Skip to main content

Full text of "The Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle"

See other formats


Google 



This is a digital copy of a book that was preserved for generations on library shelves before it was carefully scanned by Google as part of a project 

to make the world's books discoverable online. 

It has survived long enough for the copyright to expire and the book to enter the public domain. A public domain book is one that was never subject 

to copyright or whose legal copyright term has expired. Whether a book is in the public domain may vary country to country. Public domain books 

are our gateways to the past, representing a wealth of history, culture and knowledge that's often difficult to discover. 

Marks, notations and other maiginalia present in the original volume will appear in this file - a reminder of this book's long journey from the 

publisher to a library and finally to you. 

Usage guidelines 

Google is proud to partner with libraries to digitize public domain materials and make them widely accessible. Public domain books belong to the 
public and we are merely their custodians. Nevertheless, this work is expensive, so in order to keep providing tliis resource, we liave taken steps to 
prevent abuse by commercial parties, including placing technical restrictions on automated querying. 
We also ask that you: 

+ Make non-commercial use of the files We designed Google Book Search for use by individuals, and we request that you use these files for 
personal, non-commercial purposes. 

+ Refrain fivm automated querying Do not send automated queries of any sort to Google's system: If you are conducting research on machine 
translation, optical character recognition or other areas where access to a large amount of text is helpful, please contact us. We encourage the 
use of public domain materials for these purposes and may be able to help. 

+ Maintain attributionTht GoogXt "watermark" you see on each file is essential for in forming people about this project and helping them find 
additional materials through Google Book Search. Please do not remove it. 

+ Keep it legal Whatever your use, remember that you are responsible for ensuring that what you are doing is legal. Do not assume that just 
because we believe a book is in the public domain for users in the United States, that the work is also in the public domain for users in other 
countries. Whether a book is still in copyright varies from country to country, and we can't offer guidance on whether any specific use of 
any specific book is allowed. Please do not assume that a book's appearance in Google Book Search means it can be used in any manner 
anywhere in the world. Copyright infringement liabili^ can be quite severe. 

About Google Book Search 

Google's mission is to organize the world's information and to make it universally accessible and useful. Google Book Search helps readers 
discover the world's books while helping authors and publishers reach new audiences. You can search through the full text of this book on the web 

at |http: //books .google .com/I 



INICOMACHEAN ETHICS 

or 

ARISTOTLE 

TRASSt.ATED BT 

¥. H. PBTEBS, M.A. 



NOTE TO THE READER 

The paper in this volume is brittle or the 
inner margins are extremely narrow. 

We have bound or rebound the volume 
utiUzing the best means possible. 

PLEASE HANDLE WITH CARE 

General Bookbinding Co.. CH^s^^H^-^■«^-C>v.\'a 



THE 



NICOMACHEAN ETHICS 



# 



or 



ARISTOTLE 



TRANSLATED BT 

F. H. PETEES, M.A. 

VSXXOW OV DVIVKB8ITT OQLLIOB, OXFUAO 



THZBD BDinOK 




LONDON 
KEGAN PAUL, TBENCH & CO., 1, PATEBNOSTEB SQUARE 

1836 

H 



LIBRARY 

OF THE 

LELAND STANFORD JUNIOR 

UNIVERSITY. 



■■MiP9»aa 




^Hb^- 



PREFACE. 



-•o^ 



A TRANSLATION of a work so well known as Aristotle's 
Ethics scarcely needs any preface. It might perhaps 
seem superfluous to do again what has already been 
done so often ; but every one who is acquainted with 
the extant English translations knows that, valuable 
as they are, they leave much to be desired. I am quite 
conscious that the version which is now offered to the 
public is still very far from being adequate; yet I 
venture to hope that it may do something towards 
supplying an acknowledged want, and that it may be 
of some service to those who (whether they be scholars 
or not) wish to know what the greatest thinker of 
antiquity has to say upon a subject which is of such 
a nature that what a great man of any age says upon 
it is usually of more permanent value than what he 
says on any other subject. 

I have, of course, made free use of other trans- 



IV PBEFACB. 

lators and commentators, and wish here to make a 
full acknowledgment of my obligations. 

But I must more particularly express my thanks 
to my friends Mr. A. C. Bradley and Mr. J. Cook 
Wilson, the former of whom has been kind enough 
to read the whole of the proof sheets, and the latter 
a large portion of them. To both, and especially to 
the former, I am indebted for many valuable sug- 
gestions. But, as I have sometimes persisted in my 
own opinion in spite of their dissent, the reader must 
not hold them responsible for any of the errors he 
may detect. 

The notes perhaps require some apology; they 
may appear to be too many for footnotes to a 
translation, but they are certainly too few for a 
regular commentary, leaving without explanation 
many points that much need it. But if this transla- 
tion should meet with any favour, I purpose before 
long to follow it up with an Introduction, in which 
I shall hope to some extent to make good this de- 
ficiency. 

F. H. P. 

OxFOBD, February, 1881. 



PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION. 



to* 



This edition is substantially the same as the first, 
though a great many slight alterations have been 
made. 

I have to thank my reviewers in general, and in 
particular Mr. J. A. Stewart of Christ Church (who 
reviewed the first edition in Mind, July, 1881), for 
much kindly criticism and many valuable suggestions. 
Where their suggestions have not been adopted, I 
trust they will believe that my persistence is due 
neither to carelessness nor to unwillingness to learn, 
but to the fact that after full consideration I find 
myself unable to agree with them. 

An Introduction, promised in the Preface to the 
first edition, is, I regret to say, not yet finished ; but 
I still hope to publish it before long. 

I omitted in the first edition to state that I have 
in the main followed Bekker's text (Betlm, \%4t^^, ^csA 



VI PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION. 

that when I have departed from it I have generally 
notified the fact ; that the chapters and sections are 
those of Zell ; and that whenever I have inserted in 
the text explanatory words of my own, I have 
enclosed them in square brackets thus [ ]. 

F. H. P. 

Oxford, Februaryf 1884« 



NOTE TO THE THIRD EDITION. 



*C* 



In this edition a few clerical errors have been 
corrected, and the wording of one or two passages 
has been improved. No other change has been made. 



F. H. P. 



Plas HfeN, Cbiooteth, Nokth Wales, 
November, 1885. 



CONSPECTUS. 



aooK 

Of the good or the end I. 

Of moral yirtne in general IL 

Of the will ... ... ... ••• ••• HI. 1-6. 

Of the several moral Tirtaes and vice.s ... III. 6-€nd of V- 

Of the intellectual virtues VL 

Of forms of moral character other than virtue 

or vice VII. 1-10. 

First account of pleasure VII. 11-end. 

Of friendship or love VITI. and IX. 

Second account of pleasure X. 1-5. 

Conclusion ••• ••• X. 6-€nd. 



TABLE OF CONTENTS. 



to* 



BOOK t 

THE END. 

CHAP. PAOB 

1. In all he does man seeks some good as end or means ••• 1 

2. The end is the good ; our subject is this and its science, 

Jx OllVlCS ••• ••• .*•• ••• ••• ••• ••• ^ 

8. Exactness not permitted by subject, nor to be expected by 

student, who needs experience and training 3 

W 4. Men agree that the good is happiness, but differ as to what 
this is. We must reason from facts accepted without 

question by the man of trained character 5 

6. The good cannot be pleasure, as some hold, nor honour, nor 

VlxliUv ••• ••• ••• ••• «•• ••• ••• O 

6. Various arguments to show against the Platoni>ts that there 

cannot be one universal good: even if there were it 
would not help us here 8 

7. The good is the final end, and happiness is this. To find it 

we ask, What is man's function ? Eesulting definition 

of happiness 12 

3. This view harmonizes various current views 18 

9. Is happiness acquired, or the gift of Gods or chance? ... 22 

10. Can no man be called happy during life? 23 

11. Cannot the fortunes of survivors affect the dead ? 27 

12. Happiness as absolute end is above praise 28 

18. Division of the faculties and resulting division of the virtues 30 



TABLE OP CONTENTS. 



BOOK 11. 
MORAL VIRTUE. 

CHAP. PAGB 

1. Moral virtue is acquired by the repetition of the corre- 

sponding acts ... ... ..« ... ••• ••• 34 

2. These acts must be such as reason prescribes ; they cannot 

be defined exactly, but must be neither too much nor 

lOo iii/iie •.. ••• •.» ... •.* ••• ••• *^^ 

8. Virtue is in various ways concerned with pleasuie and 

pstiii ••• ••• ••• ••• ••• •• • ••• ••• 

4. The conditions of virtuous action as distinct from artistic 

production ••• ••• ... .*. ... ... ... 41 

6. Virtue not an emotion, nor a faculty, but a trained faculty 

or na di v ... ... .•« ••« ... ... ... *^ 

6. Viz. the habit of choosing the mean 43 

-7. This must be applied to the several virtues 48 

8. The two vicious extremes are opposed to one another and to 

the intermediate virtue ... 52 

9. The mean is hard to hit, and is a mutter of perception not 

of reasoning... ••• ... 55 



38 



BOOK III. 

Ohaptbbs 1-6. THE WILL. 

1. An act is involuntary when done (a) under compulsion, or . 

(6) through ignorance : (a) means not originated by doer, 
(6) means through ignorance of the circumstances: 
voluntary, then, means originated with knowledge of 
circumstances 58 

2. Purpose, a mode of will, means choice after deliberation ... 66 
8. « We deliberate on what we can do — not on ends, but means 68 

4. We wish for the end, the real or apparent good 72 

5. Virtue and vice are alike voluntary : our acts are our own ; 

for we are punished for them : ignorance is no excuse 
when due to negligence : if this be our character, we have 
made it by repeated acts : even bodily vices are blam- 
able when thus formed. We cannot plead that our 



TABLE OP CONTENTS. Xi 

CHAP. PAGI 

notion of good depends on our nature ; for (1) vice would 
still be as voluntary as virtue, (2) we help to make our- 

selves wDa« we are**« ••• ••• •«• ••• ••• /« 

Chapters 6-12. THE SEVERAL MOBAL VIBTUES 

AND VICES. 

6. Of courage and the opposite vices 80 

7. Of courage — continued 82 

8. Of courage improperly so called 85 

9. How courage involves both pain and pleasure 89 

10. Of temperance 91 

11. Of temperance — continued 93 

12. How profligacy is more voluntary than oowordice 96 



BOOK IV. 

THE BATHE— Continued, 

1. Of liberality ,..* ... 99 

2. Of magnificence 108 

^'^. Of high-mindedness ... 113 

4. Of a similar virtue in smaller matters 120 

5. Of gentleness 122 

6. Of agreeableness 125 

7. Of truthfulness 127 

8. Ofwittiness 131 

9. 0/ the feeling of shame 133 



BOOK V. 

THE SAWS^Concluded, JUSTICE. 

1. Preliminary. Two senses of justice distinguished. Of 

justice (1) = obedience to law, = complete virtue ... 136 

2. Of justice (2) = fairness, how related to justice (1). What 

is just in distribution distinguished from what is just 

in correction ... ... ... ... ... ••• 140 



XU TABLE OF CONTENTS. 

CHAP. PACK 

8. Of what is just in distribution, and its rule of geometrical 

proportion ... ... ... ... ... ... ... 144 

4. Of what is just in correction, and its rule of arithmetical 

proportion 147 

5. Simple requital is not identical with what is just, but pro- 

portionate requital is what is just in exchange ; and this 
is eflfected by means of money. We can now give a 
general definition of justice (2) 1 52 

6. (It is possible to act unjustly without being unjust.) That 

which is just in the strict sense is between citizens 
only, for it implies law 160 

7. It is in part natural, in part conventional 163 

8. The internal conditions of a just or unjust action, and of a 

just or unjust agent 165 

8. Sundry questions about doing and suffering injustice ... 169 

10. Of equity 174 

11. Can a man wrong himself ? 176 



BOOK VI. 

THE INTELLECTUAL VIRTUES. 

1. Must be studied because (a) reason prescribes the mean, 

(b) they are a part of human excellence. The intel- 
lect is (1 ) scientific, (2) calculative : we want the virtue 
oi eacu ••• •.• ... ... •.. ... ... loU 

2. The function of the intellect, both in practice and specula- 

tion, is to attain truth 182 

8. Of the five modes of attaining truth : (1) of demonstrative 

science of things unalterable ... ... 184 

4. Of knowledge of things alterable, viz. (2) of art in what we 

maK6 ••• ••• •*. •*. *•• ... ««« XoO 

5. And (3) of prudence in what we do, the virtue of the calcula- 

tive intellect 186 

6. (4} Of intuitive reason as the basis of demonstrative science 189 

7. (5) Of wisdom as the union of science and intuitive reason. 

Comparison of the two intellectual virtues, wisdom and 
prudence ... ... ... ... ... ... ... 190 

^ 8. Prudence compared with statesmanship and cither forms of 

knowledge ••• #•• •• •• ••• ••• 192 



TABLE OP CONTENTS. Xiu 

yCHAP. TAQW 

9. Of deliberation , ... 195 

''10. Of intelligence 198 

vll. Of judgment Of reason or intuitiye perception as the 

basis of the practical intellect 199 

13. Of the uses of wisdom and prudence. How prudence is 

related to cleverness 202 

J 18. How prudence is related to moral virtue ... ... ... 205 



BOOK VIL 

Chaptkbs 1-10. CHABACTERS OTHEB THAN 
VIBTUE AND VICE. 

1. Of continence and incontinence, heroic virtue and brutality. 

Of method. Statement of opinions about continence 208 

2. Statement of difficulties as to how one can know right and 

do wrong ... ... ... ... ... ... ... 210 

8. Solution : to know has many senses ; in what sense such a 

man knows ... ... ... ... ... ... ... 214 

4. Of incontinence in the strict and in the metaphorical sense 220 

5. Of incontinence in respect of brutal or morbid appetites ... 224 

6. Incontinence in anger less blamed than in appetite ... 227 

7. Incontinence yields to pleasure, softness to pain. Two 

kinds of incontinence, the hasty and the weak ... 230 

8. Incontinence compared with vice and viitue ... ... 23 

9. Continence and incontinence not identical with keeping 

and breaking a resolution 235 

10. Prudence is not, but cleverness is, compatible with in- 

continence ... ... ... ... ... _ ••• ..« 237 

Chaptebs 11-14. PLEASURE. 

11. Wo must now discuss pleasure. Opinions about it ... 239 

12. Answers to arguments against goodness of pleasure. 

Ambiguity of good and pleasant. Pleasure not a tran- 
sition, but unimpeded activity 240 

13. Pleasure is good, and the pleasure that consists in the 

highest activity is the good. All admit that happiness 

is pleasant. Bodily pleasures not the only pleasures 243 

14. Of the bodily pleasures* and the distinction between natur- 

ally and accidentally pleasant 246 




XIV TABLE OF OONTENXa 



BOOK VIII. 
FRIENDSHIP OB LOVE. 

CHAP. PAOB 

1. Uses of friendship. DifTereDces of opinion about it ... 251 

2. Three motives of friendship. Friendship defined 253 

8. Three kinds of friendship corresponding to the three 

motives. Perfect friendship is that whose motive is the 

^uuu ••» •*• ... ••• ««« .«. ... .«« ^do 

4. The others are imperfect copies of this 258 

5. Intercourse necessary to the maintenance of friendship ... 260 

6. Impossible to have many true friends 262 

7. Of friendship between unequal persons, and its rule of pro- 

portion. Limits within which this is possible 265 

8. Of loving and being loved 267 

9. Every society has its own form of friendship as of justice. 

All societies are summed up in civil society 269 

10. Of the three forms of constitution 271 

11. Of the corresponding forms of friendship 274 

12. Of the friendship of kinsmen and comrades 276 

18. Of the terms of interchange and quarrels hence arising in 

equal friendships 279 

14. Of the same in unequal friendships 283 



BOOK IX. 

FBIENDSHIP OB JjOYE—Contintied, 



1. Of the rule of proportion in dissimilar friendships ... 

2. Of the conflict of duties 

8. Of the dissolution of friendships 

4. A man's relation to his friend like his relation to himself 

5. Friendship and good-will 

6. Friendship and unanimity 

7. Why benefactors love more than they are loved 

8. In what sense it is right to love one's self ... 

9. Why a happy man needs friends 

10. Of the proper number of friends 

11. Friends needed both in prosperity and adversity 

12. Friendship is realized in living together 



••• 



286 
289 
292 
294 
297 
299 
300 
303 
307 
312 
314 
316 



TABLE OF CONTENTS. XV 



BOOK X 
Chapters 1-6. PLEASURR 

CHAP. PAOK 

1. Beasons for discussing pleasure 818 

2. Arguments of Eudoxus that pleasure is the good 819 

8. Argument that it is not a quality; that it is not deter- 
mined ; that it is a motion or coming into being. Plea- 
sures differ in kind 822 

4. Pleasure defined : its relation to activity 825 

5. Pleasures differ according to the activities. The standard 

is the good man ... ... 830 

Chapters 6-9. CONCLUSION. 

6. Happiness not amusement, but life 835 

7. Of the speculative life as happiness in the highest sense ... 837 

8. Of the practical life as happiness in a lower sense, and of 

the relation between the two. Prosperity, how far 
neecieu ... ... ... ... ..• ... ... o^x 

9. How is the end to be realized ? ... 846 



/ 



THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF 

AEISTOTLE. 



BOOK r. 

THE END. 

1 1. Evert art and every kind of inquiry, and like- aob**. 
wise every act "and purpose, seeins. to aim at some«»"w^ood 
good : and so it has been well said that the good is «>«an«. 
that at which everything aims. 

2 But a difference is observable Q*mong these aims or 
ends. What is aimed at is sometimes the exercise of 
a faculty, sometimes a certain result beyond that 
exercise. And where there is an end beyond the act, 
there the result is better than the exercise of the 
faculty. 

3 Now since there are many kinds of actions and 
many arts and sciences, it follows that there are many 
ends also ; e.g, health is the end of medicine, ships 
of shipbuilding, victory of the art of war, and wealth 
of economy. 

4 But when several of these are subordinated to 

B 



2 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. L 

some one art or science, — as the making of bridles and 
other trappings to the art of horsemanship, and this 
in turn, along with all else that the soldier does, to the 
art of war, and so on, — then the end of the master-art 
is always more desired than the ends of the subordinate 
arts, since these are pursued for its sake. And this is 5 
equally true whether the end in view be the mere 
exercise of a faculty or something beyond that, as in 
the above instances. 
send is 2. If then in what we do there be some end which i 
^S^t 18 we wish for on its own account, choosing all the others • 
tcience as mcaus to this, but not every end without exception 
*"' as a means to something else (for so we should go on 
ad infinitum, and desire would be left void and 
objectless), — ^this evidently will be the good or the 
best of aU things. 

And surely from a practical point of view it much 2 
concerns us to know this good ; for then, like archers 
shooting at a definite mark, we shall be more likely 
to attain what we want. 

If this be so, we must try to indicate roughly what 8 
it is, and first of aU to which of the arts or sciences it 
belongs. 

It would seem to belong to the supreme art or '4 
science, that one which most of all deserves the name 
of master-art or master-science. 

Now Politics* seems to answer to this description.. 6 

• To Aristotle Politics is a mncli wider term than to ns; it 
covers the whole field of hnman life, since man is essentially social 
(7f 6) ; it has to determine (1) what is the good ? — the question of 
this treatise (§ 9). — and (2) what can law do to promote this good ? — 
the question of the seqnel, which is speciallj called "The Politics :'' 
c/. X. 9. 



1, 5-8. 4.] THE END. 3 

For it prescribes which of the sciences a state needs, 
and which each man shall study, and up to what 
6 point ; and to it we see subordinated even the highest 
arts, such as economy, rhetoric, and the art of war. 

Since then it makes use of the other practical 
sciences, and since it further ordains what men are 
to do and from what to refrain, its end must include }• 
the ends of the others, and must be the proper good of /■ 
man. 

8 For though this good is the same for the individual 
and the state, yet the good of the state seems a grander 
and more perfect thing both to attain and to secure ; 
and glad as one would be to do this service for a 
single individual, to do it for a people and for a 
number of states is nobler and more divine. 

9 This then is the aim of the present inquiry, which 
is a sort of political inquiry.* 

1 • 3. We must be content if we can attain to so much EMetneu 
precision in our statement as the subject before us muted bjf 

, tuMtct nor 

admits of : for the same deeree of accuracy is no more ^ expeet4a 
to be expected in all kinds of reasoning than in all ^f^needt 
kinds of manufacture. <»«<« . 

2 Now what is noble and just (with which Politics 
deals) is so various and so uncertain, that some think 
these are merely conventional and not natural dis- 
tinctions. 

3 There is a similar uncertainty also about what is 
good, because good things often do people harm : men 
have before now been ruined by wealth, and have 
lost their lives through courage. 

4 Our subject, then, and our data being of this 

* i,e, oovers a part of the ground onl^ : see preceding note. 



^ t 

u 






4 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk. L 

nature^ we must be content if we can indicate the 
truth roughly and in outline, and if, in dealing with 
matters that are not amenable to immutable laws, and 
reasoning from premises that are but probable, wo 
can arrive at probable conclusions.* 

The reader, on his part, should take each of my 
statements in the same spirit ; for it is the mark of 
an educated man to require, in each kind of inquiry, 
just so much exactness as the subject admits of: it is 
equally absurd to accept probable reasoning from a 
mathematician, and to demand scientific proof from an 
\orator. 

But each man can form a judgment about what he 5 
. knows, and is called " a good judge " of that — of any 
special matter when he has received a special educa- 
tion therein, ''a good judge " (without any qualifying 
ly' epithet) when he has received a universal education. 
And hence a young man is not qualified to be a 
student of Politics; for he lacks experience of the 
' afiairs of life, which form the data and the subject- 
matter of Politica 

Further, since he is apt to be swayed by his 6 
feelings, he will derive no benefit from a study whose 
aim is not speculative but practical 

But in this respect young in character counts the 7 
same as young in years ; for the yoimg man's dis- 
qualification is not a matter of time, but is due to the 
fact that feeling rules his life and directs all his 
desires. Men of this character turn the knowledge 

• The expression tA &s iwl rh xoA^ ooyers both (1) what is gene- 
rally thongh not nniversallj tme, and (2) what is probable though 
aet certain* 



} aotioQs of the good or happiness, it 

mdge, aa wo reasonably may, Iroin their 

' 3 masses, who are the least refined, hold 

ire, ajid so accept the life of enjoyment 

B most conspicuous kinds of life are three : 

t enjoyment, the life of the statesman, and, 

B contemplative life. 

Binass of men show themselves utterly alaviali 

p preference for the life of brute beasts, but 

; receive consideration because many of 

1 high places have the tastes of Sardanapalus. 

■en of retinement with a practical turn prefer 

; for I suppose we may say that honour i^ the 

^ of the statesman's Ufe. 

f But this seeina too superficial to be the good we 

B seelcing : for it appears to depend upon those who 

pve rather than upon those who receive it ; while wo 

lave a presentiment that the good is something that^ 

I peculiarly a man's own and can scarce be taken 

[ away from him. 

Moreover^ these men seem to pursue honoiir in 
order that they may be assured of their own 
excellence, — at least, they wish to be honoured by 
men of sense, and by those who know them, and on 
tlis ground of their virtue or excellence. It is plain, 
ihen, that ia their view, at any rate, virtue or excellence 
6 is better than honour ; and perhaps we should takd 
this to be the end of the statesman's life, rather than 
honour. 

But virtue or excellence also appears too ii 
plete to be what we want ; for it seems that i 



6 NICOMACHEAN IJTHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. L 

it But we must hot omit to notice the distinction 6 

J-, that is drawn between the method of proceeding from 

ition your starting-points or principles, and the method of 

%ed working up to them. Plato used with fitness to raise 

this question, and to ask whether the right way ig 

from or to your starting-points, as in the race-course 

you may run from the judges to the boundary, or vice 

versa. 

Well, we must start from what is known. 
But "what is known" may mean two things: 
'* what IS known to us," which is one thing, or *' what ^ 
is known " simply, which is another. 

I think it is safe to say that we must start from 
what is known to its. 

And on this account nothing but a good moral 6 
training can qualify a man to study what is noble 
and just — in a word, to study questions of Politics. 
For the undemonstrated fact is here the starting- 
point, and if this undemonstrated fact be suf- 
ficiently evident to a man, he will not require a 
" reason why." Now the man who has had a good 
moral training either has already arrived at starting- 
points or principles of action, or will easily accept 
them when pointed out. But he who neither has them 
nor will accept them may hear what Hesiod says * — 

" The best is he who of himself doth know ; 
Good too is he who listens to the wise ; 
Bnt he who neither knows himself nor heeds 
The words of others, is a useless man." 

i 6. Let US now take up the discussion at the point i 

^nor from which we digressed. 

tfwr 

• « Works and Days," 291-295. 



4, 6-6, 6.] THE END. 7 

As to men's notions of the good or happiness, it 
seems (to judge, as we reasonably may, from their 

2 lives) that the masses, who are the least refined, hold 
it to be pleasure, and so accept the life of enjoyment 
as their ideal. 

For the most conspicuous kinds of life are three : 
this life of enjoyment, the life of the statesman, and, 
thirdly, the contemplative life. 

3 The mass of men show themselves utterly slavish 
in their preference for the life of brute beasts, but 
their views receive consideration because many of 
those in high places have the tastes of Sardanapalus. 

4 Men of refinement with a practical turn prefer'^ 
honour ; for I suppose we may say that honour is the 
aim of the statesman s life. 

But this seems too superficial to be the good we 
are seeking : for it appears to depend upon those who 
give rather than upon those who receive it ; while wo 
have a presentiment that the good is something that ^ 
is peculiarly a man's own and can scarce be taken 
away from him. 

5 Moreover, these men seem to pursue honour in 
order that they may be assured of their own 
excellence, — at least, they wish to be honoured by 
men of sense, and by those who know them, and on 
the ground of their virtue or excellence. It is plain, 
then, that in their view, at any rate, virtue or excellence 

6 is better than honour ; and perhaps we should take 
this to be the end of the statesman's life, rather than 
honour. 

But virtue or excellence also appears too income 
plete to be what we want; for it seems that a man 



I 



8 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OP AEIBTOTLE. [Bn. T. 

might have virtue and yet Tjo asleep or be inactive 
all Ills life, and, moreover, might meet with the 
greatest disasters and misfortunes ; and no one would 
maintain that such a man is happy, except for 
argument's sake. But we will not dwell on these 
matters now, for they are sufficiently discussed in the 
popular treatises. 

The third kind of life is the life of contemplation: 7 
we will treat of it further on." 

Aa for the money-making life, it is something 
quite contrary to nature ; and wealth evidently is not 
the good of which we are in search, for it is merely 
useful as a means to something else. So we might 
rather take pleasure and virtue or excellenco to he 
ends than wealth ; for they are chosen on their own 
account. But it seems that not even they are the 
end, though much breath has been wasted in attempts^ 
to show that they are. '^ 

!,m fl. Dismissing these views, then, we have now to 

u^in.i consider the "universal good," and to state the diffi- 
Mm cultics which it presents ; though such an inquiry is 
tunf- not a pleasant task in view of our friendship for the 
authors of the doctrine of ideas. But wo venture to 
think that this is tlie right course, and that in the 
interests of truth we ought to sacrifice even what 
is nearest to us, especially as we call ourselves philo- 
sophers. Both are dear to us, but it is a sacred duty 
to give the preference to truth. 

In the first place, the authors of this theory them- 
selves did not assert a common idea in the case of 
tilings of which one is prior to the other; and for this 
• CS. VI. 7, 12, and S. 7, 8. 



6, 7-6, 6.J THE END. 9 

reason they did not hold one common idea of numbers. 
Now the predicate good^ applied to substances and 
also to qualities and relations. But that which has 
independent existence, what we call "substance/* is 
logically prior to that which is relative ; for the latter 
is an offshoot as it were, or [in logical language] an 
accident of a thing or substance. So [by their own 
showing] there cannot be one common idea of these 
goods. 

8 Secondly, the term good is used in as many 
different ways as the term *' is " or " being ;" we apply 
the term to substances or independent existences, as 
God, reason ;, to qualities, as the virtues ; to quantity, 
as the moderate or due amount ; to relatives, as the 
useful ; to time, as opportunity ; to place, as habitation, 
and so on. It is evident, therefore, that the word good 
cannot stand for one and the same notion in all these 
various applications ; for if it did, the term could not 
be applied in all the categories, but in one only. 

4 Thirdly, if the notion were one, since there is but 
one science of all the things that come under one idea, 
there would be but one science of all goods ; but as it 
is, there are many sciences even of the goods that 
come under one category ; as, for instance, the science 
which deals with opportunity in war is strategy, but 
in disease is medicine; and the science of the due 
amount in the matter of food is medicine, but in the 
matter of exercise is the science of gymnastic. 

6 Fourthly, one might ask what they mean by the 
'' absolute : " in " arbsolute man " and " man " the word 
" man " has one and the same sense ; for in respect of 
manhood there will be no difference between them ; 



/ 



10 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk. I. 

and if, so, neither will there be any difference in 
respect of goodness between "absolute good" and 
"good." 

Fifthly, they do not make the good any more good 6 
by making it eternal ; a white thing that bsta a long 
while is no whiter than what lasts but a day. 

There seems to be more plausibility in the doctrine 7 
of the Pythagoreans, who [in their table of opposites] 
place the one on the same side with the good things 
[instead of reducing all goods to unity]; and even 
Speusippus * seems to follow them in this. 

However, these points may be reserved for another 8 
occasion ; but objection may be taken to what I have 
said on the ground that the Platonists do not speak 
in this way of all goods indiscriminately, but hold 
that those that are pursued and welcomed on their 
own account are called good by reference to one 
common form or type, while those things that tend to 
produce or preserve these goods, or to prevent their 
opposites, are called good only as means to these, and 
in a different sense. 

It is evident that there will thus be two classes of 9 
goods: one good in themselves, the other good as 
means to the former. Let us separate then from the 
things that are merely useful those that are good in 
themselves, and inquire if they are called good by 
reference to one common idea or type. 

Now what kind of things would one call "good K 
in themselves " ? 

Surely those things that we pursue even apart 
from their consequences, such as wisdom and sight 

* Plato's nephew and snccessor. 



6, 6-13.] THE END. 11 

and certain pleasures and certain honours; for 
although we sometimes pursue these things as means, 
no one could refuse to rank them among the things 
that are good in themselves. 

If these be excluded, nothing is good in itself 
except the idea ; and then the type or form will be 
meaningless.* 

Li If however, these are ranked among the things 
that are good in themselves, then it must be shown 
that the goodness of all of them can be defined in the 
same terms, as white has the same meaning wheu 
applied to snow and to white lead. 

But, in fact, we have to give a separate and 
different account of the goodness of honour and 
wis(lom and pleaSire. 

Good, then, is not a term that is applied to all these 
things alike in the same sense or with reference to 
one common idea or form. 

L2 But how then do these things come to be called 
good? for they do not appear to have received the 
same name by chance merely. Perhaps it is because 
they all proceed from one source, or all conduce to 
one end; or perhaps it is rather in virtue of some 
analogy, just as we call the reason the eye of the soul 
because it bears the same relation to it that the eye 
does to the body, and so on. 

L3 But we may dismiss these questions at present j 
for to discuss them |n detail belongs more properly to 
another branch of philosophy. 

And for the same reason we may dismiss the sven if i 

* For there is no meaning in a form which is a form of nothing, 
in a nniveraal whioh has no particulars under it. 



12 NIOOMACHEAN ETHICS OP ABISTOTLE. [Bk. t 

t* further consideration of the idea; for even granting 
uthere. that this term good, which is applied to all thess 
different things, has one and the same meaning 
throughout, or that there is an absolute good apart 
from these particulars, it is evident that this good 
•will not be anything that man can realize or attain : 
but it is a good of this kind that we are now 
seeking. 

It might, perhaps, be thought that it would never- 14 
theless be well to make ourselves acquainted with 
this imiversal good, with a view to the goods that are 
attainable and realizable. With this for a pattern, it 
may be said, we shall more readily discern our own 
good, and discerning achieve it 

There certainly is some plausibility in this argu- 15 
ment, but it seems to be at variance with the existing 
sciences ; for though they are all aiming at some good 
and striving to make up their deficiencies, they neglect 
to inquire about this universal good. And yet it is 
scarce likely that the professors of the several arts and 
sciences should not know, nor even look for, what 
would help them so much. 

And indeed I am at a loss to know how the weaver l( 
or the carpenter would be furthered in his art by a 
knowledge of the absolute good, or how a man would 
be rendered more able to heal the sick or to command 
an army by contemplation of the pure form or idea. 
For it seems to me that the physician does not even 
seek for health in this abstract way, but seeks for the 
health of man, or rather of some particular man, for it 

Ttr is individuals that he has to heaL 

■. «■ 

nod {9 7. Leaving these matters, then, let us return once i 



e, 14-7, 4] THE END. 13 

more to the question, what this good can be of which otefma 
we are in search. mmutk 

It seems to be different in different kinds of action 
and in different arts, — one thing in medicine and 
another in war, and so on. What then is the good in 
each of these cases ? Surely that for the sake of which 
all else is dona And that in medicine is health, in 
war is victory, in building is a house, — a different thing 
in each different case, but always, in whatever we do 
and in whatever we choose, the end. For it is always 
for the sake of the end that all else is done. 

If then there be one end of all that man does, this 
end wiU be the realizable good, — or these ends, if 
there be more than one. 

2 Our argument has thus come round by a different 
path to the same point as before.* This point we 
must try to explain more clearly. 

3 We see that there are many ends. But some of 
these are chosen only as means, as wealth, flutes, and 
the whole class of instruments. And so it is plain that 
not all ends are finaL 

But the best of all things must, we conceive, be 
something final. 

If then there be only one final end, this will be 
what we are seeking, — or if there be more than one, 
then the most final of them. 

4 Now that which is pursued as an end in itself is ^ 
more final than that which is pursued as means to 
something else, and that which is never chosen as 
means than that which is chosen both as an end in 
itself and as means, and that is strictly final which 



N 



14 NICOMAOHEAN ETHICS OP AEISTOTLE. [Bk. I. 



is always chosen as an end in itself and never as 
means. 

^ Happiness seems more than anything else to answer 5 
, to this description : for we always choose it for itself, 
^ and never for the sake of something else \ while honour 
and pleasure and reason, and all virtue or excellence, 
we choose partly indeed for themselves (for, apart jfrom 
any result, we should choose each of them), but partly 
also for the sake of happiness, supposing that they will 
help to make us happy. But no one chooses happiness 
for the sake of these things, or as a means to anything 
else at all. 

We seem to be led to the same conclusion when we 6 
start from the notion of self-sufficiency, 
y The final good is thought to be self-suiBcing [or 
^ all-sufficing]. In applying this term we do not regard 
a man as an individual leading a solitary life, but we 
also take account of parents, children, wife, and, in 
short, friends and fellow-citizens generally, since man 
y is naturally a social being. Some limit must indeed 7 
be set to this ; for if you go on to parents and descend- 
ants and friends of friends, you will never come to a 
stop. But this we will consider further on : for the 
present we will take self-sufficing- to mean what by 
itself makes life desirable and in want of nothing. 
And happiness is believed to answer to this descrip- 
tion. 

And further, happiness is believed to be the most 8 

/ desirable thing in the world, and that not merely as 

one among other good things : if it were merely one 

among other good things [so that other things could 

be added to it], it is plain that the addition of the least 



7, 6-13.] THE END. 15 

of other goods must make it more desirable ; for the 
addition becomes a surplus of good, and of two goods 
the greater is always more desirable. n 

Thus it seems that happiness is something final 
and self-sufficing, and is the end of all that man 
does. 

9 But perhaps the reader thinks that though no one jb jind u w 
will dispute the statement that happiness is the best man's 
thing in the world, yet a still more precise definition ^^ ^ 
of it is needed. 

O This will best be gained, I think, by asking, What 
is the function of man ? For as the gOQdneaajand the i^' 
excellence of a piper or a sculptor, or the practiser of 
any art, and generally of those who have any function 
or business to do, liesJnjbaJLfuiiQtiQn, so man*s good 
would seem to lie in his function, if he has one* 

Li But can we suppose that, while a carpenter and a 
cobbler has a function and a business of his own, man 
has no business and no function assigned him by 
nature ? Nay, surely as his several members, eye and 
hand and foot, plainly have each his own function, 
so we must suppose that man also has some function^--' 
over and above all these. 

L2 "What then is it? 

Life evidently he has in common even with the 
plants, but we want that which is peculiar to him. 
We must exclude, therefore, the life of mere nutrition 
and growth. 

Next to this comes the life of sense ; but this too 
he plainly shares with horses and cattle aniall kinds 
of animals. 

3 There remains then the life whereby he acts — the 




16 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. I, 

/-life of his rational nature,* with its two sides or 
divisions, one rational as obeying reason, the other 
rational as having and exercising reason. 

But as this expression is ambiguous,"!* we must be 
understood to mean thereby the life that consists in 
the exercise of the faculties ; for this seems to be more 
properly entitled to the name. 

The function of man, then, is exercise of his vital l 



K.-I faculties [or soul] on one side in obedience to reason, 
\^ and on the other side with reason. 

But what is called the function of a man of any 
profession and the function of a man who is good 
in that profession are generically the same, cgr. of a 
harper and of a good harper ; and this holds in all 
cases without exception, only that in the case of the 
latter his superior excellence at his work is added ; for 
we say a harper's function is to harp, and a good 
harper's to harp well 

Man's function then being, as we say, a kind of life 
— ^that is to say, exercise of his faculties and action of 
various kinds with reason — ^the good man's function 
is to do this well and beautifully [or nobly]. 

But the function of anything is done well when it U 
is done in accordance with the proper excellence of 
that thing. 
na»iLinig Putting all this together, then, we find that the 

• Tpcacrticfi TI5 rod \6yov ^xo»^os. Aristotle frequently uses the 
terms ir/>a{is, irpaKr6sy TrpaKrtK6s in this wide sense, covering all that 
man does, t.e. all that part of man's life that is within the control 
of his will, or that is consoionslj directed to an end, including there* 
fore specnlation as well as action. 

f For it might mean either the mere possession of the vital 
faculties, or their exercise* 



7, 14-19J THE END. 17 



good of man is exercise of his faculties in accordance d^nindnt^ 
with excellence or virtue, or, if there be more than j^- 
one, in accordance "with the best and most complete Vv 
virtue.* 

16 But there must also be a full term of years for? 
this exercise ; f for one swallow or one fine day does j^ 
not make a spring, nor does one day or any small 
space of time make a blessed or happy man. 

L7 This, then, may be taken as a rough outline of the 
good ; for this, I think, is the proper method, — first to 
sketch the outline, and then to fill in the details. But 
it would seem that, the outline once fairly drawn, any 
one can carry on the work and fit in the several items 
which time reveals to us or helps us to find. And this 
indeed is the way in which the arts and sciences have 
grown ; for it requires no extraordinary genius to fill 
up the gaps. 

8 We must bear in mind, however, what was said 
above, and not demand the same de^ee of accuracy in 
all branches of study, but in each case so much as the 
subject-matter admits of and as is proper to that kind 

L9 of inquiry. The carpenter and the geometer both look 
for the right angle, but in different ways : the former 
only wants such an approximation to it as his work 
requires, but the latter wants to know what con'» 
stitutes a right angle, or what is its special quality ; 
his aim is to find out the truth. And so in other cases 
we must follow the same course, lest we spend more 

* This '' best and most complete excellence or yirtne *' is the 
trained facnltj for philosophic specolation, and the contemplative life 
is man's highest happiness. Cf, X. 7, 1. 

t Cf. 9, 11. 

C 



18 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OP ABISTOTLE. [ftc. I. 

time on what is immaterial than on the real business 
in hand. 

Nor must we in all cases alike demand the reason SO 
why ; sometimes it is enough if the undemonstriited 
fact be fairly pointed out, as in the case of the start- 
ing-points or principles of a science. Undemonstrated 
facts always form the first step or starting-point of 
a science ; and these starting-points or principles are fl 
arrived at some in one way, some in another — some 
by induction, others by perception, others again by ' 
some kind of training. But in each case we must try 
to apprehend them in the proper way, and do our 
best to define them clearly ; for they have great in- 
fluence upon the subsequent course of an inquiry. 
A good start is more than half the race, I think, and 
our starting-point or principle, once found, clears up 
a number of our diflSculties. 
^uview 8. We must not be satisfied, then, with examining 1 

iarmont«et .1.1.. . . • • i /• i • 

uriom this startmg-pomt or prmciple of ours as a conclusion 

•iewf. from our data, but must also view it in its relation 

to current opinions on the subject ; for all experience 

harmonizes with a true principle, but a false one is 

soon found to be incompatible with the facts. 

Now, good things have been divided into three s 

. /classes, external goods on the one hand, and on the 

^ other goods of the soul and goods of the body ; and 

the goods of the soul are commonly said to be 

goods in the fullest sense, and more good than any 

other. ,^ 9f 

But " actions and exercises of the vital faculties or 
soul " may be said to be *' of the soul." So our account 
is confirmed by this opinion, which is both of long 



7, 20-8, 9.] THE END. 19 

standing and approved by all who busy themselves 
with philosophy, v 

8 But, indeed, we secure the support of this opinion 
by the mere statement that certain actions and 
exercises are the end; for this implies that it is to 
be ranked among the goods of the soul, and not 
among external goods. 

4 Our account, again, is in harmony with the com- 
mon saying that the happy man lives well and does 
well ; for we may say that happiness, according to us, 
is a living well and doing well. 

5 And, indeed, aU the characteristics that men expect 
to find in happiness seem to belong to happiness as 
we define it. 

6 Some hold it to be virtue or excellence, some 
prudence, others a kind of wisdom ; others, again, hold 
it to be all or some of these, with the addition of 
pleasure, either as an ingredient or as a necessary, 
accompaniment; and some even include external 
prosperity in their account of it. 

7 Now, some of these views have the support of 
many voices and of old authority; others have few 
voices, but those of weight ; but it is probable that 
neither the one side nor the other is entirely wrong, 
but that in some one point at least, if not in most, 
they are both right. 

8 First, then, the view that happiness is excellence 
or a kind of excellence harmonizes with our account ; 
for "exercise of faculties in accordance with excel- 
lence " belongs to excellence. 

9 But I think we may say that it makes no small 
difference whether the good be conceived as the mere 



20 NIOOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLB. [Bk. I. 

. possession of something, or as its use — as a mere habit 
I or trained faculty, or as the exercise of that faculty. 
For the habit or faculty may be present, and yet issue 
in no good result, as when a man is asleep, or in any 
other way hindered jfrom his function ; but with its 
exercise this is not possible, for it must show itself 
in acts and in good acts. And as at the Olympic 
games it is not the fairest and strongest who receive 
the crown, but those who contend (for among these 
are the victors), so in life, too, the winners are those 
1^ who not only have all the excellences, but manifg^t 
these in deed. 

And, further, the life of these men is in itself 10 
pleasant. For pleasure is an affection of the soid, 
and each man takes pleasure in that which he is said 
to love, — ^he who loves horses in horses, he who loves 
sight-seeing in sight-seeing, and in the same way he 
who loves justice in acts of justice, and generally the 
lover of excellence or virtue in virtuous acts or the 
manifestation of excellence. 

And while with most men there is a perpetual 11 
conflict between the several things in which they find 
pleasure, since these are not naturally pleasant, those 
1 who love what is noble take pleasure in that which 
is naturally pleasant. For the manifestations of ex- 
cellence are naturally pleasant, so that they are both 
pleasant to them and pleasant in themselves. 

Their life, then, does not need pleasure to be added II 
to it as an appendage, but contains pleasure in itself. 
Indeed, in addition to what we have said, a man 
is not good at all unless he takes pleasure in noble 
deeds. No one would call a man just who did not 



I- 



v-> 



8, 10-17.] THE END. 21 

take pleasure in doing justice, nor generous who took 
no pleasure in acts of generosity, and so on. 

L3 If this be so, the manifestations of excellence will 
be pleasant in themselves. But they are also both 
good and noble, and that in the highest degree — at 
least, if the good man's judgment about them is rights 
for this is his judgment. 

L4 Happiness, then, is at once the best and noblest} ^ r 
and pleasantest thing in the world, and these are not/ 
separated, as the Delian inscription would have then» 
to be : — 

« What is most jast is noblest, health is best, 
Pleasantest is to get your heart's desire/' 

For all these characteristics are united in the best 
exercises of our faculties ; and these, or some one of 
them that is better than all the others, we identify 
with happiness. 

15 But nevertheless happiness plainly requires ex- 
ternal goods too, as we said ; for it is impossible, or 
at least not easy, to act nobly without some furniture 
of fortune. There are many things that can only be *^ 
done through instruments, so to speak, such as friends 

L6 and wealth and political influence : and there are some 
things whose absence takes the bloom off our happi- 
ness, as good birth, the blessing of children, personal 
beauty ; for a man is not very likely to be happy if 
h'e is very ugly in person, or of low birth, or alone in 
the world, or childless, and perhaps still less if he has 
worthless children or friends, or has lost good ones 
that he had. 

.7 As we said, then, happiness seems to stand in need 
of this kind of prosperity ] and so some identify it 



22 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk. I. 

with good fortune, just as others identify it with 
excellence. 
rthappinesM 9. This has led people to ask whether happiness i 

lequired, or "iiv ^ 

^^Jl^^ l/^ attained by learning, or the formation of habits, or 
\f chancer any other kind of training, or comes by some divine 
dispensation or even by chaiice. 

Well, if the Gods do give gifts to men, happiness 2 
is likely to be among the nimiber, more likely, indeed, 
than anything else, in proportion as it is better than 
all other human things. 

This belongs more properly to another branch of in- 3 
quiry ; but we may say that even if it is not heaven- 
^ sent, but comes as a consequence of virtue or some 
kind of learning or training, still it seems to be one 
of the most divine things in the world ; for the prize 
and aim of virtue would appear to be better than 
anything else and something divine and blessed. 

Again, if it is thus acquired it will be widely i 
accessible; for it will then be in the power of all 
except those who have lost the capacity for excellence 
to acquire it by study and diligence. 

And if it be better that men should attain happi* 5 
ness in this way rather than by chance, it is reasonable 
to suppose that it is so, since in the sphere of nature 
all things are arranged in the best possible way, and 
likewise in the sphere of art, and of each mode of 6 
causation, and most of all in the sphere of the noblest 
mode of causation. And indeed it would be too 
absurd to leave what is noblest and fairest to the 
dispensation of chance. 

But our definition itself clears up the difficulty;* 7 

* C/.8 ^ras 7, 21. 



9, 1-10, 2.] THE END. 23 

for happiness was defined as a certain kind of exercise 
of the vital faculties in accordance with excellence or 
virtue. And of the remaining goods [other than goods 
of the soul], some must be present as necessary con- 
ditions, while others are aids and useful instruments 

8 to happiness. And this agrees with what we said at 
starting. We then laid down that the end of the art i- — 
political is the best of all ends ; but the chief business 

of that art is to make the citizens of a certain character 

9 — that is, good and apt to do what is noble. It is not ,^ 
without reason, then, that we do not call an ox, or a 
horse, or any brute happy ; for none of them is able 
to share in this kind of activity. ^ . 

10 For the same reason also a child is not happy ;\\ ]\\l 
he is as yet, because of his age, unable to do such " -^ 
things. If we ever call a child happy, it is because V 
we hope he will do them. For, as we said, happi- 
ness requires not only perfect excellence or virtue, 

Li but also a full term of years for its exercise. For 
our circumstances are liable to many changes and 
to all sorts of chances, and it is possible that he 
who is now most prosperous will in his old age meet 
with great disasters, as is told of Priam in the 
tales of the heroes; and a man who is thus used 
by fortune and comes to a miserable end cannot be 
called happy. 

1 10. Are we, then, to call no man happy as long as £*"'tj^" 
he lives, but to wait for the end, as Solon said ? *«iw , 

2 And, supposing we have to allow this, do we mean "" 
that he actually is happy after he is dead ? Surely 
that is absurd, especially for us who say that happi- 
ness is a kind of activity or life. 



24 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OP ARISTOTLE. [Bk. L 

But if we do not call the dead fnan happy, and if 3 
Solon meant not this, but that only then could we 
safely apply the term to a man, as being now beyond 
the reach of evil and calamity, then here too we 
find some ground for objection. For it is thought 
that both good and evU may in some sort befall a 
dead man (just as they may befall a living man, 
although he is unconscious of them), e.g, honours 
rendered to him, or the reverse of these, and again the 
prosperity or the misfortune of his children and all 
his descendants. 

But this, too, has its difficulties ; for after a man 4 
has lived happily to a good old age, and ended as he 
lived, it is possible that many changes may befall him 
in the persons of his descendants, and that some of 
them may turn out good and meet with the good 
fortune they deserve, and others the reverse. It ia» 
evident too that the degree in which the descendants 
are related to their ancestors may vary to any extent. 
And it would be a strange thing if the dead man were 5 
to change with these changes and become happy and 
miserable by turns. But it woidd also be strange to 
suppose that the dead are not affected at all, even for 
a limited time, by the fortunes of their posterity. 

But let us return to our former question ; for its 6 
solution wiQ, perhaps, clear up this other difficulty. 

The saying of Solon may mean that we ought to 7 
look for the end and then call a man happy, not 
because he now is, but because he once was happy. 

But surely it is strange that when he is happy 
we should refuse to say what is true of him, because 
we do not like to apply the term to living men in view 



10, 3-11.] THE END. 25 

of the changes to which they are liable, and because we 

. hold happiness to be something that endures and is 

little liable to change, while the fortunes of one and 

8 the same man often undergo many revolutions : for, it 
is argued, it is plain that, if we follow the changes of 
fortune, we shall call the same man happy and miserable > 
many times over, making the happy man "a sort of 
chameleon and one who rests on no sound foundation." 

9 We reply that it cannot be right thus to follow 
fortune. For it is not in this that our weal or woo 
lies ; but, as we said, though the life of man needs 
these gifts of fortune, yet it is the excellent employ- 

, ment of his powers that constitutes his happiness, as A~ 
the reverse of this constitutes his misery. 

.0 But the discussion of this difficulty leads to a 
further confirmation of our account. For nothing 
human is so constant as the excellent exer dse of our ^ 
faculties. The sciences themselves seem to be less 
abiding. And the highest of these exercises * are the 
most abiding, because the happy are occupied with 
them most of all and most continuously (for this seems 
to be the reason why we do not forget how to do 
them t). 

Li The happy man, then, as we define him, will have 
this required property of permanence, and all through 
life will preserve his character ; for he will be occupied' 
continually, or with the least possible interruption, in 

* Tlie ** highest exercise of onr fisicuUies " is, of coarse, philo- 
sophic contemplation, as above, I. 7, 15 ; cf. X. 7, 1. 

f We may forget scientific truths that we have known more 
easily than we lose the habit of scientific thinking or of virtaoua 
action; cf, X. 7, 2j VI. 6, 8. 



26 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OP ARISTOTLE. [Bk, I. 

excellent deeds and excellent speculations ; and, what- 
ever his fortune be, he will take it in the noblest 
fashion, and bear himself always and in all things 
suitably, since he is truly good and " foursquare with- 
out a flaw." 

But the dispensations of fortune are many, some li 
great, some small. The small ones, whether good or 
evil, plainly are of no weight in the scale ; but the 
great ones, when numerous, will make life happier if 
they be good ; for they help to give a grace to life 
themselves, and their use is noble and good ; but, if 
they be evil, will enfeeble and spoil happiness ; for 
they bring pain, and often impede the exercise of our 
faculties. 

But nevertheless true worth shines out even here, 
in the calm endurance of many great misfortunes, not 
through insensibility, but through nobility and great- 
ness of soul. And if it is what man does that deter- 13 
mines the character of his life, as we said, then no 
happy man will become miserable ^ for he will never 
do what is hateful and base. For we hold that the 
man who is truly good and wise will bear with dignity 
whatever fortune sends, and will always make the 
best of his circumstances, as a good general will turn 
the forces at his command to the best account, and a 
good shoemaker will make the best shoe that can be 
made out of a given piece of leather, and so on with 
all other crafts. 

If this be so, the happy man will never become u 
V miserable, though he will not be truly happy if he 
meets with the fate of Priam. 

But yet he is not unstable and lightly changed : he 



/ 



10, 12-11, 8.1 THE END. 27 

will not be moved from his happiness easily, nor by any 
ordinary misfortunes, but only by many heavy ones ; 
and after such, he will not recover his happiness again 
in a short time, but if at all, only in a considerable 
period, which has a certain completeness, and in which 
he attains to great and noble things. 
5 We shall meet all objections, then, if we say thatV 
a happy man is "one who exercises his faculties in ^ 
accordance with perfect excellence, being duly fur- 
nished with external goods, not for any chance time, 
but for a full term of years : " to which perhaps we 
shoidd add, " and who shall continue to live so, and 
shall die as he lived," since the future is veiled to us, 
but happiness we take to be the end and in all ways 
perfectly final or complete. 

If this be so, we may say that those living men are 
blessed or perfectly happy who both have and shall 
continue to have these characteristics, but happy as 
men only. 

1 11. Passing now from this question to that of the oannoia 
fortunes of descendants and of friends generally, the *^I^^* 
doctrine that they do not affect the departed at all *»<*' 
seems too cold and too much opposed to popular 

2 opinion. But as the things that happen to them are 
many and differ in all sorts of ways, and some come 
home to them more and some less, so that to discuss 
them all separately would be a long, indeed an end- 

. less task, it will perhaps be enough to speak of them / 
in general terms and in outline merely. 

3 Now, as of the misfortunes that happen to a man's 
self, some have a certain weight and influence on his 
life, while others are of less moment, so is it also with 



28 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. L 

what happens to any of his friends. And, again, it 4 
always makes much more difference whether those 
who are affected by an occurrence are alive or dead 
than it does whether a terrible crime in a tragedy be 
enacted on the stage or merely supposed to have 
already taken place. We must therefore take these 6 
differences into account, and still more, perhaps, the 
^/ \ fact that it is a doubtful question whether the dead 
■ are at all accessible to good and ill. For it appears 
from what has been said that even if anything, whether 
good or evil, does come home to them, yet it is some- 
thing unsubstantial and slight to them if not in itself; 
or if not that, yet at any rate its influence is not of 
that magnitude or nature that it can make happy 
those who are not, or take away their happiness from 
those that are. 

It seems then — to conclude — that the prosperity, 6 
and likewise the adversity, of friends does affect the 
y dead, but not in such a way or to such an extent as to 
make the happy unhappy, or to do anything of the 
kind. 
ipr«n«««a» 12. These points being settled, we may now inquire 1 
<»^ whether happiness is to be ranked among the goods 
that we praise, or rather among those that we revere ; 
for it is plainly not a mere potentiality, but an actual 
good. 

What we praise seems always to be praised 2 
as being of a certain quality and having a certain 
relation to something. For instance, we praise the 
just and the courageous man, and generally the good 
man, and excellence or virtue, because of what they do 
or produce ; and we praise also the strong or the swift- 



11, 4-12, 7.1 THE END. 29 

footed man, and so on, because he has a certain gift 
or faculty in relation to some good and admirable 
thing. 

3 This is evident if we consider the praises bestowed 
on the Gods. These appear ridiculous, because they 
imply a reference to a human standard; and this 
necessarily happens, because all praise, as we said, 
involves a reference to some standard. 

4 If, then, praise be proper to such things as we 
mentioned, it is evident that to the best things is due, 
not praise, but something greater and better, as our 
usage shows ; for the Gods we call blessed and happy, 
and " blessed " is the term we apply to the most god- 
like men. 

And so with good things: no one praises happiness 
a^ he praises justice, but calls it blessed, as something 
better and more divine. 
6 On these groimds Eudoxus is thought to have 
based a strong argument for the claims of pleasure to 
the first prize : for he maintained that the fact that it 
is not praised, though it is a good thing, shows that it. 
is higher than the goods we praise, as God and the 
good are higher ; for these are the standards by refer- 

6 ence to which we judge all other things, — ^giving praise 
to excellence or virtue, since it makes us apt to do 
what is noble, and passing encomiujos on the results 
of virtue, whether these be bodily or psychical. 

7 But to refine on these points belongs more properly 
to those who have made a study of the subject of 
encomiums ; for us it is plain from what has been said 
that happiness is one of the goods which we revere 
and count as final 



rtiut. 



30 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLB. [Bk. L 

• 

And this further seems to follow from the fact that 8 
it is a starting-point or principle : for everything "w^ 
do is always done for its sake ; hut the principle and 
cause of all good we hold to be something divine and 
^ worthy of reverence. 
ivttionqf 13. Since happiness is an exercise of the vital 1 
Id result- facultics in accordance with perfect virtue or excel- 
^tj«_ lence, we will now inquire about virtue or excellence; 
for this will probably help us in our inquiry about 
happiness. 

And indeed the true statesman seems to be espe- s 
^ ciaUy concerned with virtue, for he wishes to make 
the citizens good and obedient to the laws. Of this s 
we have an example in the Cretan and the Lacedae- 
monian lawgivers, and any others who have resembled 
them. But if the inquiry belongs to Politics or the 4 
science of the state, it is plain that it will be in ac- 
cordance with our original purpose to pursue it. 

The virtue or excellence that we are to consider is, | 
of course, the excellence of man ; for it is the good of 
man and the happiness of man that we stai*ted to 
seek. And by the excellence of man I mean excel- 6 
4ence not of body, but of soid ; for hagmness we take 
» /^ to be an activity of the sojo l. 

If this be so, then it is evident that the statesman 7 
must have some knowledge of the soid, just as the 
man who is to heal the eye or the whole body must 
have some knowledge of them, and that the more in 
proportion as the science of the state is higher and 
better than medicine. But all educated physicians 
take much pains to know about the body. 

As statesmen [or students of Politics], then, we 8 



12, 8-13, IS.] DIVISION OF THE FACULTIES. 81 

must inquire into the nature of the soul, but in so 
doing we must keep our special purpose in view and »^ 
go only so far as that requires ; for to go into minuter 
detail would be too laborious for the present under-^ 
taking. 

9 Now, there are certain points which are stated with 
sufficient precision even in the popular accounts of 
the soul, and these we will adopt. 

For instance, they distinguish an irrational and 
a rational part. 

LO Whether these are separated as are the parts of the 
body or any divisible thing, or whether they are only 
distinguishable in thought but in fact inseparable, like 
concave and convex in the circumference of a circle^ 
makes no difference for our present purpose. 

Ll Of the irrational part, again, one division seems to 
be common to all things that live, and to be possessed 
by plants — I mean that which causes nutrition and 
growth ; for we must assume that all things that take 
nourishment have a faculty of this kind, even when 
they are embryos, and have the same faculty when 
they are full grown; at least, this is more reasonable 
than to suppose that they then have a different one. 

12 The excellence of this facidty, then, is plainly one 
that man shares with other beings, and not specificaUy 
human. ^ 

And this is confirmed by the fact that this part of 
the soul, or this faculty, is thought to be most active 
in sleep, while the distinction between the good and 
the bad man shows itself least in sleep — ^whence 
the saying that for half their lives there is no differ- 

18 ence between the happy and the miserable. This 



32 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLB. [Bk. I. 

indeed is what we should expect; for sleep is the 
cessation of the soul from those functions in respect of 
which it is called good or bad, except in so far as 
i the motions of the body may sometimes make their 
way in, and give occasion to dreams which are better 
/ in the good man than in ordinary people. 

However, we need not pursue this further, and may 14 
dismiss the nutritive principle, since it has no place in 
the excellence of man. 

But there seems to be another vital principle that IS 
is irrational, and yet in some way partakes of reason. 
In the case of the continent and of the incontinent 
man alike we praise the reason or the rational part, 
for it exhorts them rightly and urges them to do what 
is best ; but there is plainly present in them another 
principle besidesj^e^^iational,. one, which fights and 
struggles against the reason."" For just as a paralyzed U 
limb, when you will to move it to the right, moves on 
the contrary to the left, so is it with the soul ; the in- 
continent man's impulses run counter to his reason. 
Only whereas we see the refractory member in the ease 
of the body, we do not see it in the case of the souL 
But we must nevertheless, I think, hold that in the 
sold too there is something beside the reason, which 
opposes and runs counter to it (though in what sense 
it is distinct from the reason does not matter here). 

It seems, however, to partake of reason also, as we 1 
said : at least, in the continent man it submits to the 
reason; while in the temperate and courageous man 
we may say it is still more obedient ; for in him it is 
altogether in harmony with the reason. 

The irrational part, then, it appears, is twofold. 1 



13, 14-20.] DIVISION OP THE VIRTUEa 33 

There is the vegatfttijifiJkcuUy, which has no share of 
reason ; and the faculty of appetite or of desire in Y 
general, which partakes of reason in a manner — that 
is, in so far aa it listens to reason and submits to its . 

sway. Bub when we say " partakes of reason " or ^ 
" listens to reason," we mean this in the sense in which i 
■we talk of " listening to reason " from parents or \ 
friends, not in the sense in which we talk of listen- 
ing to reason from mathematicians. 

Further, all advice and all rebuke and exhortation 
testifies that the iiTational part is in some way 
amenable to reason. 
9 If then we like to say that this part, too, has a\ 
share of reason, the rational part also will have two I 
divisions : one rational in the strict sense as possessing / 1, 
reason in itself, the other rational aa listening to reason/ 
as a man listens to his father. 

Now", on this division of the faculties is based tho 
division of excellence; for we speak of intellectual 
excellences and of moral excellences ; wisdom and 
understanding and prudence we call intellectual, 
liberality and temperance we call moral virtues or 
excellencea When we are speaking of a man's moral 
character we do not say that he is wise or intelligent, 
but that he is gentle or temperate. But we praise 
the wise man, too, for his habit of mind or trained ^^ 
faculty ; and a habit or trained faculty that is praise- 
worthy is what we call an excellence or virtue. . 



BOOK n 

MORAL VIRTUE. 

Moral virtuei 1. EXCELLENCE, then, being of these two kindS; in- 1 
b/SS*^- tellectual and moral, intellectual excellence owes its 
riS^'^^irth and growth mainly to instruction, and so re- 
^'^ ' quires time and experience, while moral excellence 
is the residt of habit or custom (iOog), and has accord- 
ingly in our language received a name formed by a 
slight change from iOog* 

From this it is plain that none of the moral excd- 1 
lences or virtues is implanted in us by nature; for 
that which is by nature cannot be altered by training. 
For instance, a stone naturally tends to fiall down- 
wards, and you could not train it to rise upw^ards, 
though you tried to do so by throwing it up ten 
thousand times, nor could you train fire to move 
downwards, nor accustom anything which naturally 
behaves in one way to behave in any other way. 

The virtues,! then, come neither by nature nor. I 

* tdos, cnstom ; ^Oos, character ; ^0<k^ aper^ moral ezceUence : ire 
have no Bimilar sequence, bnt the Latin mos, mores, from which 
** morality ** comes, covers both Udos and ^6os. 

t It is with the moral virtues that this and the three following 
books are exclusively concerned, the discnssion of the intelleotiud 
virtues being postponed to Book VI. iperai is often nsed in these 
books, withoat any epithet, for " moral virtneS|" and perhaps ia go 
used here. 



1, 1-6.] MOBAL VIBTUE. 35 

against nature, but nature gives the capacity for /<" 
acquiring them, and this is developed by training. 

4 Again, where we do things by nature we get the 
power first, and put this power forth in act afterwards : 
as we plainly see in the case of the senses ; for it is ^ 
not by constantly seeing and hearing that we acquire 
those faculties, but, on the contrary, we had the power 
first and then used it, instead of acquiring the power 
by the use. But the virtues we acquire by doing the 
acts, as is the case with the arts too. We learn an art 
by doing that which we wish to do when we have 
learned it; we become builders by building, and 
harpers by harping. And so by doing just acts wo 
become just, and by doing acts of temperance and 
courage we become temperate and courageous. 

5 This is attested, too, by what occurs in states ; for 
the legislators make their citizens good by training \il^ 
i.e. this is the wish of all legislators, and those who 

do not succeed in this miss their aim, and it is this 
that distinguishes a good from a bad constitution. 

6 Again, both virtues and vices result from and 
are formed by the same acts in which they manifest 
themselves, as is the case with the arts also. It is by 
harping that good harpers and bad harpers alike are 
produced : and so with builders and the rest ; by 
building well they will become good builders, and bad 

7 builders by building badly. Indeed, if it were not so, 
they would not want anybody to teach them, but 
would all be bom either good or bad at their trades. 
And it is just the same with the virtues also. It is 
by our conduct in our intercourse with other men 
that we become just or unjust, and by acting in cir- 



36 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OP AEISTOTLE. [Bk. IL 

cumstances of danger, and training ourselves to feel 
fear or confidence, that we become courageous or 
cowardly. So, too, with our animal appetites and the 
passion of anger; for by behaving in this way or in 
that on the occasions with which these passions are 
concerned, some become temperate and gentle, and 
others profligate and ill-tempered. In a word, the 
several habits or characters are formed by the same 
kind of acts as those which they produce. 

Hence we ought to make sure that our acts be of 8 
a certain kind ; for the resulting character varies as 
they vary. It makes no small diflference, therefore, 
whether a man be trained from his youth up in this 
way or in that, but a great difference, or rather all 
the difference. 
fiaeadt 2. But our prcscut inquiry has not, like the rest, 1 

t reason a merely speculative aim ; we are not inquiring merely 
i^^n'!6« in order to know what excellence or virtue is, biit in ' 
\actiy,hut order to become good; for otherwise it would profit 
either too US nothing. Wc must ask therefore about these 

\uch nor 

Hfiuue. acts, and see of what kind they are to be; for, as 
we said, it is they that determine our habits or 
character. 

First of all, then, that they must be in accordance 2 
with right reason is a common characteristic of them, 
which we shall here take for granted, reserving for 
future discussion * the question what this right reason 
is, and how it is related to the other excellences. 

But let it be understood, before we go on, that all 8 
reasoning on matters of practice must be in outline 
merely, and not scientifically exact : for, as we said at 

» In Book VI. 



/ 



I, 8-2, 7J MOEAL VntTUB. 37 

starting, the kind of reasoning to be demanded varies 
with the subject in hand; and in practical matters 
and questions of expediency there are no invariable 
laws, any more than in questions of health. 
i And if our general conclusions are thus inexact, 
still more inexact is all reasoning about particular 
cases ; for these fall under no system of scientifically 
established rules or traditional maxims, but the agent 
must always consider for himself what the special 
occasion requires, just as in medicine or navi- 
gation. 

5 But though this is the case we must try to render 
what help we can. 

6 First of all, then, we must observe that, in matters 
of this sort, to fall short and to exceed are alike fataL 
This is plain (to illustrate what we cannot see by 
what we can see) in the case of strength and health. 
Too much and too little exercise alike destroy strength, 
and to take too much meat and drink, or to take too 
little, is equally ruinous to health, but the fitting 
amount produces and increases and preserves them. i. y 

7 Just so, then, is it with temperance also, and courage, ^ 
and the other virtues. The man who shuns and 
fears everything and never makes a stand, becomes 
a coward; while the man who fears nothing at all; 
but will face anything, becomes foolhardy. So, too, 
the man who takes his fill of any kind of pleasure,^ 
and abstains from none, is a profligate, but the man 
who shuns all (like him whom we call a " boor ") is 
devoid of sensibility.* For temperance and courage 

» These two, the " boor " (AypoT/cos) and he who lacks sensibility 
{}uf9!iaBii^'ros\ are afterwards distinguished : (/. II. 7, 8 and 13* 



38 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OP ARISTOTLE. [Bk. IL 

are destroyed both by excess and defect, but pre- 
served by moderation. 

But habits or types of character are not only pro- 8 
duced and preserved and destroyed by the same occa- 
sions and the same means, but they will also manifest 
themselves in the same circumstances. This is the 
case with palpable things like strength. Strength is 
produced by taking plenty of nourishment and doing 
plenty of hard work, and the strong man, in turn, has 
the greatest capacity for these. And the case is the 9 
same with the virtues : by abstaining from pleasure 
\/ we become temperate, and when we have become 
temperate we are best able to abstain. And so with 
courage : by habituating ourselves to despise danger, 
and to face it, we become courageous ; and when we 
have become courageous, we are best able to face 
danger. 
wuijtuin 3. The pleasure or pain that accompanies the acts 1 
liili^JSftS''^* must be taken as a test of the formed habit or character, 
ire and Hc who abstsins from the pleasures of the body and 

rejoices in the abstinence is temperate, while he who 
is vexed at having to abstain is profligate ; and again, 
he who faces danger with pleasure, or, at any rate, 
without pain, is courageous, but he to whom this is 
painful is a coward. 

For moral virtue or excellence is closely con- 

|/cemed with pleasure and pain. It is pleasure that 

moves us to do what is base, ancj pain that moves us 

to refrain from what is noble. And therefore, as 9 

Plato says, man needs to be so trained from his youth 

)up as to find pleasure and pain in the right objects. 
This is what sound education means. 



i»n. 



2| 8-3, 7j HOBAL VIRTUE. 39 

Another reason why virtue has to do with pleasured 
and pain, is that it has to do with actions and passions 
or affections; but every affection and every act is 
accompanied by pleasure or pain^ 

The fact is further attested by the employment of 
pleasure and pain in correction; they have a kind of 
curative property, and a cure is effected by administer- 
ing the opposite of the disease. v 

Again, as we said before, every type of character 
[or habit or formed faculty] is essentially relative to, 
and concerned with, those things that form it for good 
or for ill ; but it is through pleasure and pain that bad 
characters are formed — that is to say, through pur- 
suing and avoiding the wrong pleasures and pains, or 
pursuing and avoiding them at the wrong time, or in 
the wrong manner, or in any other of the various 
ways of going wrong that may be distinguished. 

And hence some people go so far as to define the 
virtues as a kind of impassive or neutral state of 
mind But they err in stating this absolutely, instead 
of qualifying it by the addition of the right and wrong - 
manner, time, etc. 

We may lay down, therefore, that this kind of 
excellence {i.e. moral excellence] makes us do what is 
best in matters of pleasure and pain, while vice or 
badness has the contrary effect. 

The following considerations will throw additional 
light on the point. 

There are three kinds of things that move us to 
choose, and three that move us to avoid them : on the 
one hand, the beautiful or noble, the advantageous, 
the pleasant ; on the other hand, the ugly or base, the 



/ 



40 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLK [Bk. II. 

hurtful, the painful. Now, the good man is apt to 
go right, and the bad man to go wrong, about them 
all, but especially about pleasure i for pleasure is not 
only common to man with animals, but also accom- 
panies all pursuit or choice ; since the noble, and the 
advantageous also, are pleasant in idea. 

Again, the feeling of pleasure has besn fostered in 8 
us all from our infancy by our training, and has thus 
become so engrained in our life that it can scarce be 
washed out.* And, indeed, we all more or less make 
pleasure our test in judging of actions. For this 9 
reason too, then, our whole inquiry must be concerned 
with these matters ; since to be pleased and pained in 
the right or the wrong way has great influence on our 
actions^ 

And lastly, as Heraclitus says, it is harder to fight 10 
with pleasure than with wrath, and virtue, like art, is 
always more concerned with what is harder; for the 
harder the task the better is success. For this reason 
also, then, both [moral] virtue or excellence and the 
science of the state must always be concerned with 
pleasures and pains ; for he that behaves rightly with 
regard to them will be good, and he that behaves badly 
will be bad. 

We will take it as established, then, that [moral] 1 
excellence or virtue has to do with pleasures and pains ; 
and that the acts which produce it develop it, and 
also, when differently done, destroy it; and that it 
manifests itself in the same acts which produced it. 

* Actions and the acoompanying feelings of pleasure and pain 
have so grown together, that it is impossible to separate the former 
and judge them apart : cf, X. 4^ !!• 



/ 



3, 8-4, 4.] MORAL VIRTUE. 41 

1 4. But here we may be asked what we mean by n< eon- 
saying that men can become just and temperate only virtwui 
by doing what is just and temperate : surely, it may dittinetfro 
be said, if their acts are just and temperate, they production 
themselves are already just and temperate, as they 

are grammarians and musicians if they do what is 
grammatical and musical. 

2 We may answer, I think, firstly, that this is not 
quite the case even with the arts. A man may do 
something grammatical [or write something correctly] 
by chance, or at the prompting of another person : he 
will not be grammatical till he not only does something 
grammatical, but also does it grammatically [or like a 
grammatical person], i,e, in virtue of his own know- 
ledge of grammar. 

3 But, secondly, the virtues are not in this point 
analogous to the arts. The products of art have their 
excellence in themselves, and so it is enough if when 
produced they are of a certain quality : but in the case 
of the virtuei a maa is not said to l^ justly or tem- 
pei-ately [or like a just or temperate man] if what he 
does merely be of a certain sort — ^he must also be in ^^ 
a certain state of mind when he does it ; i.e., first of 
all, he must know what he is doing; secondly, ho 
must choose it, and choose it for itself; and, thirdly, 
his act must be the expression of a formed and stable 
character. Now, of these conditions, only one, the 
knowledge, is necessary for the possession of any art ; 
but for the possession of the virtues knowledge is of 
little or no avail, while the other conditions that 
residt fix)m repeatedly doing what is just and tem- 
perate are not a little important, but all-important. 



42 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF AEISTOTLB. [Bk. IL 

The thing that is done, therefore, is called just or 4 
< \ temperate when it is such as the just or temperate 
man would do ; but the man who does it is not just or 
^ temperate, imless he also does it in the spirit of the 
just or the temperate man. 

It is right, then, to say that by doing what is just 5 
a man becomes just, and temperate by doing what is 
temperate, while without doing thus he has no chance 
of ever becoming good. 

But most men, instead of doing thus, fly to 6 
theories, and fancy that they are philosophizing and 
that this will make them good, like a sick man who 
listens attentively to what the doctor says and then 
disobeys all his orders. This sort of philosophizing 
will no more produce a healthy habit of mind than this 
sort of treatment will produce a healthy habit of body. 
irtuenot 6. We havc next to inquire what excellence or 1 

lemotiorit ... 

>ra Virtue IS. 

cultjft tut 

ih^ned Everything psychical is either (1) a passion or 

w«; emotion, or (2) a power or faculty, or (3) a habit or 
/ trained faculty ; and so virtue must be one of these 
three. By (1) a passion or emotion we mean appetite, J 
anger, fear, confidence, envy, joy, love, hate, longing, 
emulation, pity, or generally that which is accompanied 
by pleasure or pain ; (2) a power or faculty is that in 
respect of which we are said to be capable of being 
affected in any of these ways, as, for instance, that in 
respect of which we are able to be angered or pained 
or to pity; and (3) a hablb or trained faculty is 
that in respect of which we are well or ill regulated 
or disposed in the matter of our affections ; as, for 
instance, in the matter of being angered, we are ijl 



V 



4, 5-6, IJ HOBAL VIIITUB. 43 

regulated if we are too violent or too slack, but if we 
are moderate in our anger we are well regulated. 
And so with the rest. 

3 Now, the virtues are not emotions, nor are the 
vices — (1) because we are not called good or bad in 
respect of our emotions, but are called so in respect ' 
of our virtues or vices; (2) because we are neither 
praised nor blamed in respect of our emotions (a man 
is not praised for being afraid or angry, nor blamed 
for being angry simply, but for being angry in a 
particular way), but we are praised or blamed in re- 

4 spect of our virtues or vices ; (3) because we may be 
angered or frightened without deliberate choice, but 
the- virtues are a kind of deliberate choice, or at least ^r^^* 
are impossible without it ; and (4) because in respect 

of our emotions we are said to be moved, but in 
respect of our virtues and vices we are not said to be 
moved> but to be regulated or disposed in this way or 
in that. 

6 For these same reasons also they are not powers 
or faculties ; for we are not called either good or bad 
for being merely capable of emotion, nor are we either 
praised or blamed for this. And further, while 
nature gives us our powers or faculties, she does not 
make us either good or bad. ^This point, however, we 
have already treated.) 

6 If, then, the virtues be neither emotions nor 
faculties, it only remains for them to be habits or U^^^ 
ti'ained faculties. 

1 6. We have thus found the genus to which virtue «<,., tj^ 
Ibelongs ; but we want to know, not only that it is a Jj^'i^ 
trained faculty, but also what species, of trained faculty "****** 
•it is. 



1/ 



J 



/ 



44 NICOMACHEAN ^ETHICS OP ABISTOTLE. [Bk. II 

We may safely assert that the virtue or excellence 9 
of a thing causes that thing both to be itself in good 
condition and to perform its function well. The ex- 
cellence of the eye, for instance, makes both the eye 
and its work good ; for it is by the excellence of the 
eye that we see well. So the proper excellence of the 
horse makes a horse what he should be, and makes 
him good at running, and carrying his rider, and 
standing a charge. 

If, then, this holds good in all cases, the proper 8 
excellence or virtue of man will be a habit or trained 
faculty that makes a man good and makes him per- 
form his function welL 

How this is to be done we have already said, but 4 
we may exhibit the same conclusion in another way, 
by inquiring what the nature of this virtue is. 

Now, if we have any quantity, whether continuous 
or discrete,* it is possible to take either a larger [or 
too large], or a smaller [or too small], or an equal [or 
fair] amount, and that either absolutely or relatively 
to our own needs. 

By an equal or fair amount I understand a mean 
amount, or one that lies between excess and deficiency. 

By the absolute mean, or mean relatively to the 5 
thing itself, I understand that which is equidistant 
from both extremes, and this is one and the same 
for all. 

By the mean relatively to us I understand that 

* A line (or a generons emotion) is a "continnons qnanldty;'' 
70a can part it where yon please : a ronlean of sovereigns is a 
''discrete qnantitj," made up of definite part^ and primarilj 
■eparable into them. 



6, a-lO.] MORAL VntTUB. 45 

6 which is neither too much nor too little for us ; and 
this is not one and the same for alL 

For instance, if ten be larger [or too large] and 
two be smaller [or too small], if we take six we take 
the mean relatively to the thing itself [or the 

7 arithmetical mean]; for it exceeds one extreme by 
the same amount by which it is exceeded by the other 
extreme : and this is the mean in arithmetical pro- 
portion. 

But the mean relatively to us cannot be found in 
this way. If ten pounds of food is too much for a 
given man to eat, and two pounds too little, it does 
not follow that the trainer will order him six pounds : 
for that also may perhaps be too much for the man in 
question, or too little; too little for Milo, too much 
for the beginner. The same holds true in running 
and wrestling. 

8 And so we may say generally that a master in any 
art avoids what is too much and what is too little, 
and seeks for the mean and chooses it — not the 
absolute but the relative mean. 

9 Every art or science, then, perfects its work in this 
way, looking to the mean and bringing its work up 
to this standard ; so that people are wont to say of a 
good work that nothing could be taken from it or 
added to it, implying that excellence Ls destroyed by 
excess or deficiency, but secured by observing the 
mean. And good artists, as we say, do in fact keep 
their eyes fixed on this in all that they do. 

Virtue therefore, since like nature it is more exact 

and better than any art, must also aim at the mean — 

.0 virtue of course meaning moral virtue or excellence ; 



i^ 



/^ 



46 NICOMACHBAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLK IBk. H. 

for it has to do with passions and actions^ and it is 
these that admit of excess and deficiency and the 
mean. For instance, it is possible to feel fear, con- 
fidence, desire, anger, pity, and generally to be Wj^fkaUA 
pleasantly and painfully, either too mue .j^^ jr too KtUe, 
in either case wrongly; but to be thus ^ w. "died at the ii 
right times, and on the right occasions, and tdwards 
the right persons, and with the right object, and in 
the right fashion, is the mean course and the best 
course, and these are characteristics of virtue. And 13 
in the same way our outward acts also admit of 
excess and deficiency, and the mean or due amount. 

Virtue, then, has to deal with feelings or passions 
and with outward .acts, in which excess is wrong and 
deficiency also is blamed, but the mean amount is 
praised and is right — both of which are characteristics 
of virtue. 

Virtue, then, is a kind of moderation (jitaornQ rig)* Vi 
inasmuch as it aims at the mean or moderate amount 
(to fiiaov). 

Again, there are many ways of going wrong (for 14 
evil is infinite in nature, to use a Pythagorean figure, 
while good is finite), but only one way of going right; 
so that the one is easy and the other hard — easy to 
miss the mark and hard to hit. On this account also, 
then, excess and deficiency are characteristic of vice, 
hitting the mean is characteristic of virtue : 

'* Goodness is simple, ill takes any shape. ** 

1/ Virtue, then, is a habit or trained faculty of chioice, li 

* fA€<rSrriSy the abstract name for the qnalitj, is quite untrans- 
latable. 



e, ll-2a HOBAL VIRTUE. ^ 47 

the characteristic of which lies in observing the mean 
relatively to the persons concerned, and which i^ 
guided by reason, i.e. by the judgment of the pru- 
dent man. "^ 

13 And it. M^ a moderation, firstly, inasmuch as it 
comes in tlSlftniddle or mean between two vices, one 
on the side of excess, the other on the side of defect ; 
and, secondly, inasmuch as, while these vices fall short 
of or exceed the due measure in feeling and in action, 
it finds and chooses the mean, middling, or moderate . 
amount. 

.7 Regarded in its essence, therefore, or according to 
the definition of its nature, virtue is a moderation 
or middle state, but viewed in its relation to what i3 
best and right it is the extreme of perfection. 

.8 But it is not all actions nor all passions that admit 
of moderation; there are some whose very names 
imply badness, as malevolence, shamelessness, envy, 
and, among acts, adultery, theft, murder. These and 
all other like things are blamed as being bad in them- 
selves, and not merely in their excess or deficiency. 
It is impossible therefore to go right in them ; they 
are always wrong : rightness and -^Tongness in such 
things {e.g, in adultery) does not depend upon whether 
it is the right person and occasion and manner, but 
the mere doing of any one of them is wrong. 

.9 It would be equally absurd to look for modera- 
tion or excess or deficiency in unjust cowardly or 
profligate conduct ; for then there would be modera- 
tion in excess or deficiency, and excess in excess, and 
deficiency in deficiency. 

iO The fact is that just as there can be no excess 



48 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OP ARISTOTLE. [Bk. IL 

or deficiency in temperance or courage because the 
mean or moderate amount is^ in a sense, an extreme, 
so in these kinds of conduct also there can be no 
moderation or excess or deficiency, but the acts are 
wrong however they be done. For, to put it gene- 
rally, there cannot be moderation in excess (Sr de- 
ficiency, nor excess or deficiency in moderation. 
"his muH be 7. But it is uot cnouffh to make these general state- 1 
hetevena mcuts [about virtue and vice] : we must go on and 
apply them to particulars [i.e, to the several virtues 
and vices]. For in reasoning about matters of conduct 
general statements are too vague,* and do not convey 
so much truth as particular propositions. It is with 
particulars that conduct is concerned :t our state- 
ments, therefore, when applied to these particulars, 
should be found to hold good. 

These particulars then [i.e. the several virtues and 
vices and the several acts and affections with which 
they deal], we will take from the following table. J 
1^ Moderation in the feelings of fear and confidence 8 
is courage: of those that exceed, he that exceeds 
in fearlessness has no name (as often happens), but 
he that exceeds in confidence is foolhardy, while he 
that exceeds in fear, but is deficient in confidence, is 
cowardly. 

* Or " cover more ^onnd, but convey less truth than particular 
propositions," if we read Koiv6rtpoi with most manuscripts. 

t In a twofold sense : my conduct cannot be virtuous except by 
exhibiting the particular virtues of justice, temperance, etc. ; again, 
my conduct cannot be just except by being just in particular cases to 
particular persons. 

X The Greek seems to imply that this is a generally accepted list^ 
but Aristotle repeatedly has to coin names : ej, infra, § 11. 



7, 1-8J MOEAL VIRTUE. 49 

Moderation in respect of certain pleasures and 
also (though to a less extent) certain pains is 
temperance, while excess is profligacy. But defect- 
iveness in the matter of these pleasures is hardly ever 
found, and so this sort of people also have as yet J^ 
received no name : let us put them down as " void of .^ 
sensibility." 

[ In the matter of giving and taking money, modera- 
tion is liberality, excess and deficiency are prodigality 
and illiberality. But these two vices exceed and fall 
short in contrary ways: the prodigal exceeds in 
spending, but fioills short in taking ; while the illiberal 
man exceeds in taking, but falls short in sp^iding. 

) (For the present we are but giving an outline or 
summary, and aim at nothing more ; we shall after- 
wards treat these points in greater detaiL) 

s But^ besides these, there are other dispositions in 
the matter of money : there is a moderation which is 
called magnificence (for the magnificent is not the 
same as the liberal man : the former deals with large 
sums, the latter with small), and an excess which is 
called bad taste or vulgarity, and a deficiency which 
is called meanness ; and these vices differ from those 
which are opposed to liberality : how they differ will 
be explained later. 

7 With respect to honour and disgrace, there is a 
moderation which is high-mindedness, an excess which 
may be called vanity, and a deficiency which is little- 
mindedness. 

8 But just as we said that liberality is related to 
magnificence, differing only in that it deals with small 
sums, so here there is a virtue related to high-minded- 

£ 



60 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLB. [Bk. n. 

ness, and differing only in that it is concerned with 
small instead of great honours. A man may have a 
due desire for honour, and also more or less than 
! a due desire : he that carries this desire to excess is 
^ called ambitious, he that has not enough of it is called 
unambitious, but he that has the due amount has no 
name. There are also no abstract names for the cha- 
racters, except "ambition," corresponding to ambitious. 
And on this account those who occupy the extremes 
lay claim to the middle place. And in common 
parlance, too, the moderate man is sometimes ciEklled 
ambitious and sometimes unambitious, and some- 
times the ambitious man is praised and sometimes 
the unambitious. Why this is we will explain 9 
afterwards ; for the present we will follow out our 
plan and enumerate the other types of character. 
l/^ In the matter of anger also we find excess and 10 
deficiency and moderation. The characters themselves 
hardly have recognized names, but as the moderate 
man is here called gentle, we will call his charact^ 
gentleness ; of those who go into extremes, we may 
take the term wrathful for him who exceeds, with 
wrathfulness for the vice, and wrathless for him who 
is deficient, with wrathlessness for his character. 

Besides these, there are three kinds of moderation, 11 
bearing some resemblance to one another, and yet 
different. They all have to do with intercourse in 
speech and action, but they differ in that one has to 
do with the truthfulness of this intercourse, while the 
other two have to do with its pleasantness — one of 
the two with pleasantness in matters of amusement, 
the other with pleasantness in all the relations of 



7, 9-14.] MORAL VIRTUK. 51 

life, Wb must therefore speak of theae qualities alsu 
in order that we may the more plainly see how, in 
all caaea, moderation ia praiaeworthy, while the ex- 
treme eouraes are neither right nor praiseworthy, 
but blamable. 

In theae cases also natnea are for the most part 
wanting, but we must try, hei-e as elsewhere, to coin 
namea ourselves, in order to make our argument clear 
and easy to follow. 

) In the matter of truth, then, let us call him who 
observes the mean a true [or truthful] person, and 
observance of the mean truth [or tmtlil'ulnesa] : pre- 
tence, when it exaggerates, may be called boasting, 
and the person a boaster ; when it underatatea, let the 
names be irony and ironical 

3 With regard to pleasantness in amusement, he who 
obaerves the mean may be called witty, and hia ■ 
character wittineas ; excess may be called buffoonery, 
and the man a buffoon ; while boorish may stand for 
the person who is deficient, and boorishncsa for his 
character. 

With regard to pleasantness in the other affairs 
of life, he who makes himself properly pleasant may 
be called friendly, and his moderation friendliness; 
he that exceeds may be called obsequious if he have 
no ulterior motive, but a flatterer if he has an eye to 
his own advantage ; he that ia deficient in this respect, 
and always makes himself disagreeable, may be called 
a quarrelsome or peevish fellow, 

1 Moreover, in mere emotions • and in our conduct 

with regard to them, there are ways of observing the 

■ i^. wliiob do not isano in act like those hitlicrUi mentioned. 



52 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OP ABISTOTLB. [Bk. IL 

mean; for instance, shame (alSwg), is not a virtue, 
but yet the modest (alSriiuLwv) man is praised For in 
these matters also we speak of this man <» observiBg 
the mean, of that man as going beyond it (as the 
shame-faced man whom the least thing makes shy), 
whne he who is deficient in the feeling, or lacks it 
altogether, is called shameless ; but the term modest 
(atSi}jU(i>v) is applied to him who observes the mean. 

Kighteous indignation, again, hits the mean be- 
^ tween envy and malevolence. These have to do with U 
feelings of pleasure and pain at what happens to 
our neighbours. A man is called righteously indig- 
nant when he feels pain at the sight of undeserved 
prosperity, but your envious man goes beyond him 
and is pained by the sight of any one in prosperity, 
while the malevolent man is so far from being pained 
that he actually exults in the sight of prosperous 
iniquity. 

But we shall have another opportunity of discuss- 1* 
ing these matters. 

As for justice, the term is used in more senses than 
one ; we will, therefore, after disposing of the above 
questions, distinguish these various senses, and show 
how each of these kinds of justice is a kind of 
moderation. 

And then we will treat of the intellectual virtues 
in the same way. 
The two 8. There are, as we said, three classes of disposition, 1 

^tremeiare viz. two kiuds of vicc, ouc marked by excess^ the 
tSe^^ther other by deficiency, and one kind of virtue, the ob- 

and to the ^ , 

intermediau scrvaucc 01 the mcau. 

Now, the extreme dispositions are opposed both 



7, 15-8, 6.] MOBAL VIRTUE. 53 

to the mean or moderate disposition and to one ^ 
another, while the moderate disposition is opposed to ^ 

2 both the extremes. Just as a quantity which is equal 
to a given quantity is «lso greater when compared 
with a less, and less when compared with a greater 
quantity, so t^he mean or moderate dispositions exceed 
as compared with the defective dispositions, and fall 
short as compared with the excessive dispositions, both 
in feeling and in action ; e.g. the courageous man seems 
foolhardy as compared with the coward, and cowardly 
as compared with the foolhardy; and similarly the 
temperate man appears profligate in comparison with 
the insensible, and insensible in comparison with the 
profligate man ; and the liberal man appears prodigal 
by the side of the illiberal man, and illiberal by the 
side of the prodigal man. 

3 And so the extreme characters try to displace the 
mean or moderate character, and each represents him 
as falling into the opposite extreme, the coward calling 
the courageous man foolhardy, the foolhardy calling 
him coward, and so on in other casea 

i But while the mean and the extremes are thus 
opposed to one another, the extremes are still more 
contrary to each other than to the mean ; for they are /^ 
further removed from one another than from the 
mean, as that which is greater than a given magni- 
tude is further from that which is less, and that wSh 
is less is further from that which is greater, than 
either the greater or the less is from that which is 
equal to the given magnitude. 

5 Sometimes, again, an extreme, when compared 
with the mean, has a sort of resemblance to it, as fool- 



54 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OP AEISTOTLB. [Bk. U. 

hardiness to courage, or prodigality to liberality ; but 
there is the greatest possible dissimilarity between 
the extremes. 

Again, "things that are as far as possible remored 
from each other " is the accepted definition of con- 
traries, so that the farther things are removed from 
^ each other the more contrary they ara 

In comparison with the mean, however, it is some- 6 
times the deficiency that is the more opposed, and 
sometimes the excess; e.g, foolhardiness, which is 
excess, is not so much opposed to courage as cowardice, 
which is deficiency ; but insensibility, which is lack 
of feeling, is not so much opposed to temperance as 
profligacy, which is excess. 

The reasons for this are two. One is the reason 7 
V derived from the nature of the matter itself: since 
one extreme is, in fact, nearer and more similar to 
the mean, we naturally do not oppose it to the mean 
so strongly as the other ; e.g, as foolhardiness seems 
more similar to courage and nearer to it, and cowardice 
more dissimilar, we speak of cowardice as the opposite 
rather than the other : for that which is further re- 
moved from the mean seems to be more opposed to it 

This, then, is one reason, derived from the nature 8 
of the thing itself. Another reason lies in ourselves : 
and it is this — those things to which we happen 
to be more prone by nature appear to be more op- 
posed to the mean: e.g, our natural inclination is 
rather towards indulgence in pleasure, and so we more 
easily fall into profligate than into regular habits: 
those courses, then, in which we are more apt to run to 
great lengths are spoken of as more opposed to the 



8, 6-9, 4.] MOBAL VIBTUB. 55 

mean ; and thus profligacy, which is an excess^ is more 
opposed to temperance than the deficiency is. 

1 9. We have sufficiently explained, then, that moral iv mean 
virtue is moderation or observance of the mean, and ami a a 
in what sense, viz. (1) as holding a middle positioniM;rcep(u>i 
between two vices, one on the side of excess, and the reoMonini 
other on the side of deficiency, and (2) as aiming at 

the mean or moderate amoimt both in feeling and in 
action. 

2 And on this account it is a hard thing to be good ; 
for finding the middle or the mean in each case 
is a hard thing, just as finding the middle or centre 
of a circle is a thing that is not within the power of 
everybody, but only of him who has the requisite 
knowledge. .; 

Thus any one can be angry — that is quite easy; ^* : 
any one can give money away or spend it : but to do 
these things to the right person, to the right extent, 
at the right time, with the right object, and in the 
right manner, is not what everybody can do, and is 
by no means easy ; and that is the reason why right 
doing is rare and praiseworthy and noble. 
8 He that aims at the mean, then, should first of all 
strive to avoid that extreme which is more opposed 
to it, as Calypso * bids Ulysses — 

" Clear of tliese smoking breakers keep thy ship." 

4 For of the extremes one is more dangerous, the 
other less. Since then it is hard to hit the mean 
precisely, we must " row when we cannot sail," as 
the proverb has it, and choose the least of two evils ; 

• Horn., Od., xii. 101-110, and 219-220 : Calypso should b^ G\t<5,^. 



/^ 



56 NICOMACHBAN ETHICS OP AEISTOTLB. [Bk. IL] 

and that will be best effected in the way we have 
described. 
/ And secondly we must consider, each for himself, 

'^ what we are most prone to — ^for different natures are 
inclined to different things — ^which we may learn by 
the pleasure or pain we feel. And then we must bend 5 
ourselves in the opposite direction; for by keeping 
well away from error we shall fall into the middle 
course, as we straighten a bent stick by bending it 
the other way. 

But in all cases we must be especially on our guard 6 
against pleasant things, and against pleasure ; for we 
can scarce judge her impartially. And so, in our 
behaviour towards her, we should imitate the be- 
haviour of the old counsellors towards Helen,* and 
in all cases repeat their saying : if we dismiss her we 
shall be less likely to go wrong. 

This then, m outline, is the course by which we 7 
shall best be able to hit the mean. 

But it is a hard task, we must admit, especially in 
a particular case. It is not easy to determine, for 
instance, how and with whom one ought to be angry, 

\^ and upon what grounds, and for how long ; for public 
opinion sometimes praises those who fall shorty and 
calls them gentle, and sometimes applies the term 
manly to those who show a harsh temper. 

In fact, a slight error, whether on the side of excess 8 
or deficiency, is not blamed, but only a considerable 
error; for then there can be ho mistake. But it is 
hardly possible to determine by reasoning how far or 
to what extent a man must err in order to incur 

• Horn., IL, iii. 154-160 



9, 6-9.] MORAL VIRTUE. 57 

blame ; and indeed matters that fall within the scope 
of perception never can be so determined. Such 
matters lie within the region of particulars, and can 
only be determined by perception. 
9 So much then is plain, that the middle character 
is in all cases to be praised, but that we otight to incline 
sometimes towards excess, sometimes towards defi- 
ciency ; for in this way we shall most easily hit' the 
mean and attain to right doing. 



/- 



COOK III. 

CHAPTERS 1-6. THE WILL. 

AncKtis 1. Virtue, as we have seen, has to do with feet i 

wh^di^ ings( and actions. Now, praise * or blame is given 
^^2^, only to what is voluntary ; that which is involuntary 
S»^A receives pardon, and sometimes even pity. 
Q^^H^Lt It seems, therefore, that a dear distinction between 
^^^ the volimtary and the involuntary is necessary for 
km^*** those who are investigating the nature of virtue, and 
^^^c^- will also help legislators in assigning rewards and 

cumttancet: , . , 

voluntary punisiiments. 

oriffinated That is generally held to be involuntary which is 2 

with know- I 1 . 11. 

ledge qfcir- douc uudcr compulsiou Or throuffh imorance. 

"Done under compulsion" means that the cause 8 
^ ; is external, the agent or patient contributing nothing 
, towards it ; as, for instance, if he were carried some- 
where by a whirlwind or by men whom he could not 
j:- resist. 

/ But there is some question about acts done in order i 
to avoid a greater evil, or to obtain some noble end ; 
e.g. if a tyrant were to order you to do something dis- 

* It mnst be remembered that ''virtue" is synonymoiis with 
"praiseworthy habit ; ** 1. 13| 20 j II. 0, 9. 



1, 1-7.] THE WILL. 59 

graceful^ having your parents or children in his power, 
who were to live if you did it, but to die if you did 
not^t is a matter of dispute whether such acts are 
involuntary or voluntary. 

5 Throwing a cargo overboard in a storm is a some- 
what analogous case. No one voluntarily throws away /, - 
his property if nothing is to come of it,* but any 
sensible person would do so to save the life of himself 

and the crew. 

6 Acts of this kind, then, are of a mixed nature, but 
they more nearly resemble voluntary acts. For they 
are desired or chosen at the time when they are done, 
and the end or motive of an act is that which is in 
view at the time. In applying the terms voluntary i^ 
and involuntary, therefore, we must consider the 
state of the agent's mind at the tima Now, he wills 

J^the act at the time; for the cause which sets the 
limbs going lies in the agent in such cases, and where 
the cause lies in the agent, it rests with him to do 
or not to do. 

Such acts, then, are voluntary, though in them- 
selves [or apart from these qualifying circumstances] 
we may allow them to be involuntary; for no one 
would choose anything of this kind on its own account. 

7 And, in fsu^t, for actions of this sort men are 
sometimes praised,t e.g, when they endure something 
disgraceful or painful in order to secure some great -^ 

and noble result : but in the contrary case they are 

« 

* &TX&5, " without qaalification : " no one ohooses loss of property 
simply, but loss of property with, saving of life is what all sensible 
people would choose. 

f Which shows that the acts are regaxded «ya VQ\\m\ax^. 



60 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OP ABISTOTLE. [Bk. HI. 

blamed ; for no worthy person would endure the ex- 
tremity of disgrace when there was no noble result in 
view, or but a trifling one. 

But in some cases we do not praise^ but pardon, 
^ i,e. when a man is induced to do a wrong act by 
pressure which is too strong for human nature and 
which no one could bear. Though there are some cases 8 
of this kind, I think, where the plea of compulsion is 
inadmissible,* and where, rather than do the act, a 
man ought to suffer death in its most painful form ; 
for instance, the circumstances which "compelled" 
Alcmseon in Euripides t to kill his mother seem absurd. 

It is sometimes hard to decide whether we ought 9 
to do this deed to avoid this evil, or whether we ought 
to endure this evil rather than do this deed ; but it is 
stiU harder to abide by our decisions : for generally 
the evil which we wish to avoid is something painful, 
the deed we are pressed to do is something disgrace- 
ful ; and hence we are blamed or praised according as 
we do or do not suffer ourselves to be compelled. 

What kinds of acts, then, are to be called com- lo 
pulsory ? 

I think our answer must be that, in the first place, 

* obK tffnv iLyayKaaOrjucu, " compulsion is impossible." If the aot 

was oompTilBor7 it was not my act, I cannot be blamed : there are 

^ some acts, says Aristotle, for which we could not foi'give a man, for 



m 



which, whatever the circumstances, we must blame him ; therefore no 
circumstances can compel him, or compulsion is impossible. The 
rgument is, in fact, " 1 ought not, therefore I can not (am able not 
to do it),'*— like Kant's, " I ought, therefore I can." But, if valid at 
all, it is valid universaUy, and the conclusion should be that the 
body only can be compelled, and not the will — that a compulsory 
act is impossible. 

t The play alluded to seems to be entirely lost. 



1, 8-11.] THE WILL. 61 

when the cause lies outside and the agent has no part 
in it^ the act is called, without qualification, " com- 
pulsory " [and therefore involuntary]; but that, in the 
second place, when an act that would not be volun- 
tarily done for its own sake is chosen now in prefer- 
ence to this given alternative, the cause lying in the 
agent, such an act must be called "involuntary in 
itself," or " in the abstract," but " now, and in pre- 
ference to this alternative, voluntary." But an act 
of the latter kind is rather of the nature of a 
voluntary act : for acts fall within the sphere of par- 
ticulars ; and here the particular thing that is done is 
voluntary. 

It is scarcely possible, however, to lay down rules 
for determining which of two alternatives is to be 
preferred; for there are many differences in the 
particular casea 
Ll It might, perhaps, be urged that acts whose motive 
is something pleasant or something noble are com- 
pulsory, for here we are constrained by something 
outside us. 

But if this were so, all our acts would be com- 
pulsory; for these are the motives of every act of 
every man.* 

Again, acting under compulsion and against one's 
will is painful, but action whose motive is something 
pleasant or noble involves pleasurcf 

* Therefore, strictly speakiog, a " compulsory act " is a contra- 
diction in terms ; the real qnestiou is, " What is an act ? " 

f Therefore, since these are the motives of every act, all volun- 
tary action involves pleasnre. If we add " when successful," this 
quite agrees with Aristotle's theory of pleasnre in Books VIIi 
and X. 



/ 



V 



62 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. OL 

It is absurd, then, to blame things outside us 
instead of our own readiness to yield to their allure- 
ments, and, while we claim our noble acts as our own, 
to set down our disgraceful actions to "pleasant 
things outside us." 

Compulsory, then, it appears, is that of which the l 
cause is external, the person compelled contributing 
nothing thereto. 

What is done through ignorance is always " not- li 
voluntary," but is " involuntary " * when the agent 
is pained afterwards and sorry when he finds what 
he has done.f For when a man, who has done 
something through ignorance, is not vexed at what 
he has done, you cannot indeed say that he did it 
voluntarily, as he did not know what he was doing, 
but neither can you say that he did it involuntarily 
or unwillingly, since he is not sorry. 

A man who has acted through ignorance, then, if he 
is sorry afterwards, is held to have done the deed in- 
voluntarily or unwillingly ; if he is not sorry after- 
wards we may say (to mark the distinction) he did the 
deed " not-voluntarily ; " for, as the case is different, it 
is better to have a distinct name. 

Acting through ignorance, however, seems to be 14 
/ different from acting in ignorance. For instance, 
when a man is drunk or in a rage he is not thought 

♦ t.e. not merely " not -willed," but done " nnwillingly," or 
" against the agent's will." Unfortunately our usage recognizes no 
such distinction between " not-voluntary " and " inyoluntary." 

t iv /Li(Tafi€\c(f, lit. "when the act involves change of mind." 
This, under the circumstances, can only mean that the agent who 
willed the act, not seeing the true nature of it at the time, is sorry 
afterwards, when he comes to see what he has done. 



1, 12-17] THE WILL. 63 

to act through ignorance, but through intoxication or . 
rage, and yet not knowingly, but in ignorance. 

Every vicious man, indeed, is ignorant of* what 
ought to be done and what ought not to be done, and 
it is this kind of error that makes men unjust and 

5 bad generally. But the term " involuntary " is not 
properly applied to cases in which a man is ignorant 
of what is fitting."!* The ignorance that makes an 
act involuntary is not this ignorance of the principles 
which should determine preference (this constitutes 
vice), — ^not, I say, this ignorance of the universal (for 
we blame a man for this), but ignorance of the 
particular occasion and circumstances of the act 

.6 These are the grounds of pity and pardon; for he 
who is ignorant of any of these particulars acts 
involuntarily. 

It may be as well, then, to specify what these 
particulars are, and how many. They are — first, the 
doer; secondly, the deed; and, thirdly, the circum- 
stance or occasion of it ; sometimes also that where- 
with (e.g, the instrument with which) it is done, 
and that for the sake of which it is done {e.g, for 
protection), and the way in which it is done (e.g. 
gently or violently.) 

7 Now, a man cannot (unless he be mad) be igno- 

• i,e* fbrms a wrong judgment j c/. ^ fioxBifipta Sicn^c^ccrOat voici 
T€pi rhs TtpiucTucht ^X<^') ^^* 1<3» 10 : not that the vioions man does 
not know that snch a conrae is condemned bj sooietj, but he does 
not assent to society's rules — ^adopts other maxims contrary to them. 

f rh a'vfi4>4pou, what condaces to a given end, expedient. The 
meaning of the term varies with the end in view : here the end in 
view is the snpreme end, happiness : rh cvfiAp^poy, then, means here 
the role of conduct to which, in a given case, the agent must con- 
form in order to realize this end j cf. II. 2, 8. 



/^ 



t 



64 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OP ABISTOTLE. [Bk. IlL 

rant of all these particulars ; for instance, he evidently 
cannot be ignorant of the doer : for how can he not 
know himself? 

But a man may be ignorant of what he is doing ; 
e.g. a man who has said something will sometimes 
plead that the words escaped him unawares, or that 
he did not know that the subject was forbidden (as 
-ZEschylus pleaded in the case of the Mysteries) ; or a 
man might plead that when he discharged the weapon 
he only intended to show the working of it, as the 
prisoner did in the catapult case. Again, a man might 
A/ mistake his son for an enemy, as Merope * did, or a 
\ ^* sharp spear for one with a button, or a heavy stone for 
^"^ a pumice-stone. Again, one might kill a man with 
* a blow intended to save him, or strike a serious blow 

■ 

when one only wished to show how a blow should 
be delivered (as boxers do when they spar with open 
hands). 

Ignorance, then, being possible with regard to all 18 

^J these circumstances, he who is ignorant of any of them 

is held to have acted involuntarily, and especially 

when he is ignorant of the most important particulars, 

which are generally taken to be the occasion and the 

result.t 

Besides this, however, the agent must be grieved M 
and sorry for what he has done, if the act thus igno- 
rantly committed is to be called involuntary [not 
merely not-volimtary]. 

* Nothing eeems to be known of the case alluded to. 

t T^ o5 ^yfKa usually is the intended result (and so cyfiea riros in 
§ 16), but of course it is only the actual result that the agent can be 
ignorant of. 



1, 1&-27.] THB WnX. 66 

20 But now, having found that an act is involuntary 
when done under compxdsion or through ignorance, 
we may conclude that a voluntary act is one which is ^ 
originated by the doer with knowledge of the parti- 
cular circumstances of the act. 

21 For I venture to think that it is incorrect to say 
that acts done through anger or desire are involuntary* 

22 In the first place, if tiiis be so we can no longer 
allow that any of the other a.nimal8 act voluntarily/ \^ ^ 
nor even children. ' c ^ ,' 

23 Again, does the saying mean that none of the acts 
which we do through desire or anger are voluntary, or 
that the noble onesi^are voluntary and the disgraceful*^ 
ones involuntary ? Interpreted in the latter sense, it 
is surely ridiculous, as one man is the author of both. 

14 If we take the former interpretation, it is absurd, I 
think, to say that we ought to desire a thing, and also to 
say that its pursuit is involuntary ; but, in fact^ there 
are things at which we ought to be angry, and things 
which we ought to desire, e,g. health and learning. 

6 Again, it seems that what is done unwillingly is ^ 
painful, while what is done through desire is pleasant. 

6 Again, what difference is there, in respect of in- 
voluntariness, between wrong deeds done updn calcu« ^ 

7 lation and wrong deeds done in anger ? Both alike 
are to be avoided, and our unreasoning passions or 
feelings seem to be just as much our own [as our 
reasonings or calculations]. 

But the fact is that all human actions proceed ^ 
either from anger or from desire : * to make all such 
actions involuntary, therefore, would be too absurd. 
* Not thai reason or calculation cannot modify caUgci) \$«^ ^\ 



66 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF AEISTOTLB. [Bk. IH. 

purpoM^a 2. Now that we have distinguislied voluntary from l 
n^jcAoicc* involuntary acts, our next task is to discuss choice 
Miberation. OF purposc. For it sccms to be most intimately con- 
nected with virtue, and to be a surer test of character 
than action itself. 

It seems that choosing is willing, but that the two 2 
terms are not identical, willing being the wider. For 
children and other animals have will, but not choice 
or purpose; and acts done upon the spur of the 
moment are said to be voluntary, but not to be done 
with deliberate purpose. 
tr Those who say that choice is appetite, or anger, or 3 

wish, or an opinion of some sort, do not seem to give 
a correct account of it. 

In the first place, choice is not shared by irra- 
^ tional creatures, but appetite and anger are. 

Again, the incontinent man acts from appetite 4 
and not from ehoice or purpose, the continent man 
from purpose and not from appetite. 

Again, appetite may be contrary to purpose, but 5 
one appetite can not be contrary to another appetite.* 
Again, the object of appetite [or aversion] is the 
v/ pleasant or the painful, but the object of purpose [as 
such] is neither painful nor pleasant. 

can only do so by modifying desire or feeling. Erery action (wpt^ut) 
issues from a feeling or passion (irddos), which feeling (and there*, 
fore the resultant action) is mine (the ontcome of my character, 
and therefore imputable to me), whether it be modified by reason 
(deliberation, calculation) or no. 

• Two appetites may pull two differenty but not contrary ways 
{ivcufTiovrai) ; that which not merely diverts but restrains me from 
satisfying a,n appetite must be desire of a different kind, e.g. deaize 
to do what is right. *Eiri0vfiia is used loosely in cap. 1 for desire 
(ifpt^if) , here more strictly for appetite, a species of desire, purpoM 
(irpoalptffif) being another species : cf, infrai 8, 19, 



2, 1-11.] THE WILL. 67 

6 Still less can purpose be anger (OvfAog) ; for acts 
done in anger seem to be least of all done of purpose 
or deliberate choice. 

7 Nor yet is it wish, though it seem very like ; for 
we cannot purpose or deliberately choose the impos- 
sible, and a man who should say that he did would 
be thought a fool ; but we may wish for the impossible, 
e.g. to escape death. 

8 Again, while we may wish what never could be 
effected by our own agency (e.g. the success of a par- 
ticular actor or athlete), we never purpose or deliber- 
ately choose such things, but only those that we think 
may be effected by our own agency. 

9 Again, we are more properly said to wish the end, 
to choose the means ; e.g. we wish to be healthy, but 
we choose what will make us healthy : we wish to be 
happy, and confess the wish, but it would not be correct 
to say we purpose or deliberately choose to be happy ; 
for we may say roundly that purpose or choice deals 
with what is in our power. 

Nor can it be opinion; for, in the first place, 
anything may be matter of opinion — what is un- 
alterable and impossible no less than what is in 
our power ; and, in the second place, we distinguish 
opinion according as it is true or false, not ac- 
cording as it is good or bad, as we do with purpose 
or choice. 

We may say, then, that purpose is not the same 
as opinion in general; nor, indeed, does any one 
maintain this. 

1 But, further, it is not identical with a particular 
kind of opinion. For our choice of good or evil 



/ 



68 NIOOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. lH 

makes us morally good or bad, holding certain opinions 
does not. 

Again, we choose to take this or to avoid it, and 12 
so on ; we opine what its nature is, or what it is good 
for, or in what way ; but we cannot opine to take or 
to avoid. 

Again, we commend a purpose for its rightness 13 
rather than its correctness, an opinion for its truth. 

Again, we choose a thing when we know well 
^ that it is good; we may have an opinion about a 
thing of which we know nothing. 

Again, it seems that those who are best at choosing 14 
are not always the best at forming opinions, but that 
^ some who have an excellent judgment fail, through 
depravity, to choose what they ought. 

It may be said that choice or purpose must be 15 
preceded or accompanied by an opinion or judgment; 
but this makes no difference : our question is not that^ 
but whether they are identical ' 

What, then, is choice or purpose, since it is none 16 
of these ? 

It seems, as we said> that what is chosen or pur- 
posed is willed, but that what is willed is not always 
chosen or purposed. 

The required differentia, I think, is " after previous 17 
\/ deliberation." For choice or purpose implies calcu-^ 
lation and reasoning. The name itself, too, seems to 
indicate this, implying that something is chosen before 
or in preference to other things.* 
rtioiberau 3. Now, as to deliberation, do we deliberate about 1 

• irpocdp€(ns, lit. " choosing before.** Onr " preference " exsiMj 
corresponds here^ but nnf ortnnately cannot always be employed. 



2, 12-8, 7.] THE WILL. 69 

everything, and may anything whatever be msitteT on what % 
for deliberation, or are there some things about which <mendt,b 
deliberati(Hi is impossible ? 

2 By "matter for deliberation" we should under- 
stand, I think, not what a fool or a maniac, but what 
a rational being would deliberate about. 

3 Now, no one deliberates about eternal or unalter-^ y 
able things, e,g, the system of the heavenly bodies, or 
the incommensurability of the side and the diagonal 

of a square. 

4 Again, no one deliberates about things which 
change, but always change in the same way (whether 
the cause of change be necessity, or nature, or any 

6 other agency), e.g. the solstices and the sunrise ; * nor 
about things that are quite irregular, like drought and 
wet; nor about matters of chance, like the finding 
of a treasure. 

B Again, even human affairs are not always matter 
of deliberation ; e.g. what would be the best consti- '^ 
tution for Scythia is a question that no Spartan 
would deliberate about. 

The reason why we do not deliberate about 
these things is that none of tbem are things thatK^ 
we can ourselves effect. 

7 But the things that we do deliberate about are 
matters of conduct that are within our controL And 
these are the only things that remain ; for besides 
nature and necessity and chance, the only remain- 
ing cause of change is reason and human agency in 
generaL Though we must add that men severally 
deliberate about what they can themselves do. 

* These are instances of " necessity ; ** a tree growB hj " nature," 
%.e, bj its own natural powers. 



70 NICOMACHEAN ETmOS OF AKISTOTLE. [Bk. m. 

V A further limitation is that where there is exact 8 
V and absolute knowledge, there is no room for delibera- 
tion; e.g, writing: for there is no doubt how the 
letters should be formed. 

^ We deliberate, then, about things that are brought 

, about by our own agency, but not always in the same 
'^^-y; ^'9' about medicine and money-making, and 
about navigation more than about gymnastic, inas- 
much as it is not yet reduced to so perfect a system, 
and so on ; but more about matters of art than matters 9 
of science, as there is more doubt about them. 

Matters of deliberation, then, are matters in lo 
which there are rules that generally hold good, but 
in which the result cannot be predicted, i,e, in which 
there is an element of uncertainty. In important 
matters we call in advisers, distrusting our own 
powers of judgment. 

j/ It is not about ends, but about means that we ii 

deliberate. A physician does not deliberate whether 
he shall heal, nor an orator whether he shall persuade, 
nor a statesman whether he shall make a good system 
of laws, nor a man in any other profession about his 
end ; but, having some particular end in view, we con- 
sider how and by what means this end can be 
attained ; and if it appear that it can be attained 
by various means, we further consider which is the 
easiest and best; but if it can only be attained 
by one means, we consider how it is to be attained 
by this means, and how this means itself is to be 
. secured, and so on, until we come to the first link ' 
in the chain of causes, which is last in the order of 
discovery. 



3, 8-16.] THE WILL. 71 

For in deliberation we seem to inquire and to 
analyze in the way described, just as we analyze a 
geometrical figure in order to learn how to construct 

2 it * (and though inquiry is not always deliberation — 
mathematical inquiry, for instance, is not — delibera* 
tion is always inquiry); [that which is last in the 
analysis coming first in the order of construction. 

13 If we come upon something impossible, we give up 
the plan ; e.g. if it needs money, and money cannot 
be got : but if it appear possible, we set to work. By /^' 
possible I mean something that can be done by ua; 
and what can be done by our friends can in a manner 
be done by us \ for it is we who set our friends to 
work. 

A Sometimes we have to find out instruments, some- 
times how to use them; and so on with the rest: some- K 
times we have to find out what agency will produce 
the desired efiect, sometimes how or through whom 
this agency is to be set at work. 

.6 Now, it appears that a man, as we have already 
said, originates his acts ; that he deliberates about that 
which he can do himself, and that what he does is done 

6 for the sake of something else.t From this it follows 

♦ If we have to constmct a geometrical figure, we first " snppose 
it done,'' then analyze the imagined figure in order to see the con- 
ditions which it implies and which imply it, and continne the chain 
till we come to some thing (drawing of some lines) which we already 
know how to do. 

t 0/. m. 2, 9, and 6, 1, and X. 7, 5. There is no real incon- 
sistency between this and the doctrine that the . end of life is 
life, that the good act is to be chosen for its own sake (II. 4, 3), 
because it is noble (III. 7, 13) : for the end is not outside the 
means; happiness or the perfect life is the complete system of 
these acts, and the real nature of each act is determined by its rela* 



/ 



72 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk. IIL 

that he does not deliberate about the end, but about 
i/ the means to the end. 

Again, he does not deliberate about particular facts, 
e.g, whether this be a loaf, or whether it be properly- 
baked: these are matters of immediate perception. 
And if he goes on deliberating for ever he will never 
come to a conclusion. 

The object of deliberation and the object of choice 17 
y or purpose are the same, except that the latter is 
already fixed and determined; when we say, "this 
is chosen " or '* purposed," we mean that it has been 
selected after deliberation. For we always stop in our 
inquiry how to do a thing when we have traced back 
the chain of causes to ourselves, and to the com- 
manding part of ourselves ; for this is the part that 
chooses. 

This may be illustrated by the ancient constitu- 18 
tions which Homer describes; for there the kings 
announce to the people what they have chosen. 

Since, then, a thing is said to be chosen or pur- 19 
posed when, being in our power, it is desired after 
^ deliberation, choice or purpose may be defined as 
deliberate desire for something in our power; for 
we first deliberate, and then, having made our 
decision thereupon, we desire in accordance with 
deliberation. 

Let this stand, then, for an account in outline of 20 
choice or purpose, and of what it deals with, viz. 
means to ends. 
ijwi»A/or/ 4. Wish, we have already said, is for the end; but i 

tion to this sjstem ; to choose it as a means to thJs end is to choose 
it for itself. 



3, 17-4, 6j THE WILL. 73 

-whereas some hold that the object of wish is the good *^ 
others hold that it is what seems good. 
8 Those who maintain that the object of wish * is , 
the good have to admit that what those wish for who 
choose wrongly is not object of wish (for if so it 
would be good ; but it may so happen that it was 

3 bad); on the other hand, those who maintain that 
the object of wish is what seems good have to admit 
that there is nothing which is naturally object of 
wish, but that each wishes for what seems good to 
him — different and even contrary things seeming 
good to different people. 

4 As neither of these alternatives quite satisfies us, 
perhaps we had better say that the good is the real ^ 
object of wish (without any qualifying epithet), but 
that what seeifis good is object of wish to each ^ 
man. Tha good man, then, wishes for the real object 
of wish ; but what the bad man wishes for may be 
anything whatever ; just as, with regard to the body, 
those who are in good condition find those things 
healthy that are really healthy, while those who are 
diseased find other things healthy (and it is just the 
same with things bitter, sweet, hot, heavy, etc.) : for 
the good or ideal man judges each case correctly, and 
in each case what is true seems true to him. 

6 For, corresponding to each of our trained faculties, 
there is a special form of the noble and the pleasant, 

* fiovKrirSu. This word hovers between two senses, (1) wished 
for, (2) to be wished for, just as aiptrSv hovers between (1) desired, 
(2) desirable. The diffionlty, as here pnt, tarns entirely npon the 
eqaivocation; bat at bottom lies the fundamental question, whether 
there be a eommon human nature, such that we o«n Buy, ** This kind 
of life is man*s real life." 



y 



74 NICOMAGHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk. IH 

and perhaps there is noiJiing so distinctive of the 
good or ideal man as the power he has of discerning 
these special forms in each case, being himself, as it 
were, their standard and measure. 

What misleads people seems to be in most cases 
pleasure ; it seems to be a good thing, even when it is 
not. So they choose what is pleasant as good, and 
shun pain as eviL 
TiriiiAans, yr 6. We havc seen that, while we wish for the end, 1 

vic€ are alike 

voluntary: we deliberate upon and choose the means thereto. 

ouractiare i • t t • t Ji_ mi 

^ ouroum:for Actious that are concerned with means, then, will 

we are / 

Sm'^twi ^® guided by choice, and so will be voluntary. 

be our But the acts in which the virtues are manifested 

characUTttoe 

^noSa^*' are concerned with means.* 

bSdiiy^ y Therefore virtue depends upon ourselves : and 8 
SSS^'Slf ^ vice likewise. For where it lies with us to do, it 
S^pieS lies with us not to do. Where we can say no, we 
^?foSir^ can say yes. If then the doing a deed, which is 
^^''' noble, lies with us, the not doing it, which is dis- 
na^un:for graceful, Kcs with us; and if the not doing, which is 
u^f^^ noble, lies with us, the doing, which is disgraceful, 
wrfJ? also lies with us. But if the doing and likewise the 8 
tolJSLJfSr- ^ot doing of noble or base deeds lies with us, and if 
this is, as we found, identical with being good or bad, 
then it follows that it lies with us to be worthy or 
worthless men. 

And so the saying— 4 

" None would be wicked, none would not be blessed,** 

• Each virtuous act is desired and chosen as a means to lealiziiig 
a particular virtue, and this again is desired as a part or oon- 
Btituent of, and so as a means to, that perfect self-realization whidi 
is happiness : c/. 8, 15. 



selves tcha^ 
we are. 



6, 1-8.3 TAB WILL. 76 

seems partly false and partly true : no one indeed 
is blessed against his will ; but vice is voluntary. 

K we deny this, we must dispute the statements 
made just now, and must contend that man is not the 
originator and the parent of his actions, as of his 
children. 

But if those statements commend themselves to 
us, and if we are unable to trace our acts to any 
other sources than those that depend upon oiurselves, 
then that whose source is within us must itself 
depend upon us and be voluntary. 

This seems to be attested, moreover, by each one of 
us in private life, and also by the legislators; for they 
correct and punish those that do evil (except when it 
is done under compulsion, or through ignorance for 
which the agent is not responsible), and honour those 
that do noble deeds, evidently intending to encourage 
the one sort and discourage the other. But no one 
encourages us to do that which does not depend on 
ourselves, and which is not voluntary : it would bo 
useless to be persuaded not to feel heat or pain or 
hunger and so on, as we should feel them all the same* 

I say " ignorance for which the agent is not re- 
sponsible," for the ignorance itself is punished by the 
law, if the agent appear to be responsible for his 
ignorance, e.g. for an offence committed in a fit of 
drunkenness the penalty is doubled: for the origin 
of the offence lies in the man himself; he might have 
avoided the intoxication, which was the cause of his 
ignorance. Again, ignorance of any of the ordinances 
of the law, which a man ought to know and easily 
can know, does not avert punishment. And so in 



1^ 



76 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk. IIL 

other cases, where ignorance seems to be the result of s 
negligence, the offender is punished, since it lay with 
him to remove this ignorance; for he might have 
taken the requisite trouble. 

It may be objected that it was the man's character i 
not to take the trouble. 

We reply that men are themselves responsible for 
acquiring such a character by a dissolute life, and for 
being unjust or profligate in consequence of repeated 
acts of wrong, or of spending their time in drinking 
and so on. For it is repeated acts of a particular 
kind that give a man a particular character. 
V This is shown by the way in which men train 11 
themselves for any kind of contest or performance: 
they practise continually. 

Not to know, then, that repeated acts of this or 12 
that kind produce a corresponding character or habit, 
shows an utter want of sense. 

Moreover, it is absurd to say that he who acts 13 
unjustly does not wish to be unjust, or that he who 
behaves profligately does not wish to be profligate. 
^L If then a man knowingly does acts which must 14 
make him unjust, he wiU be voluntarily unjust; but 
it does not foUow that, if he wishes it, he can cease to 
be imjust and be just, any more than he who is sick 
can, if he wishes it, be whola And it may be that 
he is voluntarily sick, through living incontinently 
and disobeying the doctor. At one time, then, he had 
the option not to be sick, but he no longer has it now 
that he has thrown away his health. When you 
have discharged a stone it is no longer in your power 
to call it back; but nevertheless the throwing and 



fi, 9-I7-] THE WILL. 77 

casting away of that etona rests with you ; for the "y 
beginning of its flight depended upon you.* ) 

Just so the unjust or the profligate man at thft 
beginning was free not to acquire tliia character, and 
therefore he is voluntarily unjust or profligE^ ; but 
now that he has acc[uired it, he is no longer free to put 
it ofl: 

But it is not only our mental or moral vices that . 
are voluntary ; bodily vices also are sometimes volun- 
tary, and then are censured, We do not censure 
natural ugliness, but we do censure that which is due 
to negligence and want of exercise. And so with 
weakness, and infirmity ; we should never reproach a 
man who was bom blind, or had lost his sight in aa 
illness or by a blow — we should rather pity him ; but 
we should all censure a man who had blinded himself 
by excessive drinking or any other kind of profligacy. 

j We see, then, that of the vices of the body it is 
those that depend on ourselves that are censured, 
while those that do not depend on ourselves are not 
censured. And if this be so, then in other fields also 
those vices that are blamed must depend upon oi^- 
selves. 

7 Some people may perhaps object to this, 

"All men," they may say, "desire that which 
appears good to them, but cannot control this ajipear- 
ance ; a man's character, whatever it be, decides what^ 
shall appear to him to bo the end." 

* My act ia ■nans, and does not ceaaa to be mine becunae I woald 
nndo it if I conld ; imd eo, further, since we made the habits whose 
bonds we cannot now unloose, we are responsible, not merely for the 
acta which made them, bnt also for the acts which thoy now pro- 
dnoe " in epite ot oa : " whttt comtraiua us ia onrselres. 



78 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk. m. 

If, I answer, each man be in some way responsible 
for his habits or character, then in some way he must 
be responsible for this appearance also. 

But if this be not the case, then a man is not 
responsible for, or is not the cause of, his own evil 
doing, but it is through ignorance of the end that he 
/ does evil, fancying that thereby he will secure the 
^eatest good: and the striving towards the true 
end does not depend on our own choice, but a man 
must be bom with a gift of sight, so to speak, if he is 
to discriminate rightly and to choose what is really 
good : and he is truly well-bom who is by nature 
richly endowed with this gift ; for, as it is the greatest 
and the fairest gift, which we cannot acquire or 
learn from another, but must keep all our lives just 
as nature gave it to us, to be well and nobly bom in 
this respect is to be well-born in the truest and com- 
pletest sense. 

Now, even supposing this to be true, how will 18 
virtue be any more voluntary than vice ? 

For whether it be nature or anything else that 
determines what shall appear to be the end, it is de- 
termined in the same way for both alike, for the good 
man as for the bad, and both alike refer all their 
acts of whatever kind to it. 

And so whether we hold that it is not merely M 
nature that decides what appears to each to be the 
end (whatever that be), but that the man himself 
contributes something ; or whether we hold that the 
end is fixed by nature, but that virtue is voluntary, 
v/ inasmuch as the good man voluntarily takes the steps 
to that end — ^in either case vice will be just as volun- 



6, 18-22.] THE WILL. 79 

tary as virtue ; for self is active in the bad man just 
as much as in the good man, in choosing the particular 
acts at least, if not in determining the end. ^ 

If then, as is generally allowed, the virtues are 
voluntary (for we do, in fact, in some way help to 
make our character, and, by being of a certain cha- 
racter, give a certain complexion to our idea of the 
end), the vices also must be voluntary; for all this 
applies equally to them. 

We have thus described in outline the nature of the 
virtues in general, viz. that they are forms of moder- 
ation or modes of observing the mean, and that they 
are habits or trained faculties ; and we have shown 
what produces them, and how they themselves issue 
in the performance of the same acts which produce 
them, and that they depend on ourselves and are 
volimtary, and that they follow the guidance of right 
reason. 

But our particular acts are not voluntary in the 
same sense as our habits. 

We are masters of our acts from beginning to end, 
when we know the particular circumstances ; but we 
are masters of the beginnings only of our habits or 
characters, while their growth by gradual steps is 
imperceptible, like the growth of disease. Inasmuch, 
however, as it lay with us to employ or not to em- 
ploy our faculties in this way, the resulting characters 
are on that account voluntary. 



i^ 



80 NICOMACHBAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bjk. Ul 



BOOK IIL CHAPTEB 8. — END OF BOOK V. THE SEVERAL 

MORAL VIRTUES AND VICEa 

Of courage 6. Now let US take up each of the virtues again l 
oppMite in turn, and say what it is, and what its subject is, 
and how it deals with it ; and in doing this, we shall 
at the same time see how many they are. 

First of all, let us take courage. 2 

We have already said that it is moderation or 
L-^ observance of the mean with respect to feelings of 
fear and confidence. 

Now, fear evidently is excited by fearful things, 
and these are, roughly speaking, evU things; and 
SO fear is sometimes defined as "expectation of 
eva" 

Fear, then, is excited by evil of any kind, e.g. by 8 
disgrace, poverty, disease, friendlessness, death; but 
it does not appear that every kind gives scope for 
courage. There are things which we actually ought 
to fear, which it is noble to fear and base not to fear, 
e.g. disgrace. He who fears disgrace is an honourable 
man, with a due sense of shame, while he who fears it 
not is shameless (though some people stretch the word 4 
courageous so far as to apply it to him ; for he has a 
certain resemblance to the courageous man, courage 
also being a kind of fearlessness). Poverty, per- 
haps, we ought not to fear, nor disease, nor generally 
those things that are not the result of vice, and do 
not depend upon ourselves. But still to be fearless 
in regard to these things is not strictly courage; 



6, 1-11.] COUKAGB. 81 

though here also the term is sometimes applied in 
virtue of a certain resemblance. There are people, 
for instance, who, though cowardly in the presence 
of the dangers of war, ai-e yet liberal and bold in the 
spending of money. 

1 On the other hand, a man ia not to be called 
cowardly for fearing outrage to his children or hia 
wife, or for dreading envy and things of that kind, 
nor courageous for being unmoved by the prospect 
of a whipping. 

1 In what kind of terrors, then, does the courageous 
man display his quality? Surely in the greatest; 
for no one is more able to endure what is terrible. 
But of all things the most terrible is death ; for death 
is our limit, and when a man is once dead it seems 
that there is no longer either good or evil for him. 

' It would seem, however, that even death does not 
on all occasions give scope for courage, e.g. death by 
water or by diaeaae, 

* On what occasions then ? Surely on the noblest 

occasions : and those are the occasions which occur in 
war ; for they involve the greatest and the noblest 
danger, 

I This is confirmed by the honours which courage 
receives in free states and at the hands of princes. 

I The term courageous, then, in the strict senise, will 
be applied to him who fearlessly faces an honourable 
death and all sudden emergencies which involve 
death ; and such emergencies mostly occur in war. 

I Of course the courageous man ia fearless in 'ttie 
presence of illness also, and at sea, but in a different 
way from the sailors ; for the sailors, because of their 



t^ 



L i J 



82 KICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk. UL 

experience, are full of hope when the landsmen are 
already despairing of their lives and filled with aver- 
sion at the thought of snch a death. 

Moreover, the drcumstanees which especially crJl 12 
out courage are those in which prowess may be dis- 
played, or in which death is noble; but in these 
forms of death there is neither nobiliiy nor room for 
prowess. 

7. Fear is not excited in all men by the same 1 
things, but yet we commonly speak of fearful things 
that surpass man's power to face. Such things, then, 
inspire fear in every rational man. But the fearful 
things that a man may face differ in importance and 
in being more or less fearful (and so with the things 
that inspire confidence). Now, the courageous man 2 
always keeps his presence of mind (so far as a man 
can). So though he will fear these fearful things, he 
wiU endure them as he ought and as reason bids him, 
for the sake of that which is noble ; * for this is the 
end or aim of virtue. 

But it is possible to fear these things too much or 8 
\y too little, and again to take as fearful what is not 
^eally so. And thus men err sometimes by fearing 4 
the wrong things, sometimes by fearing in the wrong 
manner or at the wrong time, and so on. 

And all this applies equally to things that ini^ire 
confidence. 

He, then, that endures and fears what he ought 5 
from the right motive, and in the right manner, and 

* to^ fcoXoD Ivcica, the highesfc expression that Aristotle has for 
the moral motive, = koXov Ivcica (§ 6) and Sri icax<$v(§ 13), " as a means 
to or as a constitnent part of the noble life." 



6, 12^7, 9.] COURAGE. 83 

at the right time^ and similarly feels confidence, is 
courageoua 

For the courageous man regulates both his feeling 
and his action according to the merits of each case 
and as reason bids him. 

6 But the end or motive of every manifestation of 
a habit or exercise of a trained faculty is the end or 
motive of the habit or trained faculty itself 

Now, to the courageous man courage is essentially 
a fair or noble thing 

Therefore the end or motive of his courage is also 
noble ; for everything takes its character from its end. 

It is from a noble motive, therefore, that the 
courageous man endures and acts courageously in each 
particidar case.* . 

7 Of the characters that run to excess, he that^ 
exceeds in fearlessness has no name (and this is often 
the case, as we have said before) ; but a man would 
be either a maniac or quite insensible to pain who 
should fear nothing, not even earthquakes and 
breakers, as thoy say is the case with the Celts. 

He that is over-confident in the presence of 

8 fearful things is called foolhardy. But the foolhardy 
man is generally thought to be really a braggart, and 
to pretend a courage which he has not. He wishes 
therefore to seem what the courageous man really 
is in the presence of danger; so he imitates him 

9 where he can. And so your foolhardy man is gene- 
rally a coward at bottom : he blusters so long as he 

* The courageous man desires the courageous act for the same 
reaHon for which he desires the virtue itself, viz. simply because it is 
noble : see note on § 2. 



s/ 



84 NICOMACHEAN ETmOS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. Ill 

can do so safely,* but turns tail when real danger 
comes. 

He who is over-fearful is a coward ; for he fears lo 
what he ought not, and as he ought not, etc. 

He is also deficient in confidence; but his 
character rather displays itself in excess of fear in the 
presence of pain. 

The coward is also despondent, for he is frightened ii 
at everything. But it is the contrary with the 
courageous man ; for confidence implies hopefulnesa \ 

Thus the coward and the foolhardy and the 12 
courageous man display their characters in the same 
circumstances, behaving difierently under them: for 
while the former exceed or fall short, the latter 
behaves moderately and as he ought ; and while the 
foolhardy are precipitate and eager before , danger 
comes, but fall away in its presence, the courageous 
are keen in action, but quiet enough beforehand. 

Courage then, as we have said, is observance of 
the mean with regard to things that excite confidence 
or fear, under the circumstances which we have 
siDCcified, and chooses its course and sticks to its post 13 
because it is noble to do so, or because it is disgrace- 
ful not to do so. 

But to seek death as a refuge from poverty, or love, 
or any painful thing, is not the act of a brave man, but 
of a coward. For it is efieminacy thus to fly from 
vexation ; and in such a case death is accepted not 
because it is noble, but simply as an escape from 
evil. 

* iv roirois, i.e, iv oh B^varou, so long as lie can imitate the 
courageoas man without being courageous. 



t^ 



7, 10-8, 4.] COURAGE. 85 

8. Courage proper, then, is something of this sort. g^««"^ 

But besides this there are five other kinds of «oS^ 
courage so called. 

Firsi, "political courage," which most resembles 
true courage. 

Citizens seem often to face dangers because of 

legal pains and penalties on the one hand, and 

a honours on the other. And on this account the 

people seem to be most courageous in those states 

where cowards are disgraced and brave men honoured. 

This, too, is the kind of courage which inspires 
Homer's characters, e.gr. Diomede and Hector. 

" Polydamas will then reproach me first," * 

says Hector ; and so Diomede : 

*' Hector one day will speak among his folk 
And say, * The son of Tydens at my hand * *' f 

3 This courage is most like that which we described 
above, because its impulse is a virtuous one, viz* 
a sense of honour (alSwc), and desire for a noble thing 
(glory), and aversion to reproach, which is dis- 
gracefuL 

4 We might, perhaps, put in the same class men who 
are forced to fight by their officers ; but they are in- 
ferior, inasmuch as what impels them is not a sense 
of honour, but fear, and what they shun is not disgrace, 
but pain. For those in authority compel them in 
Hector's fa^shion — 

*' Wheso is seen to sknlk and shirk the fight 
Shall nowise save his carcase from the dog^." X 

• II., xxii. 200. t Ibid., viii. 148, 149. 

J Ibid., XV. 348, u. 391. 



86 NICOMAOHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. Ill 

And the same thing is done by commanders who 5 
order their men to stand, and flog them if they nm, 
or draw them up with a ditch in their rear, and so 
on : all alike, I mean, employ compulsion. 
\/ But a man ought to be courageous, not under 
compulsion, but because it is noble to be so. 

Secondly, experience in this or that matter is 6 
sometimes thought to be a sort of courage ; and this 
indeed is the ground of the Socratic notion that 
\x^ courage is knowledge. 

This sort of courage is exhibited by various 
persons in various matters, but notably by regular 
troops in military affairs ; for it seems that in war 
there are many occasions of groundless alarm, and 
with these the regulars are better acquainted; so 
they appear to be courageous, simply because the 
other troops do not understand the real state of the 
case. 

. j^- Again, the regular troops by reason of their 7 
-^^^.experience are more efficient both in attack and 
defence; for they are skilled in the use of their 
weapons, and are also furnished with the best kind 
of arms for both purposes. So they fight with the 8 
advantage of armed over unarmed men, or of trained 
over untrained men; for in athletic contests also it 
is not the bravest men that can fight best, but those 
who are strongest and have their bodies in the best 
order. 

But these regular troops turn cowards whenever 9 
the danger rises to a certain height and they find 
themselves inferior in numbers and equipment ; then 
they are the first to fly, while the citizen-troops stand 



.v*' 



8, 6-11.] COURAGE. 87 

and are cut to pieces^ as happened at the temple of 
Hermes.* For the citizens deem it base to fly, and 
hold death preferable to saving their lives on these 
terms; but the regulars originally met the danger 
only because they fancied they were stronger, and 
run away when they learn the truth, fearing death 
more than disgrace. But that is not what we mean 
by courageous. 

Thirdly^ people sometimes include rage within the Ir 
meaning of the term courage. Ji' 

Those who in sheer rage turn like wild beasts 
on those who have wounded them are taken for 
courageous, because the courageous man also is full 
of rage ; for rage is above all things eager to rush on 
danger ; so we find in Homer, " Put might into his 
rage," and " roused his wrath and rage," and " fierce 
wrath breathed through his nostrils," and " his blood 
boiled." For all these expressions seem to signify 
the awakening and the bursting out of rage. 

The truly courageous man, then, is moved to act 
by what is noble, rage helping him : but beasts are 
moved by pain, i.e, by blows or by fear; for in a 
wood or a marsh they do not attack man. And so 
beasts are not courageous, since it is pain and rage 
that drives them to rush on danger, without foresee- 
ing any of ihe terrible consequences. If this be 
courage, then asses must be called courageous when 
they are hungry; for though you beat them they 
will not leave ofi" eating. Adulterers also are moved 
to do many bold deeds by their lust. 

* Oatside Coronea, when the town was betrayed, in the Saorcd 



88 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLB. [Bk. UI. 

Being driven to face danger by pain or rage, then, 12 
is not courage proper. However, this kind of courage, 
whose impulse is rage, seems to be the most natural, 
and, when deUberate purpose and the right motive 
are added to it, to become real courage. 

Again, anger is a painful state, the act of revenge 
is pleasant ; but those who fight from these motives 
[i.e. to avoid the pain or gain the pleasure] may fight 
well, but are not courageous: for they do not act 
because it is noble to act so, or as reason bids, but are 
driven by their passions; though they bear some 
resemblance to the courageous man. 

Fourthly, the sanguine man is not properly called 13 
courageous : he is confident in danger because he has 
often won and has defeated many adversaries The 
two resemble one another, since both are confident; 
but whereas the courageous man is confident for the 
reasons specified above, the sanguine man is confident 
because he thinks he is superior and will win without 
receiving a scratch. (People behave in the same sort 14 
of way when they get drunk ; for then they become 
sanguine.) But when he finds that this is not the 
case, he runs away ; while it is the character of the 
courageous man, as we saw, to face that which is 
terrible to a man even when he sees the danger, 
because it is noble to do so and base not to do so. 

And so (it is thought) it needs greater isourage to \i 
be fearless and cool in sudden danger than in danger 
that has been foreseen; for behaviour in the former 
case is more directly the outcome of formed character, 
or, in other words, is less dependent on preparation. 
When we see what is coming we may choose to meet 



8, 12-9, 2.] COUBAGB. 83 

it, as ihe result of calculation and reasoning, but when 
it comes upon us suddenly we must choose according 
to our character. 

6 Fifthly^ those who are unaware of their danger L/^ 
sometimes appear to be courageous, and in fact are 

not veiy far removed from the sanguine persons we 
last spoke of, only they are inferior in that they have 
not necessarily any opinion of themselves, which the 
sanguine must have. And so while the latter hold 
their ground for some time, the former, whose courage 
was due to a false belief, run away the moment they 
perceive or suspect that the case is different ; as the 
Argives did when they engaged the Spartans under 
the idea that they were Sicyonians.* 

7 Thus we have described the character of the 
courageous man, and of those who are taken lor 
courageous. 

But there is another point to notice. 

1 9. Couraffe is concerned, as we said, with feelins^ how wura 
both of confidence and of fear, yet it is not equally pacnand 
concerned with both, but more with occasions of fear : 

it is the man who is cool and behaves as he ought on 
such occasions that is called courageous, rather than 
he who behaves thus on occasions that inspire con- 
fidence. 

And so, as we said, men are called courageous for 
enduring painful things. 

2 Courage, therefore, brings pain, and is justly 
praised ; for it is harder to endure what is painful 
than to abstain from what is pleasant. 

I do not, of course, mean to say that the end of 

* The incident is narrated by Xenophon, Hell., it. 10. 



90 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. IBk. m. 

courage is not pleasant^ but that it seems to be hidden 
from view by the attendant circumstances, as is the 
case in gymnastic contests also. Boxers, for instance, 
have a pleasant end in view, that fcr which they 
strive, the crown and the honours; but the blows 
they receive are grievous to flesh and blood, and 
painful, and so are all the labours they undergo ; and 
as the latter are many, while the end is small^ the 
pleasantness of the end is hardly apparent. 

If, then, the case of courage is analogous, death s 
and wounds will be pain;ful to the courageous man 
and against his will, but he endures them because it 
is noble to do so or base not to do so. 

And the more he is endowed with every virtue, 4 
and the happier he is, the more grievous will death 
be to him ; for life is more worth living to a man of 
his sort than to any one else, and he deprives himself 
knowingly of the very best things ; and it is painful 
to do that. But he is no less courageous because he 5 
feels this pain; nay, we may say he is even more 
courageous, because in spite of it he chooses noble 
conduct in battle in preference to those good things. 
I. Thus we see that the rule that the exercise of a 
virtue is pleasant * does not apply to all the virtues, 
except in so far as the end is attained. 

Still there is, perhaps, no reason why men of this 6 
character should not be less efficient as soldiers than 
those who are not so courageous, but have nothing 
good to lose ; for such men are reckless of risk, and 
will sell their lives for a small price. 

Here let us close our account of courage ; it will 7 

♦ C/. L 8, 10, f. 



9, 3-10, 4] TEMPERANCE. 91 

not be hard to gather an outline of its nature from 
what we have said. 

10. After courage, let us speak of temperance, or temper. 
for these two seem to be the virtues of the irrational *^ 
parts of our nature. 

We have already said that temperance is modera- 
tion or dbservance of the mean with regard to 
pleasures (for it is not concerned with pains so much, 
nor in the same manner); profligacy also manifests 
itself in the same field. 

Let us now determine what kind of pleasures 
these are. 

First, let us accept as established the distinction 
between the pleasures of the body and the pleasures 
of the soul, such as the pleasures of gratified ambition 
or love of learning. 

When he who loves honour or learning is 
delighted by that which he loves, it is not his body 
that is affected, but his mind. But men are not 
called either temperate or profligate for their be- 
haviour with regard to these pleasures ; nor for their 
behaviour with regard to any other pleasures that 
are not of the body. For instance, those who are 
fond of gossip and of telling stories, and spend their aA /j 
days in trifles, are called babblers, but not profligate ; O^^a*^ 
nor do we apply this term to those who are pained 
beyond measure at the loss of money or friends. 

Temperance, then, will be concerned with the 
pleasures of the body, but not with all of these even : 
for those who delight in the use of their eyesight, in 
colours and forms and painting, are not called either 
temperate or profligate ; and yet it would seem that 



/ 



92 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF AKISTOTLE. [Bk. IIL 

it is possible to take delight in these things too as 
one ought, and also more or less than one ought. 

Ati<^ so with the sense of hearing : a man is never 5 
called profligate for takmg an excessive delight in 
music or in acting, nor temperate for taking a proper 
delight in them. 

Nor are these terms applied with respect to the 6 
sense of smell, except accidentally.' We do not say 
that those who delist in the smell of froit or roses 
or incense are profligate, but rather those who delight 
in the smell of unguents and savoury dishes ; for the 
profligate delights in these smells because they re- 
mind him of the things that he lusts after. 

Tou may, indeed, see other people taking delight 7 
in the smell of food when they are hungry; but only 
a profligate takes delight in such smells [constantly], 
as he alone is [constantly] lusting after such things. 

The lower animals, moreover, do not get pleasure 8 
through these senses, except accidentally. It is not 
the scent of a hare that delights a dog, but the eating 
of it; only the announcement comes through his 
sense of smelL The lion rejoices not in the lowing 
of the ox, but in the devouring of him ; but as the 
lowing announces that the ox is near, the lion appears 
to delight in the sound itself. So also, it is not seeing 
or discovering a stag or a wild goat that pleases him, 
but the anticipation of a meaL 

Temperance and profligacy, then, have to do with 9 
those kinds of pleasure which are common to the 
lower animals, for which reason they seem to be 
slavish and brutal; I mean the pleasures of touch 
and taste. 



10, 5-11, 1.] TEMPEBANOB. 93 

Taste, however, seems to play but a small part 
here, or perhaps no part at alL For it is the function 
of taste to distinguish flavours, as is done by wine- 
tasters and by those who season dishes ; but it is by 
no means this discrimination of objects that gives 
delight (to profligates, at any rate), but the actual 
enjoyment of them, the medium of which is always 
the sense of touch, alike in the pleasures of eating, 
of drinking, and of sexual intercourse. 

And hence a certain gourmand wished that his 
throat were longer than a crane's, thereby implying 
that his pleasure was derived from the sense of touch. 

That sense, then, with which profligacy is concerned 
is of all senses the commonest or most widespread; ^/ 
and so profligacy would seem to be deservedly of all 
vices the most censured, inasmuch as it attaches not 
to our human, but to our animal nature. 

To set one's delight in things of this kind, then, 
and to love them more than all things, is brutish. 

And further, the more manly sort even of the 
pleasures of touch are discarded by the profligate, 
such as the pleasures which the gymnast finds in 
rubbing and the warm bath ; for the profligate does 
not cultivate the sense of touch over his whole body, 
but in certain parts only. 

11. Now, of our desires or appetites some appear 
to be common to the race, others to be individual and 
acquired. 

Thus the desire of food is natural [or common to 
the race] ; every man when he is in want desires meat 
or drink, or sometimes both, and sexual intercourse, as 
Homer says, when he is young and vigorous. 



9 4 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. IIL 

But not all men desire to satisfy their wants in 
this or that particular way, nor do all desire the same 
things ; and therefore such desire appears to be pecu- 
liar to ourselves, or individuaL 

Of course it is also partly natural : diflferent people 2 
are pleased by different things, and yet there are 
some things which all men like better than others. 

Firstly, then, in the matter of our natural or 3 
\ common desires but few err, and that only on one 
side, viz. on the side of excess ; e,g. to eat or drink of 
whatever is set before you till you can hold no more 
is to exceed what is natural in point of quantity, 
for natural desire or appetite is for the filling of 
our want simply. And so such people are called 
" belly-mad," implying that they fill their bellies too 
full. 

It is only utterly slavish natures that acquire this 
vice. 

Secondly, with regard to those pleasures that are 4 
individual [i.e. which attend the gratification of our 
individual desires] many people 6rr in various ways. 

People are called fond of this or that because they 
delight either in wrong things, or in undue measure, 
or as the many do, or in a wrong fashion. Now, in 
all these ways the profligates exceed. They delight in 
some things in which they ought not to delight (since 
they are hateful things), and if it be right to delight 
in any of these things they delight in them more than 
is right, and as the many do. 

It is plain, then, that excess in these pleasures is 5 
profligacy, and is a thing to be blamed. 

But in respect of the corresponding pains the case 



TEMPERANCE. 

is not the same here as it was with regard to courage; 
a man is not called temperate for bearing them, and 
profligate for not bearing them; hut the profligate 
mania called profligate for heingmore pained than he 
ought at not getting certain pleasant thioga (his pain 
being caused by hia pleasure*), and the temperate 
man ia called temperate because the absence of these 
pleasant things or the abstinence from them ia not 
painful to him. 

6 The profligate, then, desires all pleasant things or 
those that are most intensely pleasant, and is led by 
his desire so as to choose these in preference to all other 
things. And so he is constantly pained by failing to 
get tbera and by lusting after them : for all appetite 
involves pain; but it seems a strange thing to be 
pained for the sake of pleasure. 

r People who fall short in the matter of pleasure^, 
and take leas delight than they ought in these things, 
are hardly found at all ; for this sort of insens: 
is scarcely in human natura And indeed even the 
lower animals discriminate kinds of food, and delight 
in some and not in others; and a being to whom 
nothing was pleasant, and who found no difference 
between one thing and another, would be very far 
removed from being a man. We have no name for 
such a being, because he does not exist. 

1 But the temperate man observes the mean in these 
things. He takes no pleasure in those things that 
the profligate most delights in (but rather disdains 



• Cf. VII, 14, 2; "the oppoaite of this 
going -without B wronK pleasure] ia not pain, 
gsta hia heart on this escBHsiTe pleaanro." 



opl™ 



reI.-.< 



except to the man who 



96 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF AEISTOTLB. [Bk. IH. 

them), nor generally in the wrong things, nor very 
much in any of these things,* and when they are 
absent he is not pained, nor does he desire them, or 
desires them but moderately, not more than he ought, 
nor at the wrong time, etc. ; but those things which, 
being pleasant, at the same time conduce to health 
and good condition, he will desire moderately and in 
the right manner, and other pleasant things also, pro- 
vided they are not injurious, or incompatible with 
what is noble, or beyond his means ; for he who cares 
for them then, cares for them more than is fitting, and 
the temperate man is not apt to do that, but rather 
to be guided by right reason. 

row pro/It- v.- 12. Profligacy seems to be more voluntary than l 

^unuiry^ cowardicc. 

^rdice. FoT a man is impelled to the former by pleasure, 

to the latter by pain ; but pleasure is a thing we choose, 
while pain is a thing we avoid. Pain puts us beside 2 
ourselves and upsets the nature of the sufferer, while 
pleasure has no such effect, but leaves free play to the 
\ wilL 

''^^ Profligacy is for these reasons more to be blamed 
than cowardice, and for another reason too, viz. that 
it is easier to train one's self to behave rightly on these 
occasions [i.e. those in which profligacy is displayed]; 
for such occasions are constantly occurring in our 
lives, and the training involves no risk; but with 
occasions of fear the contrary is the case. 

Again, it would seem that the habit of mind or S 
character called cowardice is more volimtary than 
the particular acts in which it is exhibited. It is not 

* i,e, the pleasures of taste and tonoh. 



18, 1-7.] TEMPEBANCB, 97 

painful to be a coward, but the occasions which exhibit 
cowardice put men beside themselves through fear of 
pain, so that they throw away their arms and alto- 
gether disgrace themselves ; and hence these particular 
acts are even thought to be compulsory. 

In the case of the profligate, on the contrary, the 
particular acts are voluntary (for they are done with 
appetite and desire), but the character itself less so ; 
for no one desires to be a profligate. 

The term " profligacy " we apply also to childish 
faults,* for they have some sort of resemblance. It 
makes no difference for our present purpose which of 
the two is named after the other, but it is plain that 
the later is named after the earlier. 

And the metaphor, I think, is not a bad one: what 
needs " chastening " or " correction " t is that which 
inclines to base things and which has great powers of 
expansion. Now, these characteristics are nowhere 
BO strongly marked as in appetite and in childhood ; 
children too [as well as the profligate] live according 
to their appetites, and the desire for pleasant things is 
most pronounced in them. If then this element be not 
submissive and obedient to the governing principle, 
it will make great head : for the desire for pleasant 
things is insatiable, and in an irrational being is ready 
to satisfy itself in any way, and the exercise of the 
appetite increases the natural tendency: and if the 
desires are great and intense they will even thrust out 
reason altogether : so it is needful that they be few 

* Of cotirse the Englisli term is not so used, 
t K6\a/ffiSf chasteniug; iuc6\a(TTos, uncliastened, inoorrigiblet 
psx>fiigate. 

H 



^/ 



98 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OP ARISTOTLE. CBk. m 

and moderate, and in no respect opposed to reason. 
But 'when this part of our nature is in this state 8 
we call it submissive and "chastened;" for as a child 
should live in subjection to his tutor, so should the 
appetites be subject to reason. 
\y And so the appetites of the temperate man should 9 
be in harmony with his reason; for the aim of both 
is that which is noble: the temperate man desires 
what he ought, and as he ought, and when he ought; 
and this again is what reason prescribes. 

This, then, may be taken as an account of tem- 
perance. 



BOOK IV. 
THE SAME — Contimud. 

1 1. Liberality, of which we will next speak, o/nberaii 
seems to be moderation in the matter of wealth. 
What we commend in a liberal man is his behaviour, 

not in war, nor in those circumstances in which tem- 
perance is commended, nor yet in passing judgment, 
but in the giving and taking of wealth, and especially 

2 in the giving — wealth meaning all those things whose 
value can be measured in money. 

3 But both prodigality and illiberality are at once ^ 
excess and defect in the matter of wealth. 

Illiberality always means caring for wealth more 
than is right; but prodigality sometimes stands for 
a combination of vicea Thus incontinent people, 
who squander their money in riotous living, are called 

4 prodigals. And so prodigals are held to be very 
worthless individuals, as they combine a number of 
vices. 

But we must remember that this is not the proper 

5 use of the term ; for the term " prodigal " (aawrog) is 
intended to denote a man who has one vice, viz. that 
of wasting his substance : for he is aawroc,* or " pro- 
digal," who is destroyed through his own fault, and 

* iffwroSf a priy. and aQs, fftiCuy* 



V 



100 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OP AEISTOTLE. [Bk. IV. 

the wasting of one's substance is held to be a kind 
of destruction of one's self, as one's life is dependent 
upon it This, then, we regard as the proper sense 
of the term " prodigality." 

Anything that has a use may be used well or ilL 6 
Now, riches is abundance of useful things (ra 

But each thing is best used by him who has the 
virtue that is concerned with that thing. 

Therefore he will use riches best who has the 
virtue that is concerned with wealth * (ra ^PW^to), 
i.e, the liberal man. 
\\ Now, the ways of using wealth are spending and 7 

giving, while taking and keeping are rather the ways 
of acquiring wealth. And so it is more distinctive of 
the liberal man to give to the right people than to 
take from the right source and not to take from the 
.^ wrong source. For it is more distinctive of virtue to 
do good to others than to have good done to you, 
and to do what is noble than not to do what is base. 
And here it is plain that doing good and noble 8 
actions go with the giving, while receiving good and 
not doing what is base goes with the taking. 

Again, we are thankful to him who gives, not to 
him who does not take; and so also we praise the 
former rather than the latter. 

Again, it is easier not to take than to give; for we 9 
-^^^ are more inclined to be too stingy with our own 
goods than to take another's. 

♦ The connection is plainer in the original, because ra, xfyfifuma^ 
" wealth," is at once seen to be identical with rh xp'h^^y^ " useful 
things, *' and connected with xp^ia, " use." 



1, 6-16.] LIBERALITY 101 

LO Again, it is those who give that are commonly 
called liberal; while those who abstain from taking 
are not praised for their liberality especially, but 

.1 rather for their justice; and those who take are not 
praised at alL 

Again, of all virtuous characters the liberal man is 
the most beloved, because he is useful ; but his use- 
fulness lies in his giving. 

2 But virtuous acts, we said, are noble, and are 
done for the sake of that which is noble. The liberal 
man, therefore, like the. others, will give with a view 
to, or for the sake of, that which is noble, and give • 
rightly ; i,e. he will give the right things to the right 
persons at the right times — in short, his giving will 
have aU the characteristics of right giving. 

3 Moreover, his giving will be pleasant to him, or at l/"^ 
least painless; for virtuous acts are always pleasant 

or painless— certainly very far from being painful 

4 He who gives to the wrong persons, or gives from 
some other motive than desire for that which is noble, 
is not liberal, but must be called by some other name. 

Nor is he liberal who gives with pain ; for that 
shows that he would prefer * the money to the noble 
action, which is not the feeling of the liberal man. 

5 The liberal man, again, will not take from wrong 
sources; for such taking is inconsistent with the 
character of a man who sets no store by wealth. 

6 Nor will he be ready to beg a favour ; for he who 
confers benefits on others is not usually in a hurry to 
receive them. 

* Were it not for some extraneous consideration, e.g. desire to 
stand weU with his neighbours. 



102 NICOMACHBAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLB. [Bk. IV. 

But from right sources he will take (e.g. from his 17 
own property), not as if there were anything noble in 
taking, but simply as a necessary condition of giving. 
And so he will not neglect his property, since he 
wishes by means of it to help others. But he will 
refuse to give to any casual person, in order that he 
may have wherewithal to give to the right persons, at 
the right times, and where it is noble to give. 

It is very characteristic of the liberal man ♦ to 18 
go even to excess in giving, so as to leave too little 
for himself; for disregard of self is part of his 
character. 

In applying the term liberality we must take 19 
account of a mail's fortune; for it is.not the amount 
of what is given that makes a gift liberaj, but the 
liberal habit or character of the doer; and this 
character proportions the gift to the fortune of the 
giver^>^And so it is quite possible that the giver of 
the smaller sum may be the more liberal man, if his 
means be smaller. 

Those who have inherited a fortune seem to be 20 
more liberal than those who have made one ; for they 
have never known want ; and all men are particularly 
fond of what themselves have made> as we see in 
parents and poets. 

It is not easy for a liberal man to be rich, as he is 
not apt to take or to keep, but is apt to spend, and 
cares for money not on its own account, but only for 
the sake of giving it away. 

* This is strictly a departare from the virtue ; but Aristotle 
seems often to pass insensibly from the abstract ideal of a virtue to 
its imperfect embodiment in a complex character. Cf. infra, cap. 3* 



I, 17-36.3 LIBEBALITY. 103 

21 Hence the charge often brought against fortune, 
that those who most deserve wealth arc least blessed 
with it. But this is natural enough; for it is just as 
impossible to have wealth without taking trouble 
about it, as it is to have anything else. 

22 Nevertheless the liberal man will not give to the 
■wrong people, nor at the wrong times ; for if ho did, 
he would no longer be displaying true hberality, 
and, after spending thus, would not have enough to ^ 

23 spend on the right occasions. For, as we have already k 
said, he is liberal who spends in proportion to his 
fortune, on proper objects, while he who exceeds this 
is prodigal. And so princes * are not called prodigal, 
because it does not seem easy for them to exceed the 
measure of their possessions in gifts and expenses. 

2i Liberality, then, being moderation in the giving 
and taking of wealth, the liberal man will give and 
spend the proper amount on the proper objects, alike 
in small things and in great, and that with pleasure; 
and will also take the proper amount from the proper 
sources. For since the vktue is moderation in both 
giving and taking, the man who has the virtue will 
do both rightly. Right taking is consistent with 
right giving, but any other taking is contrary to it. 
Those givings and takings, then, that are consistent 
with one another are found in the same person, while 
those that are contrary to one another manifestly 
are not. 

15 But if a liberal man happen to spend anything in 



* No Eingle English word can ccnvej tlis asBoaiatiaiis of tLe 
Greeb tifwvm, a monarch who has seixed Bbsaluta power, aob 
jwcesaarll; one who abases it. 



Il 



J 



104 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLB. [Bk. It. 

a manner contrary to what is right and noble, he will 
be pained, but moderately and in due measure ; for 
it is a characteristie of virtue to be pleased and pained 
on the right occasions and in due measure. 

The liberal man, again, is easy to deal with in 26 
money matters; it is not hard to cheat him, as he 
does not value wealth, and is more apt to be vexed 
at having failed to spend where he ought, than to be 
pained at having spent where he ought not — ^th^ sort 2fi 
of man that Simonides would not commend.* 

The prodigal, on the other hand, errs in these 2i 
points also ; he is not pleased on the right occasions 
nor in the right way, nor pained : but this wilL be 
clearer as we go on. 

We have already said that both prodigality and as 
illiberality are at once excess and deficiency, in two 
things, viz. giving and taking (expenditure being 
included in giving). Prodigality exceeds in giving 
and in not taking, but falls short in taking; illiber- 
ality falls short in giving, but exceeds in taking — in 
small things, we must add 

Now, the two elements of prodigality- are not 30 
commonly united in the same person : f it is not 
easy for a man who never takes to be always giving ; 
for private persons soon exhaust their means of 
giving, and it is to private persons that the name is 
generally applied.} 

A prodigal of this kind [ie. in whom both the 31 

* The sa/ing referred to seems to be lost. 

f i,e, in men of some age and fixed oharacter ; they often coexist 
in very joung men, he says, but cannot possibly coexist for long. 
{ As he has already said in effect, sujpra, § 23« 



1, 20-36] LIBEBALITY. 105 

elements are combined], we must observe, would seem 
to be not a little better than an illiberal man. For 
he is easily cured by advancing years and by lack of 
means, and may come to the middle course. For he 
has the essential points of the liberal character; he 
gives and abstains from taking, though he does neither 
well nor as he ought. If then he can be trained to 
this, or if in any other way this change in his nature 
can be effected, he will be liberal ; for then he will 
give to whom he ought, and will not take whence he 
ought not. And so he is generally thought to be not 
a bad character ; for to go too far in giving and in f /' 
not taking does not show a vicious or ignoble nature 
so much as a foolish one. 

A prodigal of this sort, then, seems to be much 
better than an illiberal man, both for the reasons 
already given, and also because the former does good 
to many, but the latter to no one, not even to himsel£ 

But most prodigals, as has been said, not only give 
wrongly, but take from wrong sources, and are in this 
respect illiberal They become grasping because they 
.wish to sp^nd, but cannot readily do so, as their 
supplies soon fail. So they are compelled to draw 
from other sources. At the same time, since they care 
nothing for what is noble, they will take quite reck- 
lessly from any source whatever; for they long to 
give, but care not a whit how the money goes or 
whence it comes. 

And so their gifts are not liberal ; for they are not 
noble, nor are they give6 with a view to that which 
is noble, nor in the right manner. Sometimes they 
enrich those who ought to be poor, and will give 



106 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. IV. 

nothing to men of well-regulated character, while 
they give a great deal to those who flatter them, or . 
furnish them with any other pleasure. And thus the v 
greater part of them are profligates ; for, being ready 
to part with their money, they are apt to lavish^ it on 
riotous living, and as they do not shape their lives 
with a view to that which is noble, they easily fall 
away into the pursuit of pleasure. 

The prodigal, then, if he fail to find guidance, 36 
comes to this, but if he get training he may be brought 
to the moderate and right course. 
\ ' But illiberality is incurable ; for old age and all 37 

loss of power seems to make men illiberal 

It also runs in the blood more than prodigality; 
the generality of men are more apt to be fond of 
money than of giving. 

Again, it is far-reaching, and has many forms ; for 38 
there seem to be many ways in which one can be 
illiberal. 

It consists of two parts — deficiency in giving, and 
excess of taking; but it is not always found in its 
entirety; sometimes the parts are separated, and 
one man exceeds in taking, while another falls short 
in giving. Those, for instance, who are called by such 81 
names as niggardly, stingy, miserly, all fall short 
in giving, but do not covet other people's goods, or 
wish to take them. 

Some are impelled to this conduct by a kind of 
honesty, or desire to avoid what is disgraceful — I 
mean that some of them seem, or at any rate profess, 
to be saving, in order that they may never be com- 
pelled to do anything disgraceful; e.g. the cheese- 



A^ 



1, 36-43.] LIBEBALITY. 107 

parer * (and those like him), who is so named because 
of the extreme lengths to which he carries his un- 
willingness to give. 

But others are moved to keep their hands from 
their neighbours' goods only by fear, believing it to 
be no easy thing to take the goods of others, without 
having one's own goods taken in turn ; so they are 
content with neither taking nor giving. 

Others, again, exceed in the matter of taking so far 
as to make any gain they can in any way whatever, 
e.g. those who ply debasing trades, brothel-keepers 
and such like, and usurers who lend out small sums 
at a high rate. For all these make money from im- 
proper sources to an improper extent. 

The common characteristic of these last seems to 
be the pursuit of base gain ; for all of them endure 
reproach for the sake of gain, and that a small gain. 
For those who make improper gains in improper ways 
on a large scale are not called illiberal, e.g, tyrants who 
sack cities and pillage temples ; they are rather called 
wicked, impious, unjust. The dice-sharper, however, 
and the man who steals clothes at the bath, or the 
common thief, are reckoned among the illiberal ; for 
they all make base gains ; i.e. both the thief and the 
sharper ply their trade and endure reproach for gain, 
and the thief for the sake of his booty endui'es the 
greatest dangers, while the sharper makes gain out of 
his friends, to whom he ought to give. Both then, 
•wishing to make gain in improper ways, are seekers 
of base gain ; and all such ways of making money are 
illiberal 

• Lit. " oummin-Bplitter,** 



nificence. 



108 NICOMAOHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk IV. 

^ ^^ Thus Uliberality is rightly called the opposite of 

liberalityXfor it is a worse evil than prodigality, and 
men are more apt to err in this way than in that 
which we have described as prodigality. 

Let this, then, be taken as our account of liberality, i 
and of the vices that are opposed to it. 
ofma0r^<r 2. Our next ta^k would seem to be an examina- 1 
tion of magnificence. For this also seems to be a 
virtue that is concerned with wealth. 

But it does not, like liberality, extend over the 
whole field of money transactions, but only over those 
that involve large expenditiire ; and in these it goes 
beyond liberality in largeness. For, as its very name 
(juLeyaXoTrpiTTBia) suggests, it is suitable expenditure on 
a large scale. But the largeness is relative : the 2 
expenditure that is suitable for a man who is fitting 
out a war-ship is not the same as that which is suit- 
able for the chief of a sacred embassy. 

What is suitable, then, is relative to the person, 3 
and the occasion, and the business on hand. Yet he 
who spends what is fitting on trifling or moderately 
important occasions is not called magnificent; e.g, 
the man who can say, in the words of the poet— 

" To many a wandering beggar did I give ; " 

but he who spends what is fitting on great occa^ons. 
For the magnificent man is liberal, but a man may be 
liberal without being magnificent. 
<i The deficiency of this quality is called meanness ; i 
the excess of it is called vulgarity, bad taste, etc. ; 
the characteristic of which is not spending too much 
on proper objects, but spending ostentatiously on im- 



\ 



1, 44r-2, 10.] MAGNIFIOBNOB. 109 

proper objects and in improper fashion. But we will 
speak of them presently. 

But the magnificent man is like a skilled artist ; 
he can see what a case requires, and can spend great 
sums tastefully. For, as we said at the outset, a 
habit or type of character takes its complexion 
from the acts in which it issues and the things it 
produces. 

The magnificent man's expenses, therefore, must be 
great and suitable. 

What he produces then will also be of the same 
nature; for only thus will the expense be at once 
great and suitable to the result. 

The result, then, must be proportionate to the ex- 
penditure, and the expenditure proportionate to the 
result, or even greater. 

Moreover, the magnificent man's motive in thus 
spending his money will be desire for that which is 
noble ; for this is the common characteristic of all the 
virtues. 

Further, he will spend gladly and lavishly ; for a 
minute calculation of cost is mean. He will inquire 
how the work can be made most beautiful and most 
elegant, rather than what its cost will be, and how 
it can be done most cheaply. 

So the magnificent man must .be liberal also ; for 
the liberal man, too, will spend the right amount in 
the right manner; only, both the amount and the 
manner being right, magnificence is distinguished from 
liberality (which has the same sphere of action) by 
greatness — I mean by actual magnitude of amount 
spent : and secondly, where the amount spent is the 



110 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. IV. 

same, the result of the magnificent man's expenditure 
will be more magnificent* 

For the excellence of a possession is not the same 
as the excellence of a product or work of art: as a 
possession, that is most precious or estimable which is 
worth most, e.g. gold ; as a work of art, that is most 
estimable which is great and beautiful : for the sight 
of such a work excites admiration, and a magnificent 
thing is always admirable ; indeed, excellence of work 
on a great scale is magnificence. 

Now, there is a kind of expenditure which is U 
called in a special sense estimable or honourable, such 
as expenditure on the worship of the gods {e.g. 
offerings, temples, and sacrifices), and likewise all ex- 
penditure on the worship of heroes, ahd again all 
public service which is prompted by a noble ambi- 
tion ; e.g. a man may think proper to furnish a chorus 
or a war-ship, or to give a public feast, in a hand- 
some style. 

But in all cases, as we have said, we must have 12 
regard to the person who spends, and ask who, he is, 
and what his means are; for expenditure should be 
proportionate to means, and be suitable not only to 
the result but to the persons who spend. 

And so a poor man cannot be magnificent : he 18 
has not the means to spend large sums suitably : if he 
tries, he is a fool ; for he spends disproportionately and 
in a wrong way; but an act must be done in the 

• A worthy expenditure of £100,000 would be magnificent from 
its mere amonnt; bnt even £100 may be spent in a magnificent 
manner (bj a man who can afford it), e.g. in buying a rare engraying 
to£ a public collection : cf. § 18. 



2, 11-17.] MAGNIFIOBNCB. Ill 

4 right way to be virtuous. But magnificence is becom- 
ing in those who have got the requisite means, either 
by their own efforts or through their ancestors or 
their connections, and who have birth and reputation, 
etc. ; for all these things give a man a certain great- 
ness and importance. 

.5 The magnificent man, then, is properly a man of 
this sort^ and magnificence exhibits itself most 
properly in expenditure of this kind, as we have 
said; for this is the greatest and most honourable 
kind of expenditure : but it may also be displayed 
on private occasions, when they are such as occur but 
once in a man's life, e.g. a wedding or anything of 
that kind; or when they are of special interest to 
the state or the governing classes, e.g. receiving 
strangers and sending them on their way, or making 
presents to them and returning their p;esents; fof 
the magnificent man does not lavish money on himself, 
but on public objects ; and gifts to strangers bear some 
resemblance to offerings to the gods. 

16 Again, a magnificent man will build his house in 
a style suitable to his wealth ; for even a fine house 
is a kind of public ornament. And he will spend 
money more readily on things that last ; for these are 
the noblest. 

17 And on each occasion he will provide what is suit- 
able—which is not the same for gods as for men, for 
a temple as for a tomb — ^and in his expenditure every 
detail will be great after its kind, great expenditure 
on a great occasion being the most magnificent, and 
then in a less degree that which is great for the 
occasion^ whatever it be. 



112 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OP ABISTOTLE. [Bk. IV. 

Again, the greatness of the result is not the same 18 
as the greatness of the expense ; e.gr. the most beauti- 
ful ball or the most beautiful bottle that can be got 
is a magnificent present for a child, though its price 
is something small and mean. 

And so it is characteristic of the magnificent man 19 
to do magnificently that which he does, of whatever 
kind it be ; for such work cannot easily be surpassed, 
and the result is proportionate to the expense. 

This, then, is the character of the magnificent man. 2C 

The man who exceeds (whom we call vulgar) ex- 
. ceeds, as we said, in spending improperly. He spends 
great sums on little objects, and makes an unseemly 
display ; e,g, if he is entertaining the members of his 
club, he will give them a wedding feast ; if he provides 
the chorus for a comedy, he will bring his company 
on the stage all dressed in purple, as they do at 
Megara. And all this he will do from no desire for 
what is noble or beautiful, but merely to display his 
wealth, because he hopes thereby to gain admiration, 
spending little where he should spond much, and much 
where he should spend little. 

But the mean man will fall short on every occa- 21 
sion, and, even when he spends very large sums, will 
spoil the beauty of his work by niggardliness in a 
trifle, never doing anything without thinking twice 
about it, and considering how it can be done at the 
least possible cost, and bemoaning even that, and think- 
ing he is doing everything on a needlessly large scale. 

Both these characters, then, aj-e vicious, but they 
do not bring reproach, because they are neither 
injurious to others nor very offensive in themselves. 



2, 18-3, 9.] EIGH-MINDEDNESS. 113 

3. High-mindednesa would seem from its very of high- 



m^uitedn 



name (fjieya\o\pvx(a) to have to do with great things ; 
let us first ascertain what these are. 

3 It wlQ make no difierence whether we consider 

the quality itself, or the man who exhibits the quality. []/ 
8 By a high-minded man we seem to mean "one who ] 
claims much and deserves much : for he who claims 
much without deserving it is a fool ; but the possessor 

4 of a virtue is never foolish or silly. The man we 
have described, then, is high-minded. 

He who deserves little and claims little is tem- 

5 perate [or modest], but not high-minded: for high- 
mindedness [or greatness of soul] implies great- 
ness, just as beauty implies stature ; small men may 
be neat and well proportioned, but cannot be called 
beautiful 

6 He who claims much without deserving it is l/* 
vain (though not every one who claims more than 

he deserves is vain), 

7 He who claims less than he deserves Is little- i' ' 
minded, whether his deserts be great or moderate, or 
whether they be small and he claims still less : but 
this little-mindedness is most conspicuous in him 
whose deserts are great ; for what would he do if his 
deserts were less than they are ? 

8 The high-minded man, then, in respect of the 
greatness of his deserts occupies an extreme position, 
but in that he behaves as he ought, observes the 
xnean ; for he claims that which he deserves, while all 
the others claim too much or too little. 

9 But now if he deserves much and claims much, 
and most of all deserves and claims the greatest 

I 



114 NICOMACHBAN ETHICS O* ARISTOTLE. CBk. IV. 

things, there mil be one thing with which he wiU be 
espeeially concemeA For desert has reference to 10 
external good things. Now, the greatest of external 
good things we may assume to be that which we 
render to the Oods as their due, and that which 
people in high stations most desire, and which is the 
prize appointed for the noblest deeda But the thing 
that answers to this description is honour, which, 
we may safely say, is the greatest of all external 
goods. Honours ii,nd dishonours, therefore, are the 
field in which the high-minded man behaves as he 
ought. 
'», ) And indeed we may see, without going about to ii 
prove it, that honour is what high-minded men are 
concerned with; for it is honour that great men claim 
and deserve. 

The little-minded man faUs short, whether we 
compare his claims with his own deserts or with what • 
the high-minded man claims for himself. 

The vain or conceited man exceeds what is due to 13 
himself, though he does not exceed the high-minded 
man in his claims.* 

But the high-minded man, as he deserves the 14 
greatest things, must be a perfectly good or excellent 
man ; for the better man always deserves the greater 
things, and the best possible man the greatest possible ' 
things. The really high-minded man, therefore, must 
be a good or excellent man. And indeed greatness 
in every virtue or excellence would seem to be 
necessarily implied in being a high-minded or great- 
Bouled man. 

* For that is impossible. 

r 



3, 1(^-18.] HIGH-MINDEDNESa 115 

It would be equally inconsistent with the high- 
minded man's character to run along swinging his 
arms, and to commit an act of injustice ; for what thing 
is there for love of which he would do anything 
unseemly, seeing that all things are of little account 
to him? 

Survey him point by point and you will find that 
the notion of a high-minded man that is not a good or 
excellent man is utterly absurd. Indeed, if he were 
not good, he could not be worthy of honour; for 
honour is the prize of virtue, and is rendered to the 
good as their due. y 

High-mindedness, then, seems to be the crowning V 
grace, as it were, of the virtues ; it makes them greater, 
and cannot exist without them. And on this account 
it is a hard thing to be truly high-minded ; for it is 
impossible without the union of all the virtues. 

. The high-minded man, then, exhibits his character 
especially in the matter of honours and dishonours 
and at great hoDour from good men he will be 
moderately pleased, as getting nothing more than his 
due, or even less ; for no honour can be adequate to 
complete virtue ; but nevertheless he will accept it, as 
they have nothing greater to otfer him. But honour 
from ordinary men and on trivial grounds he will 
utterly despise ; for that is not what he deserves. 
And dishonour likewise he will make light of; for he 
will never merit it. 

But though it is especially in the matter of 
honours, as we have said, that the high-minded man 
displays his character, yet he will also observe the 
mean in his feelings with regard to wealth and power 



116 NICOMAOHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. DBk. IV. 

V and all kinds of good and evil fortune, whatever may 
befall him, and will neither be very much exalted 
by prosperity, nor very much cast down by adversity; 
seeing that not even honour affects him as if it were 
a very important thing. For power and wealth are 
desirable for honour's sake (at least, those who have 
them wish to gain honour by them). He then who 
thinks lightly of honour must think lightly of them 
/ also. 

N^ And so high-minded men seem to look down upon 
everything. 

But the gifts of fortune also are commonly thought 
to contribute to high-mindednesa For those who are 19 
well born are thought worthy of honour, and those 
who are powerful or wealthy; for they are in a posi- 
tion of superiority, and that which is superior in any 
good thing is always held in greater honour. And so 
these things do make people more high-minded in a 
sense ; for such people find honour from some. But 20 
in strictness it is only the good man that is worthy of 
honour, though he that has both goodness and good 
fortune is commonly thought to be more worthy of 
honour. Those, however, who have these good things 
without virtue, neither have any just claim to great 
things, nor are properly to be called high-minded; 
for neither is possible without complete virtue. 

\ But those who have these good things readily 21 

come to be supercilious and insolent. For without 
virtue it is not easy to bear the gifts of fortune 
becomingly ; and so, being unable to bear them, and 
thinking themselves superior to everybody else, such 
people look down upon others, and yet themselves do 



3, 19-26.] HIGH-MINDEDNESS. 1 1 7 

whatever happens to please them. They imitate the 
high-minded man without being really like him, and 
they imitate him where they can ; that is to say, they 
do not exhibit virtue in their acts, but they look down 

52 upon others. Only the high-minded man never looks 
down upon others without justice (for he estimates 
them correctly), while most men do so for quite 
irrelevant reasons. 

J3 The high-minded man is not quick to run into 
petty dangers, and indeed does not love danger, since 
there are few things that he much Values ; but he is 
ready to incur a great danger, and whenever he does 
so is unsparing of his life, as a thing that is not worth 
keeping at all costs. / 

M It is his nature to confer benefits, but he is'^ 
ashamed to receive them ; for the former is the part 
of a superior, the latter of an inferior. And when 
he has received a benefit, he is apt to confer a greater 
in return; for thus his creditor will become his 
debtor and be in the position of a recipient of his 
favour. 

25 It is thought, moreover, that such men remember 
those on whom they have conferred favours better 
than those from whom they have received them ; for 
the recipient of a benefit is inferior to the benefactor, 
but such a . man wishes to be in the position of a 
superior. So he likes to be reminded of the one, but 
dislikes to be reminded of the other ; and this is the 
reason why we read * that Thetis would not mention 
to Zeus the services she had done him, and why the 
Lacedaemonians, in treating with the Athenians, re- 

• Homer, U. i. 894 f ., 603 f. 



nI 



118 NIGOMAGHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk. IY^ 

minded them of the benefits received by Sparta rather 
than of those conferred by her. 

It is characteristic of the high-minded man, again, 2( 
never or reluctantly to ask favours, but to be ready 
to confer them, and to be lofty in his behaviour to 
those who are high in station and favoured by fortune, 
but affable to those of the middle ranks ; for it is a 
difficult thing and a dignified thing to assert supe- 
riority over the former, but easy to assert it over the 
\i latterj A haughty demeanour in dealing with the 
great is quite consistent with good breeding, but in 
dealing with those of low estate is brutal, like show- 
ing off one's strength upon a cripple. 

Another of his characteristics is not to rush in 2' 
wherever honour is to be won, nor to go where others 
take the lead, but to hold aloof and to shun an enter- 
prise, except when great honour is ix) be gained, or a 
great work to be done — ^not to do many things, but 
great things and notable. 
^ Again, he must be open in his hate and in his 2( 
love ; for coucealment shows fear. 

He must care for truth more than for what men 
will think of him, and speak and act openly ; he will 
not hesitate to say all that he thinks, as he looks down 
upon mankind. So he will speak the truth, except 
when he speaks ironically; and irony he will employ 
in speaking to the generality of men. 

Another of his characteristics is that he cannot 2 
fashion his life to suit another, except he be a friend; 
for that is servile : and so all flatterers or hangers on 
of great men are of a slavish nature, and men of low 
natures become flatterera 



3, 26-34.] HIGH-MraDEDNESS. 119 

Nor is he easily moved to admiration; fornothing '^ 
ia great to him. 
) He readily forgets injuries ; for it ia not consiBtent ' 
with his character to brood on the past, especially on 
past injuries, but rather to overlook them. - 

1 He ia no goasip; he will neither talk about him- '^ 
self nor about others; for he cares not that men 
should praise him, nor that others should be blamed 
(though, on the other hand, he is not very ready to 
bestow praise) ; and so he is not apt to speak evil of 
others, not even of hia enemies, except with the ex- 
press purpose of giving offence. 

2 When an event happens that cannot be helped or 
ia of slight importance, he is the last man in the 
world to cry out or to beg for help ; for that ia the 
conduct of a man who thinks these events very 
important. 

^ He loves to possess beautiful things that bring no 
profit, rather than useful things that pay; for this is 
characteristic of the man whose resources are in 
himself. 

t Further, the character of the high-minded man ^^ 
seems to require that hia gait should be slow, his 
voice deep, his speech measured; for a man is not ,(_ 
likely to he in a hurry when there are few things in ' 
which he is deeply interested, nor excited when he 
holds nothing to be of very great importance: and 
these are the causes of a high voice and rapid move- 
menta 

This, then, ia the character of the high-minded man. 
But he that is deficient in this quality ia called 
litt'Ie-minded ; he that exceeda, vain or conceited. 



120 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF AHlSTOTLE. [Bk.IV. 

Now these two also do not seem to be bad — for lu 
they do no harm — though they are in error. 
\ For the little-minded man, though he deserves 
good things, deprives himself of that which he 
deserves, and so seems to be the worse for not claim- 
ing these good things, and for misjudging himself; 
for if he judged right he would desire what he 
deserves, as it is good. I do not mean to say that 
such people seem to be fools, but rather too re- 
tiring. But a misjudgment of this kind does seem 
actually to make them worse; for men strive for 
that which they deserve, and shrink from noble deeds 
and employments of which they think themselves 
unworthy, as well as from mere external good things. 
\ But vain men are fools as well as ignorant of 86 

themselves, and make this plain to all the world ; for, 
not doubting their worth, they undertake honourable 
offices, and presently stand convicted of incapacity: 
they dress in fine clothes and put on fine airs and so 
on; they wish everybody to know of their good 
fortune ; they talk about themselves, as if that were 
the way to honour. 
>j But little-mindedness is more opposed to high- 87 
mindedness than vanity is ; for it is both commoner 
and worse. 

High-mindedness, then, as we have said^ has to do 8( 
with honour on a large scale. 
u^i^^^ 4. But it appears (as we said at the outset) that 1 
^^ there is also a virtue concerned with honour, which 
bears the same relation to high-mindedness that 
liberality bears to magnificence ; i.e, both the virtue 
in question and liberality have nothing to do with 



3, 35-4, 5.] HIGH-MIKBEDNESS. Ht 

great thiDgs, but cause us to behave properly in 

2 matters of moderate or of trifling importance. Just 
as in the taking and giving of money it is possible 
to observe the mean, and also to exceed or fall short 
of it, so it is possible in desire for honour to go too 
far or not far enough, or, again, to desire honour from 
the right source and in the'right manner. 

3 A man is called ambitious or fond of honour 
(0tAoT(jLcoc) in reproach, as desiring honoiu: more than 
he ought, and from wrong sources; and a man is 
called unambitious, or not fond of honour (a(j>i- 
XoTifjLog) in reproach, as not desiring to be honoured 
even for noble deeds. 

But sometimes a man is called ambitious or fond 
of honour in praise, as being manly and fond of 
noble things; and sometimes a man is called un- 
ambitious or not fond of honour in praise, as being 
moderate and temperate (as we said at the outset). 
i It is plain, then, that there are various senses 
in which a man is said to be fond of a thing, and 
that the term fond of honpur has not always the 
same sense, but that as a term of praise it means 
fonder than most men, and as a term of reproach it 
means fonder than is right. But, as there is no re- 
cognized term for the observanqe of the mean, the ex- 
tremes fight, so to speak, for what seems an empty place. 
But wherever there is excess and defect there is also 
a mean : and honour is in fact desired more than is 
right, and less: therefore * it may also be desired to the 
right degree ; at least, this character is praised as ob- 
servance of the mean in the matter of honour, though it 

• Beading Hffri 8^ with aU the best MSS. 



ess. 



V 



122 KICOMACHBAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLK [Bk. IV. 

has no recognized name. Compared with ambition, 
it seems to be lack of ambition ; compared with lack 
of ambition, it seems to be ambition; compared with 
both at once^ it seems in a wa; to be both at once. 
This, we may observe, also happens in the case of 6 
the other virtues. But in this case the extreme 
characters seem to be opposed to one another [instead 
of to the moderate character], because the character 
that observes the mean has no recognized name. 
^genoe^ 6. Gcntlcness is a kind of moderation with respect l 

to anger; but there is no recognized name for him 
who strictly observes the mean, and scarcely any 
recognized names for those who go into extremes; 
and so, though the term gentleness properly denotes 
an inclination towards deficiency in anger (for which 
also there is no proper name), we sometimes apply it 
to the man who observes the mean.* 

The excess may be called wrathfulness ; for the 2 
emotion concerned is wrath or anger, though the 
things that cause it are many and various. 

He then who is angry on the right occasions and 3 
with the right persons, and also in the right manner, 
and at the right season, and for the right length of 
time, is praised ; we will call him gentle, therefore, 
since gentleness is used as a term of praise. For the 

• This seems the only way of constraing the passage as it 
stands, for the context itself shows that he cannot mean ** there is a 
name for the quality thongh none for the man," not to mention 
that II. 7, 10 says distinctly " there is no recognized name for the 
quality." But it is possible that irpa^ris 8* has crept in, and that 
the passage should begin *E<rTl /li^y, etc.; then it runs smoothly 
enough : ** there is a moderation in anger : we will call it vpaoniSf 
though this term properly denotes an inclination to deficiency." 



4, 6-5, 8.] GENTLENESS. 123 

man who is called gentle wishes not to lose his 
balance, and not to be carried away by his emotions 
or passions, but to be angry only in such manner, 
and on such occasions, and for such period as reason 

4 shall prescribe. But he seems to err rather on the 
side of deficiency ; he is loth to take vengeance and 
very ready to forgive. "^ , 

5 But the deficiency — call it wrathlessness or 
what you will — ^is censured. Those who are not 
angered by what ought to anger them seem to be 
foolish, and so do those who are not angry as and 

6 when and with whom they ought to be ; for such a 
man seems to feel nothing and to be pained by 
nothing, and, as he is never angered, to lack spirit to 
defend himself. But to suffer one's self to be insulted, X/ 
or to look quietly on while one's friends are being 
insulted, shows a slavish nature. 

7 It is possible to exceed in all points, {.e. to be 
angry with persons with whom one ought not, and 
at things at which qAe ought not to be angry, and 
more than one ought, and more quickly, and for a 
longer time. All these errors, however, are not found 
in the same person. That would be impossible; for 
evil is self-destructive, and, if it appears in its entirety, 
becomes quite unbearable. 

8 So we find that wrathful men get angry very 
soon, and with people with whom and at things 
at which they ought not, and more than they ought; 
but they soon get over their anger, and that is a very 
good point in their character. And the reason is that 
they do not keep in their anger, but, through the 
quickness of their temper, at once retaliate, and so let 



^^l 



124 NIOOMAOHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk. IV. ' 

what is in them come to light, and then have done 
with it. 

But those who are called choleric are excessively 9 
quick-tempered, and apt to be angered at anything 
and on any occasion ; whence the name (aKpoxoXoi). 

Sulky men are hard to appease and their anger ifl 
lasts long, because they keep it in. For so soon as 
we retaliate we are relieved : vengeance makes us 
cease from our anger, substituting a pleasant for a 
painful state. But the sulky man, as he does not thus 
relieve himself, bears the burden of his wrath about 
with him ; for no one even tries to reason him out of 
it, as he does not show it, and it takes a long time 
to digest one's anger within one's self. Such men 
are exceedingly troublesome to themselves and their 
dearest friends. 

Lastly, hard (xoXcttoc) is the name we give to 11 
those who are offended by things that ought not to 
offend them, and more than they ought, and for a 
longer time, and who will not be appeased without 
vengeance or punishment. 

Of the two extremes the excess is the more opposed 12 
to gentleness ; for it is commoner (as men are naturally 
more inclined to veiigeance)7 and a hard-tempered 
person is worse to live with [than one who is too 
easy-tempered]. 

What we said some time ago * is made abundantly 13 
manifest by what we have just been saying; it is not 
easy to define how, and with whom, and at what, and 
for how long one ought to be angry — how far it is 
right to go, and at what point misconduct begins. 

• n. 9, 7. 



6, 9-6, 3J AGBEEABLENESS. 125 

He who errs slightly from the right course is not 
blamed, whether it be on the side of excess or of , 
deficiency; for sometimes we praise those who fall 
short and call them gentle, and sometimes those who 
behave hardly are called manly,- as being able to rule. 
But what amount and kind of error makes a man 
blamable can scarcely be defined; for it depends 
upon the pai^ticular circumstances of each case, and 
can only be decided by immediate perception. 
L4 But so much at least is manifest, that on the one 
hand the habit which observes the mean is to be 
praised, i.e. the habit which causes us to be angry 
with the right persons, at the right things, in the right 
manner, etc. ; and that, on the otfier hand, all habits 
of excess or deficiency deserve censure — slight censure 
if the error be trifling, graver censure if it be con- 
siderable, and severe censure if it be great. 

1 6. It is evident, therefore, that we must strive for 
the habit which observes the mean. 

This then may be taken as our account of the 
habits which have to do with anger. 

In the matter of social intercourse, i.e. the living or offree^ 
with others and joining with them in conversation 
, and in common occupations, some men show them- r 
selves what is called obsequious — those who to 
please you praise everything, and never object to 
anything, but think they ought always to avoid 

2 giving pain to those whom they meet. Those who 
take the opposite line, and object to everything and '., >. 
never think for a moment what pain they may give, 

are called cross and contentious. 

3 It is sufficiently plain that both these habits 



\y-' 






126 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OP ARISTOTLE. CBk. IV 

merit censure, and ihat the habit which takes the 
middle course between them is to be commended — 
the habit which makes a man acquiesce in what ho 
ought and in the right manner, and likewise refuse 
to acquiesce. This habit or type of character has no i 
recognized name, but seems most nearly to resemble 
friendliness (<fn\la). For the man who exhibits this 
moderation is the same sort of man that we mean 
when we speak of an upright fi:iend, except that 
then affection also is implied. This differs firom i 
friendliness in that it does not imply emotion and 
affection for those with whom we associate; for he 
who has this quality acquiesces when he ought, not 
because he loves or hates, but because that is his 
character. He will behave thus alike to those whom 
he knows and to those whom he does not know, to 
strangers and to acquaintances, to those with whom 
he is intimate and to those with whom he is not, 
only that in each case he will behave as is fitting; 
for we are not bound to show the same consideration 
to strangers as to intimates, nor to take the same 
care not to pain them. 

We have already said in general terms that such 6 
a man will behave as he ought in his intercourse 
with others, but we must add that, while he tries to 
contribute to the pleasure of others and to avoid 
giving them pain, he will always be guided by refer- 
ence to that which is noble and fitting. It seems to 1 
be with the pleasures and pains of social intercourse 
that he is concerned. Now, whenever he finds that 
it is not noble, or is positively hurtful to himself, to 
contribute to any of these pleasures^ he will refuse to 



8, 4-7, L] TBUTHPULNESfl. 127 

acquiesce and will prefer to give^pain. And if the 
pleasure is such as to involve discredit^ and no slight 
discredit, or some injury to him who is the source 
of it, while his opposition will give a little pain, 
he will not acquiesce, but will set his face against 

8 it. But he will behave differently according as he is 
in the company of greatj)eople or ordinary^ jieople, 
of intimate friends or mere acquaintances, and so on, 
rendering to each his due; preferring, apart from 
other considerations, to promote pleasure, and loth to 
give pain, but regulating his conduct by consideration 
of the consequences, if they be considerable — by con- 

9 sideration, I mean, of what is noble and fitting. And 
thus for the sake of great pleasure in the future he 
will inflict a slight pain now. 

The man who observes the mean, then, is some- 
thing of this sort, but has no recognized name. ' 

The man who always makes himself pleasant, if ' 
he aims simply at pleasing and has no ulterior object 
in view, is called ob sequi ous ; but if he does so in 
order to get some profit for himself, either in the way ^ ^ ^ 
of money or of money's worth, he is a flatterer. 

But he who sets his face against everything is, as 
we have already said, cross and contentious. 

But the extremes seem here to be opposed to one 
another [instead of to the mean], because there is no 
name for the mean. 
I 7. The moderation which avoids boastfulness oftruth^ 
(which 'virtue also lacks a name) seems to display * 
itself in almost the same field. 

It will be as well to examine these qualities also ; 
for we shall know more about human character, when 



1 28 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. IV. 

we have gone through each of its forms ; and we shall 
be more fully assured that the virtues are modes of 
observing the mean, when we have surveyed them all 
and found that this is the case with every one of 
them. 

We have already spoken of the characters that 

are displayed in social intercourse in the matter of 

-^ pleasure and pain; let us now go on to speak in like 

:^--^''" manner of those who show themselves truthful or 

untruthful in what they say and do, and in the 

pretensions they put forward. ^^^ 

^ First of all, then, the boaster seems to be fond of 2 
pretending to things that men esteem, though he has 
them not, or not to such extent as he pretends ; the 3 
ironical man, on the other hand, seems to disclaim 
..- y what he has, or to depreciate it; while he who ob- 4 
serves the mean, being a man who is "always himself'* 
{avQiKCLGTOQ tlq), is truthful in word and deed, con- 5 
fessing the simple facts about himself, and neither 
exaggerating nor diminishing them. 

Now, each of these lines of conduct may be pur- 6 
sued either with an ulterior object or without one. 

When he has no ulterior object in view, each man 
speaks and acts and lives according to his character. 

But falsehood in itself is vile and blamable; 
truth is noble and praiseworthy in itself. 

jSid so the truthful man, as observing the mean, 
is praiseworthy, while the untruthful characters are 7 
both blamable, but the boastful more than the ironical. 

J Let us speak then of each of them, and first of the 

truthful character. 

We must remember that we are not s^eakin^ of 



4 



( 






7, a-12.] TRUTHFULNESS. 129 

the mail who tells the truth in matters of business, or 
in matters which come within the sphere of injustice 
and justice (for these matters would belong to another 

8 virtue) ; the man we are considering is the man who 
in cases where no such important issues, are involved 
is truthful in his speech and in his life, because that 
is his character. 

Such a man would seem to be a good man 
fliricMc^c). For he who loves truth, and is truthful 
where nothing depends upon it, will still more surely 
tell the truth where serious interests are involved; 
he will shim falsehood as a base thing here, seeing 
that he shunned it elsewhere, apart from any con- 

9 sequences : but such a man merits praise. 

He inclines rather towards under-statement than 
LO overrstatement of the truth; and this seems to be i 



'The more suitable course,'^since all exaggeration is I 
offensive. 

On the other hand, he who pretends to more than 
he has with no ulterior object [the boaster proper] 
seems not to be a good character (for if he were he 

11 would not take pleasure in falsehood), but to be silly 
rather than bad. 

But of boasters who have an ulterior object, he 
whose object is reputation or honour is not very 
severely censured (ju^t as the boaster proper is not), 

12 but he whose object is money, or means of making 
money, is held in greater reproach. 

For we must obsei've that what distinguishes the 
boaster proper from the other kinds of boasters, is no^j 
the faculty of boasting, but the purpose of his boast- 
ing: the boast^ proper is a boaster by habit, and 



130 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk. IV. 

because that is his character ; just as there is on the 
one hand the l iarjpr oper, who delights in falsehood 
itself, and on the other hand the liar who lies through 
desire of honour or gain. 

Those who boast with a view to reputation pre- 13 
tend to those things for which a man is commended 
or is thought happy ; those whose motive is gain pre- 
tend to those things which are of advantage to others, 
and whose absence may escape detection, e.g, to skill . 
in magic or in medicine. And so it is usually some- 
thing of this sort that men pretend to and boast of; 
for the conditions specified are realized in them. 
\ ^ , / Ironical people, on the other hand, with their 14 
^.-'-^depreciatory way of speaking of themselves, seem to 
be of a more refined character; for their motive in 
speaking thus seems to be not love of gain, but desire 
to avoid parade : but what they disclaim seems also * 
to be especially that which men esteem — of which 

Socrates was an instance. 

(Those who [do not disclaim creditable qualities is 
which they have, but] pretend to contemptible quali- 
/ ^ i ties which they plainly have not, are called sham 
scoundrels {fiavK^yiravovfyyoi), and may well be held in 
contempt.) 

And sometimes this self-depreciation is scarcely . 
^ distinguishable from boasting, as for instance dressing " 
I like a Spartan ; for there is something boastful in 
^s^extreme depreciation as well as in exaggeration. 
- .. But those who employ irony in moderation, and Ifi 

speak ironically in matters that are not too obvious 
and palpable, appear to be men of refinement. 

• The things that the boaster pretends to are also the things 
that the ironical man disclaims. 



7, 13-8, 4.] WITTINESS. 131 ^. 

\ .-' 

17 Finally, the boaster seems to be especially the "^ 
opposite of the truthful man; for he is worse than 
the ironical man. 

1 8. Again, since relaxation is an element in our of^miMk 
life, and one mode of relaxation is amusing conver- 
sation, it seems that in this respect also there is a 
proper way of mixing with others ; i,e, that there are 
things that it is right to say, and a right way of say- 
ing them : and the same with hearing ; though here 

also it will make a difference what kind of people 
they are in whose presence you are speaking, or to 
whom you are listening. 

2 And it is plain that it is possible in these matters 

also to go beyond,- or to fall short of, the mean. y^ 

3 Now, those who go to excess in ridicule seem to r 
be buffoons and vulgar fellows, striving at all costs for 

a ridiculous effect, and bent rather on raising a laugh 
than on making their witticisms elegant and inoffen- 
sive to the subject of them. While those who will 
never say anything laughable themselves, and frown 
on those who do, are considered boorish and morose, i 
But those who jest gracefully are called witty, or 
men of ready wit (cirpaTrcXoi), as it were ready or 
versatile men. 

For* a man's character seems to reveal itself in 
these sallies or playful movements, and so we judge of 
his moral constitution by them, as we judge of his 
body by its movements. 

4 But through the prominence given to ridiculous 
things, and the excessive delight which most people 

* What follows explains why all these terms have a specific 
moral meaning. 



132 NICOMAOHEAN ETHICS OP ARISTOTLE. [Bk. IV. 

take in amusement and jesting, the buifoon is often 
called witty because he gives delight. But that there 
is a difference, and a considerable difference, between 
the two is plain from what we have said. 

An element in the character that observes the 5 
mean in these matters is tact. A man of tact will 
only say and listen to such things as it befits an 
honest man and a gentleman to say and listen to; 
for there are things that it is quite becoming for such 
a man to say and to listen to in the way of jest, and 
the jesting of a gentleman differs from that of a man 
of slavish nature, and the jesting of an educated from 
that of an uneducated man. 
\ J This one may see by the difference between the old 6 

comedy and the new : the fun of the earlier writers 
is obscenity, of the later innuendo ; and there is no 
slight difference between the two as regards decency. 

Can good jesting, then, be defined as making 7 
jests that befit a gentleman, or that do not pain the 
hearer, or even that give him pleasure ? Nay, I 
think this also is a thing that cannot be defined: 
different things are hateful and pleasant to different 
people. 

But the things that he will listen to will be of the 8 
same sort [as those that he wiU say, whatever that 
be] : jests that a man can listen to he can, we think, 
make himself 

So then there are jests that he will not make 9 
[though we cannot exactly define them] ; for to 
make a jest of a man is to vilify him in a way, and 
the law forbids certain kinds of vilification, and ought 
perhaps also to forbid certain kinds of jesting. 




8, 5-9, 2 J SHAME. 133 

The refined and gentlemanly man, therefore, will 
thus regulate his wit, being as it were a law to 
himself. 

10 This then is the character of him who observes 
the mean, whether we call him a man of tact or a 
man of ready wit. 

The bufibon, on the other hand, cannot resist an 
opportunity for a joke, and, if he can but raise a laugh, 
will spare neither himself nor others, and wiU say 
things which no man of refinement would say, and 
some of which he would not even listen to. 

The boor, lastly, is wholly useless for this kind of 
intercourse ; he contributes nothing, and takes every- "^ 

11 thing in ill part. And yet recreation and amusement Ir 
seem to be necessary ingredients in our life. 

12 In conclusion, then, the modes just described of 
observing the mean in social life are three in number,* 
and all have to do with conversation or joint action 
of some kind : but they differ in that one has to do 
with truth, while the other two are concerned witli 
what is pleasant; and of the two that are concerned 
with pleasure, one finds its field in our amusements> 
the other in all other kinds of social intercourse. 

1 9. Shame (alSwc) cannot properly be spoken of 
as a virtue ; for it is more like a feeling or emotion "^^^m. 
than a habit or trained faculty. At least, it is 

2 defined as a kind of fear of disgrace, and its effects 
are analogous to those of the fear that is excited by 
danger ; for men blush when they are ashamed, while 
the fear of death makes them pale. Both then seem 
to be in a way physical, which is held to be a mark 

* Friendliness, tmtbfulness, wit. 




7 



134 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk. IV. 

of a feeling or emotion, rather than of a habit or 
trained faculty. 

Again, it is a feeling which is not becoming at aU 3 
times of life, but only in youth ; it is thought proper 
for young people to be ready to feel shame, because, 
as their conduct is guided by their emotions, they 
often are misled, but are restrained from wrong 
actions by sham6. 

And so we praise young men when they are 
ready to feel shame, but no one would praise a man 
of more advanced years for being agt to be ashamed ; 
for we consider that he ought not to do anything 
which could make him ashamed of himself. 
X And so a good man has no business with shame, 4 
seeing that it is occasioned by base acts ; for such acts 
should not be done at all. 

It may be said that some acts are really disgrace- 5 
ful, others disgraceful only in public estimation ; but 
that makes no difference : neither ought to be done, 
and so a man ought to have no occasion to be ashamed. 

And to be the sort of a man that would do a dis- 6 
graceful deed is to be other than a good man. 

But supposing a man's character to be such that, 
if he were to do one of these disgraceful acts, he 
would be ashamed, it is absurd to fancy that he is a 
good man on that account ; for shame is only felt at 
voluntary acts, and a good man will never voluntarily 
do vile acts. 

At the utmost, shame would be hypothetically 7 
good ; that is to say, supposing he were to do the act, 
a good man would be ashamed : but there is nothing 
hypothetical about the virtues. 



9, 8-8.] 8HAMB. 135 

Again, granting that it is bad to be shameless, or 
not to be ashamed to do disgraceful things, it does not 
therefore follow that it is good to do them and be 
ashamed of it 
8 Coiithwuce,* in the same way, is not a virtue, hMti/^ 
something between virtue and vice. 

But we will explain this point about continence 
later ; t 1©^ ^^ ^^ow treat of justice. 

* The continent man desires the evil which he onght not to 
desire, and so is not good ; but he does not do it, and so is not bad i 
thus continence also might be called ** hypotheticallj good" ; granting 
the eyU desire (which ezdades goodness proper), the best thing is 
to master it. 

t Book VIL 



BOOK V. 



THE SAME — concluded. JUSTICE. 



prdimu 1, We uow have to inquire about justice and in- 1 



nary 



S^S" justice, and to ask what sort of acts they are concerned 
^uhk. Qf^^^f ^^^ ^^ what sense justice observes the mean, 
SSSjwto ^^^ what are the extremes whose mean is that which 
^IdHM, is just. And in this inquiry we will follow the same 3 
, method as before. 
V We see that all men intend by justice to signify 3 

the sort of habit or character that makes men apt to 
do what is just, and which further makes them act 
justly* and wish what is just; while by injustice 
they intend in like manner to signify the sort of 
character that makes men act unjustly and wish what 
is unjust. Let us lay this down, then^ as an outline 
to work upon. 

We thus oppose justice and injustice, because a 4 
habit or trained faculty differs in this respect both 
from a science and a fietculty or power. I mean that 
whereas both of a pair of opposites come under the 
same science or power^ a habit which produces a 

* A man may " do that which is just '' without " acting jostly : * 
<^. siipraf II. 4, 8> and infra, oap. 8. 



1, 1-8.] JUSTICE. 137 

certain result does not also produce the opposite 
result; e.g, health produces healthy manifestations 
only, and not unhealthy; for we say a man has a 
healthy gait when he walks like a man in health. 
6 [Not that the two opposites are unconnected] In 
the first place, a habit is often known by the opposite 
habit, and often by its causes and results: if we 
know what good condition is, we can learn from 
that what bad condition is; and, again, from that 
which conduces to good condition we can infer what 
good condition itself is, and conversely from the latter 
can infer the former. For instance, if good condition 
be firmness of flesh, it follows that bad condition is 
flabbiness of flesh, and that what tends to produce 
firmness of flesh conduces to good condition. 

6 And, in the second place, if one of a pair of 
opposite terms have more senses than one, the other 
term will also, as a general rule, have more than one ; 
so that here, if the term ''just" have several senses, 
the term " unjust " also will have several. 

7 And in fact it seems that both "justice" and 
'* injustice " have several senses, but, as the difierent 
things covered by the common name are very closely 
related, the fact that they are difierent escapes notice 
and does not strike us, as it does when there is a 
great disparity— a great difference, say, in outward 
appearance — as it strikes every one, for instance, that 
the kKzIq (clavis, collar-bone) which lies under the 
neck of an animal is different from the K\dg {clavis, 
key) with which we fasten the door. 

8 Let us then ascei'tain in how many difierent 
senses we call a man unjust. 



138 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLB. [Bk. V. 

i Firstly, he who breaks the laws is considered 

unjust, and, secondly, he who takes more than his 
share, or the unfair man. 
\^ Plainly, then, a just man will mean (1) a law- 
abiding and (2) a fair man. 

A just thing then will be (1) that which is in 
accordance with the law, (2) that which is fiaix ; and 
the unjust thing will be (1) that which is contrary 
to law, (2) that which is unfair. 

But since the unjust man, in one of the two senses 9 
of the word, takes more than his share, the sphere oi 
his action will be good things — ^not all good things, 
but those with which good and ill fortune are con- 
cerned, which are always good in themselves, but 
not always good for us — the things that we men pray 
for and pursue, whereas we ought rather to pray that 
what is good in itself may be good for us, while 
we choose that which is good for us. 

But the unjust man does not always take more lO 
than his share ; he sometimes take less, viz. of those 
things which are bad in the abstract; but as the 
lesser evil is considered to be in some sort good, and 
taking more means taking more good, he is said to 
take more than his share« But in any case he is 
imfair; for this is a wider term which includes the ii 
other. 

We found that the law-breaker is unjust, and is 
the law-abiding man is just. Hence it follows that 
whatever is according to law is just in one sense of 
the word. [And this, we see, is in fact the case ;] for 
what the legislator prescribes is according to law, 
and is always said to be just. 



1, 9-16.] JUSTICE. 139 

.3 Now, the laws prescribe about all maimer of 
things, aiming at the common interest of all, or of the 
best men, or of those who are supreme in the state / ,i 
(position in the state being determined by reference to Jf 
personal excellence, or to some other such standard) ; ■; 
and so in one sense we apply the term just to what- 
ever tends to produce and preserve the happiness 
of the community, and the several elements of that 

14 happiness. The law bids us display courage (as not 
to leave our ranks, or run, or throw away our arms), 
and temperance (as not to commit adultery or out- 
rage), and gentleness (as not to strike or revile our 
neighbours), and so on with all the other virtues and 
vices, enjoining acts and forbidding them, rightly 
when it is a good law, not so rightly when it is a 
hastily improvised one. 

16 Jus tice, then, in this sense of the word, is com- 
plete virtue, with the addition that it is displayed 
towards othera On this account it is often spoken 
of as the chief of the virtues, and such that "neither 
evening nor morning star is so lovely;" and the 
saying has become proverbial, "Justice sums up all 
virtues in itself." 

It is complete virtue, first of aU, because it is 
the exhibition of complete virtue : it is also complete 
because he that has it is able to exhibit virtue in 
dealing with his neighbours, and not merely in his 
private affairs ; for there are many who can be vir- 
tuous enough at home, but fail in dealing with their 
neighbours. 

.6 This is the reason why people commend the say- 
ing of Bias, " Office will show the man ; " for he that 



140 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARiSTOTLE. DBk. V. 



Of justice 
(2) =fair- 
nesSf how 
related to 
justice (1^, 
What isju^t 
in distri- 
Imtion dii- 
tinguished 
frwn, what it 
Justin 
correction. 



is in office ipso facto stands in relation to otheis,* 
and has dealings with them. 

This, too, is the reason why justice alone of all i 
the virtues is thought to be another's good, as imply- 
ing this relation to others ; for it is another's interest 
that justice aims at — the interest, namely, of the ruler 
or of our fellow-citizens. 

While then the worst man is he who displays i 
vice both in his own affairs and in his dealings with 
his friends, the best man is not he who displays 
virtue in his own affairs merely, but he who displays 
virtue towards others ; for this is the hard thing to do. 

Justice, then, in this sense of the word, is not a part i 
of virtue, but the whole of it ; and the injustice which is 
opposed to it is not a part of vice, but the whole of it. 

How virtue differs from justice in this sense is 2i 
plain from what we have said; it is one and the 
same character differently viewed : f viewed in rela- 
tion to others, this character is justice; viewed simply 
as a certain character, J it is virtue. 

2. We have now to examine justice in that sense i 
in which it is a part of virtue — for we maintain that 
there is such a justice — and also the corresponding 
kind of injustice. 

That the word is so used is easily shown. In the 2 
case of the other kinds of badness, the man who dis- 
plays them, though he acts imjustly [in one sense 
of the word], yet does not take more than his sh€tre : 

* While bis children are regarded as parts of him, and even his 
wife is not regarded as an independent person : cf. infra, 6, 8. 

t Or " differently manifested : " the phrase is used in both 
senses. 

{ Fatting comma after airX«s instead of after t^n (Trendelenburg) . 



1, 17-2, 6.] JUSTICE. 141 

for instance, when a man throws away his shield 
through cowardice, or reviles another through ill 
temper, or through illiberality refuses to help another 
with money. But when he takes more than his 
share, he displays perhaps no one of these vices, nor 
does he display them all, yet he displays a kind of 
badness (for we blame him), namely, injustice [in the 
second sense of the word]. 

3 We see, then, that there is another sense of the 
word injustice, in which it stands for a part of 
that injustice which is coextensive with badness, and 
another sense of the word unjust, in which it is 
applied to a part only of those things to which it 
is applied in the former sense of " contrary to law." 

4 Again, if one man commits adultery with a view 
to gain, and makes money by it, and another man 
does it from lust, with expenditure and loss of money, 
the latter would not be called grasping, but profli- 
gate, while the former would not be called profligate, 
but unjust [in the narrower sense]. Evidently, then, 
he would be called unjust because of his gain. 

5 * Once more, acts of injustice, in the former sense, 
are always referred to some particular vice, as if a 
man commits adultery, to profligacy ; if he deserts his 
comrade in arms, to cowardice ; if he strikes another, 
to anger : but in a case of unjust gain, the act is 
referred to no other vice than injustice. 

6 It is plain then that, besides the injustice which 

♦ This is not merely a repetition of what has been said in § 2 1 
acts of injustice (2) are there distinguished from acts of injustice 
(1) by the motive (gain), here by the fact that they are referred to 
no other vice than injustice. 




V 



142 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. CBk. V. 

is coextensive with vice, there is a second kind of 
injustice, which is a particular kind of vice, bearing 
the same name * as the first, because the samB generic 
conception forms the basis of its definition; i.e. both 
display themselves in dealings with others, but the 
sphere of the second is limited to such things as 
honour, wealth, security (perhaps some one name might 
be found to include all this class t), and its motive 
is the pleasure of gain, while the sphere of the first 
is coextensive with the sphere of the good man's action. 

We have ascertained, then, that there are more 7 
kinds of justice than one, and that there is another 
kind besides that which is identical with complete 
virtue ; we now have to find what it is, and what 
are its characteristics. 

We have already distinguished two senses in 8 
\ / which we speak of things as unjust, viz. (1) contrary 
to law, (2) unfair; and two senses in which we speak 
of things as just, viz. (1) according to law, (2) fair. 

The injustice which we have already considered 
corresponds to the first of these senses of unjust. 

But since unfair or too much is not the same 9 
as contrary to law, but stands for a part, while the 
latter stands for the whole (I name " unfair " as well 
as " too much," because although too much is always 
unfair, what is imfair is not always too much), 

♦ Before (1, 7) the two kinds of injustioe were called 6fA(&ttv/Aa, 
i,e, strictly, " things that have nothing in common but the name ; ** 
here they are called a'vv<&vuiMa, " different things bearing a common 
name becanse they belong to the same genns," as a man and an os 
are both called animals : cf. Categ. I. 1. 

+ T«k iKrhs ay add is the name which Aristotle most frequently 
uses, sometimes reb avKas hyaOd, as sujprOf 1, 9. 



2, 6-llJ JUSTICE. 143 

the corresponding senses of unjust and injustice 
will not be the same, but different from the former 
senses, standing for a part, while the former stood 
for the whole ; for this injustice is a part of complete 
injustice, and the corresponding justice is a part of 
complete justice. We must therefore speak of justice 
and i]:\justice, and of that which id just and that 
which is unjust, in this limited sense. 

10 We may dismiss, then, the justice which coincides 
with complete virtue and the corresponding injustice, 
the former being the exercise of complete virtue 
towards others, the latter of complete vice. 

It is easy also to see how we are to define that 
which is just and that which is unjust in their corre- 
sponding senses [according to law and contrary to 
law]. The acts which manifest complete virtue 
form, we may say, the great bulk of the acts which 
are according to law ; for the law orders us to dis- 
play all the virtues and none of the vices in our 

11 lives. But the acts which tend to produce complete 
virtue are those of the acts according to law which 
are prescribed with reference to the education of a 
man as a citizen. 

As for the education of the individual as such, 
which tends to make him simply a good man, wo 
may reserve the question whether it belongs to the 
science of the state or not ; for it is possible that to 
be a good man is not the same as to be a good citizen 
of any state whatever.* 

12 But of justice as a part of virtue, and of that 

* The two characters coincide perfectly only in the perfect 
state : qf. Pol. III. 4, 1276 ^IS f . 



144 NICOMAOHEAN ETHICS OF ARISIOTLE. [Bk. T. 

whieli is just in the corresponding sense, one kind 
ia that which has to do with the distribution of 
hoDouFj wealth, and the other things that are divided 
among the members of the body politic (for in theaa 
circumstances it ia possible for one man's share to be 
imfair or fair as compared with another's) ; and another 
kind is that which has to give redress in privata 
transactions. 

The latter kind is again subdivided ; for private 
transactions are (1) voluntary, (2) involuntary, 

" Voluntary transactions or contracts " are such 
as selling, buying, lending at interest, pledging, lend- 
ing without interest, depositing, hiring ; these are 
called "voluntary contracts," because the parties enter 
into them of their own will, 

" Involuntary transactions," again, are of two 
kinds : one involving secrecy, such as theft, adultery, 
poisoning, procuring, cornaption of slaves, assassina- 
tion, false witness ; the other involving open violence, 
such as assault, seizure of the person, murder, rape, 
maiming, slander, contumely, 

o/u,hiiu\ 3. The unjust man [in this limited sense of the! 

indui"'""' ^'^'^]' '^^ ^^Y' ^^ unfair, and that which is lu^ust 

m'Si-^i?"" ^ unfair. 

iraporiion.''^ Now, it is plain that there must be a mean which 
lies between what is unfair on this side and on that. 

»And this is that which is fair or equal ; for any J 
act that admits of a too much and a too little admita 
also of that which is fair. 

If then that which is unjust be unfair, that whiclj 
is just will he fair, which indeed is admitted by all 
Without further proof. 



2, 12-3, 7.] JUSTICE. 145 

But since that which is fair or equal is a mean 
between two extremes, it follows that what is just 
will be a mean. 

4 But equality or fairness implies two terms at 
least.* 

It follows, then, that that which is just is both 

a mean quantity and also a fair amount relatively to 

something else and to certain persons — in other words, 

that, on the one hand, as a mean quantity it implies 

certain other quantities, i.e. a more and a less ; and, 

on the other hand, as an equal or fair amount it 

involves two quantities,t and as a just amount it 

involves certain persons. 

5 That which is just, then, implies four terms at l^ 
least : two persons to whom justice is done, and two 
things. 

6 And there must be the same " equality " [i.e. the 
same ratio] between the persons and the things : as 
the things are to one another, so must the persons 
be. For if the persons be not equal, their shares will 
not be equal ; and this is the source of disputes and 
accusations, when persons who are equal do not 
receive equal shares, or when persons who are not 
equal receive equal shares. 

7 This is also plainly indicated by the common 
phrase " according to merit." For in distribution all 
men allow that what is just must be according to 
merit or worth of some kind, but they do not all adopt 
the same standard of worth ; in democratic states /"^'^ 

* If this amonnt be eqnal, it mnst be equal to something else ; 
if m7 share is fair, I mast be sharing with one other person at least. 
t A's share and B's, 

L 



146 NICOMACHEAN ETmOS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk. V. 

they take free birth as the standard,* in oligarchic 
states they take wealth, in others noble birth, and in 
the true aristocratic state virtue or personal merit. 

We see, then, that that which is just is in some sort 8 
proportionate. For not abstract numbers only, but 
all'things that can be numbered, admit of proportion; 
proportion meaning equality of ratios, and requiring 
four terms at least. 

That discrete proportion t requires four terms is 9 
evident at once. Continuous proportion also requires 
four terms: for in it one term is employed as two 

and is repeated; for instance, t = - The term 6 

c 

then is repeated ; and so, counting b twice over, we 

find that the terms of the proportion are four in 

number. 

That which is just, then, requires that there be lo 

four terms at least, and that the ratio between the 

two pairs be the same, i.e. that the persons stand 

to one another in the same ratio as the things. 

Let us say, then, - = -, or altemaTido - = j. li 

The sums of these new pairs then will stand to 

one another in the original ratio [ i.e. ^ = | or |] • 

But these are the pairs which the distribution 
joins together ; J and if the things be assigned in this 
manner, the distribution is just. 

* Connting all free men as equals entitled to eqnal shares. 

X Assigning or joining certain quantities of goods (e and d) to 
certain persons (a and h^» 



3, 8-4, I.] JUSTICE. 147 

13 This joining, then, of o to c and of 6 to d is 

that which is just in distribution; and that which 
ia just in this senBe ia a mean between that 
which violates the proportion on this side and on 
that ; for that which is proportionate is a mean 
quantity, and that which is just ia, aa we said, 
proportionate. 
:3 This proportion ia called by the mathematiciana a 
geometrical proportion ; for it is when four terms 
are in geometrical proportion that the sum [of the 
first and third] ia to the sum [of the second and 
fourtli] in the original ratio [of the first to the second 
or the third to the fourth]. 
L4 But this proportion [as applied in justice] cannot 
be a continuous proportion ; for one term cannot 
represent both a person and a thing. /" 

That which ia just, then, in this sense ia that •' 
which is proportionate; but that which is unjust 
is that which ia disproportionate. In the latter 
ease one quantity hecomea more or too much, the 
other less or too Httle. And this we see in practice ; 
for be who wrongs another gets too much, and 
he who ia wronged gets too little of the good in 

15 question: but of the evil conversely; for the leaser 
evil stands in the place of good when compared 

16 with the greater evil i for the lesser evil is more 
desirable than the greater, but that which is desirable 
ia good, and that which is more desirable is a greater, 
good. ^ 

1 4. This then ia one form of that which ia just ofoat 

[in the limited sense]; the other form of it is thatJicorr™ 

^■irhich is just in the way of redreaa, the sphoro of n^aHU- 



148 NIOOMAOHBAN ETHICS OP ABISTOTLB. [Bk. V. 

meticai which is private transactions, whether voluntary or 
involuntary. 

This differs in kind from the former. 

For that which is just in the distribution of a 2 
common stock of good things is always in accordance 
with the proportion above specified (even when it is a 
common fund that has to be divided, the sums which 
the several participants take must bear the same ratio 
to one another as the sums they have put in), and that 
which is unjust in the corresponding sense violates 
this proportion. 
J But that which is just in private transactions * is 3 

indeed fair or equal in some sort, and that which is 
unjust is imfair or unequal ; but the proportion to be 
observed here is not a geometrical proportion as 
above, but an arithmetical one. 

For it makes no difference whether a good man 

defrauds a bad one, or a bad man a good one, nor 

whether a man who commits an adultery be a good 

or a bad man ; the law looks only to the difference 

created by the injury, treating the parties themselves 

as equal, and only asking whether the one has done, 

and the other suffered, injury or damage. 

yj That which is tJiyust, then, is here something 4 

unequal [or unfair] which the judge tries to make 

equal [or fair]. For even when one party is struck 

and the other strikes, or one kills and the other is 

killed, that which is suffered and that which is done 

* In the way of redress, as given by the law-courts : later on 
(cap. 5) he gives as an after-thought the kind of jnstice which 
ought to regulate bnjing and selling, etc. ; bat the law onlj en- 
forces these contracts and does not regulate them (4, IS). 



4, 2-7.] JUSTICE. 149 

may be said to be unequally or unfairly divided ; the 
judge then tries to restore equality by the penalty or 
loss which he inflicts upon the offender, subtracting 
it from his gain. 

5 For in such cases, though the terms are not 
always quite appropriate, we generally talk of the 

6 doer's "gain" (e.gr. the striker's) and the sufi'erer's 
" loss ; " but when the suffering has been assessed 
by the court, what the doer gets is called "loss" 
or penalty, and what the sufferer gets is called 
"gain." 

Now, what is fair or equal is a mean between 
more or too much and less or too little ; but gain and 
loss are both more or too much and less or too little 
in opposite ways, i.e, gain is more or too much good 
and less or too little evil, and loss the opposite of 
this. 

And in the mean between them, as we found, 
lies that which is equal or fair, which we say is 
just. 

That which is just in the way of redress, then, is 
the mean between loss and gain. 
7 When disputes arise, therefore, men appeal to the 
judge :* and an appeal to the judge is an appeal to 
that which is just ; for the judge is intended to be 
as it were a living embodiment of that which is 
just; and men require of a judge that he shall be 
moderate [or observe the mean], and sometimes even 
call judges "mediators" (jiemSiovg), signifying that 

* The ZiKaTToi at Athens combined the f anotions of jadge and 
jury. 



/ 



150 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk. V. 

if they get the mean they will get that which is 
just. 
\/ That which is just, then, must be a sort of mean, 8 

if the judge be a " mediator." 

But the judge restores equality ; it is as if he 
found a line divided into two unequal parts, and 
were to cut off from the greater that by which it 
exceeds the half, and to add this to the less. 

But when the whole is equally divided, the parties 
are said to have their own, each now receiving an 
equal or fair amount. 

But the equal or fair amount is here the arith- 9 
TTietic mean between the more or too much and the 
less or too little. And so it is called SIkqiov Qust) 
because there is equal division (8ix°); SiKaiov being 
in fact equivalent to Slxaiov, and Siicaorijc G^^g®) ^ 
Sixaarrig. 

If you cut off a part from one of two equal lines lO 
and add it to the other, the second is now greater 
than the first by two such parts (for if you had only 
cut off the part from the first without adding it to 
the second, the second would have been greater by 
only one such part) ; the second exceeds the mean by 
one such part, and the mean also exceeds the first by 
one. 

Thus we can tell how much to take away from U 
him who has more or too much, and how much 
to add to him who has less or too little : to the 
latter's portion must be added that by which it falls 
short of the mean, and from the former s portion 
must be taken away that by which it exceeds the 
mean. 



4, 8-13.] JUSTICE. 151 

3 To iUustrate this, let A A', BB', CC be three 
equal lines : — 

A E A' 

i 

B B' 

D Z C 



From A A' let A E be cut off; and let C D [equal to 
AE] be added to C C; then the whole D CC exceeds 
EA' by CD and CZ [equal to AE or CD], and 
exceeds BB' by CD. 

And this * holds good not only in geometry, but 
in the arts also; they could not exist unless that 
which is worked upon received an impression corre- 
sponding in kind and quantity and quality to the 
exertions of the artist. 
L3 These terms, "loss" and "gain," are borrowed from 
voluntary exchange. For in voluntary exchange 
having more than your own is called gaining, and 
having less than you started with is called losing 
(in buying and selling, I mean, and in the other trans- 

• The point to be illnstrated is, that in these private trans- 
actions what one man gains is eqnal to what the other loses, so that 
the penalty that will restore the balance can be exactly measured. 
Of this principle (on which the possibility of jastice does in fact 
depend) Aristotle first gives a simple geometrical illustration, and 
then says that the same law holds in all that man does : what is 
snffered by the patient (whether person, as in medicine, or thing, as in 
scnlptnre or agriculture) is the same as what is done by the agent. 
This paragraph occurs again in the next chapter (5, 9) : but it 
can hardly have come into this place by accident; we rather see 
the author's thought growing as he writes. I follow Trendelenburg 
(who omits the passage here) in inserting 8 before inoUi, but not 
in omitting t^ before ir<£(rxoi^. 



152 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk. V. 

actions in which the law allows free play) ; hut when u 
neither gets more or less, but both parties get, by free 
exchange,* the very same amount with which they 
started, then they allow that they have their own, and 
are neither losers nor gainers. That which is just, 
then, in these voluntary transactions f is a mean 
between a gain and a loss, and consists in having after 
the transaction an amount equal to that which you 
\ had before it. 
simpUre- ^ 6. Somc people, indeed, go so far as to think that i 
nSJideniicaz simple requital is just. And so the Pythagoreans 
ju*t,butpro- used to teach ; for their definition of what is just was 
requitaiis simply that what a man has done to another should 

what U just J " , 1 . 

in exchange ; be donC tO him. 
and this is 

effected by But this simple rcQuital does not correspond either 2 

means of ■*■ , "^ •*• 

numey. We with that which is lust in distribution or with that 

cannowgive ^ , , •* 

dffStSSnof ^^^^^ ^^ j^^^ i^ ^^® ^^y ^^ redress (though this 3 
justice (2), certainly is what people mean to express in the 
Rhadamanthine rule — 

" To suffer that which thon hast done is just ") ; 

for in many cases it is quite different. For instance, i 
if an officer strike a man, he ought not to be struck 
in return; and if a man strike an officer, he ought 
not merely to be struck, but to be punished. 

Further, it makes a great difference whether what 5 
was done to the other was done with his consent or 
against it. 

• aurd, almost = rh, aurd, " the very amount with which they 
Btarted j " and 5t* aOrwv = 4k rrjs kKovaiov iiKKarrfis, by their own 
will : neither party is defrauded secretly or openly, but each believes 
that what he gives is worth precisely what he takes: the next 
chapter gives the rule for determining this worth. 

t For this use of vapd qf, I. 8, 7. 



4, U-6, 8.1 JUSTICE. 153 

6 But it is true that, in the interchange of services, 
this is the rule of justice that holds society together, , 
viz. requital-'^^^^t proportionate requital, and not 
simple repayment of equals for equals. For the very 
existence of a state depends upon propoi-tionato 
return. K men have suffered evil, they seek to 
return it; if not, if they cannot requite an injury, 
we count their condition slavish. And again, if men 
have received good, they seek to repay it : for other- 
wise there is no exchange of services ; but it is by 
this exchange that we are bound together in society. 

7 This is the reason why we set up a temple of the 
graces [charities, x«/>«'"€c] in sight of all men, to re- 
mind them to repay that which they receive; for 
this is the special characteristic of charity or grace. ) 

8 We ought to return the good offices of those who 
have been gracious to us, and then again to take the 
lead in good offices towards them. 

But proportionate interchange is brought about 
by "cross conjunction." 

For instance, let A stand for a builder, B for a 
shoemaker, C for a house, D for shoes.* 

• We had before (3, 11, 12) as the mle of distributive justice 

A 

^ =^i and the distribution was expressed by the "joining " (crjJfcwfts) 

of the opposite or corresponding symbols, A and 0, B and D. Here 
we have the same two pairs of symbols, ranged opposite to each 
other as before ; but the exchange will be expressed by joining A to 
D and B to C, i.e. by " cross conjunction" or by drawing diagonal 
lines (4 Karh, Bid/xerpoy a^Cfv^is) thus : 

A . .0 






B. .0 



154 NICOMACHEAN ETmOS OF ABISTOTLB. [Bk. V. 

The builder then must take some of the shoemaker's 
WQrk, and give him his own work in exchanga 

Now, the desired result will be brought about if 
requital take place after proportionate equality has 
first been established.* 

If this be not done, there is no equality, and 
intercourse becomes impossible ; for there is no reason 
why the work of the one should not be worth more 
than the work of the other. Their work, then, must 
be brought to an equality [or appraised by a common 
standard of value]. 

This is no less true of the other arts and pro- 9 
fessions [than of building and shoemaking] ; for they 
could not exist if that which the patient [client or 
consumer] receives did not correspond in quantity 
and quality with that which the agent [artist or 
producer] does or produces.! 

* i,e, (as will presently appear), it mast first be determined 
bow mnch builder's work is eqnal to a given quantity of shoemaker's 
work: i.e. the price of the two wares must first be settled; that 
done, they simply exchange shilling's worth for shilling's worth 
{jkvri'ni'Kovd6{) ; e.g. if a fonr-roomed cottage be valued at £100, and 
a pair of boots at £1, the builder must supply such a cottage in 
return for 100 such pairs of boots (or their equivalent). 

Fixing the price of the articles is called securing equality, 
because, evidently, it means fixing how much of one article shaU be 
considered equal to a given quantity of the other. It is called 
securing proportionate equality, because, as we shall see, the ques- 
tion that has to be determined is, ''in what ratio must work 
be exchanged in order to preserve the due ratio between the 
workers ? " 

t Benefit to consumer = cost to producer; e.g, if £100 be a fair 
price for a picture, it must fairly represent both the benefit to the 
purchaser and the effort expended on* it by the artist. I follow 
Trendelenburg in inserting before ivoUif but not in omitting rh 
before vd<rxoy, Cf, note on 4, 12. 



6, 9-11.] JUSTICE. 165 

For it is not between two physicians that ex- 
change of services takes place, but between a phy- 
sician and a husbandman, and generally between 
persons of different professions and of unequal worth ; 
these unequal persons, then, have to be reduced to 
equality [or measured by a common standard].* 
[0 All things or services, then, which are to be ex- 
changed must be in some way reducible to a common 
measure. 

For this purpose money was invented, and serves \ 
as a medium of exchange ; for by it we can measure 
everything, and so can measure the superiority and 
inferiority of different kinds of work — the number 
of shoes, for instance, that is equivalent to a house 
or to a certain quantity of food. 

What is needed then is that so many shoes shall 
bear to a house (or a measure of com) the same ratio 
that a builder [or a husbandman] bears to a shoe- 
maker.f For unless this adjustment be effected, no 
dealing or exchange of services can take place ; and 
it cannot be effected unless the things to be ex- 
changed can be in some way made equal 
11 We want, therefore, some one common measure 
of value, as we said before. 

This measure is, in fact, the need for each other's 
services which holds the members of a society 
together; for if men had no needs, or no common 

* The persons have to be appraised as well as their work ; but, 
as we soon see, these are two sides of the same thing : the relative 
yalne at which persons are estimated by society is indicated by the 
relative value which society pats npon their services, and this ia 
indicated by the price put upon a certain quantity of their work. 

t See note on § 12. 




156 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk. V. 

needs, there would either be no exchange, or a dif- 
ferent sort of exchange from that which we know. 

\( But money has been introduced by convention as 
a kind of substitute for need or demand ; and this is 
why we call it vofiKTfid, because its value is derived, 

i not from nature, but from law (yofio^), and can be 
altered or abolished at wiU. 

Requital then will take place after the wares 12 
have been so equated [by the adjustment of prices] 
that the quantity of shoemaker's work bears to the 
quantity of husbandman's work [which exchanges for 
it] the same ratio that husbandman bears to shoe- 
maker,* But this adjustment must be made,t ^ot at 
the time of exchange (for then one of the two parties 
would get both the advantages!), but while they 
are still in possession of their own wares; -if this be 

* e.g. suppose the husbandman is twice as good a man as the 
shoemaker, then, if the transaction is to follow the nniversal role 
of justice and leave their relative position unaltered, in exchange 
for a certain quantity of husbandman's work the shoemaker must 
give twice as much of his own. The price, that is, of com and 
shoes must be so adjusted that, if a quarter of corn seU for 508. 
and three pair of shoes sell for the same sum, the three pair of 
shoes must represent twice as much labour as the quarter of com. 
Aristotle speaks loosely of the ratio between the shoes and the com, 
etc., but as their value is ex hypotheH the same, and as the relative 
size, weight, and number of articles is quite accidental {e.g. we 
might as well measure the corn by bushels or by pounds), the ratio 
intended can oply be the ratio between the quantities of labour. He 
omits to tell us that these quantities must be measured by time, 
but the omission is easily supplied. He omits also to tell us how 
the relative worth of the persons is to be measured, but he has 
already said all that is necessary in 8, 7. 

t Lit. " they must be reduced to proportion," i.e., in strictness, 
the four terms (two persons and two things). 

X i.e. have his superiority counted twice over. His {e.g. the hus* 
bandman's) superiority over the other party (the shoemaker) has 



6, 12-14] JUSTICE. 157 

done^ they are put on an equal footing and can make 
an exchange^ because this kind of equality can be 
established between them. 

If A stand for a husbandman and C for a certain 
quantity of his work (or com), B will stand for a 
shoemaker, and D for that quantity of shoemaker's 
work that is valued as equal to C. 

If they could not requite each other in this way, 
interchange of services would be impossible. 

13 That it is our need which forms, as it were, a 
common bond to hold society together, is seen from the 
fact that people do not exchange unless they are in 
need of one another's se:vices (each party of the 
services of the other, or at least one party of the 
service of the other), as when that which one has, 
e.g. wine, is needed by other people who offer to 
export com in return. This article, then [the com to 
be exported], must be made equal [to the wine that is 
imported}.* 

14 But even if we happen to want nothing at the 
moment, money is a sort of guarantee that we shall be 
able to make an exchange at any future time when we 
happen to be in need ; for the man who brings money 
must always be able to take goods in exchange. 

been already taken into account in fixing the price of a quarter 
of com as eqnal to three pairs of shoes : this is one advantage 
which is fairly tis j bat it would be plainly unfair if, at the time 
of exchange, the husbandman were to demand 50s. worth of shoes 
for 25s. worth of com, on the ground that he was twice as good a 
man : c/. Munro, Journal of Classical a/ad Sacred Philology^ vol. ii 
In the text I have followed Trendelenburg's stopping, throwing 
the words el 8^ /u^ . . . 6,Kpov into a parenthesis. 

♦ i.e, each must be valued in money, so that so many quarters o.' 
oom fifhft ii exchange for so many hogsheads of wine. 



/ 158 KICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF AEISTOTLE. £Bk. V. 

■ V Money is, indeed, subject to the same conditions 
as other things : its value is not always the same ; 
but still it tends to be more constant than the value 
of anything else. 
^1 Everything, then, must be assessed in money ; for 
this enables men always to exchange their services, 
and so makes society possible. 
\/ Money, then, as a standard, serves to reduce things 
to a common measure, so that equal amounts of each 
may be taken ; for there would be no society if there 
were no exchange, and no exchange if there were no 
equality, and no equality if it were not possible to 
reduce things to a common measure. 

In strictness, indeed, it is impossible to find any 15 
common measure for things so extremely diverse; 
but our needs give a standard which is sufficiently 
accurate for practical purposes. 

There must, then, be some one common symbol for 
this, and that a conventional symbol ; so we call it 
money (yofxiafxa, vojuoc). Money makes all things 
commensurable, for all things are valued in money. 
For instance, let A stand for a house, B for ten minse, 

C for a bed; and let A = — , taking a house to be 

• worth or equal to five minse, and let C (the bed) = ^. 

We see at once, then, how many beds are equal to 
one house, viz. five. 

It is evident that, before money came into use, 16 
all exchange must have been of this kind : it makes 
no difference whether you give five beds for a house, 
or the value of five beds. 

Thus we have described that which is unjust and 17 



6, 15-18.] JUSTICE. 159 

that which is just. And now that these are deter- 
mined^ we can see that doing justice is a mean 
between doing and suffering injustice; for the one 
is having too much, or more, and the other too little, . 
or less than one's due. 

We see also that the virtue justice is moderation 
[or a mode of observing the mean], but not quite in 
the same way as the virtues hitherto spoken of. It 
does indeed observe a mean, but both the extremes 
fall under the single vice injustice.* 

We see also that justice is that habit in respect 
of which the just man is said to be apt to do 
deliberately that which is just; that is to say, in 
dealings between himself and another (or between 
two other parties), to apportion things, not so that he 
shall get more or too much, and his neighbour less or 
L8 too little, of what is desirable, and conversely with 
what is disadvantageous, but so that each shall get 
his fair, that is, his proportionate share, and similarly 
in dealings between two other parties. 

And from this we may get the definition of 
injustice, if for "that which is just" we substitute 
*' that which is unjust," which is a disproportionate 
amount, that is, too much and too little of what is 
advantageous and disadvantageous respectively. 

• The mean which justice aims at (the just thing, the due share 
of goods) lies between two extremes, too much and too little ; so 
fskr justice is analogous to the other virtues : but whereas in 
other jQelds these two extremes are chosen hj different and opposite 
characters (e.g. the cowardly and the foolhardy), the unjust man 
chooses both, too much good for himself and too little for his neigh- 
bour, too little evil for himself and too much fo^ his neighbour. 
To get too little good is to suffer injustice, but the habitual choice 
of it is regarded as an impossibility. 



^/ 



160 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE, [Bk. V. 



4 



Thus injustice, as we say, is both an excess and 
a deficiency, in that it chooses both an excess and a 
deficiency — in one's own affairs choosing excess of 
what is, as a general rule, advantageous, and de- 
ficiency of what is disadvantageous ; in the affairs of 
others making a similarly disproportionate assign- 
ment, though in which way the proportion is violated 
wiU depend upon circumstances. 

But of the two sides of the act of injustice, suffer- 
ing is a lesser wrong than doing the injustice. 

Let this, then, be accepted as our account, in li 
general terms, of the nature of justice and injustice 
respectively, and of that which is just and that which 
is imjust. 
iotu can act ®* "^^^ sincc it is possiblc for a man to do an act i 
^at!^ of injustice without yet being xmjust, what acts of 
,^t5"**" injustice are there, such that the doing of them 
u^ui^ stamps a man at once as unjust in this or that parti- 
'uut^ cular way, e.g, as a thief, or an adulterer, or a 

fort<ijnpii«rODDer f 

Perhaps we ought to reply that there is no such 
difference in the acts.* A man might commit 
adultery, knowing what he was about, and yet be 
acting not from a deliberate purpose at all, but from 
a momentary passion. In such a case, then, a man 2 
acts unjustly, but is not imjust; e.g, is not a thief 
though he commits a theft, and is not an adulterer 
though he commits adultery, and so on.t 

* It is in the state of mind of the doet that the difference liefli 
not in the particular things done : c/. iTt/ra, cap. 8. 

f This passage, cap. 6, §§ 1, 2, seems to have quite a natural 
connection with what goes before, though the discussion is not carried 
on here, but in cap. 8. Again, the disoassion which begins with 



6, 19-6, 4.] JUSTICE. 161 

8 We have already explained the relation which 
4 requital bears to that which is just. But we must 
not £ail to notice that what we are seeking is at 
once that which is just simply [or without any 
qualifying epithet], and that which is just in a state 
or between citizens * Now, this implies men who 
associate together in order to supply their deficiencies, 
being free men, and upon a footing of equality, either 
absolute or proportionate. 

Between those who are not upon this footing, 
then, we cannot speak of that which is just as be- 
tween citizens (though there is something that can be 
called just metaphorically),- For the term just can- 
not be properly applied, except where men have a 
law to appeal to,t and the eidstence of law implies 
the existence of injustice; for the administration of 
the law is the discrimination of what is just from 
what is unjust. 

But injustice impHes an act of injustice (though 
an act of injustice does not always imply injustice) 
which is taking too much of the goods and too little 

tlie words irws fi^v oZy, cap. 6, § 8, though it has no connection with 
§ % oomes naturally enough after the end of cap. 6, rh airXSos 
tUtauiv oorrespondiag to rov hucaiov Koi iLdUov koBSxov, We haye, 
then, two disonssions, both growing ont of and attached to the 
disonssion which closes with the end of cap. 6, bnt not connected 
-with each other. If the author had revised the work, he would, no 
doubt, have fitted these links together ; but as he omitted to do so, 
it is useless for us to attempt, by any rearrangement of the links, to 
secure the close connection which could only be effected by forging 
them anew. 

* These are not two distinct kinds of justice ; justice proper, he 
means to say, implies a state. 

t Only the citizen in an ancient state could appeal to the law in 
his own person ; the non-citizen could only sue through a citizen. 

M. 



; 



162 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. V. 

of the evils of life. And so we do not allow an indi- 5 
vidual to rule over us, but make written laws; for 
an individual is apt thus to take more for himseli^ 
and to become a tyrant. 

The magistrate's function, then, is to secure that 
which is just, and if that which is just, then that 
which is equal or fair. But it seems that he gets no 6 
advantage from his office, if he is just ; for he does 
not take a larger share of the good things of life, 
except when that larger share is proportionate to his 
worth. He works, therefore, in the interests of others 
(which is the reason why justice is sometimes called 
"another's good," as we remarked before).* Some 7 
salary, therefore, must be given him, and this he 
receives in the shape of honours and privileges ; and 
it is when magistrates are not content with these 
that they make themselves tyrants. 

That which is just as between master and slave, 8 
or between father and child, is not the same as this, 
though like. We cannot speak (without qualification) 
of injustice towards what is part of one's self — and a 
man's chattels and his children (so long as they are of 
a certain age and not yet separated from their parent) 
are as it were a part of him — for no one deliberately 
chooses to injure himself; so that a man cannot be 9 
unjust towards himself. 

We cannot speak in this case, then, of that which 
is unjust, or of that which is just as between citizens; 
for that, we found, is according to law, and subsists 
between those whose situation implies law, i.e., as we 
found, those who participate equally or fairly in 
governing and being governed. 

* Supi'ttf 1, 17. 



tr 
verUumal. 



6, 5-7, 4.] JUSTICE. 1G3 

The term just, therefore, is more appropriate to 
a man's relations to his wife than to his relations to 
his children and his chattels, and we do speak in 
this sense of that which is just in a family ; but even 
this is not the same as that which is just between 
citizens.* (,. ^ 

7. Now, of that which is just as between citizens, n it in pa 
part is natural, part is conventional. That is natural partcorU 
which has the same validity everywhere, and does 
not depend on our accepting or rejecting it; that is 
conventional which at the outset may be determined 
in this way or in that indifferently, but which when 
once determined is no longer indifferent ; e.g. that a 
man's ransom be a mina, or that a sacrifice consist 
of a goat and not of two sheep ; and, again, those 
ordinances which are made for special occasions, such 
as the sacrifice to Brasidas [at Amphipolis], and all 
ordinances that are of the nature of a decree. 

Now, there are people who think that what is just 
is always conventional, because that which is natural 
is invariable, and has the same validity everywhere, 
as fire bums here and in Persia, while that which is 
just is seen to be'xiot invariable. 

But this is not altogether true, though it is true in 
a way. Among the gods, indeed, we may venture to 
say it is not true at all ; but of that which is just 
among us part is natural, though all is subject to 
change. Though all is subject to change, nevertheless, 
I repeat, part is natural and part not. 

Nor is it hard to distinguish, among things that 
may be other than they are, that which is naturjj 

* Which alone is properly jnsfc. 



164 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. V. 

from that which is not natural but dependent on law 
or convention, though both are alike variable. In 
other fields we can draw the same distinction ; we 
say, for instance, that the right hand is naturally the 
stronger, though in some * men the left may become 
equally strong. 

And so, of that which is just, that part which is 5 
conventional and prescribed with a view to a par- 
ticular endt varies as measures vary; for the measures 
of wine and of com are not everywhere the same, but 
larger where the dealers buy, and smaller where they 
selL So I say that which is just not by nature but 
merely by human ordinance is not the same every- 
where, any more than constitutions are everywhere 
the same, though there is but one co nstitu tion that is 
naturally the best everywhere. 

The terms "just " and " lawful" in each of their 6 
several senses stand for universal notions which em- 
brace a number of particulars ; i,e, the acts are many, 
but the notion is one, for it is applied to all alike. 

" That which is unjust," we must notice, is different 7 
from " an act of injustice," and " that which is just" 
from " an act of justice : " for a thing is unjust either 
by nature or by ordinance ; but this same thing when 
done is called " an act of injustice," though before it 
was done it could only be called unjust. And so with 
" an act of justice " (Siicafwjua) ; though in the latter 

* Or " in any man,'* if we read irdyras, which is found according 
to Jackson in all of the manuscripts. 

t rh ^vix<l>4poyf which is nsually rendered " expedient," means 
simply that which condnces to any desired end ; as the end varies, 
then, so will the expedient vary : cf. III. 1, 15, note. 



7, 5-8, 3.] JUSTICE. 1G5 

case we rather employ SiKaioirpayriiia as the gen- 
eric term, and restrict SiKaltofm to the correction of 
an act of injustice. But as to the several species of 
acts of justice and injustice, we must postpone for the 
present the inquiry into their nature and number and 
the ground which they cover. 

8. Now that we have ascertained what is just and jv A^r 
what is xmjust, we may say that a man acts unjustly ajJior 
or justly when he does these things V^oluntarily ; but oce^Xa 
when he does them involuntarily, he does not, strictly unjutti 
speaking, act either unjustly or justly, but only 
" accidentally," i,e, he does a thing which happens to 
be just or unjust.* For whether an act is or is not 
to be called an act of injustice (or of justice) depends 
upon whether it is voluntary or involuntary ; for if it 
be voluntary the agent is blamed, and at the same 
time the act becomes an act of injustice : so something 
unjust may be done, and yet it may not be an act of 
injustice, i.e. if this condition of voluntariness be absent. 

By a voluntary act I mean, as I explained before, 
anything which, being within the doer's control, is 
done knowingly (i.e. with knowledge of the person, 
the instrument, and the result ; e.g, the person whom 
and the instrument with which he is striking, and the 
effect of the blow), without the intervention at any 
point of accident or constraint; e.g. if another take 
your hand and with it strike a third person, that is 
not a voluntary act of yours, for it was not within 
your control ; again, the man you strike may be your 
father, and you may know that it is a man, or perhaps 
that it is one of the company, that you are striking 

♦ Of. § 4. 



166 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. V. 

but not know that it is your father ; and it must be 
understood that the same distinction is to be made 
with regard to the result, and, in a word, to the whole 
act. That then which either is done in ignorance, or, 
though not done in ignorance, is not imder our control, 
or is done under compulsion, is involuntary ; besides 
which, there are many natural processes in which we 
knowingly take an active or a passive part, which 
cannot be called either voluntary or involuntary, such 
as growing old and dying. 

An accidentally unjust act and an accidentally just 4 
act are equally possible ; e.g. a man might restore a 
deposit against his will for fear of consequences, and 
then you could not say that he did what was just or 
acted justly except accidentally : * and, similarly, a 
man who against his will was forcibly prevented from 
restoring a deposit would be said only accidentally 
to act unjustly or to do that which is unjust. 

\^ Voluntary acts, again, are divided into (1) those 5 
that are done of set purpose, and (2) those that are 
done without set purpose ; i.e. (1) those that are done 
after prevdous deliberation, and (2) those that are done 
without previous deliberation. 
. ■ Now, there are three ways in which we may hurt fi 
/ our neighbour. Firstly, a hurt done in ignorance is 

/ generally called a mistake when there is a misconcep- 
tion as to the person affected, or the thing done, or the 
instrument, or the result ; e.g. I may not think to hit, 

* i.e. he willed the act not as jnst, bnt as a means of avoiding 
the painfnl consequences ; the justice of it, therefore, was not part of 
the essence of the act to him, was not among the qualities of the act 
which moved him to choose it, or, in Aristotle's language, was 
"accidental." 



8, 4-9.1 JUSTICE 167 

or not to hit with this instrument, or not to hit this 
person, or not to produce this effect, but an effect 
follows other than that which was present to my 
mind; I may mean to inflict a prick, not a wound, or 
not to wound the person whom I wound, or not to 
deal a wound of this kind. 

7 But [if we draw the distinction more accurately] 
when the hurt comes about contrary to what might 
reasonably be expected, it may be called a mishap : 
but when, though it is not contrary to what might 
reasonably be expected, there is stiU no vicious inten- 
tion, it is a mistake ; for a man makes a mistake 
when he sets the train of events in motion,* but he is 
unfortunate when an external agency interferes.f 

8 Secondly, when the agent acts with knowledge 
but without previous deliberation, it is an act of 
injustice ; e.g. when he is impelled by anger or any 
of the other passions to which man is necessarily or 
naturally subject. In doing such hurt and committing 
such errors, the doer acts unjustly and the acts are 
acts of injustice, though they are not such as to stamp 
him as unjust or wicked; for the hurt is not done out 
of wickedness. 

9 But, thirdly, when it is done of set purpose, the ^ 
doer is unjust and wicked. 

On this account acts done in anger are rightly 
held not to be done of malice aforethought; for he who 
gave the provocation began it, not he who did the 
deed in a passion. 

♦ whioh leads by a natural, though by him unforeseen, sequence 
to his neighbour's hurt : negligence, or error of judgment. 

t and gives a fatal termination to an act that would ordinarily 
be harmless t accident. 



168 KICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. V. 

Again, in such cases as this last, what men dispute 10 
about is usually not whether the deed was done or 
not, but what the justice of the case is ; for it is an 
apparent injustice that stirs the assailant's wrath. 
There is a difference between cases of this kind and 
disputes about contracts: in the latter the question 
is a question of fact, and one or other of the parties 
must be a vicious character, imless his memory be at 
fault; but in these cases they agree about the facts, 
but differ as to which side is in the right, so that the 
assailant (differing herein from the deliberate aggressor, 
who knows very well the rights of the case) thinks 
that he is wronged, while the other thinks differently.* 
\ But if a man hurt another of set purpose, he acts li 

unjustly, and acts of injustice (i.e. violations of what 
is proportionate and fair), when so done, stamp the 
doer as an tmjust character. 

In like manner a man is a just character when he 
of set purpose acts justly ; but he is said to act justly 
if he merely do voluntarily that which is just, 
v/ Of involuntary injuries, on the other hand, some 12 
are pardonable, some unpardonabla Errors that 
are committed not merely in ignorance but by reason 
of ignorance are pardonable; but those that are 
committed not through ignorance but rather in 
ignorance, through some unnatural or inhuman pas- 
sion, are not pardonable.f 

♦ Throwing the words b 8* ^tjSovXe^as oIk hyvou into a paren- 
thesis, after Zell. Bekker's stopping gives a sense which does not 
seem to fit the context. 

t In strictness, of conrse, snch acts cannot be called involun- 
tary (hcoifffui) at all : c/. 8uj^ay III. 1, where the conditions of an 
involuntary act are stated more precisely. 



8, 10-9, 8.] JUSTICE. 169 

9. But it may be doubted whether we have suffi- aundy 
ciently explained what it is to suffer and to do c^oain, 
injustice. First of all, are these terms applicable to ing irvuSi 
such a case as that which is described in those strange 
verses of Euripides ? — 

" I slew my mother — brief shall be my tale — 
Both willed it ; she at least willed, if not I." ) 

Is it really possible, I mean, to suffer injustice [or be i 
wronged] voluntarily ? or is suffering injustice always / 
involuntary, as doing injustice is always voluntary ? 

Again, is suffering injustice always one way or 1/ 
the other (as doing injustice is always voluntary), or 
is it sometimes voluntary and sometimes involuntary? 

Similarly with regard to having justice done to 
you: doing justice is always voluntary [as doing 
injustice is], so that one might expect that there is 
the same relation in both cases between the active 
and the passive, and that suffering injustice and 
having justice done to you are either both voluntary 
or both involuntary. But it would surely be absurd 
to maintain, even with regard to having justice done 
to you, that it is always voluntary; for some that 
have justice done to them certainly do not will it. 

So we may raise the question in this [more general] 
form : Can a man who has that which is unjust done 
to him always be said to suffer injustice [or be 
wronged] ? or are there further conditions necessary 
for suffering as there are for doing injustice ? 

Both what I do and what I suffer may be (as we 
saw) "accidentally" just; and so also it may be 
"accidentally" unjust: for doing that which is un- 
tust is not identical with doing injustice, nor is 



n/ 



170 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk. V. 

suffering that which is unjust the same as suffering 
injustice; and similarly with doing justice and having 
justice done to you. For to have injustice done to 
you implies some one that does injustice, and to 
have justice done to you implies some one that does 
justice. 

But if to do injustice means simply to hurt a man i 
voluntarily, and voluntarily means with knowledge 
of the person, the instrument, the manner, etc., then 
the incontinent man, who voluntarily hurts him- 
self, will voluntarily suffer injustice, and it will be 
possible for a man to do injustice to himself — ^the 
possibility of which last is also one of the questions 
in dispute. 

Again, a man might, through incontinence, volun- 5 
tarily suffer himself to be hurt by another also acting 
voluntarily; so that in this case also a man might 
voluntarily suffer injustice. 

I think rather that the above definition is in- 
correct, and that to " hurting with knowledge of the 
person, the instrument, and the manner," we must 
add " against his will." * If we define it so, then a 6 
man may voluntarily be hurt and suffer that which 
is imjust, but cannot voluntarily have injustice done 
to him. (For no one wishes to be hurt, — even the 
incontinent man does not wish it, but acts contrary 
to his wish. No one wishes for anything that he 
does not think good ; what the incontinent man does 

* ^oiXiiffiv is used loosely for wUl, as there is no abstract term 
corresponding to kKdv. Hence the well-known difficoltj in § 6, to 
be solved I think (even after reading Jackson's ingenious ezplaim* 
tion) by disregarding the words which I have bracketed. 



9, 4-10.] JUSTICE. 171 

7 is not that which he thinks he ought to do.) But he 
that gives, as Glaucus gives to Diomede in Homer — 

" Gk>ld for his bronze, fivescore kino's worth for nine/' 

does not suffer injustice; for the giving rests with 
him, but suffering injustice does not rest with one's 
self; there must be some one to do injustice. 

8 Itjs^plsiiin^iheii, ihaX suffering injustice cannot be 
voluntary. 

There are still two questions that we purposed to 
discuss: (1) Is it the man who assigns or the man 
wha receives a disproportionately large share that 
does injustice ? (2) Is it possible to do injustice to 
yourself? 

9 In the former case, i.e. if he who assigns and not 
he who receives the undue share does injustice, then 
if a man knowingly and voluntarily gives too much 
to another and too little to himself, he does injustice 
to himself And this is what moderate persons are 
often thought to do ; for the equitable man is apt to 
take less than his due. But the case is hardly so 
simple: it may be that he took a larger share of 
some other good, e,g. of good fame or of that which is 
intrinsically noble. 

Again, the difficulty may be got over by reference 
to our definition of doing injustice; for in this case 
nothing is done to the man against his wish, so that 
no injustice is done him, but at most only harm. 
It is plain, moreover, that the man who makes 

the unjust award does injustice, but not always he 
who gets more than his share ; for a man does not 
always do injustice when we can say of what he 



\ 



172 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OP ARISTOTLE. [Bk. V. 

does that it is unjust, but only when we can say 
that he voluntarily does that which is uiyust; and 
that we can only say of the prime mover in the 
action, which in this case is the distributor and not 
the receiver. 

Again, there are many senses of the word " do," ii 
and in a certain sense an inanimate instrument, or my 
hand, or again my slave under my orders, may be said 
to slay ; but though these may be said to do what is 
unjust, they cannot be said to act ujijustly or to do an 
act of injustice. 

Again, if a man unwittingly gives unjust judg- 12 
ment, he does not commit injustice in the sense of 
contravening that which is just according to law, 
nor is his judgment unjust in this sense, but in a 
certain sense it is myuSt-T^for there is a diflFerence 
i between that which is just according to law and that 
I which is just in the primary sense of the word : but 
if he knowingly gives unjust judgment, he is himself 
grasping at more than his share, in the shape either 
of favour with one party or vengeance on the 
other. The judge, then, who gives unjust judgment 13 
on these grounds, takes more than his due, quite as 
much as if he received a share of the unjust award ; 
for even in the latter case a judge who awards a piec€ 
of land would receive, not land, but money. 

Men fancy that as it is in their power to act 14 
unjustly, so it is an easy matter to be just. But it is 
not so. To lie with your neighbour's wife, or to strike 
your neighbour, or to pass certain coins from your 
hand to his is easy enough, and always within your 
power, but to do these acts as the outcome of a certain 



9, 11-16.] JUSTICE. 173 

character is not an easy matter, nor one which is 
always within your power.* ^ 

16 Similarly men think that to know what is just 
and what is unjust needs no great wisdom, since any 
one can inform himself in those matters about which the 
law prescribes. But what is just is not given (unless 
it be accidentally) by the mere rules of law, but by 
the application of these in a particular manner to our 
actions and the distribution of gooda And to know 
this, application is a harder matter than to know 
what conduces to health; though that is no easy 
matter. It is easy enough to know the meaning of 
honey, and wine, and hellebore, and cautery, and the f 
knife, but to know how, and to whom, and when they 
must be applied in order to produce health, is so far 
from being easy, that to have this knowledge is to be 
a physician. 

16 For the same reason, some people think that the 
just man is as able to act unjustly as justly, for he 
is not less but rather more capable than another of 
performing the several acts, e.g. of lying with a 
woman or of striking a blow, as the courageous man 
is rather more capable than another of throwing away 
his shield and turning his back and running away 
anywhere. But to play the coward or to act unjustly 
means not merely to do such an act (though the 

* Yon can always do the acts if yon want to do them, t.e. if yon 
wiU them j bnt yon cannot at will do them in the spirit of a jnst 
man or as the ontcome of a jnst character; for character is the 
result of a series of acts of will : cf. sv/pra^ III. 5, 22. The contra- 
diction between this and III. 5, 2, is only apparent : we are respon- 
sible for onr character, though we cannot change it at a moment's 
notice. 



174 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF AEISTOTLB. [Bk. V 



doer might be said " accidentally " to act unjustly 






but to do it in a certain firame of mind ; just as to act 
the part of a doctor and to heal does not mean simply 
to apply the knife or not to apply it, to give or to 
jnthhold a drug, but to do this in a particular fashion. 
V Justice, lastly, implies persons who participate in 17 
those things that, generally speaking, are good, but who 
can have too much or too little of them. For some — 
for the gods perhaps — no amoimt of them is too much ; 
and for others — ^for the incurably vicious — ^no amount 
is beneficial, they are always hurtful ; but for the rest 
of mankind they are useful within certain limits : 
justice, therefore, is essentially human. 
f equity. 10* Wc havo ucxt to spcak of equity and of that 1 

which is equitable, and to inquire how equity is 
related to justice, and that which is equitable to that 
which is just. For, on consideration, they do not 
seem to be absolutely identical, nor yet generically 
different. At one time we praise that which is 
equitable and the equitable man, and even use the 
word metaphorically as a term of praise synonymous 
with good, showing that we consider that the more 
equitable a thing is the better it is. At another 
time we reflect and find it strange that what is 
equitable should be praiseworthy, if it be different 
from what is just ; for, we argue, if it be something 
sj else, either what is just is not good, or what is equit- 
able is not good ; f if both be good, they are the same. 

* Gf. swpray 8, 1-4. 

t Ow iUaiov I have omitted (after Trendelenburfr) as obviously 
wrong. We may suppose either that the original ov ffirovdouoy was 
altered into od SlKcuoPt or (more probably) that ov dfKcuoy or Hkouop 
was inserted by a bungling copyist. 



9, 17-10, 5.J JUSTICE. • 175 

2 These are the reflections which give rise to the 
difficulty about what is equitable. Now, in a way, 
they are all correct and not incompatible with one 
another; for that which is equitable, though it is 
better than that which is just (in one sense of the 
word), is yet itself just, and is not better than what 

is just in the sense of being something generically j 
distinct from it. What is just, then, and what is y 
equitable are generically the same, and both are good, 
though what is equitable is better, 

3 But what obscures the matter is that though \J 
what is equitable is just, it is not identical with, but 

a correction of, that which is just according to law. 
\ The reason of this is that every law is laid down 
in general terms, while there are matters about which y 
it is impossible to speak correctly in general terms. 
Where, then, it is necessary to speak in general terms, 
but impossible to do so correctly, the legislator lays 
down that which holds good for the majority of 
cases, being quite aware that it does not hold good 
for aU. 

The law, indeed, is none the less correctly laid 
down because of this defect; for the defect lies not 
in the law, nor in the lawgiver, but in the nature of 
the subject-matter, being necessarily involved in the 
very conditions of human action. 

When, therefore, the law lays down a general rule, 
but a particular case occurs which is an exception to 
this rule, it is right, where the legislator fails and is 
in error through speaking without qualification, to 
make good this deficiency, just as the lawgiver him- 
self would do if he were present, and as he would 



176 NIOOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. V. 

have provided in the law itself if the case had occurred 
to him. 

What is equitable, then, is just, and better than 6 
what is just in one sense of the word — ^not better 
than what is absolutely just, but better than that 
which fails through its lack of qualification. And the 
essence of what is equitable is that it is an amend- 
\ ment of the law, in those points where it fails through 
the generality of its language. 

The reason why the law does not cover all cases 
is that there are matters about which it is impossible 
to lay down a law, so that they require a special 
decree. For that which is variable needs a variable 7 
rule, like the leaden rule employed in the Lesbian style 
of masonry ; as the leaden rule has no fixed shape, but 
adapts itself to the outline of each stone, so is the 
decree adapted to the occasion. 

We have ascertained, then, what the equitable 8 
course is, and have found that it is just, and also 
better than what is just in a certain sense of the 
word. And after this it is easy to see what the 
equitable man is: he who is apt to choose such a 
course and to follow it, who does not insist on his 
rights to the damage of others, but is ready to take 
less than his due, even when he has the law to back 
him, is called an equitable man; and this type of 
character is called equitableness, being a sort of justice, 
and not a difierent kind of character. 
'.naman ^^* The foregoing discussion enables us to answer 1 
jng htm- ^j^^ qucstiou whcthcr it be possible or not for a man 
to act unjustly to himself. 

That which is just in one sense of the word we 



10, 6-11, 4] JlJSTIOa. 177 

found to be those manifestations of the sevelral virtues 
which the law prescribes : e.g. the law does not order 
a man to kill himself; and what the law does not 
order it forbids : and, further, when a man, contrary 
to the law, voluntarily inflicts hurt without provoca- 
tion, he acts unjustly (voluntarily meaning with know- 
ledge of the person and the instrument). Now, the 
man who kills himself in a rage voluntarily acts thus 
against right reason and does what the law forbids : • 
he acts unjustly therefore. 

But unjustly to whom ? To the state surely, not \J 
to himself; for he suffers volimtarily, but no one can 
have an injustice done him voluntarily. And upon 
this ground the state actually punishes him, i.e. it pro- 
nounces a particular kind of disfranchisement upon 
the man who destroys himself, as one who acts unjustly 
towards the state. 

Again, if we take the word imjust in the other 
sense, in which it is used to designate not general 
badness, but a particular species of vice, we find that 
in this sense also it is impossible to act unjustly to 
one's self (This, we found, is different from the former 
sense of the word : the unjust man in this second sense 
is bad in the same way as the coward is bad, i,e. as 
having a particular form of vice, not as having a 
completely vicious character, nor do we mean to say 
that he displays a completely vicious character when 
we say that he acts unjustly). For if it were possible, 
it would be possible for the same thing at the same 
time to be taken from and added to the same person. 
But this is impossible ; and, in fact, a just deed or an ^ 
unjust deed always implies more persons than one. '' 

K 



178 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OP ARISTOTLE. [Bk. T. 

Further, an act of injiistice, besides being voluntary, 6 
if not deliberate, must be prior to hurt received Cfor 
he who, having received some hurt, repays the same 
that he received is not held to act unjustly) ; but he 
who hurts himself suffers that very hurt at the same 
time that he inflicts it. 
V Again, if it were possible for a man to act unjustly 6 

to himself, it would be possible to suffer injustice 
voluntarily. 

Further, a man cannot act unjustly without doing 
an act of injustice of some particular kind ; but no 
one commits adultery with his own wife, or burglari- 
ously breaks through his own walls, or steals his 
own property. 

But the whole question about acting unjustly to 
one's self is settled (without going into detail) by the 
answer we gave * to the question whether a man could 
voluntarily suffer injustice. 

(It is plain that to suffer and to do injustice are 7 
both bad, for the one is to get less and the other more 
than the mean amount, which corresponds to what is 
healthy in medicine, or to what promotes good con- 
dition in gymnastics : but, though both are bad, to do 
injustice is the worse ; for to do injustice i& blamable 
and implies vice (either completely formed vice, what 
we call vice simply, or else that which is on the way 
to become vice ; for a voluntary act of injustice does 
not always imply injustice), but to have injustice done 
to you is no token of a vicious and tmjust character. 

In itself, then, to be unjustly treated is less bad, 8 
but there is nothing to prevent its being accidentally 

• Supray cap. 0. 



11, 5-9.] JUSTICE. 171) 

the greater eviL Science, however, does not concern 
itself with these accidents, but calls a pleurisy a 
greater malady than a stumble;- and yet the latter 
might, on occasion, accidentally become the greater, 
as, for instance, if a stumble were to cause you to fall 
and be caught by the enemy and slain.) 
9 Though we cannot apply the term just to a man's 
behaviour towards himself, yet we can apply it meta- 
phorically and in virtue of a certain resemblance to 
the relations between certain parts of a man's self— 
not, however, in all senses of the word just, but in that 
sense in which it is applied to the relations of master 
and slave, or husband and wife ; for this is the soi-t 
of relation that exists between the rational and the 
irrational parts of the souL 

And it is this distinction of parts that leads people 
to fancy that there i& such a thing as injustice 
to one's self : one part of a man can have something 
done to it by another part contrary to its desires ; 
and so they think that the term just can be applied 
to the relations of these parts to one another, just as 
to the relations of ruler and ruled.* 

We may now consider that we have concluded our 
examination of justice and the other moral virtues. 

* Whereas, says Aristotle, we cannot sp^k alt all of jnstioe or 
injustice to one's self, and it is only by way of metaphor that we 
can apply the terms even to the relations of parts of the self — not 
strictly, since the parts are not persons. 



^Jatk... 



BOOK VI. 

THE INTELLECTUAL VIRTXJES. 

MuH he 1. We said above that what we should choose is 1 

hecause neither too much nor too little, but " the mean," and 
^L^jS? that " the mean " is what " right reason " prescribes. 

th^ meant rm.* i_ x i • 

(b) they are ihis WO now havo to explain. 

hJ^ln Each of the viriiues we have discussed implies (as 

esBcellenee 

TheinteLUct evcpy mental habit implies) some aim which the 
tijic, (2) cau rational man keeps in view when he is regulating his 

culative: we c? «^ 

v>ant tha efforts : in other words, there must be some standard 

virtue (ff %.( 

each. Xfor determining the several modes of moderation, 
which we say lie between excess and deficiency, and 
are in accordance with "right reason." But though 2 
this is quite true, it is not sufficiently precise. In 
any kind of occupation which can be reduced to 
rational principles, it is quite true to say that we 
must brace ourselves up and relax ourselves neither 
too much nor too little, but "in moderation," " as right 
reason orders ; " but this alone would not tell one 
much ; e.g. a man would hardly learn how to treat a 
case by being told to treat it as the art of medicine 
prescribes, and as one versed in that art would 
treat it. 

So in the case of mental habits or types of 3 
character also it is not enough that the rule we have 



1, 1-6.] THE IKTELLEOTUAL VIRTUES. 181 

laid down is correct ; we need further to know pre- ^^ 
cisely what this right reason is, and what is the 
standard which it aflTords. 

4 * The virtues or excellences of the mind or soul, it 
will be remembered, we divided t into two classes, / 
and called the one moral and the other intellectual, v 
The moral excellences or virtues we have already 
discussed in detail; let us now examine the other 
class, the intellectual excellences, after some prelimi- 
nary remarks about the soul. / 

6 We said before that the soul consists of two ]/ 
parts, the rational and the irrational part. We will 
now make a similar division of the former, and will 
assume that there are two rational faculties : (1) that ^ 
by which we know those things that depend on 
invariable principles, (2) that by which w^ know 
those things that are variable. For to generically 
different objects must correspond generically different 
faculties, if, as we hold, it is in virtue of some kind 
of likeness or kinship with their objects that our 
faculties are ablato know them. 

6 Let us call the former the scientific or demonstra- <^ 

• This really forms quite a fresh opening, independent of §§ 1-3 ; 
and it is one among many signs of the incomplete state in which 
this part of the treatise was left, that these two openings of 
Book VI. were never fnsed together. The scheme of the treatise, as 
unfolded in Book I. (c/. especially I. 7, 13; 13, 20), gives the 
intellectual virtues an independent place alongside of, or rather 
above, the moral virtues ; now that the latter have been disposed of 
it naturally remains to consider the former : this is the natural 
transition which we have in § 4. But besides this the dependence 
of the moral virtues upon the intellectual virtues makes an examina. 
tiou of the latter absolutely necessary to the completion of the 
theory of the former; thus we get the transition of §§ 1-3. 
t 5if2>ra, 1. 18, 20. 



.82 NIOOMACHBAN ETHICS OF AEISTOTLE. [Bk. \ I. 

tive, the latter the calculative or deUberafcive fiaculty. 

For to deliberate is the same as to calculate, and no 
I one deliberates about things that are invariable. On6 
I division then of the rational faculty may be fairly 
i^ called the calculative faculty. 

\/ Our problem, then, is to find what each of these 7 
faculties becomes in its full development, or in its 
best state ; for that will be its excellence or virtue. 

But its excellence will bear direct reference to 
its proper function. 
he functions/ 2. Now, the facultics which ffuide us in action and l 

'thtxnteir- , ° 

ct, both in in the apprehension of truth are three : sense, reason,* 

racticeand it. " — ■ ■■ » --.» 

)ecuiation, and dcsire. 

to attain. *■ /• i . . • 

"<^ The first of these cannot originate action, as we 2 

see from the fact that brutes have sense but are 
incapable of action. 

If we take the other two we find two modes of 
reasoning, viz. affirmation and negation [or assent 
I and denial], and two corresponding modes of desire, 
\ viz. pursuit and avoidance [or attraction and re- 
pulsion]. 
V Now, moral virtue is a habit or formed faculty of 

choice or purpose, and purpose is desire following 
upon deUberation. 

It follows, then, that if the purpose is to be all it 
should be, both the calculation or reasoning must be 
true and the desire right, and that the very same 
things must be assented to by the former and pursued 
by the latter. 

This kind of reasoning, then, and this sort of truth 
has to do with action. 

* vovs : the word is used here in its widest sense. 



1, 7-2, 6.] THE INTELLEOTUAL VIBTUES. 183 

/ 

3 But epeculative reasoning that has to do neither 
with action nor production is good or bad according 
as it is true or false simply : for the function of the 
intellect is always the apprehension of truth; but 
the function of the practical intellect is the appre- 

/ hension of truth in agreement with right desire. 

4 Purpose, then, is the cause — not the final but the 
efficient cause or origin — of action, and the origin of 
purpose is desire and calculation of means ; so that 
purpose necessarily implies on the one hand the 
faculty of reason and its exercise, and on the other 
hand a certain moral character or state of the desires ; 
for right action and the contrary kind of action are 
alike impossible without both reasoning and moral 

. character. 

U Mere reasoning, however, can never set anything 
going, but only reasoning about means to an end— 
what may be called practical reasoning (which 
practical reasoning also regulates production ; for in 
making anything you always have an ulterior object 
in view — ^what you make is desired not as an end in 
itself, but only as a means to, or a condition of, some- 
thing else ; but what you do is an end in itself, for 
well-doing or jdght. action is the end, and this is the 
IpJgedrsrHesire). 

"^ Purpose, then, may be called either a reason that _rp 
desires, or a desire that reasons ; and this faculty of 
originating action constitutes a man. f '" - — ^. 

\ — --lia.-pa^? event can be purposed ; e.g, no one 
purposes to have sacked Troy ; for no one delibe- 
rates about that which is past, but about that which 
is to come, and which is variable : but the past 



/ 



[ 






mHATiaOU- 



184 NICOMACHBAN ETHICS OP ARISTOTLE. [Bk. VL 

cannot be undone ; so that Agathon is right when he 
says — 



We have thus found that both divisions of the 
reason, or both the intellectual faculties, have the 
attainment of truth for their function ; that developed 
state of each, then, in which it best attains truth will 
be ita excellence or virtue. 

3. Let us describe these virtues then, starting : 
afresh from the beginning. 

Let us assume that the modes in which the mind 
arrives at truth, either in the way of affirmation or 



^ negation, are five in number, viz. art, science,_pru-^ 
dence, wisdom, reason j • for conception and opinion 
may be erroneous. 

What science is we may learn from the following 
consideratiom^ (for we want a precise account, and 
must not content ourselves with metaphors). We all 
suppose that what we know with scientific know- 
ledge is invariable ; but of that which is variable 
we cannot say, so soon as it is out of sight, whether 
it la in existence or not. The object of science, then, 
is necessary. Therefore it is eternal : for whatever i* 
of its own nature necessary is eternal : and what ia 
eternal neither begins nor ceases to be. 

Further, it is held that all science can be taught, 
and that what can be known in the way of science 
can be learnt. But all teaching starts from some- 

■ roCs — need now in anarrowet apecial sense which will presently 
be eiplaicod. 1 



8, 1-4, 3.] THE INTELLEOTUAL V1BTUE8. 185 

thing already known, as we have explained in the 
Analytics ; for it proceeds either by induction or by 
syllogism. Now, it is induction that leads the learner 
up to universal principles, while syllogism starts from 
these. There are principles, then, from which syllo- 
gism starts, which are not arrived at by syllogism, and 
which, therefore, must be arrived at by induction.* 
4 Science, then, may be defined as a habit or \/ 
formed faculty of demonstration, with all the further 
qualifications which are enumerated in the Analytics. 
It is necessary to add this, because it is only when 
the principles of our knowledge are accepted and 
known to us in a particular way, that we can pro- 
perly be said to have scientific knowledge ; for imless 
these principles are better known to us than the 
conclusions based upon them, our knowledge will be 
merely accidental, f 

This, then, may be taken as our account of science, ty^ 

1 4. That which is variable includes that which ^*«o»- 

ledge of 

man makes and that which man does ; but making JJj;^{^,^ 
or production is different from doing or action (here ^^^^^^l^ 

2 we adopt the popular distinctions). The habit oT^^t 
formed faculty of acting with reason or calculation, ^ 
then, is different from the formed faculty of producing 
with reason or calculation. And so the one cannot 
include the other ; for action is not production, nor is 
production action. 

8 Now, the bmlder's faculty is one of the arts, and 

* Thongh, as we see later, induction can elicit them from e:c« 
perience only because they are plready latent in that experience. 

f We m&j know truths of science, but unless we know these 
in their necessary connection, we have not scientific knowledge. 



/ 



186 NIOOMACHBAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk VL 

may be described as a certain formed faculty of pro- 
ducing with calculation ; and there is no art which 
is not a faculty of this kind^ nor is there any faculty 
of this kind which is not an art : an art^ then, is 
the same thing as a formed faculty of producing 
with correct calculation. 
yj And every art is concerned with bringing some- 4 
thing into being, i,e. with contriving or calculating 
how to bring into being some one of those things 
that can either be or not be, and the cause of whose 
production lies in the producer, not in the thing itself 
\ which is produced. AFor art has not to do with that 
which is or comes into being of necessity, nor with 
the products of nature ; for these have the cause of 
their production in themselves. 

Production and action being diflTerent, art of course 5 
has to do with production, and not with action. And, 
in a certain sense, its domain is the same as that 
of chance or fortune, as Agathon says — 

" Art waits on fortune, f oitiine waits on art," 

Art, then, as we said, is a certain formed faculty 6 
or habit of production with correct reasoning or cal- 
culation, and the contrary of this (arcx^fa) is a habit 
of production with incorrect calculation, the field of 
both being that which is variable. 
td (3) of 5. In order to ascertain what prudence is, we will i 

hat we do, first ask who they are whom we call prudent. 

£ virtue ^f -r, Jii ••^i 

e cdunda- , It secms to OB charactcnstic of a prudent man that 

ve intellect. , , 

he is able to deliberate weU about what is good or 
^ expedient for himself, not with a view to some par- 
ticular end, such as health or strength, but with a 
view to well-being or living well. 



4, 4-6, 6j THE INTELLECTUAL VIRTUES. 187 

2 This is confirmed by the fact that we apply the 
name sometimes to those who deliberate well in some 
particular field, when they calculate well the means 
to some particular good end, in matters that do not 
fell within the sphere of art. So we may say, gene- 
rally, that a man who can deliberate well is prudent 

3 But no one deliberates about that which cannot ^ 
be altered, nor about that which it is not in his 
power to do. 

Now science, we saw, implies demonstration ; but 
things whose principles or causes are variable do not 
admit of demonstration ; for everything that depends 
upon these principles or causes is also variable ; and, 
on the other hand, things that are necessarily deter- 
mined do not admit of deliberation. It follows, \/ 
therefore, that prudence cannot be either a science 
or an art : it cannot be a science, because the sphere 
of action is that which is alterable ; it cannot be an 
. art, because production is generically different from 
action. 

4 It follows from all this that prudence is a formed ^ 
feculty that apprehends truth by reasoning or calcu- 
lation, and issues in action, in the domain of human 
good and ill; for while production has another end 
than itself, this is not so with action, since good 
action or well doing is itself the end. 

5 For this reason Pericles and men who resemble 
him are considered prudent, because they are able to 
see what is good for themselves and for, men ; and 
this we take to be the character of those who are able 
to manage a household or a state. 

This, too, is the reason why we call temperance 



188 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLB. [Bk. VI. 

(raxppoaivri, signifying thereby that it is the virtue 
which preserves prudence. But what temperance 6 
preserves is this particular kind of judgment. For it 
is not any kind of judgment that is destroyed or 
perverted by the presentation of pleasant or painful 
objects (not such a judgment, for instance, as that 
the angles of a triangle are equal to two right angles), 
but only judgments about matters of practice. For 
the principles of practice [or the causes which originate 
action] * are the ends for the sake of which acts are 
done ; but when a man is corrupted by pleasure or 
pain, he straightway loses sight of the principle, and 
no longer sees that this is the end for the sake of 
which, and as a means to which, each particular 
act should be chosen and done; for vice is apt to 
obHterate the principle. 

\/ Our conclusion then is that prudence is a formed 

faculty which apprehends truth by reasoning or cal- 
culation, and issues in action, in the field of human 
good. 

Moreover, art [or the artistic faculty] has its excel- 7 
lence [or perfect development] in something other than 
itself, but this is not so with prudencaJI Again, in 

, the domain of art voluntary error is not so bad as 
involuntary, but it is worse in the case of prudence, 
as it is in the case of all the virtues or excellence& 
It is plain, then, that prudence is a virtue or excel- 
lence, and not an art. 

y And the rational parts of the soul or the intellectual 8 
faculties being two in number, prudence will be the 

* The oonoeption of the end is at once a cause er sonroe of 
action and a principle of knowledge ; ipx'i covers both. 



6, 6-6, 2.] THE INTELLEOTUAL VIRTUES. 189 

virtue of the second^ [the calculative part or] the 
faculty of opinion ; for opinion deals with that which 
is variable, and so does prudence. 

But it is something more than " a formed faculty 
of apprehending truth by reasoning or calculation ; ** 
as we see from the fact that such a faculty may be 
lost, but prudence, once acquired, can never be lost.* 

6. Science is a mode of ludging that deals with (*) ofintv 
umversal and necessary truths : but truths that « «*« ««*<j 

, qf demon' 

can be demonstrated depend upon principles, and J^^^ 
(since science proceeds by demonstrative reasoning) ^ 
every science has its principles^The principles, then, 
on which the truths of science depend cannot fall 
within the province of science, nor yet of art or 
prudence; for a scientific truth is one that can be 
demonstrated, but art and prudence have to do with' 
that which is variable. 

Nor can they fall within the province of wisdom ; 1/ 
for it is characteristic of the wise man to have a 
demonstrative knowledge of certain things. 

But the habits of mind or formed faculties by 
which we apprehend truth without any mixture of 
error, whether in the domain of things invariable or 
in the domain of things variable, are science, prudence, 
wisdom, and reason.t If then no one of the first 
three (prudence, science, wisdom) can be the faculty 

• For it implies a determination of the will which is more per- 
manent in its nature than a merely intellectual habit. And further, 
when once acquired it must be constantly strengthened by exercise, 
as occasions for action can never be wanting. 

t Art, which is one of the five enumerated above, is here 
omitted, either in sheer carelessness, or perhaps because it is sub- 
ordinate to prudence : qf. supra 5, 7. 



/ 



190 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk. VL 

which apprehends these principles, the only possible 
conclusion is that they are apprehended by reason. 
c6j Of 7. The term aotfila (wisdom*) is sometimes applied 1 

the union of in the domain of the arts to those who are consnm- 

science and <»i« •• ft -rvt • -i • 

intuuive mate masters of their art ; e.g, it is aj^lied to Phidias 



reaton. 



^htt^ as a master of sculpture, and to Polyclitus for his 
tJlJ^'**^ skill in portrait-statues; and in this application it 
'"^dSwe**^ means nothing else than excellence of art or perfect 

development of the artistic faculty. 

But there are also men wio are considered wise, 2 

not in part nor in any particular thing (as Homer 

says in the Margites — 

" Him the gods gave no skiU with spade or plough, 
Kor made him wise in aught"), 

but generally wise. In this general sense, then, 
wisdom plainly will be the most perfect of the sciences. 

\j The wise man, then, must not only know what 3 
follows from the principles of knowledge, but also 
know the truth about those principles. Wisdom, 

. therefore, will be the union of [intuitive] reason with 
[demonstrative] scientific knowledge, or scientific 
knowledge of the noblest objects with its crowning 
perfection, so to speak, added to it. For it would be 
absurd to suppose that the political faculty or pru- 
dence is 'the highest of our faculties, unless indeed 
man is the best of all things in the universe. 

Now, as the terms wholesome and good mean one 
thing in the case of men and another in the case of 
fishes, whUe white and straight always have the 
same meaning, we must all allow that wise means 

* Of course we do not use ** wisdom *' in this sense. 



7, 1-6.1 THE INTELLECl'UAL VIBTUEa 191 

\/oiie thing always, while prudent means different 
things; for we should aU say that those who are 
dear-sighted in their own affairs are prudent, and 
deem them fit to be entrusted with those affairs. 
(And for this reason we sometimes apply the term 
prudent even to animals, when they show a faculty 
of foresight in what concerns their own life.) 

Moreover, it is plain that wisdom cannot be the \^ 
same as statesmanship. If we apply the term wisdom 
to knowledge of what is advantageous to ourselves, 
there will be many kinds of wisdom ; for the know- 
ledge of what is good will not be one and the same 
for all animals, but different for each species. It 
ean no more be one than the art of healing can be 
one and the same for all kinds of living things. 

Man may be superior to aU other animals, but 
that will not make any difference here ; for there are 
other things of a far diviner nature than man, as — 
to take the most obvious instance — the heavenly 
bodies. 

5 It is plain, then, after what we have said, that 
wisdom is the union of scientific [or demonstrative] 
knonorledge and [intuitive] reason about objects of 
the noblest nature. 

sJ And on this account people call Anaxagoras and 
Thales and men of that sort wise, but not prudent, 
seeing them to be ignorant of their own advantage ; 
and say that their knowledge is something out of the 
common, wonderful, hard of attainment, nay super- 
human, but useless, since it is no human good that 
tb^seds:. 

5 Prudence, on the other hand, deals with human 



192 KIOOMAGHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. pte. Yt 

affidrs, and with matters that admit of deliberation : 
for the pradent man's special function^ as we conceive 
it, is to deliberate well ; but no one deliberates about 
what is invariable^ or about matters in which there 
is not some end, in the sense of some realizable good. 
\J But a man is said to deliberate well (without any 
qualifying epithet) when he is able, by a process of 
reasoning or calculation, to arrive at what is best for 
man in matters of practice. 
V Prudence, moreover, does not deal in general pro- 7 

positions only, but implies knowledge of particular 
facts also; for it issues in action, and the field of 
action is the field of particulars. 

This is the reason why some men that \bjSl 
[scientific] knowledge are more efficient in practice 
than others that have it, especially men of wide ex- 
perience ; for if you know that light meat is digestible 
and wholesome, but do not know what meats are 
light, you will not be able to cure people so well as 
a man who only knows that chicken is light and 
wholesome. 
V But prudence is concerned with practice; so that 
it needs knowledge both of general truths and of 
particular facts, but more especially J)hejp,tter. 

But here also \i,e. in the domain of practice] there 
must be a supreme form of the faculty [which we will 

\now proceed to consider]. 
I 8. And in fact statesmanship and prudence are the 1 
wit^stata- same faculty, though they are differently manifested. 
S?S?/^ Of this faculty in its application to the state the % 
wtetv*- supreme form is the legislative faculty, but the special 
form which deals with particular cases is called by 



T, 7-8, 4.] THE INTELLECTUAL VIRTUES. 193 

the generic name statesmanship. The field of the 
latter is action and deliberation ; for a decree directly 
concerns action, as the last link in the chain.* And 
on this account those enoraored in this field are alone 
said to be statesmen, for they alone act like handi- 
craftsmen. 

8 Bat it is when applied to the individual and to 
one's own affairs that this faculty is especially re- 
garded as prudence, and this is the form which 

I receives the generic name prudence or practical 

' wisdom (the other forms being (1) the faculty of 
managing a household, (2) the legislative faculty, 
(3) statesmanship [in the narrower sense], which is 
subdivided into (a) the deliberative, (6) the judicial 
faculty). 

4 Knowing one's own good, then, would seem to 
be a kind of knowledge (though it admits of great 
variety),! and, according to the general opinion, he 
who knows and attends to his own affairs is prudent, 
while statesmen are busybodies, as Euripides says^- 

•'What ? was I wise, who might without a oare 
Have lived a unit in the maltitade 
Like any other unit ? . • • 
For those who would excel and do great things " 

For men generally seek their own good, and fancy 
that is what they should do ; and from this opinion 
comes the notion that these men are prudent. 

And yet, perhaps, it is not possible for a man to 
manage his own affairs well without managing a 

* wpcucrhv &5 rh itrxo-rovt i.e. as the last link in the chain of causes 
Inading to the proposed end — last in the order of deliberation, but 
first in the order of events : c/. III. 8, 12. 

t Yarying as the good varies ; cf, sv^rob, 7, 4, and I. 3, 2. 

O 



/ 



194 NICOMACHBAN ETHIOS OP ABISTOTLB. [Bk. VL 

household and taking part in the management of a 
state. 

Moreover, how a man is to manage his own affairs 
is not plain and requires consideration. And this is 5 
attested by the fact that a young man may become 
proficient in geometry or mathematics and wise* 
in these matters, but cannot possibly, it is thought, 
become prudent. The reason of this is that prudence 
deals with particular facts, with which experience 
alone can familiarize usjf but a young man must be 
inexperienced, for experience is the fruit of years. 

Why again, we may ask, can a lad be a mathema- 6 
tician but not wise, nor proficient in the knowledge 
\^ of nature ? / And the answer surely is that mathematics 
is an abstract science, while the principles of wisdom 
and of natural science are only to be derived from 
a large experience ; f ^^^ that thus, though a young 
man may repeat propositions of the latter kind, he 
does not really believe them, while he can easily 
apprehend the meaning of mathematical terms. 

Error in deliberation, again, may lie either in 7 
the universal or in the particular judgment ; for in- 
stance, you may be wrong in judging that all water 
that weighs heavy is unwholesome, or in judging 
that this water weighs heavy. But prudence [in 8 
spite of its universal judgments] plainly is not science ; 

* Here in the looser sense, below (§ 6) in the stricter sense, which 
is the technical meaning of the term in Aristotle: cf. supra, 7, 12. 

t He does not mean that the principles of mathematics are not 
derived from experience, but only that they are derived frozn the 
primitive experience which every boy has, being in fact (as wo 
shonld say) the framework on which the simplest knowledge of- an 
external world is built. 



1 



8, £h-9, 2.] THB INTELLEOTUAL YIBTUES. 195 

for, as we said,* it deals with the ultimate or par- 
ticular fact [the last link in the chain], for anything 
that can be done must be of this nature. 

9/ And thus it is in a manner opposed to the 
intuitive reason also: the intuitive reason deals 
with primary principles which cannot be demon- 
strated, while prudence deals with ultimate [particular] 
facts which cannot be scientifically proved, but are 
perceived by sense — ^not one of the special senses, 
but a sense analogous to that by which we perceive 
in mathematics that this ultimate [particular] figure 
is a triangle ;t for here too our reasoning must come 
to a stand. But this faculty [by which we appre- 
hend particular facts in the domain of practice] should, 
after all, be called sense rather than prudence; for 
prudence cannot be defined thus.]: 

9. Inquiry and deliberation are not the same; for o/dda« 
deliberation is a particular kind of inquiry. But we 
must ascertain what good deliberation is — whether 
it is a kind of science or opinion, or happy guessing, 
or something quite diflferent. 

a v/ It is not science ; for we do not inquire about that 

• Of, supra, § 2. 

t The perception "that the ultimate fact is a triangle" (which 
IB the more obvions translation of these words), whether this means 
"that three lines is the least number that will enclose a space," 
or ''that the possibility of a triangle is a fact that cannot be 
demonstrated/' is in either case not the perception of a particular 
fact ; bnt it is the perception of a particular fact that is needed if 
the illustration is to be in point. 

X The intuitive reason (yovs) is here opposed to prudence 
{ppSm/icrts) , but presently (cap. 11) is found to be included in it; 
reason (vovs) was similarly in cap. 6 opposed to wisdom (ao^ia), but 
in cap. 7 found to be included in it. 



/: 



196 KICOMACJHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLB. [Bk. VL 

which we know: but good deliberation is a kind 
of deliberation, and when we deliberate we inquire 
and calculate. 

\/ Nor is it happy guessing; for we make happy 
guesses without calculating and in a moment, but we 
take time to deliberate, and it is a common saying 
that execution should be swift, but deliberation slow. 

^ Good deliberation, again, is diflferent from sagacity, 3 
which is a kind of happy guessing. 
Nor is it any kind of opinion. 
But since in deliberating iU we go wrong, and in 
deliberating weU we go right, it is plain that good 
deliberation is a kind of rightness, but a rightness 
or correctness neither of science nor opinion; for 
science does not admit of correctness (since it does 
not admit of error), and correctness of opinion is 
simply truth ; and, further, that concerning which we 
have an opinion is always something already settled. 

y Good deliberation, however, is impossible without 

calculation. 

>( We have no choice left, then, but to say that it 

is correctness of reasoning (Stavom) ; for reasoning is 
not yet assertion: and whereas opinion is not an 
inquiry, but already a definite assertion, when we 
are deliberating, whether well or ill, we are inquiring 
and calculating. 

But as good deliberation is a kind of correctness 4 
in deliberation, we must first inquire what delibera- 
tion means, and what its field is.* 

Now, there are various kinds of correctness, and it 

* This, however, is not done here, perhaps because it has been 
already done at length in III. 3« 



9, 3-7.] THE INTELLECTUAL ViBTUEa 197 

is plain that not every kind of correctness in delibera* 
tion is good deliberation; for the incontinent man 
or the vicious man may duly arrive, by a process of 
calculation^ at that which he started to find,* so that 
, he will have deliberated correctly, though what he 
^ gains is a great e vil ) But to have deliberated well is 
thought to be a good thing ; for it is only a particular 
kind of correctness in deliberation that is called 
good deliberation — ^that, namely, which arrives at 
what is good. 

5 But, further, what is good may be arrived at by a 
false syllogism ; I mean that a right conclusion as to 
what is to be done may be arrived at in a wrong way 
or upon wrong grounds — the middle teim being 
wrong ;t so that what leads to a right conclusion as 
to what should be done is not good deliberation, 
unless the grounds also be right. 

6 A further difference is that one may arrive at the 
right conclusion slowly, another rapidly. So we 
must qdd yet another condition to the above, and say 
that good deliberation means coming to a right con- 
clusion as to what is expedient or ought to be done, and 
coming to it in the right manner and at the right time. 

Again, we speak of deliberating weU simply, and 
of deliberating weU with a view to a particular 
kind of end. So good deliberation simply [or with- 
out any qualifying epithet] is that which leads to 
right conclusions as to the means to the end simply ; 

* The means to bis bad end. 

t e.g. this act should be done simply becanse it is just ; I may 
decide to do it for reputation, or for pleasure's sake, or thinking it 
to be an act of generosity* 



/ 



ence. 



198 KICOMACHEAN ETHICS OP ARISTOTLK [Bk. VL 

a particular kind of good deliberation is that which 
leads to right conclusions as to the means to a par- 
ticular kind of end. And so^ when we say that 
prudent men must deliberate well^ good deliberation 
in this case will be correctness in judging what is 
expedient to a particular end, of which prudence has 
a true conception. 
fintdiu 10. The faculty of intelligence (along with its l 

opposite, unintelligence), in respect of which we call 
men intelligent (and unintelligent), is not the same as 
science generally, nor as opinion (for then all men 
would be intelligent), nor is it identical with any par- 
ticular science, such as medicine, which deals with 
matters of health, and geometry, which deals with 
magnitudes ; for intelligence has not to do with what 
. is eternal and unchangeable, nor haa it to do with 

J events of every kindy4)ut only with those that one 
may doubt and deliberate about. And so it has to do 

. with the same matters as prudence ; but they are not 
identical ? prudence issues orders, for its scope is that 
which is to be done or not to be done; while in- 2 
telligence discerns merely (intelligence being equiva- 
lent to sound intelligence, and an intelligent man to 
a man of sound intelligence). 

Intelligence, in fact, 15 equivalent neither to the 3 
possession nor to the acquisition of prudence; but 
just as the learner in science is said to show in- 
telligence when he makes use of the scientific know- 
ledge which he hears from his teacher, so in the 

\ domain of prudence a man is said to show intelli- 
gence when he makes use of the opinions which he 
hears from others in judging, and judging fitly — 



} 



10, l-U, 2.] THE INTELLECTUAL VIRTUES. 199 

for BOTindly [when we speak of sound intelligence] 
means fitly. 

And from this nse of the term with regard to 
learning comes its employment to denote that faculty 
which we imply when we call a man intelligent ; for 
we often speak of the intelligence of a learner. 

U. Judgment (what we mean when we speak cfjvOdmen 
of a man of good judgment, or say a man has judg- ^u^S^ ^ 
ment) is a correct discernment of that which \&M^^^hMii 
equitable. A proof of this is that the equitable ^C^^cat 
man is thought to be especially ready to forgive, *" 
and that to forgive some things is considered equit- 
able. But forgiveness (avyyvwiiri) is judgment (yvw/iri) 
^hich correctiy discerns that which is equitable- 

/ correctly meaning truly. 

2 Now, all these four formed faculties which we 
have enumerated not unnaturally tend in the same 
direction. We apply all these terms — judgment, 
intelligence, prudence, and reason — to the same 
persons, and talk of people as having, at a certain 
age, already acquired judgment and reason, and as 
being prudent and intelligent. For all these four 
faculties deal with ultimate and particular* facts, 
and it is in virtue of a power of discrimination in 
the matters with which prudence deals that we call 
a person intelligent, or a man of sound judgment, 
or a forgiving man jj for equitable is a common 
term that is applicable to all that is good in our 
dealings with others. 

• All parfcionlar facts (rh Ka^ tKwrrov) are tiltimato (?<rxaTo), ♦.«. 
-nndemonstrable ; bnt not all ultimate facts (^o-xara) are particular 
|^K>fcs — as presently appears. 



i 



200 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk, VL 

^ But that which is to be done is always some 3 
particular thing, something ultimate. As we have 
seen, it is the business of the prudent man to know it, 
and intelligence and judgment also have to do with 
that which is to be done, which is something ultimate. 
And the intuitive reason [the last of the four 4 
y faculties above enumerated] also deals with ulti- 
mate tniths, in both senses of the word ; * for both 
primary principles and ultimate facts [in the nar- 
rower sense of the word ultimate = particular] are 
apprehended by the intuitive reason, and not by 
demonstration : on the one hand, in connection with 
/ deductions [of general truths in morals and politics],! 

Y reason apprehends the unalterable first principles;, 
on the other hand, in connection with practical cal- 
culations, reason apprehends the ultimate [particular] 
alterable fact which forms the minor premise [in 
the practical syllogism]. These particular judgments, 
we may say, are given by reason, as they are 
the source of our conception of the final cause or 
end of man ; the universal principle is elicited from 
the particular facts : these particular facts, there- 6 
fore, must be apprehended by a sense or intuitive 
perception ; and this is reason.J 

(And so it is thought that these faculties are 
natural, and that while nature never makes a man 

/ wise, she does endow men with judgment and intelli- 
gence and reason. This is shown by the fact that 6 

* Lit. in both directions, i.e. not the last only, bnt the first also. 

t 0/. sitjwa, 8, 1, 2. 

X This atcOria-is may be called vovs because the nniversal (the 
general conception of human good) is elicited from these partioa« 
lar judgments* 



V 



11, 8-6.] THE INTELLECTUAL VIRTUES. 201 

these powers are believed to accompany certain 
periods of life^ and that a certain age is said to 
bring reason and judgment^ implying that they come 
by nature.) 

^ The intuitive reason, then, is both beginning 
and end ; for demonstration both starts from and 
terminates in these ultimate truths [which reason 
supplies]. And on this account we ought to pay the 

l/^same respect to the undemonstrated assertions and 
opinions of men of age and experience and prudence 
as to their demonstrations. For experience has given 
them a faculty of vision which enables them to see 
correctly.* 

• Tlironghont this chapter we are concerned with the practical 
inteUect alone. He has already stated in cap. 6 that the intnitive 
reason is the basis of the speculative intellect ; here ho says that it 
is also the basis of the practical intellect. We have to distinguish 
here three different employments of the practical faculty : 

(1) (if we invert the order), undemonstrated assertion, viz. 
that .under the circumstances this is the right thing to do (§ 6) : 
here the judgment is altogether intuitive ; i.e. no grounds are given. 

(2) demonstration (improperly so called, more properly cal- 
culation) that this is the right thing to do ; e.g, this act is to be 
done because it is just : here the intuitive reason supplies the minor 
premise of the practical syllogism (this act is just), and also (in- 
directly) the major (whatever is just is good), i.e. it supplies the 
data — the several particular intuitions from which the general pro- 
position is elicited : iv rais irpaKriKois, sc. aTroBei^cffi (practical calcu- 
lations), § 4; <if. Twy ^iroSei^ewj', § G, and oi cvKKoyifffiol rS>v ttpaKTuv^ 
12, 10. 

(3) deduction or demonstration (also improperly so called) of 
general truths in morals and politics : Kara ras hroSei^^tSf § 4 : here 
also the data from which deduction starts can only be apprehended 
by intuitive perception or reason : cf. I. 4, 7, 7, 20. The difference 
between (2) and (3) is plainly shown supra 8, 2, where voXitik'^ 
in the wider sense (= vofioOenicfi) which deals with laws, is distin- 
guished from iroXirticfi in the narrower sense which has to do with 
decrees : ef. also 1,2, 7, and X. 9, 14. 



202 NICOMAOHEAK ETHIGS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. VL 

We have said, then, what prudence is, and what 7 
wisdom is, and what each deals with, and that each 
is the virtue of a different part of the souL 
fduiuei 12. But here an objection may be raised. "What l 
idpru- is the use of them ? " it may be asked. " Wisdom does 
rudenceii not cousidcr what tends to make man happy (for 

iated to , rrt/ \ 

evemcu. it does uot ask how anything is brought about). 
\ Prudence indeed does this, but why do we need it ? 
Pnidence is the faculty which deals with what is just 
and noble and good for man, i.e. with those things 
which it is the part of the good man to do ; but the 
knowledge of them no more makes us apter to do 
them, if (as has been said) the [moral] virtues are 
habits, than it does in the case of what is healthy and 
wholesome — ^healthy and wholesome, that is, not in 
the sense of conducing to, but in the sense of issuing 
from, a healthy habit ; for a knowledge of medicine 
and gymnastics does not make us more able to do 
these things. 

" But if it be meant that a man should be prudent, 2 
not in order that he may do these acts, but in order 
that he may become able to do them, then prudence 
wiU be no use to those who are good, nor even to 
those who are not. For it will not matter whether 
they have prudence themselves, or take the advice of 
others who have it. It will be enough to do in these 
matters as we do in regard to health ; for if we wish 
to be in health, we do not go and learn medicine, 
v/ " Again, it seems to be a strange thing that 3 
prudence, though inferior to wisdom, must yet govern 
it, since in every field the practical faculty bears 
sway and issues orders." 



U, 7-12, 7.] THB INTELLECTUAL YIBTUES. 203 

We must now discuss these points ; for hitherto 
we have been only stating objections. 

4 First of all, then, we say that both prudence and 
/ wisdom must be desirable in themselves, since each is 
the virtue of one of the parts of the soul, even if 
neither of them produces anything. 

B^ Next, they do produce something. 

Y On the one hand, wisdom produces happiness, not 
in the sense in which medicine produces health, but 
in the sense in which health produces health ; * that 
is to say, wisdom being a part of complete virtue, its 
possession and exercise make a man happy. 

6 On the other hand [in the sphere of action], man 
performs his function perfectly when he acts in accord- 
ance with both prudence and moral virtue ; for while 
the latter ensures the rightness of the end aimed at, 
the former ensures the rightness of the means thereto. 

The fourth t part of the soul, the vegetative part, 
or the faculty of nutrition, has no analogous excellence; 
for it has no power to act or not to act. 

7 But as to the objection that prudence makes us 
no more apt to do what is noble and just, let us take 
the matter a little deeper, beginning thus : — 

* «.e. in the sense in wUcli a healthy state of the body (f yfcm as 
a c{(s in Aristotle's language) prodaces healthy performance of the 
bodily functions {p^i^ia as an iv€py€ia), 

t The other three are sense, reason, desire [oUffOTiffis, vovs, ^pe^is) : 
<^. suprOf cap. 2. The excellences or best states of the desires have 
already been described as the moral virtues. Wisdom and prudenco 
are the excellences of the reason or intellect (^i/ovs in its widest 
meaning). Sense {cHaOriffis^ does not need separate treatment, as it 
is hero regarded as merely subsidiary to reason and desire; for 
human life is (1) speculative, (2) practical, and no independent place 
Shallowed to the artistic life. The fourth part therefore alone remains. 



/ 



204 NICOMACHEAK ETHICS OF ABISTOTLB. [Bk. Vl. 

We allow, on the one hand, that some who do just 
acts are not yet just ; e.g. those who do what the laws 
enjoin either unwillingly or unwittingly, or for some 
external motive and not for the sake of the acts them- 
selves (though they do that which they ought and aU 
that a good man should do). And, on the other hand, 
it seems that when a man does the several acts with 
a certain disposition he is good; i.e. when he does 
them of deliberate purpose, and for the sake of the 
acts themselves. 

Now, the rightness of the purpose is secured by 8 
[moral] virtue, but to decide what is proper to be 
done in order to carry out the purpose belongs not to 
[moral] virtue, but to another faculty. But we must 
dwell a little on this point and try to make it quite 
clear. 

There is a faculty which we call cleverness 9 
(Sctvorijc) — the power of hitting upon and carrying 
out the means which tend to any proposed end. If 
then the end be noble, the power merits praise ; but 
if the end be base, the power is the power of the 
villain. So we apply the term clever both to the 
prudent man and the villain.* 

Now, this power is not identical with prudence, 10 
but is its necessary condition. But this power, the 
" eye of the soul " as we may call it, does not attain 
its perfect development t without moral virtue, as we 
said before, and as may be shown thus : — 

All syllogisms or deductive reasonings about what 
is to be done have for their starting point [principle 
or major premise] "the end or the supreme good 

* Beading rohs vcwoipyovs, ^ ^ As <l>p6v7iaiSf pmdenoe^ 



1% a-lS, 2.] THE INTELLECTUAL VIBTUEa 205 

is so and so " (whatever it be ; any definition of the 
good will do for the argument). But it is only to the 
good man that this presents itself as the good ; for 
vice perverts us and causes us to err about the prin- 
ciples of action. So it is plain, as we said, that it 
is impossible to be prudent without being morally 
good* 
L 13. This suggests a further consideration of moral nbwpru^ 
virtue : for the case is closely analogous to this — I raated to 

. , moral virtttt 

' mean that just as prudence is related to cleverness, 
being not identical with it, but closely akin to it, so 
is fully developed moral virtue related to natural 
virtue. 

All admit that in a certain sense the several kinds 
of character are bestowed by nature. Justice, a 
tendency to temperance, courage, and the other types 
of character are exhibited from the moment of birth. 
Nevertheless, we look for developed goodness as some- 
thing different from this, and expect to find these 
same qualities in another form. For even in children 
and brutes these natural virtues are present, but 
without the guidance of reason they are plainly 
hurtful* So much at least seems to be plain — that 
just as a strong-bodied creature devoid of sight 
stumbles heavily when it tries to move, because it 
cannot see, so is it with this natural virtue; but 
when it is enlightened by reason it acts surpassingly 

2 well; and the natural virtue (which before was only 
like virtue) will then be fully developed virtue. 

• We find, then, that just as there are two forms of 
the calculative faculty, viz. cleverness and prudence, so 
there are two forms of the moral qualities, viz. natural 



206 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLB. [Bk. YI. 

virtue and fully developed virtue, and that the latter 
is impossible without prudence. 

On this account some people say that all the 3 
virtues are forms of prudence, and in particular 
Socrates held this view, being partly right in his 
inquiry and partly wrong— wrong in thinking that 
all the virtues are actually forms of prudence, but 
right in saying that they are impossible without 
prudence. 

This is corroborated by the fact that nowadays 4 
every one in defining virtue would, after specifying 
its field, add that it is a formed faculty or habit in 
accordance with right reason, "right" meaning "in 
accordance with prudence." 

Thus it seems that every one has a sort of inkling 
that a formed habit or character of this kind {i.e. in 
accordance with prudence) is virtue. 

Only a slight change is needed in this expression. 6 
Virtue is not simply a formed habit in dccordance 
with right reason, but a formed habit implying right 
reason.* But right reason in these matters is prudence. 

So whereas Socrates held that the [moral] virtues 
are forms of reason (for he held that these are all 
modes of knowledge), we hold that they imply reason. 

It is evident, then, from what has been said that it 6 
is impossible to be good in the full sense without 
prudence, or to be prudent without moral virtue. 
And in this way we can meet an objection which 
may be urged. " The virtues," it may be said, " are 
found apart from each other ; a man who is strongly 

♦ fi€rh \6yov : the agent must not only be guided by reason, bat 
by bis own reason, not another's. 



13, 8-ej THE INTELLEOTUAL VIBTUEa 207 

predisposed to one virtue has not an equal tendency 
towards all the others, so that he will have acquired 
this virtue while he still lacks that." We may answer 
that though this may be the case with the natural 
virtues, yet it cannot be the case with those virtues 
for which we call a man good without any qualify- 
ing epithet. The presence of the single virtue of 
prudence implies the presence of all the moral virtues. 

And thus it is plain, in the first place, that, even 
if it did not help practice, we should yet need pru- 
dence as the virtue or excellence of a part of our 
nature ; and, in the second place, that purpose cannot 
be right without both prudence and moral virtue; for 
the latter makes us desire the end, while the former 
makes us adopt the right means to the end. 

Nevertheless, prudence is not the mistress of wis- 
dom and of the better part of our nature [the reason], 
any more than medicine is the mistress of health. 
Prudence does not employ wisdom in her service, but 
provides means for the attainment of wisdom — does 
not rule it, but rules in its interests. To assert the 
contrary would be like asserting that statesmanship 
rules the gods, because it issues orders about all public 
concerns [including the worship of the gods.] 



BOOK VIL 

CHAPTERS 1-10. CHARACTERS OTHER THAN VIRTUE 

AND VICE. 

ofeonti- 1. At this point we will make a fresh start and 1 

incwunencJsB.y that the Undesirable forms of moral character are 

heroic virtui ,-, . , ... ,. -i i tx 

and H three in number, viz. vice, incontinence, brutality. 
ojmet?u)d. lu the casc of two of these it is plain what the 

statement qf •• • • i • .i • j ji •! 

opivioM opposite IS : virtue is the name we give to the opposite 
cotuingnce, of vicc, and Continence to the opposite of incon- 
tinence ; but for the opposite of the brutal character 
it would be most appropriate to take that excellence 
which is beyond us, the excellence of a hero or a 
god, — as Homer makes Priam say of Hector that he 
was surpassingly good — 

" Nor seemed the child 
Of any mortal man, but of a god." 

If, then, superlative excellence raises men into gods, 2 
as the stories tell us, it is evident that the opposite 
of the brutal character would be some such super- 
lative excellence. For just as neither virtue nor vice 
belongs to a brute, so does neither belong to a god; 
to the latter belongs something higher than virtue, 
to the former something specifically diiferent from 
vice. 



1, 1-6.] INCONTINENCE. 209 

8 But as it is rare to find a godlike man (an epithet 
which the Spartans are wont to give to a man whom 
they admire exceedingly, calling him aeXog* avfip), 
so also is the brutal character rare among men. It 
occurs most frequently among the barbarians; it is 
also produced sometimes by disease and organic in- 
juries ; and, thirdly, we apply the name as a term of 
reproach to those who carry vice to a great pitch.t 

4 However, we shall have to make some mention 
of this disposition further on, J and we have already 
discussed vice ; so we will now speak of incontinence 

N/and softness and luxuriousness, and also of con- 
tinence and hardiness — for we must regard these as 
the names of states or types of character that are 
neither identical with virtue and vice respectively 
nor yet generically different. 

6 And here we must follow our usual method, and, 
after stating the current opinions about these aflfec- 
tions, proceed first to raise objections, and then to 
establish, if possible, the truth of all the current 
opinions on the subject, or, if not of all, at least of the 
greater number and the most important. For if the 
difficulties can be resolved and the popular notions 
thus confirmed, we shall have attained as much 
certainty as the subject allows. 

6 It is commonly thought (1) that continence and 

V hardiness are good and laudable, while incontinence 
and softness are bad and blamable; and, again (2), 

• orcTos is a dialectical variety for Buosy godlike. 
+ (1) Some men are born brutal j (2) others are made soj (3) 
others make themselves so, 
J InfrOf cap. 6. 

P 



t*" 



210 NIGOMAGHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk. YIL 

that a continent man is identioal with one who abides 
by his calculations, and an incontinent man with 
one who swerves from them; and (3) that the in- 
continent man, knowing that an act is bad, is impelled 
to do it by passion, while the continent man, knowing 
that his desires are bad, is withheld from following 
them by reason. Also (4) it is commonly thought 
that the temperate man is continent and hardy : but 
while some hold that conversely the latter is always 
temperate, others think that this is not always so ; 
and while some people hold that the profligate is 
incontinent, and that the incontinent man is pro- 
fligate, and use these terms indiscriminately, others 
make a distinction between them. Again (5), with 7 
regard to the prudent man, sometimes people say it 
is impossible for him to be incontinent; at other times 
they say that some men who are prudent and clever 
are incontinent. Lastly (6), people are called in- 
continent even in respect of anger and honour and 
gain. 
statenuntof 2. Theso, then, are the common sayings or current l 

iiffimltiescu • • 

to how me OpmiOnS. 

ri^htanddo But in what sense, it ma^r be objected, can a man 
'*''^^' judge rightly when he acts incontinently ? 

Some people maintain that he cannot act so if 
he really knows what is right; for it would be 
strange, thought Socrates, if, when real knowledge 
were in the man, something else should master him 
and hale him about like a slave. Socrates, indeed, 
contested the whole position, maintaining that there 
is no such thing as incontinence: when a man 
acts contrary to what is best, he never, according to 



1, 7-2, 5.] INCONTINENCE. 211 

Socrates, lias a right judgment of the case, but acts 
so by reason of ignorance. 

2 Now, this theory evidently conflicts with ex- 
perience; and with regard to the passion which 
sways the incontinent man, if it really is due to 
ignorance, we must ask what kind of ignorance it 
is due to. For it is plain that, at any rate, he who 
acts incontinently does not fancy that the act is good 
tiU the passion is upon him. 

3 There are other people who in part agree and 
in part disagree with Socrates. They allow that 
nothing is able to prevail against knowledge, but 
do not allow that men never act contrary to what 
seems best; and so they say that the incontinent 
man, when he yields to pleasure, has not knowledge, 
but only opinion. 

4 But if, in truth, it be only opinion and not 
knowledge, and if it be not a strong but a weak 
belief or judgment that opposes the desires (as is the 
case when a man is in doubt), we pardon a man for 
not abiding by it in the face of strong desires ; but, in 
fact, we do not pardon vice nor anything else that we 
call blamable. 

5 Are we, then, to Sy that it is prudence that op- 
poses desire [in those cases when we blame a man for 
yielding] ? For it is the strongest form of belief. 
Surely that would be absurd : for then the same man 
would be at once prudent and incontinent ; but no 
one would maintain that a prudent man could volun- 
tarily do the vilest acts. Moreover, we have already 
shown that prudence is essentially a faculty that 
issues in act ; for it is concerned with the ultimate 



212 NIOOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLB. [Bk. VII. 

thing [the thing to be done], and implies the pos- 
session of all the moral virtues. 
/ Again, if a man cannot be continent without 6 

having strong and bad desires, the temperate man 
will not be continent, nor the continent man 
temperate ; for it is incompatible with the temperate 
character to have either very violent or bad desires. 

They must, however, be both strong and bad in 
the continent man : for if they were good, the habit 
that hindered from following them would be bad, so 
that continence would not be always good ; if they 
were weak and not bad, it would be nothing to re- 
spect ; and if they were bad, but at the same time 
weak, it would be nothing to admire. 

Again, if continence makes a man apt to abide by 7 
any opinion whatsoever, it is a bad thing — as, for 
instance, if it makes him abide by a false opinion : 
and if incontinence makes a man apt to abandon any 
opinion whatsoever, there will be a kind of incon- 
tinence that is good, an instance of which is Neopto- 
lemus in the Philoctetes of Sophocles ; for he merits 
praise for being prevented from persevering in the 
plan which Ulysses had persuaded him to adopt, by 
the pain which he felt at telling a lie. 

Again, the well-known argument of the sophists, 8 
though fallacious, makes a diflSculty : for, wishing to 
establish a paradoxical conclusion, so that they may 
be thought clever if they succeed, they construct a 
syllogism which puzzles the hearer ; for his reason is 
fettered, as he is unwilling to rest in the conclusion, 
which is revolting to him, but is unable to advance, 
since he cannot find a hole in the argument. Thus it 



2, 6-12.1 INCONTINENOB. 213 

9 may be argued* that folly combined with incon- 
tinence is virtue: — by reason of his incontinence a 
man does the opposite of that which he judges to be 
good ; but he judges that the good is bad and not to 
be done ; the result is that he will do the good and 
not the bad. 

.0 Again, he who pursues and does what is pleasant 
from conviction, and deliberately chooses these things, 
would seem [if this doctrine be true] to be better than 
he who does so, not upon calculation, but by reason of 
incontinence. For the former is more curable, as his 
convictions might be changed ; but to the incontinent 
man we may apply the proverb which says, " If water 

Ll chokes you, what will you wash it down with ? " For 
if he were not convinced that what he does is bad, a 
change in his convictions might stop his doing it; 
but, as it is, though he is convinced that a certain 
thing is good, he nevertheless does something else. 

Again, if incontinence and continence may be 
displayed in anything, who is the man whom wo 
call incontinent simply? For though no one man 
unites all the various forms of incontinence, there 
yet are people to whom we apply the term without 
any qualification. 

2 Something of this sort, then, are the objections 
that suggest themselves; and of these we must re- 
move some and leave others ; f for the resolution of 
a difficulty is the discovery of the truth. 

• This is the sophistical paradox alluded to. 

t Of these objections, as well as of the opinions which called 
them forth, it is to be expected that some should prove ground- 
less, and that others should be established and taken up into the 
Answer. 



214 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [BK.VIL 

Hution: to V 8. We have, then, to inquire (1) whether the in^ 1 
Mnytentes: Continent man acts with knowledge or not, and what 
mieiueha knowledge means here; then (2) what is to. be re- 
garded as the field in which continence and incon- 
tinence manifest themselves — I mean whether their 
field be all pleasures and pains, or certain definite 
classes of these ; then (3), with regard to the continent 
and the hardy man, whether they are the same or 
different ; and so on with the other points that are 
akin to this inquiry. 

(But we ought to begin by inquiring whether the 2 
species of continence and the species of incontinence 
of which we are here speaking are to be distinguished 
from other species by the field of their manifestation 
or by their form or manner — I mean whither a man 
is to be called incontinent in this special sense merely 
because he is incontinent or uncontrolled by reason 
in certain things, or because he is incontinent in 
a certain manner, or rather on both grounds; and 
in connection with this we ought to determine 
whether or no this incontinence and this continence 
may be displayed in all things. And our answer 
to these questions will be that the man who is 
called simply incontinent, without any qualification, 
does not display his character in all things, but only 
in those things in which the profligate manifests 
himself; nor is it simply an uncontrolled disposition 
with regard to them that makes him what he is 
(for then incontinence would be the same as pro- 
fligacy), but a particular kind of uncontrolled dis- 
position. For the profligate is carried along of hia 
own deliberate choice or purpose, holding that what 



3, 1-4.] INOONTINENCB. 216 

is pleasant at the moment is always to be pursued ; 
while the incontinent man thinks otherwise, but 
pursues it all the same.)* [Let us now turn to 
question (1).] 

3 As to the argument that it is true opinion 
and not knowledge against which men act in- 
continently, it really makes no difference here; for 
some of those who merely have opinions are in no 
doubt at all, but fancy that they have exact know- 
ledga 

4 If then it be said that those who have opinion 
more readily act against their judgment because 
of the weakness of their belief, we would answer 
that there is no such difference between knowledge 
and opinion; for some people have just as strong 
a belief in their mere opinions as others have in 

* This Bectiom (§ 2) seems to me not an alternative to § 1 ; but a 
(oorreotion of it, or rather a remark to the effect that the whole 
passage (both § 1 and the discnssion introduced by it) onght to 
. be rewritten, and an indication of the way in which this should be 
done. Of considerable portions of the Nicomachean Ethics we may 
safely say that the author coald not have regarded them as finished 
in the form in which we have them. It is possible that the author 
liiade a rough draft of the whole work, or of the several parts of it, 
which he kept by him and worked upon, — working some parts up to 
completion; sometimes rewriting a passage without striking out the 
miginal yersion, or even indicating which was to be retained (0.^. 
the theory of pleasure) ; more frequently adding an after-thought 
which required the rewriting of a whole passage, without rewriting 
it {e,g,, to take one instance out of many in Book V., rh &vriv€vop$6s 
18 an after-thought which strictly requires that the whole book 
should be rewritten) ; sometimes (as here) making a note of the way 
in which a passage should be rewritten. Suppose, if need be, that 
the work, left in this incomplete state, was edited and perhaps 
farther worked upon by a later hand, and we have enough, I think, to 
aooount for the facts. 



216 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. tBK.Vn. 

what they teally know, of which Heraclitus is an 
instance.* 

But we use the word know {iTrlfrraaOai) in two 5 
different senses : he who has knowledge which he is 
not now using is said to know a thing, and also he 
who is now using his knowledge. Having knowledge, 
therefore, which is not now present to the mind, 
about what one ought not to do, will be different 
from having knowledge which is now present. Only 
in the latter sense, not in the former, does it seem 
strange that a man should act against his knowledge. 

Again, since these reasonings involve two kinds 6 
of premises [a universal proposition for major and 
a particular for minor], there is nothing to prevent a 
man from acting contrary to his knowledge though 
he has both premises, if he is now using the universal 
only, and not the particular ; for the particular is the 
thing to be done. 

Again, different kinds of universal propositions 
may be involved : one may concern the agent him- 
self, another the thing ; for instance, you may reason 
(1) "all men are benefited by dry things, and this 
is a man ; " and (2) " things of this kind are dry ; " 
but the second minor, "this thing is of this kind," 
may be unknown or the knowledge of it may be 
dormant.f 

These distinctions, then, will make a vast difference, 

• Alluding to the Heraclitean doctrine of the union of opposites, 
which Aristotle rather unfairly interprets as a denial of the law of 
contradiction. 0/. Met. iii. 7, 1012* 24. 

t i-e, not now present, ovk iyepyu : but in § 10 cVcpyc? seems to 
mean " is e^ectively present." 



3, 5-8] . INCONTINENCE. 217 

SO much so that it does not seem strange that a man 
should act against his knowledge if he knows in one 
way, though it does seem strange if he knows in 
another way. 

7 But, again, it is possible for a man to " have know- 
ledge " in yet another way than those just mentioned : 
we see, I mean, that "having knowledge without 
using it *' includes different modes of having, so that 
a man may have it in one sense and in another 
sense not have it ; for instance, a man who is asleep, 
or mad, or drunk. But people who are under the 
influence of passion are in a similar state ; for anger, 
and sexual desire and the Kke do evidently alter 
the condition of the body, and in some cases actually 
produce madness. It is plain, then, that the in- 
continent man must be allowed to have knowledge 
in the same sort of way as those who are asleep, 
mad, or drunk.* 

8 But to repeat the words of knowledge is no proof 
that a man reaUy has knowledge [in the full sense of 
having an effective knowledge] ; for even when they 
are under the influence of these passions people 
repeat demonstrations and sayings of Empedocles, 

• Action, in spite of knowledge presents no difficnlty (1) if that 
knowledge be not present at the time of action, § 5, or (2) if, though 
the major (or majors) be known and present, the minor (or one of 
the minors) be nnknown or absent, § 6. But (3) other cases remain 
which can only be explained by a farther distinction introduced in 
§ 7 ; i»e. a man who has knowledge may at times be in a state in 
which his knowledge, though present, has lost its reality — in which, 
though he may repeat the old maxims, they mean no more to him 
than to one who talks in his sleep. § 7, I venture to think, is (like . 
§ 2) not a repetition or an alternative version, but an after-thought, 
which requires the rewriting of the whole passage. 



218 NICOMAOHEAN ETHICS OP AEISTOTLE. [Bk.VIL 

just as learners string words together before they 
understand their meaning — ^the meaning must be 
ingrained in them, and that requires time. So we 
must hold that the incontinent repeat words in the 
same sort of way that actors do. 

Again, one may inquire into the cause of this 9 
phenomenon [of incontinence] by argimients based 
upon its special nature,* as follows : — You may have 

(1) a universal judgment, (2) a judgment about par- 
ticular facts which faU at once within the province 
of sense or perception ; but when the two are joined 
together,! the conclusion must in matters cf specu- 
lation be assented to by the mind, in matters of 
practice be carried out at once into act ; for instance, 
if you judge (1) "aU sweet things are to be tasted,*' 

(2) " this thing before me is sweet " — a particular fact, 
— ^then, if you have the power and are not hindered, 
you cannot but at once put the conclusion ["this is 
to be tasted "] into practice. 

Now, when you have on the one side the lO 
universal judgment forbidding you to taste, and on 
the other side the universal, ''all sweet things are 
pleasant,"! and the particular judgment, " this thing 
before me is sweet," and this latter judgment is 
effectively present, or, in other words, appetite for 
the sweet is there — then, though iha former train of 
reasoning bids you avoid this, appetite moves you [to 

• ^vtriKcoSf by arguments based npon the special nature of the 
subject-matter, opposed to hoyiKcoSf by arguments of a general nature ; 
accordingly, in what follows both the elements of reason and desire 
are taken into account. 

t In a practical syllogism. 

X Notice that 7jd\> here corresponds to yfifaOai Set above. 



INCONTINENCE. 219 

take it] ; for appetite ia able to put the several bodily 
organa in motion. 

And thus it appears that it is in a way under the 
influence of reason, that ia to say of opinion, that 
people act incontinently — opinion, too, that ia, not in 
itself, but only accidentally, opposed to right reason, 

11 For it ia the desire, not the opinion, that is opposed 
to right reason.* 

And this ia the reason why brutes cannot 1 
incontinent; they have no universal judgments, but 
only images and memories of particular facts. 

12 As to the process by which the incontinenT" 
gets out of this ignorance and recovers his knowledge, 
the account of it will be the same as in the case of a 
man who ia drunk or asleep, and will not be peculiar 
to this phenomenon ; and for such an account we must 
go to the professors of natural science. 

1 3 But since the minor premise t is an opinion or 
judgment about a fact of perception, and determines 
action, the incontinent man, when under the influence 
of passion, either has it not, or has it in a sense 
in which, as we explained, ha\Tng ia equivalent, 

• ThBminorpreniiBe,"thiBiaBweet,"obrioi:iBljifl not "opposed to 
right reason ;" bat iB not tho major prcmiBe? In ona of the two 
forniB in wliich it here appeoTB, viz, " aU sweet thingfl are pleaeant," 
it certainl]' is not bd opposed ; it morelf stateB a fact of experience 
which the continent or temperate man oasentB to bb ninch aa the 
incontinent. In its othor form, however, "all Bweet things ace to be 
toBled," the judgment ia "opposed to right reasan;" bat it is bo 
because desire for an object oondenmed by reason has bean added j 
and thna it may be said tliat it is not the opinion, but tho desire, 
which is opposed to right reason. It ia a defect in the e:?poBition 
hero that the difference between these two forms of the major pre- 
miae is not more CKpresely noticed. 

■t Of the BjUogism which would forbLd him 





220 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. DBk.VIC 

not to knomng in the full sense, but to repeating 
words as a drunken man repeats the sayings of Em- 
pedoeles. 

And thus, since the minor premise is not universal, 
and is thought to be less a matter of knowledge than 
the universal judgment [or major premise], it seems 
that what Socrates sought to establish really is the u 
case ; * for when passion carries a man away, what is 
present to his mind is not what is regarded as know- 
ledge in the strict sense, nor is it such knowledge 
that is perverted by his passion, but sensitive know- 
yledge merely, f 
fincon- 4. So much, then, for the question whether the l 



nence in 



le strict incontinent man knows or not, and in what sense it 

net in the 

etaphoricai is possiblc to act incontinently with knowledge. We 
next have to consider whether a man can be 
incontinent simply, or only incontinent in some 
particular way, J and, if the former be the case, what 
is the field in which the character is manifested. 

It is evident that it is in the matter of pleasures ji 
and pains that both continent and hardy and/ 
incontinent and soft men manifest their characters. / 

Of the sources of pleasure, some are necessary, an^ 
others are desirable in themselves but admit of 
excess : " necessary " are the bodily processes, such 

* Heading fnll stop after *EfivedoK\€ov5 and comma after Zpop. 

t Or the perception of the particnlar fact. After all Socrates is 
right: the incontinent man does not really know; the fact does 
not come home to him in its trne significance : he says it is bad, 
but says it as an actor might, withoat feeling it ; what he realizes is 
that it is pleasant. 

J As a man may be greedy (avXQs), or greedy for a particnlar 
kind of food. 



3, 14-4, 3.] INCONTINENCB. 221 

as nutrition, the propagation of the species, and 
other bodily processes, with which we said that 
profligacy and temperance have to do ; others, though 
not necessary, are in themselves desirable, such as 
victory, honour, wealth, and other things of the kind 
that are good and pleasant* 

Now, those who go to excess in these latter in 
spite of their own better reason are not called in- 
continent simply, but with a qualifying epithet, as 
incontinent with respect to money, or gain, or honour, 
or anger — not simply, since they are different 
characters, and only called incontinent in virtue of a 
resemblance — just as the victor in the last Olympic 
games was called a man; for though the meaning 
of the name as applied to him was but slightly 
different from its common meaning, still it was 
different.! A 

And this may be proved thus: incontinence is 
blamed, not simply as a mistake, but as a kind of 
vice, either of vice simply, or of some particular vice ; 
but those who are- thus incontinent [in the pursuit of 
wealth, etc.] are not thus blamed. 
8 But of the characters that manifest themselves in 
the matter of bodily enjoyments, with which we say 
the temperate and the profligate are concerned, he 

• CaTlQd also airXQs hryaBdf "good in themselves,*' as in V. 1, 9 
(c/. V. 2y 6), and inrhs iyadd, " external goods," as in I. 8, 2. 

f Ab we do not know the facts to which Aristotle alludes we can 
only oonjectnre his meaning. It may be that the man in question 
had oertain physical pecaliarities, so that though he *' passed for a 
man " he was not quite a man in the common meaning of the name. 
So Locke asks (Essay iv, 10, 13), *' Is a changeling a man or a 
beast?" 




i 



y 



222 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk VIT. 

who goes to excess in pursuing what is pleasant and 
avoiding what is painful, in the matter of hunger 
and thirst, and heat and cold, and all things that 
affect us by touch or taste, and who does this not 
of deliberate choice, but contrary to his deliberate 
choice and reasoning, is called incontinent — ^not 
with the addition that he is incontinent with re- 
spect to this particular thing, as anger, but simply/ 

incontinent. ^ 

- A proof of this is that people are also called soft 4 

in these latter matters, but not in any of the former 
Pionour, gain, etc.]. 

And on this account we group the incontinent 
• with the profligate and the continent and the 
temperate (but do not dass with them any of those 
who are metaphorically called continent and incon- 
tinent), because they are in a way concerned with the 
same pleasures and 'pains. They are, in fact, con- 
cerned with the same matters, but their behaviour is 
different; for whereas the other three deliberately 
. choose what they do, the incontinent man does not 
And so a man who, without desire, or with only 
a moderate desire, pursues excess of pleasure, and 
avoids even slight pains, would more properly be 
called profligate than one who is impelled so to act 
by violent desires ; for what would the former do if 
the violent passions of youth were added, and if it 
were violent pain to him to forego the satisfaction of 
his natural appetites ? 

But some of our desires and pleasures are to be 5 
classed as noble and good; for of the things that 
please us, some are naturally desirable (others being 



4, 4-6.1 INCONTINENOB. 223 

the reverse of this, and others, again, between the 
two, as we explained before*), such as money and 
gain and victory and honour. With regard both to 
these, then, and to the intermediate class [of things 
indifferent], men are blamed not for being affected 
by them, or desiring them, or caring for them, but 
only for exceeding the bounds of moderation in 
certain waya 

So we blame those who are moved by, or pursue, 
some good and noble object to an unreasonable extent, 
as, for instance, those who care too much for honour, 
or for their children or parents : for these, too, are 
noble objects, and men are praised for caring about 
them ; but still one might go too far in them also, if 
one were to fight even against the gods, like Niobe, or 
to do as did Satyrus, who was nicknamed Philopator 
from his affection for his father — for he seemed to 
carry his affection to the pitch of folly. 

In these matters, then, there is no room for vice 
or wickedness for the reason mentioned, viz. that all 
these are objects that are in themselves desirable ; but 
excess in them is not commendable, and is to be 
avoided 
6 Similarly, in these matters there is no room for in- 
continence [strictly so called] ; for incontinence is not 
only to be avoided, but is actually blamable. But 
because of the similarity of the state of mind we do 
here use the term incontinence with a qualification, 
saying *' incontinent in this or in that," just as we 
apply the term " bad physician " or " bad actor " to a 

• Supra, § 2; though there only two divisions are speoifiedg 
Tiz. (1) necessary, (2) desirable bat admitting of exoess* 



224 KIOOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bs. VIL 

man whom we should not call bad simply or ■withoat 
a qualifying epithet. Just as in the latter ease, then, 
the term hadneas or vice is applied, not simply, but 
with a qualification, because each of these qualities is 
not a vice strictly, but only analogous to a vice, so in 
this case also it is plain that we must understand 
that only to be strictly incontinence (or continence) 
which is manifested in those matters with which 
temp3rance and profligacy are concerned, while that 
which is manifested with regard to anger ia only 
metaphorically called so ; and therefore we call a 
man "incontinent in anger," as "in honour" or 
gain," adding a qualiiying epithet. 

S. While some things are naturally pleasant (of 
which some are pleasant in themselves, others pleasaat 
to certain classes of animals or men), other things, 
though not naturally pleasant, come to be pleasant 
(1) through organic injuries, or (2) through custom, 
or again (3) through an originally bad natui-e . and 
in each of these three classes of things a coiTespond- 
ing character is manifested. 

For instance [taking (3) first], there are the brutal 
characters, such as the creature in woman's shape 
that is said to rip up pregnant females and devour 
the embryos, or the people who take delight, as si 
of the wild races about the Black Sea are said to 
take delight, in such things as eating raw meat or 
human flesh, or giving thoir children to one another 
to feast upon ; or, again, in such things as are reported. 
of Phalaris, 

These, then, are what we call brutal natures 
[corresponding to (3) ] : but in other cases the dia- 



ff, 1-6.] INCONTINENCE. 225 

position is engendered by disease or madness ; for 
instance, there was the man who slew and ate his 
mother, and that other who devoured the liver of 
his fellow-slave [and these correspond to (1)]. 

Other habits are either signs of a morbid state, 
or the result of custom [and so come either under 
(1) or under (2)]; e.g, plucking out the hair and biting 
the nails, or eating cinders and earth, or, again, the 
practice of unnatural vice ; for these habits sometimes 
come naturally,* sometimes by custom, as in the case 
of those who have been ill treated from their childhood. 

Whenever nature is the cause of these morbid 
habits, no one would think of applying the term 
incontinence, any more than we should call women 
incontinent for the part they play in the propagation 
of the species ; nor should we apply the term to those 
who, by habitual indulgence, have brought themselves 
into a morbid statcf 

Habits of this kind, then, fall without the pale 
of vice, just as the brutal character does ; but when 
a man who has these impulses conquers or is con- 
quered by them, this is not to be called [continence 
or] incontinence strictly, but only metaphorically, 
just as the man who behaves thus in the matter 
of his angry passions cannot be strictly called in- 

* i.e. here " by disease : " i^^xris bears three different senses in 
tlie space of a few lines — (1) in § l, beginning, natural = in aocord- 
ance with the true nature of the thing, the thing as it ought to be ; 
(2) in § 1, end, natural = what a man is bom with, as opposed to 
sobseqnent modifications of this ; (3) in § 3 natural includes what 
my body does by powers in it over which I have no control, e.g, 
modifications of my nature produced by disease. 

t Because incontinence is a human weakness; these acts are 
brutal or morbid. 

Q 



/ 



226 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OP ARISTOTLE. [Bk. Vlf 

continent. For even folly, and cowardice and pro- 
fligacy, and ill temper, whenever they are carried 
beyond a certain pitch, are either brutal or morbid. 
When a man is naturally so constituted as to be 6 
frightened at anything, even at the sound of a mouse, 
his cowardice is brutal [inhuman] ; but in the well- 
known case of a man who was afraid of a weasel, 
disease was the cause. And of irrational human 
beings, those who by nature are devoid of reason, 
and live only by their senses, are to be called brutal, 
as some races of remote barbarians, while those in 
whom the cause is disease {e.g. epilepsy) or insanity 
are to be called morbidly irrational. 

Again, a man may on occasion have one of these 7 
impulses without being dominated by it, as, for 
instance, if Phalaris on some occasion desired to eat 
the flesh of a child, or to indulge his unnatural lusts, 
and yet restrained himself; and, again, it is possible 
not only to have the impulse, but to be dominated 
by it. 

To conclude, then : as in the case of vice there is s 
a human vice that is called vice simply, and another 
sort that is called with a qualifying epithet " brutal "" 
or " morbid vice " (not simply vice), so also it is plain 
that there is a sort of incontinence that is called 
brutal, and another that is called morbid incontinence, 
while that only is caUed incontinence simply which 
can be classed with human profligacy. 

We have thus showii that incontinence and con- s 
tinence proper have to do only with those things 
with which profligacy and temperance have to do, 
and that in other matters there is a sort of incon- 




5, 6-6, 2.] INCONTIKEKCB. 227 

tinence to which the name is applied metaphorically 
and with a qualifying epithet. 

L 6. The next point we have to consider is that Jneonth 
incontinence in anger is less disgraceful than incon- biamia 
tinence in appetite. 

The angry passions seem to hear something of 
what reason says, but to mis-hear it, like a hasty 
servant who starts off before he has heard all you 
are saying, and so mistakes his errand, or like a dog 
that barks so soon as he hears a noise, without wait* 
ing to find out if it be a friend. Just so our angry 
passions, in the heat and haste of their nature, hear- 
ing something but not hearing what reason orders, 
make speed to take vengeance. For when reason or 
imagination announces an insult or slight, the angry 
passion infers, so to speak, that its author is to be 
treated as an enemy, and then straightway boils up ; 
appetite, on the other hand, if reason or sense do but 
proclaim " this is pleasant," rushes to enjoy it. Thus 
anger, in some sort, obeys reason, which appetite does 
not. The latter, therefore, is the more disgraceful; 
for he who is incontinent in anger succumbs in some 
sort to reason, while the other succumbs not to reason, 
but to appetite. 

2 Again, when impulses are natural, it is more 
excusable to follow them (for even with our appetites 
it is more pardonable to follow them when they are 
common to all men, and the more pardonable the 
commoner they are) ; but anger and ill temper are 
more natural than desire for excessive and unneces- 
sary pleasures, as we see in the story of the man who 
excused himself for beating his father. " He beat his 

i 



228 NICOMAOHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. VII. 

own father/' he said, '' and that father beat his, and 
my son here," pointing to his child, "will beat me 
when he is a man ; for it runs in the famUy." And 
there is that other story of the man who was being 
dragged out of the house by his son, and bade him 
stop at the doorway; for he had dragged his own 
' father so far, but no further. / 

Again, the more a man is inclined to deliberate 3 
malice, the more unjust he is. Now, the hot-tem- 
pered man is not given to deliberate malice, nor is 
anger of that xmderhand nature, but asserts itself 
openly. But of appetite we may say what the 
poets say of Aphrodite : " Craft- weaving daughter of 
Cyprus ; " or what Homer says of her " embroidered 
girdle," 

" Whose charm doth steal the reason of the wise." • 

If then this incontinence be more unjust, it is more 
disgraceful than incontinence in anger, and is to be 
called incontinence simply, and a sort of vice. 

Again, when a man commits an outrage, he does 4 
not feel pain in doing it, but rather pleasure, while 
he who acts in anger always feels pain as he is 
acting. K then the acts which rouse the justest in- 
dignation are the more unjust, it follows that incon- 
tinence in appetite is more unjust [than incontinence 
in anger] ; for such outrage is never committed in 
anger.f 

Thus it is plain that incontinence in appetite is 5 

• XL, xiv. 214, 217. 

f e.g. cmelty in the heat of battle rouses less indignation than 
ill-treatment of women afterwards. For a similar reason profligacy 
was said (III. 12) to be worse than cowardice. 



e, 3-7.3 INCONTINENCE. 229 

more disgraceful than incontinence in anger, and that 
continence and incontinence proper have to do with 
bodily appetites and pleasures. 

6 But now let us see what differences we find in 
these bodily appetites and pleasures. 

As we said at the outset, some of them are human 
and natural in kind and degree ; others are signs of 
a brutal nature; others, again, are the result of_ 
oiganic injury or disease. 

Now, it is with the first of these only that tem- 
perance and profligacy have to do: and for this 
reason we do not call beasts either temperate or 
profligate, except it be metaphorically, if we find a 
whole class of animals distinguished from others 
by peculiar lewdness and wantonness and voracity ; 
for there is no purpose or deliberate calculation in 
what they do, but they are in an xmnatural state, 
like madmen. 

7 Brutality is less dangerous than vice, but more 
horrible ; for the noble part is not corrupted here, as 
in a man who is merely vicious in a human way, but 
is altogether absent. To ask which is worse, then, 
would be like comparing inanimate things with 
animate : the badness of that which lacks the origi- 
nating principle is always less mischievous; and 
reason [which the brutal man lacks] is here the origi- 
nating principle. (To compare these, then, would be 
like comparing injustice with an unjust man : each 
is in its own way the worse.*) For a bad man 

* This comparison is rendered snperfluons by the preceding one 
(which probably was meant to be snbstitnted for it), and is not very 
apt as it stands. We should rather expect vphs rh &9ikov : the sense 
wonld then be, *' injustice is morally worse than an unjust act which 



[would do ten thousand times &a much harm as a 
brute. 
7. With regard to the pleasures and pains of touch 

pitatuTc, and taste, and the corresponding deairea and aver- 
poin. Two aiona, which we before marked out as the field of 
inmntinonr. profligacj and temperance, it is possible to be so 
B^iiita disposed as to succumb to allurements which most 
people resist, or so as to rcaiat allurements to which 

I moat people succumb. When they are exhibited in 
the matter of pleasures, the former of these characters 
is called incontinent and the latter continent ; when 
they are exhibited in the matter of pains, the former 
is called soft and the latter hardy. The character of 
the general run of men falls between these two, 
inclining perhaps rather to the worse. 

But since some pleasures are necessary, while 
others are not, and since the necessary pleasures a^e 

I necessary in certain quantities only, but not in too 

great nor yet in too small quantities, and since the 
aame is true of appetites and of pains, he who pur- 
sues pleasures that faU beyond the pale of legitimate 
pleasures, or pursues any pleasures to excess,* is 
called profligate, if he pursues them of deliberate 
purpose for their own sake and not for any result 
dooa not proceed from an onjnst character, bat the latter maj be a. 
worse evil ;" e.g. humanity has Buffered more by woU-mBaning peiv 
EBcotors than by the RreatoBt villainB. Cf. V. 11, 8. 

• Tiiia diatinotion may he iLnstratod by the distinction which 
opinion in England draws between opium-amokinB and tobacco- amofc. 
ing^. Opinm. am along is comtnonly regarded by ua as u &wtp0o\ii, &■ 
a pleaanre that in any degree ia beyond the pale at legitiipata 
pleaanrBB ; a man who is too mnoh given to tobaoco-B molting is 
regariled as parsning «afl' !nrip&o\iis (in eioesa) a pleasora which in 
jnodstBtioa is legitimate. 



230 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF AEISTOTLE. [Bk. 



7, 1-5.] INOONTINENOJB. 231 

which follows from tiiem ; * for such a man must be in- 
capable of remorses-must be incurable therefore ; for 
he who feels no remorse is incurabla In the opposite 
extreme is he who falls short of the mean (while he 
who observes the mean is temperate). So with the 
man who avoids bodily pains, not because he is 
momentarily overcome, but of deliberate purpose. 
8 But those who act thus without deliberate pur- 
pose may do so either to gain pleasure or to escape 
the pain of desire, and we must accordingly distinguish 
these from one another. 

But all would allow that a man who does some- 
thing disgraceful without desire, or with only a 
moderate desire, is worse than if he had a violent 
desire ; and that if a man strike another in cool blood 
he is worse than if he does it in anger; for what 
would he do if he were in a passion ? The profligate 
joaan, therefore, is worse than the incontinent 

Of the characters mentioned, then> we mu^ 
distinguish softness from profligacy. 

4 The continent character is opposed to the incon- 
tinent, . and the hardy to the soft ; for hardiness 
implies that you endure, while continence implies 
tiiat you overcome, and enduring is different from 
overcoming, just as escaping a defeat is different 
from winning a victory ; so continence is better than 
haiijdiness. 

5 But he that gives way to what the generality of 
men can and do resist is soft and luxurious (for 
luxury, too, is a kind of softness), — ^the sort of man 
that suffers his cloak to trail along the ground rather 

* Beading ci instead of fj. 



/ 



/ 



/ 



232 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OP ABISTOTLK [Bk. VIL 

• 

than be at the pains to pull it up; that plays the 
invalid, and yet does not consider himself wretched, 
though it is a wretched man that he imitates. 

Similarly with continence and incontinence. If 6 
a man give way to violent and excessive pleasures or 
pains, we do not marvel, but are ready to pardon him 
if he struggled, like Pbiloctetes when bitten by the 
viper in the play of Theodectes, or Cercyon in the 
Alope of Carcinus ; or like people who, in trying to 
restrain their laughter, burst out into a violent explo- 
sion, as happened to Xenophantus. But we do 
marvel when a man succumbs to and cannot resist 
what the generality of men are able to hold out 
against, unless the cause be hereditary disposition 
or disease {e.g, softness is hereditary in the Scythian 
kings, and the female is naturally softer than the 
male). 

The man that is given up to amusement is gene- 7 
rally thought to bo profligate, but in fact he is soft ; 
for amusement is relaxation, since it is a rest £rom 
labour ; and among those who take too much relaxa- 
tion are those who are given up to amusement. 

There are two kinds of incontinence, the hasty and a 
the weak. Some men deliberate, but, under the in- 
fluence of passion, do not abide by the result of their 
deliberations ; others are swayed by passion because 
they do not deliberate ; for as there are people who 
cannot be tickled if they are prepared for it, so there 
are people who when they see what is coming, and 
are forewarned and rouse themselves and their reason, 
are able to resist the impulse, whether it be pleasant 
or painful. People of quick sensibility or of a melan- 



7, 6-8, 2.] INCONTINENCE. 233 

cliolic temperament are most liable to incontinence of 
the hasty sort ; such people do not wait to hear the 
voice of reason, because, in the former case through the 
rapidity, in the latter case through the intensity of their 
impressions, they are apt to follow their imagination. 

8. Again, a profligate man, as we said, is not given inconHnme 
to remorse, for he abides by his deliberate purpose ; vnthmce 
but an incontinent man is always apt to feel remorse. 
So the case is not as it was put in one of the difficul- 
ties we enumerated,* but the former is incurable, the 
latter is curable. For full-formed vice [profligacy] 
seems to be like such diseases as dropsy or consump- 
tion, incontinence like epilepsy; for the former is 
chronic, the latter intermittent badness. 

Indeed, we may roundly say that incontinence is I 
generically difierent from vice; for the vicious man 
knows not, but the incontinent man knows, the nature . 
of his acts.t 

But of these incontinent characters, those who 
momentarily lose their reason are not so bad as those 
who retain their reason but disobey it; J for the latter 
give way to a slighter impulse, and cannot, like the 
former, be said to act without deliberation. For an 
incontinent man is like one who gets drunk quickly 
and with little wine, i,e, with less than most men. 

• Of. supra, 2, 10, 11. 

t The inoontinent man, when the fit is over and the better part 
of him reasserts itself (c/. § 5) , recognizes the badness of his act * 
bni the vicious man, thoagh he is aware that his acts are called bad, i 
dissents from the judgments of societj (c/. 9, 7), and so ma,j be 
said not to know : cf. III. 1, 12. 

J The weak (ISur6fy€7s) are worse than the hasty (-rpoir) €Te"s : c/. 
9upra, 7, 8. 



234 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk. VIL 

We have seen that incontinenoe is not vice^ but 3 
perhaps vre may say that it is in a Buomer vice. The 
difference is that the vicious man acts with deliberate 
purpose^ while the incontinent man acts against it 
But in spite o( this difference their acts are similar ; 
as Demodocus said against the Milesians^ ''The 
Milesians are not fools, but they act like fools." So an 
^continent man is not unjust, but he acts unjustly. 

It is the character of the incontinent man to 4 
pursue, without being convinced of their goodness, 
bodily pleasures that exceed the bounds of moderation 
and are contrary to right reason ; but the profligate 
man is convinced that these things are good because it 
is his character to pursue them : the former, then, may 
be easily brought to a better mind, the latter not. For 
virtue preserves, but vice destroys the principle ; but 
in matters of conduct the motive [end or final cause] 
is the principle [beginning or efficient cause] of action, 
holding the same place here that the hypotheses do in 
mathematics.* In mathematics no reasoning or de- 
monstration can instruct us about these principles or 
starting points ; so here it is not reason but virtue, 
either natural or acquired by training, that teaches 
us to hold right opinions about the principle of 
action. A man of this character, then, is temperate, 
while a man of opposite character is profligate. 

But there is a class of people who are apt to be 5 
momentarily deprived of their right senses by passion, 
and who are swayed by passion so far as not to act 

* i,e, the definitions j not the axioms, sinpe in Aristotle's 
language a ivSdea'is, strictly speaking, inTolTes the assumption of 
the existence of a corresponding object. 



8, 8-9, 20 mCONTINENOE. 235 

according to reason, but not so far that it has become 
part of their nature to believe that they ought to 
pursue pleasures of this kind without limit. These 
are the incontinent, who are better than the profli- 
gate, and not absolutely bad ; for the best part of our 
nature, the principle of right conduct, still sui'vives in 
them. 

To these are opposed another class of people who 
are wont to abide by their resolutions, and not to be 
deprived of their senses by passion at least. It is 
plain from this, then, that the latter is a good type of 
character, the former not good. 

9. Now, who is to be called continent ? he who cmtinence 
abides by any kind oi reason and any kind of purpose, unence not 
or he who abides by a right purpose ? And who is to u^ith keepit 
be called incontinent? is it he who abandons einyingaTwu 
kind of purpose and any kind of reason ? is even he 
who abandons a false reason and a wrong purpose to 
be called incontinent ? — a difficulty which we raised 
before.* Is it not the case that though " accidentally " 
it may be any kind, yet " essentially " it is a true 
reason and a right purpose that the one abides by 
and the other abandons ? For if you choose or pursue 
A for the sake of B, you pursue and choose B 
" essentially," but A " accidentally." But by " essen- 
tially " {icaO' avTo) we mean "absolutely" or " simply*'. 
{aw\big) ; so that we may say that in a certain sense 
it may be any kind of opinion, but absolutely or 
simply it is a true opinion that the one abides by ^ 
and the other abandons. 

But there is another class of persons that are apt 



236 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OP ARISTOTLE. [Bk. VH. 

to stick to their opinions (I mean those whom we caJl 
stubborn or obstinate), because they are averse to per- 
suasion and not readily induced to change their mind. 
These bear some resemblance to the continent, as the 
prodigal does to the liberal, and the foolhardy to the 
courageous, but in many respects are different. For 
it is changing his mind at the prompting of passion or 
appetite that the continent man dislikes ; he is ready 
enough on occasion to yield to reason : but it is to 
reason especially that the obstinate man will not 
listen, while he often conceives a passion^ and is led 
about by his pleasures. 

The opinionated, the ignorant, and the boorish are 3 
all obstinate — the opinionated from motives of pleasure 
and pain; for they delight in the sense of victory 
when they hold out against argument, and are pained 
if their opinion comes to naught like a decree that 
is set aside. They resemble the incontinent man, 
therefore, rather than the continent. 

Sometimes also people abandon their resolutions 4 
from something else than incontinence, as, for instance, 
Neoptolemus in the Philoctetes of Sophocles. It may 
be said, indeed, that pleasure was his motive in aban- 
doning his resolution : but it was a noble pleasure ; 
for truth was fair in his eyes, but Ulysses had persuaded 
him to lie. For he who acts with pleasure for motive 
is not always either profligate, or worthless, or in- 
continent, but only when his motive is a base 
pleasure. 

Again, there are people whose character it is to 5 
take too little delight in the pleasures of the body, and 
who by reason of this character swerve from reason ; 



9, 8-10, 1.] INCONTINENCE. 237 

and between these and the incontinent come the con- 
tinent For while the incontinent swerve from reason 
because of an excess, and these because of a deficiency, 
the continent man holds fast and is not turned aside 
by the one or the other. 

But if continence be a good things the characters 
that are opposed to it must be bad, as in fact they 
evidently are ; only, since the other extreme is found 
but rarely and in few cases, incontinence comes to 
be regarded as the only opposite of continence, just 
as profligacy comes to be regarded as the only oppo- 
site of temperance. 

We often apply names metaphorically ; and so we 
come to speak metaphorically of the continence of 
the temperate man. For it is the nature both of the 
continent and of the temperate man never to do 
anything contrary to reason for the sake of bodily 
pleasures ; but whereas the former has, the latter has 
not bad desires, and whereas the latter is of such a 
nature as to take no delight in wh^t is contrary to 
reason, the former is of such a nature as to take 
delight in, but not to be swayed by them. 

The incontinent and the profligate also resemble 
each other, though they are different; both pursue 
bodily pleasures, but the latter pursues them on 
principle,* while the former does not. 

10. It is impossible for the same man to be at once Prudence u 

^ nott but 

prudent and incontinent : for we have shown that a cleverness is, 

* ' compatible 

man cannot be prudent without being at the same ^^^;^^ 
time morally good. 

• Literally, -thinking that he onght {oUfievos 8e2y) ; ue. adopting 
them as his end. 



236 NICOMAOHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. Vlt 

Moreover, a man is not made prudent by merely 2 
knowing, but also by being apt to act, and the in- 
continent man is not apt to act [as he resolves]. But 
there is nothing to prevent a man who is clever at 
calculating means from being incontinent; and so 
people sometimes think a man prudent and yet in- 
continent, because this cleverness is related to 
prudence in the manner before * expla;ined, and as far 
as reason goes they are closely allied, though they 
differ in purpose. 
V The incontinent man, however, has knowledge, 3 
not as one who knows in the sense of using his know- 
ledge, but as one may know who is asleep or drunk. 

He acts voluntarily (for in a manner he knows 
what he is doing and with what object), aad yet is 
not bad : for his purpose is good ; so he is only half 
bad. Moreover, incontinent men jwe not unjust,t for 
they are not deliberately malicious-^some of them 
being apt to swerve from their deliberate resolutions, 
others of melancholic temper and apt to act without 
deliberating at all. An incontinent man, then, may 
be compared to a state which always makes excellent 
decrees and has good laws, but never carries them 
out ; as Anaxandrides jestingly says — 

" So willed the state that takes no heed of laws." 

The bad man, on the contrary, may be compared to a 4 
state that carries out its laws, but has bad laws. 

• Of. supra, VI. 12, 9. 

t Though they do what is unjust or wrong. It must be remem- 
bered that above (V. 1, 12-end) it was laid down that all vicious 
action, when viewed in relation to others, is unjust (in the wider 
sense of the term). 



10, 2-11, 8.] OF PLEASURE. 239 

Both incontinence and continence imply some- 
thing beyond the average character of men ; for the 
one is more steadfeust than most men can be, the other 
less. 

Of the several kinds of incontinence, that of the 
melancholic temper is more curable than that of those 
who make t^solutions but do not keep them, and that 
which proceeds from custom than that which rests on 
natural infirmity: it is easier to alter one's habit 
than to change one's nature. For the very reason 
why habits are hard to change is that they are a sort 
of second nature, as Euenus says — 

'* Train men bnt long enough to what 70a will, 
And that shall be their nature in the end." 

5 We have now considered the nature of continence 
and incontinence, of hardiness and softness, and the 
relation of these types of character to each other. 



CHAPTEKS 11 — 14. OF PLEASURE. 

11. The consideration of pleasure and pain also we mutt 
falls within the scope of the political philosopher, «>^«*«. 
since he has to construct the end by reference to «*»«*' *'• 
which we call everything good or bad. 

Moreover, this is one of the subjects we are bound 
to discuss; for we said that moral virtue and vice 
have to do with pleasures and pains, and most people 
say that happiness implies pleasure, which is the 
reason of the name fiwcipiog, blessed, from xafp^w, to 
rejoice. 

Now, (1) some people think that no pleasure is 



240 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OP AKISTOTLB. [Bk. VII. 

good, either essentially or accidentally^ for they say 
that good and pleasure are two distinct things ; (2) 
others think that though some pleasures are good 
most are bad; (3) others, again, think that even 
though all pleasures be good, yet it is impossible that 
the supreme good can be pleasure. 

(1) It is argued that pleasure cannot be good, (a) 4 
because all pleasure is a felt transition to a natural 
state, but a transition or process is always generically 
different from an end, e.g. the process of building is 
genericaUy different from a house; (6) because the 
temperate man avoids pleasures ; (c) because the pru- 
dent man pursues the painless, not the pleasant ; (d) 
because pleasures impede thinking, and that in pro- 
portion to their intensity (for instance, the sexual 
pleasures: no one engaged therein could think at all) ; 
(e) because there is no art of pleasure, and yet every 
good thing has an art devoted to its production ; (/) 
because pleasure is the pursuit of children and brutes. 

(2) It is argued that not aU pleasures are good, 5 
because some are base and disgraceful, and even 
hurtful; for some pleasant things are unhealthy. 

(3) It is argued that pleasure is not the supreme 
good, because it is not an end, but a process or 
transition. 

Anstoersto 12. Thcsc, then, we may take to be the current 1 
J^iSr** opinions on the subject ; but that it does not follow 
^amre. thcrefrom that pleasure is not good, or even the 
tf^and highest good, may be shown as follows. 
puamr'eMt In the first place, since "good" is used in two 
but^iii^' senses ("good in itself" and "relatively good"), 
nctivity. natures and faculties will be called good in two 



11, 4-13, 2.] OF PLBASUBB. 241 

senses, and so also will motions and processes : and 
when they are called bad, this sometimes means that 
they are bad in themselves, though for particular 
persons not bad but desirable ; sometimes that they 
are bad in themselves and not desirable even for 
particular persons, though desirable occasionally and 
for a little time ; while some of them are not even 
pleasures, though they seem to be — I mean those that 
involve pain and are used medicinally, such as those 
of sick people. 

In the second place, since the term good may be 
applied both to activities and to faculties, those 
activities that restore us to our natural faculties [or 
state] are accidentally pleasant. 

But in. the satisfaction of the animal appetites 
that which is active is [not that part which is in 
want, but] the rest of our faculties or of our nature ; * 
for there are pleasures which involve no previous 
pain or appetite, such as the activity of philosophic 
study, wherein our nature is not conscious of any 
want. 

This is corroborated by the fact that while our 
natural wants are being filled we do not take delight 
in the same things which delight us when that process 
has been completed : when the want has been filled ( 
we take delight in things that are pleasant ip them- ' 
selves, while it is being filled in their opposites ; for 
we then take delight in sharp and bitter things, none ; 
of which are naturally pleasant or pleasant in them- ' 

• Cf* ir^frat 14, 7. I have frequently in this chapter rendered 
l|cs by facnlty, in order to express the opposition to iv^pyftOf actiyity 
cr ezerciBe of faculty ; but no single word is satisfactory. 

R 



/ 



242 NICOMACHEAK iSTHIOS OP ABISTOTLK [Bk. TIL 

selves. The pleasures, then, which these things give 
are not real pleasures; for pleasures are related to one 
another as the things that produce them. 

Again, it does not necessarily follow, as some 3 
maintain, that there is something else better than 
pleasure, as the end is better than the process or 
transition to the end : for a pleasure is not a transi- 
tion, nor does it always even imply a transition ; but 
it is an activity [or exercise of faculty], and itself an 
end : further, it is not in becoming something, but in 
doing something that we feel pleasure: and, lastly, 
the end is not always something diflFerent from the 
process or transition, but it is only when something is 
being brought to the completion of its nature that 
this is the case. 

For these reasons it is not proper to say that 
pleasure is a felt transition, but rather that it is an 
exercise of faculties that are in their natural state, 
substituting " unimpeded " for " felt." 

Some people, indeed, think that pleasure is a 
transition, just because it is in the full sense good, 
supposing that the exercise of faculty is a transition ; 
but it is in fact something different.* 

To urge, again, that some pleasures are bad, because 4 
some pleasant things are unhealthy, is like arguing 
that some things that are healthy are bad for money 
making. Both indeed are bad in this sense, but that 

• The argument in foil would be thus : pleasure is good ; but 
good is exercise of faculty {iv4pytia)f and this is a process or transi- 
tion (yivtais) ; /, pleasure is a transition^ But according to 
Aristotle the highest ivepytta involves no transition or motion at all 
(c/. 14, 8), and in every true iv4py€iay even when a transition is in- 
volvedf the end is attained at every moment. Cf, Met. iz. 6. 1048^ 



X2, 8-18, 1.] OP PLBASUBB, 243 

does not make them bad in themselves : even philo- 
sophic study is sometimes bad for one's health. 

5 As to pleasure being an impediment to thinking, 
the fact is that neither prudence nor any other faculty 
is impeded by the pleasure proper to its exercise, but 
by other pleasures ; the pleasure derived from study 
and learning will make us study and learn more. 

6 That there shoidd be no art devoted to the pro- 
duction of any kind of pleasure, is but natural ; for 

/ art never produces an activity, but only makes it 
possible : the arts of perfumery and cookery, however, 
are usually considered to be arts of pleasure. 

7 As to the arguments that the temperate man 
avoids pleasure, that the prudent man pursues the 
painless life, and that children and brutes pursue 
pleasure, they may all be met in the same way, viz. 
thus : — 

As we have already explained in what sense all 
pleasures are to be called good in themselves, and in 
what sense not good, we need only say that pleasures 
of a certain kind are pursued by brutes and by chil- 
dren, and that freedom from the corresponding pains is 
pursued by the prudent man — ^the pleasures, namely, 
that involve appetite and pain, i.e. the bodily pleasures 
(for these do so), and excess in them, the deliberate 
pursuit of which constitutes the profligate. These 
pleasures, then, the temperate man avoids; but he 
has pleasures of his own. 
L 13. But all admit that pain is a bad thing and PUantre t 
undesirable; partly bad in itself, partly bad as in«A«pka«*i 
some sort an impediment to activity. But that which *« jj^ 
is opposed to what is undesirable, in that respect in ocuvUffU 



244 NIOOMACHEAH ETmOS 0£* ABISTOTLB. [Bk. YIL 

^good,^ which it is undesirable and bad^ is good. It follows, 
uhS^^ then, that pleasure is a good thing. And this argu- 
numt. ment cannot be met, as Speusippus tried to meet it, 
miretnothj the aualogj of the greater which is opposed to 
the equal as well as to the less; for no one would 
say that pleasure is essentially a bad thing.* 
V Moreover, there is no reason why a certain kind a 
of pleasure should not be the supreme good, even 
though some kinds be bad, just as there is no reason 
why a certain kind of knowledge should not be, 
though some kinds be bad. Nay, perhaps we ought 
rather to say that since every formed faculty admits 
of unimpeded exercise, it follows that, whether hap- 
piness be the exercise of all these faculties, or of 
some one of them, that exercise must necessarily be 
most desirable when unimpeded: but unimpeded 
exercise of faculty is pleasure : a certain kind of plea- 
sure, therefore, will be the supreme good, even though 
. most pleasures should turn out to be bad in themselves. 
And on this account all men suppose that the 
happy life is a pleasant one,, and that happiness in- 
volves pleasure : and the supposition is reasonable ; for 
no exercise of a faculty is complete if it be impeded ; 
but happiness we reckon among complete things; and 
so, if he is to be happy, a man must have the goods 
of the body and external goods and good fortune, 
in order that the exercise of his faculties may not 

* The argument is, '' Pleasure is good because it is tlie opposite 
of pain, which is evil.** " No," says Speusippus j " it is neither 
pleasure nor pain, but the neutral state, which is opposite to both, 
that is good." ** No/' replies Aristotle, '< for then pleasure wiU be 
bad." 



IS, 9-7.] OF FLEASUBE. 245 

8 be impeded. And those who say that though a man 
be put to the rack and overwhehned by misfortune, 
he is happy if only he be good, whether they knowy^ 
it or not, talk nonsense. ^ 

I Because fortune is a necessary condition, some 
people consider good fortune to be identical with 
happiness ; but it is not really so, for good fortune 
itself, if excessive, is an impediment, and is then, 
perhaps, no longer to be called good fortune; for 
good fortune can only be defined by its relation to 
happiness. 

5 Again, the fietct that all animals and men pursue 
pleasure is some indication that it is in some way 
the highest good : 

''Not whollj loBt oan e*er that saying be 
Which 108117 peoples share." 

6 But as the nature of man and the best develop- 
ment of his faculties neither are nor are thought 
to be the same for all, so the pleasure which men 
pursue is not always the same, though all pursue 
pleasure. Yet, perhaps, they do in fact pursue a 
pleasure different from that which they fancy they 
pursue and would say they pursue — ^a pleasure which 
is one and the same for aU. For all beings have 
something divine implanted in them by nature. 

But bodily pleasures have come to be regarded 
as the sole claimants to the title of pleasure, because 
they are oftenest attained and are shared by all ; these 
then, as the only pleasures they know, men fancy to 
be the only pleasures that are. 

7 But it is plain that unless pleasure — ^that is, unim- 
peded exercise of the faculties — ^be good, we can no 



r 



occidenlalti/ 



216 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. TIT. 

longer say that the happy man leads a pleasant life ; 
for why should he need it if it be not good 1 Nay, 
he may just as well lead a painful life: for pain is 
neither bad nor good, if pleasure be neither; so why 
should he avoid pain ! The life of the good man, 
then, would be no pleasanter than others unless the 
exercise of hia faculties were pleasanter, 

14. Those who say that though some pleasures 
are very desirable — to wit, noble pleasures — the 
pleasures of the body, with which the profligate is 
concerned, are not desirable, should consider the 
nature of these pleasures of the body. Why [if they 
are bad] are the opposite pains bad ? for the opposite 
of bad is good. Are we to say that the "necessary " 
pleasures are good in the sense that what is not bad 
ia good ? or are they good up to a certain point ? 

Those faculties and those motions or activities 
which do not admit of excess beyond what is good,* 
do not admit of excessive pleasure ; but those which 
admit of excess admit also of excessive pleaaore. 
Now, bodily goods admit of excess, and the bad man 
is bad because he pursues this excess, not merely 
because he pursues the necessary pleasures ; for men 
always take some delight in meat, and drink, and 
the gratification of the sexual appetite, but not 
always as they ought. But with pain the case is 
reversed: not merely the excess of pain, but pain 
generally is to be avoided ; f for the opposite of exces- 

• VirbQons faculties and aotivities (II. 6, 20) do not admit 
of oxceaa, bocanse liy Iheir very uatnre they are right and ooonpj 
the mean ; too much of tbem wonid be s, contradiction in terma. 



14, l-i.] OF PLEABUBE. 247 

sive pleasure is not painful^ except to the man who 
pursues the excess.* 

But "we ought to state not only the truth, but 
also the cause of the error ; for this helps to produce 
conviction, as, when something has been pointed out 
to us which would naturally make that seem true 
which is not, we are more ready to believe the truth. 
And so we must say why it is that the bodily 
pleasures seem more desirable. 

First of all, then, it is because of its efficacy in 
expelling pain, and because of the excessiveness of 
the pain to which it is regarded as an antidote, that 
men pursue excessive pleasure and bodily pleasure 
generally. But these remedies produce an intense 
feeling, and so are pursued, because they appear in 
strong contrast to the opposite pain. 

(The reasons why pleasure is thought to be not 
good are two, as we said befor§j_(l) some pleasures 
are the manifestation of a nature that is bad either 
from birth, as with brutes, or by habit, as with 
bad men: (2) the remedial pleasures imply want; 
and it is better to be in a [natural] state than in 
a transition to such a state ; but these pleasures are 
felt while a want in us is being filled up, and therefore 
they are only accidentally good.t) 

* Fain generally (p\tos) is bad, to be avoided. 

Objection: The pain of foregoing certain excessive pleasnres 
is not to be avoided. 

Answer : The opposite of these excessive pleasnres, i.e, the fore- 
going them, is not painfnl to the virtnons man, bnt only to him who 
sets his heart npon them, i.e, to a vicious or incontinent man. 

t As these words disturb the order of the arg^oment, I have, 
following Bamsaner, pat them in brackets ; bat I see no sufficient 
TOMon for regarding them as spnrions* 



^1 



V 



248 NIOOMACHEAN ETHIGS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk. YIL 

Again, these pleasures are pursued because of 5 
their intensity by those who are unable to take 
delight in other pleasures ; thus we see people make 
themselves thirsty on purpose. When the pleasures 
they pursue are harmless, we do not blame them 
(though when they are hurtful the pursuit is bad) ; for 
they have no other sources of enjoyment, and the 
neutral state is painful to many because of their 
nature : for an animal is always labouring, as physical 
science teaches, telling us that seeing and hearing is 
labour and pain, only we are all used to it, as the 
saying ia And thus in youth, because they are 6 
growing, men are in a state resembling drunkenness ; 
and youth is pleasant. But people of a melancholic 
nature are always wanting something to restore their 
balance; for their bodies are always vexing them 
because of their peculiar temperament, and they are 
always in a state of violent desire. But pain is ex- 
pelled either by the opposite pleasure or by any 
pleasure, if it be suflSciently strong ; and this is the 
reason why such men become profligate and worthless. 

But pleasures that have no antecedent pain do not 
admit of excess. These are the pleasures derived from 7 
things that are naturally and not merely accidentally 
pleasant. I call those things accidentally pleasant that 
have a restorative effect ; for as the restoration cannot 
take place unless that part of the system which remains 
healthy be in some way active, the restoration itself 
seems pleasant : but I call those things naturally plea- 
sant that stimulate the activity of a healthy system.* 

• qf. «uj>r», IS, 2. 

I am sick and take medioine, hangrj and take food (which 



14, 6-a] OF FLEASUBEk 249 

■ 

But nothing can continue to give us uninter- 
rupted pleasure, because our nature is not simple, 
but contains a second element which makes us mortal 
beings ; * so that if the one element be active in any 
way, this is contrary to the nature of the other 
element, but when the two elements are in equili- 
brium, what we do seems neither painful nor pleasant; 
for if there were a being whose nature were simple, 
the same activity would be always most pleasant to 
him. And on this account God always enjoys one 
simple pleasure; for besides the activity of move- 
ment, there is also activity without movement, and 
rest admits of truer pleasure than motion. But 
change is "the sweetest of all things," as the poet 
says, because of a certain badness in us : for just as 
it is the bad man who is especially apt to change, 
so is it the bad nature that needs change; for it 
is neither simple nor good. 

seems to be here included under medicine) ; but neither the drug 
nor the food can of themselTes cure me and restore the balance of 
my system — ^they must be assimilated (for the body is not like a jar 
that can be filled merely by pouring water from another jar), i.e. part 
of my system must remain in its normal state and operate in its 
normal manner. But this operation, this ivipytia r^s Karh <p{Mriv t^eus, 
is pleasure (by the definition given above, 12, 3), and in ignorance 
of the process we transfer the pleasure to the medicine and call it 
pleasant. The weakness of this account is that it overlooks the 
fact that, though the medicine cannot itself cure without the 
operation of rrjs Karh, (piariv c|€»f, yet on the other hand this c|ir, 
this faculty, cannot operate in this manner without this stimulus ; 
80 that there seems to be no reason why the medicine, as setting 
up an iytpytia rrjs Kark ^{xriv U^tcos, should not itself be called ^{uru 
ifil. But the whole passage rests on the assumption that there can 
be activity without stimulus, i.e, without want — an assumption 
which has become inconceivable to us. 
♦ C/. X. 7, 8. 



250 NICOHACHEAN ETHICS OF AHISTOTLE. [Bk^YIL 

We have now considered continence and incon- p 
tinence, and pleasure and pain^ and have explained 
\7l1at each is, and how some of them are good and 
some bad. It remains to consider friendship. 



A 




1 1. After the foregoing, a discnsaion of friendship 
will naturally follow, aa it is a sort of virtue, or at '^'''^-;^ 
least implies vhiue, and is, moreover, most ne cessar y ai*"'' ^-^ 
to our life. For no one would caro to live without 

friends, though he had all other good things. Indeed, I 
it is when a man is rich, and has got power and 

authority, that ho seems most of all to stand in need of i 

friends ; for what is the use of all this prosperity if he | 

have no opportunity for benevolence, which is most ', 

frequently and most eommendably displayed towards , 

friends ? or how could hia position he maintained and i 

preserved without friends ? for the greater it is, the | 
2 more is it exposed to danger. In poverty and all 

other misfortunes, again, we regard our friends as our | 

only refuge. We need friends when we are young | 
to keep us from error, when we get old to tend upon ' 

U3 and to carry out those plans which we have not , 
strength to execute ourselves, and in the prime of 
life to help us in noble deeds — "two together" [aa 
Homer says] ; for thus we are more efficient both in 

thought and in action. 1 

3 Love seems to be implanted by nature in the ' 

parent towards the ofispring, and in the ofTsprinE; ' 

L J 



262 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLB. [Bk, yilL 

towards the parent, not only among men, but also 
among birds and most animals; and in those of the 
same race towards one another, among men especially 
— for which reason we commend those who love their 
\ fellow-men. And when one travels one may see how 
man is always akin to and dear to. man. 
V Again, it seems that friendship is the bond that 4 
holds states together, and that lawgivers are even 
more eager to secure it than justice. For concord 
bears a certain resemblance to friendship, and it 
is concord that they especially wish to retain, and 
dissension that they especially wish to banish as an 
enemy. If citizens be friends, they have no nee d 
of justice, but though they be just, they need friend- 
ship or love also ; indeed, the completest realization 
of justice * seems to be the realization of friendship 
or love also. 

Moreover, friendship is not only an indispensable, 5 
but also a beautiful or noble thing : for we commend 
those who love their friends, and to have many 
friends is thought to be a noble thing; and some 
even think that a good man is the same as a friend .f 

But there are not a few diflFerences of opinion 6 
about the matter. Some hold that it is a kind of 
likeness, and that those who are like one another are 
friends ; and this is the origin of *' Like to like," and 
"Birds of a feather flock together," J and other similar 
sayings. Others, on the contrary, say that " two of 
a trade never agree." § 

• r&y ZiKuiav rh fidkitrrOf «c, rh iTiUK4s : cf. V. 10, and VT; 11, 2. 
t Cf. Plato, Eep., 334. J Literally, " Crow to crow." 

§ LiteraUy, " saj that all who thus resemble one another are to 



1, 4-2, IJ FRIENDSHIP OR LOVK 253 

Others go deeper into these questions, and into 
the causes of the phenomena ; Euripides, for instance 
says — 

** The parched earth loves the rain, 
And the high heaven, with moistiire laden, loves 
Earthwards to fall." 

Heraclitus also says, "Opposites fit together," and 
*'Out of discordant elements comes the fairest har- 
mony," and " It is by battle that all things come into 
the world." Others, and notably Empedocles, take 
the opposite view, and say that like desires like. 

7 Of these difficulties, all that refer to the constitu- 
tion of the universe may be dismissed (for they do not 
properly concern our present inquiry) ; but those that 
refer to human nature, and are intimately connected 
with man's character and affections, we will discuss 
—as, for instance, whether friendship can exist in aU 
men, or whether it is impossible for men to be friends 
if ^ they are bad, and whether there be one form of 
friendship or rather many. For those who suppose 
that there is only one kind of friendship, because 
it admits of degrees, go upon insufficient grounda 
Things that differ in kind may differ also in degree 
(But we have already spoken about this point.*) 
1 2. Perhaps these difficulties will be cleared up i£j^reemoth 
we first ascertain what is the nature of the lovable. «J"?- ^ ^ . 
For it seems that we do not Jove anything y but*^***^- 
only the lovable, and that the lovable is v.either'^-' 

^good or p leasan t or useful, ^i But useful would appear 

one another like potters," alluding to the saying of Hesiod,-^ 

Kal K€pafX€us Kepafxet kot^u koI tsktovi tc/ctwk — 
'* Potter qoarrels with potter, and carpenter with carpenter.** 
* See Bamsaner. 



254 NIOOMACHEAK ETHICS OF ABISTOTLB. [Bk. Vm. 

to mean that which helps us to get something good, 
or some pleasure ; so that the good and the pleasant 
only would be loved as ends. 

Now, do men love what is good, or what is good a- 
for themselves ? for there is sometimes a discrepancy 
between these two. 

The same question may be asked about the 
pleasant. 

It seems that each man loves what is _good_for 
himself, and that, while^the good is lov able i n itse lf, 
V that is lovable to each man which is good for him . 
It may be said that each man loves not what is 
really good for him, but what seems good for him. 
But this wiU make no diflFerence ; for the lovable we 
are speaking of will then be the apparently lovable. 

The motives of love being thus threefold, the love 8 
of inanimate things is not called friendship. For ^ 
there is no return of affection here, nor any wish for 
the good of the object : it would be absurd to wish 
well to wine, for instance ; at the most, we wish that 
it may keep well, in order that we may have it. 
But it is commonly said that we must wish our 
friend's good for his own sake. One who thus wishes 
the good of another is called a well-wisher, when the 
wish is not reciprocated; when the well-wishing is ,- 
mutual, it is called friendship. 

But ought we not to add that each must be aware 4 
of the other's well-wishing ? For a man often wishes 
well to those whom he has never seen, but supposes 
to be good or useful men ; and one of these may have 
the same sentiments towards him. These two, then, 
are plainly well-wishers one of another; but how 



8, 3-3, 2.] FRIENDSHIP OB LOYB. 255 

could one call them friends when each is unaware of 

the other's feelings ? 
V V In order to be friends, then, they must be well- 
j wishers one of another, i.e. must wish each other s 
■ good from one of the three motives above mentioned, 

and be aware of each other's feelings. 
1 3. But these three motives are specifically difierent Three kindt 

from one another ; the several affections and friend- «m>, corre. 



ships based upon them, therefore, wiU also be specific- rj£2f *" 
ally different. The kinds of friendship accordingly Fer/eci 
are three, being equal in number to the motives oiuhat whose 

i* /»! iii'p imotive i» 

• love; for any one of these may be the basis of ^thegoo<L 
mutual affection of which each is aware. 

Now, those who love one another wish each 
other's good in respect of that which is the motive / 
of their love. Those, therefore, whose love for one 
another is based on the useful, do not love each v 

"^ other for what they are, but only in so far as each 
gets some good from the other. 

It is the same also with those whose affection is 
based on pleasure ; people care for a wit, for instance, h 
not for what he is, but as the source of pleasure to 
themselves. 

% Thow, then, whose love is based on the useful care 

^for each other on the ground of their own good, and 
those whose love is based on pleasure care for each 
other on the ground of what is pleasant to them- 
selves, each loving the other, not as being what he is, 
but as useful or pleasant. 

These friendships, then, are "accidental ; " for the 
object of affection is loved, not as being the person or 
character that he is, but as the source of some good 



256 NICOMAOHBAN ETHICS OP ABISTOTLE. [Be. Vin. 

or Bome pleasure. Friendships of this kind, therefor^, 3 
are easily dissolved, as the persons do not continue \ 
unchanged ; for if they cease to be pleasant or useful ] 
to one another, their love ceases. But the useful is 
nothing permanent, but varies from time to time. 
On the disappearance, therefore, of that which was the 
motive of their friendship, the friendship itself is dis- 
solved, since it existed solely with a view to that. 

Friendship of this kind seems especially to be 4 
found among elderly men (for at that time of life men 
pursue the useful rather than the pleasant) and those 
middle-aged and young men who have a keen eye to 
what is profitable. But friends of this kind do not 
generally even live together ; for sometimes they are 
by no means pleasant (nor indeed do they want such 
constant intercourse with others, unless they are use- 
ful) ; for they make themselves pleasant only just so 
far as they have hopes of getting something good 
thereby. 

With these friendships is generally classed the kind 
of friendship that exists between host and guest.* 

The friendship of young men is thought to be 5 
< based on pleasure; for young men live by impulse, 
and, for the most part, pursue what is pleasant to 
themselves and what is immediately present. But 
the things in which they take pleasure change as 
they advance in years. They are quick to make ^ 
friendships, therefore, and quick to drop them; for 

* A family of importance in a Greek state was nsuallj connected 
by ties of hospitality with other families in other states : persons 
so connected were not ipi\oi, not strictly friends, since they lived 
apart; bat (4votf for whioh there is no Snglish equivalent. 






8, 8-7J FBIENDSHIP OR LOVE. 257 

their friendship changes as the object which pleases 
'^^them changes ; and pleasure of this kind is liable to 

rapid alteration. 
^ Moreover, young men are apt to fall in love; for 
/ love is, for the most part, a matter of impulse and 

based on pleasure: so they fall in love, and again 

soon cease to love, passing from one state to the 

other many times in one day. 

Friends of this kind wish to spend their time 

together and to live together; for thus they attain 

the object of their friendship. 

6 YBut-the4)erfect kind of friendship is that of good 
men who resemble one another in virtue. For they 
both alike wish well to one another as good men, 
and it is their essential character to be good men. 

I And those who wish well to their friends for the 

/friends' sake are friends in the truest sense ; for they 

i have these sentiments towards each other as being 

what they are, and not in an accidental way : their 

friendship, therefore, lasts as long as their virtue, and 

that is a lasting thing. 

Again, each is both good simply and good to his 
friend ; for it is true of good men that they are both 
good simply and also useful to one another. 

In like manner they are pleasant too; for good 
men are both pleasant in themselves and pleasant to 
one another : for every kind of character takes delight 
in the acts that are proper to it and those that re- 
semble these ; but the acts of good men are the same 
or similar. 

7 This kind of friendship, then, is lasting, as we 
might expect, since it unites in itself all the con- 

s 



258 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk. VHL 

ditions of true firiendship. For every friendship has 
for its motive some good or some pleasure (whether 
it be such in itself or relatively to the person who 
loves), and is founded upon some similarity: but 
in this case all the requisite characteristics belong to 
the friends in their own nature; for here there is 
similarity and the rest, viz. what is good simply and 
pleasant simply, and these are the most lovable 
things : and so it is between persons of this sort that 
the truest and best love and friendship is founi 
/ It is but natural that such friendships £fhould be 8 

uncommon, as such people are rare. Such a friend- 
ship, moreover, requires long and familiar inter- 
course. For, as the proverb says, it is impossible for 
people to know one another till they have consumed 
the requisite quantity of salt together. Nor can 
they accept one another as friends, or be friends, till 
each show and approve himself to the other as 
worthy to be loved. Those who quickly come to 9 
treat one another like friends may wish to be friends, 
but are not really friends, unless they not only are 
lovable, but know each other to be so ; a wish to be 
friends may be of rapid growth, but not friendship. 

This kind of friendship, then, is complete in 
respect of duration and in all other points, and that 
which each gets from the other is in all respects 
identical or similar, as should be the case with fri^Kis. 
'%eot*i€n^^ 4. The friendship of which pleasure is the motive i 
J^tU^*^*' bears some resemblance to the foregoing; for good 
men, too, are pleasant to each other. So also does 
that of which the useful is the motive ; for good men 
are useful also to one another. And in these cases. 



8, 8-4, .3.] FRIENDSHIP OR LOVE. 259 

too, the fiiendship is most likely to endure when that 
which each gets from the other is the same {e.g. 
pleasure), and not only the same, but arising from 
the same source — ^a friendship between two wits, for 
instance, rather than one between a lover and his be- 
loved. For the source of pleasure in the latter case is 
not the same for both : the lover delights to look upon 
his beloved, the beloved likes to have attentions paid 
him; but when the bloom of youth is gone, the 
friendship sometimes vanishes also; for the one 
misses the beauty that used to please him, the other 
misses the attentions. But, on the other hand, they 
frequently continue friends, i,e. when their inter- 
course has brought them to care for each other's 
characters, and they are similar in character. 

Those who in matters of love exchange not pleasure 
but profit, are less truly and less permanently friends. 
The friendship whose motive is profit ceases when 
the advantage ceases; for it was not one another 
that they loved, but the profit. 

For pleasure, then, or for profit it is possible even 
for bad men to be friends with one another, and good 
men with bad, and those who are neither with people 
of any kind, but it is evident that the friendship in 
which each loves the other for himself is only possible 
between good men; for bad men take no delight in 
each other unless some advantage is to be gained. 

The friendship of good men, again, is the only one 
that can defy calumny ; for people are not ready to 
accept the testimony of any one else against him 
whom themselves have tested. Such friendship also 
implies mutual trust, and the certainty that neither 



260 NICOMACHBAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. VIII. 

would ever wrong the other, and all else that is im- 
plied in true friendship; while in other friendships 
there is no such security. 

For since men also apply the term friends to 4 
those who love one another for profit's sake, as hap- 
pens with states (for expediency is thought to be the 
ground on which states make alliances), and also to 
those who love one another for pleasure's sake, as 
children do, perhaps we too ought to apply the name 
to such people, and to speak of several kinds of friend- 
ship — ^firstly, in the primary and strict sense of the 
word, the friendship of good men as such ; secondly, 
the other kinds that are so called because of a resem- 
blance to this : for these other people are called friends 
in so far as their relation involves some element of 
good, which constitutes a resemblance; for the pleasant, 
too, is good to those who love pleasant things. But 5 
these two latter kinds are not apt to coincide ; nor do 
the same people become friends for the sake both of 
profit and pleasure ; for such accidental properties 
are not apt to be combined in one subject. 

Now that we have distinguished these several 6 
kinds of friendship, we may say that bad men will 
be friends for the sake of pleasure or profit, resembling 
true friends in this respect, while good men, when they 
. are friends, love each other for what they are, i.e. as 
good men. These, then, we say, are friends simply ; 
the others are friends accidentally and so far as they 
\ resemble these. 
tercaurse 6* But just as with regard to the virtues we l 
rS'.^ distinguish excellence of character or faculty from 
^fup. excellence manifested, so is it also with friendship: 



4, 4-6, 4] FRIENDSHIP OR LOVE. 261 

when friends are living together, they take pleasure 
in, and do good to, each other ; when they are asleep 
or at a distance from one another, they are not acting 
as friends, but they have the disposition which, if 
manifested, issues in friendly acts ; for distance does 
not destroy friendship simply, but the manifestation 
of friendship. But if the absence be prolonged, it is 
thought to obliterate even friendship ; whence the 
saying — 



y 



\j " Full many a friendship hath ere now been loosed 
By lack of converse." 



Old men do not seem apt to make friends, nor 
morose men ; for there is little in them that can give 
pleasure : but no one can pass his days in intercourse 
with what is painful or not pleasant ; for our nature 
seems, above all things, to shun the painful and seek 
the pleasant. 

8 Those who accept each other's company, but do 
not live together, seem to be rather well-wishers than 
friends. For there is nothing so characteristic of 
friendship as living together : * those who need help 
seek it thus, but even those who are happy desire 
company; for a solitary life suits them least of all 
men. But people cannot live together unless they 
are pleasant to each other, nor unless they take de- 
light in the same things, which seems to be a neces- 
sary condition of comradeship. 

>--- The truest friendship, then, is that which exists 
between good men, as we have said again and again. 

•To a Greek, of course, this does not necessarily imply living 
nnderthe «ajne roof, as it does to ns with our very different oon« 
ditions of lif e. 



262 NICOMACHBAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. \1IL 

For that, it seems, is lovable and desirable which is 
good or pleasant in itself, but to each man that which 
is good or pleasant to him ; and the friendship of good 
D^ien for one another rests on both these grounds. 

But it seems that while love is a feeling, friend- 5 
ship is a habit or trained faculty. For inanimate 
things can equally well be the object of love, but 
the love of friends for one another implies purpose, 
and purpose proceeds from a habit prtramed faculty. 
And in wishing well for their sakes to those they 
love, they are swayed not by feeling, but by habit. 
Again, in loving a friend they love what is good for 
themselves; for he who gains a good man for his 
friend gains something that is good for himself. 
Each then, loves what is good for himself, and what 
he gives in good wishes and pleasure is equal to 
what he gets; for equality is friendliness, as they 
say. All these characteristics, then, are found in the 
>^ highest degree in the friendship of good men. 
iposxibieto 6. Morose men and elderly men are less apt i 

ivc many t/»»-i« • i ^ i_ 

uefriendt. to make fricuds in proportion as they are harsher 
in temper, and take less pleasure in society; for 
delight in society seems to be, more than anything 
else, characteristic of friendship and productive of it. 
So young men are quick to make friends, but not old 
men (for people do not make friends with those who 
do not please them), nor morose men. Such people 
may, indeed, be well-wishers, for they wish each other 
good and help each other in need; but they are by 
no means friends, since they do not live with nor 
delight in each other, which things are thought to be. 
more than anything else, characteristic of friendship. 



/ 

5, 5-6, 4.] FBIENDSmP OB LOVE. 263 

2 It is impossible to have friendship, in the full 
sense of the word, for many people at the same time, 
just as it is impossible to be in love with many 
persons at once ; for it seems to be something intense, 
which may naturally be felt for one person, while it 
is not easy for one man to find at one time many 
very agreeable persons, perhaps not many good 

3 ones. Moreover, they must have tested and become 
accustomed to each other, which is a matter of great 
difficulty. But in the way of profit or pleasure, it is 
quite possible to find many * agreeable persons ; for 
such people are not rare, and their services can be 
rendered in a short time. 

4 Of these other kinds, that which more nearly 
resembles true friendship is that whose motive is 
^easure, when each renders the same service to the 
other, and both take pleasure in one another, or in 
the same things, such as young men's friendships 
are wont to be; for a generous spirit is commcmer 
in them than in others. But the friendship whose 
motive ia utility is the friendship of sordid souls. 
Those who are happy do not need useful, but pleasant 
fri^ids ; it is people to live with that they want, and 
though they may for a short time put up with what 
is painful, yet no one could endure anything con- 
tinually, not even the good itself, if it were painful ^ 
to him; so they require that their Mends shall be 
pleasant. But they ought, we may say, to require that 
they shall be good as well as pleasant, and good for 
them ; then all the characteristics of a friend will be 
combined. 

* Beading xoXAo^s. 



264 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk. Vlll. 

^ People in exalted positions seem to make distinct 5 
classes of friends. They have, some who are useful, 
and others who are pleasant, but seldom any that 
imite both these qualities; for they do not seek for 
people who are at once agreeable and virtuous, or 
people who can be useful to them in noble actions, 
but they seek for witty persons to satisfy their 
craving for pleasure, while for other purposes they 
choose men who are clever at carrying out their 
instructions: but these two qualities are seldom 
imited in one person. 

. The good man, indeed, as we have already said, 6 
is both pleasant and useful ; but such a man does 
not make friends with a man in a superior station, 
unless he allows himself inferior in virtue :* only thus 
does he meet the good man on equal terms, being 
inferior in one respect in the same ratio as he is 
superior in another. But great men are by no means 
wont to behave in this manner. 

In the friendships hitherto spoken of the persons 7 
are equal, for they do the same and wish the same 
for each other, or else exchange equal quantities of 
different things, as pleasure for profit (We have 
already explained that the latter less deserve the 
name of friendship, and are less lasting than the 
former kind. We may even say that, being at once 

• Tile words tiv fi)j ical ry ipcr^ 6irip4xri'^cu literally ineaii ** unless 
he also be snrpassed in virtne." Who is " he " P Not the former, for 6 
CTov^cuoSf the ideally good man, oannot be snrpassed in virtne ; there, 
fore the latter — the great man, the tyrant, kin^ or prince. The 
whole passage displays a decided cmimv^ against princes (perhaps, 
as Stahr suggests, a reminiscence of experiences in the Macedonian 
court). 



6, 6-7, 2.] FRIENDSHIP OR LOVE. 265 

both like it and unlike it, they seem both to be and 
not to be friendships. On the ground of their re- 
semblance to the friendship that is based on virtue, 
they seem to be friendships ; for one involves pleasure, 
the other profit, both of which belong to true friend- 
ship ; but, again, inasmuch as it is beyond calumny 
and is lasting, while they are liable to rapid change 
and diflferent in many other respects, they seem 
not to be friendships because of their unlikeness 
to it.) 

7. But, besid3s these, there is aiiother land of ey/rim 
friendship, in which the persons are unequal, as that tmequai 
of a father for a son, and generally of an elder for satsrtdei 
younger person, or of a man for a woman, or of a ¥^^^ 
rxilOT_ofany kmd Jot^ *^^^ 

These also are different from one another; for 
that of parent for child is not the same as that of 
ruler for subject, nor even that of father for son the 
same as that of son for father, nor that of man for 
woman the same as that of woman for man. For 
each of t hese cl asses has a different excellence and a 
different function, and the grounds of their affection 
are differen t ; therefore their love and their friendship 
also are different. What each does for the other, then, 



is not the same, nor should they expect it to be the 
same ; but when children give to their parents what 
they owe to those who begat them, and parents give 
to their sons what they owe to their children, then 
such friendship wiU be lasting, and what it ought 
to be. But in^all__friendships based on inequality, 
the love on either side should be proportional — I 
mean that the better of the two (and the more useful, 



V- 



266 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF AKISTOTLB. [B«. VIII. 

and BO on in each case) should receive more love than \ 
he gives; for when love is proportioned to de sert, 
then there is established a sort of eq uality^ vhich 
seems tobe a n^essary condition of friendship. 

But there seems to be a difference between the 3 
equality that prevails in the sphere of justice and 
that which prevails in friendship : for in the sph ere 
of justice the-primary Rftnse of /'e qual'* ror_ [[jair/' 
Jcrov] is "proportionate to merit/* and "equal_jn 
quantity" is only the secondary sen^ Jibut m friend- 
ship "equal in quantity" is the primary, and "pro- 
portionate to merit" the secondary sense.* 

This is plainly seen in cases where there comes to 4 
be a great distance between the persons in virtue, or 
vice, or wealth, or in any other respect ; for they no 
longer are, nor expect to be, friends. It is most 
plainly seen in the case of the gods ; for they have 
the greatest superiority in all good things. But it is 
seen also in the case of princes ; for here also those 
who are greatly inferior do not claim their friend- 
ship ; nor do people of no consideration expect to be 
friends with the best and wisest in the state. It is 5 
impossible accurately to determine the limits within 
which friendship may subsist in such cases: many 
things may be taken away, and it may remain ; but 

* The general rule of jnstice is that what different people re- 
ceive is different, being proportionate to their respective merits (rh 
/COT* i|(oi/ Xaovt or Mrris K6y(cv : c/. V. 8, 6, 5, 6 and 17) ; in exceptional 
cases, when the merits of the persons are the same, what they receive 
is eqnal {rh Kar* ii^lay becomes rh Karh, Tocrhv Xaov). Bnt friendship 
in the primary sense is friendship between equals, so that the gfeneral 
mle here is that both give and take equal amounts of love, etc. ; in 
the exceptional case of inequality between the persons, the amounts 
must be proportionate* 



7, 3-8, 2.] PRIENDSHIP OB LOVE. 267 

again, if a person be very far removed, as Qod is, it 
can no longer be. 

6 This has suggested the objection that, after all, a 
friend does not wish his friend the greatest of aU 
goods, that he should become a god; for then he 
would lose a friend — that is, a good ; for a friend is a 
good thing. If then we were right in saying that a 
friend wishes good to his friend for his (the friend's) 
saJke, we must add, " the friend remaining what he 
is: '* so far ad is compatible with his being a man, he 
will wish him the greatest good — but perhaps not 
everything that is goodT; for every man wishes good 

I most of all to himself. 

1 8. Most people seem, from a desire for honour, to (^ 

* * • — ami. 

wish to be loved rather than to love, and on this '«»*• 
account most men are fond of flatterers ; for a flatterer 
is an inferior friend, or pretends to be so and to love 
more than he is loved: but being loved is thought to 
come near to being honoured, and that most mei 
strive for, 

2 But they seem to desire honour not for its own 
sake, but accidentally : it is expectation that makes 
most men delight in being honoured by those in 
authority ; for they hope to get from them anything 
they may want : they delight in this honour, there- 
fore, as a token of good things to come. On the 
other hand, those who desire the honour or respect of 
good men and men who know, are anxious to confirm 
th^ir own opinion of themselves ; they rejoice, thereA 
fore, in the assurance of their worth which they 
gain from confidence in the judgment of those who 
declare it. 



268 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. Vllt. 

But men delight in being loved for its own sake ; 
wherefore it would seem that being loved is better 
than being honoured, and that friendship is desirable 
for its own sake. 

Friendship, however, seems to lie in the loving, 3 
rather than in the being loved. This is shown by the 
delight that mothers take in loving ; for some give 
their children to others to rear, and love them since 
they know them, but do not look for love in return, 
if it be impossible to have both, being content to see 
their children doing well, and loving them, though 
they receive from them, in their ignorance, nothing of 
. what is due to a mother. 
\/ , Since friendship Ues more in loving [than in being 4 
loved], and since we praise those who love their 
friends, it would seem that the virtue of a friend is 
to love, so that when people love each other in pro- 
\ portion to their worth, they are lasting friends, and 
theirs is a lasting friendship. 

This is also the way in which persons who are 5 
unequal can be most truly friends ; for thus they will 
make themselves equal : but equality and similarity 
tend to friendship, and most of all the similarity of 
"^ those who resemble each other in virtue; for such 
men, being little liable to change, continue as they 
were in themselves and to one another, and do not 
ask anything unworthy of one another, or do any- 
thing unworthy for one another — ^nay, rather restrain 
one another from anything of the sort ; for it is charac- 
teristic of a good man neither to go wrong himself, 
nor to let his friend go wrong. 

Bad men on the other hand [as friends] have no 



8, 3-9, 1.] FBIENDSHIP OR LOVE. 269 

stability : for they do not even continue like them- 
selves; but for a short space they become friends, 
rejoicing in each other's wickedness. 

Those, however, who are useful and agreeable to 
one another continue friends longer, i.e. so long as 
they continue to furnish pleasure or profit. 

The friendship whose motive is utility seems, more 
than any other kind, to be a union of opposites, as of 
rich and poor, ignorant and learned ; for when a man 
wants a thing, in his desire to get it he will give 
something else in exchange. And perhaps we might 
include the lover and his beloved, the beautiful and 
the ugly person, in this class. And this is the 
reason why lovers often make themselves ridiculous 
by claiming to be loved as they love; if they werej^ 
equally lovable they might perhaps claim it, but 
when there is nothing lovable about them the claim 
is absurd. 

But perhaps nothing desires its opposite as such 
but only accidentally, the desire being really for the 
mean which is between the two ; for this is good. 
For the dry, for instance, it is good not to become wet, 
but to come to the intermediate state, and so with the 
hot, and with the rest of these oppositea But we 
may dismiss these questions; for, indeed, they are 
somewhat foreign to our present purpose. 

9. It seems, as we said at the outset, that the sub- bv^ 
ject-matter and occasion of friendship and of justice ^un/<m 
are the same. Every community or association, it is ^ qfjustic) 
thought, gives some occasion for justice, and also for aretummPi 
friendship ; at least, people address as friends their ««^j/. 
partners in a voyage or campaign, and so on with 




270 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OP ABISTOTLB. [Bk. Vin. 

other associations. To what extent soever they are 
partners, to that extent is there occasion for friendship ; 
for to that extent is there occasion for justice. 

Moreover, " friends' goods are common property," 
says the proverb rightly ; for friendship implies com- 
munity. Brothers, indeed, and comrades have all 2 
things in common : other friends have certain definite 
things in common, some more and some less; for 
friendships also diflfer in degrea But what justice 
requires is also diflferent in different cases ; it does not 
require from parents towards children, for instance, 
the same as from brothers towards one another, nor 
from comrades the same as from fellow-citizens, and 
so on through the other kinds of friendship. 

Injustice also assumes different forms in these 3 
several relations, and increases according to the 
degree of friendship ; e.g. it is a grosser wrong to rob 
a comrade than a fellow-citizen, and to refuse help to 
a brother than to a stranger, and to strike one's father 
than to strike any other man. The claims of justice, 
in fact, are such as to increase as friendship increases, 
both having the.same field and Rowing paH pasm. 

But all kinds of association or community s^em to 4 
be, as it were, parts of the political community or 
association of citizens. For in all of them men join 
together with a view to some common interest, and 
in pursuit of some one or other of the things they 
need for their life. But the association of citizens 
seems both originally to have been instituted and to 
continue for the sake of common interests; for this 
is what legislators aim at, and that which is for the 
common interest of aU is said to be just. 



9, ^10, IJ FRIENDSHIP OB LOVE. 271 

5 Thus all other associations seem to aim at some 
particular advantage, e.g, sailors work together for a 
successful voyage, with a view to making money or 
something of that sort ; soldiers for a successful cam- 
paign, whether tiieir ulterior end be riches, or victory, 
or the founding of a state ; and so it is with the mem- 
bers of a tribe or a deme. Some associations, again; 
seem to have pleasure for their object, as when men 
join together for a feast or a club dinner; for the 
object here is feasting and company. But all these 
associations seem to be subordinate to the associa- 
tion of citizens ; for the association of citizens seems 
to have for its aim, not the interests of the moment, 
but the interests of our whole life, even when its 
members celebrate festivals and hold gatherings 
on such occasions, and render honour to the gods, 
and provide recreation and amusement for them- 
selves.* For the ancient festivals and assemblies 
seem to take place after the gathering in of the harvest, 
being of the nature of a dedication of the first-fruits, 
as it was at these seasons that people had most 
leisure. 

6 All associations, then, seem to be parts of the 
association of citizens; and the several kinds of w ,^ 
friendship will correspond to the several kinds of 
association. 

1 10. Now, of constitutions there are three kinds, and ?/ <^« ^»'«« 

forms oi 

an equal number of perverted forms, which are, so to consutuium 
speak, corruptions of these. Constitutions proper are 
kingly government and aristocracy ; and, thirdly, there 

* It is the institntion of the state whioh gives a permanent 
eignificance to these amusements of a daj. 






/ 

I 

I 



\ 



272 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk. VIIL 

is a form of government based upon an assessm ent p f 
property^ which should strictly be called timocracy, 
though most people are wont to speak of it as consti- 
tutional government simply. 

Of these, kingly ^gov^riment _is_.t-hft hftfftf »^<^ 
timocracy the worst. The perversion of kingly 
government is tyranny: both are monarchies, but 
there is a vast difference between them; for the tyrant 
seeks his own interest, the king seeks the interest of 
> his subjecta For he is not properly a kin g who is 

\ not self-sujS5cient and superabundantly furnished with 

all that is good ; such a man wants nothing more; his 
own advantage, then, will not be his aim, but that of 
his subjects. A man of another character than this 
could only be the sort of king that is chosen by 
lot.* 

Tyranny is the opposite of kingly rule, because 
the tyrant seeks his own good ; and of this govern- 
ment it is quite obvious f that it is the worst of all : 
we may add that the opposite of the best must be 
the worst. 

Kingly government degenerates into tyranny ; for 
tyranny is a vicious form of monarchy : the bad 
king, then, becomes a tyrant. 

Aristocracy degenerates into oligarchy through 
the vice of the rulers, who, instead of distributing 
public property and honours according to merit, take 
all or most of the good things for themselves, and 
give the offices always to the same people, setting 
the greatest store by wealth ; you have, then, a small 

* As tlie lipx»v PaffiXe^s at Athens. 

t Lit. " more evidont," sc. than that kingly rule is the best. 



\ 



k 



10, 2-5J FRIENDSHIP OB LOVK 273 

number of bad men in power, in place of the best 

ymen. 
Lastly, timo<aa(5L.dege.nerates into democracy: 
and -indeed they border closely upon each other ; for 
even timocracy is intended to be government by the ^ 
\ multitude, and all those who have the property 

qualification are equal, 
y Democracy is the least bad [of the corrupt forms'], 
for it is but a slight departure from the correspond- 
ing form of constitution. 

These, then, are the ways in which the several 
constitutions are most apt to change; for these are 
the directions in which the change is slightest, and 
encounters the least resistance. 

4 Likenesses of these forms of government and pat- 
terns of them, so to speak, may be found in families. 
For instance, the association of father and sons has 
the form of kingly rule ; for the father cares for his 
children. This, also, is the reason why Homer ad- 
dresses Zeus as father ; for kingly government aims 
at being a paternal government. But in Persia the 
association of father and son is tyrannical; for fathers 
there use their sons as slaves. The association of 
master aAd slave is also tyrannical; for it is the 
interest of the master that is secured by it. But 
this seems to be a legitimate kind of tyranny, while 
the Persian kind seems to be wrofag ; for different ^ 
beings require different kinds of government. 

5 The association of man and wife seems to be 
aristocratic : for the husband bears rule proportionate 
to his worth, i.e. he rules in those matters which are 
his province; but he entrusts to his wife those matters 

T 



274 NICOMAOHBAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLB. [Bk. VIIL , 

that properly belong to her. But when the man 
lords it in aU things, he perverts this relation into 
an oligarchioal one ; for he then takes rule where he 
is not entitled to it, and not only in those matters 
in which he is better. Sometimes, on the other 
hand, the wife rules because she is an heiress. In 
these cases authority is not proportionate to merit, 
but is given on the ground of wealth and influence, 
^ust as in oligarchies. 

The association of brothers resembles a timocracy; 6 
for they are equal except in so far as they differ in 
age. On this account, if they differ very widely in 
age, their friendship can no longer be a brotherly 
friendship. 

A democratic form of association is chiefly found 
in those households which have no master (for there 
\ all are on a footing of equality), or where the head 
of the house is weak, and every one does what he 
likes. 
ofthec<>r- 11. In each of these forms of government friend- i 
ft^^f^ ship has place to the same extent as justice. In the 
^ ^* first place, the king shows his friendship for his 
subjects * by transcendent benefits ; for he does good 
to his subjects, seeing that he is good, and tends them 
with a view to their welfare, as a shepherd tends his 
sheep, — whence Homer calls Agamemnon "shepherd 
of peoples." 4.UQ- ' '0>-^ U*^i ? 

The friendship of a father fcr his child is of a 2 
similar kind, though the benefits conferred are still 
greater. For the father is the author of the child's 
existence, which seems the greatest of aU benefits, 

• Scarcely consistent with 7, 4; but ef, 7, U 



10, 6-11, 6.J FRIENDSHIP OR LOVE. 275 

and of his nurture and education; and we also 
ascribe these to our forefathers generally : and thus 
it is in accordance with nature that fathers shoiddJ^ 
rule their children, forefathers their descendants, 
kings their subjects. 

3 These fiiendships involve the superiority of one 
side to the other ; and on this account parents receive 
honour as well [as service].* Moreover, what justice 
requires here is not the same on both sides, but that 

/ I which is proportionate to their worth ; for this is the 
' rule of fiiendship also [as well as of justice]. 

4 The friendship, again, of man and wife is the same 
as that which has place in an aristocracy ; for both 
benefit in proportion to their merit, the better getting 
more good, and each what is fitting ; but this is the 
rule of justice also. 

6 The friendship of brothers resembles that of com- 
rades, for they are equal and of like age ; but those 
with whom that is the case for the most part have 
the same feelings and character. And the friendship 
in a timocracy is of the same type as this; for the 
citizens here wish to be equal and fair ; so they take 
office in turn, and share it equally : their friendship, 
then, will follow the same rule, 

6 In the corrupt forms, as there is but little room 

for justice, so there is but little room for fiiendship, 

and least of all in the worst ; in a tyranny there is 

I little or no friendship. For where ruler and subject 

have nothing in common, there cannot be any friend- 

* We pay taxes to the king, and tend our parents in their old 
age ; but, as this is no adequate repayment of what they have done 
for ms, we owe them honour besides. 



276 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. Vni. 

ship, any more than there can be any justice. But 
here the relation is like that of a workman to his 
tools, or of the soul to the body, or of master to slave. 
The tools and the body and the slave are all benefited 
by those who use them; but our relations with in- 
animate objects do not admit of friendship or justice ; 
nor our relations with a horse or an ox; nor our 
relations with a slave as such. For there is nothing 
in common between master and slave. The slave is 
/a living tool ; the tool is a lifeless slave. As a slave, 
' then, his master's relations with him do not admit 
of friendship, but as a man they may: for there 
seems to be room for some kind of justice in the 
relations of any man to any one that can participate 
in law and contract, — and if so, then for some kind of 
friendship, so far, that is to say, as he deserves the 
name man. 

/ And so friendships and justice are found to some 

small extent even in tyrannies, but to a greater 

extent in democracies than in any other of the 

corrupt forms; for there the citizens, being equal, 

have many things in common. 

%S1mx f ^^* ^^ friendship, as we have already said, implies 

^•Mmen and associatiou ! but wc mav separate from the rest the 

friendship of kinsmen and that of comrades. The 

friendships of fellow-citizens, of fellow-tribesmen, of 

fellow-sailors, eta, seem, as opposed to these, to have 

more to do with association; for they appear to be 

founded upon some sort of compact. The friendship 

of host and guest might also be included in this class. 

Kinsmen's friendship seems to include several 

species, but to be dependent in aU its forms upon the 



11, 7-12, 4] FBIENDSHIP OR LOVE. 277 

friendship of parent and child. For parents love 
their children as part of themselves; children love 
their parents as the source of their being. But 
parents know their children better than the children 
know that these are their parents, and that which gives 
birth is more closely attached to that which proceeds 
from it, than the oflFspring is to that which gave it 
life : for that which proceeds from us belongs to us, 
as a tooth or a hair, or anything of that sort, to its 
owner ; but we do not belong to it at all, or belong 
to it in a less degree. 

Again, there is a difference in respect of time; 
for parents love their offspring from the moment of 
their birth, but children love their parents only after 
the lapse of time, when they have acquired under- 
standing or sense. 

These considerations also show why mothers love 

/ their children more than fathers do. 

8 Parents, then, love their children as themselves 

(for what proceeds from them is as it were a second 

self when it is severed), but children love their parents 

as the source of their being, and brothers love each 

\ other because they proceed from the same source : for 

the identity of their relation to this source constitutes 

an identity between them; so that they say that 

they are of the same blood and stock, etc. And so 

they are in a way identical, though they are separate 

persons, 

4 But friendship between brothers is greatly ftur- 

thered by common nurture and similarity of age ; for 

those of the same age naturally love one another, as 

the saying is, and those who are used to one another 






/ 



278 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLB. [Bk. Vin. 

naturally make comrades of one anotlier, so that the 
friendship of brothers comes to resemble that of 
comrades. 

Cousins and other kinsfolk become attached to^\ 
each other for the same reason — I mean because they ^ 
come of the same stock. But the attachment is more 
or less close according to the nearness or remoteness 
of the founder of the family. ' 

The friendship of children for their parents (like 5 
that of men for the gods) is friendship for what is 
good and superior to themselves, as the source of the 
greatest benefits, namely, of their life and nurture, 
and their education from their birth upwards. 

Friendship of this kind brings with it more, both 6 
of pleasure and profit, than that of strangers, in pro- 
portion as there is more community of life. 

The friendship of brothers has all the character- 
istics of the friendship of comrades, and has them in 
a greater degree (provided they are good and generally 
resemble one another) inasmuch as they belong more 
to one another and love each other from their birth 
up, and have more similarity of character, as being 
of the same stock and brought up together and 
educated alike ; moreover, they have had the longest 
and the surest experience of one another. 

In all other kinsmen's friendships the same ele- 7 
ments will be found in proportion to the relationship, 
r The friendship of man and wife seems to be 
natural ; for human beings are by nature more apt to 
join together in couples than to form civil societies, 
inasmuch as the family is prior in time to the state 
and more indispensable, and the propagation of the 



/ 



12, 5-13, Ij PBIENDSHIP OR LOVE. 279 

species is a more fundamental characteristic of animal 
existence. The other animals associate for this purpose 
alone, but man and wife live together not merely for 
the begetting of children, but also to satisfy the needs 
of their life : for the functions of the man and the 
woman are clearly divided and distinct the one from 
the other ; they supply each other's wants, therefore, 
both contributing to the common stock. And so this 
sort of friendship is thought to bring with it both 
pleasure and profit* But it will be based on virtue, 
too, if they be good ; for each sex has its own virtue, 
and both will rejoice in that which is of like nature. 

Children also seem to be a bond that knits man 
and_jwife together (which is a reason why childless 
unions are more quickly dissolved) ; for children are 
a good which both have in common, but that which 
people have in common holds them together. 

8 To ask on what terms a man should live with his 
wife, and generally friend with friend, seems the same 
as to ask what justice requires in these cases; for 
what is required of a man towards his friend is 
difierent from what is required of him towards a 
stranger, a comrade, or a travelling companion. 

1 13^ There are three kinds of friendship, as we said of the t 
at the outset, and in each kind there are both equal dimige 
and unequal friendships ; I mean that sometimes two ^Hc^w 
equally good persons make friends, and sometimes a/riend«i 
better and a worse (and so with those who are 
pleasant to one another, and with those who are 
friends with a view to profit) — eflecting equality by 
the services they exchange, even though they are 
themselves difierent. 




280 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. Vin. 

{Now, those who are equal should effect equality 
by loving one another, etc., equally, but those who are 
unequal should effect equality by making what each 
renders proportionate to the greater or less merit o, 
the other. 
\J But accusations and reproaches arise solely or 

mostly in friendships whose motive is profit, as wi 
should expect. For those whose friendship istJbSsed 
on virtue are eager to do good to each other ; for this 
is the office of virtue and friendship. And between 
people who are thus vieing with one another no 
accusations or quarrels can arise ; for a man cannot 
be embittered against one who loves him and does 
him a service, but, if he be of a gracious nature, 
requites him with a like service. But the superior 
wiU not reproach his friend, since he gets what he 
desires; * for each desires what is good. 
u Such quarrels, again, are not apt to arise in fidend- 3 

ships whose motive is pleasure ; for both get at the 
same time that which they desire, if they delight in 
each other's company ; but if one were to accuse the 
other for not being agreeable to him, he would make 
himself ridiculous, seeing that he was under no 
compulsion to associate with him. 
V . But the friendship whose motive is utility is 4 
fruitful in accusations ; for as the friends here use 
each other solely with a view to their own advantage, 
each always wants the larger share and thinks he has 
less than his due, and reproaches the other with not 
doing for him so much as he requires and deserves ; 
though, in truth, it is impossible for the one who 

* For lie desires the good of his friend. 



13, 2-8.] FRIENDSHIP OR LOVE. 281 

is doing a service to supply all that the other 
wants. 
6 As the rules of justice are twofold, the unwritten 
and those that are set down in laws, so the friendship 
whose motive is profit is of two kinds — one resting on 
disposition, the other on contract. And accusations 
are most apt to arise when the relation is understood 
in one sense at the commencement, and in the other 
sense at the conclusion. 

6 That which rests on contract is that in which 
there are specified conditions, and it is of two kinds : 
one is purely commercial, on the principle of cash 
payments ; the other is less exacting in point of time, 
though in it also there is a specified quid pro quo. 

In the latter case, what is due is evident and can- 
not be disputed, but there is an element of fiiendliness 
in the deferment of payment; for which reason, in 
some states, there is no recovery by law in such cases, 
but it is held that when a man has given credit he 
must take the consequences. 

7 That which rests on disposition has no specified 
conditions, but one gives another presents (or what- 
ever else it may be) as a friend. But afterwards he 
claims as much or more in return, regarding what he 

8 gave not as a gift, but as a loan. And thus, wishing 
to terminate the relation in a diflferent spirit from 
that in which he entered upon it, he will accuse the 
other.* And this is apt to happen because all or nearly 

* In the papers of October 8, 1880, a suit is reported in which A 
tries in vain to recover from B certain goods given during court- 
ship, — according to B as presents, according to A lirl ^tois, viz, 
_ 2 on condition of marriage, which condition had not been fulfilled. 



282 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk, VHI. 

all men, though they wish for what is noble, choose 
what is profitable ; and while it is noble to do a good 
service without expecting a return, it is profitable to 
receive a benefit. 

In such cases, then, we should, if we have the 9 
power, make an equivalent return for benefits_rfir 
ceived, even if there be no necessity to do so ; for we 
must not treat a man as a friend if he does_not wish 
it. We shoidd consider that we made a mistake 
at the beginning, and received a benefit from a person 
from whom we ought not to have accepted it — ^for he 
was not a friend and did not act disinterestedly — 
and so we ought to terminate the relation in the 
same way as if we had received a service for a stipu- 
lated consideration. But the stipulation would only 
be to repay if we have the power ; if we have it not, 
even the donor would not claim repayment : so we 
may fairly say that we should repay if we have the 
power. 

But we ought at the outset carefully to consider 
who it is that is doing us a service, and on what 
understanding, so that we may accept it on that 
imderstanding or else reject it. 

It is a debatable question whether the requital lo 
is to be measured by, and to be made proportionate 
to, the value of the service to the recipient or to 
the benefactor. For the recipients are apt to say 
that they received what was but a small matter to 
their benefactors, and what they might just as well 
have got from others, depreciating the service done 
them ; but the others, on the contrary, are apt to say 
that what they gave was the best they had, and what 



13, 9-14, IJ FBIENDSHIP OB LOVE. 283 

could not be got from any one else, and that it was 
given in a time of danger or on some other pressing 
occasion. 

Perhaps we may say that, if the friendship have 
profit for its motive, the benefit received should be 
taken as the measure ; for it is the recipient who asks 
a service, which the other renders in expectation of an 
equal service in return : the amount of the assistance 
rendered, then, is determined by the extent to which 
the former is benefited, and he shoidd repay as much 
as he received, or even more; for that would be the 
nobler course. 

In friendships based on virtue, on the other hand, 
such accusations do not occur, but it woidd seem that 
the measure of the service is the purpose of him who 
does it ; for virtue and moral character are determined 
by purpose. 

14. Quarrels occur also in unequal friendships; for oftheiaiM 
sometimes each claims the larger share, but when this/ri^Mjw. 
happens the friendship is dissolved. For instance, the 
better of the two thinks he ought to have the larger 
share ; " the good man's share is larger," he says •. 
the more useful of the two makes the same claim ; " it 
is allowed," he says, " that a useless person should not 
share equally; for friendship degenerates into gra- 
tuitous service imless that which each receives from 
the friendship be proportionate to the value of what 
he does." For such people fancy that the same rule 
should hold in friendship as in a commercial partner- 
ship, where those who put in more take a larger 
share. 

Thft needy man and the inferior man argue in the 



284 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk. VIH. 

contrary way ; " it is the office of a good friend," they 
say, " to help you when you are in need ; for what is 
the use of being friends with a good man or a 
powerful man, if you are to get nothing by it ? '* 

It seems that the claims of both are right, and 2 
that each ought to receive a larger share than the 
other, but not of the same things — ^the superior more 
honour, the needy man more profit ; for honour is the 
tribute due to virtue and benevolence, while want 
receives its due succour in the pecuniary gain. 

This seems to be recognized in constitutions too : 3 
no hono ur is paid to him who contributes nothing to 
the common stock of good; the common stock is 
distributed among those who benefit the community, 
and of this common stock honoiir is a part. For he 
who makes money out of the community must not 
expect to be honoured by the community also ; and 
no one is content to receive a smaller share in every- 
thing. To him, then, who spends money on public 
objects we pay due honour, and money to him whose 
services can be paid in money; for, by giving to each 
what is in proportion to his merit, equality is eflFected 
and friendship preserved, as we said before. 

The same principles, then, must regulate the inter- 
course of individuals who are unequal ; and he who is 
benefited by another in his purse or in his character, 
must give honour in return, making repayment in 
that which he can command. For friendship exacts 
what is possible rather than what is due : what is 
due is sometimes impossible, as, for instance, in the 
case of the honour due to the gods and to parents ; 
for no one coidd Qver pay all his deb^ to them ; but 



14, 2, 3.] FRIENDSHIP OB LOVE. 285 

he who gives them such service as he can command 
is held to fulfil his obligation. 

For this reason it would seem that a man may 
not disown his father, though a father may disown 
his son ; for he who owes must pay : but whatever 
a son may do he can never make a full return for 
what he has received, so that he is always in debt. 
But the creditor is at liberty to cast off the debtor ; 
a father, therefore, is at liberty to cast off his son. 
But, at the same time, it is not likely that any 
one would ever disown a son, unless he were a very 
great scoundrel ; for, natural affection apart, it is but 
human not to thrust away the support that a son 
would give. But to the son, if he be a scoundrel, 
assisting his father is a thing that he wishes to avoid, 
or at least is not eager to undertake ; for the gene- 
rality of men wish to receive benefits, but avoid 
doing them as unprofitable. So much, then, for these 
questions. 



BOOK IX 
FRIENDSHIP OR LOVE — Continued. 

o{^^^^%m ^' ^^ ^^ dissimilar friendshigs * it is proportionate 1 
f!-^dshi^^ exchange that maintains equalit y and preserves the 
friendship (as we have already said), just^ as fiTIQie 
association of citizens, where the shoemaker, in~ex- 
change for his shoes, receives some return propor- 
tionate to his desert, and so on with the weaver and 
the rest. 

Now, in these latter cases, a common measure 2 
is supplied by money; money is the standard to 
which everything is referred, and by which it is 
measured. 

In sentimental friendships, on the other hand, the 
lover sometimes complains that while he loves ex- 
cessively he gets no love in return, although, maybe, 
there is nothing lovable about him ; often the beloved 
complains that whereas the other used to promise 
eveiything, he now performs nothing. 

Complaints of this sort are wont to arise when, 3 
pleasure being the motive of the friendship witihime 
person and profit with the other, they do not both get 
what they want. For the friendship, being based on 

* Where the two friends have different motives. 



1, 1-6.] FEIENDSHIP OR LOVE. 287 

these motives, is dissolved whenever they fail to obtain 
that for the sake of which they made friends ; for it 
was not the other's self that each loved, but only 
something which he had, and which is not apt to 
endure; for which reason these friendships also are 
not apt to endure. But friendship based on character, 
being pure, is likely to last, as we said. 
~^ Sometimes, again, friends quarrel when they find 
they are getting something different from what they 
want ; for failing to get what you want is like getting 
nothing. This may be illustrated by the story of the 
harper: a man promised him that the better he 
played, the more he should receive; but when, as 
dawn drew near, the harper claimed the fulfilment 
of his promise, the other replied that he had already 
paid him pleasure * for pleasure. Now, if this was 
what both wished, there would be nothing more to 
say : but if the one wanted pleasure and the other 
profit, and the one has what he wants, while the 
other has not, the bargain will not be fairly carried 
out; for it is what a man happens to want that he 
sets his heart on, and consents for the sake of it to 
render this particular service. 

But whose bu siness is it to fix the value of the 
service ? his who first gives, or rather, iia who first 
receives? — ^for he who first gives seems to leave it 
to the other. This, they say, was the custom of 
Protagoras : when he had been giving lessons in any 
subject, he used to tell his pupil to estiipiate the value 
of the knowledge he "had acquired, and so much he 
would take. 

^.^^ ♦ Viz. the pleasure of anticipation. 



288 NICOMACHBAN ETfflOS OF ABISTOtLK. [Bk. K. 

Some^ however, think the rule shotdd be, "Let a 6 
friend be content with his stated wage." * 

But if a man, after being paid in advance, fulfils 
none of his engagements, because he had promised 
more than he could perform, he is rightly held charge- 
able; for he does not fulfil his contract. But the 7 
sophists, perhaps, are compelled to adopt this plan [of 
payment in advance]; for otherwise no one would 
give anything for what they know. 

He, then, who fails to do that for which he has 
already been paid, Is rightly chargeable. But wh en 
there i s no express agreement about the service 
rende red, (a) when one voluntarily helps another for 
that q tiier's sake, no accusation can arise, as we said : 
for^this is the guajbiLre of friendship^ based o n vut ue. 
The return must here be regulated by the purpose 
of him who renders the first service ; for it is purpose 
that makes both friend and virtue. The same rule 
would seem to apply also to the relations of a philo- 
sopher and his disciples; for desert cannot here be 
measured in money, and no honour that could be paid 
him would be an adequate return ; but, nevertheless, 
as in our relations to gods and parents, the possible 
is accepted as sufficient, (b) If, however, the first 8 
gift has been made, not in this spirit, but on the under- 
standing that there shall be some return, the return 
should, if possible, be such as both deem proportionate 
to desert: but if this cannot be, it would seem to 
be not only necessary, but just, that the recipient of 
the first benefit should assess it ; for whatever be the 
amount of the advantage he has received, or whatever 

* fiiadhs 8* &v9p\ <f>l\q> €iprifi4yos UpKios tarco. — Hesiod. 



1, 6-2, 2.1 FRIENDSHIP OB LOVE. 289 

he would have been willing to give for the pleasure, 
the other, in receiving the same amount, will receive 
as much as is due from him. For even in sales this 

9 is plainly what takes place ; and in some states there 
is no recovery by law in voluntary contracts, as it 
is held that when you have given a man credit, you 
must conclude your bargain with him in the same 
spirit in which you began it. It is held to be fairer J 
that the service should be valued by him who is/ 
trusted than by him who trusts. For most things 
are differently valued by those who have them and 
by those who wish to get them : what belongs to us, 
and what we give away, always seems very precious 
to us. Nevertheless, the return to be made must be 
measured by the value which is set upon the service 
by the receiver. But j>erha ps he ought to put it, not 
at what it seems to be worth when he has got it, but 
atihe value Te set upon it before he had it. 

1 2. There are some further questions that here o/m 
suggest themselves, such as whether the father's duOM, 
claims to service ought to be unlimited, and the son 
should obey him in everything, or whether in sick- 
ness he should obey the physician, and in the election 
of a general should choose him who is skilled in 
war ; and, similarly, whether one ought to help one's 
friend rather than a good man, and repay a benefactor 

^ rather than make a present to a comrade, if one 
cannot do both. 

•2 We may, perhaps, say that to lay down precise 
rules for all such cases is scarcely possible ; for the 
different cases differ in all sorts of ways, according 
to the importance or unimportance, the nobility or 

u 



290 NIOOMAGHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bx.IZ. 

necessity of the act. But it is tolerably evident that 3 
no single person's claims can override all others ; and 
that, as a gene ral rule^we ought to repay benefits 
received before we do a favour to a c6inra3e-----just as, 
if we had borrowed money, we ought to pay ou r 
creditors before we make presents to our comrades. 

But it may be that even this rule wHl ioof hold 4 
good in all cases; for instance, if a man has been 
ransomed &om a band of brigands, ought he in turn 
to ransom his ransomer, whoever he may be, or repay 
him when he demands it, even though he be not 
captured, in preference to ransoming his father ? For 
it would seem that a man ought to ransom his father 
even before himself. 

As we said then, g enerallv spe akings we should 6 
repay what we owe : but if giving [instead of repay- 
ing] be more noble or meet a more pressing need, it 
is right to incline in this direction ; for sometimes it 
is not even fair to repay the original service, e,g, 
when one man has helped another, knowing him 
to be a good man, while the latter in repaying him 
would be helping one whom he believes to be a bad 
man. And so a man is sometimes not boimd to lend 
in turn to one who has lent him money: A may 
have lent to B in full expectation of being repaid, 
as B is an honourable man; but B may have no 
hope of being repaid by A, who is a rascal If this 
be the real state of the case, the demand for a loan 
in return is not fair ; but even if the facts be other- 
wise, yet, if they think thus of each other, their con- 
duct would be regarded as natural 

As we have often said, statements concerning G 



2, 3-9.1 FRIENDSHIP OB LOVE. 291 

human affections and actions must share the in- 
definiteness of their subject. 

It is tolerably plain^ then^ that^ on the one hand, 
the claims of aU men are not the same^ but that, on 
the other hand, the father's claims do not override all 
others, just as^Zeus does not receive all our sacrifices; 

7 the daims of parents, brothers, comrades, and bene- 
factors are all different, and to each must be rendered 

- that which is his own and his due. 

And this is the way in which men appear to act : 
to a wedding they invite their kinsfolk; for they 
have a share in the family, and therefore in all acts 
relating thereto : and for the same reason it is held 
that kinsfolk have more claim than any others to be 
invited to funerals. 

8 Parents would seem to have a special claim upon 
us for sustenance, as we owe it them, and as it is 
nobler to preserve the life of those to whom we are 
indebted for our own than to preserve ourselves. 

Honour, also, we should pay to our parents, as to 
the gods ; but not aU honour : for the honour due 
to a father is not the same as that due to a mother ; A 
nor do we owe them the honour due to a wise man 
or a good general, but that which is due to a father 
and that which is due to a mother. 

9 To all our elders, again, we should pay the honour 
due to their age, by rising up at their approach and 
by giving them the place of honour at the table, and 
so forth. But between comrades and brothers there 
should be freedom of speech and community in every- 
thing. And to kinsfolk and fellow-tribesmen and 
fellow-citizens^ and aU other persons^ we should 



292 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. IXi 

always try to give their due, and to discriminate 
what properly belongs to each, according to the close- 
ness of his connection with us, and his goodness or 
usefulness. When the persons are of one kind this 10 
discrimination is comparatively easy, but when they 
are of different kinds it is more difficult. We must 
not, however, on this account shirk the difficulty, but 
must distinguish as best as we can. 
fthe 3. Another difficult question is, whether we should l 

'friend- or shouM uot bre ak off friendship with those who 
have ceased to be wliat they were. 

We may, perhaps, say that those whose friendship 
is based on profit or pleasure naturally part when 
V^hese cease ; for it was these that they loved : when 
these are gone, therefore, it is to be expected that the 
ve goes too. But complaints would be likely to 
arise if a man who loved another for profit or plea- 
sure's sake pretended to love him for his character ; 
for, as we said at the outset, quarrels between friends 
very frequently arise from a difference between the 
real and the supposed motives of the friendship. If, 2 
then, a man deceives himself, and supposes that he 
is beloved for his character, though the other's be- 
haviour gives no groimd for the supposition, he has 
only himself to blame ; but if he is deceived by the 
other's pretence, then there is a fair ground of com- 
plaint against such an impostor, even more than 
against those who counterfeit the coinage, inasmuch 
as it is a more precious thing that is tampered with. 

But if a man admit another to his friendship as 3 
a good man, and he becomes and shows himself to be 
a bad man, is he still to be loved ? Perhaps we may 




2, lOS, 4.] FBIENDSHIP OE LOYE. 293 

answer that it is inipossible/ as it_is not everything 
that is lovable, but only the goodT) A bad man, then, 
is not lovable, and ought not to be loved: for we 
ought not to love what is bad, nor to make ourselves 
like what is worthless ; but, as we said before, it is 
like that makes friends with like. 

Is the friendship, then, to be immediately broken 
off ? Perhaps not in all cases, but only in the case 
of those who are incurably bad : when their reforma- 
tion is possible, we are more bound to help them 
in their character than their fortune, inasmuch as 
character is a nobler thing, and has more to do with 

^j^mendship than fortune has. But a man who with- 
draws his friendship in such a case, would seem to do 
nothing unnatural ; for it was not with such a man 
that he made friends : his friend has become another 
man, and as he cannot restore him, he stands aloof 
from him. 

4 But suppose that the one remains what he was 
while the other gets better and becomes far superior 
in vi rtue : is the latter still to treat the former as a 
friend ? Perhaps it is hardly possible that he should 
do so. We see this most plainly if the interval be- 
tween the two bQ very considerable. Take, for instance, 
a boyish friendship : if one of the two remains a child 
in understanding, while the other has become a man 
in the fullest sense of the word, how can they any 
longer be friends, now that the things that will please 
them, and the sources of their joys and sorrows^ are 
no longer the same ? for not even in regard to each 
other's character will their tastes agree, and without 
this, we found, people cannot be friends, since they 



291 NIGOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk-IX. 

cannot live together. (But this point has been 
already discussed.) 

Shall we, then, simply say that the latter should 5 
regard the former as no more a stranger than if he 
had never been his friend ? Perhaps we may go 
further than this, and say that he should not entirely 
forget their former intercourse, and that just as w€ 
hold that we ought to serve friends before strangers, 
so former friends have some claims upon us on the 
ground of past friendship, unless extraordinary 
depravity were the cause of our parting. 
A man*» 4. Friendly relations to others, and all the charac- 1 

hit/Heni teristics by which Mendship is defined, seem to be 
relation to derfvcd from our relations towards ourselves. A 
friend is sometimes described as one who wishes and 
does to another what is good or seems good for that 
other's sake, or as one who wishes his friend to 
exist and to live for his (the friend's) sake. (This 
is what mothers feel towards their children, and 
what friends who have had a difference feel for one 
another.) Others describe a friend as one who lives 
with another and chooses what he chooses, or as one 
who sympathizes with the griefs and joys of his 
friend. (This, also, is especially the case with 
mothers.) And, similarly, friendship is usually de- 
fined by some one or other of these characteristics. 

Now, every one of these characteristics we find 2 
in the good man's relations to himself, and in other 
men so far as they suppose themselves to be good. 
(For it seems, as we have said, that virtue and the 
good man are in everything the standard.) 

The good man is of one mind with himself, and 8 



S, 5-4, «J FBIENDSmP OE LOVEL 295 

desires the same tilings with all his soul^ and wishes 
for himself what both is and seems good, and does 
that (for it is characteristic of him to work out that 
which is good) for his own sake — for the sake, that 
is to say, of the rational part of him, which seems to 

4 be a man's self And he wishes his self to live and 
be jareserved, and especially that part of his self by 
which he thinks : for existence is good to the good 
man ; and every man wishes for himself that which 
is good. But no one desires that, as he becomes 
another man [i.e, as he grows older], that other self 
should be in all respects the same as his present self 
(With God, indeed, this may be, for God already is 
in complete possession of the good ; but that is only 
as being what he is [not man, but God].) But his 
reason would seem to be a man's self, or, at least, 
to be so in a truer sense than any other of his faculties. 

6 Such a man also wishes to live with himself; for 
his own_company is pleasant to him. The memory 
of his past life is sweet, and for the future he has 
good hopes ; and such hopes are pleasant. His mind, 
moreover, is well stored with matter for contem- 
plation : and he sympathizes with himself in sorrow 
and in joy ; for at all seasons the same things give 
him pain and pleasure, not this thing now, and then 
another thing, — for he is, so to speak, not apt to 
change his blind. 

Since, then, all these characteristics are found in 
the good man's relations to himself, and since his 
relations to his friend are the same as his relations to \ 
himself (fbr_his friend is his second self), friendship \ 
is described by one or other of these characteristics. 



296 NICX)MACHEAK ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. CBk.IX. 

and tiiose are called friends in whom these character- 
istics are found. 

The question whether friendship towards one's seK 6 
is or is not possible may be dismissed at present ; but 
that it is possible so far as one has two or more 
selves would seem to follow from what has been 
aheady said, and also from the fact that the extreme 
of friendship for another is likened to friendship for 
one's self. 

But the characteristics we have mentioned appear 7 
to be foimd in the generality of men, though tibej^SC^ 
not good.* Perhaps we may say that so far as they 
are agreeable to themselves, and believe they are good, 
so far do they share these characteristics. People who 
are utterly worthless and impious never have them, nor 
do they even seem to have them. But we might almost 8 
say roundly that they are wanting in all who are not 
good ; for such men are not at one with themselves : 
they desire one thing while they wish another, as the 
incontinent do, for instance (for, instead of what they 
hold to be good, they choose what is pleasant though 
injurious). Others, again, through cowardice or lazi- 
.. ness, shrink from doing that which they believe is 
the best for them ; while those who have done many 
terrible things out of wickedness, hate life, and wish 
to get rid of it, and sometimes actually destroy them- 
selves. • 

Bad men try to find people with whom to spend 9 
their time, and eschew their own company ; for there 
is much that is painful in the past on which IHey 

* fpavKos here as elsewhere inolades aU yrho are not good, the 
incontinent as well as the vicioas. 



4, 6-5, 2.] PEIENDSHIP OB LOVE. 297 

look back and in the future to which they look 
forward when they are by themselves, but the 
company of others diverts them from these thoughts. 
As there is nothing lovable in them, they have no 
frienjjly feelings towards themselves. 

He who is not good, then, cannot sympathize with 
himself in joy or sorrow ; for his soul is divided against . 
itself: one part of him, by reason of its viciousness, is 
pained at being deprived of something, while another' 
part of him is pleased ; one part pulls this way, another 
that, tearing him to pieces, as it were, between themJ 
10 Or if it be impossible to be pained and pleased at the 
same time, yet. at any rate, after a short interval he 
is pained that he was pleased, and wishes that he had 
never partaken of this pleasure; for those who are 
not good are full of remorse. 
^^ Thus we may say roundly that he who is not 
good has no friendly feelings even for himself, as there 
is nothing lovable in him. If, then, to be in this state 
is utterly miserable, we ought to strain every nerve 
to avoid vice, and try to be good ; for thus we may 
be friendly disposed towards ourselves, and make 
friends with others. 

1 6. Well-wishing resembles, but is not the same as, Prund» 
friendship : for we may wish well to those who are wiuf^ 
unknown to us, and who are not aware that we wish 
them well; but there can be no friendship in such 
cases. But this we have already said. 

Neither is well-wishing the same as love; for it 
has none of the intense emotion and the desire which 
accompany love. 

2 Love, moreover, implies intimate acquaintance^ 



\ 



298 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF AEISTOTLE. LBk.IX. 

while wdl- wishing may spring up in a moment; it 
does so, for instance, when athletes are competing for 
a prize : we may wish well to a competitor, and be 
eager for his success, though we would not do any- 
thing to help him; for, as we said, we suddenly 
become well-wishers and ccmceive a sort of superficial 
affection in such casea 

The truth seems to be that well-wishin g is the 3 
germ of friendship, in the same way as pleasure 
in the sight of a person is the germ of love : Kr 
no one falls in love unless he is first pleased by 
visible beauty; but he who delights in the beauty 
of a person is not one whit in love on that account, 
unless he also feels the absence and desires the 
presence of that person. Just so it is impossible for 
people to be friends unless they first become well- 
wishers, but people who wish each other well are not 
a whit on that account friends ; for they merely wish 
good to those whose well-wishers they are, but would 
never help them in any enterprise, or put themselves 
out for them. One might say, then — extending the 
meaning of the term — ^that well-wishing is an un- 
developed friendship, which with time and intimate 
acquaintance may become friendship proper, — not 
that friendship whose motive is profit, nor that whose 
motive is pleasure ; for well-wishing is no element in 
them. He who has received a benefit does indeed 
give his good wishes in return to his benefactor, and 
it is but just that he should ; but he who wishes that 
another may prosper, in the hope of good things to be 
got by his means, does not seem really to wish well 
to the other, but rather to himself, just as he is not 



and 
unanim 



6, 3-6, 2.] FBIENPSHIP OB LOVB. 299 

really a &iend if he serves him with an eye to 
profit. 
i But, generally speaking, well-wishing is grounded 
upon some kind of excellence or goodness, and arises 
when a person seems to us beautiful or brave, or 
endowed with some other good quality, as we said in 
the case of the athletes. 

1 6, Unanimity [or unity of sentiment] also seems priendt. 
to be an element in friendship ; and this shows that 
it is not mere agreement in opinion, for that is 
possible even between .people who know nothing of 
each other. 

Nor do we apply the term to those who agree in 
judgment upon any kind of subject, 6.gr. upon astronomy 
(for being of one mind in these matters has nothing 
to do with friendship) ; but we say that unanimity 
prevails in a state when the citizens agree in their 
judgments about what is for the common interest, and 
choose the same course^ and carry out the decision 

2 of the community. It is with regard to practical 
matters, therefore, that people are said to be of one 
mind, especially with regard to matters of importance 
and things that may be given to both persons, or to all 
the persons concerned ; for instance, a state is said to 
be of one mind when all the citizens are agreed that 
the magistracies shall be elective, or that an alliance 
be made with Sparta, or that Fittacus be governor, 
Pittacus himself being willing to accept the office. 
But when each wishes the government for himself, 
like the brothers in the Fhoenissse of Euripides, then 
they are at discord: for being of one mind means 
that each not merely thinks of the same thing (what- 



300 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLB. [Bk. IX. 

ever it be), but thinks of it under the same con- 
ditions — ^as, for instance, if both the populace and the 
upper classes agree that the best men shall govern ; 
for thus they all get what they want. 

Unanimity, then, seems to be, as it is called, the 
kind of friendship that prevails in states ; for it has 
to do with what is for the common interest, and with 
things that have a considerable influence upon life. 

This kind of unanimity is found in good men; 3 
for they are of one mind with themselves and with 
each pther> standing, so to speak^^ always on the same 
ground : for the wishes of such people aro-Constant, 
and do not ebb and flow like the Euripus ; they wish 
what is just and for the common interest, and make 
united efforts to attain it. But people who are not 4 

fgood cannot be of one mind, just as they cannot be 
friends except for a little space or to a. slight extent, 
as they strive for more than their share of profit, 
but take less than their share of labours and public 
services: but every man, while wishing to do this 
himself, keeps a sharp eye upon his neighbour, and 
prevents him from doing it ; for if they are not thus 
on their guard, the community is ruined. The result 
is that they are at discord, striving to compel one 
another to do what is just, but not willing to do it 
themselves. 
% lene- 7. Bcnefactors seem to love those whom they have l 

ore than benefited more than those who have received benefits 
»ed. love those who have conferred them; and as this 
appears irrational, people seek for the cause of this 
phenomenon. 

Mobt people think the reason is that the one is in 



6, 3-7, 4 ] FEIENDSHIP OB LOVE. 301 

the position of a debtor, the other in the position of 

a creditor; and that, therefore, just as in the case 
of a loan the debtor wishes his creditor were out of 
the way, while the lender, on the other hand, is 
anxious that his debtor may be preserved, so here 
the benefactor desires the existence of him whom he 
has benefited in hopes of receiving favours in return, 
while the other is not at all anxious to repay. 

Epicharmus, indeed, might perhaps say that this 
is only the view of "those who have bad places 
at the play," * but it seems to be true to life ; for 
the generality of men have short memories, and are 
more eager to receive benefits than to confer them, 

2 But the real cause would seem to be something 
that lies deeper in the nature of things, and not like 
that which operates in the case of creditors : for the 
creditors have no real affection for their debtors, but 

^ only a wish that they may be preserved in order 
that they may repay ; but those who have conferred 
benefits have a real love and affection for those whom 
they have benefited, even though they are not, and 
are never likely to be, of any service. 

3 The same phenomenon may be observed in crafts- 
men ; for every craftsman loves the work of his own 
hands more than it would love him if it came to life. 
But perhaps poets carry it furthest; for they love 
their ovni poems to excess, and are as fond of them 
as if they were their children. 

4 Now, the case of the benefactors seems to resemble 
theirs; those whom they have benefited they have 
made, so to speak : that which they have made, then, 

* Epioharmus was a Sicilian dramatist. 



302 NICOMAOHBAN ETHICS OP ABISTOTLR [BK.IX. 

they love more than the work loves its maker. And 
the reason of this is that we all desire exi stenc e and 
love it : but it is in the exercise of our faculties, or in 
vthe realization of ourselves, that our existen ce lie s; 
for it lies in living and doiiig. But* that which 
"^fl. man makes is, in a way, a realization of his self; 
therefore he loves it, because he loves existence. 

But this is in accordance with the nature of 
things ; for it is a law of nature that what a thing 
is as yet potentially is exhibited in realization by 
that which it makes or does. 

Moreover, the manifestation of his action is beau- 6 
tiful to the benefactor, so that he delights in the 
person that makes it manifest ; but to him who has 
received the benefit there is nothing beautiful in the 
benefactor, but at the most something useful; and 
such an object is less pleasing and less lovable. 

Again, we take pleasure in realizing ourselves in 6 
the present, in hopes for the future, and in memories 
of the past ; but that in which we are realizing our- 
selves is the most pleasant, and likewise the most 
lovable. Now, for the benefactor what he has done 
endures (for that which is beautiful is lasting), while 
for him who has received the benefit the advantage 
soon passes away. t« 

Again, the memory of beautiful deeds is pleasant, 

of profitable actions not at all pleasant, or not so 

pleasant ; but with expectation the reverse seems to 

be the case. 

p Again, loving seems like doing something, being 

; loved like having something done to you. Those 

* Beading *Ey€pytl(f 8* 6 iroi^eros rh tpyov iarl w»s. 



7, S-8, 2.] FRIENDSHIP OR LOVE. 303 

who have the better part in such transactions then 
naturally feel and show more love. 

Again, we all have more affection for what we have 
achieved with toil, as those who have made money 
love it more than those who have inherited it; now, 
receiving a benefit seems to involve no labour, while 
conferring one seems to be troublesome. And for 
this reason mothers have more affection for their 
children than fathers; for they have more trouble 
in giving them birth, and fuller assurance that they 
are their own. But this would seem to be a charac* 
teristic of benefactors also. 

8. Another question which is raised is, whether {!•"**?. 
we ought most to love ourselves or others. ^^^tJT* 

We blame, it is said, those who love themselves 
most, and apply the term self-loving to them ,as a 
term of reproach : and, again, he who is not good is 
thought to have regard to himself in everything that 
he does, and the more so the worse he is ; and so we 
accuse him of doing nothing disinterestedly. The 
good man on the other hand, it is thought, takes 
what is noble as his motive, and the better he is the 
more is he guided by this motive, and by regard for 
his friend, neglecting his own interest. 

But this thA)ry disagrees with facts, nor is it 
surprising that it* should. For it is allowed that we 
ought to love him most who is most truly a friend, 
and that he is most truly a friend who, in wishing 
well to another, wishes well to him for his (the 
other's) sake, and even though no one should ever 
know. But all these characteristics, and all the 
others which go to make up the definition of a friend. 



304 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OP ARISTOTLE. [Bk. DL 

are found in the highest degree in a man's relations 
to himself; for w e have already seen h ow it is f rom 
our relations to ourselves that all our frie ndly rela- 
tions to others are derived; Moreover, all the proverbs 
point to the same conclusion — such as "Friends.have 
one soul," "Friends have all things in common," 
"Equality makes friendship," "The knee is nearer 
than the shin." All these characteristics are found 
in the highest degree in a man's relations to himself; 
for he is his own best friend : and_so he m ust love 
himself better than any one else. 

People not imnaturally are puzzled to know 
which of these two statements to adopt, since both 
appeal to them. 

Perhaps the best method of dealing with con- 3 
flicting statements of this kind is to analyze them, 
and then clearly distinguish how far and in what 
sense each is right. So here, if we first ascertain 
what self-loving means in each statement, the diffi- 
culty will perhaps be cleared up. 

Those who use self-loving as a term of reproach 4 
apply the name to those who take more than their 
due of money, and honour, and bodily pleasures ; for 
the generality of men desire these things, and set 
their hearts upon them as the best things in the 
world, so that they are keenly competed for. Those, 
then, who grasp at more than their share of these 
things indulge their animal appetites and their 
passions generally — ^in a word, the irrational part of 
their nature. But this is the character of the gene- 
rality of men; and hence the term self-loving has 
come to be used in this bad sense from the fact that 



8, 3-6.] FBIENDSHIP OB LOVE. 305 

the greater part of mankind are not good. It is with 
justice, then, that we reproach those who are self- 
loving in this sense. 

That it really is to those who take more than 
their due of these things that the term is usually 
applied by the generality of men, may easily be shown; 
tor if what a man always set his heart upon were 
that he, rather than another, should do what is just 
or te inperate, or in any other way virtuous — ^if, in a 
word, he were always claiming the noble course of 
conduct, no one would call him self-loving and no 
one would reproach him. 

And yet such a man would seem to be more 
truly self-loving. At least, he takes for himself that 
which is noblest and most truly good, and gratifies 
the ruling power in himself, and in all things obeys 
jt. But just as the ruling part in a state or in any 
other system seems, more than any other part, to be 
the state or the system, so also the ruling part of a 
man seems to be most truly the man's self. He 
therefore who loves and gratifies this part of himself 
is most truly self-loving. 

Again, we call a man continent or incontinent,* 
according as his reason has or has not the mastery, 
implying that his reason is his self; and when a man 
has acted under the guidance of his reason he is 
thought, in the fullest sense, ta have done the deed 
himself, and of his own will. 

It is plain, then, that this part of us is our self, or 
is most truly our self, and that the good man more 

♦ iyKpar-fis, continent, in whom the true masters the false self; 
Afcpar^s, incontinent, in whom the true self is mastered. 



306 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OP ARISTOTLE. [Bk.IX. 

than any other loves this part of himself. He, then, 
more than any other, will be self-loving, in another 
sense than the man whom we reproach as self-loving, 
differing from him by all the difference that exists 
between living according to reason and living_ accord- 
ing to passion, between desiring what is noble md 
desiring what appears to be profitable. 

Those who beyond other men set their hearts on 7 
noble deeds are welcomed and praised by all ; but if 
all men were vieing with each other in the pursuit 
of what is noble, and were straining every nerve to 
act in the noblest possible manner, the result would 
be that both the wants of the community would be 
perfectly satisfied, andT ai the" samer-time each in- 
dividually would win the greatest of all good things 
—for virtue is that. 

The good man, therefore, ought to be self-loving ; 
for by doing what is noble he will at once benefit 
himself and assist others: but the bad man ought 
not; for he will injure both himself and his neigh- 
bours by following passions that are not good. • 

Thus, with the bad man there is a discrepancy 8 
between what he ought to do and what he does : but 
with the good man what he ought to do is what he 
does; for reason always chooses that which is best 
for itself; and the good man obeys the voice of 
reason. 

Again, it is quite true to say of the good man 9 
that he does many things for the sake of his friends 
and of his country, and will, if need be, even die for 
them. He will throw away money and honour, and, 
in a word, all the good things for which men compete, 



8, 7-9, IJ FRIENDSHIP OB LOVE. 307 

claiming for himself that which is noble ; for he will 
prefer a brief period of intense pleasure to a long 
period of mild pleasure, one year of noble life to many -« 
years of ordinary life, one great and noble action to 
many little ones. This, we may perhaps say, is what 
he gets who gives his life for others : and so he 
chooses for himself something that is noble on a 
grand scale. 

Such a man will surrender wealth to enrich his 
friend : for while his friend gets the money, he gets 
what is noble; so he takes the greater good for him- 
self. 

10 His conduct will be the same with regard to 
honours and offices : he will give up all to his friend ; 
for this he deems noble and praiseworthy. 

Such a man, then, is not unreasonably considered 
good, as he chooses what is noble in preference to 
everything else. 

But, again, it is possible to give up to your friend 
an opportunity for action, and it may be nobler to 
cause your friend to do a deed than to do it yourselt 

11 It is plain, then, that in all cases in which he is 
praised the good man takes for himself a larger share 
of what is noble. And in this sense, as we have said, 
a man ought to be self-loving, but not in the sense 
in which the generality of men are self-loving. 

1 9. Another disputed question is whether a happy i^^y „ 
man needs friends or not. nJS^^ 

It is said that those who are blessed and self- *^'^^' 
sufficient have no need of friends; for they are already, 
supplied with good things : as self-sufficient, then 
they need nothing more, while a friend is an alter ego 



308 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk.IX. 

who procures for you what you cannot procure 
yourself; whence the saying — 

" When the god fayoors you, what need of friends ?" 

But it seems jtrange, while endowing the happy 2 
man with all good things, to deny him friends, which 
are thought to be the greatest of all extemaI~gooas. 

And if it is more characteristic of a fneiid to 
confer than to receive benefits, and if it is character- 
istic of a good man and a virtuous character to do 
good to others, and if it is nobler to confer benefits 
on friends than on strangers, the_ggod man will need 
friends to receive benefits from him. 

And so people ask whether friends are more 
needed in prosperity or adversity, considering that 
in adversity we want some one to help us, and in 
prosperity some one that we may help. 

Again, it is surely absurd to make the happy man 3 
a solitary being : for no one would choose to have all 
conceivable good things on condition of being alone ; 
for man is a social being, and by nature adapted to 
share his life with others. The happy man, then, 
must have this good, since he has whatever is 
naturally good for man. But it is obvious that it 
is better to Kve with friends and good people, than 
with strangers and casual persons. The happy man, 
then, must have friends. 

What, then, do those who maintain the former 4 
opinion mean ? and in what sense are they right ? Is 
it that the generality of men think that friends means 
useful people ?^ Friends in this sense certainly the 
happy or blessed man will not need, as he already has 



9, 2-6.] FRIENDSHIP OB LOVE. 309 

whatever is good. And, again, he wiU have no need, ^ 
or but little need, of the friendship that is based on ) 
pleasure; for his life is pleasant and does not require/ 
adventitious pleasure. Because he does not need 
these kind of friends then, people come to think he 
does not need friends at alL 

But I think we may say that this opinion is not 
true. For we said at the outset that happiness is a 
c ertain exercise of our faculties ; but the exercise of 
our faculties plainly comes to be in time, and is not 
like a piece of property acquired once for all. But 
if happiness consists in living and exercising our 
faculties ; and if the exercise of the good man's 
faculties is good and pleasant in itself, as we said 
at the outset ; and if the sense that a thing belong 
to us is one of the sources of pleasure, but it is easier \ 
to contemplate others than ourselves, and others' acts 
than pur own — then the acts of the good men who 
are his friends are pleasant to the good man ; for both ' 
the natural sources of pleasure are united in them.-* 
The happy or blessed man, then, will need such friends, 
since he desires to contemplate acts that are good and 
belong to him, and such are the acts of a good man 
who is his friend. 

Again, it is thought that the happy man's life 
must be pleasant. Now, if he is solitary, life is hard 
for him ; for it is very difficult to be continuously 
active by one's self, but not so difficult along with 
others, aiid in relation to others. With friends, then, 
the exercise of his faculties will be more continuous, 
being pleasant in iteel£ And this is what ought 

• (1) They are good, (2) they belong to him. 



310 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLB. [BK.IX. 

to be the case with the blessed man; for the good 
man, as such, del ights in acts of virtue and is vexed 
by acts of vice, just as a musician is pleased by good 
music and pained by bad. 
/ Again, he would get ajort pfj^rflfCtice 7 

^living with good men, as Theognis Qays.* 

But if we look a little deeper into the nature of 
things, a good friend appears to be naturally desirable 
to the good man : — 

What is naturally good, we have already said, is 
good and pleasant in itself to the good man. 

Now, life is defined in the case of animals by the 
power of feeling, in the case of man by the power of 
feeling or thought: but the power involves refer- 
ence to its exercise ; and it is in this exercise that the 
reality lies: life, then, in its reality, seems to be 
feeling or thinking. 

Life, again, is one of the things that are good and 
pleasant in themselves ; for it is determinate or 
formed, and the determinate or formed is of the 
nature of the good ; but that which is naturally [or in 
itself] good is good to the good man. (And hence life 
seems to be pleasant to all men. But by life we must s 
not understand a bad or corrupt life, or a life of pain; 
for such a life is formless, as are all its constituents. 
We shall endeavour, presently, to throw some light on 
the nature of pain.) 

Life itself, then, is good and pleasant (as appears 9 
also from the fact that all desire it, and especially 
the good and the blessed ; for life is most desirable 
to them, and their life is the most blessed). 

* C/. the last words of this book* 



9, 7-10 J FBIENDSHIP OB LOVK 311 

But he who sees feels that he sees, and he who 
hears feels that he hears, and he who walks feels that 
he walks; and similarly, whatever else we do, there 
is something that perceives that we are putting forth 
power, so that we must feel that we feel, and know 
that we know. 

But to feel that we feel, or to know that we know, 
is to feel or to know that we exist ; for our existence, 
we found, is feeling or knowing. 

But to feel that we exist is a thing that is pleasant 
in itself; for life is naturally good, and to feel that 
one has a good is pleasant. 

Life, then, is desirable, and most of all desirable 
to the good man, because his existence is good to 
him, and pleasant ; for he is pleased by the conscious- 
ness of that which is good in itself. 
10 But the good man stands in the same relation to 
^ his friend as to himself, for his friend is another self : 
just as his own existence, then, is desirable to each, 
so, or nearly so, is his friend's existence desii;able. 

But existence, we found, is desirable because of the 
feeling that one's self is good, such a feeling being 
pleasant in itself. 

The good man, then, should be conscious of the 
existence of his friend also, and this consciousness will 
be given by living with him and by rational converse 
with him (for this would seem to be the proper mean- 
ing of living together, when applied to man, and not 
merely feeding in the same place, which it means 
when applied to beasts). 

Putting all this together, then, if his own existence 
is desirable in itself to the good man, being naturally 



812 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLB. [BK.IX. 

good and pleasant, and if his Mend's existence is also 
desirable to him in nearly the same way, it follows 
that a friend is a desirable thing^ for_him. ^BuOhat 
which is desirable for him he ought to have, or in 
that respect he will be incomplete. Our conclusion, 
therefore, is that he who is. to be happy must have 
good friends. 
offktpnmer 10. Are wc to make as many friends asjno«5able ? i 
/ri«kto. or, as in the case of guest-friendship * we approve of 
the saying, "neither a host of guest-friends nor yet 
none," shall we say that in the case of friendship 
also it is best neither to be friendless nor yet to have 
too many friends ? 

With regard to friends who are chosen with a 2 
view to being useful, the saying would seem to be 
perfectly appropriate; for it would be troublesome 
to repay the services of a large number, and indeed 
life is not long enough to enable us to do it. Of such 
friends, therefore, a larger number than is sufficient 
for one's own life would be superfluous and a hin- 
drance to noble living ; so we do not want more than 
that number. 

Again, of friends chosen with a view to pleasure 
a small number is enough, as a small proportion of 
sweets is enough in our diet. 

But are we to have as many good men for friends 3 
as we can, or is there any limit of numbers in friend- 
ship, as there is in a state ? for you could not make 
a state out of ten men, and if you had a hundred 
thousand your state would cease to be a state. But 
perhaps the right number of citizens is not one fixed 

* CJ. note on ?iii. 3, 4. 



10, IH).] FBIENDSHIP OR LOVE. 313 

number, but any number within certain limita And 
so with friends there is a limit to their number, and 
that is, we may say, the largest number that one can 

4 live with ; for living together is, as we saw, one of the 
most essential characteristics of friendship, and it is 
quite evident that it is impossible to live with and 
spread one's self abroad among a large number. 

Moreover, a man's friends must be friends with 

- one another, if all are to spend their time together; 
but this is difficult with a large number. 

6 Again, it becomes hard for him to sympathize 
duly with the joys and sorrows of a large number ; 
for then he is likely to have at the same time to 
rejoice with one and to grieve with another. Per- 
haps, then, the best plan is not to try to have as 
many friends as possible, but so many as are suffi- 
cient for a life in common ; and indeed it would be 
impossible to have an ardent friendship with a great 
number. 

. And, for the same reason, it is impossible to be in 
love with many persons at once ; for it seems that 
love is a^ort of superlative friendship, and that this 
is only possible towards one person, and an ardent 
friendship towards a few only. 

6 And this seems, in fact, to happen : we do not 
find a number of people bound together by the sort 
of friendship that exists between comrades, but the 
friendships that the poets celebrate are friendships of 
two persons. And the man of many friends, who is 
hail-fellow-well-met with everybody, seems to be 
really friends with no one (in any other way than as 
fellow-citizens are friends) — I mean the man whom 
we call obsequious. 



814 NICOMAOHBAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [BK.IX. 

After the manner of fellow-citizens, indeed, it is 
possible to be friends with a great number, and yet 
not to be obsequious, but to be a truly good man ; but 
that kind of friendship which is based on virtue and 
on regard for the friend's self one cannot have for 
many, but must be well satisfied if one can find even 
a few such persons. 
Mendt 11. Is it in prosperity or adversity that we most 1 

nproMperity need fricuds ? For under both circumstances wo 
ujf, have recourse to them : in misfortune we need help, 

in prosperity we need people to live with and to do 
good to ; for we wish to do good. 

In adversity, it may be answered, the need is 
more pressing; we then require useful friends: but 
friendship is a nobler, j^^ing in prnspprify 3 we then 
seek out good men for friends ; for it is mpr§,deaiiable 
to do good to and to live with such people. 

The mere presence of friends is. sweet, even in 2 
misfortune; for our grief is lightened when our 
friends share it. And so it might be asked whether 
they literally take a share of it as of a weight, or 
whether it is not so, but rather that their presence, 
which is sweet, and the consciousness of their sym- 
pathy, make our grief less. But whether this or 
something else be the cause of the relief, we need not 
further inquire; the fact is evidently as we said. 

But their presence seems to be complex in its 
eflects. On the one hand, the mere sight of friends 3 
is pleasant, especially when we are in adversity, and 
contributes something to assuage our grief; for a 
friend can do much to comfort us both by sight and 
speech, if he has tact : he knows our character, and 



11, l^J FBIENDSHIP OB LOVE. 315 

4 what pleases and what pains us. But, on the other^ 
hand, to see another grieving over our misfortunes is ^ 
a painful thing; for every one dislikes to be the 
cause of sorrow to his fiiends. For this reason he 
who is of a manly nature takes care not to impart 
his grief to his friends, shrinking from the pain that 
would give them, imless this is quite outweighed by 
the relief it would give him ; ♦ and generally he does 
not allow others to lament with him, as he is not 
given to lamentations himself; but weak women 
and effeminate men delight in those who lament with 
them, and love them as friends and sympathizers. 
(But evidently we ought in all circumstances to take 
the better man for our model.) 

5 In prosperity, again, the presence of friends not 
only makes the time pass pleasantly, but also brings 
the consciousness that our friends are pleased at our 
good fortune. And for this reason it would seem 
that we should be eager to invite our friends to share 
our prosperity, for it is noble to be ready to confer 
benefits, — but slow to summon them to us in adversity, 
for we ought to be loth to give others a share of our 
evil things : whence comes the saying, " That I am in 
sorrow is sorrow enough." But we should be least 
unwilling to call them in when they will be likely to 
relieve us much without being greatly troubled them-/- 
selves. 

6 But, on the other hand, when our friends are in 
trouble, we should, I think, go to them unsummoned 
and readily (for it is a friend's ofiice to serve his 
friend, and especially when he is in need and does not 

* See a few lines on, end of § 6> 



316 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. IX. 

claim assistance, for then it is nobler and pleasanter 
to both) : when they are in prosperity, we should go 
readily to help them (for this is one of the uses of a 
friend), but not so readHy to share their good things; 
for it is not a noble thing to be very ready to receive 
a benefit. But we may add that we ought to be 
careful that our refusal shall not seem ungracious, as 
sometimes happens. 

The presence of friends, then, in ' conclusion, is 
manifestly desirable on all occasions, 
►^^^ti) 12. Lovers delight above all things in the sight i 

■u£ of each other, a^d prefer the gratification of this 
sense to that of all the others, as this sense is more 
concerned than any other in the being and origin of 
love. In like manner, we may venture to say, do 
friends find living together more desirable than any- 
thing else ; for friendship is essentially community. 
\ Moreover, a man stands to his friend in the same 

y^ relation in which he stands to himself: but with 
' regard to himself the feeling of existence is desirable ; 
therefore the same feeling with regard to his friend is 
desirable. But it is in a common life that they attain 
this feeling; therefore they naturally desire a life in 
common. 

Again, whatever that be which a man holds to 2 
constitute existence, or for the sake of which he 
chooses to live, in that he wishes to pass his time 
together with his friends ; and thus some drink to- 
gether, others gamble, others practise gymnastics, or 
hunt, or study philosophy together — in each case 
spending their time together in that which they love 
most of all things in life; for, wishing to live in 



12, 1-3.] FRIENDSHIP OB LOVE. 317 

common with their friends, they do those things and 
take part together in those things which, as they 
think, constitute life in common. 
8 Thus the friendship of those who are not good 
comes to be positively bad ; for, having no stability of 
character, they confirm each other in things that are not 
good, and thus become positively bad as they become 
more like one another. But the friendship of good 
men is good, and grows with their intercourse ; and 
they seem to become better as they exercise their 
faculties and correct each other's deficiencies: for 
each moulds himself to the likeness of that which 
he approves in the other ; whence the saying, " From 
good men thou shalt learn good things/' * 

So much, then, for friendship. We will now pass 
to the consideration of pleasure. 

♦ iffdK&y fily y^ dir* i<rd\it /ta^crecu. — Theognij, 



BOOK X. 

CHAPTERS 1-8. PLEASURE. 

Reaiongfor !• 0^^^ next business, I think, should be to treat 1 
^£2SJj[*^ of pleasure. For pleasure seems, more than anything 
else, to have an intimate connection with our nature ; 
which is the reason why, in educating the young, we 
use pleasure and pain as the rudders of their course. 
Moreover, delight in what we ought to delight in, and 
hatred of what we ought to hate, seem to be of the 
utmost importance in the formation of a virtuous 
' character ; for these feelings pervade the whole of 
life, and have power to draw a man to virtue and 
happiness, as we choose what pleases, and shun what 
pains us. 

And it would seem that the discussion of these 2 
matters is especially incumbent on us, since there 
is much dispute about them. There are people 
who say that the good is pleasure, and there are 
people who say, on the contrary, that pleasure is 
altogether bad — some, perhaps, in the conviction that 
it is really so, others because they think it has a 
good effect on men's lives to assert that pleasure is a 
bad thing, even though it be not; for the generality 



1, 1-2, 1.] PLEASURE. 319 

of men, they say, incline this way, and are slaves to 
their pleasures, so that they ought to be pulled in the 
opposite direction : for thus they will be brought into 
the middle course. 

But I cannot think that it is right to speak thus. 
For assertions about matters of feeling and conduct 
carry less weight than actions ; and so, when assertions 
are found to be at variance with palpable facts, they 
fall into contempt, and bring the truth also into dis- 
credit. Thus, when a man who speaks ill of pleasure 
is seen at times to desire it himself, he is thought to 
show by the fact of being attracted by it that he really 
considers all pleasure desirable ; for the generality of 
men are not able to draw fine distinctions. It seems, 
then, that true statements are the most useful, for 
practice as well as for theory ; for, being in harmony 
with facts, they gain credence, and so incline those 
who understand them to regulate their lives by them. 
But enough of this : let us^owgo^hrough the current 
opinions about pleasure. 

2. Eudoxus thought pleasure was the good, because ^^ 
he saw that all beings, both rational and irrational, 2*Jftf ^ 
strive after it ; but in all cases, he said, that which is 
desirable * is good, and that which is most desirable 
is best : the fact, then, that all beings incline to one 
and the same thing indicates that this is the best 
thing for all ; for each being finds out what is good 
for itself — ^its food, for instance : that, then, which is 
good for all, and which all strive after, is the good. 

The statements of Eudoxus were accepted rather 

* rh alptrSy covers, as no English word can, the transition from 
desired to desirable. 



320 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. X. 

because of the excellence of his character than on 
their own account; for he seemed to be a remark- 
ably temperate man ; and so people thought that it 
was not from love of pleasure that he spoke thus, but 
that what he said really was the fact. 

Eudoxus also thought that his point could be 2 
proved no less clearly by the argument from the 
opposite of pleasure : — pain is, in itself, an object of 
aversion to all beings ; therefore its opposite is desir- 
able for all. 

Again, he argued, that is most desirable which we 
choose, not on account of something else, but for its 
own sake : but this is admitted to be the case with 
pleasure ; for we never ask a man for his motive in 
taking pleasure, it being understood that pleasure is 
in itself desirable. 

Again, he argued iihat any good thing whatso- 
ever is made more desirable by the addition of 
pleasure, e.g. just or temperate conduct; but it can 
only be by the good that the good is increased. 

Now, this last argument seems indeed to show 3 
that pleasure is a good thing, but not that it is one 
whit better than any other good thing ; for any good 
thing is more desirable with the addition of another 
good thing than by itself. 

Nay, Plato actually employs a similar argument 
to show that pleasure is not the good. "The pleasant 
life,'' he says, "is more desirable with wisdom than 
without: but if the combination of the two be better, 
pleasure itself cannot be the good ; for no addition can 
make the good itself more desirable." And it is equally 
evident that, if any other thing be made more desir- 



2, 2-6.1 PLEASUBE. 321 

able by the addition of one of the class of things that 
are good in themselves, that thing cannot be the good. 

4 What good is there, then, which is thus incapable of 
addition, and at the same time such that men can 
participate in it 2 For that is the sort of good that 
we want. 

But those who maintain, on the contrary, that 
what all desire is not good, surely talk nonsense. 
What all men think, that, we say, is true. And to 
him who bids us put no trust in the opinion of man- 
kind, we reply that we can scarce put greater trust in 
his opinion. If it were merely irrational creatures 
that desired these things, there might be something 
in what he says; but as rational beings also desire 
them, how can it be anything but nonsense ? Indeed, 
it may be that even in inferior beings there is some 
natural principle of good stronger than themselves, 
which strives after their proper good. 

5 Again, what the adversaries of Eudoxus say about 
his argument from the nature of the opposite of 
pleasure, does not seem to be sound. They say that, 
though pain be bad, yet it does not follow that 
pleasure is good ; for one bad thing may be opposed 
to another bad thing, and both to a third thing which 
is diflTerent from either.* Now, though this is not a 
bad remark, it does not hold true in the present 
instance. For if both were bad, both alike ought to 
be shunned, or if neither were bad, neither should be 
shunned, or, at least, one no more than the other: 
but, as it is, men evidently shun the one as bad and 

* The neutral state, neither pleasure nor pain, which they hold 
to be good. 

Y 



S22 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OP ABISTOTLE. [Bk.X. 

choose the other as good; they are, in feet, there- 
fore, opposed to one another in this respect. 

j^m«n« 3, Again, even though pleasure is not a quality, ; 

a quality; it docs not follow that it is not a good thin£:. The 

that %tu not , , , , , ° ° 

d^^rminei; exercise of virtue, happiness itself, is not a quality. 
^^m^%ito ^^ ^ objected, again, that the good is determinate, j 

^^^ while pleasure is indeterminate, because it admits of 

diffar in ^k more and a less. 

Now, if they say this because one may be itiore 
or less pleased, then the same thing may be said of 
justice and the other virtues ; for it is plain that, with 
regard to them, we speak— of people as more or less 
virtuous : some men are moi^ just and more brave 
than others, and it is possil^e to act more or less 
justly and temperately. 

But if they mean that one pleasure may be more 
or less of a pleasure than another, I suspect that they 
miss the real reason when they say it is because 
some are pure and some are mixed. Why should it 8 
not be the same with pleasure as with health, which, 
though something determinate, yet allows of more 
and less ? Fot the due proportion ^f elements 
[which constitutes health] is not the same for all, nor 
always the same for the same person, but may vary 
within certain limits without losing its character, 
being now more and now less truly health. And it 
may be the same with pleasure. 

Again, assuming that the good is complete, while 4 
motion and coming into being are incomplete, they try 
to show that pleasure is a motion and a coming into 
being. 

But they do not seem to be right even in saying 



8, 1-7.] PLEASUBB. 323 

that it is a motion : for every motion seems necessarily 
to be quick or slow, either absolutely, as the motion of 
the universe, or relatively; but pleasure is neither 
quick nor slow. It is, indeed, possible to be quickly 
pleased, as to be quickly angered ; the feeling, how- 
ever, cannot be quick, even relatively, as can walk- 
ing and growing, etc. The passage to a state of 
pleasure, then, may be quick or slow, but the exercise 
of the power, i.e, the feeling of pleasure, cannot be 
quick. 

Again, how can pleasure be a coming into being ? 

It seems that it is not possible for anything to 
come out of just anything, but what a thing comes 
out of, that it is resolved into. Pain, then, must be 
the dissolution of that whose coming into being is plea- 
sura Accordingly, they maintain that pain is falling 
short of the normal state, pleasure its replenishment. 

But these are bodily processes. If, then, pleasure 
be the replenishment of the normal state, that in which 
the replenishment takes place, i,e. the body, must be 
that which is pleased. But this does not seem to be 
the case. Pleasure, therefore, is not a replenishment, 
but while the process of replenishment is going on we 
may be pleased, and while the process of exhaustion 
is going on we may be pained.* 

This view of pleasure seems to have been suggested 
by the pleasures and pains connected with nutrition; 
for there it is true that we come into a state of want, 
and, after previous pain, find pleasure in replenish- 
ment. But this is not the case with all pleasures ; 
for there is no previous pain involved in the pleasures 

* Adopting Spongers conjecture, jccvo^/icvos for T9fxv6fi€uos, 



324 NICOMAOHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk. X. 

of the mathematician, nor among the sensuous plea- 
sures in those of smell, nor, again, in many kinds of 
sights and sounds, nor in memories and hopes. What 
is there, then, of which these pleasures are the be- 
coming ? Here there is nothing lacking that can be 
replenished. 

To those, again, who [in order to show that 8 
pleasure is not good] adduce the disgraceful kinds of 
pleasure we might reply that these things are not 
pleasant. Though they be pleasant to ill-conditioned 
persons, we must not therefore hold them to be 
pleasant except to them ; just as we do not hold that 
to be wholesome, or sweet, or bitter, which is whole- 
some, sweet, or bitter to the sick man, or that to be 
white which appears white to a man with ophthalmia. 

Or, again, we might reply that these pleasures 9 
are desirable, but not when derived from these 
sources, just as it is desirable to be rich, but not at 
the cost of treachery, and desirable to be in health, 
but not at the cost of eating any kind of abominable 
food. 

Or we might say that the pleasures are specifically lo 
different. The pleasures derived from noble sources 
are different from those derived from base sources, 
and it is impossible to feel the just man's pleasure 
without being just, or the musical man's pleasure 
without being musical, and so on with the rest. 

The distinction drawn between the true friend U 
and the flatterer seems to show either that pleasure is 
not good, or else that pleasures differ in kind. For 
the former in his intercourse is thought to have the 
good in view, the latter pleasure ; and while we blame 



3, 8-4, 2.] PLEASURE. 325 

the latter, we praise the former as having a different 
aim in his intercourse. 

12 Again, no one would choose to live on condition 
of having a child's intellect all his life, though he 
were to enjoy in the highest possible degree all the 
pleasures of a child ; nor choose to gain enjoyment by 
the performance of some extremely disgraceful act, 
though he were never to feel pain. 

There are many things, too, which we should care 
for, even though they brought no pleasure, as sight, 
memory, knowledge, moral and intellectual excellence. 
Even if we grant that pleasure necessarily accom- 
panies them, this does not affect the question ; for we 
should choose them even if no pleasure resulted from 
them. 

13 It seems to be evident, then, that pleasure is not 
the good, nor are all pleasures desirable, but that some 
are desirable, differing in kind, or in their sources, 
from those that are not desirable. Let this be taken 
then as a sufficient account of the current opinions 
about pleasure and paia. 

1 4. As to the nature or quality of pleasure, we shall ^JJJ^ . 
more readily discover it if we make a fresh start as ''*^^ ^ 
follows : — 

Vision seems to be perfect or complete at any 
moment; for it does not lack anything which can 
be added afterwards to make its nature complete. 
Pleasure seems in this respect to resemble vision ; for 
it is something whole and entire, and it would be 
impossible at any moment to find a pleasure which 
woidd become complete by lasting longer. 

2 Therefore pleasure is not a motion ; fot every 



326 NICOMAOHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk. X. 

motion requires time and implies an end; e,g. the 
motion or process of building is complete when the 
required structure is made — either in the whole time 
therefore^ or in this final moment of it. But in the 
several portions of this time all the motions are in- 
complete, and specifically different from the whole 
motion and from each other; the fitting together of 
the stones is difierent from the fluting of the pillar, 
and both from the building of the temple. The 
building of the temple is complete ; nothing more is 
required for the execution of the plan. But the 
building of the foundation and of the triglyph are 
incomplete ; for each is the building of a part only. 
These motions, then, are specifically different from 
one another, and it is impossible to find a motion 
whose nature is complete at any moment — ^it is com- 
plete, if at all, only in the whole time. 

It is the same also with walking and the other 3 
kinds of locomotion. For though all locomotion is a 
motion from one place to another, yet there are dis- 
tinct kinds of locomotion, as fiying, walking, leaping, 
etc. Nay, not only so, but even in walking itself 
there are differences, for the whence and whither are 
not the same in the entire course and in a portion 
of the course, or in this portion and in that, nor is 
crossing this line the same as crossing that ; for you 
do not cross a line simply, but a line that is in a given 
place, and this line is in a different place from that 
I must refer to my other works * for a detailed dis- 

♦ Physios, Book iii. f. : c/. especially viii. 8, 264 b, 27, quoted by 
Bamsaner, who fonnds on it an ingenions emendation of this 
passage. 



4, 3-6.] PLEASURE. 327 

cussion of motion; but it seems that it is. not complete 
at any moment, but that its several parts are incom- 
plete, and that they are specifically dififerent from 
one another, the whence and whither being a specific 
difierence. 

Pleasure, on the other hand, is complete in its 
nature at any moment. It is evident, therefore, that 
these two must be distinct from each other, and that 
pleasure must be one of the class of whole and 
complete things. And this woidd also seem to follow 
from the fact that though duration is necessary for 
motion, it .is not necessary for pleasure — for a 
momentary pleasure is something whole and entire. 

From these considerations it is plain that they 
are wrong in saying that pleasure is a motion or a 
coming into being. For these terms are not applied 
to every thing, but only to those things that are 
divisible into parts and are not wholes. We cannot 
speak of the coming into being of vision, or of a 
mathematical point, or of unity ; nor is any one of 
them a motion or a/coming into being. And these 
terms are equally inapplicable to pleasure; for it is 
something whole and entire. 

Each sense exercises itself upon its proper object, 
and exercises itself completely when it is in good 
condition and the object is the noblest of those that 
fall within its scope ; for the complete exercise of a 
faculty seems to mean this ; and we may assume that 
it makes no difference whether we speak of the sense, 
or of the sensitive subject as exercising itself: in 
either case, then, we may say that the exercise is best 
when on the one side you have the finest condition. 



328 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. X. 

and on the other the highest of the objects that fall 
within the scope of this faculty. 

But this exercise of the faculty will he not only 
the most complete, but also the pleasantest : for the 
exercise of every sense is attended with pleasure, and 
so is the exercise of reason and the speculative faculty; 
and it is pleasantest when it is most complete, and it 
is most complete when the faculty is well-trained 
and the object is the best of those that fall under this 
faculty. 

And, further, the pleasure completes the exercise 6 
of the faculty. But the pleasure completes it in a 
different way from that in which the object and the 
faculty of sense complete it, when both are as they 
should be ; just as health causes healthy activities in 
a different way from that in which the physician 
causes them. 

(That the exercise of every sense is accompanied 7 
by pleasure is evident : we speak of pleasant sights 
and pleasant sounds. 

It is evident also that the pleasure is greatest 
when both the faculty and that upon which it is 
exercised are as good as they can be: when this is the 
case both with the object of sense and the sentient 
subject, there will always be pleasure, so long, that is, 
as you have the subject to act and ihe object to be 
acted upon.) 

Now, the pleasure makes the exercise complete 8 
not as the habit or trained faculty* does, being 

• As already remarked, there is no one English word whioh 
includes these varions senses of l|is, (1) habit of body, (2) moral 
habit or character, (8) inteUectoal habit or trained faculty. 



4, 6-10.] PLEASURE. 329 

already present in the subject, but as a sort of super- 
added completeness, like the grace of youth.* 

So long, then, as both the object of thought or of 
sense and the perceptive or contemplative subject are 
-as they ought to be, so long will there be pleasure in 
the exercise; for so long as the object to be acted 
upon and the subject that is able to act remain the 
same, and maintain the same relation to each other, 
the result must be the same. 

9 How is it, then, that we are incapable of continuous 
pleasure? Perhaps the reason is that we become 
exhausted; for no human faculty is capable of con- 
tinuous exercise. Pleasure, then, also cannot be con- 
tinuous; for it is an accompaniment of the exercise 
of faculty. And for the same reason some things 
please us when new, but afterwards please us less. 
For at first the intellect is stimidated and exercises 
itself upon them strenuously, just as we strain our 
eyes to look hard at something ; but after a time the 
exertion ceases to be so intense, and becomes relaxed; 
and so the pleasure also loses its keenness. 

10 The desire for pleasure we should expect to be 
shared by all men, seeing that all desire to live. 

But life is an exercise of faculties, and each man 
exercises the faculties he most loves upon the things 
he most loves; e.g, the musical man exercises his 
hearing upon melodies, and the studious man exer- 

* At oliher periods of life the various organs of the body may 
perform their f nnotions completely, but in youth this is acoompanied 
by an inexpressible charm which all other ages lack. 

The only analogy between pleasnre and the doctor is that both 
" complete the activity " from oatside : medicines alter the f onctions ; 
pleasure, like beauty, does not alter them, bnt is an added perfection* 



830 NIOOMAOHEAN ETHICS OP AEISTOTLE. [Bk. X. 

cises his intellect upon matters of speculation, and so 
on with the rest. 

And pleasure completes the exercise of faculties, 
and therefore life, which men desire. 

Naturally, therefore, men desire pleasure too ; for 
each man finds in it the completion of his life, which 
is desirable. 

But whether we desire life for the sake of plea- H 
sure, or pleasure for the sake of life, is a question 
which we may dismiss for the present. For the two 
seem to be joined together, and not to admit of 
separation : without exercise of faculties there is no 
pleasure, and every such exercise is completed by 
pleasure. 
Pleasures 6. And from this it seems to follow that pleasures i 

wrZ'^to differ in kind, since specifically different things we 
m standard belicve to be completed by specifically different things. 
nan, For this sccms to be the case with the products both 
of nature and of art, as animals and trees, paintings, 
sculptures, houses, and furniture. Similarly, then, 
we believe that exercises of faculty which differ in 
kind are completed by things different in kind. 

But the exercises of the intellectual faculties are 2 
specifically different from the exercises of the senses, 
and the several kinds of each from one another; 
^ therefore the pleasures which complete them are also 
different. 

The same conclusion would seem to foUow from 
the close connection that exists between each pleasure 
and the exercise of faculty which it completes. For 
the exercise is increased by its proper pleasure ; e,g, 
people are more likely to understand any matter, and 



) 



4, 11-6, 6.] PLEASUBE. 331 

to go to the bottom of it, if the exercise is pleasant to 
them. Thus, those who delight in geometry become 
geometricians, and imderstand all the propositions 
better than others ; and similarly, those who are fond 
of music, or of architecture, or of anything else, mako 
progress in that kind of work, because they delight in 
it. The pleasures, then, help to increase the exercise ; 
but that which helps to increase it must be closely 
connected with it : but when things are specifically 
different from one another, the things that are closely 
connected with them must also be specifically different. 
3 The same conclusion follows perhaps still more 
clearly from the fact that the exercise of one faculty 
is impeded by the pleasure proper to another; e.gr, 
a lover of the flute is unable to attend to an argu- 
ment if he hears a man playing, since he takes more 
delight in flute-playing than in his present business ; 
the pleasure of the flute-player, therefore, hinders 
the exercise of the reason. 

The same result follows in other cases, too, when- 
ever a man is exercising his faculties on two things 
at a time ; the pleasanter business thwarts the other, 
and, if the difference in pleasantness be great, thwarts 
it more and more, even to the extent of suppressing 
it altogether. Thus, when anything gives us intense 
delight, we cannot do anything else at all, and when 
we do a second thing, we do not very much care about 
the first; and so people who eat sweetmeats in the 
theatre do this most of all when the actors are bad. 

Since its proper pleasure heightens the exercise 
of a faculty, making it both more prolonged and 
better, while pleasure from another source spoils it, 



332 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF AHISTOTLK TBr. X. 

it is evident that there is a great difference between 
these two pleasures. Indeed, pleasure from another 
source has almost the same effect as pain from the 
activity itself. For the exercise of a faculty is spoilt 
by pain arising from it; as happens, for instauce, 
when a man finds it disagreeable and pamful to write 
or to calculate; for he stops writing in the one 
case and calculating in the other, since the exer- 
cise is painful The exercise of a faculty, then, is 
affected in opposite ways by its proper pleasure and its 
proper pain; and by "proper" I mean that which is 
occasioned by the exercise itself. But pleasure from 
another source, we have already said, has almost the 
same effect as its proper pain ; i.e. it interferes with the 
exercise of the faculty, though not to the same extent. 

Agam, as the exercises of our faculties differ in 6 
goodness and badness, and some are to be desired and 
some to be shunned, while some are indifferent, so do 
the several pleasures differ ; for each exercise has its 
proper pleasure. Th^ pleasure which is proper to a 
good activity, then, is ^ood, and that which is proper 
to one that is not good is bad : for the desire of noble 
things is laudable, and the desire of base things is 
blamable; but the pleasures which accompany the 
exercises of our faculties belong to them even more 
than the desires do, since the latter are distinct both in 
time and in nature, while the former are abnost coin- 
cident in time, and so hard to distinguish from them 
that it is a matter of debate whether the exercise bo 
not identical with the pleasure. 

It seems, however, that the pleasure is not the 7 
same as the act of thinking or of feeling; that is im- 



5, 6-9.] PLEASTJBE. 333 

possible: but the fact that the two are inseparable 
makes some people fancy that they are identical. 

As, then, the exercises of the faculties vary, so do 
their res pective pleasures. Sight is purer than touch, 
hearing and smell than taste * : there is a correspond- 
ing difference, therefore, between their pleasures ; and 
the pleasures of the intellect are purer than these 
pleasures of sense, and some of each kind are purer 
than others. 

8 Each kind of being, again, seems to have its 
proper pleasure, as it has its proper function, — ^viz. the 
pleasure which accompanies the exercise of its faculties 
or the realization of its natura And a separate con- 
sideration of the several kinds of animals will confirm 
this : the pleasures of a horse, a dog, and a man are 
all different — as Heraditus says, a donkey would 
prefer hay to gold; for there is more pleasure in 
fodder than in gold to a donkey. 

The pleasurfs of specificaUy different beings, then, 
are specifically different; and we might naturally 
suppose that there would be no specific difference 
between the pleasures of beings of the same species. 

9 And yet there is no small difference, in the pleasures 
of men at least : what pleases this man pains that ; 
what is grievous and hateful to one is pleasant and 
lovable to another. This occurs in the case of sweet 

* Sight and tonch are classed together on the one hand, and 
hearing, smell, and taste on the other, because, while the announce- 
ments of all the senses are, in the first instance, of secondary 
qualities (colours, sounds, etc.), it is mainly from the announce- 
ments of sight and touch that we advance to the knowledge of 
the mathematical properties or primary qualities (number, figure^ 
motion, etc.). 



334 NIOOMAOHEAN ETHICS OF AEISTOTLB. [Bk. X. 

things, too : a man in a fever has a different notion 
of what is sweet from a man in health ; and a feeble 
man's notion of what is hot is different from that of 
a robust man. And the like occurs in other matters 
also. 

But in all matters of this kind we hold that lo 
things are what they appear to be to the perfect man. 
Now, if this opinion is correct, as we hold it to 
be — ^if, that is, in every case the test is virtue, or the 
good man as such — ^then what appears to him to be 
pleasure will be pleasure, and what he delights in 
will be pleasant. 

If what is disagreeable to him appears pleasant 
to another, we need not be astonished ; for there are 
many ways in which men are corrupted and per- 
verted: such things, however, are not pleasant, but 
only pleasant to these men with their disposition. It li 
is plain, then, that we must not allow the confessedly 
base pleasures to be pleasures at all, except to corrupt 
men. 

But of the pleasures that are considered good, 
which or what kind are to be called the proper 
pleasures of man ? We cannot be in doubt if we 
know what are the proper exercises of his faculties ; 
for the proper pleasures are their accompaniments. 
Whether, then, the exercise of faculties proper to the 
complete and happy man be one or many, the plea- 
sures that complete that exercise will be called 
pleasures of man in the full meaning of the words, 
and the others in a secondary sense and with a 
fraction of that meaning, just as is the case with the 
exercises of the faculties. 



A.^-^ 

% 10-6. 3'] CONCLUSION. 335 



F 

^H CEAPTEBS 6-9. COKCLnSIOK. 

^ 6. Now that we have diacuBsed the several kindq m 
of virtue and friendship and pleaaiire, it remains to » 
give a summary account of happiness, since we 
assume that it is the end of aU that man does. And 
it will shorten our statement if we first recapitulate 
what we have said above. 
■3 We said that happiness is not a habit or trained 
faculty. If it were, it would be within the reaeh of 
a man who slept all his days and hved the life of a 
vegetable, or of a man who met with the greatest 
misfortunes. As we cannot accept this conclusion, 
we must place happiness in some exercise of faculty, 
as we said before. But as the exercises of faculty are 
sometimes necessary (i.e. desirable for the sake of 
something else), sometimes desirable in themselves, it 
is evident that happiness must be placed among those 
that are desirable in themselves, and not among those 
that are desirable for the sake of something else ; for 
happiness lacks nothing; it is sufficient in itself. 
3 Now, the exercise of faculty is desirable in itself 
when nothing is expected irom it beyond itself. 

Of this nature are held to be (1) the manifesta- 
tions of excellence ; for to do what is noble and excel- 
lent must be counted desirable for itself: and (2) 
those amusements which please us ; for they are not 
chosen for the sake of anything else, — indeed, men 
are more apt to be injured than to be benefited 
by them, through neglect of their health and fortunes. 
Now, most of those whom men call happy have 
recourse to pastimes of this sort. And on this account 



336 NIOOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk. X. 

those who show a ready wit in such pastimes find 
favour with tyrants ; for they make themselves plea- 
sant in that which the tyrant wants^ and what he 
wants is pastime. These amusements, then, are gene- 
rally thought to be elements of happiness, because 
princes employ their leisure in them. But such per- 
sons, we may venture to say, are no criterion. For i 
princely rank does not imply the possession of virtue 
or of reason, which are tiie sources of all excellent 
exercise of faculty. And if these men, never having 
tasted pure and refined pleasure, have recourse to the 
pleasures of the body, we should not on that account 
think these more desirable ; for children also fancy 
that the things which they value are better than 
anything else. It is only natural, then, that as chil- 
dren differ from men in their estimate of what is 
valuable, so bad men should differ from good. 

As we have often said, therefore, that is truly 6 
valuable and pleasant which is so to the perfect man. 
Now, the exercise of those trained faculties which are 
proper to him is what each man finds most desirable ; 
what the perfect man finds most desirable, therefore, 
is the exercise of virtue. 

Happiness, therefore, does not consist in amuse- 6 
ment; and indeed it is absurd to suppose that the 
end is amusement, and that we toil and moil all our 
life long for the sake of amusing ourselves. We may 
say that we choose everything for the sake of some- 
thing else, excepting only happiness ; for it is the end. 
But to be serious and to labour for the sake of 
amusement seems silly and utterly childish ; while to 
amuse ourselves in order that we may be serious, as 



e, 4-7, 1.1 CONCLUSION. 337 

Anacharsis says, seems to be right; for amusement 
is a sort of recreation, and we need recreation because 
we are unable to work continuously. 

Recreation, then, cannot be the end ; for it is taken 
as a means to the exercise of our faculties. 

Again, the happy life is thought to be that which 
exhibits virtue ; and such a life must be serious and 
cannot consist in amcisement. 

7 Again, it is held that things of serious import- 
ance * are better than laughable and amusing things, 
and that the better the organ or the man, the more 
important is the function ; but we have already said 
that the function or exercise of that which is better 
is higher and more conducive to happiness. 

8 Again, the enjoyment of bodily pleasures is 
within the reach of anybody, of a slave no less than 
the best of men; but no one supposes that a slave 
can participate in happiness, seeing that he cannot 
even participate in our life. For indeed happiness 
does not consist in pastimes of this sort, but in the 
exercise of virtue, as we have already said. 

1 7. But if happiness be the exercise of virtue, it is of the 
reasonable to suppose that it will be the exercise of ma^h^^ 
the highest virtue ; and that will be the virtue or f<^V»^'il 
excellence of the best part of us. 

Now, that part or faculty — call it reason or what 

' you wiU — ^which seems naturally to rule and take 
the lead, and to apprehend things noble and divine— 

* rh orvoviaTd, It is impossible to convey in a translation the 
play upon the words (nrovS^ and cirovdaios : fnrovd'fi is earnestness ; 
cirovdaios usually = good : here, however, avovdaTos carries both 
senses, earnest or serious, and good. 



J 



338 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLB. [Bk. X. 

whether it be itaelf divine, or only the divinest part 
of us — ia the faculty the exercise of which, in its 
proper exceUence, will be perfect happiness. 

That this consists in speculation ^r contemplation 
we have already said. 

This conclusion would seem to agree both with 2 
what we have said above, and with known trutha 

This exercise of faculty must be the highest pos- 
sible ; for the reason is the highest of our £Ebcidties, 
and of all knowable things those that reason deals 
with are the highest. 

Again, it is the most continuous ; for speculation 
can be carried on more continuously than any kind 
of action whatsoever. 

We think too that pleasure ought to be erne of the 3 
ingredients of happiness ; but of all virtuous exercises 
it is allowed that the pleasantest is the exercise of 
wisdom.* At least philosophy t is thought to have 
pleasures that are admirable in purity and stead- 
fastness; and it is reasonable to suppose that the 
time passes more pleasantly with those who possess, 
than with those who are seeking knowledge. 

Again, what is called self-sufficiency will be most 4 
of all found in the speculative life. The necessaries 
of life, indeed, are needed by the wise man as well 
as by the just man and the rest; but, when these 
have been provided in due quantity, the just man 
further needs persons towards whom, and along with 
whom, he may act justly ; and so does the temperate 
and the courageous man and the rest; while the 

* ^ Korit rV (TO<pi<w iy4py€ia, the contemplation of abBolote truth, 
f The search for this tmth. 



7, 2-70 CONCLUSION. 339 

wise man is able to speculate even by himself, and 
the wiser he is the more is he able to do thia He 
could speculate better, we may confess, if he had 
others to help him, but nevertheless he is more self- 
sufOcient than anybody else. 
6 Again, it would seem that this life alone is desired 
solely for its own sake ; for it yields no result beyond 
lEe^Contemplation itself, while from all actions we 
get something more or less besides the action itself. 

6 Again, happiness is thought to imply leisure ; for 
we toil in order that we may have leisure, as we 
make war in order that we may eiyoy peace. Now, 
the practical virtues are exercised either in politics 
or in war; but these do not seem to be leisurely 
occupations : — 

War, indeed, seems to be quite the reverse of 
leisurely; for no one chooses to fight for fighting's 
sake, or arranges a war for that puq)ose : he would 
be deemed a bloodthirsty villain who should set 
friends at enmity in order that battles and slaughter 
might ensue. 

But the politician's life also is not a leisurely 
occupation, and, beside the practice of politics itself, 
it- brings power and honours, or at least happiness, to 
himself and his fellow-citizens, which is scanething 
different from politics ; for we {who are asking what 
happiness is] also ask what politics is, evidently 
implying that it is something different from happi- 

7 The life of the statesman and of the soldier, then, 
though they surpass all other virtuous exercises in 
nobility and grandeur, are not leisurely occupations. 



340 NICOMAOHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. X. 

and aim at some ulterior end, and are not desired 
merely for themselves. 

But the exercise of the reason seems to be superior 
in seriousness (since it contemplates truth), and to 
aim at no end beside itself, and to have its proper 
pleasure (which also helps to increase the exercise) ; 
and its exercise seems further to be self-sufficient, and 
leisurely, and inexhaustible (as far as anything human 
can be), and to have all the other characteristics that 
are ascribed to happiness. 

This, then, will be the complete happiness of man, 
i,e. when a complete term of days is added; for 
nothing incomplete can be admitted into our idea of 
happiness. 

But a life which realized this idea would be some- 8 
thing more than human; for it would not be the 
expression of man's nature, but of some divine element 
in that nature — the exercise of which is as far supe- 
rior to the exercise of the other kind of virtue \i,e. 
practical or moral virtue], as this divine element is 
superior to our compound human nature.* 

K then reason be divine as compared with man, 
the life which consists in the exercise of reason will 
also be divine in comparison with human life. Never- 
theless, instead of listening to those who advise us as 
men and mortals not to lift our thoughts above what 
is human and mortal, we ought rather, as far as pos- 
sible, to put off our mortality and make every effort 
to live in the exercise of the highest of our faculties ; 
for though it be but a small part of us, yet in power 
and value it far surpasses all the rest. 

* f .0. our nature as moral agents, as oomponnds of reason and 
desire. 



7, 8-8, 3.] CONCLUSION. 341 

And indeed this part would even seem to constitute 
our true self, since it is the sovereign and the better 
part. It would be strange, then, if a man were to 
prefer the life of something else to the life of his true 
self. 

Again, we may apply here what we said above — 
for every being that is best and pleasantest which 
is naturally proper to it. Since, then, it is the reason 
that in the truest sense is the man, the life that 
consists in the exercise of the reason is the best and 
pleasantest for man — and therefore the happiest 

1 8. The life that consists in the exercise of the ofthepr 

tiMLl life 

other kind of virtue is happy in a secondary sense ; ^F^^ 
for the manifestations of moral virtue are emphati- »«»»«.««; 

•*■ the rdatt 

caUy human [not divine]. Justice. I mean, and ^^^ 
p. courage, and the other moral virtues are displayed in ?JJ^^ 
\ our relations towards one another by the observance, 
in every case, of what is due in contracts and ser- 
vices, and all sorts of outward acts, as well as in our 
inward feelings. And all these seem to be emphati- 
cally human affairs. 

2 Again, moral virtue seems, in some points, to be 
actually a result of physical constitution, and in many 
points to be closely connected with the passions. 

3 Again, prudence is inseparably joined to moral 
virtue, and moral virtue to prudence, since the moral 
virtues determine the principles of prudence,* while 
prudence determines what is right in morals. 

But the moral virtues, being bound up with the 

* ♦.& the prineiples of morals cannot be proved, but are accepted 
without proof bj the man whose desires are properly trained. Cf. 
au^pra, I. 4^ 6. 



842 NIOOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ABISTOTLK [Bk. X. 

passions, must belong to our compound nature ; and • 
the virtues of the compound nature are emphatically 
human. Therefore the life whidi manifests them, 
and the haj^iness which consists in this, must be 
emphaticaUy human. 

But the happiness which Consists in the exercise of 
the reason is separate from the lower nature. (So 
much we may be allowed to assert about it : a detailed 
discussion is beyond our present purpose.) 

Further, this happiness would seem to need but a 4 
small supply of external goods, certainly less than the 
moral life needs. Both need the necessaries of life to 
the same extent, let us say ; for though, in fact, the 
politician takes more care of his pers<Hi thsoi the 
philosopher, yet the difference will be quite incon- 
siderable. But in what they need for their activities 
there will be a great difference. Wealtihi will be 
needed by the liberal man, that he may act liberally ; 
by the just man, that he may discharge his obliga- 
tions (for a mere wish caamot be tested, — even 
unjust people pretend a wish to act justly); the 
courageous maa wiU need strength if he is to execute 
any deed of courage ; and the temperate man liberty 
of indulgence, — ^for how else can he, or the possessor of 
any other virtue, show what he is ? 

Again, people dispute whether the purpose or the 5 
action be more essential to virtue, virtue being under- 
stood to imply both. It is plain, then, that both are 
necessary to completeness. But many things are 
needed for action, and the greater and nobler the 
action, the more is needed. 

On the other hand, he who is engaged in specula- 6 



8, 4-7.] CONCLUSION. 343 

tion needs none of these things for his work ; nay, it 
may even be said that they are a hindrance to 
speculation: but as a man living with other men, 
he chooses to act virtuously; and so he will need 
things of this sort to enable him to behave like a 
man. 
r That perfect happiness is some kind of speculative 
activity may also be shown in the foUowing way :— 

It is always supposed that the gods are, of all 
beings, the most blessed and happy ; but what kind 
of actions shall we ascribe to them ? Acts of justice ? 
Surely it is ridiculous to conceive the gods engaged 

of courage ? Can we conceive them enduring fearful 
things and fa<;ing danger because it is noble to do 
80 ? Or acts of liberality ? But to whom are they to 
give ? and is it not absurd to suppose that they have 
money or anything of that kind ? And what could 
acts of temperance mean with them? Surely it 
would be an insult to praise them for having no evil 
desires. In short, if we were to go through the 
whole list, we should find that all action is petty and 
unwodihy of the goda 

And yet it is universally supposed that they live, 
and therefore that they exert their powers ; for we 
cannot suppose that they lie asleep like Endymion. 

Now, if a being Uves, and action cannot be 

ascribed to him, stiU less production, what remains 

I but contemplation ? It follows, then, that the divine 

life, which surpasses all others in blessedness, consists 

in contemplation. 

Of all modes of human activity, therefore, that 



i 



[ 




I 



3i4 NIOOMAOHEAN ETHICS OF AEISTOTLE. [Bk. X. 

which is most akin to this will be capable of the 
greatest happiness. 

And this is further confirmed by the fact that the a 
other animals do not participate in happiness, being 
quite incapable of this kind of activity. For the life 
of the gods is entirely blessed, and the life of man is 
blessed just so far as he attains to some likeness 
of this kind of activity ; but none of the other animals 
are happy, since they are quite incapable of con- 
templation. 

Happiness, then, extends just so far as contempla- 
tion, and the more contemplation the more happiness 
is there in a life, — ^not accidentally, but as a necessary 
accompaniment of the contemplation; for contem- 
plation is precious in itself. 

Our conclusion, then, is that happiness is a kind of 
speculation or contemplation. 

But as we are men we shall need external good 9 
fortune also : for our nature does not itself provide aU 
that is necessary for contemplation ; the body must 
be in health, and supplied with food, and otherwise 
cared for. We must not, however, suppose that 
because it is impossible to be happy without external 
good things, therefore a man who is to be happy will 
want many things or much. It is not the super- 
abundance of good things that makes a man inde- 
pendent, or enables him to act ; and a man may do 10 
noble deeds, though he be not ruler of land and sea. 
A moderate equipment may give you opportunity for 
virtuous action. 

It is easy to find illustrations of this. Private 
persons seem to do what is right not less, but rather 



8, 8-lS.] CONCLUSION. 345 

more, than princes. And so much as gives this oppor- 
tunity is enough ; for that man's life will be happy 
who has virtue and exercises it. 

11 Solon too, I think, gave a good description of the 
happy man when he said that, in his opinion, he was 
a man who was moderately supplied with the gifts of 
fortune, but had done the noblest deeds, and lived 
temperately ; for a man who has but modest means 
may do his duty. 

Anaxagoras also seems to have held that the 
happy man was neither a rich man nor a prince ; for 
he said that he should not he surprised if the happy 
man were one whom the masses could hardly believe 
to be so; for they judge by the outside, which is 
all they can appreciate. 

L2 The opinions of the wise, then, seem to agree with 
our theory. But though these opinions carry some 
weight, the test of truth in matters of practice is 
to be found in the facts of life ; for it is in them that 
the supreme authority resides. The theories we have 
advanced, therefore, should be tested by comparison 
with the facts of life; and if they agree with the 
facts, they should be accepted, but if they disagree 
they should be accounted mere theories. 

13 But, once more, the man who exercises his reason 
and cultivates it, and has it in the best condition, 
seems also to be the most beloved of heaven. For 
if the gods take any care for men, as they are thought 
to do, it is reasonable to suppose that they delight 
in that which is best in man and most akin to them- 
selves (i,e, the reason), and that they requite those 
who show the greatest love and reverence for it, as 



846 KIGOMAGHEAK ETHICS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk. X. 

caring for that which is dear to themselves and doing 
rightly and nobly. But it is plain that all these 
points are found most of all in the wise man. The 
wise man, therefore, is the most bekryed of heaven ; 
and therefore, we may conclude, the happiest. 

In this way also, therefore^ the wise man will be 
happier than any one else. 
Wow is the 9. Now that we have treated (sufficiently, though i 
rea,iz€dT summarily) of these matters, and of the virtues, and 
also of fiiendship and pleasure, are we to suppose that 
we have attidned the end we proposed ? Nay, surely 
the saying holds good, that in practical matters the 
end is not a mere speculative knowledge of what is 
to be done, but rather the doing of it It is not 2 
enough to know about virtue, then, but we must 
endeavour to possess it and to use it, or to take any 
other steps that may make us good. 

Now, if theories alone were sufficient to make 3 
people good, th^y would deservedly receive many 
and great rewards, to use the words of Theognis ; but, 
in fact, it seems that though they are potent to guide 
and to stimulate liberal-minded young men, and 
though a generous disposition, with a sincere love of 
what is noble, may by them be opened to the in- 
fluence of virtue, yet they are powerless to turn the 
mass of men to goodness. For the generality of men 4 
are naturally apt to be swayed by fear rather than 
by reverence, and to refrain from evil rather because 
of the punishment that it brings than because of its 
own foulnesa For under the guidance of their 
passions they pursue the pleasures that suit th^ir 
nature and the means by which those pleasures may 



/ 
J 



9, 1-8.] CONCLUSION. 347 

be obtained, aootd avoid the opposite pains, while of 
that which is noble and truly pleasant they have not 
even a conception, as they have never tasted it. 

5 /what theories or arguments, then, can bring such 
m^i as these to order? Siu*ely it is impossible, or 
at least very diflScult, to remove by any argument 
what has long been ingrained in the character. For 
my part, I think we must be well content if we can 
get some modicum of virtue when all the circum- 
stances are present that seem to make men good. 

B Now, what makes men good is held by some to 
be nature, by others habit [or training], by others 
instruction. 

As for the goodness that comes by nature, it is 
plain that it is not within our control, but is bestowed 
by some divine agency on certain people who truly 
deserve to be called fortunate. 

As for theory or instructicm, I fear that it cannot 
avail in all cases, but that the hearer^s soul must be 
prepared by training it to feel delight and aversion 
on the right occasions, just as the soil must be pre- 

J pared if the seed is to thrive. For if Qe lives imder 
the sway of his passions, he will not nsten to the 
arguments by which you would dissuade him, nor 
even understand them. And when he is in this state, 
how can you change his mind by argument ? To 
put it roundly, passion seems to yield to force only, 

( and not to reason. The character, then, must be 

» already * formed, so as to be in some way a^^^ ^ 
virtue, loving what is noble and hating wh^^ • ^ "base. 
• But to get right guidance from youtlx -i Vo- ^^ 

* Before theory or instruction can be any V 



348 NIGOMAGHEAK ETHIGS OF ABISTOTLE. [Bk. X 

road to virtue is hard, unless we are brought up 
under suitable laws ; for to live temperately and re- 
gularly is not pleasant to the generality of men, 
especially to the young. Our nurture, then, should 
be prescribed by law, and our whole way of life ; for 
it will cease to be painful as we get accustomed to it. 
And I venture to think that it is not enough to get 9 
proper nurture and training when we are young, but 
that as we ought to carry on the same way of life 
after we are grown up, and to confirm these habits, 
we need the intervention of the law in these matters 
also, and indeed, to put it roundly, in our whole life. 
For the generality of men are more readily swayed 
by compulsion than by reason, and by fear of punish- 
ment than by desire for what is noble. 

For this reason, some hold that the legislator l( 
should, in the first instance, invite the people and 
exhort them to be virtuous because of the nobility 
of virtue, as those who have been well trained 
will listen to him; but that when they will not 
listen, or are of less noble nature, he should apply 
correction and punishment, and banish utterly those 
who are incorrigible. For the good man, who takes 
what is noble as his guide, will listen to reason, but 
he who is not good, whose desires are set on pleasure, 
must be corrected by pain like a beast of burden. 
And for this reason, also, they say the pains to be 
applied must be those that are most contrary to the 
pleasures which the culprit loves. 

As we have said, then, he who is to be good must u 
be well nurtured and trained, and thereafter must 
•continue in a like excellent way of life, and must never. 



9, 9-U.] CONCLUSION. 349 

either voluntarily or involuntarily, do anything vile ; 
and /this can only be effected if men live subject to 
some kind of reason and proper regimen, backed by 
force. ' 
12 Now, the paternal rule has not the requisite force 
or power of compulsion, nor has the rule of any 
individual, unless he be a king or something like 
one; but the law has a compulsory power, and at 
the same time is a rational ordinance proceeding from 
a kind of prudence or reason.* / And whereas we 
take offence at individuals who oppose our inclina- 
tions, even though their opposition is right, we do 
not feel aggrieved when the law bids us do what is 
right. ' 

13 But Sparta is (with a few exceptions) the only 
state where the legislator seems to have paid atten- 
tion to the nurture and mode of life of the citizens. 
In most states these matters are entirely neglected, 
and each man lives as he likes, ruling wife and 
children in Cyclopean fashion, f ' 

14 It would be best, then, that the regulation of 
these matters should be undertaken and properly 
carried out by the state, and that individuals shoidd 
be able to render this service to the community ; but 
as the state neglects it, it would seem that we should 
each individually help (or at least, try to help) our 
own children or friends on the road to virtue. J 

Now, it would seem from what has been said that 
to enable one to do this the best plan would be to 
learn how to legislate. For state training is carried 
on by means of laws, and is good when the laws are 

• Cf. TI. 8, I'd. t Of' Horn. Od. ix. 114. J Cf. I. «, B. • 



350 NIOOMACHEAK ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. X. 

good; but it woidd seem to make no difference 
whether the laws be written or unwritten, nor wiiether 
they regulate the education of one person or many, 
any more than it does in the case of music, or gym- 
nastics, or any other course of training. For as in 
the state that pre^^B which is ordained by law ^md 
custom, so in the household that which is ordained 
by the word of the father of the family and by 
custom prevails no less, or even more, because of the 
ties of kinship and of obligation ; for affection anid 
obedience are already implaxited by nature in the 
members of the fanuly. 

Moreover, ui spite of what has just b^n said, ii 
individual treatment is better than treatment by 
masses, in education no leas than in medicina As a 
general xtde, repose and fia^sting are good for a fever 
patient, but in a particular case they may not be 
good. A teacher of bo;sing, I suppose, does not re- 
commend every one to adopt the same style. It 
would seem, then, that individuals are educated more 
perfectly under a system of private education; for 
then each gets more precisely what he needs. 

But you will best be able to treat an individual 
case (whether you are a doctor, or a trainer, or any- 
thing else) when you know the general rule, " Such 
and such a thing is good for all men," or " for all of a 
certain temperament;" for science is said to deal, 
and does deal, with that which is common to a 
number of individuals. 

I do not mean to deny that it may be quite pos- 16 
sible to treat an individual weU, even without any 
scientific knowledge, if you know precisely by ex- 



9, 15-18.] OONCLUfilON, 351 

perience tke effect of particular eauses upon him, 
JTist as some men seem to be able to treat themselves 
better than any doctor, though they would be quite 
unable to prescribe for another person. 

But, nevertheless, I venture to say that if a man 
wishes to master any art, or to gain a scientific know- 
ledge of it, he must advance to its general principles, 
and make himself acquainted with them in the 
proper method; for, as we have said, it is with 
xmiversal propositions that the sciences deal. 

L7 And so I think that he who wishes to make men 
better by training (whether mitny or few) should 
try to acquire the art or science of legislation, sup- 
posing that men may be made good by tbe iflgency of 
law. For fairly to mould the chaj'ftcter of any 
person 4ihat may present himself is not a thing that 
can be done by anybody, but (if at aU) only by him 
who has knowledge, just as is the case in medicine 
and other professions where careful treatment and 
prudence are required. 

18 Our next business, th^Q, I think, is to inquire 
from whom or by what means we are to learn the 
science or art of legislation. 

^'As we learn the other arts," it will be said, — 
" i,e, from the politicians who practise it : for we found 
that legislation is a part of poKtios." 

But I think the case is not quite the same with 
politics as with the other sciences and arts. For in 
other cases it is plain that the same people eommuni- 
cate the art and practise it, as physicians and painters 
do. But in the case of politics, while the sophists pro- 
fess to teach the art, it is never they that practise itj 



352 NICOMAOHEAN ETmOS OF AEISTOTLB. [Bk. X. 

but the statesmen. And the statesmen would seem to 
act by some instinctive faculty, proceeding empirically 
rather than by reasoning. For it is plain that they 
never write or speak about these matters (though 
perhaps that were better than making speeches in the 
courts or the assembly), and have never communi- 
cated the art to their sons or to any of their friends, li 
And yet we might expect that they would have 
done so if they could ; for they could have left no 
better legacy to their country, nor have chosen any- 
thing more precious than this power as a possession 
for themselves, and, therefore, for those dearest to 
them. 

Experience, however, seems, we must allow, to b^ 
of great service here; for otherwise people would 
never become statesmen by familiarity with politics. 
Those who wish for a knowledge of statesmanship, 
then, seem to need experience [as well as theory]. 

But those sophists who profess to teach states- 20 
manship seem to be ludicrously incapable of fulfilling 
their promises: for, to speak roundly, they do not 
even know what it is or what it deals with. If they 
did know, they would not make it identical with 
rhetoric, or inferior to it, nor would they think it 
was easy to frame a system of laws when you had 
made a collection of the most approved of existing 
laws. " It is but a matter of picking out the best," 
they say, ignoring the fact that this selection requires 
understanding, and that to judge correctly is a matter 
of the greatest difficulty here, as in music. Those 
who have special experience in any department can 
pass a correct judgment upon the result, and under- 



V 



^ 19-28.] CONCLUSION. 353 



^■Mand bow and by what means it is produced, and 

^H^bat combinations are barmonious; but those who 

have no special experience must be content if tbey 

are able to say whether the result is good or bad — as, 

for instance, in the case of painting. Now, laws are 

^tJle work or result, so to speak, of statesmanship. 
■How then could a collection of laws make a man ablp 
to legislate, or to pick out the best of the collection ? 

21 Even the art of healing, it seems, can not be 
taught by compendia. And yet the medical com- 
pendia try to tell you not only the remedies, but how 
to apply them, and how to ti-eat the several elaases of 
patients, distinguishing them according to their tem- 
perament. But all this, though it may be serviceable 

»to those who have experience, would seem to be quite 
oseless to those who know nothing of medicine. 
So also, I think we may say, collections of laws 
and constitutions may be very serviceable to those 
who are able to examine them with a discriminating 
eye, and to judge whether an ordinance is good or 

kbad, and what ordinances agree with one another; 
but if people who have not the trained faculty go 
through such compendia, they cannot judge properly 
(unless indeed a coiTect judgment comes of itself), 
though tbey may perhaps sharpen their intelligence 
in these matters, 

22 Since then our predecessors have left this matter 
of legislation uninvestigated, it will perhaps be better 
ourselves to inquire into it, and indeed into the 

» whole question of the management of a state, in order 
Fthat our philosophy of human life may be completed 
I to the best of our power. 

2 a 



354 NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE. [Bk. X. 

Let US try, then, first of all, to consider any valu- 23 
able utterances that our predecessors have made upon 
this or that branch of the subject; and then, look- 
ing at our collection of constitutions, let us inquire 
what things tend to preserve or to destroy states, and 
what things tend to preserve or destroy the several 
kinds of constitution, and what are the causes of the 
good government of some states and the misgovem- 
ment of others : for when we have got an insight 
into these matters we shall, I think, be better able to 
see what is the best kind of constitution, and what is 
the best arrangement of each of the several kinds ; 
that is to say, what system of laws and customs is 
best suited to each. 

Let us begin thea* 

* The work to which this conclusion forms a preface is the 
Politics of Aristotlei still extant, but in an incomplete state. 



THE E\D./^ 



PRINTED BY WILLIAM CLOWES AND SONS, LIMITED, LONDON AND hBCCLlIS, 



TNtKAL aboKBINOINO CO. 



^ ^ \V 



'■■■liiiiil f ^ ' 



3 bias DID 233 23S 



STANFORD UNIVERSITY LIBRARIES 

STANFORD AUXILIARY LIBRARY 

STANFORD, CALIFORNIA 94305-6004 

(415] 723-9201 

All books may be recoiled offer 7 doys 



DATE DUE 



DEC 19 1^95 



^^^