggested at once the thought that it contained 
mechanism more various and more vast than had 
yet been coiyectured. And when the system of 
the planet Jupiter thus offered to the bodily eye a 
model or image of the solar system according to the 
views of Copernicus, it supported the belief of such 
an arrangement of the planets, by an analogy all but 
irresistible. It thus, as a writer^ of our own times 
has said, ^' gave the hMing turn to the opinions of 
mankind respecting the Copemican system." We 
may trace this effect in Bacon, even though he does 

^ Sir J. Hersehel. 



SEQUEL TO COPERNICUSi 395 

not adsent to the motion of the earth. *^ We afi&rm," 
he s&ysS ^^the mn^fcUowing arrangement (solisequiuxn) 
of Veaus and Mercury ; since it has be^n found by 
Galileo that Jupiter also has attendants." 

The " Nuncius Sidereus" contained other dis- 
coveries which had the same tendency in other ways. 
The examination of the moon showed, or at least 
seemed to show, that she was a solid body, with a 
surface extremely rugged and irl'egular. This, 
though perhaps not bearing directly upon the ques- 
tion of the heliocentric theory, was yet a blow to 
the Aristotelians, who had, in their philosophy^ made 
the moon a body of a kind altogether different from 
this, and had giyen an abundant quantity of reasons 
for the visible marks on her surface, all proceeding 
on these preconceived views. Others of his dis- 
coveries produced the same effect ; for instance, the 
new stars invisible to the naked eye, and those 
extraordinary appearances called nebulae. 

But before the' end of the year, Galileo had new 
information to communicate, bearing more decidedly 
on the Copernican controversy. This intelligence was 
indeed decisive with regard to the motion of Venus 
itbout the sun ; for he found that that planet, in the 
course of her revolution, assumes the same succession 
of phases ti'hich the moon exhibits in the course of 
a month. This he expressed by a Latin verse : 

CjAthitt figuras aBinulatur mater amoruln : 

The ^ueen of lore like Cjruthia shapes her forms : 

^ Thema Cceli, ix. p^ S53. 



396 HISTORY OF FORMAL ASTRONOMY. 

transposing the letters of this Une in the pubUshed 
account, according to the practice of the age ; which 
thus showed the ancient love for combining verbal 
puzzles with scientific discoveries, while it betrayed 
the newer feeling, of jealousy respecting the priority 
of discovery of physical fsucts. 

It had always been a formidable objection to the 
Copemican theory that this appearance of the planets 
had not been observed. The author of that theory 
had endeavoured to account for this, by supposing 
that the rays of the sun passed freely through the 
body of the planet, and Galileo takes occasion to 
praise him for not being deterred from adopting 
the system which, on the whole, appeared to agree 
best with the phenomena, by meeting with some 
which it did not enable him to explain*. Yet while 
the fate of the theory was yet undecided, this could 
not but be looked upon as a weak point in its defences. 

The objection, in another form also, wa* embarrass- 
ing alike to the Ptolemaic and Copernican systems. 
Why, it was asked, did not Venus appear four times 
as large when near her perigee, as when near her apo- 
gee ? The author of the epistle prefixed to Coperni- 
cus's work had taken refdge in this argument from 
the danger of being supposed to believe in the reality 
of the system ; and Bruno had attempted to answer 
it by saying, that luminous bodies were not governed 
by the same laws of perspective as opaque ones. 
But a more satisfactory answer now readily offered 

• L. U. K. Life of Galileo, p. 35. 



SEQUEL TO COPERNICUS. 397 

itself. Venus does not appear four times as large 
when she is four times as near, because her briglU 
part is not four times as large, though her visible 
diameter is ; and as she is too small for us to see 
her shape, we judge of her size only by the quantity 
of light. 

The other great discoyeries made in the heavens 
by means of telescopes, as that of Saturn's ring and 
his satellites, the spots in the sun, and others, belong 
to the further progress of astronomy. But we may 
here observe, that this doctrine of the motion of 
Mercury and Venus about the sun was further con- 
firmed by Kepler's observation of the transit of the 
former planet over the sun in 1631. Our country- 
man Horrox was the first person who, in 1639, had 
the satisfaction of seeing a transit of Venus. 

These events are a remarkable instance of the 
way in which a discovery in art, (for at this period, 
the making of telescopes must be mainly so con- 
sidered,) may influence the progress of science. We 
shall soon have to notice a still more remarkable 
example of the way in which two sciences (astro- 
nomy and mechanics) may influence and promote 
the progress of each other. 

Sect 4. — The Copemican System opposed on 

Theological Grounds. 

We have seen that the doctrines promulgated by 
Copernicus excited no visible alarm among the 
theologians of his own time ; and we have assigned 



308 Hi&rroRT op formal astronomy. 

as a reason for this, that those who were disposed to 
assert the sway of authority in all matters of belief, 
had not yet been roused and ruffled by the aggres- 
sions of innovators in philosophy and religion, as 
they soon afterwards were. Probably, also, we ought 
to take into account the different temper and cir- 
eumstances of the ultramontane and Italian learned 
men. The latter, liying under the immediate shadow 
of the papal chair, were necessarily less bold in their 
speculations, and less open in their promulgation of 
any opinions which might have a taint of heresy. 
This influence operated less strongly in Poland and 
Germany ; and we find no evidence which leads us 
to deny to these countries the glory of having re* 
oeived the Copemioan system of the world, from the 
first, with satis&ction, and without bigoted oppo- 
sition. The great religious reform which had its 
rise in Germany about the time of the promulgation 
.of the Copemican system, showed sufficiently that 
that was the land where opinions would assert their 
freedom ; and where authority could not, with pru- 
dence, urge superfluous claims. 

But in Italy the church entertained the persuasion 
that her authority could not be upheld at all, with- 
out uMrmtaining it to be supreme ou all poiiits. The 
spirit of dogmatism of the middle ages, which we 
have already endeavoured to characterize, had de- 
scended upon the ecclesiastical institutions of the 
seventeenth ^etitury ; and in consistency with that 
spirit, it was criminal to disturb received doctrines, 



SBQUEL TO 00PERNICU8. 890 

or to separate philosophy from religion. The tenet 
of the earth being at rest in the centre of the uni<« 
verse, was not only a part of the established school-* 
philosophy, but was also, it was conceived, sanctioned 
by Scripture. The Copemican system, therefore, so 
lar as it came into view, was looked at with sus^ 
picion and aversion. But though this system is 
afterwards, in the official condemnation of it, spoken 
of as " entertained by many," it never came under 
the notice of the spiritual judges in any conspicuous 
manner, till it had been illustrated by Galileo's 
discoveries, and recommended by his writings. 

The story of the condemnation of Galileo by the 
Inquisition, for asserting the motion of the earth, 
and of his formal renunciation of this doctrine in 
the presence of his judges, has been so often told, 
that I need not here repeat the details. It rather 
belongs to our purpose to consider what lessons may 
be gathered from it with regard to the progress of 
science. 

One reflection which occurs is, that both Galileo's 
behaviour and that of his judges, appear to disclose 
some Italian traits of character. The assumption of 
supreme authority in all matters of opinion, an 
assumption unsuited to the powers and condition of 
man, had led, it would seem, to a kind of artificial 
state of compromise, in which men's published opi- 
nions were treated as a point of decorum only, the 
truth being left out of consideration. Thus Galileo 
seems to have expected that the flimsiest veil of 



B 



400 HISTORY OP FORMAJL AfimtONOBCY. 

professed submissioH in his b^ef would enable his 
arguments in fiivour of the Gop^mioan dootrine to 
pass unidsited; and the inquisitors were satisfied 
with a renunciation which they eouM not beUeve to 
be sincere. TMs artificial state, again, was probably 
one occasion of the furtive mode of insinuating his 
doctrines, so mudi employed by Galileo, which some 
of his historians admire as subtle irony, and others 
blame as insincerity. Nor do we see anything to 
lead us to believe tiiat Galileo was not at all times 
roady to make such submissions as the spiritual tri- 
bunals roquirod ; although undoubtedly he was also 
very desirous of promoting the cause of what he 
conceived to be philosophical truth. The same 
absence of earnestness appears on the other side, in 
the courtesy and indulgence with which, as is now 
almost universally allowed, Gralileo .was treated 
throughout the course of the proceedings against 
him. For his being confined in the dungeons of the 
Inquisition, as his lot has sometimes been desisribed, 
appears to have consisted principaUy in his being 
placed under some slight rostrictions, firsts in the 
house of Nicolini, the ambassador of his own sove- 
reign, the Duke of Tuscany, and afterwards in the 
country-fieat of Archbishop Piecolomini, one of his 
own warmest friends. It appears to be not going 
too £str to suppose that the extravagant assumptions 
of the churdi of Borne, which it was impossible 
sincerely to allow, and necessary to evade by arti- 
fice, generated in the philosophers of Italy an 



SEQUEL TO COPERNICUS. 401 

acuteness and subtlety^ but also a suppleness and 
servility very different from the vigorous independent 
habits of thought of Germany and England. 

But there remains something more to be attended 
to in the case of Galileo; for though the >See of 
Rome might exaggerate the claims of religious 
authority, there is a question of no small real diffi-> 
culty, which the progress of science often brings into 
notice, as it did then. The revelation on which 
our religion is founded, seems to declare, or to take 
for granted, opinions on points on which science also 
gives her decision ; and we then come to this di- 
lenmia, — ^that doctrines, established by a scientific use 
of reason, may seem to contradict the declarations of 
revelation according to our view of its meaning; — and 
yet, that we cannot, in consistency with our religious 
views, make reason a judge of the truth of revealed 
doctrines. In the case of astronomy, on which 
Galileo was called in question, the general sense of 
cultivated and sober-minded men has long ago drawn 
the distinction between religious and physical tenets 
which is necessary to resolve this dilemma. On 
this point, it is reasonably held, that the phrases 
which are employed in Scripture respecting astro- 
nomical facts, are not to be made use of to guide 
our scientific opinions; they may be supposed to 
answer their end if they fall in with common notions, 
and are thus effectually subservient to the moral and 
religious import of revelation. But the establishment 
of this distinction was not accomplished without 

VOL. I. 2D 



402 HISTORY OF FOkHAli AfltBOKOMY. 

long and diBti*e8skig cont2y)ver8ie8. Nol*» if Wd Wish 
to include all cages in which the fiatne dilemma may 
again come into play, is it easy to lay down an ade* 
quate canon for the purpose, l^ot we can hardly 
foresee, beforehand, what part of the past history of 
the universe may eventually be found to Come Within 
the domain of science ; or what bearing the tenets, 
which science establishes, may have upon our view 
of the providential and revealed government of the 
World. But without attempting here to generalise 
on this subject, there are two reflections which may 
be worth our notice : they are supported by What 
took place in reference to astronomy on the occasion 
of which we are speaking ; and may, at other periods^ 
be applicable to other sciences. 

In the first place, the meaning Which any genera* 
tion puts upon the phrases of Scripture, depends; 
more than is at first sight supposed, upon the 
received philosophy of the time. Hence, while men 
imagine that they are contending for revelation, they 
are, in fact, contending for their own interpretation of 
revelation, unconsciously adapted to what they be- 
lieve to be rationally probable. And the new inter- 
pretation, which the new philosophy requires, and 
which appears to the older school to be a fetal 
violence done to the authority of religion, is accepted 
by their successors without the dangerous results 
which Were apprehended. When the language of 
Scripture, invested with its new meaning, has be- 
come familiar to men, it is found that the ideas 



SfiCtUEL TO COPEltNIOUB. 405 

WMich it fealls upi are quite as reconcileable as the 
f6rthei* ohes Wei*^, ^^th the soundest religious views. 
And the worid then Iboks back with surprise at the 
6i*tti» df thosej who thoU^t that the esseuce df retd* 
lation was involved in their own arbitrary version of 
some collateral circumstance. At the present day 
we can hardly conceive how reasonable men should 
have imagined that religious reflections on the sta- 
bility of the earth, and the beauty and use of the 
luminaries which revolve round it, would be interfered 
With by its beiiig Acknowledged that thifil test and 
tadtidh are aj)parent ohly. 

In the next place, w^ tnay observe that those who 
thU!^ adhere tenaciously to the tt^ditionary or arbi- 
trary mode of understaudilig Scriptural expressions 
df physical stents, ai*e always strongly condemned 
hy suceefeding genefAtidns. They are looked upon 
with feonteUipt by the 'world at Mrgd, who cartnot 
enter Into thd obsolete difficulties With which they 
encumbered theUiselveS 5 fend with pity by the more 
fedUsiddiAtd and serious, whd know how much saga- 
City and right-mindedness Jli*e requisite for the con*- 
dufet df philoi^ophers and religious men on such 
occasions ; but who know also hoW weak fend vain 
is the attempt to get rid of the difficulty by merely 
denouncing the new tenets as inconsistent with 
religious belief, and by visiting the promulgators of 
them with severity such as the state of opinions and 
institutions may allow. The prosecutors of Galileo 
fere still held up to the scorn and aversion of man- 

2 D 2 



404 HISTORY OF FORMAL ASTRONOMY. 

kind ; although^ as we have seen^ they did not act 
till it seemed that their position compelled them to 
do SO, and then proceeded with all the gentleness 
and moderation which were compatible with judicial 
forms. 

Sect. 5. — The Heliocentric THteory confirm^ on Phy- 
sical cofisiderations. — {Prdude to Kepler^s Astroruh 
micd Discoveries.) 

By physical views, I mean, as I have already said, 
those which depend on the causes of the motions of 
matter, as, for instance, the oonsidefation of the 
nature and laws of the force by which bodies fall 
downwards. Such considerations were necessarily 
and immediately brought under notice by the exa- 
mination of the Copernican theory ; but the loose 
and inaccurate notions Fhich prevailed respecting 
the nature and lawa of force, prevented, for som^ 
time, all distinct reasoning on this subject, aad gave 
truth little advantage ovev error. . The fonnation of 
a new science, the science of m^otion BSkA. its causes, 
was requisite, before the helioc^oitric system could 
have justice done it with regard . to this part of the 
subject. 

This discussion was at first carried on, as was to 
be expected, in terms of the received^, that, is, the 
Aristotelian doctrines. Thus, Copernicus says that 
terrestrial things appear to be at r^st when they 
have a motion according to nature, tiiat is, a circular 



SEQUEt t6 COPbRNlCUS. 405 

motion ; and ascend or descend when they have, in 
addition to this, a rectilinear motion by which they 
endeavour to get into their own place. But his 
disciples soon began to question the Aristotelian 
dogmas, and to seek for sounder views by the use of 
their own reason. "The great argument against 
this system,'* says Maestlin, " is that heavy bodies 
are said to move to the centre of the universe, and 
light bodies from the centre. But I would ask, 
where do we get this experience of heavy and light 
bodies ? and how is our knowledge on these subjects 
extended so far that we can reason with certainty 
concerning the centre of the whole universe? Is 
not the only residence and home of all the things 
which are heavy and light to us, the earth and the 
air which surrounds it ? and what is the earth and 
the ambient air with respect to the immensity of the 
universe ? It is a point, a punctule, or something, 
if there be anything, still less. As our light and 
heavy bodies tend to the centre of our earth, it is 
credible that the sun, the moon, and the other lights, 
have a similar affection, by which they reniain found 
as we see them, but none of these centres is neces- 
sarily the centre of the universe." 

The most obvious and important physical difficulty 
attendant upon the supposition of the motion of 
the earth was thus stated. If the earth move, how 
is it that a stone, dropped from the top of a high 
tower, fialls exactly at the foot of the tower ? since 
the tower bein^ carried from west to east by the 



406 HISTORY OF FORMAL ASTRONOMY. 

diurnal revolution of the earth, the stone must bei 
left behind to the west of the place fron^ which it 
was let fall. The proper answer to this was, thfit 
the motion which the falling body received from its 
tendency downwards w9J3 compotmded witli thp mo^ 
tion which, before it fell, it had in virt\je of the 
earth's rotation : but this answer* cqu14 not be ^leswrly 
made or apprehended, till Gralileo find his pupi}^ had 
established the laws of such copipositions of motion 
arising from different forces. Bothmaai, Kepler, and 
other defenders of the Copemioan system, g^ve tJiaip 
reply somewhat at a venture, when they asserted 
that the motion of the earth was conn^unicated to 
bodies at its surface. Still, the iacts which indicate 
and establish this truth are obyipT^fl, when the siibject 
is steadily considered; and the Copernic£i.i|d mon 
found that they had the superiority of argument on 
this point as well as others. The attacks upon the 
Copemican system by Durrat, Moiin, Riocioli, and 
the defewe of it by GnUle^ Lanaheig, Gafiae»di ^\ 
left ou all caadid jeasQuerft a oleai* impresiicai m 
feyour of the system. Morin attempted to atop the 
motiQU of the earth, which he oalled breal^ng^ ite 
wings ; his Ake Term Froi^ was publiihed ia 1€48» 
and aaaweved by Gbifiaacqdi. And Rieeidii m late 
as 16^, in his Almageatum Novum, emsmemted 
fifty-seven Copeimoan arguments, and pretended to 
reltite them all : but such reaaoniags now made na 



10 



Pel. A. M. a, 504. 



8EQ.UEli TO COPERNICUS. 407 

converts ; md by this time the mechanical objections 
to the motion of the earth were generally seen to be 
baaeleasi m we shall relate when we come to speak 
of the progress of mechanics aa a distinct science. 
In the mean time, the beauty and simplicity of the 
heliocentric theory were perpetually winning the 
admiration even of those who, from one cause or 
other, reftised their assent to it. Thus Riccioli, the 
last of its considerable opponents, allows its supe^ 
riority in these respects ; and acknowledges (in 1658) 
that the Gopemican belief appears rather to increase 
than diminish under the condemnation of the de-i 
ereea of the Cardinals. He applies to it the lines 
of Horace'^! 

Per danma per oeBdes, ab ipso 
Sumit opes aaimumque ferro. 

Untamed its pride, unchecked its course, 
Froia fben w4 wounds it gathers force. 

We have spoken of the influence of the motion of 
the earth on the motions of bodies at its surfkee ; but 
the notion of a physical connexion among the parts 
of the universe was taken up by Kepler in another 
point of view, which would probably have been con- 
sidered as highly fantastical, if the result had not been, 
that it led to by far the most magnificent and most 
certain train of truths which the whole expanse of 
human knowledge can show. I speak of the peiv 
suasion of the existence of numerical and geometrical 



408 HISTORY OF FORMAL ASTRONOMY. 

laws connecting the distances, times, and forces of 
the bodies which revolve about the central sun. That 
steady and intense conviction of this governing prin- 
ciple, which made its developement and verification 
the leading employment of Kepler's most active and 
busy life, cannot be considered otherwise than as an 
example of profound sagacity. That it was con- 
nected, though dimly and obscurely, with the notion 
of a central agency or influence of some sort, ema« 
nating from the sun, cannot be doubted. Kepler in 
his first essay of this kind, the Mysterium Cosmogra- 
phicum, says, ^^ The motion of the earth, which 
Copernicus had proved by mathematical reasons, I 
wanted to prove by physical^ or, if you prefer it, 
metaphysicaL" In the twentieth chapter of that 
work, he endeavours to make out some relation 
between the distances of the planets from the sun 
and their velocities. The inveterate yet vague 
notions of forces which preside in this attempt, may 
be judged of by such passages as the following : — 
" We must suppose one of two things : eith^ 
that the moving spirits, in proportion as they are 
more removed from the sun, are more feeble; or 
that there is one moving spirit in the centre of all 
the orbits, namely, in the sun, which urges each body 
the more vehemently in proportion as it is nearer ; 
but in more distant spaces languishes in consequence 
of the remoteness and attenuation of its virtue." 

We must not forget, in reading such passages, that 
they were written under a belief that force was re- 



SEQUEL TO COPERNICUS. 409 

quisite to keep up, as well as to change the motion 
of each planet ; and that a body, moving in a circle, 
would stop when the force of the central point 
ceased, instead of moving off in a tangent to the 
circle, as we now know it would do. The force 
which Kepler supposes is a tangential force, in the 
direction of the body's motion, and nearly perpen- 
dicular to the radius ; the force which modem phi- 
losophy has established, is in the direction of the 
radius, and nearly perpendicular to the body's path. 
Kepler was right no further than in his suspicion of 
a connexion between the cause of motion and the 
distance from the centre ; not only was his know- 
ledge imperfect in all particulars, but his most gene- 
ral conception of the mode of action of a cause of 
motion was erroneous. 

With these general convictions and these physical 
notions in his mind, Kepler endeavoured to detect 
numerical and geometrical relations among the parts 
of the solar system. After extraordinary labour, 
perseverance, and ingenuity, he was eminently suc- 
cessful in discovering such relations ; but the glory 
and merit of interpreting them according to their 
physical meaning, was reserved for his greater suc- 
cessor, Newton. 



410 HISTORY op FOBMAL ASTRONOMY. 



CHAPTER IV. 



INPUCnVB EPOCH OF KilFLER. 



Sect. 1. — InteUedual Character of Kepler. 

Several persons*, especially in recent times, who 
have taken a view of the discoveries of Kepler, 
appear to have been surprised and somewhat dis- 
contented that conjectures, apparently so fenclftil 
and arbitrary as his, should have led to important 
discoveries. They seem to have been alarmed at 
the Moral that their readers might draw, from the 
tale of a Quest of Knowledge, in which the Hero, 
though fkntastical and self-willed, and violating in his 
conduct, 2A they conceived, all right rule and sound 

* Laplaoe, Precis de PHist. d'Ast. p. 94. <^ II eat affiigeant potur 
Teiiprit bumaiii de iw e^ gra^d homme m^e« daQ« s^ d^nii^if^ 
auyn^ea, se compl^ire avec delicea dana ses chiin^ri<juQa speoiU^i- 
tions, et les regarder CQmme Tame et la yie de rastronomiQ." 

Hist, of A»t., L. U. K., p. 53. " This success []of Kepler] 
may well inspire with dismay those who are aeoastoined to 
consider experiment and rigorous induction as the only means 
to interrogate nature with success." 

life of Kepler, L. U. K., p. 14, « Bad philosophy." P. 15, 
'^ Kepler's miraculous good fortune in seizing truths across the 
wildest and most absurd theories." P. 5^ ^^ The danger of 
attempting to follow his method in the pursuit of truth." 



inductive; epoch of kbpleb, 411 

philosophy, is rewarded with the most signal tri. 
umphs. Perhaps one or two reflections may in some 
measure reooncile us to this result. In the first 
place, we may observe th«i.t the leading thought 
which suggested and animated all Kepler's attempts 
^as true, and we may add, sagacious and philosot 
phical ; namely, that there must be ^ome numerical 
or geometrical relations among the times, distances, 
md velocities of the revolving bodies of the solar 
system. This settled and constant conviction of an 
important truth regulated all the coi\jectures, ap« 
parently so capricious and fanciful, which he made 
and examined, respecting particular relations in the 
siystem. 

In the next place, we may venture to ^y, that 
advances in knowledge are not commonly made witht* 
put (he previous exercise of some boldness and license 
in guessing. The discovery of new truths requires, 
undoubtedly, minds careftil and scrupulous in examin** 
ing what is suggested ; but it requires, no less, such as 
are quick and fertile in suggesting. What is inven* 
tion, except the talent of rapidly calling before us 
many possibilities, and selecting the appropriate one ? 
It is true, that when we have rejected all the inadr 
missible suppositions, they are quickly forgotten by 
mast persons ; and few think it necessary to dwell 
on these discarded hypotheses, and on the process 
by which they were condemned, as Kepler has dona 
But all who disi^over truths must have reasoned 
upon many errors, to obtain each truth; Qveiy 



412 HISTORY OP FORMAL ASTRONOMY. 

accepted doctrine must have been one selected out 
of many candidates. In making many conjectures, 
which on trial proved erroneous, Kepler was no 
more fanciful or unphilosophical than other dis- 
coverers have been. Discovery is not a " cautious" 
or "rigorous" process, in the' sense of abstaining 
from such suppositions. But there are great dif-^ 
ferences in different cases, in the £Etcility with which 
guesses are proved to be errors, and in the degree 
of attention with which the error and the proof are 
afterwards dwelt on. Kepler certainly was remark- 
able for the labour which he gave to such self-refu- 
tations, and for the candour and copiousness with 
which he narrated them ; his works are in this way 
extremely curious and amusing ; and are a very in- 
structive exhibition of the mental process of dis-* 
covery. But in this respect, I venture to believe^ 
they exhibit to us the usual process (somewhat 
caricatured) of inventive minds : they mther exem-- 
plify the rule of genius than (as has genendly been 
hitherto taught,) the eaeeptiosfu We may add^ that 
if many of Kepler^s guesses now appear fimcifiil and 
absurd, because time and observation have reftited 
them, others, which were at the time equally gra* 
tuitous, have been confirmed by sueeeeding diseo^ 
veries in a manner which makes them appear 
marvellously sagacious ; as for instance^ his assertion 
of the rotation of the sun on his axis, beforo the 
invention of the telescope, and his opinion that the 
obliquity of the ecliptic was decreasing, but would, 



INDUCTIVE EPOCH OF KEPLER. 413 

after a long-continued diminution, stop, and then 
increase again". Nothing can be more just, as well 
as more poetically happy, than Kepler's picture of 
the philosopher's pursuit of scientific truth, conveyed 
by means of an allusion to Virgil's shepherd and 
shepherdess :^- 

Malo ne Cblatea petit, lascira puella 
Et fiigit ad salioes et se cupit ante videri. 

Ooy yet inTittng, Galatea lores 
To sport in sight, then plunge into the grores ; 
The challenge given, she darts along the green, 
"Will not be caught, yet woidd not run unseen. 

We may notice aa another peculiarity of Kepler's 
reasonings, the length and laboriousness of the pro- 
cesses by which he discovered the errors of his first 
guesses. One of the most important talents requi- 
site for a discoverer, is the ingenuity and skill which 
devises means for rapidly testing false suppositions 
as they offer theansdves. This talent Kepler did 
not possess : he was not even a good arithmetical 
calculator, often making mistakes, some of which he 
detected and laments, while others escaped him to 
the last. But his defects in this respect were com- 
pensated by his courage and perseverance in under- 
taldng and executing such tasks ; and, what was still 
more admirable, he never allowed the labour he had 
spent upon any conjecture to produce any reluctance 
in abandoning the hypothesis, as soon as he had 

* Bailly, A. M. ui. 175. ; 



414 HISTOBT OF FOttMAt AfiTTEONOMY. 

evidence of its inaccuracy* The only way in which 
he reWftMed himaelf for his ti^ubl^ Was by d^ 
Scribitlgf to the world, in his lively mAtmet, Mn 
ichetnes, ekertions, and feelings; 

The mtfstical parts df Kepler's t^inioAs^ aji hiii 
belief in astrology, his persuasion that the earth WM 
an animal, and many of the loose moral and spiritual 
as well as sensible analyses by which he rej^tesented 
to himself the powers which he supposed to prevail 
in the uuivei^e, do not appear to have Interfered 
with his discovery, but rather to have stimulated 
his invention, and animated his exertions. Indeed, 
Where there ai*e cleat* scientific ideaa on one subject 
in the rnind^ it does not appeal! that mysticism on 
others is at all unfavourable to the successful prose< 
cution of research. 

It appears, then, that We may eonsidet Kepler's 
character as containing the general features of the dltt* 
Iticter of a scientific discoverer^ though some of the 
features are exaggerated, and some too feebly mat^ked* 
His spirit of invention was undoubtedly very l^ile 
and ready, and this and his pers^erance B&ffeA to 
remedy his deficiency in mathematical artifice and 
method. But the peculiar physiognomy is giVett to 
his intellectual aspect by his dwelling in a mdit 
prominent manner on those erroneous ttidns df 
thought which other persons conceal from the 
worlds and often themselves forget, because they 
find means of stopping them at the outset. In 
the beginning of his book {Arffummta Capiium) 



INbUCTlVfi EPOCH OP KEPLER. 416 

h(§ mp^ " if Christophei» Columbus, if Magellan, if the 
Pdrtugfuese when they narrate their Wanderings, are 
not only excusedj but if we do not wish these pas- 
sages omitted, and should lose much pleasure if they 
Wer^, let no one blame me for doing the same.** 
Kepter's talents were a kindly and fertile soil, which 
h^ cultivated with abundant toil and vigour; but 
With great scantiness of agricultural skill and imple- 
ments. Weeds and the grain throve and flourished 
side by side almost undistinguished ; and he gave a 
peculiar appearance to his harvest, by gathering and 
preserving the one class of plants with as much care 
and diligence as the other. 

Sect 2. — Kepler's Discovery of his Third Lata* 

I sriALL now give some account of Kepler's specula- 
tions and discoveries. The first discovery which hd 
attempted, the relation among the successive dis** 
tances of the planets from the sun, was a fkilure; 
his doctrine being without any solid foundation, 
although propounded by him with great triumph, 
in a work which he called " Mysterlum Cosmogra- 
phlcum,*' and which was published in 1596. The 
account which he gives of the train of his thoughts 
on this subject, viz. the various suppositions assumed, 
examined, and rejected, is curious and instructive, for 
the reasons Just stated ; but we shall not dwell upon 
th^se essays, since they led only to an opinion now 
entirely abandoned. The doctrine which professed to 



416 HISTORY OF FORMAL ASTRONOMY. 

give the true relation of the orbits of the different 
planets, was thus delivered'. ^* The orbit of the earth 
is a circle ; round the sphere to which this circle be- 
longs describe a dodecahedron ; the sphere including 
this will give the orbit of Mars. Bound Mars describe 
a tetrahedron ; the circle including this will be the 
orWt of Jupiter. Describe a cube round Jupiter's 
orbit ; the circle including this will be the orbit of 
Saturn. Now inscribe in the earth's orbit an icosar 
hedron ; the circle inscribed in it will be^ the orbit 
of Venus. Inscribe an octahedron in the orbit of 
Venus ; the circle inscribed in it will be Mercury's 
orbit. This is the reason of the number of the 
planets." The five kinds of polyhedral bodies here 
mentioned are the only " regular solids." 

But though this part of the " Mysterium Cosmo- 
graphicum" was a failure, the same researches con-* 
tinned to occupy Kepler^s mind; and twenty-two 
years later led him to one of the important rules 
known to us as "Kepler's laws;" namely, to the 
rule connecting the mean distances of the planets 
from the sun with the times of their revolutions. 
This rule is expressed in mathematical terms by say- 
ing that the squares of the periodic times are in the 
same proportion as the cubes of the distances ; and 
was of great importance to Newton in leading him 
to the law of the sun's attractive force. We may 
properly consider this discovery as the sequel of the 
train of thought already noticed. In the beginning 

^ L. U. K. Kepler, 6. 



INDUCTIVE EPOCH OF KEPLER. 417 

of the " Mysterium," Kepler had said, " In the year 
15^5, I brooded with the whole energy of my mind 
on the subject* of the Copemican system. There 
were three things in particular of which I pertina- 
ciously sought the causes why they are not other 
than they are ; the number, the size, and the motion 
of the orbits." We have seen the nature of his 
attempt to account for the two first of these points* 
He had also made some essays to connect the motions 
of the planets with their distances, but with his suc- 
cess in this respect he was not himself completely 
satisfied. But in the fifth book of the ^' Harmonice 
Mundi," published in 1619, he says, " What I pro- 
phesied two-and-twenty years ago as soon as I had 
discovered the five solids among the heavenly bodies ; 
—-what I firmly believed biefore I had seen the Har- 
monics of Ptolemy ; — ^what I promised my friends in 
the title of this book (On the most perfect Harmony 
of the Celestial Motions) which I named before I 
was sure of my discovery ; — ^what sixteen years ago I 
regarded as a thing to be sought ; — that for which I 
joined Tycho Brahe, for which I settled in Prague, 
for which I have devoted the best part of my life to 
astronomical contemplations; — ^at length I have 
brought to light, and have recognised its truth 
beyond my most sanguine expectations." 

The rule thus referred to is stated in the third 
chapter of this fifth book. " It is," he says, " a 
most certain and exact thing that the proportion 
which exists between the periodic times of any 

VOL. I. 2 E 



418 FOBHAL HISTORY OF AGTrBONOMT. 

two planets is precisely the sesquiplicate of the pro- 
portion of their mean distances; that is, of the 
radii of the orbits. Thus, the period of the earth is 
one year, that of Saturn thirty years; if any one 
trisect the proportimi, that is, take the cube root of 
it, and double the proportion so found, that is, square 
it, he will find the exact proportion of the distances 
of the earth and of Saturn from the sun. For the 
cube root of 1 is 1, and the square of this is I ; and 
the cube root of 30 is greater than 8, and therefore 
the square of it is greater than fi. And Saturn at 
his mean distance from the sun is at a little more 
than 9 thnes the mean distance of the earth.'' 

When we now look back at the time and exer- 
tions which the establishment of this law cost 
Kepler, we are tempted to imagine that he was 
strangely blind in not seeing it sooner. His object, 
we might reason, was to discover a law connecting 
the distances and the periodic times. What law of 
connexion could be more simple and obvious, we 
might say, than that one of these quantities should 
vary as some power of the other, or as some root, or 
as some combination of the two, which in a more 
general sense, may still be called a power? And if 
the problem had been viewed in this way, the ques* 
tion must have occurred, to what power of the 
periodic times are the distances proportional ? And 
the answer must have been, that they are propor- 
tional to the square of the cube root. This ea^posi- 
facto obviousness of discoveries is a delusion to 



INDUOTIVB EPOCH OP KEPLER. 419 

which we are liable wittf regard to many of the 
most important principles. In the case of Kepler, 
we may observe, that the process of connecting two 
classes of quantities by comparing their powers, is 
obvious only to those who are familiar with general 
algebraical views 5 and that in Kepler's time, algebra 
had not taken the place of geometry, as the most 
usual vehicle of mathematical reasoning. It may be 
added, also, that Kepler always sought his formal 
laws by means of physical reasonings ; and these, 
though vague or erroneous, determined the nature 
of tie mathematical connexion which he assumed. 
Thus in the « Mysterium" he had been led by his 
notions of moving virtue of the sun to this conjec- 
ture, among others, — ^that, in the planets, the increase 
of the periods will be double of the difference of 
the distances ; which supposition he found to give 
him an approach to the actual proportion of the 
distances, but one not sufficiently close to satisfy 

him. 

* 

The greater part of the fifth book of the Har- 
monics of the Universe consists in attempts to ex- 
plain various relations among the distances, times, 
and eccentricities of the planets, by means of the 
ratios which belong to certain concords and discords. 
This portion of the work is so complex and labo- 
rious, that probably few modem readers have had 
courage to go through it. Delambre* acknowledges 

* A. M. i. 358. 

2 E 2 



420 HISTORY OF FORMAL ASTRONOMY. 

that his patience often foiled him during the task ; 
and subscribes to the judgment of Bailly ; "After this 
sublime eflTort, Kepler replunges himself in the rela^ 
tions of music to the motions, the distance, and the 
eccentricities of the planets. In all these harmonic 
ratios there is not one true relation ; iii a crowd of 
ideas there is not one truth : he becomes a- man 
after being a spirit of light." Certainly these spe- 
culations are of no value ; but we may look on them 
with toleration when we recollect that Newton * has 
sought for analogies between the spaces occupied by 
the prismatic colours and the notes of the gamut* 
The numerical relations of concords are so peculiar, 
that we can easily suppose them to have other bear- 
ings than those which first oiflfer themselves. 

It does not belong to my present purpose to speak 
at length of the speculations, concerning the forces 
producing the celestial motions, by which Kepler 
was led to this celebrated law ; or of those which he 
deduced from it, and which are foimd in the " Epi- 
tome Astronomise Copemicande," published 1622. 
In that work also (p. 554), he extended this law, 
though in a loose manner, to the satellites of Jupiter. 
These physical speculations were only a vague and 
distant prelude to Newton's discoveries; and the 
law, as 9^ formal rule, was complete in itself. We 
must now attend to the history of the other two 
laws with which Kepler's name is associated. 

* Optics, b. 2. p. iy. obs. 5. 



INDUCTIVE EPOCH OF KEPLER. 421 



Sect, 3. — Kepler's Discovery of his First and Second 
Laws. Elliptical Themy of the Planets. 

The propositions designated as Kepler's first and 
second laws are these; — that the orbits of the planets 
are elliptical ; — and that the areas described by 
lines drawn from the sun to the planet are propor- 
tional to the times employed in the motion. 

The occasion of the discovery of these laws was the 
attempt to reconcile the theory of Mars to the hypo- 
thesis of eccentrics and epicycles ; the event of it was 
the complete overthrow of that hypothesis, and the 
establishment, in its stead, of the elliptical theory of 
the planets. Astronomy was now ripe for such a 
change. As soon as Copernicus had taught men 
that the orbits of the planets were to be referred to 
the sun, it obviously became a question, what was the 
true form of these orbits, and the rule of the motion 
of each planet in its own orbit. Copernicus repre- 
sented the motions in longitude by means of eccen- 
tries and epicycles, a« we have already said ; and the 
motions in latitude by certain librations, or alternate 
elevations and depressions of epicycles. If a mathe- 
matician could have obtained a collection of true posi- 
tions of a planet, the form of the orbit, and the motion 
of the star would have been determined with refe- 
rence to the sun as well as to the earth ; but this 
was not possible, for though the geocentric position, 
or the direction in which the planet was seen, could 



422 HISTORY OF FORMAL ASTRONOMY. 

be observed, its distance from the earth was not 
known. Hence, when Kepler attempted to deter- 
mine the orbit of a planet, he combined the observed 
geocentric places with successive modifications of 
the theory of epicycles, till at last he was led, by 
one step after another, to change the epicyclical into 
the elliptical theory. We may observe, moreover, 
that at every step he endeavoured to support his 
new suppositions by what he called, in his fitnciful. 
phraseology, " sending into the field a reserve of new 
physical reasonings on the rout and dispersion of the 
veterans:" that is, by connecting his astronomical 
hjrpotheses with new imaginations, when the old 
ones became untenable. We find, indeed, that this 
is the spirit in which the pursuit of knowledge is 
generally carried on with success ; those men arrive 
at truth who eagerly endeavour to connect remote 
points of their knowledge, not those who stop cau- 
tiously at each point till something compels them to 
go beyond it. 

Kepler joined Tycho Brahe at Prague in 1600, 
and found him and Longomontanus busily employed 
in correcting the theory of Mars ; and then he also 
entered upon that train of researches which he 
published in 1609 in his extraordinary work " On 
the Motion of Mars." In this work, as in others, 
he gives an account, not only of his success, but of 
his failures, explaining, at length, the various suppo- 
sitions which he had made, the notions by which he 
had been led to invent or to entertain them, tha 



INDUCTIVE EPOCH OF KEPLEB. 423 

processes by which he had proved their falsehood, 
and the alternations of hope and sorrow, of vexation 
and triumph, through which he had gone. It will 
not be convenient however for us to cite many pas- 
sages of these kinds, curious and amusing as they are. 
Oiie of the most important truths contained in 
the "Motion of Mars," is the discovery that the plane 
of the orbit of the planet should be considered with 
reference to the sun itself, instead of referring it to 
any of the other centres of motion which the eccen- 
tric hypothesis introduced ; and that, when so con- 
sidered) it has none of the librations which Ptolemy 
and Copernicus had attributed to it. The fourteenth 
chapter of the second part asserts, " Plana eccentri- 
dorum esse irdXavTaf that the planes are urdi- 
bratingi retaining always the same inclination to the 
ecliptic, and the same line of nodes. With this step 
Kepler appears to have been justly delighted. His 
reflections on it are very philosophical. " Coper- 
nicus," he says, " not knowing the value of what he 
possessed (his system), undertook to represent 
Ptolemy rather than nature, to which, however, he 
had approached more nearly than any other person. 
For being rejoiced that the quantity of the latitude 
was increased by the approach of the earth to the 
stars, according to his theory, he did not venture to 
reject the rest of Ptolemy's increase of latitude, but 
in order to express it, devised librations of the 
planes of the eccentric, depending not upon its own 
eccentric, but (most improbably) upon the orbit of 



424 HISTORY OF FORMAL ASTRONOMT. 

the earth, which has nothing to do with it. I always 
fought against this impertinent tying together of two 
orbits, even before I saw the observations of Tycho; 
and I therefore rejoice much, that in this, as in 
others of my preconceived opinions, the observations 
were found to be on my side." Kepler established 
his point by a fair and laborious calculation of the 
results of observations of Mars, made by himself 
and Tycho Brahe ; and had a right to exult, when 
the result of these calculations confirmed his views 
of the symmetry and simplicity of nature. 

We may judge of the difficulty of casting off the 
theory of eccentrics and epicycles, by recollecting 
that Copernicus did not do it at all, and that Kepler 
did it only after repeated struggles, the history of 
which occupies thirty-nine chapters of his book. At 
the end of them he says, " This prolix disputation 
was necessary, in order to prepare the way to the 
natural form of the equations, of which I am now to 
treat*. My first error was, that the path of a planet 
is a perfect circle ; — ^an opinion which was a more 
mischievous thief of my time, in proportion as it was 
supported by the authority of all philosophers, and 
apparently agreeable to metaphysics." But before 
he attempts to correct this erroneous part of his 
hypothesis, he sets about discovering the law ac- 
cording to which the different parts of the orbit are 
described in the case of the earth, in which case the 

• iii. 40. 



INDUCTIVE EPOCH OF KEPLER. 425 

ecGentricity is so small that the effect of the oval 
form is insensible. The result of this inquiry was', 
the rule that the time of describing any arc of the 
orbit is proportional to the area intercepted between 
the curve and two lines drawn to the extremities of 
the arc. It is to be observed that this rule, at first, 
though it had the recommendation of being selected 
after the unavoidable abandonment of many, which 
were suggested by the notions of those times, was far 
from being adopted upon any very rigid or cautious 
grounds. A rule had been proved to hold at the ap-» 
sides of the orbit, by calculation from observations, 
and had then been extended by conjecture to other 
parts of the orbit ; and the rule of the areas was only 
an approximate and inaccurate mode of representing 
this rule, employed for the purpose of brevity and 
convenience, in consequence of the difficulty of 
applying, geometrically, that which Kepler then 
conceived to be the true rule, and which required 
him to find the sum of the lines drawn from the sun 
to every point of the orbit. When he proceeded to 
apply this rule to Mars, in whose orbit the oval form 
is much more marked, additional difficulties came in 
his way ; and here again the true supposition, that 
the oval is of that special kind called ellipse, was 
adopted at first only in order to simplify calculation"; 
and the deviation from exactness in the result was 
attributed to the inaccuracy of those approximate pro- 

' p. 194. « iv. c. 47. 



426 HISTORY OP FORMAL ASTRONOMY. 

cesses. The supposition of the oval had ahreadj been 
forced upon Purbach in the case of Mercury, and 
upon Reinhold in the case of the Moon. The centre 
of the epicycle was made to describe an egg-shaped 
figure in the former case, and a lenticular figure in 
the latter*. 

It may serve to show the kind of labour by which 
Kepler was led to his result, if we here enumerate, 
as he does in his fortynseventh chapter ^% six hypo- 
theses^ on which he calculated the longitudes of 
Mars, in order to see which best agreed with obser- 
yation. 

1. The simple eccentricity. 

2. The bisection of the eccentricity, and the dupli- 
cation of the superior part of the equation. 

3. The bisection of the eccentricity and a stationary 
point of equations, after the manner of Ptolemy. 

4. The vicarious hypothesis by a free section of 
the eccentricity made to agree as nearly as possible 
with the truth. 

5. The physical hypothesis on the supposition of 
a perfect circle. 

6. The physical hypothesis on the supposition of 
a perfect ellipse. 

By the physical hypothesis, he meant the doctrine 
that the time of a planet's describing any part of its 
orbit is proportional to the distance of the planet 
from the sun, for which supposition, as we have 

• L. U. K. Kepler, p. 30. '' p. 228. 



INDUCTIVE EPOCH OF KEPLER. 427 

8aid| he conceived that he had assigned physical 
reasons. 

The two last hypotheses came the nearest to the 
truth, and differed from it only by about eight 
minutes, the one in excess and the other in defect. 
And, after being much perplexed by this remaining 
error, it at last occurred to him'* that he might take 
another ellipsis, exactly intermediate between the 
former one and the circle, and that this must give 
the path and the motion of the planet. Making this 
assumption, and taking the areas to represent the 
times, he now saw'* that both the longitude and the 
distances of Mars would agree with observation to 
the requisite degree of accuracy. The rectification 
of the former hypothesis, when thus stated, may, 
perhaps, appear obvious. And Kepler informs us that 
he had nearly been anticipated in this step. (c. 55.) 
•' David Fabricius, to whcSn I had communicated my 
hypothesis of cap. 45, was able, by his observations, 
to show that it erred in making the distances too 
short at mean longitudes ; of which he informed me 
by letter while I was labouring, by repeated eiforts, 
to discover the true hypothesis. So nearly did he get 
the start of me in detecting the truth." But this was 
less easy than it might seem. When Kepler's first 
hypothesis was enveloped in the complex construction 
which was requisite in order to apply it to each point 
of the orbit, it was far more difficult to see where 
the error lay; and Kepler hit upon it only by noticing 

»» c. 58. " p. 235. 



428 HISTORY OP FORMAL ASTRONOMY. 

the coincidences of certain numbers, which, as he 
says, raised him as if from sleep, and gave him a new 
light. We may observe, also, that he was perplexed 
to reconcile this new view, according to which the 
planet described an exact ellipse, with his former 
opinion, which represented the motion by means of 
libration in an epicycle. ** This,'* he says, " was my 
greatest trouble, that, though I considered and re- 
flected till I was almost mad, I could not find why 
the planet, to which, with so much probability, and 
with such an exact accordance of the distances, the 
libration in the diameter of the epicycle was attri- 
buted, should, according to the indication of the 
equations, go in an elliptical path. What an ab- 
surdity on my part ! as if libration in the diameter 
might not be a way to the ellipse !'* 

Another scruple respecting this theory arose 
from the impossibility of sdlving, by any geometrical 
construction, the problem to which Kepler was thus 
led, namely, " to divide the area of a semicircle in a 
given ratio, by a line drawn from any point of the 
diameter." This is still termed " Kepler's problem," 
and is, in fact, incapable of exact geometrical solu- 
tion. As, however, the calculation can be performed, 
and, indeed, was performed by Kepler himself, with 
a sufficient degree of accuracy to show that the 
elliptical hypothesis is true, the insolubility of this 
problem is a mere mathematical difficulty in the 
deductive process, to which Kepler's inductions 
gave rise. 



INDUCTIVE EPOCH OP KEPLER. 429 

Of Kepler's physical reasonings we shall speak 
more at length on another occasion. His numerous 
and fanciful hypotheses had discharged their office, 
when they had suggested to him his many lines of 
laborious calculation, and encouraged him under the 
exertions and disappointments to which these led. 
The result of this work was, the formal laws of the 
motion of Mars, established by a clear induction, 
since they represented, with sufficient accuracy, the 
best observations. And we may allow that Kepler 
was entitled to the praise which he claims in the 
motto on his first leaf. Ramus had said that if any 
one would construct an astronomy without hypothesis, 
he would be ready to. resign to him his professorship 
in the University of Paris. Kepler quotes this pas- 
sage, and adds, " it is well, Rsimus, that you have 
run from this pledge, by quitting life and your pro- 
fessorship*'; if you held it still, I should, with justice, 
claim it." This was not saying too much, since he 
had entirely overturned the hypothesis of eccentrics 
and epicycles, and had obtained a theory which was 
a mere representation of the motions and distances 
as they were observed. 



18 



Ramus perished in the Massacre of St. Bartholomew* 



430 



CHAPTER y. 

Sequel to the Epoch op Keplbm. RECEPnoif, 
Verification, and Extension of the Elliptical 
Theoby. 



Sect. 1. — ApplicatioH of the Elliptical Theory to the 

Planets. 

The extension, to the other planets, of Keplei^s dis- 
coveries concerning the orbit of Mars, obviously 
offered itself as a strong probability, and was con- 
firmed by trial. This was made in the first place 
upon the orbit of Mercury ; which planet, in conse- 
quence of the largeness of its eccentricity, exhibits 
more clearly than the others the circumstances of the 
elliptical motion. These and various other supple- 
mentary portions of the views to which Kepler^s 
discoveries had led, appeared in the latter part of his 
** Epitome Astronomiae CopemicanaB," published in 
1622. 

The real verification of the new doctrine concern- 
ing the orbits and motions of the heavenly bodies 
was, of course, to be found in the construction of 
tables of those motions, and in the continued com- 
parison of such tables with observation. Kepler's 
discoveries had been founded, as we have seen, prin- 



SEQUEL TO THE EPOCH OF KEPLER. 431 

cipally on Tyoho's observations. Longomontanus (so 
ealled as being a native of Langberg in Denmark,) 
published, in 1621, in his •* Astronomia Danica,'* 
tables founded upon the theories as well as the ob* 
servations of his countryman. Kepler^ in 1627 
published his tables of the planets, which he called 
^* Budolphine Tables," the result and application of 
his own theory. In 1683, Lansberg, a Belgian, pub- 
lished also ** Tabulae Perpetuee ;" a work which was 
ushered into the world with considerable pomp and 
pretension, and in which the author cavils very 
keenly at Kepler and Brahe. We may judge of the 
impression made upon the astronomical world in 
general by these rival works, from the account which 
our countryman Jeremy Horrox has given of their 
effect on him. He had been seduced by the mag- 
nificent promises of Lansberg, and the praises of his 
admirers, which are prefixed to the work ; and was 
persuaded that the common opinion which preferred 
Tycho and Kepler to him was a prejudice. In 1636, 
however, he became acquainted with Crabtree, 
another young astronomer, who lived in the same 
part of Lancashire. By him Horrox was warned 
that Lansberg was not to be depended on ; that his 
hypotheses were vicious, and his observations falsi- 
fied or forced into agreement with his theories. He 
then read the works and adopted the opinions of 
Kepler ; and after some hesitation which he felt at 

^ Rheticus, Narratio, p. 98, 



432 HISTORY OF FORMAL ASTRONOMY. 

the thought of attacking the object of his former 
idolatry, he wrote a dissertation on the points of di& 
ference between them. It appears that» at one 
time, he intended to have offered himself as the 
timpire who was to adjudge the prize of excellence 
among the three rival theories, of Longomontanus, 
Kepler and Lansberg ; and, in allusion to the story 
of ancient mythology, his work was to have been 
called " Paris Astronomicus ;" we easily see that he 
would have given the golden apple to the Keplerian 
goddess. Succeeding observations confirmed his judg- 
ment : and the ^^ Budolphine Tables," thus published 
seventy-six years after the Prutenic, which were 
founded on the doctrines of Copernicus, were for a 
long time those universally used. 

Sect 2. — Application of the Elliptical Theory to the 

Moon. 

The reduction to rule of the motions of the moon 
was a harder task than the formation of planetary 
tables, if accuracy was required ; for the moon's 
motion is affected by an incredible nmnber of diffe- 
rent and complex inequalities, which, till their law 
is detected, appear to defy a^l theory. Still, how- 
ever, progress was made in this work. The most 
important advances were due to Tycho Brahe. In 
addition to the first and second inequalities of the 
moon (the equation of the centre^ known very early, 
and the evectiouy which Ptolemy had discovered) 



INDUCTIVE EPOCH OF KEPLER. 438 

Tycho proved that there was another inequality, 
which he termed the variation^ 'which depended on 
the moon's position with respect to the sun, and 
which at its maximum was forty minutes and a half, 
about a quarter of the evection. He also perceived, 
though not very distinctly, the necessity of another 
correction of the moon's place depending on the 
sun's longitude, which has since been termed the 
€mnual eqtmtion. 

These steps concerned the longitude of the moon ; 
Tycho also made important advances in the know- 
ledge of the latitude. The inclination of the orbit 
had hitherto been assumed to be the same at all 
times ; and the motion of the node had been sup- 
posed uniform. He found that the inclination in- 
creased snd diminished by twenty minutes, according 
to the position of the line of nodes ; and that the 
nodes, though they regress upon the whole, some- 
times go forwards and sometimes go backwards. 

Tycho's discoveries concerning the moon are given 
in his " Progynmasmata," which was published in 
1603, two years after the author's death. He repre- 
sents the moon's motion in longitude by means of 
certain combinations of epicycles and eccentrics. 
But after Kepler had shown that such devices are to 
be banished from the planetary system, it was impos- 

» We have seen (Book III, p. 228), that Aboul-Wefa, in the 
tenth century, had already noticed this inequality ; but his dis- 
covery had been entirely forgotten long before the time of 
Tycho, and has only recently been brought again into notice. 

VOL. I. 2 F 



4d4 HISTORY OF FORMAL ASTRONOMY. 

sifole not to think of extending the elliptical theory 
to the moon. Horrox succeeded in doing this ; and 
in 1638 sent his essay to his fiiend Crabtree. It 
was published in 1673, with the'numerical elements 
i^uisite for its application added by Flamsteed. 
Flamsteed had also (in 1671 and 2) compared ibis 
theory with observation, and found that it agreed 
fiir more nearly than the " Philolaic Tables" oF 
BolUaldus, or the '' Carolinian Tables" of Street 
(Epilogus and Tabulas.) Halley, by making ihe 
centre of the ellipse revolve in an epicycle, gaTe mn 
explanation of the evection, as well as of > the 
equation of the centre. 

Modem astronomers, by calculating the effoete^Rf 
the perturbing forces of the solar system, and cooh 
paring their calculations with observafaon, .jiavd 
added many new corrections or equations to tbosd 
known at the time of Horrox ; and since ihe m^ 
tions of the heavenly bodies were even tib^i aflfeot^ 
by these variations as yet undetected, it is clear, itmlk 
the tables of that time must have shown some errors 
when compared with observation. These errors 
much perplexed astronomers, and naturally gave rise 
to the question, whether the motions of the heav^f 
bodies really were exactly regular, or whether they 
were not affected by accidents as little reducible to 
rule as wind and weather. Kepler had held the 
opinion of the casualty of such errors ; but Horrox, 
far more philosophically, argues against this opinion, 
though he allows that he is much embarrassed by 



INDUCTIVE EPOCH OF KKPLEB. 43& 

the deviations. His arguments show a singukrly- 
olear and strong apprehension of the features of the 
oase» and their real import. He saysS '^ these errors 
of .the tables are alternately in excess and defect ; 
bow could this constant compensation happen, if they 
wetie casual ? Moreover, the alternation from excess 
to defect is most rapid in the moon, most slow in 
Jupiter and Saturn, in which planets the error con- 
tinues sometimes for years. If the errors were casual, 
why should they not last as long in the moon as in 
Saturn ? But if we suppose the tables to be right 
in the mean motions, but wrong in the equations, 
these facts are just what must happen ; since Saturn's 
ineqimlities are of long period, while those of the 
Bfeoon aafe numerous, and rapidly changing." It would 
be impossible, at the present moment, to reason 
better on this subject ; and the doctrine, that all the 
a^pparent irregularities of the celestial motions are 
teally regular, was one of great consequence to 
establish at this period of the science. 

Sect. ^. -^Causes of the further Progress of Astronomy. 

We are now arrived at the time when theory and 
observation sprang forwards with emulous energy. 
The physical theories of Kepler, and the reasonings 
of other defenders of the Copemican theory, led 
inevitably, after some vagueness and perplexity, to a 

' Astron. Kepler. Proleg. p. 17* 

2 F 2 



436 HifirroRY of formal astronomy. 

sound science of mechanics ; and this science in time 
gave a new fece to astronomy. But in the mean 
time, while medbanical mathematicians were gene- 
ralising from the astronojny already established, 
astronomers were accumulating new fiacts, which 
pointed the way to new theories and new generalisa- 
tions. Copernicus, while he bad established the per- 
manent length of the year, had confirmed the motion 
of the sun's apogee, and had shown that the eccen- 
tricity of the earth's orbit, and the obliquity of the 
ecliptic, were gradually, though slowly, diminishing. 
Tycho had accumulated a store of excellent observa- 
tions. These, as well as the laws of the motions of 
the moon and planets already explained, were mate- 
rials on which the Mechanics of the Universe was 
afterwards to employ its most matured powers. In 
the mean time, the telescope had opened other new 
subjects of notice and speculation; not only c<m- 
firming the Copemican doctrine by the phases of 
Venus, and the analogical examples of Jupiter and 
Saturn, which appeared like models of the solar sys- 
tem ; but disclosing unexpected objects, as the ring 
of Saturn, and the spots of the sun. The art of ob- 
serving made rapid advances, both by the use of the 
telescope, and by the sounder notions of the con- 
struction of instruments which Tycho introduced. 
Copernicus had laughed at Rheticus, when he was 
disturbed about single minutes ; and declared that if 
he could be sure to ten minutes of space, he should 
be as much delighted as Pythagoras was when he 



INDUCTIVE EPOCH OF KEPLER. 437 

discovered the property of the right angle. But 
Kepler founded the revolution which he introduced 
on a quantity less than this. " Since," he says*, 
" the divine goodness . has given us in Tycho an 
observer so exact that this error of eight minutes is 
impossible, we must be thankful to God for this, 
and turn it to account. And these eight minutes, 
which we must not neglect, will, of themselves, 
enable us to reconstruct the whole of astronomy." 
In addition to other improvements, the art of nume- 
rical calculation made an inestimable advance by 
Napier's invention of logarithms ; and the progress 
of other parts of pure mathematics was proportional 
to the calls which astronomy and physics made upon 
them. 

The exactness which observation had attained 
enabled astronomers both to verify and improve 
the existing theories, and to study the yet unsys- 
tematised facts. The science was, therefore, forced 
along by a strong impulse on all sides. We now 
proceed to speak of the new path into which this 
pressure forced it, and first we must trace the rise 
and progress of the science of mechajiics. 

* De Mot. Mart. 19. 



END OF THE FIRST VOLUME. 



Errata. 



. ..c bed 



ERRATA IN VOL. I. 



Page 42, line 16, /or inscribed, read invented. 
126,. line 1, &c., read 

Chorus op Clouds. 

The Moon by us to you her greeting sends. 
But bids lis say that she*8 an ill-used moon. 
And takes it much amiss that you should still 
Shuffle her days and turn them topsy-turvey ; 
And that the gods (who know their feast-days well,) 
By your false count are sent home supperless. 
And scold and storm at her for your neglect. 

ATo^tf.— This passage is supposed by the commentators to be intended as a 
satire upon those who had introduced the cycle of Meton at Athens, which 
had been done a few years before ^' The Clouds** was acted. 

Page 146, note ^* Acronieai, read Aeronyeai (joKpowKiog, happening at the 
extremity of the night). 
181, bottom line, for somewhat, read somehow. 

245, note, line 7? /or audentes, read rudentes. 

246, line 11, read of Caius. 

271, note, line 2, for essus, read fessus. 

273, line 3 from bottom, /or compounds, read compends. 

274, line 5 from bottom, /or Padiymeus read Pachymerus* 
291, line 11, /or rerpaxrifv, read rrrpcutrxiv. 

301, line 1, for astronom. read Astroninu 
413, line 7; for Male ne, read lialo me. 



London: 

JOHN W. PARKER, 
Wbst Stband.