Skip to main content

Full text of "Plato and Platonism : a series of lectures"

See other formats


rch 
vs 
' 
ate 
‘ 
: 


bas 

ΠῚ 

ra 
: 


5 κι 
ΟΝ r.> 
ὁ ὦ ΠῚ 
Pibyn ee S 
ἐτοζεές 
και . 
<a 


‘aoa via 
ee enn γ᾽ is 
wise 
‘ νὐπιῖτεςε 
Seria hast ies 
‘ ἜΣ : 
es, ds noe 
hot bet er 
4.» Ἢ 
πές τὴ ΜΝ 
re : 


εὖ 


ie . 
ϑάδηνενα 
τὸν 
ἐν τὸς 
“ταν 
Sh νεὼν 4 
τν κἢ 


= oon 
‘ 24 


as in 2011 \ with funding from 


Digitized by the Ἕ Archive 


niversity of Toronto 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


MACMILLAN AND CO., LIMITED 
LONDON : BOMBAY - CALCUTTA 
MELBOURNE 
THE MACMILLAN COMPANY 
NEW YORK - BOSTON - CHICAGO 
ATLANTA - SAN FRANCISCO 
THE MACMILLAN CO. OF CANADA, LTD. 
TORONTO 


ΙΡΡΙΑΤΟ 
AND PLATON 


A SERIES OF LECTURES ᾿ 


ΒΥ 


WALTER /PATER/ 


‘Qs φιλοσοφιας μὲν οὔσης μεγιστης μουσικῆς 


MACMILLAN AND CO., LIMITED 
ST. MARTIN’S STREET, LONDON 
Ι910 


\— LIBRARY 


WOE er 
RET Ua πο σ ΔΑΝ ΄' 


First Edition 1893 
Second Edition 1895; Reprinted 1896, 1897 
Edition de Luxe 190t 
Third Edition 1901 ; Reprinted 1902, 1905, 1907, 1909 
Library Edition 1910 


Tue Lectures of which this volume is com- 
posed were written for delivery to some young 
students of philosophy, and are now printed 
with the hope of interesting a larger number 
of them. By Platonism is meant not Neo- 
Platonism of any kind, but the leading principles 
of Plato’s doctrine, which I have tried to see in 
close connexion with himself as he is presented 


in his own writings. 
Wea 8 


P. VI I B 


ἵ CONTENTS 

CHAP, 

1. PLATO AND THE DOCTRINE OF MOTION 
2. PLATO AND THE DOCTRINE OF REST 


. PLATO AND SOCRATES 

. PLATO AND THE SOPHISTS 

. THE GENIUS OF PLATO . 

. THE DOCTRINE OF PLATO— 


I, THE THEORY OF IDEAS 


Y AWN | ὦ 


II. DIALEcTIC 
8. LACED/EMON 
9. THE REPUBLIC 
¥ το. PLATO'S AESTHETICS 


. PLATO AND THE DOCTRINE OF NUMBER . 


ἽΝ 


uf 
Cea ie 
th 


Ἧ 
Σ 
᾽ 


eas, ! 


PLATO AND THE DOCTRINE OF MOTION 


Wiru the world of intellectual production, as 
with that of organic generation, nature makes 
no sudden starts. Natura nihil facit per saltum ; 
and in the history of philosophy there are no 
absolute beginnings. Fix where we may the 
origin of this or that doctrine or idea, the 
doctrine of “reminiscence,” for instance, or of 
“the perpetual flux,” the theory of “induction,” 
or the philosophic view of things generally, 
the specialist will still be able to find us some 
earlier anticipation of that doctrine, that mental 
tendency. ‘The most elementary act of mental 
analysis takes time to do; the most rudimentary 
sort of speculative knowledge, abstractions so 
simple that we can hardly conceive the human 
mind without them, must grow, and with 
difficulty. Philosophy itself, mental and moral, 
has its preparation, its forethoughts, in the 
poetry that preceded it. A powerful general- 
isation thrown into some salient phrase, such as 
| 5 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


that of Heraclitus—Tldvra ῥεῖ, all things fleet 
away—may startle a particular age by its novelty, 
but takes possession only because all along its 
root was somewhere among the natural though 
but half-developed instincts of the human mind 
itself. 

Plato has seemed to many to have been 
scarcely less than the creator of philosophy ; and 
it is an immense advance he makes, from the 
crude or turbid beginnings of scientific enquiry 
with the Ionians or the Eleatics, to that wide 
range of perfectly finished philosophical litera- 
ture. His encyclopedic view of the whole 
domain of knowledge is more than a mere step 
in a progress. Nothing that went before it, for 
compass and power and charm, had been really 
comparable to it. Plato’s achievement may 
well seem an absolutely fresh thing in the morn- 
ing of the mind’s history. Yet in truth the 
world Plato had entered into was already almost 
weary of philosophical debate, bewildered by 
the oppositions of sects, the claims of rival 
schools. Language and the processes of thought 
were already become sophisticated, the very air 
he breathed sickly with off-cast speculative 
atoms. 

In the Tzmeus, dealing with the origin of the 
universe he figures less as the author of a new 
theory, than as already an eclectic critic of older 
ones, himself somewhat perplexed by theory 
and counter-theory. And as we find there a 

6 


THE DOCTRINE OF MOTION 


sort of storehouse of all physical theories, so 
in reading the Parmenides we might think that 
all metaphysical questions whatever had already 
passed through the mind of Plato. Some of the 
results of patient earlier thinkers, even then dead 
and gone, are of the structure of his philosophy. 
They are everywhere in it, not as the stray 
carved corner of some older edifice, to be found 
here or there amid the new, but rather like 
minute relics of earlier organic life in the very 
stone he builds with. The central and most 
intimate principles of his teaching challenge us 
to go back beyond them, not merely to his 
own immediate, somewhat enigmatic master— 
to Socrates, who survives chiefly in his pages— 
but to various precedent schools of speculative 
thought, in Greece, in Ionia, in Italy ; beyond 
these into that age of poetry, in which the first 
efforts of philosophic apprehension had hardly 
understood themselves; beyond that uncon- 
scious philosophy, again, to certain constitutional 
tendencies, persuasions, forecasts of the intellect 
itself, such as had given birth, it would seem, 
to thoughts akin to Plato’s in the older civilisa- 
tions of India and of Egypt, as they still exercise 
their authority over ourselves. 

The thoughts of Plato, like the language he 
has to use (we find it so again, in turn, with 
those predecessors of his, when we pass from 
him to them) are covered with the traces of 
previous labour and have had their earlier 

7 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


proprietors. If at times we become aware in 
reading him of certain anticipations of modern 
knowledge, we are also quite obviously among 
the relics of an older, a poetic or half-visionary 
world. It is hardly an exaggeration to say that 
in Plato, in spite of his wonderful savour of 
literary freshness, there is nothing absolutely 
new: or rather, as in many other very original 
products of human genius, the seemingly new 18 
old also, a palimpsest, a tapestry of which the 
actual threads have served before, or like the 
animal frame itself, every particle of which 
has already lived and died many times over. 
Nothing but the life-giving principle of cohesion 
is new; the new perspective, the resultant 
complexion, the expressiveness which familiar 
thoughts attain by novel juxtaposition. In 
other words, the form is new. But then, in the 
creation of philosophical literature, as in all 
other products of art, form, in the full significa- 
tion of that word, is everything, and the mere 
matter is nothing. 


There are three different ways in which the 
criticism of philosophic, of all speculative opinion 
whatever, may be conducted. The doctrines of 
Plato’s Repubsic, for instance, may be regarded as 
so much truth or falsehood, to be accepted or 
rejected as such by the student of to-day. That 
is the dogmatic method of criticism ; judging 
every product of human thought, however alien 

8 


THE DOCTRINE OF MOTION 


or distant from one’s self, by its congruity with 
the assumptions of Bacon or Spinoza, of Mill or 
Hegel, according to the mental preference of the 
particular critic. There is, secondly, the more 
generous, eclectic or syncretic method, which 
aims at a selection from contending schools of 
the various grains of truth dispersed among them. 
It is the method which has prevailed in periods 
of large reading but with little inceptive force 
of their own, like that of the Alexandrian Neo- 
Platonism in the third century, or the Neo- 
Platonism of Florence in the fifteenth. Its 
natural defect is in the tendency to misrepresent 
the true character of the doctrine it professes to 
explain, that it may harmonise thus the better 
with the other elements of a pre-conceived 
system. 

Dogmatic and eclectic criticism alike have in 
our own century, under the influence of Hegel 
and his predominant theory of the ever-chang- 
ing “ Time-spirit”” or Zezt-geist, given way to a 
third method of criticism, the historic method, 
which bids us replace the doctrine, or the 
system, we are busy with, or such an ancient 
monument of philosophic thought as The Re- 
public, as far as possible in the group of con- 
ditions, intellectual, social, material, amid which 
it was actually produced, if we would really 
understand it. ‘That ages have their genius as 
well as the individual ; that in every age there 
is a peculiar ensemble of conditions which deter- 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


mines a common character in every product of 
that age, in business and art, in fashion and 
speculation, in religion and manners, in men’s 
very faces ; that nothing man has projected from 
himself is really intelligible except at its own 
date, and from its proper point of view in the 
never-resting “‘ secular process” ; the solidarity of 
philosophy, of the intellectual life, with common 
or general history; that what it behoves the 
student of philosophic systems to cultivate is the 
“historic sense”: by force of these convictions 
many a normal, or at first sight abnormal, phase 
of speculation has found a reasonable meaning 
for us. As the strangely twisted pine-tree, 
which would be a freak of nature on an English 
lawn, is seen, if we replace it, in thought, amid 
the contending forces of the Alpine torrent that 
actually shaped its growth, to have been the 
creature of necessity, of the logic of certain facts ; 
so, beliefs the most fantastic, the ““ communism ” 
of Plato, for instance, have their natural propriety 
when duly correlated with those facts, those 
conditions round about them; of which they are 
in truth a part. 

In the intellectual as in the organic world the 
given product, its normal or abnormal charac- 
teristics, are determined, as people say, by the 
“environment.” The business of the young 
scholar therefore, in reading Plato, is not to 
take his side in a controversy, to adopt or refute 
Plato’s opinions, to modify, or make apology for, 

10 


THE DOCTRINE OF MOTION 


what may seem erratic or impossible in him ; 
still less, to furnish himself with arguments on 
behalf of some theory or conviction of his own. 
His duty is rather to follow intelligently, but 


with strict indifference, the mental process there, 


as he might witness a game of skill ; better still, 
as in reading Hamlet or The Divine Comedy, so in 
reading The Republic, to watch, for its dramatic 
interest, the spectacle of a powerful, of a sovereign 
intellect, translating itself, amid a complex group 
of conditions which can never in the nature of 
things occur again, at once pliant and resistant 
to them, into a great literary monument. To 
put Plato into his natural place, as a result 
from antecedent and contemporary movements 
of Greek speculation, of Greek life generally : 
such is the proper aim of the historic, that is 
to say, of the really critical study of him. 


At the threshold, then, of The Republic of 
Plato, the historic spirit impresses upon us the 
fact that some of its leading thoughts are 
partly derivative from earlier thinkers, of whom 
we happen to possess independent information. 
From that brilliant and busy, yet so unconcerned 
press of early Greek life, one here another there 
stands aside to make the initial act of conscious 
philosophic reflexion. It is done with some- 
thing of the simplicity, the immediate and 
visible effectiveness, of the visible world in action 
all around. Among Plato’s many intellectual 

11 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


predecessors, on whom in recent years much 
attention has been bestowed by ἃ host of 
commentators after the mind of Hegel, three, 
whose ideas, whose words even, we really find 
in the very texture of Plato’s work, emerge 
distinctly in close connexion with The Republic : 
Pythagoras, the dim, half-legendary founder of the 
philosophy of number and music; Parmenides, 
““My father Parmenides,” the centre of the 
school of Elea; Heraclitus, thirdly, author of 
the doctrine of “‘the Perpetual Flux”: three 
teachers, it must be admitted after all, of whom 
what knowledge we have is to the utmost degree 
fragmentary and vague. But then, one way of 
giving that knowledge greater definiteness is by 
noting their direct and actual influence in Plato’s 
writings. 

Heraclitus, a writer of philosophy in prose, 
yet of a philosophy which was half poetic figure, 
half generalised fact, in style crabbed and obscure, 
but stimulant, invasive, not to be forgotten—he 
too might be thought, as a writer of prose, one 
of the “‘ fathers” of Plato. His influence, how- 
ever, on Plato, though himself a Heraclitean in 
early life, was by way of antagonism or reaction ; 
Plato’s stand against any philosophy of motion 
becoming, as we say, something of a “fixed 
idea” with him. Heraclitus of Ephesus (what 
Ephesus must have been just then is denoted by 
the fact that it was one of the twelve cities of 
the [onian League) died about forty years before 

12 


THE DOCTRINE OF MOTION 


Plato was born. Here then at Ephesus, the 
much frequented centre of the religious life of 
Ionia, itself so lately emancipated from its 
tyrants, Heraclitus, of ancient hereditary rank, 
an aristocrat by birth and temper, amid all the 
bustle of still undiscredited Greek democracy, 
had reflected, not to his peace of mind, on the 
mutable character of political as well as of 
physical existence ; perhaps, early as it was, on 
the mutability of intellectual systems also, that 
modes of thought and practice had already been 
in and out of fashion. Empires certainly had 
lived and died around; and in Ephesus as else- 
where, the privileged class had gone to the wall. 
In this era of unrestrained youthfulness, of Greek 
youthfulness, one of the haughtiest of that class, 
as being also of nature’s aristocracy, and a man 
of powerful intellectual gifts, Heraclitus, asserts 
the native liberty of thought at all events ; 
becomes, we might truly say, sickly with “the 
pale cast” of his philosophical questioning. 
Amid the irreflective actors in that rapidly 
moving show, so entirely immersed in it 
superficial as it is that they have no feeling of 
themselves, he becomes self-conscious. He re- 
flects; and his reflexion has the characteristic 
melancholy of youth when it is forced suddenly 
to bethink itself, and for a moment feels already 
old, feels the temperature of the world about 
it sensibly colder. Its very ingenuousnes, its 
sincerity, will make the utterance of what comes 
13 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


to mind just then somewhat shrill or over- 
emphatic. 

Yet Heraclitus, thus superbly turning aside 
from the vulgar to think, so early in the 
impetuous spring-tide of Greek history, does 
but reflect after all the aspect of what actually 
surrounds him, when he cries out—his philo- 
sophy was no matter of formal treatise or system, 
but of harsh, protesting cries—TIlavra χωρεῖ καὶ 
οὐδὲν μένε. All things give way: nothing 
remaineth. There had been enquirers before 
him of another sort, purely physical enquirers, 
whose bold, contradictory, seemingly impious 
guesses how and of what primary elements the 
world of visible things, the sun, the stars, the 
brutes, their own souls and bodies, had been 
composed, were themselves a part of the bold 
enterprise of that romantic age; a series of 
intellectual adventures, of a piece with its 
adventures in unknown lands or upon the sea. 
The resultant intellectual chaos expressed the 
very spirit of gifted and sanguine but insub- 
ordinate youth (remember, that the word νεότης, 
youth, came to mean rashness, insolence !) 
questioning, deciding, rejecting, on mere rags 
and tatters of evidence, unbent to discipline, 
unmethodical, irresponsible. Those opinions 
too, coming and going, those conjectures as to 
what under-lay the sensible world, were them- 
selves but fluid elements on the changing surface 
of existence. 

14 


THE DOCTRINE OF MOTION 


Surface, we say; but was there really any- 
thing beneath it? That was what to the 
majority of his hearers, his readers, Heraclitus, 
with an eye perhaps on practice, seemed to 
deny. Perpetual motion, alike in things and 
in men’s thoughts about them,—the sad, self- 
conscious, philosophy of Heraclitus, like one, 
knowing beyond his years, in this barely 
adolescent world which he is so eager to instruct, 
makes no pretence to be able to restrain that. 
Was not the very essence of thought itself also 
such perpetual motion? a baffling transition from 
the dead past, alive one moment since, to a 
present, itself deceased in turn ere we can say, 
It is here? A keen analyst of the facts of 
nature and mind, a master presumably of all the 
knowledge that then there was, a vigorous 
definer of thoughts, he does but refer the 
superficial movement of all persons and things 
around him to deeper and still more masterful 
currents of universal change, stealthily with- 
drawing the apparently solid earth itself from 
beneath one’s feet. The principle of disinte- 
gration, the incoherency of fire or flood (for 
Heraclitus these are but very lively instances 
of movements, subtler yet more wasteful still) 
are inherent in the primary elements alike of 
matter and of the soul. Aéyeu που Ἡράκλειτος, Says 
Socrates in the Cratylus, ὅτι πάντα χωρεῖ καὶ οὐδὲν 
μένε. But the principle of lapse, of waste, was, 
in fact, in one’s self. ‘No one has ever passed 

15 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


twice over the same stream.”” Nay, the passenger 
himself is without identity. Upon the same 
stream at the same moment we do, and do not, 
embark: for we are, and are not: εἶμέν τε καὶ 
οὐκ εἶμεν. And this rapid change, if it did not 
make all knowledge impossible, made it wholly 
relative, of a kind, that is to say, valueless in the 
judgment of Plato. Man, the individual, at this 
particular vanishing-point of time and _ place, 
becomes “ the measure of all things.” 


To know after what manner (says Socrates, after discuss- 
ing the question in what proportion names, fleeting names, 
contribute to our knowledge of things) to know after what 
manner we must be taught, or discover for ourselves, the 
things that really are (τὰ ὄντα) is perhaps beyond the measure 
of your powers and mine. We must even content ourselves 
with the admission of this, that not from their names, but 
much rather themselves from themselves, they must be learned 
and looked for. . . . For consider, Cratylus, a point I oft-times 
dream on—whether or no we may affirm that what is beautiful 
and good in itself, and whatever is, respectively, in itself, zs 
something καὶ 

Cratylus. ‘To me at least, Socrates, it seems to be some- 
thing. 

Socrates. Let us consider, then, that ‘in-itself’; not 
whether a face, or anything of that kind, is beautiful, and 
whether all these things seem to flow like water. But, what 
is beautiful in itself—may we say ?—has not this the qualities 
that define it, always? 

Cratylus. It must be so. 

Socrates. Can we then, if it is ever passing out below, 
predicate about it ; first, that it zs that; next, that it has this 
or that guality; or must it not be that, even as we speak, it 
should straightway become some other thing, and go out under 
on its way, and be no longer as it is? . . . Now, how could 
that which is never in the same state be a thing at all? ... 


16 


THE DOCTRINE OF MOTION 


Nor, in truth, could it be an object of knowledge to any one ; 
for, even as he who shall know comes upon it, it would become 
another thing with other qualities; so that it would be no 
longer matter of knowledge what sort of a thing it is, or in 
what condition. Now, no form of knowing, methinks, has 
knowledge of that which it knows to be no-how. 

Cratylus. It is as you say. 

Socrates. But if, Cratylus, all things change sides, and 
nothing stays, it is not fitting to say that there is any 
knowing at all. . . . And the consequence of this argument 
would be, that there is neither any one to know, nor anything 
to be known. If, on the other hand, there be always that 
which knows, and that which is known; and if the Beautiful 
is, and the Good zs, and each one of those things that really 
are, 7s, then, to my thinking, those things in no way resemble 
that moving stream of which we are now speaking. Whether, 
then, these matters be thus, or in that other way as the followers 
of Heraclitus affirm and many besides, I fear may be no easy 
thing to search out. But certainly it is not like a sensible 
man, committing one’s self, and one’s own soul, to the rule of 
names, to serve them, and, with faith in names and those who 
imposed them, as if one knew something thereby, to maintain 
(damaging thus the character of that which is, and our own) 
that there is no sound ring in any one of them, but that all, 
like earthen pots, let water. Cratylus, 439. 


Yet from certain fragments in which the 
Logos is already named we may understand that 
there had been another side to the doctrine of 
Heraclitus ; an attempt on his part, after all, to 
reduce that world of chaotic mutation to cosmos, 
to the unity of a reasonable order, by the search 
for and the notation, if there be such, of an. 
antiphonal rhythm, or logic, which, proceed- 
ing uniformly from movement to movement, 
as 1n some intricate musical theme, might link to- 
gether in one those contending, infinitely diverse 

P. VI 17 c 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


impulses. It was an act of recognition, even on 
the part of a philosophy of the inconsecutive, 
the incoherent, the insane, of that Wisdom 
which, “reacheth from end to end, sweetly 
and strongly ordering all things.” But if the 
“weeping philosopher,” the first of the pessi- 
mists, finds the ground of his melancholy in the 
sense of universal change, still more must he 
weep at the dulness of men’s ears to that 
continuous strain of melody throughout it. In 
truth, what was sympathetic with the hour and 
the scene in the Heraclitean doctrine, was the 
boldly aggressive, the paradoxical and negative 
tendency there, in natural collusion, as it was, 
with the destructiveness of undisciplined youth ; 
that sense of rapid dissolution, which, according 
to one’s temperament and one’s luck in things, 
might extinguish, or kindle all the more eagerly, 
an interest in the mere phenomena of existence, 
of one’s so hasty passage through the world. 
The theory of the perpetual flux was indeed 
an apprehension of which the full scope was 
only to be realised by a later age, in alliance 
with a larger knowledge of the natural world, a 
closer observation of the phenomena of mind, 
than was possible, even for Heraclitus, at that 
early day. So, the seeds of almost all scientific 
ideas might seem to have been dimly enfolded in 
the mind of antiquity ; but fecundated, admitted 
to their full working prerogative, one by one, 
in after ages, by good favour of the special 
18 


THE DOCTRINE OF MOTION 


intellectual conditions belonging to a particular 
generation, which, on a sudden, finds itself pre- 
occupied by a formula, not so much new, as 
renovated by new application. 

It is in this way that the most modern 
metaphysical, and the most modern empirical 
philosophies alike have illustrated emphatically, 
justified, expanded, the divination (so we may 
make bold to call it under the new light now 
thrown upon it) of the ancient theorist of 
Ephesus. The entire modern theory of “de- 
velopment,” in all its various phases, proved or 
unprovable,—what is it but old Heracliteanism 
awake once more in a new world, and grown to 
full proportions ? 

Πάντα χωρεῖ, πάντα pet.—It is the burden of 
Hegel on the one hand, to whom nature, and 
art, and polity, and philosophy, aye, and religion 
too, each in its long historic series, are but so 
many conscious movements in the secular process 
of the eternal mind; and on the other hand of 
Darwin and Darwinism, for which “ type” itself 
properly zs not but is only always Jdecoming. 
‘The bold paradox of Heraclitus is, in effect, 
repeated on all sides, as the vital persuasion just 
now of a cautiously reasoned experience, and, in 
illustration of the very law of change which it 
asserts, may itself presently be superseded as a 
commonplace. Think of all that subtly dis- 
guised movement, /afens processus, Bacon calls 
it (again as if by a kind of anticipation) which 
19 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


modern research has detected, measured, hopes 
to reduce to minuter or ally to still larger 
currents, in what had seemed most substantial to 
the naked eye, the inattentive mind. To the 
“observation and experiment” of the physical 
enquirer of to-day, the eye and the sun it lives 
by reveal themselves, after all, as Heraclitus had 
declared (scarcely serious, he seemed to those 
around him) as literally in constant extinction 
and renewal; the sun only going out more 
gradually than the human eye; the system 
meanwhile, of which it is the centre, in ceaseless 
movement nowhither. Our terrestrial planet is 
in constant increase by meteoric dust, moving to 
it through endless time out of infinite space. 
The Alps drift down the rivers into the plains, 
as still loftier mountains found their level there 
ages ago. The granite kernel of the earth, it 
is said, is ever changing in its very substance, 
its molecular constitution, by the passage through 
it of electric currents. And the Darwinian 
theory—that “species,” the identifying forms 
of animal and vegetable life, immutable though 
they seem now, as of old in the Garden of 
Eden, are fashioned by slow development, while 
perhaps millions of years go by: well! every 
month is adding to its evidence. Nay, the idea 
of development (that, too, a thing of growth, 
developed in the progress of reflexion) is at last 
invading one by one, as the secret of their ex- 
planation, all the products of mind, the very 
20 


THE DOCTRINE OF MOTION 


mind itself, the abstract reason; our certainty, 
for instance, that two and two make four. 
Gradually we have come to think, or to feel, 
that primary certitude. Political constitutions, 
again, as we now see so Clearly, are “‘ not made,” 
cannot be made, but “‘ grow.” Races, laws, arts, 
have their origins and end, are themselves 
ripples only on the great river of organic life ; 
and language is changing on our very lips. 


In Plato’s day, the Heraclitean flux, so deep 
down in nature itself—the flood, the fire— 
seemed to have laid hold on man, on the social 
and moral world, dissolving or disintegrating 
opinion, first principles, faith, establishing amor- 
phism, so to call it, there also. All along indeed 
the genius, the good gifts of Greece to the 
world had had much to do with the mobility 
of its temperament. Only, when Plato came 
into potent contact with his countrymen (Pericles, 
Phidias, Socrates being now gone) in politics, 
in literature and art, in men’s characters, the 
defect naturally incident to that fine quality 
_ had come to have unchecked sway. From the 
lifeless background of an unprogressive world— 
Egypt, Syria, frozen Scythia—a world in which 
_ the unconscious social aggregate had been every- 
| thing, the conscious individual, his capacity and 
rights, almost nothing, the Greek had stepped 
_ forth, like the young prince in the fable, to set 
_ things going. To the philosophic eye however, 

21 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


about the time when the history of Thucydides 
leaves off, they might seem to need a regulator, 
ere the very wheels wore themselves out. 
Mobility ! We do not think that a neces- 
sarily undesirable condition of life, of mind, of the 
physical world about us. *Tis the dead things, 
we may remind ourselves, that after all are most 
entirely at rest, and might reasonably hold that 
motion (vicious, fallacious, infectious motion, as 
Plato inclines to think) covers all that is best 
worth being. And as for philosophy—mobility, 
versatility, the habit of thought that can most 
adequately follow the subtle movement of things, 
that, surely, were the secret of wisdom, of the 
true knowledge of them. It means susceptibility, 
sympathetic intelligence, capacity, in short. It 
was the spirit of God that moved, moves still, in 
every form of real power, everywhere. Yet to 
Plato motion becomes the token of unreality in 
things, of falsity in our thoughts about them. 
It is just this principle of mobility, in itself so 
welcome to all of us, that, with all his contriv- 
ing care for the future, he desires to withstand. 
Everywhere he displays himself as an advocate 
of the immutable. The Republic is a proposal to 
establish it indefectibly in a very precisely regu- 
lated, a very exclusive community, which shall 
be a refuge for elect souls from an ill-made world. 


That four powerful influences made for the 
political unity of Greece was pointed out by 
22 


THE DOCTRINE OF MOTION 


Grote : common blood, common language, a com- 
mon religious centre, the great games in which 
all alike communicated. He adds that they 
failed to make the Greeks one people. Pan- 
hellenism was realised for the first time, and then 
but imperfectly, by Alexander the Great. The 
centrifugal tendency had ever been too much for 
the centripetal tendency in them, the progres- 
sive elements for the element of order. Their 
boundless impatience, that passion for novelty 
noted in them by Saint Paul, had been a matter 
of radical character. Their varied natural gifts 
did but concentrate themselves now and then to 
an effective centre, that they might be dissipated 
again, towards every side, in daring adventure 
alike of action and of thought. Variety and 
novelty of experience, further quickened by a 
consciousness trained to an equally nimble power 
of movement, individualism, the capacities, the 
claim, of the individual, forced into their utmost 
play by a ready sense and dexterous appliance of 
opportunity,—herein, certainly, lay at least one- 
half of their vocation in history. The material 
conformation of Greece, a land of islands and 
peninsulas, with a range of sea-coast immense 
as compared with its area, and broken up by 
repellent lines of mountain this way and that, 
nursing jealously a little township of three or four 
thousand souls into an independent type of its 
own, conspired to the same effect. Independ- 
ence, local and personal,—it was the Greek ideal | 
23 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


Yet of one side only of that ideal, as we may 
see, of the still half-Asiatic rather than the full 
Hellenic ideal, of the Ionian ideal as conceived 
by the Athenian people in particular, people of 
the coast who have the roaming thoughts of 
sailors, ever ready to float away anywhither amid 
their walls of wood. And for many of its 
admirers certainly the whole Greek people has 
been a people of the sea-coast. In Lacedemon, 
however, as Plato and others thought, hostile, 
inaccessible in its mountain hollow where it had 
no need of any walls at all, there were resources 
for that discipline and order which constitute 
the other ingredient in a true Hellenism, the 
saving Dorian soul in it. Right away thither, 
to that solemn old mountain village, now mistress 
of Greece, he looks often, in depicting the 
Perfect City, the ideal state. Perfection, in 
every case, as we may conceive, is attainable 
only through a certain combination of opposites, 
Attic dea with the Doric ὄξος ; and in the 
Athens of Plato’s day, as he saw with acute 
prevision, those centrifugal forces had come to 
be ruinously in excess of the centripetal. Its 
rapid, empiric, constitutional changes, its restless 
development of political experiment, the sub- 
divisions of party there, the dominance of faction, 
as we see it, steadily increasing, breeding on 
itself, in the pages of Thucydides, justify Plato’s 
long-drawn paradox that it is easier to wrestle 
against many than against one. ‘The soul, 

24 


THE DOCTRINE OF MOTION 


moreover, the inward polity of the individual, 
was the theatre of a similar dissolution; and 
truly stability of character had never been a 
prominent feature in Greek life. Think of 
the end of Pausanias failing in his patriotism, 
of Themistocles, of Miltiades, the saviours of 
Greece, actually selling the country they had so 
dearly bought to its old enemies. 

It is something in this way that, for Plato, 
motion and the philosophy of motion identify 
themselves with the vicious tendency in things 
and thought. Change is the irresistible law of 
our being, says the Philosophy of Motion. 
Change, he protests, through the power of a 
true philosophy, shall not be the law of our 
being; and it is curious to note the way in 
which, consciously or unconsciously, that philo- 
sophic purpose shapes his treatment, even in 
minute detail, of education, of art, of daily life, 
his very vocabulary, in which such pleasant or 
innocent words, as ““ manifold,” ‘‘ embroidered,” 
“ changeful,” become the synonyms of what is 
evil. He, first, notes something like a fixed cycle 
of political change; but conceives it (being 
change) as, from the very first, backward towards 
decadence. The ideal city, again, will not be 
an art-less place: it is by irresistible influence of 
art, that he means to shape men anew; by a 
severely monotonous art however, such art as 
shall speak to youth, all day long, from year to 
year, almost exclusively, of the loins girded about. 

25 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


Stimulus, or correction,— one hardly knows 
which to ask for first, as more salutary for our 
own slumbersome, yet so self- willed, northern 
temperaments. Perhaps all genuine fire, even 
the Heraclitean fire, has a power for both. 

« Athens,” says Dante, 


—Athens, aye and Sparta’s state 
That were in policy so great, 
And framed the laws of old, 
How small a place they hold, 
How poor their art of noble living 
Shews by thy delicate contriving, 
Where what October spun 
November sees outrun ! 
Think in the time thou canst recall, 
Laws, coinage, customs, places all, 
How thou hast rearranged, 
How oft thy members changed ! 
Couldst thou but see thyself aright, 
And turn thy vision to the light, ᾿ 
Thy likeness thou would’st find 
In some sick man reclined ; 
On couch of down though he be pressed, 
He seeks and finds not any rest, 
But turns and turns again, 
To ease him of his pain. 


Purgatory: Canto VI: Shadwell’s Translation. 


Now what Dante says to Florence, contrasting 
τ with Athens and Sparta as he conceives them, 
Plato might have said to Athens, in contrast 
with Sparta, with Lacedemon, at least as he 


conceived it. 


26 


Π 


PLATO AND THE DOCTRINE OF REST 


Over against that world of flux, 
Where nothing is, but all things seem, 


it is the vocation of Plato to set up a standard 
of unchangeable reality, which in its highest 
theoretic development becomes the world of 
“eternal and immutable ideas,” indefectible out- 
lines of thought, yet also the veritable things 
of experience: the perfect Justice, for instance, 
which if even the gods mistake it for perfect 
Injustice is not moved out of its place; the 
Beauty which is the same, yesterday, to-day and 
for ever. In such ideas or ideals, ‘‘ eternal” as 
participating in the essential character of the 
facts they represent to us, we come in contact, 
as he supposes, with the insoluble, immovable 
granite beneath and amid the wasting torrent 
of mere phenomena. And in thus ruling the 
deliberate aim of his philosophy to be a survey 
of things sub specie eternitatis, the reception of a 
kind of absolute and independent knowledge 
27 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


(independent, that is, of time and position, the 
accidents and peculiar point of view of the 
receiver) Plato is consciously under the influ- 
ence of another great master of the Pre-Socratic 
thought, Parmenides, the centre of the School of 
Elea. 

About half a century before the birth of 
Plato, Socrates being then in all the impressi- 
bility of early manhood, Parmenides, according 
to the witness of Plato himself—Parmenides at 
the age of sixty-five—had visited Athens at the 
great festival of the Panathenea, in company 
with Zeno the Eleatic, a characteristic specimen 
of Greek cleverness, of the acute understanding, 
personally very attractive. Though forty years 
old, the reputation this Zeno now enjoyed seems 
to have been very much the achievement of his 
youth, and came of a mastery of the sort of 
paradox youth always delights in. It may be 
said that no one has ever really answered him ; 
the difficulties with which he played so nicely 
being really connected with those ‘‘ antinomies,” 
or contradictions, or inconsistencies, of our 
thoughts, which more than two thousand years 
afterwards Kant noted as actually inherent in the 
mind itself—a certain constitutional weakness or 
limitation there, in dealing by way of cold- 
blooded reflexion with the direct presentations 
of its experience. The “Eleatic Palamedes,” 
Plato calls him, ‘“‘ whose dialectic art causes one 
and the same thing to appear both like and 

28 


THE DOCTRINE OF REST 


unlike, one and many, at rest and in motion,” — 
Ah! you hear already the sort of words that 
seem sometimes so barren and unprofitable even 
in Plato. 

It is from extant fragments of a work of his, 
not a poem, but, appropriately, To Σύγγραμμα--- 
The Prose, of Zeno, that such knowledge as we 
have of his doctrine, independently of the Par- 
menides of Plato, is derived. The active prin- 
ciple of that doctrine then lies in the acuteness 
with which he unfolds the contradictions which 
make against the very conceivability of the funda- 
mental phenomena of sense, in so far as those 
phenomena are supposed to be really existent 
independently of ourselves. The truth of ex- 
perience, of a sensible experience, he seems to 
protest:— Why! sensible experience as such 
is logically inconceivable. He proved it, or 
thought, or professed to think, he proved it, in 
the phenomenon which covers all the most 
vivid, the seemingly irresistible facts, of such 
experience. Motion was indeed, as the Hera- 
cliteans said, everywhere: was the most incisive 
of all facts in the realm of supposed sensible fact. 
Think of the prow of the trireme cleaving the 
water. Fora moment Zeno himself might have 
seemed but a follower of Heraclitus. He goes 
beyond him. All is motion: he admits.—Yes : 
only, motion is (I can show it!) a nonsensical 
term. Follow it, or rather stay by it, and it 
transforms itself, agreeably enough for the 

29 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


curious observer, into rest. Motion must be 
motion in space, of course ; from point to point 
in it,—and again, more closely, from point to 
point within such interval ; and so on, infinitely ; 
tis rest there: perpetual motion is perpetual 
rest:—the hurricane, the falling tower, the 
deadly arrow from the bow at whose coming 
you shake there so wretchedly, Zeno’s own rapid 
word-fence—all alike at rest, to the restful eye 
of the pure reason! ‘The tortoise, the creature 
that moves most slowly, cannot be overtaken by 
Achilles, the swiftest of us all; or at least you 
can give no rational explanation how it comes to 
be overtaken. Zeno had an armoury of such 
enigmas. Can a bushel of corn falling make a 
noise if a single grain makes none? Again, 
that motion should cease, we find inconceivable : 
but can you conceive how it should so much as 
begin? at what point precisely, in the moving 
body? Ubiquitous, tyrannous, irresistible, as it 
may seem, motion, with the whole so dazzling 
world it covers, is—nothing ! 


Himself so striking an instance of mobile 
humour in his exposure of the unreality of 
all movement, Zeno might be taken so far only 
for a master, or a slave, of paradox; such 
paradox indeed as is from the very first inherent 
in every philosophy which (like that of Plato 
himself, accepting even Zeno as one of its 
institutors) opposes the seen to the unseen as 

30 


THE DOCTRINE OF REST 


falsehood to truth. It was the beginning of 
scholasticism ; and the philosophic mind will 
perhaps never be quite in health, quite sane 
or natural, again. The objective, unconscious, 
pleasantly sensuous mind of the Greek, becom- 
ing a man, as he thinks, and putting away childish 
thoughts, is come with Zeno one step towards 
Aristotle, towards Aquinas, or shall we say into 
the rude scholasticism of the pedantic Middle 
Age? And we must have our regrets. There 
is always something lost in growing up. 

The wholesome scepticism of Hume or Mill 
for instance, the scepticism of the modern world, 
beset now with insane speculative figments, has 
been an appeal from the preconceptions of the 
understanding to the authority of the senses. 
With the Greeks, whose metaphysic business 
was then still all to do, the sceptical action of 
the mind lay rather in the direction of an appeal 
from the affirmations of sense to the authority of 
newly-awakened reason. Just then all those real 
and verbal difficulties which haunt perversely 
the human mind always, all those unprofitable 
queries which hang about the notions of matter 
and time and space, their divisibility and the 
like, seemed to be stirring together, under the 
utterance of this brilliant, phenomenally clever, 
perhaps insolent, young man, his master’s 
favourite. ‘To the work of that grave master, 
nevertheless—of Parmenides—a very different 
person certainly from his rattling disciple, Zeno’s 

31 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


seemingly so fantastic doctrine was sincerely in 
service. By its destructive criticism, its dissipa- 
tion of the very conceivability of the central and 
most incisive of sensible phenomena, it was a 
real support to Parmenides in his assertion of the 
nullity of all that is but phenomenal, leaving 
open and unoccupied space (emptiness, we might 
say) to that which really is. That which 2s, so 
purely, or absolutely, that it is nothing at all 
to our mixed powers of apprehension :— Par- 
menides and the Eleatic School were much 
occupied with the determination of the thoughts, 
or of the mere phrases and words, that belong to 
that. 

Motion discredited, motion gone, all was 
gone that belonged to an outward and concrete 
experience, thus securing exclusive validity to the 
sort of knowledge, if knowledge it is to be called, 
which corresponds to the “Pure Being,” that 
after all is only definable as “* Pure Nothing,” that. 
colourless, formless, impalpable existence (οὐσία 
ἀχρώματος, ἀσχημάτιστος, ἀναφής) to use the words of 
Plato, for whom Parmenides became a sort of 
inspired voice. Note at times, in reading him, 
in the closing pages of the fifth book of The 
Republic for instance, the strange accumulation 
of terms derivative from the abstract verb “Τὸ 
be.” As some more modern metaphysicians 
have done, even Plato seems to pack such terms 
together almost by rote. Certainly something 
of paradox may always be felt even in his 

32 


# 


“4; ΝῊ > ie 
6 ee 


ay δ" fy 


exposition of ““ Being,” or perhaps a kind of 
paralysis of speech—é¢acia. 


Parmenides himself had borrowed the thought 
from another, though he made it his own. 
Plato, in The Republic, as a critic of Homer, by 
way of fitting Homer the better for the use of 
the schoolboys of the ideal city, is ready to 
sacrifice much of that graceful polytheism in 
which the Greeks anticipated the du/ia of saints 
and angels in the catholic church. He does 
this to the advantage of a very abstract, and as it 
may seem disinterested, certainly an uninteresting, 
notion of deity, which is in truth :—well ! one of 
the dry sticks of mere “ natural theology,” as it is 
called. In this he was but following the first, 
the original, founder of the Eleatic School, Xeno- 
phanes, who in a somewhat scornful spirit had 
urged on men’s attention that, in their prayers 
and sacrifices to the gods, in all their various 
thoughts and statements, graceful or hideous, 
about them, they had only all along with much 
_ fallacy been making gods after their own like- 
ness, as horse or dog too, if perchance it cast a 
glance towards heaven, would after the same 
_ manner project thither the likeness of horse or 
_ dog: that to think of deity you must think of it 
as neither here nor there, then nor now ; you 
must away with all limitations of time and space 
_and matter, nay, with the very conditions, the 
limitation, of thought itself; apparently not 

P. VI 33 D 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


observing that to think of it in this way was in 
reality not to think of it at all :—That in short 
Being so pure as this is pure Nothing. 

In opposition then to the anthropomorphic 
religious poetry of Homer, Xenophanes elaborates 
the notion, or rather the abstract or purely verbal 
definition, of that which really is (τὸ ὄν) as in- 
clusive of all time, and space, and mode; yet so 
that all which can be identified concretely with 
mode and space and time is but antithetic to it, 
as finite to infinite, seeming to being, contingent 
to necessary, the temporal, in a word, to the 
eternal. Once for all, in harshest dualism, the 
only true yet so barren existence is opposed to 
the world of phenomena—of colour and form and 
sound and imagination and love, of empirical 
knowledge. Objects, real objects, as we know, 
grow in reality towards us in proportion as we 
define their various qualities. And yet, from 
another point of view, definition, qualification, 
is a negative process: it is as if each added 
quality took from the object we are defining one 
or more potential qualities. The more definite 
things become as objects of sensible or other 
empirical apprehension, the more, it might be 
said from the logician’s point of view, have we 
denied about them. It might seem that their 
increasing reality as objects of sense was in direct 
proportion to the increase of their distance from 
that perfect Being which is everywhere and at 
all times in every possible mode of being. A 

34 


Ἵ 
ἡ 


| 
Ul 


THE DOCTRINE OF REST 


thing visibly white is found as one approaches it 
to be also smooth to the touch ; and this added 
quality, says the formal logician, dses but deprive 
it of all other possible modes of texture ; Omnis 
determinatio est negatio. Vain puerilities ! you may 
exclaim :—with justice. Yet such are the con- 
siderations which await the mind that suffers itself 
to dwell awhile on the abstract formula to which 
the “rational theology” of Xenophanes leads 
him. It involved the assertion of an absolute 
difference between the original and all that is or 
can be derived from it; that the former annuls, 
or is exclusive of, the latter, which has in truth 
no real or legitimate standing-ground as matter 
of knowledge; that, in opposite yet equally 
unanswerable senses, at both ends of experience 
there is—nothing ! Of the most concrete object, 
as of the most abstract, it might be said, that it 
more properly is not than is. 

From Xenophanes, as a critic of the polytheism 
of the Greek religious poets, that most abstract 
and arid of formule, Pure Being, closed in indiffer- 
ently on every side upon itself, and suspended in 
the midst of nothing, like a hardtransparent crystal 
ball, as he says ; “The Absolute”; “The One”; 
passed to his fellow-citizen Parmenides, seeking, 
doubtless in the true spirit of philosophy, for the 
centre of the universe, of his own experience of 
it, for some common measure of the experience 
ofall men. To enforce a reasonable unity and 
order, to impress some larger likeness of reason, 

35 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


as one knows it in one’s self, upon the chaotic 
infinitude of the impressions that reach us from 
every side, is what all philosophy as such pro- 
poses. Κόσμος: order; reasonable, delightful, 
order ; 184 word that became very dear, as we 
know, to the Greek soul, to what was perhaps 
most essentially Greek in it, to the Dorian 
element there. Apollo, the Dorian god, was but 
its visible consecration. It was what, under his 
blessing, art superinduced upon the rough stone, 
the yielding clay, the jarring metallic strings, 
the common speech of every day. Philosophy, 
in its turn, with enlarging purpose, would project 
a similar light of intelligence upon the at first 
sight somewhat unmeaning world we find actually 
around us :—project it; or rather discover it, as 
being really pre-existent there, if one were happy 
enough to get one’s self into the right point of 
view. To certain fortunate minds the efficacious 
moment of insight would come, when, with 
delightful adaptation of means to ends, of the 
parts to the whole, the entire scene about 
one, bewildering, unsympathetic, unreasonable, 
on a superficial view, would put on, for them at 
least, κοσμιότης, that so welcome expression of 
fitness, which it is the business of the fine arts 
to convey into material things, of the art of 
discipline to enforce upon the lives of men. 
The primitive Ionian philosophers had found, 
or thought they found, such a principle (ἀρχή) in 
the force of some omnipresent physical element, 
36 


THE DOCTRINE OF REST 


air, water, fire ; or insome common law, motion, 
attraction, repulsion ; as Plato would find it in 
an eternally appointed hierarchy of genus and 
species ; as.the science of our day embraces it 
(perhaps after all only in fancy) in the ex- 
pansion of a large body of observed facts into 
some all-comprehensive hypothesis, such as 
«ἐ evolution.” 

For Parmenides, at his early day, himself, as 
some remnants of his work in that direction bear 
witness, an acute and curious observer of the 
concrete and sensible phenomena of nature, that 
principle of reasonable unity seemed attainable 
only by a virtual negation, by the obliteration, 
of all such phenomena. When we have learned 
as exactly as we can all the curious processes at 
work in our own bodies or souls, in the stars, in or 
under the earth, their very definiteness, their 
limitation, will but make them the more antago- 
nistic to that which alone really is, because it is 
always and everywhere itself, identical exclu- 
sively with itself. Phenomena !—by the force 
of such arguments as Zeno’s, the instructed 
would make a clean sweep of them, for the 
establishment, in the resultant void, of the 
““QOne,” with which it is impossible (παρὰ πάντα 
λεγόμενα) in spite of common language, and of 
what seems common sense, for the “ Many ’— 
the hills and cities of Greece, you and me, 
Parmenides himself, really to co-exist at all. 
“ Parmenides,” says one, “had stumbled upon 

37 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


the modern thesis that thought and being are 
the same.” 

Something like this—this impossibly abstract 
doctrine—is what Plato’s “ father in philosophy ” 
had had to proclaim, in the midst of the busy, 
brilliant, already complicated life of the recently 
founded colonial town of Elea. It was like the 
revelation to Israel in the midst of picturesque 
idolatries, “‘ The Lord thy God is one Lord” ; 
only that here it made no claim to touch the 
affections, or even to warm the imagination. 
Israel’s Greek cousin was to undergo a harder, 
a more distant and repressive discipline in 
those matters, to which a peculiarly austere 
moral beauty, at once self-reliant and submis- 
sive, the zsthetic expression of which has a 
peculiar, an irresistible charm, would in due 
time correspond. 


It was in difficult hexameter verse, in a poem 
which from himself or from others had received 
the title—Tlepi φύσεως (De Naturd Rerum) that 
Parmenides set forth his ideas. From _ the 
writings of Clement of Alexandria, and other 
later writers large in quotation, diligent modern 
scholarship has collected fragments of it, which 
afford sufficient independent evidence of his 
manner of thought, and supplement conveniently 
Plato’s, of course highly subjective, presentment 
in his Parmenides of what had so deeply influ- 
enced him.— 

38 


THE DOCTRINE OF REST 


“Now come!” (this fragment of Parmenides 
is in Proclus, who happened to quote it in 
commenting on the Timeus of Plato) “Come ! 
do you listen, and take home what I shall tell 
you: what are the two paths of search after 
right understanding. The one, 


"vl, Vice " ᾿ wy ee top 8 
Ἢ μεν OTWS ἐστιν TE καὶ WS οὐκ EOTL μὴ εἰναι 


“that what is, is; and that what is not, is ποῖ ἢ; 
or, in the Latin of scholasticism, here inaugurated 
by Parmenides, esse ens : non esse non ens— 


πειθοῦς ἐστι κέλευθος ; ἀληθείη yap ὀπηδεῖ 


“this is the path to persuasion, for truth goes 
along with it. The other—that what is, is not ; 
and by consequence that what is not, is :—I tell 
you that is the way which goes counter to 
persuasion : 

τὴν δή τοι φράζω παναπειθέα ἔμμεν ἀταρπόν" 

οὔτε γὰρ ἂν γνοίης τό γε μὴ ἐὸν οὐ γὰρ ἐφικτόν" — 
That which is not, never could you know: 
there is no way of getting at that ; nor could you 
explain it to another; for Thought and Being 
are identical."—Famous utterance, yet of so 
dubious omen !—T6 γὰρ αὐτὸ νοεῖν ἐστίν τε καὶ εἶναι 
—idem est enim cogitare etesse. ‘‘It is one to me,” 
he proceeds, ‘‘ at what point I begin ; for thither 
I shall come back over again: τόθι γὰρ πάλιν 
ἵξομαι avis.” 

Yes, truly! again and again, in an empty 
circle, we may say; and certainly, with those 
39 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


dry and difficult words in our ears, may think 
for a moment that philosophic reflexion has 
already done that delightfully superficial Greek 
world an ill turn, troubling so early its ingenuous 
soul ; that the European mind, as was said, will 
never be quite sane again. It has been put on 
a quest (vain quest it may prove to be) after a 
kind of knowledge perhaps not properly attain- 
able. Hereafter, in every age, some will be 
found to start afresh quixotically, through what 
wastes of words ! in search of that true Substance, 
the One, the Absolute, which to the majority of 
acute people is after all but zero, and a mere 
algebraic symbol for nothingness. In themselves, 
by the way, such search may bring out fine 
intellectual qualities; and thus, in turn, be of 
service to those who can profit by the spec- 
tacle of an enthusiasm not meant for them ; 
must nevertheless be admitted to have had all 
along something of disease about it; as indeed 
to Plato himself the philosophic instinct as such 
is a form of “ mania.” 

An infectious mania, it might seem,—that 
strange passion for nonentity, to which the Greek 
was so oddly liable, to which the human mind 
generally might be thought to have been con- 
stitutionally predisposed ; for the doctrine of 
‘The One” had come to the surface before in 
old Indian dreams of self-annihilation, which 
had been revived, in the second century after 
Christ, in the ecstasies (ecstasies of the pure 


40 


THE DOCTRINE OF REST 


spirit, leaving the body behind it) recommended 
by the Neo-Platonists; and again, in the Middle 
Age, as a finer shade of Christian experience, in 
the mystic doctrines of Eckhart and Tauler 
concerning that union with God which can only 
be attained by the literal negation of self, by a 
kind of moral suicide; of which something also 
may be found, under the cowl of the monk, in 
the clear, cold, inaccessible, impossible heights 
of the book of the Imitation. It presents itself 
once more, now altogether beyond Christian 
influence, in the hard and ambitious intellect- 
ualism of Spinoza; a doctrine of pure repellent 
substance—substance “in vacuo,” to be lost 
in which, however, would be the proper con- 
summation of the transitory individual life. 
Spinoza’s own absolutely colourless existence 
was a practical comment upon it. Descartes ; 
Malebranche, under the monk’s cowl again ; 
Leibnitz; Berkeley with his theory of the 
*‘ Vision of all things in God”; do but present 
variations on the same theme through the seven- 
teenth and eighteenth centuries. By one and all 
it is assumed, in the words of Plato, that to be 
colourless, formless, impalpable is the note of 
the superior grade of knowledge and existence, 
evanescing steadily, as one ascends towards that 
perfect (perhaps not quite attainable) condition 
of either, which in truth can only be attained by 
the suppression of all the rule and outline of one’s 
own actual experience and thought. 


> ae 
, : Ἢ: 
41 = ae 
δὲ, ὁ aap. ὶ 
«ε s 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


Something like that certainly there had been 
already in the doctrine of Parmenides, to whom 
Plato was so willing to go to school. And in 
the nineteenth century, as on the one hand the 
philosophy of motion, of the “ perpetual flux,” 
receives its share of verification from that theory 
of development with which in various forms 
all modern science is prepossessed ; so, on the 
other hand, the philosophy of rest also, of the 
perpetual lethargy, the Parmenidean assertion 
of the exclusive reign of “The One,” receives 
an unlooked-for testimony from the modern 
physical philosopher, hinting that the phenomena 
he deals with—matter, organism, consciousness— 
began in a state of indeterminate, abstract in- 
difference, with a single uneasy start in a sort of 
eternal sleep, a ripple on the dead, level surface. 
Increasing indeed for a while in radius and 
depth, under the force of mechanic law, the 
world of motion and life is however destined, by 
force of its own friction, to be restored sooner or 
later to equilibrium ; nay, is already gone back 
some noticeable degrees (how desirably !) to the 
primeval indifference, as may be understood by 
those who can reckon the time it will take for 
our worn-out planet, surviving all the fret of the 
humanity it housed for a while, to be drawn 
into the sun. 

But it is of Plato after all we should be think- 
ing ; of the comparatively temperate thoughts, 
the axiomata media, he was able to derive, by a 

42 


THE DOCTRINE OF REST 


sort of compromise, from the impossible paradox 
of his ancient master. What was it, among 
things inevitably manifest on his pages as we 
read him, that Plato borrowed and kept from 
the Eleatic School ! 


Two essential judgments of his philosophy : 
The opposition of what zs, to what appears ; and 
the parallel opposition of knowledge to opinion ; 
(ἕτερον ἐπιστήμης δόξα" ἐφ᾽ ἑτέρῳ ἄρα ἕτερόν τι δυναμένη 
ἑκατέρα αὐτῶν πέφυκε" οὐκ ἐγχωρεῖ γνωστὸν καὶ δοξαστὸν 
ταὐτὸν εἶναι") and thirdly, to illustrate that opposi- 
tion, the figurative use, so impressed on thought 
and speech by Plato that it has come to seem 
hardly a figure of speech at all but appropriate 
philosophic language, of the opposition of light 
to darkness.— 


Well, then (Socrates is made to say in the fifth book of The 
Republic) if what is, is the object of knowledge, would not 
something other than what is, be the object of opinion ? 

Yes ! something else. 

Does opinion then opine what is not ; or is it impossible to 
have even opinion concerning what is not? Consider! does 
not he who has opinion direct his opinion upon something? or 
is it impossible, again, to have an opinion, yet an opinion about 
nothing ? 

Impossible ! 

But he who has an opinion has opinion at least about some- 
thing ; hasn’t he? Yet after all what is not, is not a thing ; 
but would most properly be denominated nothing. 

Certainly. 

Now to what is not, we assigned of necessity ignorance: te 
what is, knowledge. 

Rightly : he said. 

43 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


Neither what is, then, nor what is not, is the object of 
opinion. 

No! 

Opinion therefore would be neither ignorance nor knowledge. 

It seems not. 

Is it, then, beyond these ; going beyond knowledge in clear- 
ness, beyond ignorance in obscurity καὶ | 

Neither the one, nor the other. 

But, I asked, opinion seems to you (doesn’t it?) to be a 
darker thing than knowledge, yet lighter than ignorance. 

Very much so; he answered. 

Does it lie within those two? 

Yes. 

Opinion, then, would be midway, between these two con- 
ditions ? 

Undoubtedly so. 

Now didn’t we say in what went before that if anything 
became apparent such that it is, and is not, at the same time, a 
thing of that kind would lie between that which ἐς in unmixed 
clearness, and that which wholly is mot; and that there would 
be, in regard to that, neither knowledge nor ignorance ; but, 
again, a condition revealing itself between ignorance and 
knowledge? 

Rightly. 

And now, between these two, what we call ‘opinion’ has 
in fact revealed itself. 

Clearly so. 

It would remain for us therefore, as it seems, to find that 
which partakes of both—both of Being and Not-being, and 
which could rightly be called by neither term distinctly ; in 
order that, if it appear, we may in justice determine it to be 
the object of opinion ; assigning the extremes to the extremes, 
the intermediate to what comes between them. Or is it not 
thus ὃ 

Thus it is. 

These points then being assumed, let him tell me! let him 
speak and give his answer—that excellent person, who on the 
one hand thinks there is no Beauty itself, nor any idea of Beauty 
itself, ever in the same condition in regard to the same things 
(ἀεὶ κατὰ ταὐτὰ ὡσαύτως ἔχουσαν) yet, on the other hand, holds 


44 


THE DOCTRINE OF REST 


that there are the many beautiful objects :—that lover of sight 
(ὁ φιλοθεάμων) who can by no means bear it if any one says that 
the beautiful is one; the just also; and the rest, after the same 
way. For good Sir! we shall say, pray tell us, is there any one 
of these many beautiful things which will not appear ugly 
(under certain conditions) of the many just or pious actions 
which will not seem unjust or impious ? 

No! he answered. Rather it must be that they shall seem, 
in a manner, both beautiful and ugly ; and all the rest you 
ask of. 

Well! The many double things :—Do they seem to be at 
all less half than double? 

Not at all. 

And great, in truth, and little, and light, and heavy—will 
they at all more truly be called by these names which we may 
give them, than by the opposite names ? 

No! he said ; but each of them will always hold of both. 

Every several instance of ‘The Many,’ then—is it, more 
truly than it is not, that which one may affirm it to be? 

It is like people at supper-parties he said (very Attic supper- 
parties !) playing on words, and the children’s riddle about the 
eunuch and his fling round the bat—with what, and on what, 
the riddle says he hit it ; for these things also seem to set both 
ways, and it is not possible, fixedly, to conceive any one of them 
either to be, or not to be; neither both, nor the one, nor the 
other. 

Have you anything then you can do with them; or any- 
where you can place them with fairer effect than in that posi- 
tion between being and the being not? For presumably they 
will not appear more obscure than what is not, so as not to be, 
still more ; nor more luminous than what is, so as to de, even 
more than that. We have found then that the many customary 
notions of the many, about Beauty and the rest are revolved 
somewhere between not-being and being unmixedly. 

So we have. 

And agreed, at least, at the outset, that if anything of 
this sort presented itself, it must be declared matter not of 
knowledge, but of opinion ; to be apprehended by the inter- 
mediate faculty ; as it wanders unfixed, there, between. 

Republic, 478. 


45 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


Many a train of thought, many a turn of 
expression, only too familiar, some may think, 
to the reader of Plato, are summarised in that 
troublesome yet perhaps attractive passage. The 
influence then of Parmenides on Plato had made 
him, incurably (shall we say ἢ) a dualist. Only, 
practically, Plato’s richly coloured genius will 
find a compromise between the One which 
alone really is, is yet so empty a thought 
for finite minds; and the Many, which most 
properly is not, yet presses so closely on eye 
and ear and heart and fancy and will, at every 
moment. That which really is (τὸ ὄν) the One, 
if he is really to think about it at all, must admit 
within it a certain variety of members ; and, in 
effect, for Plato the true Being, the Absolute, 
the One, does become delightfully multiple, as 
the world of ideas—appreciable, through years 
of loving study, more and more clearly, one by 
one, as the perfectly concrete, mutually adjusted, 
permanent forms of our veritable experience: the 
Bravery, for instance, that cannot be confused, 
not merely with Cowardice, but with Wisdom, 
or Humility. One after another they emerge 
again from the dead level, the Parmenidean 
tabula rasa, with nothing less than the reality 
of persons face to face with us, of a personal 
identity. It was as if the firm plastic outlines 
of the delightful old Greek polytheism had 
found their way back after all into a repellent 
monotheism. Prefer as he may in theory that 

46 


THE DOCTRINE OF REST 


blank white light of the One—its sterile, “form- 
less, colourless, impalpable,” eternal identity with 
itself—the world, and this chiefly is why the 
world has not forgotten him, will be for him, 
as he is by no means colour-blind, by no means 
a colourless place. He will suffer it to come to 
him, as his pages convey it in turn to us, with 
the liveliest variety of hue, as in that conspicu- 
ously visual emblem of it, the outline of which 
(essentially characteristic of himself as it seems) 
he had really borrowed from the old Eleatic 
teacher who had tried so hard to close the 
bodily eye that he might the better apprehend 


the world unseen.— 


And now (he writes in the seventh book of The Republic) 
take for a figure of human nature, as regards education and the 
lack thereof, some such condition as this. ‘Think you see 
people as it were in some abode below-ground, like a cave, 
having its entrance spread out upwards towards the light, 
broad, across the whole cavern. Suppose them here from 
childhood ; their legs and necks chained ; so that there they 
stay, and can see only what is in front of them, being unable 
by reason of the chain to move their heads round about: and 
the light of a fire upon them, blazing from far above, behind 
their backs: between the fire and the prisoners away up aloft : 
and see beside it a low wall built along, as with the showmen, 
in front of the people lie the screens above which they exhibit 
their wonders. 

I see: he said. 

See, then, along this low wall, men, bearing vessels of all 
sorts wrought in stone and wood ; and, naturally, some of the 
bearers talking, other silent. 

It is a strange figure you describe: said he: and strange 
prisoners.— 

They are like ourselves: I answered! Republic, 514. 


47 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


Metaphysical formule have always their 
practical equivalents. The ethical alliance of 
Heraclitus is with the Sophists, and the 
Cyrenaics or the Epicureans; that of Par- 
menides, with Socrates, and the Cynics or the 
Stoics. The Cynic or Stoic ideal of a static calm 
is as truly the moral or practical equivalent of 
the Parmenidean doctrine of the One, as the 
Cyrenaic μονόχρονος ἡδονή ----(ἣξ pleasure of the 
ideal now—is the practical equivalent of the 
doctrine of motion ; and, as sometimes happens, 
what seems hopelessly perverse as a metaphysic 
for the understanding is found to be realisable 
enough as one of many phases of our so flexible 
human feeling. The abstract philosophy of the 
One might seem indeed to have been translated 
into the terms of a human will in the rigid, 
disinterested, renunciant career of the emperor 
Marcus Aurelius, its mortal coldness. Let me 
however conclude with a document of the Eleatic 
temper, nearer in its origin to the age of Plato: 
an ancient fragment of Cleanthes the Stoic, 
which has justly stirred the admiration of Stoical 
minds ; though truly, so hard is it not to lapse 
from those austere heights, the One, the Abso- 
lute, has become in it after all, with much varied 
colour and detail in his relations to concrete 
things and persons, our father Zeus. 

An illustrious athlete ; then a mendicant dealer 
in water-melons ; chief pontiff lastly of the sect 
of the Stoics; Cleanthes, as we see him in anec- 

48 


THE DOCTRINE OF REST 


dote at least, is always a loyal, sometimes a very 
quaintly loyal, follower of the Parmenidean or 
Stoic doctrine of detachment from all material 
things. It was at the most critical points perhaps 
of such detachment, that somewhere about the 
year three hundred before Christ, he put to- 
gether the verses of his famous “‘ Hymn.” By 
its practical indifference, its resignation, its passive 
submission to the One, the undivided Intelli- 
gence, which διὰ πάντων gorra— goes to and fro 
through all things, the Stoic pontiff is true to 
the Parmenidean schooling of his flock; yet 
departs from it also in a measure by a certain 
expansion of phrase, inevitable, it may be, if one 
has to speak at all about that chilly abstraction, 
still more make a hymn to it. He is far from 
the cold precept of Spinoza, that great re-assertor 
of the Parmenidean tradition : That whoso loves 
God truly must not expect to be loved by Him 
in return. In truth, there are echoes here from 
many various sources. "Ex cod γὰρ γένος ἐσμεν :-— 
that is quoted, as you remember, by Saint 
Paul, so just after all to the pagan world, as its 
testimony to some deeper ὕσμόσις than its own. 
_ Certainly Cleanthes has conceived his abstract 
monotheism a little more winningly, somewhat 
_ better, than dry, pedantic Xenophanes ; perhaps 
because Socrates and Plato have lived meanwhile. 
_ You might even fancy what he says an echo from 
_Israel’s devout response to the announcement : 
“Τῆς Lord thy God is one Lord.” The Greek 


P. VI 49 E 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


certainly is come very near to his unknown 
cousin at Sion in what follows :— 


΄ὔ Ἡ pe ,ὔ , Ν 2 
κύδιστ᾽, ἀθανάτων, πολυώνυμε, παγκρατὲς αἰεὶ 
Ζεῦ, φύσεως ἀρχηγέ, νόμου μέτα πάντα κυβερνῶν, 
χαῖρε" σὲ γὰρ πάντεσσι θέμις θνητοῖσι προσαυδᾷν. κ.τ.λ. 


Mullach, Fragmenta Philosophorum Grecorum, I. p. 151. 
Thou O Zeus art praised above all gods: many are Thy 


names and Thine is all power for ever. 

The beginning of the world was from Thee: and with law 
Thou rulest over all things. 

Unto Thee may all flesh speak: for we are Thy offspring. 

Therefore will I raise a hymn unto Thee: and will ever 
sing of Thy power. 

The whole order of the heavens obeyeth Thy word: as it 
moveth around the earth : 

With little and great lights mixed together : how great art 
Thou, King above all for ever ! 

Nor is anything done upon earth apart from Thee: nor in 
the firmament, nor in the seas : 

Save that which the wicked do: by their own folly. 

But Thine is the skill to set even the crooked straight : 
what is without fashion is fashioned and the alien akin before 
Thee. 

Thus hast Thou fitted together all things in one: the 
good with the evil : 

That Thy word should be one in all things: abiding for 
ever. 

Let folly be dispersed from our souls: that we may repay 
Thee the honour, wherewith Thou hast honoured us : 

Singing praise of Thy works for ever: as becometh the 
sons of men. 


50 


ΠῚ 
PLATO AND THE DOCTRINE OF NUMBER 


His devotion to the austere and abstract philo- 
sophy of Parmenides, its passivity or indifference, 
could not repress the opulent genius of Plato, or 
transform him into a cynic. Another ancient 
philosopher, Pythagoras, set the frozen waves in 
motion again, brought back to Plato’s recogni- 
tion all that multiplicity in men’s experience 
to which Heraclitus had borne such emphatic 
witness; but as rhythm or melody now—in 
movement truly, but moving as disciplined sound 
and with the reasonable soul of music in it. 
Pythagoras, or the founder of the Pythagorean 
philosophy, is the third of those earlier masters, 
who explain the intellectual confirmation of 
Plato by way of antecedent. What he said, or 
was believed to have said, is almost everywhere 
in the very texture of Platonic philosophy, as 
vera vox, an authority with prescript claim on 
sympathetic or at least reverent consideration, 
to be developed generously in the natural growth 
of Plato’s own thoughts. 
| ΕΙ 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


Nothing remains of his writings: dark state- 
ments only, as occasion served, in later authors. 
Plato himself attributes those doctrines of his 
not to Pythagoras but to the Pythagoreans. 
But if no such name had come down to us we 
might have understood how, in the search for 
the philosophic unity of experience, a common 
measure of things, for a cosmical hypothesis, 
number and the truths of number would come 
to fill the place occupied by some omnipresent 
physical element, air, fire, water, in the philo- 
sophies of Ionia; by the abstract and exclusive 
idea of the unity of Being itself in the system 
of Parmenides. To realise unity in variety, to 
discover cosmos—an order that shall satisfy one’s 
reasonable soul—below and within apparent 
chaos: is from first to last the continuous pur- 
pose of what we call philosophy. Well! Pytha- 
goras seems to have found that unity of principle 
(ἀρχή) in the dominion of number everywhere, 
the proportion, the harmony, the music, into 
which number as such expands. Truths of 
number: the essential laws of measure in time 
and space :—Yes, these are indeed everywhere in 
our experience: must, as Kant can explain to us, 
be an element in anything we are able so much 
as to conceive at all. And music, covering all it 
does, for Pythagoras, for Plato and Platonism 
—music, which though it is of course much 
besides, is certainly a formal development of 
purely numerical laws: that too surely zs some- 

52 


THE DOCTRINE OF NUMBER 


thing, independently of ourselves, in the real 
world without us, like a personal intelligible 
soul durably resident there for those who bring 
intelligence of it, of music, with them; to be 
known on the favourite Platonic principle of 
like by like (ὅμοιον ὁμοίῳ) though the incapable 
or uninstructed ear, in various degrees of dulness, 
may fail to apprehend it. 

The Golden Verses of Pythagoras parted early 
into dust (that seems strange, if they were ever 
really written in a book) and antiquity itself 
knows little directly about his doctrine. Yet 
Pythagoras is much more than a mere name, a 
term, for locating as well as may be a philosophical 
abstraction. Pythagoras, his person, his memory, 
attracted from the first a kind of fairy-tale of 
mystic science. The philosophy of number, of 
music and proportion, came, and has remained, 
in a cloud of legendary glory; the gradual 
accumulation of which Porphyry and Iamb- 
lichus, the fantastic masters of Neo-Platonism, 
or Neo-Pythagoreanism, have embodied in their 
so-called Lives of him, like some antique fable 
richly embossed with starry wonders. In this 
spirit there had been much writing about him : 
that he was a son of Apollo, nay, Apollo himself 
—the twilight, attempered, Hyperborean Apollo, 
like the sun in Lapland : that his person gleamed 
at times with a supernatural brightness: that he 
had exposed to those who loved him a golden 
thigh: how Abaris, the minister of that god, 

53 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


had come flying to him on a golden arrow: of 
his almost impossible journeys: how he was 
seen, had lectured indeed, in different places at 
the same time. As he walked on the banks of 
the Nessus the river had whispered his name: 
he had been, in the secondary sense, various 
persons in the course of ages ; a courtesan once, 
for some ancient sin in him; and then a hero, 
Euphorbus, son of Panthus; could remember 
very distinctly so recent a matter as the Trojan 
war, and had recognised in a moment his own 
old armour, hanging on the wall, above one of 
his old dead bodies, in the temple of Athene at 
Argos ; showing out all along only by hints and 
flashes the abysses of divine knowledge within 
him, sometimes by miracle. For if the philo- 
sopher really is all that Pythagoras or the 
Pythagoreans suppose ; if the material world is 
so perfect a musical instrument, and he knows 
its theory so well, he might surely give practical 
and sensible proof of that on occasion, by himself 
improvising music upon it in direct miracle. 
And so there, in Porphyry and Iamblichus, the 
appropriate miracles are. 

If the mistaken affection of the disciples of 
dreamy Neo-Platonic Gudészs at Alexandria, in 
the third or fourth century of our era, has thus 
made it impossible to separate later legend from 
original evidence as to what he was, and said, 
and how he said it, yet that there was a brilliant, 
perhaps a showy, personality there, infusing the 

54 


THE DOCTRINE OF NUMBER 


most abstract truths with what would tell on 
the fancy, seems more than probable, and, 
though he would appear really to have had 
from the first much of mystery or mysticism 
about him, the thaumaturge of Samos, “ whom 
even the vulgar might follow as a conjuror,” 
must have been very unlike the lonely “weep- 
ing” philosopher of Ephesus, or the almost 
disembodied philosopher of Elea. In the very 
person and doings of this earliest master of the 
doctrine of harmony, people saw that philo- 
sophy is 

Not harsh and crabbed, as dull fools suppose, 

But musical as is Apollo’s lute. 


And in turn he abounded in influence on the 
deeds, the persons, of others, as if he had really 
carried a magic lute in his hands to charm them. 


As his fellow-citizens had all but identified 
Pythagoras with him, so Apollo remained the 
peculiar patron of the Pythagoreans; and we 
may note, in connexion with their influence 
on Plato, that as Apollo was the chosen ancestral 
deity, so Pythagoreanism became especially the 
philosophy, of the severely musical Dorian 
Greeks. If, as Plato was aware, or fancied, 
true Spartans knew more of philosophy than 
they let strangers suppose—turned them all out 
from time to time and feasted on it in secret, 
for the strengthening of their souls—it was 

55 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 
precisely the Pythagorean philosophy of music, 


of austere music, mastering, remoulding, men’s 
very bodies, they would then have discussed 
with one another. 

A native of Ionia, it is in one of the Dorian 
cities of Magna Grecia, at Crotona, that Pytha- 
goras finds the fitting scene of his mysterious 
influence. He founds there something like an 
ideal republic, or rather a religious brotherhood, 
under a rule outwardly expressive of that inward 
idea of order or harmony, so dear to the Dorian 
soul, and, for it, as for him, ever the peculiar 
pledge of the presence of philosophic truth. 
᾿Αλήθειαν δὲ ἀμετρίᾳ ἡγεῖ συγγενῆ εἶναι, ἢ ἐμμετρίᾳ ; asks 
one in the The Republic ; and ’Eyperpia’ of course. 
is the answer. 

Recalling the student of Plato to penetrate 
as far as he can into that mysterious community, 
there, long before, in the imagination of Pytha- 
goras is the first dream of the Perfect City, 
with all those peculiar ethical sympathies which 
the Platonic Republic enforces already well 
defined—the perfect mystic body of the Dorian 
soul, built, as Plato requires, to the strains of 
music. Asa whole, and in its members severally, 
it would reproduce and visibly reflect to others 
that inward order and harmony of which each 
one was a part. As such, the Pythagorean 
order (it was itself an “ order”) expanded and 
was long maintained in those cities of Magna 
Grecia which had been the scene of the prac- 

56 


4 


! 


! 


THE DOCTRINE OF NUMBER 


tical no less than of the speculative activity of 
its founder ; and in one of which, Metapontum, 
so late as the days of Cicero what was believed 
to be the tomb of Pythagoras was still shown. 
Order, harmony, the temperance, which, as 
Plato will explain to us, will convince us by the 
visible presentment of it in the faultless person 
of the youthful Charmides, is like a musical 
harmony,—that was the chief thing Pythagoras 
exacted from his followers, at least at first, 
though they were mainly of the noble and 
wealthy class who could have done what they 
liked—temperance in a religious intention, with 
many singular scruples concerning bodily puri- 
fication, diet, and the like. For if, according 
to his philosophy, the soul had come from 
heaven, to use the phrase of Wordsworth re- 
producing the central Pythagorean doctrine, 
“‘from heaven,” as he says, “trailing clouds of 
glory,’ so the arguments of Pythagoras were 
always more or less explicitly involving one in 
consideration of the means by which one might 
get back thither, of which means, surely, absti- 
nence, the repression of one’s carnal elements, 
must be one; in consideration also, in curious 
questions, as to the relationship of those carnal 
elements in us to the pilgrim soul, before and 
after, for which he was so anxious to secure full 
use of all the opportunities of further perfecting 
which might yet await it, in the many revolutions 
of its existence. In the midst of that zsthetic- 
57 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


ally so brilliant world of Greater Greece, as if 
anticipating Plato, he has, like the philosophic 
kings of the Platonic Republic, already something 
of the monk, of monastic ascésis, about him. Its 
purpose is to fit him for, duly to refine his nature 
towards, that closer vision of truth to which 
perchance he may be even now upon his way. 
The secrecy again, that characteristic silence of 
which the philosopher of music was, perhaps 
not inconsistently, a lover, which enveloped the 
entire action of the Pythagoreans, and had 
indeed kept Pythagoras himself, as some have 
thought, from committing his thoughts to writ- 
ing at all, was congruous with such monkish 
discipline. Mysticism—the condition of the 
initiated—is a word derived, as we know, from a 
Greek verb which may perhaps mean to close the 
eye that one may better perceive the invisible, 
but more probably means to close the lips while 
the soul is brooding over what cannot be uttered. 
Later Christian admirers said of him, that he 
had hidden the words of God in his heart. 

The dust of his golden verses perhaps, but 
certainly the gold-dust of his thoughts, lies 
scattered all along Greek literature from Plato to 
the latest of the Greek Fathers of the Church. 
You may find it serviceably worked out in the 
notes of Zeller’s excellent work on Greek philo- 
sophy, and, with more sparing comment, in 
Mullach’s Fragmenta Philosophorum Grecorum. 
No one of those Pre-Socratic philosophers has 

58 


THE DOCTRINE OF NUMBER 


been the subject of a more enthusiastic erudition. 
For his mind’s health however, if in doing so he 
is not making a disproportionate use of his time, 
inconsistent certainly with the essential temper 
of the doctrine he seeks for, and such asa true 
Pythagorean would instantly condemn, the young 
scholar might be recommended to go straight 
to the pages of Aristotle—those discreet, un- 
romantic pages, salutary therefore to listen to, 
concerning doctrines in themselves so fantastic.’ 
In the Ethics, as you may know, in the Meta- 
physics, and elsewhere, Aristotle gives many 
not unsympathetic notices at least of the dis- 
ciples, which, by way of sober contrast on a 
matter from the first profusely, perhaps cheaply, 
embroidered, is like quiet information from 
Pythagoras himself. Only, remember always 
in reading Plato—Plato, as a sincere learner in 
the school of Pythagoras—that the essence, the 
active principle of the Pythagorean doctrine, 
resides, not as with the ancient Eleatics, nor 
as with our modern selves too often, in the 
‘“‘infinite,” those eternities, infinitudes, abysses, 
Carlyle invokes for us so often—in no cultus of 
the infinite (τὸ ἄπειρον) but in the finite (τὸ πέρας). 
It is so indeed, with that exception of the 
Parmenidean sect, through all Greek philosophy, 
congruously with the proper vocation of the 


1 Or to Mr. Burnet’s Early Greek Philosophy ; which I have read 
since these pages went to press, with much admiration for its 
learning and lucidity, and its unconventionality of view. 


59 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


people of art, of art as being itself the finite, 
ever controlling the infinite, the formless. ‘Those 
famous συστοιχίαι τῶν ἐναντιῶν, OT parallel columns 
of contraries : the One and the Many : Odd and 
Even, and the like: Good and Evil: are indeed 
all reducible ultimately to terms of ar, as the 
expressive and the inexpressive. Now observe 
that Plato’s “theory of ideas” is but an effort to 
enforce the Pythagorean πέρας, with all the unity- 
in-variety of concerted music,—eternal definition 
of the finite, upon τὸ ἄπειρον, the infinite, the 
indefinite, formless, brute matter, of our experi- 
ence of the world. 


For it is of Plato again we should be thinking, 
and of Pythagoras or the Pythagoreans, only so 
far as they explain the actual conformation of 
Plato’s thoughts as we find them, especially in 
The Repubhc. Let us see, as much as possible 
in his own words, what Plato received from 
that older philosophy, of which the two leading 
persuasions were ; first, the universality, the ulti- 
mate truth, of numerical, of musical law ; and 
secondly, the pre-existence, the double eternity, 
of the soul. 

In spirit, then, we are certainly of the 
Pythagorean company in that most characteristic 
dialogue, the Meno, in which Plato discusses the 
nature, the true idea, of Virtue, or rather how 
one may attain thereto ; compelled to this sub- 
ordinate and accessory question by the intel- 

60 


THE DOCTRINE OF NUMBER 


lectual cowardice of his disciple, though after his 
manner he flashes irrepressible light on that 
other primary and really indispensable question 
by the way. Pythagoras, who had founded his 
famous brotherhood by way of turning theory 
into practice, must have had, of course, definite 
views on that most practical question, how virtue 
is to be attained by us; and Plato is certainly 
faithful to him in assigning the causation of virtue 
partly to discipline, forming habit (ἄσκησις) as en- 
forced on the monk, the soldier, the schoolboy, 
as he is true to his own experience in assigning 
it partly also to a good natural disposition (φύσει) 
and he suggests afterwards, as I suppose some of 
us would be ready to do, that virtue is due also 
in part (θείᾳ μοίρᾳ) to the good pleasure of heaven, 
to un-merited grace. Whatever else, however, 
may be held about it, it is certain (he admits) 
that virtue comes in great measure through 
learning. But is there in very deed such a thing 
as learning? asks the eristic Meno, who is so 
youthfully fond of argument for its own sake, 
and must exercise by display his already well- 
trained intellectual muscle. Is not that favourite, 
that characteristic, Greek paradox, that it is 
impossible to be taught, and therefore useless 
to seek, what one does not know already, after 
all the expression of an empirical truth ?— 


Meno. After what manner Socrates will you seek for that 
which you do not know at all—what it is? For what sort of 
thing, among the things you know not, will you propose as your 

61 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


object of search? Or even if you should have lighted full 
upon it, how will you know that it is this thing which you 
knew not? 

Socrates. Ah! I understand the kind of thing you mean 
to say, Meno. Do you see what a contentious argument this 
is you are bringing down on our heads '—that forsooth it is 
not possible for a man to seek either for what he knows, or for 
what he knows not; inasmuch as he would not seek what he 
knows, at least ; because he knows it, and to one in such case 
there is no need of seeking. Nor would he seek after what he 
knows not; for he knows not what he shall seek for. 


Meno, 80. 


Well! that is true in a sense, as Socrates 
admits; not however in any sense which en- 
courages idle acquiescence in what according to 
common language is our ignorance. There is a 
sense (it is exemplified in regard to sound and 
colour, perhaps in some far more important 
things) in which it is matter of experience that 
it is impossible to seek for, or be taught, what 
one does not know already. He who is in total 
ignorance of musical notes, who has no ear, will 
certainly be unaware of them when they light 
on him, or he lights upon them. Where could 
one begin? we ask, in certain cases where not 
to know at all means incapacity for receiving 
knowledge. Yes, certainly ; the Pythagoreans 
are right in saying that what we call learning is 
in fact reminiscence—dvdéyryors: famous word ! 
and Socrates proceeds to show in what precise 
way it is impossible or possible to find out what 
you don’t know: how that happens. In full 
use of the dialogue, as itself the instrument most 

: 62 


THE DOCTRINE OF NUMBER 


fit for him of whatever what we call teaching 
and learning may really be, Plato, dramatic 
always, brings in one of Meno’s slaves, a boy 
who speaks Greek nicely, but knows nothing of 
geometry : introduces him, we may fancy, into 
a mathematical lecture-room where diagrams are 
to be seen on the walls, cubes and the like lying 
on the table—particular objects, the mere sight 
of which will rouse him when subjected to the 
dialectical treatment, to universal truths con- 
cerning them. The problem required of him 
is to describe a square of a particular size: to 
find the line which must be the side of such a 
square ; and he is to find it for himself. Meno, 
carefully on his guard, is to watch whether the 
boy is taught by Socrates in any of his answers ; 
whether he answers anything at any point other- 
wise than by way of reminiscence and really out 
of his own mind, as the reasonable questions of 
Socrates fall like water on the seed-ground, or 
like sunlight on the photographer’s negative. 
“See him now!” he cries triumphantly, 
‘‘ How he remembers ; in the logical order ; as 
he ought to remember!” The reader, in truth, 
following closely, scrupulously, this pretty process, 
cannot help seeing that after all the boy does not 
discover the essential point of the problem for 
himself, that he is more than just guided on his 
way by the questioning of Socrates, that Plato 
has chosen an instance in itself illusively clear as 
being concerned with elementary space. It is 
63 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


once for all, however, that he recognises, under 
such questioning, the immovable, indefectible 
certainty of this or that truth of space. So 
much, the candid reader must concede, is clearly 
to the advantage of the Pythagorean theory : 
that even his false guesses have a plausibility, a 
kinship to, a kind of claim upon, truth, about 
them: that as he remembers, in logical order 
(ὡς Se@) so he makes the mistakes also which he 
ought to make—the right sort of mistakes, such 
as are natural and ought to occur in order to the 
awakening mind, a kind of properly innate errors. 
Νῦν αὐτῷ ὥσπερ ὄναρ ἄρτι ἀνακεκίνηνται ai δόξαι αὗται. 
--“ Just now, as in a dream, these opinions have 
been stirred up within him”; and he will 
perform, Socrates assures us, similar acts of re- 
miniscence on demand, with other geometrical 
problems, with any and every problem whatever. 
“If then,” observes Socrates in the Phedo, 
wistfully pondering, for such consolation as 
there may be in it, in his last hours, the larger 
outlook suggested by this hopeful doctrine :— 
If, having apprehended it (having apprehended a certain 
mathematical principle, that is) before birth, we were born 
already possessed of this principle, had we not knowledge, both 
before and immediately upon our begetting here, not merely 
about the equal and the greater and the less, but about all other 
things of the kind? For our theory (of an innate knowledge, 
that is to say, independent of our experience here) our theory 
holds not a bit more about two equal lines, than about the 
absolute Beauty (was he going now to see its very face again, 


after the dim intermediate life here?) and about what is 
absolutely just and good, and about all things whatever, upon 


64 


THE DOCTRINE OF NUMBER 


which, in all our past questioning and answering, we set this 
seal—ois ἐπισφραγιζόμεθα rovro— That, which really is. Pheda, 
75: 


But to return to the cheerful pages of the 
Meno—from the prison-cell to the old mathe- 
matical lecture-room and that psychological ex- 
periment upon the young boy with the square :— 
Οὔκουν οὐδένος διδάξαντος, ἀλλ᾽ ἐρωτήσαντος, ἐπιστήσεται, 
ἀναλαβών, αὐτὸς ἐξ αὑτοῦ, ἐπιστήμην ᾽ ““ Through no 
one’s teaching, then, but by a process of mere 
questioning, will he attain a true science, 
knowledge in the fullest sense (ἐπιστήμη) by the 
recovery of such science out of himself ?”—Yes ! 
and that recovery is an act of reminiscence. 


These opinions therefore, the boy’s discover- 
able right notions about side and square and 
diagonal, were innate in him (ἐνῆσαν δέ ye αὐτῷ 
αὗται ai δόξαι) and surely, as Socrates was observing 
later, right opinions also concerning other things 
more important, which too, when stirred up by 
a process of questioning, will be established in 
him as consciously reasoned knowledge (ἐρωτήσει 
ἐπεγερθεῖσαι, ἐπιστῆμαι γίγνονται). That at least is 
what Plato is quite certain about: not quite so 
confident, however, regarding another doctrine, 
fascinating as he finds it, which seemed to afford 
an explanation of this leading psychological fact of 
an antecedent knowledge within us—the doctrine 
namely of metempsychésts, of the transmigration 
of souls through various forms of the bodily life, 

P. VI 65 F 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


under a law of moral retribution, somewhat 
oracularly suggested in the ancient poets, by 
Hesiod and Pindar, but a matter of formal con- 
sciousness with the Pythagoreans, and at last 
inseparably connected with the authority of 
Socrates, who in the Phedo discourses at great 
length on that so comfortable theory, venturing 
to draw from it, as we saw just now, a personal 
hope in the immediate prospect of death. The 
soul, then, would be immortal (ἀθάνατος ἂν ἡ 
ψυχὴ εἴη) prospectively as well as in retrospect, 
and is not unlikely to attain to clearer levels of 
truth “over the way, there,” as, in the Meno, 
Socrates drew from it an encouragement to the 
search for truth, here. Retrospectively, at all 
events, it seemed plain that ‘‘the soul is eternal. 
It is right therefore to make an effort to find out 
things one may not know, that is to say, one 
does not remember, just now.” Those notions 
were im the boy, they and the like of them, in 
all boys and men; and he did not come by them 
in this life, a young slave in Athens. Ancient, 
half-obliterated inscriptions on the mental walls, 
the mental tablet, seeds of knowledge to come, 
shed by some flower of it long ago, it was in an 
earlier period of time they had been laid up in 
him, to blossom again now, so kindly, so firmly! 

Upon a soul thus provided, puzzled as that 
seed swells within it under the spring-tide 
influences of this untried atmosphere, it would 
be the proper vocation of the philosophic teacher 


THE DOCTRINE OF NUMBER 


to supervene with his encouraging questions. 
And there was another doctrine—a persuasion 
still more poetical or visionary, it might seem, 
yet with a strong presumption of literal truth 
about it, when seen in connexion with that great 
fact of our consciousness which it so conveniently 
explains—‘“‘ reminiscence.” Socrates had heard 
it, he tells us in the Meno, in the /ocus classicus 
on this matter, from the venerable lips of certain 
religious persons, priests and priestesses, 


—who had made it their business to be able to give an account 
concerning their sacred functions. Pindar too asserts this, and 
many other of the poets, so many as were divinely inspired. 
And what they say is as follows.—But do you observe, whether 
they seem to you to speak the truth. For they say that the 
soul of man is immortal ; and that at one time it comes toa 
pause, which indeed they call dying, and then is born again ; 
but that it is never destroyed. [hat on this account indeed it 
is our duty to pass through life as religiously as possible (because 
there’s ‘another world,’ namely). ‘For those,’ says Pindar, 
‘from whom Persephone shall have received a recompense of 
ancient wrong—she gives back their soul again to the sun 
above in the ninth year, of whom are begotten kings, illustrious 
and swift in strength, and men greatest in wisdom ; and for 
remaining time they are called holy heroes among us.’ Inas- 
much then as the soul is immortal, and has been born many 
times, and has seen both things here and things in Hades, and 
all things, there is nothing that it has not learned ; so that it is 
_ by no means surprising that it should be able to remember both 
_ about virtue and about other matters what it knew at least even 
_ aforetime. For inasmuch as the whole of nature is akin to 
__ itself (homogeneous) and the soul has learned all things, nothing 
hinders one, by remembering one thing only, which indeed 
_ people call ‘learning’ (though it is something else in fact, you 
_ see!) from finding out all other things for himself, if he be brave 
and fail not through weariness in his search. For in truth to 


67 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


seek and to learn is wholly Recollection. ‘Therefore one must not 
be persuaded by that eristic doctrine (namely that if ignorant 
in ignorance you must remain) for that on the one hand would 
make us idle and is a pleasant doctrine for the weak among man- 
kind to hear ; while this other doctrine makes us industrious 
and apt to seek. ‘Trusting in which that it is true, I am willing 
along with you to seek out virtue :—what it is. Adena, 81. 


These strange theories then are much with 
Socrates on his last sad day—sad to his friends— 
as justifying more or less, on ancient religious 
authority, the instinctive confidence, checking 
sadness in himself, that he will survive—survive 
the effects of the poison, of the funeral fire ; 
that somewhere, with some others, with Minos 
perhaps and other “righteous souls” of the 
national religion, he will be holding discourses, 
dialogues, quite similar to these, only a little 
better as must naturally happen with so diligent 
a scholar, this time to-morrow. 


And that wild thought of metempsychésis was 
connected with a theory, yet more fantastic, of 
the visible heaven above us. For Pythagoras, 
the Pythagoreans, had had their views also, as 
became the possessors of “a first principle ”»— 
of a philosophy therefore which need leave no 
problem untouched—on purely material things, 
above all on the structure of the planets, the 
mechanical contrivances by which their motion 
was effected (it came to just that!) on the 
relation of the earth to its atmosphere and 
the like. The doctrine of the transmigration, © 

68 | 


THE DOCTRINE OF NUMBER 


the pilgrimage or mental journeys, of the soul 
linked itself readily with a fanciful, guess-work 
astronomy, which provided starry places, wide 
areas, hostelries, for that wanderer to move or rest 
in. A matter of very lively and presentable form 
and colour, as if making the invisible show 
through, this too pleased the extremely visual 
fancy of Plato; as we may see, in many places 
of the Phedo, the Phadrus, the Timeus, and 
most conspicuously in the tenth book of The 
Republic, where he relates the vision of Er— 
what he saw of the other world during a kind of 
temporary death. Hell, Purgatory, Paradise, are 
briefly depicted in it ; Paradise especially with a 
quite Dantesque sensibility to coloured light— 
_ physical light or spiritual, you can hardly tell 
which, so perfectly is the inward sense blent with 
its visible counter-part, reminding one forcibly 
of the Divine Comedy, of which those closing 
_ pages of The Republic suggest an early outline. 
That then is the third element in Plato 
_ derivative from his Pythagorean masters: an 
astronomy of infant minds, we might call it, in 
_ which the celestial world is the scene, not as yet 
_ of those abstract reasonable laws of number and 
_ motion and space, upon which, as Plato himself 
protests in the seventh book of The Republic, it 15 


_ the business of a veritable science of the stars to 


exercise our minds, but rather of a machinery, 

which the mere star-gazer may peep into as best 

he can, with its levers, its spindles and revolving 
69 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


wheels, its spheres, he says, ‘‘like those boxes 
which fit into one another,” and the literal doors 
‘“‘ opened in heaven,” through which, at the due 
point of ascension, the revolving pilgrim soul 
will glide forth and have a chance of gazing into 
the wide spaces beyond, ‘‘as he stands outside 
on the back of the sky”’—that hollow partly 
transparent sphere which surrounds and closes 
in our terrestrial atmosphere. Most difficult to 
follow in detailed description, perhaps not to be 
taken quite seriously, one thing at least is clear 
about the planetary movements as Plato and 
his Pythagorean teachers conceive them. They 
produce, naturally enough, sounds, that famous 
“music of the spheres,” which the undisciplined 
ear fails to recognise, to delight in, only because 
it is never silent. 

That it really is impossible after all to learn, 
to be taught what you are entirely ignorant of, 
was and still is a fact of experience, manifest 
especially in regard tomusic. Now that ‘ music 
of the spheres” in its largest sense, its completest 
orchestration, the harmonious order of the whole 
universe (κόσμος) was what souls had heard of old; 
found echoes of here; might recover in its 
entirety, amid the influences of the melodious 
colour, sounds, manners, the enforced modulating 
discipline, which would make the whole life of 
a citizen of the Perfect City an education in 
music. We are now with Plato, you see! in 
his reproduction, so fully detailed for us in The 

70 


THE DOCTRINE OF NUMBER 


Republic, of the earlier and vaguer Pythagorean 
brotherhood. Musical imagery, the notions of 
proportion and the like, have ever since Plato 
wrote played a large part in the theory of morals ; 
have come to seem almost a natural part of 
language concerning them. Only, wherever in 
Plato himself you find such imagery, you may 
note Pythagorean influence. 

The student of The Republic hardly needs to 
be reminded how all-pervasive in it that imagery 
is; how emphatic, in all its speculative theory, 
in all its practical provisions, is the desire for 
harmony ; how the whole business of education 
(of gymnastic even, the seeming rival of music) is 
brought under it ; how large a part of the claims 
of duty, of right conduct, for the perfectly initi- 
ated, comes with him to be this, that it sounds 
so well. TAnupérea, discordancy,—all faultiness 
resolves itself into that. ‘Canst play on this 
flute?’ asks Hamlet:—on human nature, with 
all its stops, of whose capricious tuneableness, or 
want of tune, he is himself the representative. 
Well! the perfect state, thinks Plato, can. For 
him, music is still everywhere in the world, and 
the whole business of philosophy only as it were 
the correct editing of it : as it will be the whole 
business of the state to repress, in the great 
concert, the jarring self-assertion (πλεονεξία) of 
those whose voices have large natural power in 
them. How, in detail, rhythm, the limit (πέρας) 
is enforced in Plato’s Repudb/ic there is no time to 

γι 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


show. Call to mind only that the perfect visible 
equivalent of such rhythm is in those portrait- 
statues of the actual youth of Greece—legacy of 
Greek sculpture more precious by far than its 
fancied forms of deity—the quoit-player, the 
diadumenus, the apoxyomenus ; and how the most 
beautiful type of such youth, by the universal 
admission of the Greeks themselves, had issued 
from the severe schools of Sparta, that highest 
civic embodiment of the Dorian temper, like 
some perfect musical instrument, perfectly re- 
sponsive to the intention, to the lightest touch, 
of the finger of law.—Yet with a fresh setting of 
the old music in each succeeding generation. 
For in truth we come into the world, each one 
of us, “not in nakedness,” but by the natural 
course of organic development clothed far more 
completely than even Pythagoras supposed in a 
vesture of the past, nay, fatally shrouded, it 
might seem, in those laws or tricks of heredity 
which we mistake for our volitions; in the 
language which is more than one half of our 
thoughts ; in the moral and mental habits, the 
customs, the literature, the very houses, which 
we did not make for ourselves ; in the vesture of 
a past, which is (so science would assure us) not 
ours, but of the race, the species : that Zest-geist, 
or abstract secular process, in which, as we 
could have had no direct consciousness of it, so 
we can pretend to no future personal interest. It 
is humanity itself now—abstract humanity—that 
72 


THE DOCTRINE OF NUMBER 


figures as the transmigrating soul, accumulating 
into its “colossal manhood” the experience of 
ages ; making use of, and casting aside in its 
march, the souls of countless individuals, as 
Pythagoras supposed the individual soul to cast 
aside again and again its outworn body. 

So it may be. There was nothing of all 
that, however, in the mind of the great English 
poet at the beginning of this century whose 
famous Ode on The Intimations of Immortality from 
Recollections of Childhood, in which he made metem- 
psychosis his own, must still express for some 
minds something more than merely poetic truth. 
For Pythagoreanism too, like all the graver 
utterances of primitive Greek philosophy, is an 
instinct of the human mind itself, and therefore 
also a constant tradition in its history, which wz// 
recur ; fortifying this or that soul here or there 
in a part at least of that old sanguine assurance 
about itself, which possessed Socrates so immov- 
ably, his masters, his disciples. Those who do 
not already know Wordsworth’s Ode ought soon 
to read it for themselves. Listen instead to the 
lines which perhaps suggested Wordsworth’s :— 
The Retreat, by Henry Vaughan, one of the so- 
called Platonist poets of about two centuries ago, 
who was able to blend those Pythagorean doctrines 
with the Christian belief, amid which indeed, 
from the unsanctioned dreams of Origen onwards, 
those doctrines have shown themselves not other- 
wise than at home. 

73 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 
Happy, those days, he declares, 


Before I understood this place, 
Appointed for my second race ; 

Or taught my soul to fancy ought 
But a white celestial thought ; 

When yet I had not walked above 

A mile or two from my first love ; 
But felt through all this fleshly dress 
Bright shoots of everlastingness. 

O! how I long to travel back 

And tread again that ancient track ! 
That I might once more reach that plain, 
Where first I left my glorious train.— 
But Ah! my soul with too much stay 
Is drunk ; and staggers in the way. 
Some men a forward motion love, 

But I backward steps would move ; 
And when this dust falls to the urn 

In that state I came return. 


Summing up those three philosophies ante- 
cedent to Plato, we might say, that if Heraclitus 
taught the doctrine of progress, and the Eleatics 
that of rest, so, in such quaint phrase as 
Vaughan’s, Pythagoreanism is the philosophy of 


re-action. 


74 


IV 
PLATO AND SOCRATES 


“PLaTo,” we say habitually when we talk of 
our teacher in The Republic, the Phedrus, cut- 
ting a knot; for Plato speaks to us indirectly 
only, in his Dialogues, by the voice of the 
Platonic Socrates, a figure most ambiguously 
compacted of the real Socrates and Plato himself ; 
a purely dramatic invention, it might perhaps 
have been fancied, or, so to speak, an zdolon theatri 
—Plato’s self, but presented, with the reserve 
appropriate to his fastidious genius, in a kind 
of stage disguise. So we might fancy but for 
certain independent information we possess about 
Socrates, in Aristotle, and in the Memorabilia of 
Xenophon. 

The Socrates of Xenophon is one of the 
simplest figures in the world. From the personal 
memories of that singularly-limpid writer the 
outline of the great teacher detaches itself, as 
an embodiment of all that was clearest in the 
now adult Greek understanding, the adult Greek 
conscience. All that Socrates is seen to be in 

75 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


those unaffected pages may be explained by the 
single desire to be useful to ordinary young men, 
whose business in life would be mainly with 
practical things ; and at first sight, as delineators 
of their common master, Plato and Xenophon 
might seem scarcely reconcilable. But then, as 
Alcibiades alleges of him in the Symposium, 
Socrates had been ever in all respects a two- 
sided being ; like some rude figure of Silenus, he 
suggests, by way of an outer case for the image 
of a god within. By a mind, of the compass 
Plato himself supposes, two quite different 
impressions may well have been made on two 
typically different observers. The speaker, to 
Xenophon so simple, almost homely, earthy, 
vernacular, becomes with Plato the mouth-piece 
of high and difficult and extraordinary thoughts. 
In the absence, then, of a single written word 
from Socrates himself, the question is forced 
upon us: had the true Socrates been really 
Socrates according to Xenophon, and all besides only 
a generous loan from the rich treasury of Plato’s 
quite original and independent genius: or, had 
the master been indeed something larger and 
more many-sided than Xenophon could have 
thoroughly understood, presenting to his simpler 
disciple only what was of simpler stamp in 
himself, to the mystic and susceptible Plato all 
that far-reaching and fervid intellectuality, with 
which the Platonic Dialogues credit him. It 
is a problem about which probably no reader of 
76 


PLATO AND SOCRATES 


Plato ever quite satisfies himself :—-how much 
precisely he must deduct from Socrates, as we 
find him in those Dialogues, by way of defining 
to himself the Socrates of fact. 

In Plato’s own writing about Socrates there 
is, however, a difference. The fo/ogy, marked 
as being the single writing from Plato’s hand 
not in dialogue form, we may naturally take for 
a sincere version of the actual words of Socrates ; 
closer to them, we may think, than the Greek 
record of spoken words however important, the 
speeches in Thucydides, for instance, by the 
admission of Thucydides himself, was wont to 
be. And this assumption is supported by internal 
evidence. In that unadorned language, in those 
harsh grammatic (or rather quite ungrammatic) 
constructions we have surely the natural accent 
of one speaking under strong excitement. We 
might think, again, that the Phedo, purporting 
to record his subsequent discourse, is really no 
more than such a record, but for a lurking 
suspicion, which hangs by the fact that Plato, 
noted as an assistant at the trial, is expressly 
stated by one of the speakers in the Dialogue to 
have been absent from the dying scene of Socrates. 
That speaker however was himself perhaps the 
veracious reporter of those last words and acts ; 
for there are details in the Phedo too pedestrian 
and common-place to be taken for things of mere 
literary invention : the rubbing of the legs, for in- 
stance, now released from the chain; the rather 

77 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


uneasy determination to be indifferent ; the some- 
what harsh committal of the crudely lamenting 
wife and his child ‘‘ to any one who will take the 
trouble ’’— details, as one cannot but observe in 
passing, which leave those famous hours, even for 
purely human, or say ! pagan dignity and tender- 
ness, wholly incomparable to one sacred scene to 
which they have sometimes been compared. 

We shall be justified then, in the effort to 
give reality or truth to our mental picture of 
Socrates, if we follow the lead of his own supposed 
retrospect of his career in the Apology, as com- 
pleted, and explained to wholly sympathetic 
spirits, by the more intimate discourses of the 
Phedo. 

He pleads to be excused if in making his 
defence he speaks after his accustomed manner : 
not merely in home-spun phrase, that is to say, 
very different from what is usually heard at least 
in those sophisticated law-courts of Athens, nor 
merely with certain lapsing into his familiar 
habit of dialogue, but with a tacit assumption, 
throughout his arguments, of that logical 
realism which suggested the first outline of 
Plato’s doctrine of the “ideas.” Everywhere, 
with what is like a physical passion for what zs, 
what is ¢rue—as one engaged in a sort of religious 
or priestly concentration of soul on what God 
really made and meant us to know—he is driv- 
ing earnestly, yet with method, at those universal 
conceptions or definitions which serve to establish 

78 


PLATO AND SOCRATES 


firmly the distinction, attained by so much 
intellectual labour, between what is absolute and 
abiding, of veritable import therefore to our 
reason, to the divine reason really resident in 
each one of us, resident in, yet separable from, 
these our houses of clay — between that, and 
what is only phenomenal and transitory, as 
being essentially implicate with them. He 
achieved this end, as we learn from Aristotle, 
this power, literally, of “‘a criticism of life,” by 
induction (ἐπαγωγή) by that careful process of 
enquiry into the facts of the matter concerned, 
one by one (facts most often of conscience, of 
moral action as conditioned by motive, and 
result, and the varying degrees of inward light 
upon it) for which the fitting method is informal 
though not unmethodical question and answer, 
face to face with average mankind, as in those 
famous Socratic conversations, which again are 
the first rough natural erowth of Plato’s so 
artistic written Dialogues. The exclusive pre- 
occupation of Socrates with practical matter 
therein, his anxious fixing of the sense of such 
familiar terms as just and good, for instance, was 
part of that humble bearing of himself by which 
he was to authenticate a claim to superior 
wisdom, forced upon him by nothing less than 
divine authority, while there was something 
also in it of a natural reaction against the intel- 
lectual ambition of his youth. He had gone 
to school eagerly, as he tells his friends in the 
79 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


Phedo, in his last discourse, to a physical philo- 
sopher, then of great repute, but to his own great 
disappointment.— 


In my youth he says I had a wonderful desire for the 
wisdom which people call natural sclence—repi φύσεως ἱστορίαν. 
It seemed to me a proud thing to know the causes of every 
matter: how it comes to be ; ceases to be; why itis. I lost 
my sight in this enquiry to the degree of un-learning what 
I had hitherto seemed to myself and others to know clearly 
enough. But having heard one reading from a book written, 
as he said, by Anaxagoras, which said that it is Reason that 
arranges and is the cause of all things, I was delighted with 
this cause; and thought to myself, if this be so, then it does 
with each what may be best for it. Thus considering, it was 
with joy I fancied I had found me a teacher about the cause— 
Anaxagoras: that he would show me for instance, first, 
whether the earth was round or flat ; and then that it was best 
for it to be so: and if he made these points clear I was pre- 
pared to ask for no other sort of causes. Phedo, 96. 


Well! Socrates proceeds to the great natural 
philosopher, and is immensely discouraged to 
find him after all making very little use of 
Reason in his explanation why natural things 
are thus and not otherwise ; explaining every- 
thing, rather, by secondary and mechanical 
causes. ‘It was as if,” he concludes, “ some one 
had undertaken to prove that Socrates does 
everything through Reason; and had gone on 
to show that it was because my body is con- 
structed in a certain way, of certain bones and 
muscles, that Socrates is now sitting here in the 
prison, voluntarily awaiting death.” 

The disappointment of Socrates with the 

80 


PLATO AND SOCRATES 


spirit in which Anaxagoras actually handled and 
applied that so welcome sapiential proposition 
that Reason πάντα διακόσμει, καὶ πάντων αἴτιός ἐστιν 
—arranges and is the cause of all things—is 
but an example of what often happens when 
men seek an @ posteriori justification of their in- 
stinctive prepossessions. Once for all he turns 
from useless, perhaps impious, enquiries, into the 
material structure of the stars above him, or the 
earth beneath his feet, from all physical enquiry 
into material things, to the direct knowledge of 
man, the cosmical order in man, as it may be 
found by any one who, in good faith with 
himself, and with devout attention, looks within. 
In this precise sense it was that, according to 
the old saying, Socrates brought philosophy 
down from heaven to earth. Montaigne, the 
great humanist, expands it.—‘‘’ITwas he who 
brought again from heaven, where she lost her 
time, human wisdom, to restore her to man 
with whom her most just and greatest business 
lies. He has done human nature a great 
service,” he adds, “in showing it how much it 
can do of itself.” And a singular incident gave 
that piercing study, that relentless exposure, of 
himself, and of others, for the most part so un- 
welcome to them, a religious or mystic char- 
acter. He has a “vocation” thus to proceed, 
has been literally ‘‘ called,” as he understands, by 
the central religious authority of Greece. His 
seemingly invidious testing of men’s pretensions 
P. VI 81 G 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


to know, is a sacred service to the God of Delphi, 
which he dares not neglect. And his fidelity 
herein had in turn the effect of reinforcing for 
him, and bringing to a focus, all the other rays 
of religious light cast at random in the world 
about him, or in himself. 


“You know Cherephon,” he says, “his 
eagerness about any matter he takes up. Well! 
once upon a time he went to Delphi, and 
ventured to ask of the oracle whether any man 
living was wiser than I; and, amazing as it 
seems, the Pythia answered that there was no one 
wiser than I.” Socrates must go in order, then, 
to every class of persons pre-eminent for know- 
ledge ; to every one who seems to know more 
than he. He found them—-the Athenian poets, 
for instance, the potters who made the vases we 
admire, undeniably in possession of much de- 
lightful knowledge unattained by him. But one 
and all they were ignorant of the limitations of 
their knowledge ; and at last he concludes that 
the oracle had but meant to say: “ He indeed is 
the wisest of all men who like Socrates is aware 
that he is really worth little or nothing in 
respect of knowledge.” Such consciousness of 
ignorance was the proper wisdom of man. 

That can scarcely be a fiction. His whole- 
some appeal then, everywhere, from what seems, _ 
to what really is, is a service to the Delphic god, 
the god of sanity. To prove that the oracle had — 

82 | 


PLATO AND SOCRATES 


been right after all, improbable as it seemed, in 
the signal honour it had put upon him, would 
be henceforward his proper business. Com- 
mitting him to a sort of ironical humility 
towards others, at times seemingly petty and 
prosaic, certainly very irritating, in regard to 
himself, in its source and motive, his business in 
life as he conceived it was nothing less than 
a divine possession. He becomes therefore 
literally an enthusiast for knowledge, for the 
knowledge of man; such knowledge as by a 
right method of questioning, of self-questioning 
(the master’s questioning being after all only a 
kind of mid-wife’s assistance, according to his 
own homely figure) may be brought to birth in 
every human soul, concerning itself and its 
experience; what is real, and stable, in its 
apprehensions of Piety, Beauty, Justice, and the 
like, what is of dynamic quality in them, as 
conveying force into what one does or creates, 
building character, generating virtue. Αὐτὸ καθ᾽ 
αὑτὸ ζητεῖν τί ποτ᾽ ἔστιν ἀρετή----ἰο seek out what 
virtue is, itself, in and by itself—there’s the task. 
And when we have found that, we shall know 
already, or easily get to know, everything else 
about and about it: “how we are to come by 
virtue,” for instance. 

| Well! largely by knowing, says naturally the 
enthusiast for knowledge. There is no good 
thing which knowledge does not comprehend— 
Μηδέν ἐστιν ἀγαθὸν ὃ οὐκ ἐπιστήμη περιέχει---ἃ Strenu- 
83 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


ously ascertained knowledge however, painfully 
adjusted to other forms of knowledge which may 
seem inconsistent with it, and impenetrably 
distinct from any kind of complaisant or only 
half-attentive conjecture. ‘“‘One and the same 
species in every place: whole and sound: one, 
in regard to, and through, and upon, all par- 
ticular instances of it: catholic” !: it will be all 
this—the Virtue, for instance, which we must 
seek, as a hunter his sustenance, seek and find 
and never lose again, through a survey of all the 
many variable and merely relative virtues, which 
are but relative, that is to say, “to every several 
act, and to each period of life, in regard to each 
thing we have to do, in each one of us”—«aé’ 
ἑκάστην τῶν πράξεων, Kal τῶν ἡλικιῶν πρὸς ἕκαστον ἔργον, 
ἑκάστῳ ἡμῶν. “That, about which I don’t know 
what it is, how should I know what sort of a 
thing it is "—6 μὴ οἶδα τί ἐστι, πῶς ἂν ὁποῖόν γέ τι 
εἰδείην; What its ποιότητες, its qualities, are? ‘‘Do 


you suppose that one who does not know Meno, i 


for example, at all, who he is, can know whether 
he is fair and rich and well-born, or the reverse 
of all that?” Yes! already for Socrates, we 
might say, to know what Justice or Piety or 
Beauty really is, will be like the knowledge of a 
person; only that, as Aristotle carefully notes, 
his scrupulous habit of search for universal, or 
catholic, definitions (καθ᾽ ὅλου) was after all but 


1 Ῥαὐτὸν πανταχοῦ εἶδος---ὅλον καὶ ὑγιές---ἔν κατὰ πάντων, διὰ 
πάντων, ἐπὶ πᾶσι---καθ᾽ ὅλου. 


84 


PLATO AND SOCRATES 


an instrument for the plain knowledge of facts. 
Strange ! out of the practical cautions of Socrates 
for the securing of clear and correct and sufh- 
cient conceptions about one’s actual experience, 
for the attainment of a sort of thoroughly 
educated common-sense, came the mystic intel- 
lectualism of Plato—Platonism, with all its 
hazardous flights of soul. 

A rich contributor to the philosophic con- 
sciousness of Plato, Socrates was perhaps of larger 
influence still on the religious soul in him. 
As Plato accepted from the masters of Elea the 
theoretic principles of all natural religion—the 
principles of a reasonable monotheism, so from 
Socrates he derived its indispensable morality. 
It was Socrates who first of pagans comprised in 
one clear consciousness the authentic rudiments 
of such natural religion, and gave them clear 
utterance. Through him, Parmenides had 
conveyed to Plato the notion of a “ Perfect 
Being,” to brace and satisfy the abstracting 
intellect ; but it was from Socrates himself Plato 
had learned those correspondent practical pieties, 
which tranquillise and re-assure the soul, to- 
gether with the genial hopes which cheer the 
great teacher on the day of his death. 

Loyal to the ancient beliefs, the ancient 
usages, of the religion of many gods which he 
had found all around him, Socrates pierces 
through it to one unmistakable person, of perfect 
intelligence, power and goodness, who takes note 

85 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


of him. In the course of his seventy years he 
has adjusted that thought of the invisible to the 
general facts and to many of the subtler com- 
plexities of man’s experience in the world of 
sight. ΠΟΙ anima mea, the Athenian philo- 
sopher might say, zz Deum, in Deum vrvum, as he 
was known at Sion. He has at least measured 
devoutly the place, this way and that, which a 
religion of infallible authority must fill; has 
already by implication concurred in it; and in 
fact has his reward at this depressing hour, as 
the action of the poison mounts slowly to the 
centre of his material existence. He is more 
than ready to depart to what before one has 
really crossed their threshold must necessarily 
seem the cold and empty spaces of the world no 
bodily eye can ever look on. 

But, he is asked, if the prospect be indeed so 
cheerful, at all events for the just, why is it 
forbidden to seize such an advantage as death 
must be by self-destruction ?—Tois ἀνθρώποις, μὴ 
ὅσιον εἶναι, αὐτοὺς ἑαυτοὺς εὐποιεῖν, GAN Adrov δεῖ μένειν 
εὐεργέτην. His consistent piety straightway sug- 
gests the solution of that paradox: we are the 
property, slaves, of the gods. Now no slave 
has any sort of right to destroy himself; to take 
a life that does not really belong to him. 
Comfort himself and his friends, however, as he 
may, it does tax all his resources of moral and 
physical courage to do what is at last required 
of him : and it was something quite new, unseen 

86 


a 


PLATO AND SOCRATES 


before in Greece, inspiring a new note in litera- 
ture—this attitude of Socrates in the condemned 
cell, where, fulfilling his own prediction, multi- 
tudes, of a wisdom and piety, after all, so different 
from his, have ever since assisted so admiringly, 
this anticipation of the Christian way of dying 
for an opinion, when, as Plato says simply, he 
consumed the poison in the prison—vré φάρμακον 
ἔπιεν ἐν τῷ δεσμωτηρίῳ. It was amid larger consola- 
tions, we must admit, that Christian heroes 
did that kind of thing. But bravery, you need 
hardly be reminded, was ever one of the specially 
characteristic virtues of the pagan world—loyalty 
even unto death. It had been loyalty however 
hitherto to one’s country, one’s home in the world, 
one’s visible companions ; not to a wholly invisible 
claimant, in this way, upon one, upon one’s self. 

Socrates, with all his singleness of purpose, 
had been, as Alcibiades suggested, by natural con- 
stitution a twofold power, an embodied paradox. 
The infinitely significant Socrates of Plato, and 
the quite simple Socrates of Xenophon, may 
have been indeed the not incompatible opposi- 
tions of a nature, from the influence of which, 
as a matter of fact, there emerged on one hand 
the Cynic, on the other the Cyrenaic School, 
embodying respectively those opposed austerities 
and amenities of character, which, according to 
the temper of this or that disciple, had seemed 
to predominate in their common master. And 
so the courage which declined to act as almost 

87 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


any one else would have acted in that matter 
of the legal appeal which might have miti- 
gated the penalty of death, bringing to its appro- 
priate end a life whose main power had been 
an unrivalled independence, was contrasted in 
Socrates, paradoxically, with a genuine diff- 
dence about his own convictions which explains 
some peculiarities in his manner of teaching. 
The irony, the humour, for which he was 
famous—the unfailing humour which some 
have found in his very last words—were not 
merely spontaneous personal traits, or tricks of 
manner ; but an essential part of the dialectical 
apparatus, as affording a means of escape from 
responsibility, convenient for one who _ has 
scruples about the fitness of his own thoughts 
for the reception of another, doubts as to the 
power of words to convey thoughts, such as he 
thinks cannot after all be properly conveyed to 
another, but only awakened, or brought to birth 
in him, out of himself,—who can tell with what 
distortions in that secret place? For we judge 
truth not by the intellect exclusively, and on 
reasons that can be adequately embodied in 
propositions ; but with the whole complex man. 
Observant therefore of the capricious results of 
mere teaching, to the last he protests, dis- 
semblingly, and with that irony which is really 
one phase of the Socratic humour, that in his 
peculiar function there have been in very deed 
neither teacher nor learners. 
88 


PLATO AND SOCRATES 


The voice, the sign from heaven, that “ new 
deity” he was accused of fabricating (his 
singularly profound sense of a mental phe- 
nomenon which is probably not uncommon) 
held perhaps of the same characteristic habit of 
mind. It was neither the playful pretence 
which some have supposed ; nor yet an insoluble 
mystery ; but only what happens naturally to a 
really diffident spirit in great and still more in 
small matters which at this or that taxing 
moment seem to usurp the determination of 
great issues. Such a spirit may find itself beset 
by an inexplicable reluctance to do what would 
be most natural in the given circumstances. 
And for a religious nature, apt to trace the 
divine assistance everywhere, it was as if, in 
those perilous moments— well! as if one’s 
guardian angel held one back. A quite natural 
experience took the supernatural hue of religion ; 
which, however, as being concerned now and 
then with some circumstance in itself trifling, 
might seem to lapse at times into superstition. 

And as he was thus essentially twofold in 
character, so Socrates had to contend against 
two classes of enemies. “Ἀπ offence” to the 
whole tribe of Sophists, he was hated also by 
those who hated them, by the good old men of 
Athens, whose conservatism finds its representa- 
tive in Aristophanes, and who saw in the Socratic 
challenge of first principles, in that ceaseless 
testing of the origin and claims of what all 

89 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


honest people might seem to take for granted, 
only a further development of the pernicious 
function of the Sophists themselves, by the most 
subtly influential of them all. If in the Apology 
he proves that the fathers of sons had no proper 
locus standt against him, still, in the actual 
conduct of his defence, as often in Plato’s 
Dialogues, there is (the candid reader cannot 
but admit it) something of sophistry, of the 
casuist. Claiming to be but a simple argument, 
the Apology of Socrates moves sometimes 
circuitously, after the manner of one who really 
has to make the worse appear the better reason 
(τὸν ἥττω λόγον κρείττω ποιεῖν) aNd must needs use a 
certain kind of artificial, or ingenious, or ad 
captandum arguments, such as would best have 
been learned in the sophistic school. Those 
young Athenians whom he was thought to have 
corrupted of set purpose, he had not only 
admired but really loved and understood ; and as 
a consequence had longed to do them real good, 
chiefly by giving them that interest in themselves 
which is the first condition of any real power 
over others. ‘To make Meno, Polus, Charmides, 
really interested in himself, to help him to the 
discovery of that wonderful new world here at 
home—in this effort, even more than in making 
them interested in other people and things, lay 
and still lies (it is no sophistical paradox !) the 
central business of education. Only, the very 
thoroughness of the sort of self-knowledge he 
go 


PLATO AND SOCRATES 


promoted had in it something sacramental, so 
to speak ; if it did not do them good, must do 
them considerable harm ; could not leave them 
just as they were. He had not been able in all 
cases to expand “ the better self,” as people say, 
in those he influenced. Some of them had really 
become very insolent questioners of others, as 
also of a wholly legitimate authority within 
themselves; and had but passed from bad to 
worse. That fatal necessity had been involved 
of coming to years of discretion. His claim to 
have been no teacher at all, to be irresponsible 
in regard to those who had in truth been his 
very willing disciples, was but humorous or 
ironical; and as a consequence there was after 
all a sort of historic justice in his death. 


The fate of Socrates (says Hegel, in his peculiar manner) is 
tragic in the essential sense, and not merely in that superficial 
sense of the word according to which every misfortune is called 
“tragic.” In the latter sense, one might say of Socrates that 
because he was condemned to death unjustly his fate was 
tragic. But in truth innocent suffering of that sort is merely 
pathetic, not tragic ; inasmuch as it is not within the sphere of 
reason. Now suffering—misfortune—comes within the sphere 
of reason, only if it is brought about by the free-will of the 
subject, who must be entirely moral and justifiable ; as must 
be also the power against which that subject proceeds. ‘This 
power must be no merely natural one, nor the mere will of a 
tyrant ; because it is only in such case that the man is himself, 
so to speak, guilty of his misfortune. In genuine tragedy, 
then, they must be powers both alike moral and ‘ustifiable, 
which, from this side and from that, come into collision ; and 
such was the fate of Socrates. His fate therefore is not merely 
personal, and as it were part of the romance of an individual : 


ΟΙ 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


it is the general fate, in all its tragedy—the tragedy of Athens, 
of Greece, which is therein carried out. “Two opposed Rights 
come forth: the one breaks itself to pieces against the other : 
in this way, both alike suffer loss ; while both alike are justified 
the one towards the other: not as if this were right; that 
other wrong. On the one side is the religious claim, the 
unconscious moral habit: the other principle, over against it, 
is the equally religious claim—the claim of the consciousness, 
of the reason, creating a world out of itself, the claim to eat of 
the tree of the knowledge of good and evil. The latter 
remains the common principle of philosophy for all time to 
come. And these are the two principles which come forth 
over against each other, in the life and in the philosophy of 
Socrates. Geschichte der Philosophie, vol. ii. p. 102. 


“1 can easily conceive Socrates in the place 
of Alexander,” says Montaigne, again, ‘“‘ but 
Alexander in the place of Socrates I cannot” ; 
and we may take that as typical of the immense 
credit of Socrates, even with a vast number of 
people who have not really known much about 
him. “For the sake of no long period of years,” 
says Socrates himself, now condemned to death 
—the few years for which a man of seventy is 
likely to remain here— 

You will have a name, Men of Athens! and liability to 
reproach from those who desire to malign the city of Athens— 
that ye put Socrates to death, a wise man. For in very truth 
they will declare me to have been wise—those who wish to 
discredit you—even though I be not. Now had you waited 
a little while this thing would have happened for you in the 


course of nature. For ye see my estate: that it is now far 
onward on the road of life, hard by death. Apology, 38. 


Plato, though present at the trial, was absent 
when Socrates “consumed the poison in the 
92 


PLATO AND SOCRATES 


prison.” Prevented by sickness, as Cebes tells 
us in the Phedo, Plato would however almost 
certainly have heard from him, or from some 
other of that band of disciples who assisted at 
the last utterances of their master, the sincerest 
possible account of all that was then said and 
done. Socrates had used the brief space which 
elapsed before the officers removed him to the 
place, “ whither he must go, to die” (οἱ ἐλθόντα pe 
δεῖ τεθνάναι) to discourse with those who still 
lingered in the court precisely on what are 
called “The four last things.” Arrived at the 
prison a further delay awaited him, in consequence 
(it was so characteristic of the Athenian people !) 
of a religious scruple. The ship of sacred annual 
embassy to Apollo at Delos was not yet returned 
to Athens ; and the consequent interval of time 
might not be profaned by the death of a criminal. 
Socrates himself certainly occupies it religiously 
enough by a continuation of his accustomed 
discourses, touched now with the deepening 
solemnity of the moment. 

The Phado of Plato has impressed most 
readers as a veritable record of those last discourses 
of Socrates; while in the details of what then 
happened, the somewhat prosaic account there 
given of the way in which the work of death 
was done, we find what there would have been 
no literary satisfaction in inventing ; his indiffer- 
ent treatment, for instance, of the wife, who had 
not been very dutiful but was now in violent 

93 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


distress—treatment in marked contrast, it must 
be observed again, with the dignified tenderness 
of a later scene, as recorded in the Gospels. 

An inventor, with mere literary effect in view, 
at this and other points would have invented 
differently. ‘“‘The prison,” says Cebes, the 
chief disciple in the Phedo, “was not far from 
the court-house; and there we were used to 
wait every day till we might be admitted to 
our master. One morning we were assembled 
earlier than usual ; for on the evening before we 
heard that the ship was returned from Delos. 
The porter coming out bade us tarry till he 
should call us. For, he said, the Eleven are 
now freeing Socrates from his bonds, announcing 
to him that he must die to-day.” 

They were very young men, we are told, 
who were with Socrates, and how sweetly, 
kindly, approvingly, he listened to their so 
youthfully sanguine discussion on the immor- 
tality of the soul. For their sakes rather than 
his own he is ready to treat further, by way of 
a posteriori arguments, a belief which in himself 
is matter of invincible natural prepossession. In 
the court he had pleaded at the most for sus- 
pended judgment on that question:—“If I 
claimed on any point to be wiser than any one 
else it would be in this, that having no adequate 
knowledge of things in Hades so I do not fancy 
I know.” But, in the privacy of these last 
hours, he is confident in his utterance on the 

94 


. 
| 
: 


PLATO AND SOCRATES 


subject which is so much in the minds of the 
youths around him; his arguments like theirs 
being in fact very much of the nature of the 
things poets write (ποιήματα) or almost like those 
medicinable fictions (ψευδῆ ἐν φαρμάκου εἴδει) such 
as are of legitimate use by the expert. That the 
soul (beautiful Pythagorean thought !) is a har- 
mony ; that there are reasons why this particular 
harmony should not cease, like that of the lyre or 
the harp, with the destruction of the instrument 
which produced it ; why this sort of flame should 
not go out with the upsetting of the lamp :— 
such are the arguments, sometimes little better 
than verbal ones, which pass this way and that 
around the death-bed of Socrates, as they still 
occur to men’s minds. For himself, whichever 
way they tend, they come and go harmlessly, 
about an immovable personal conviction, which, as 
he says, “came to me apart from demonstration, 
with a sort of natural likelihood and fitness” : 
(Mot γέγονεν ἄνευ ἀποδείξεως, μετὰ εἰκότος τινός, καὶ 
εὐπρεπείας). ‘The formula of probability could 
not have been more aptly put. It is one of 
those convictions which await, it may be, 
stronger, better, arguments than are forthcom- 
ing; but will wait for them with unfailing 
patience. —“ The soul therefore Cebes,’”’ since 
such provisional arguments must be allowed to 
pass, “18 something sturdy and strong (ἰσχυρόν τι 
ἔστιν) imperishable by accident or wear; and we 
shall really exist in Hades.” Indulging a little 
95 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


further the “poetry turned logic” of those 
youthful assistants, Socrates too, even Socrates, 
who had always turned away so _ persistently 
from what he thought the vanity of the eye, 
just before the bodily eye finally closes, and his 
last moment being now at hand, ascends to, 
or declines upon, the fancy of a quite visible 
paradise awaiting him.— 


It is said that the world, if one gaze down on it from 
above, is to look on like those leathern balls of twelve pieces, 
variegated in divers colours, of which the colours here—those 
our painters use—are as it were samples. ‘There, the whole 
world is formed of such, and far brighter and purer than they ; 
part sea-purple of a wonderful beauty ; a part like gold; a part 
whiter than alabaster or snow; aye, composed thus of other 
colours also of like quality, of greater loveliness than ours— 
colours we have never seen. For even those hollows in it, 
being filled with air and water, present a certain species of 
colour gleaming amid the diversity of the others ; so that it 
presents one continuous aspect of varied hues. ‘Thus it is: 
and conformably tree and flower and fruit are put forth and 
grow. ‘The mountains again and the rocks, after the same 
manner, have a smoothness and transparency and colours 
lovelier than here. The tiny precious stones we prize so 
greatly are but morsels of them—sards and jasper and emerald 
and the rest. No baser kind of thing is to be found in that 
world, but finer rather. The cause of which is that the 
rocks there are pure, not gnawed away and corrupted like 
ours by rot and brine, through the moistures which drain 
together here, bringing disease and deformity to rocks and 
earth as well as to living things. “Ichere are many living 
creatures in the land besides men and women, some abiding 
inland, and some on the coasts of the air, as we by the sea, 
others in the islands amidst its waves ; for, in a word, what the 
water of the sea is to us for our uses, that the air is to them. 
The blending of the seasons there is such that they have no 
sickness and come to years more numerous far than ours: while 


96 


PLATO AND SOCRATES 


for sight and scent and hearing and the like they stand as far 
from us, as air from water, in respect of purity, and the ether 
from air. There are thrones moreover and temples of the 
gods among them, wherein in very deed the gods abide ; voices 
and oracles and sensible apprehensions of them ; and occasions 
of intercourse with their very selves. ‘The sun, the moon and 
the stars they see as they really are; and are blessed in all 
other matters agreeably thereto. Phedo, 110. 


The great assertor of the abstract, the im- 


palpable, the unseen, at any cost, shows there 
a mastery of visual expression equal to that of 
his greatest disciple.—Ah, good master! was 


the eye so contemptible an organ of knowledge 
after all? 


Plato was then about twenty-eight years old ; 
a rich young man, rich also in intellectual gifts ; 
and what he saw and heard from and about 
Socrates afforded the correction his opulent 
genius needed, and made him the most serious 
of writers. In many things he was as unlike 


as possible to the’ teacher—rude and rough as 
some failure of his own old sculptor’s workshop 
-—who might seem in his own person to have 
broken up the harmonious grace of the Greek 


type, and carried people one step into a world 


already in reaction against the easy Attic temper, 
ἃ world in which it might be necessary to go far 
_below the surface for the beauty of which those 


homely lips had discoursed so much. Perhaps 


he acted all the more surely as a corrective force 
on Plato, henceforward an opponent of the 


P. VI 97 H 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


obviously successful mental habits of the day, 
with an unworldliness which, a personal trait 
in Plato himself there acquired, will ever be of 
the very essence of Platonism.—‘‘ Many are 
called, but few chosen” : Ναρθηκοφόροι μὲν πολλοί, 
βάκχοι δέ τε παῦρο. He will have, as readers of 
The Republic know, a hundred precepts of self- 
repression for others—the self-repression of every 
really tuneable member of a chorus; and he 
begins by almost effacing himself. All that is 
best and largest in his own matured genius he 
identifies with his master ; and when we speak 
of Plato generally what we are really thinking 
of is the Platonic Socrates. 


98 


ν 


PLATO AND THE SOPHISTS 


“SopHIsT,” professional enemy of Socrates :—it 
became, chiefly through the influence of Plato, 
inheriting, expanding, the preferences and anti- 
_ pathies of his master, a bad name. Yet it had 
_ but indicated, by a quite natural verbal formation, 
the class of persons through whom, in the most 
_ effectual manner, supply met demand, the demand 
for education, asserted by that marvellously ready 
_ Greek people, when the youthful mind in them 
became suddenly aware of the coming of virile 
capacity, and they desired to be made by rules 
_of art better speakers, better writers and account- 
ants, than any merely natural, unassisted gifts, 
however fortunate, could make them. While 
the peculiar religiousness of Socrates had induced 
in him the conviction that he was something 
less than a wise man, a philosopher only, a mere 
seeker after such wisdom as he might after all 
never attain, here were the σοφισταί, the experts 
_—wise men, who proposed to make other people 
88 wise as themselves, wise in that sort of wisdom 
99 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


regarding which we can really test others, and 
let them test us, not with the merely approximate 
results of the Socratic method, but with the 
exactness we may apply to processes understood 
to be mechanical, or to the proficiency of quite 
young students (such as in fact the Sophists 
were dealing with) by those examinations which 
are so sufficient in their proper place. It had 
been as delightful as learning a new game,— 
that instruction, in which you could measure 
your daily progress by brilliant feats of skill. 
Not only did the parents of those young students 
pay readily large sums for their instruction in 
what it was found so useful to know, above all 
in the art of public speaking, of self-defence, 
that is to say, in democratic Athens where one’s 
personal status was become so insecure; but the 
young students themselves felt grateful for their 
institution in what told so immediately on their 
fellows; for help in the comprehension of the 
difficult sentences of another, or the improvement 
of one’s own; for the accomplishments which 
enabled them in that busy competitive world 
to push their fortunes each one for himself a 
little further, and quite innocently. Of course | 
they listened. 


“Love not the world !”—that, on the other 
hand, was what Socrates had said, or seemed to 
say ; though in truth he too meant only to teach — 
them how by a more circuitous but surer way to 

100 | 


PLATO AND THE SOPHISTS 


possess themselves of it. And youth, naturally 
curious and for the most part generous, willing 
to undergo much for the mere promise of some 
good thing it can scarcely even imagine, had 
been ready to listen to him too ; the sons of rich 
men most often, by no means to the dissatisfac- 
tion of Socrates himself, though he never touched 
their money; young men who had amplest 
leisure for the task of perfecting their souls, in 
a condition of religious luxury, as we should 
perhaps say. As was evident in the court-house 
at the trial of the great teacher, to the eyes of 
older citizens who had not come under his 
personal influence, there had been little to 
distinguish between Socrates and his professional 
rivals. Socrates in truth was a Sophist; but 
more than a Sophist. Both alike handled freely 
matters that to the fathers had seemed beyond 
question; encouraged what seemed impious 
questioning in the sons; had set “the hearts 
of the sons against the fathers”; and some 
instances there were in which the teaching of 
Socrates had been more conspicuously ruinous 
than theirs. “1 you ask people at Athens,” 
says Socrates in the Meno, “‘ how virtue is to be 
attained, they will laugh in your face and say 
they don’t so much as know what virtue is.” 
_ And who was responsible for that? Certainly 
that Dialogue, proposing to discover the essen- 
tial nature of virtue, by no means re-establishes 
one’s old prepossessions about it in the vein of 
Io! 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


Simonides, or Pindar, or one’s elders. Sophist, 
and philosopher; Protagoras, and Socrates; so 
far, their effect was the same :—to the horror 
of fathers, to put the minds of the sons in motion 
regarding matters it were surely best to take as 
settled once and for ever. What then after all 
was the insuperable difference between Socrates 
and those rival teachers, with whom he had 
nevertheless so much in common, bent like him 
so effectively, so zealously, on that new study of 
man, of human nature and the moral world, to 
the exclusion of all useless ‘“‘ meteoric or subter- 
ranean enquiries” into things. As attractive as 
himself to ingenuous youth, uncorrupt surely in 
its early intentions, why did the Sophists seem 
to Socrates to be so manifestly an instrument of 
its corruption ? 

“The citizen of Athens,” observed that great 
Athenian statesman of the preceding age, in 
whom, as a German philosopher might say, the 
spabile soul of Athens became conscious,—‘* The 
citizen of Athens seems to me to present himself 
in his single person to the greatest possible 
variety (πλεῖστα εἴδη) of thought and action, with 
the utmost degree of versatility.” As we saw, 
the example of that mobility, that daring 
mobility, of character has seemed to many the 
special contribution of the Greek people to 
advancing humanity. It was not however of 
the Greek people in general that Pericles was 
speaking at the beginning of the Peloponnesian 

102 


PLATO AND THE SOPHISTS 


war, but of Athens in particular; of Athens, 
that perfect flower of Ionian genius, in direct 
contrast to, and now in bitter rivalry with, 
Sparta, the perfect flower of the Dorian genius. 
All through Greek history, as we also saw, in 
connexion with Plato’s opposition to the philo- 
sophy of motion, there may be traced, in every 
sphere of the activity of the Greek mind, the 
influence of those two opposing tendencies :— 
the centrifugal and the centripetal tendencies, as 
we may perhaps not too fancifully call them. 
There is the centrifugal, the irresponsible, the 
Ionian or Asiatic, tendency; flying from the 
centre, working with little forethought straight 
before it in the development of every thought 
and fancy; throwing itself forth in endless play 
of undirected imagination ; delighting in colour 
and brightness, moral or physical; in beautiful 
material, in changeful form everywhere, in 
poetry, in music, in architecture and its subor- 
dinate crafts, in philosophy itself. In the social 
and political order it rejoices in the freest action 
of local and personal influences: its restless 
versatility drives it towards the assertion of the 
principles of individualism, of separatism—the 
separation of state from state, the maintenance of 
local religions, the development of the individual 
in that which is most peculiar and individual in 
him. Shut off land-wards from the primitive 
sources of those many elements it was to compose 
anew, shut off from all the rest of the world, to 
103 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


which it presented but one narrow entrance 
pierced through that rock of Tempe, so narrow 
that “in the opinion of the ancients it might be 
defended by a dozen men against all comers,” 
it did recompose or fuse those many diverse 
elements into one absolutely original type. But 
what variety within! Its very claim was in its 
grace of movement, its freedom and easy happiness, 
its lively interests, the variety of its gifts to 
civilisation ; but its weakness is self-evident, and 
was what had made the political unity of Greece 
impossible. The Greek spirit !—it might have 
become a hydra, to use Plato’s own figure, a 
monster ; the hand developing hideously into a 
hundred hands, or heads. 

This inorganic, this centrifugal, tendency, 
Plato was desirous to cure by maintaining over 
against it the Dorian influence of a severe 
simplification everywhere, in society, in culture, 
in the very physical nature of man. An enemy 
everywhere, though through acquired principle 
indeed rather than by instinct, to variegation, to 
what is cunning, or “‘myriad-minded” (as we 
say of Shakespere, as Plato thinks of Homer) he 
sets himself in mythology, in literature, in every 
kind of art, in the art of life, as if with con- 
scious metaphysical opposition to the metaphysic 
of Heraclitus, to enforce the ideal of a sort 
of Parmenidean abstractness, and monotony or 
calm. 

This, perhaps exaggerated, ideal of Plato is 


104 


PLATO AND THE SOPHISTS 


however only the exaggeration of that salutary, 
strictly European tendency, which, finding human 
mind, the human reason cool and sane, to be 
the most absolutely real and precious thing in 
the world, enforces everywhere the impress of 
its reasonable sanity ; its candid reflexions upon 
things as they really are ; its sense of logical pro- 
portion. It is that centripetal tendency, again, 
which links the individual units together, states 
to states, one period of organic growth to another, 
under the reign of a strictly composed, self- 
conscious order, in the universal light of the 
understanding. 


Whether or not this temper, so clearly trace- 
able as a distinct rival influence in the course of 
Greek development, was indeed the peculiar gift 
of the Dorian race, certainly that race, as made 
known to us especially in Lacedemon, is the 
best illustration of it, in its love of order, of that 
severe composition everywhere, of which the 
Dorian style of architecture is as it were a 
material symbol, in its constant aspiration after 
what is dignified and earnest, as exemplified 
most evidently in the religion of its preference, 
the religion of Apollo. 

Now the key to Plato’s view of the Sophists, 
Gorgias, Protagoras, Hippias, Prodicus, with 
their less brilliant followers—chosen educators 
of the public—is that they do but fan and add 
fuel to the fire in which Greece, as they wander 
‘eee 105 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


like ardent missionaries about it, is flaming itself 
away. Teaching in their large, fashionable, 
expensive schools, so triumphantly well, the arts 
one needed most in so busy an age, they were 
really developing further and reinforcing the 
ruinous fluidity of the Greek, and especially of 
the Athenian people, by turning it very adroitly 
into a conscious method, a practical philosophy, 
an art of life itself, in which all those specific 
arts would be but subsidiary—an all-supplement- 
ing ars artium, a master-art, or, in depreciatory 
Platonic mood one might say, an artifice, or, 
cynically, a trick. The great sophist was indeed 
the Athenian public itself, Athens, as the willing 
victim of its own gifts, its own flamboyancy, 
well-nigh worn out now by the mutual friction 
of its own parts, given over completely to 
hazardous political experiment with the irre- 
sponsibility which is ever the great vice of 
democracy, ever ready to float away anywhither, 
to misunderstand, or forget, or discredit, its own 
past.— 


Or do you too hold like the many (asks Socrates in the 
sixth book of The Republic) that a certain number are corrupted 
by sophists in their youth ; and that certain sophists, irrespons- 
ible persons, corrupt them to any extent worth noting ; and 
not rather that those who say these things are the greatest 
sophists ; that they train to perfection, and turn out both old 
and young, men and women, just as they choose them to be? 
—When, pray? He asked.—-When seated together in their 
thousands at the great assemblies, or in the law-courts, or 
the theatres, or the camp, or any other common gathering of 
the public, with much noise the majority praise this and blame 

106 


PLATO AND THE SOPHISTS 


that in what is said and done, both alike in excess, shouting 
and clapping ; and the very rocks too and the place in which 
they are, echoing around, send back redoubled that clamour or 
praise and blame. In such case, what heart as they say, what 
heart, think you, can the young man keep? or what private 
education he may have had hold out for him that it be not 
over-flooded by praise or blame like that, and depart away, 
borne down the stream, whithersoever that may carry it, and 
that he pronounce not the same thing as they fair or foul ; 
and follow the same ways as they; and become like them? 


Republic, 492. 


The veritable sophist then, the dynamic 
sophist, was the Athenian public of the day; 
those ostensible or professional Sophists being 
not so much its intellectual directors as the 
pupils or followers of it. They did but make it, 
as the French say, abound the more in its own 
sense, like the keeper (it is Plato’s own image) 
of some wild beast, which he knows how to 
command by a well-considered obedience to all 
its varying humours. If the Sophists are partly 
the cause they are still more the effect of the 
social environment. They had discovered, had 
ascertained with much acuteness, the actual 
momentum of the society which maintained 
them, and they meant only, by regulating, to 
maintain it. Protagoras, the chief of Sophists, 
had avowedly applied to ethics the physics or 
metaphysics of Heraclitus. And now it was as 
if the disintegrating Heraclitean fire had taken 
hold on actual life, on men’s very thoughts, on 
the emotions and the will. 

That so faulty natural tendency, as Plato holds 

107 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


it to be, in the world around them, they formu- 
late carefully as its proper conscious theory: a 
theory how things must, nay, ought, to be. 
“Just that,” they seem to say— “Just that 
versatility, that mutable spirit, shall become by 
adoption the child of knowledge, shall be care- 
fully nurtured, brought to great fortune. We'll 
make you, and your thoughts, as fluid, as shifty, 
as things themselves: will bring you, like some 
perfectly accomplished implement, to this carriere 
ouverte, this open quarry, for the furtherance of 
your personal interests in the world.” And if 
old-fashioned principle or prejudice be found in 
the way, who better than they could instruct 
one, not how to minimise, or violate it—that 
was not needed, nor perhaps desirable, regarding 
what was so useful for the control of others—not 
that ; but, to apply the intellectual solvent to it, 
in regard to one’s self? “It will break up,— 
this or that ethical deposit in your mind, Ah ! 
very neatly, very prettily, and disappear, when 
exposed to the action of our perfected method. 
Of credit with the vulgar as such, in the solitary 
chamber of the aristocratic mind such _pre- 
suppositions, prejudicies or principles, may be 
made very soon to know their place.” 

Yes! says Plato (for a moment we may 
anticipate what is at least the spirit of his answer) 
but there are some presuppositions after all, 
which it will make us very vulgar to have 
dismissed from us. ‘There are moreover,” 

108 


PLATO AND THE SOPHISTS 


those others proceed to say, “teachers of per- 
suasion (πειθοῦς διδάσκαλοι) Who impart skill in 
popular and forensic oratory; and so by fair 
means or by unfair we shall gain our ends.” It 
is with the δῆμος, with the vulgar, insubordinate, 
tag-rag of one’s. own nature—how to rule that, 
by obeying it—that these professors of rhetoric 
begin. They are still notwithstanding the only 
teachers of morals ingenuous Greece is aware 
of ; and wisdom, as seems likely, “ must die with 
them !”— 


Some very small number then (says the Platonic Socrates) 
is left, of those who in worthy fashion hold converse with 
philosophy : either, it may be, some soul of in-born worth and 
well brought up, to which it has happened to be exiled in a 
foreign land, holding to philosophy by a tie of nature, and 
through lack of those who will corrupt it; or when it may 
chance that a great soul comes to birth in an insignificant state, 
to the politics of which it gives no heed, because it thinks them 
despicable: perhaps a certain fraction also, of good parts, may 
come to philosophy from some other craft, through a just 
contempt of that. The bridle too of our companion Theages 
has a restraining power. For in the case of Theages also, all 
the other conditions were in readiness to his falling away from 
philosophy ; but the nursing of his sickly body, excluding him 
from politics, keeps him back. Our own peculiarity is not 
worth speaking of—the sign from heaven! for I suppose it has 
occurred to scarce anyone before. And so, those who have 
been of this number, and have tasted how sweet and blessed the 
possession is ; and again, having a full view of the folly of the 
many, and that no one, I might say, effects any sound result 
in what concerns the state, or is an ally in whose company one 
might proceed safe and sound to the help of the just, but that, 
like a man falling among wild beasts, neither willing to share 
their evil deeds, nor sufficient by himself to resist the whole 
fierce band, flung away before he shall have done any service 

109 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


to the city or to his own friends, he would become useless both 
to himself and to others: taking all this into consideration, 
keeping silence and doing his own business, as one standing 
aside under a hedge in some storm of dust and spray beneath 
a driven wind, seeing those about him replete with lawlessness, 
he is content if by any means, pure from injustice and unholy 
deeds, himself shall live through his life here, and in turn make 
his escape with good hope, in cheerful and kindly mood. 
(What long sentences Plato writes!) Yet in truth, he said, 
he would make his escape after not the least of achievements.— 
Nor yet the greatest, I observed, because he did not light upon 
the polity fitted for him: for, in that fitting polity, himself 
will grow to completer stature, and, together with what belongs 
to him, he will be the saviour also of the commonwealth. 


Republic, 496. 


Over against the Sophists, and the age which 
has sophisticated them, of which they are the 
natural product, Plato, being himself of a genius 
naturally rich, florid, complex, excitable, but 
adding to the utmost degree of Ionian sensibility 
an effectual desire towards the Dorian order and 
ascésis, asserts everywhere the principle of outline, 
in political and moral life; in the education 
which is to fit men for it; in the music which 
is one half of that education, in the philosophy 
which is its other half—the “ philosophy of the 
ideas,” of those eternally fixed outlines of our 
thought, which correspond to, nay, are actu- 
ally identical with, the eternally fixed outlines 
of things themselves. What the difference 
(difference in regard to continuity and clearness) 
really is between the conditions of mind, in 
which respectively the sophistic process, and the 
genuinely philosophical or dialectic process, as 

110 


PLATO AND THE SOPHISTS 


conceived by Plato, leave us, is well illustrated 
by the peculiar treatment of Justice, its proper 
definition or idea, in The Republic. Justice (or 
Righteousness, as we say, more largely) under 
the light of a comprehensive experience of it, 
carefully, diligently, adjusted to the nature of 
man on the one hand, of society on the other, 
becomes in the fourth book of The Republic, Τὸ τὰ 
αὑτοῦ mpdrrev— The doing, by every part, in 
what is essentially a whole consisting of parts, 
of its own proper business therein. That, is a 
notion of Righteousness made familiar to us b 
Saint Paul, and in Plato holds somewhat of his 
Pythagorean predecessors. It is the execution, 
neither more nor less, by every performer, of his 
own part in a musical exercise ; or, in a physical 
organism, the execution by every faculty of its 
own function, neither more nor less: it is harmony : 
it is health,—To τὰ αὑτοῦ πράττειν. There, then, is 
the eternal outline of Righteousness or Justice 
as it really is, equally clear and indefectible at 
every point; a definition of it which can by no 
supposition become a definition of anything else ; 
impenetrable, not to be traversed, by any pos- 
sible definition of Injustice ; securing an essential 
value to its possessor, independently of all falsities 
of appearance; and leaving Justice, as it really is 
in itself, unaffected even by phenomena so mis- 
representative of it as to deceive the very gods, 
or many good men, as happened pre-eminently 
in the case of Socrates. 
III 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


Here then is the reply of the Platonic Socrates 
to the challenge that he should prove himself 
master of a more certain philosophy than that 
of the people, as represented by the old gnomic 
poet Simonides, “‘whom it is hard to disbelieve,” 
(σόφος yap καὶ θεῖος ἀνήρ,) ON the one hand; than 
that of the Sophists on the other, as represented by 
Thrasymachus. ‘Show us not only that Justice 
is a better thing than Injustice ; but, by doing 
what (ἀλλὰ τί ποιοῦσα) to the soul of its possessor, 
each of them respectively, in and by itself (airy 
δι’ αὑτήν) Εν if men and gods alike mistake it 
for its contrary, is still the one a good thing, the 
other a bad one.” 

But note for a few moments the precise 
treatment of the idea of Justice in the first book 
of The Republic. Sophistry and common sense 
are trying their best to apprehend, to cover or 
occupy, a certain space, as the exact area of 
Justice. And what happens with each proposed 
definition in turn is, that it becomes, under 
conceivable circumstances, a definition of In- 
justice: not that, in practice, a confusion between 
the two is therefore likely ; but that the zte//ect 
remains unsatisfied of the theoretic validity of 
the distinction. 

Now that intellectual situation illustrates the 
sense in which sophistry is a reproduction of the 
Heraclitean flux. The old Heraclitean physical 
theory presents itself as a natural basis for the 
moral, the social, dissolution, which the sophis- 

112 


— ee 


| 


PLATO AND THE SOPHISTS 


tical movement promotes. But what a contrast 
to it, in the treatment of Justice, of the question, 
What Justice zs? in that introductory book of 
The Republic. ‘The first book forms in truth 
an eristic, a destructive or negative, Dialogue 
(such as we have other examples of) in which 
the whole business might have concluded, prema- 


_turely, with an exposure of the inadequacy, alike 


of common-sense as represented by Simonides, 


_and of a sophisticated philosophy as represented 
by Thrasymachus, to define Justice. Note, 
however, in what way, precisely. That it is 


_ Just, for instance, to restore what one owes (τὸ τὰ 
ὀφειλόμενα ἀποδιδόναι) might pass well enough for a 
general guide to right conduct ; and the sophis- 
tical judgment that Justice is ‘‘ The interest of 


the stronger”’ is not more untrue than the con- 


trary paradox that “Justice is a plot of the weak 
against the strong.” 


It is, then, in regard to the claims of Justice, 


-notso much on practice, as on the intellect, in its 


demand for a clear theory of practice, that those 


definitions fail. They are failures because they 
fail to distinguish absolutely, ideally, as towards 
the intellect, what is, from what is not. To 
Plato, for whom, constitutionally, and ex hypothes?, 


what can be clearly thought is the precise 
‘measure of what really is, if such a thought 
about Justice—absolutely inclusive and ex- 
clusive—is, after all our efforts, not to be ascer- 


tained, this can only be, because Justice is not 


ΠΡ. VI 113 I 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


a real thing, but only an empty or confused 
name. 

Now the Sophist and the popular moralist, in 
that preliminary attempt to define the nature of 
Justice—what is right, are both alike trying, © 
first in this formula, then in that, to occupy, © 
by a thought, and by a definition which may | 
convey that thought into the mind of another © 
—to occupy, or cover, a certain area of the — 
phenomena of experience, as the Just. And 
what happens thereupon is this, that by means 
of acertain kind of casuistry, by the allegation — 
of certain possible cases of conduct, the whole — 
of that supposed area of the Just is occupied by — 
definitions of Injustice, from this centre or that. — 
Justice therefore—its area, the space of ex- 
perience which it covers, dissolves away, literally, 
as the eye is fixed upon it, like Heraclitean 
water: it is and is not. And if this, and the 
like of this, is to the last all that can be known 
or said of it, Justice will be no current coin, at 
least to the acute philosophic mind. But has 
some larger philosophy perhaps something more | 
to say of it? and the power of defining an area, 
upon which no definition of Injustice, in any 
conceivable case of act or feeling, can infringe? 
That is the question upon which the essential 
argument of The Republic starts—upon a voyage 
of discovery. It is Plato’s own figure. | 

There, clearly enough, may be seen what the 
difference, the difference of aim, between Socrates 

114 | 


PLATO AND THE SOPHISTS 


and the Sophists really was, amid much that 
they had in common, as being both alike dis- 
tinguished from that older world of opinion of 
which Simonides is the mouthpiece. 

The quarrel of Socrates with the Sophists 
was in part one of those antagonisms which are 
involved necessarily in the very conditions of an 
age that has not yet made up its mind; was in 
part also a mere rivalry of individuals; and it 
might have remained in memory only as a 
matter of historical interest. It has been other- 
wise. That innocent word “Sophist” has sur- 
vived in common language, to indicate some 
constantly recurring viciousness, in the treatment 
of one’s own and of other minds, which is always 
at variance with such habits of thought as are 
really worth while. There is an every-day 
“‘sophistry”’ of course, against which we have 
all of us to be on our guard—that insincerity of 
reasoning on behalf of sincere convictions, true 
or false in themselves as the case may be, to 
_which, if we are unwise enough to argue at all 
_ with each other, we must all be tempted at times. 
Such insincerity however is for the most part apt 
_to expose itself. But there is a more insidious 
sophistry of which Plato is aware; and against 
which he contends in the Protagoras, and again 
still more effectively in the Phedrus ; the closing 
pages of which discover the essential point of 
that famous quarrel between the Sophists and 
Socrates or Plato, in regard to a matter which is 
| 115 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


of permanent interest in itself, and as being not 
directly connected with practical morals is un- 
affected by the peculiar prejudices of that age. 
Art, the art of oratory, in particular, and of 
literary composition,—in this case, how one 
should write or speak really inflammatory dis- 
courses about love, write love-letters, so to speak, 
that shall really get at the heart they’re meant 
for —that was a matter on which the Sophists 
had thought much professionally. And the © 
debate introduced in the Phedrus regarding the 
secret of success in proposals of love or friend- 
ship turns properly on this: whether it is 
necessary, or even advantageous, for one who — 
would be a good orator, or writer, a poet,a good 
artist generally, to know, and consciously to keep 
himself in contact with, the truth of his subject 
as he knows or feels it ; or only with what other +, 
people, perhaps quite indolently, think, or suppose 
others to think, about it. And here the charge ] | 
of Socrates against those professional teachers οὗ Ι | 
the art of rhetoric comes to be, that, with ΠΛΌΟΝ | 
superficial aptitude in the conduct of the matter, 
they neither reach, nor put others in the way oth Υ: | 
reaching, that intellectual ground of things (of — 
the consciousness of love for instance, when they — 
are to open their lips, and presumably their souls, — 
about that) in true contact with which alone 
can there be a real mastery in dealing with | 
them. That you yourself must have an inward, | 
carefully ascertained, measured, instituted hold | 
116 Bi 


i 
‘ 
; 


ὩΣ -ἀἰὀὸ 
--- Ὡς lia φΦΨΦΨἌΕἘΝ 


τ 5 Ee a δ δὸ 
at ee a ee eee 


PLATO AND THE SOPHISTS 


over anything you are to convey with any real 
power to others, is the truth which the Platonic 
Socrates, in strongly convinced words, always 
reasonable about it, formulates, in opposition to 
the Sophists’ impudently avowed theory and 
practice of the superficial, as such. Well! we 
all always need to be set on our guard against 
theories which flatter the natural indolence of 
our minds. 
“We proposed then just now,” says Socrates 
in the Phedrus, “to consider the theory of the 
way in which one would or would not write 
or speak well.” —“ Certainly !”—‘“‘ Well then, 
must there not be in those who are to speak 
meritoriously, an understanding well acquainted 
with the truth of the things they are to speak 
about?” —‘‘ Nay!” answers Phedrus, in that 
age of sophistry, ‘‘ It is in this way I have heard 
about it :—that it is not necessary for one who 
would be a master of rhetoric to learn what 
really is just, for instance; but rather what 
seems just to the multitude who are to give 
judgment: nor again what is good or beautiful ; 
but only what seems sotothem. For persuasion 
comes of the latter ; by no means of a hold upon 
the truth of things.” 


! 
| 
[ 
| 


b 


: 


Whether or not the Sophists were quite 
fairly chargeable with that sort of ‘inward lie,” 
just this, at all events, was in the judgment of 
Plato the essence of sophistic vice. With them 


117 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


art began too precipitately, as mere form without 
matter; a thing of disconnected empiric rules, 
caught from the mere surface of other people’s 


productions, in congruity with a general method _ 


which everywhere ruthlessly severed branch and 
flower from its natural root—art from one’s own 
vivid sensation or belief. The Lacedemonian 
(ὁ Λάκων) Plato’s favourite scholar always, as 
having that infinite patience which is the note 


of a sincere, a really impassioned lover of 


anything, says, in his convinced Lacedemonian 
way, that a genuine art of speech (τοῦ λέγειν ἔτυμος 
τέχνη) unless one be in contact with truth, there 
neither is nor can be. We are reminded of 
that difference between genuine memory, and 
mere haphazard recollection, noted by Plato in 


the story he tells so well of the invention οὗ 


writing in ancient Egypt.—It might be doubted, 
he thinks, whether genuine memory was en- 
couraged by that invention. The note on the 
margin by the inattentive reader to “remind 


himself,” is, as we know, often his final good-bye - 


to what it should remind him of. Now this 
is true of all art: Λόγων ἀρὰ τέχνην, ὁ τὴν ἀλήθειαν 
μὴ εἰδώς, δόξας τε τεθηρεύκως, γέλοιον τινα καὶ ἄτεχνον 
παρέξεται.---ἰ is but a kind of bastard art of mere 
words (τέχνη ἄτεχνος) that he will have who does 
not know the fruth of things, but has tried to 
hunt out what other people “amk about it. 
“Conception,” observed an intensely personal, 
deeply stirred, poet and artist of our own genera- 

118 


set ἄς ee et ae 
ae ee ase see ἃ πὶ, 


PLATO AND THE SOPHISTS 


tion: ‘Conception, fundamental brainwork,— 
that is what makes the difference, in all art.” 
Against all pretended, mechanically com- 
municable rules of art then, against any rule 
of literary composition, for instance, unsanctioned 
by the facts, by a clear apprehension of the facts, 
of that experience, which to each one of us 
severally is the beginning, if it be not also the 
end, of all knowledge, against every merely 
formal dictate (their name is legion with practis- 
ing Sophists of all ages) Περὶ βραχυλογίας, καὶ 
ἐλεεινολογίας, καὶ δεινώσεως, concerning freedom or 
precision, figure, emphasis, proportion of parts 
and the like, exordium and conclusion :—against 
all such the Platonic Socrates still protests, “‘ You 
know what must be known before harmony can 
be attained, but not yet the laws of harmony 
itself,” —ra πρὸ τραγῳδίας, Sophocles would object 
in like Case, τὰ πρὸ τραγῳδίας, GAN οὐ τραγικά. 
Given the dynamic Sophoclean intention or con- 
viction, and the irresistible law of right utter- 
ance, (ἀνάγκη Aoyoypadixy) how one must write or 
speak, will make itself felt; will assuredly also 
renew many an old precept, as to how one shall 
write or speak, learned at school. To speak πρὸς 
δόξαν only, as towards mere unreasoned opinion, 
might do well enough in the law-courts with 
people, who (as is understood in that case) do 
not really care very much about justice itself, 
desire only that a friend should be acquitted, 
or an enemy convicted, irrespectively of it ; but 
[19 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


it is not the principle on which Abelard and 
Heloise wrote their famous love-letters ; or Plato 
his kindled and enkindling words on love and 
friendship in the Symposium, and in that very 
Dialogue of the Phaedrus. It is not the way in 
which, as Dante records, a certain book discoursed 
of love to Paolo and Francesca, till they found 
themselves—well! in the Inferno; so potent 
it was. 


For the essence of all artistic beauty is expres- 
sion, which cannot be where there's really 
nothing to be expressed; the line, the colour, 
the word, following obediently, and with minute 
scruple, the conscious motions of a convinced 
intelligible soul. ‘To make men interested in 
themselves, as being the very ground of all 
reality for them, /2 vrai vérité, as the French 
say :—that was the essential function of the 
Socratic method: to flash light into the house 
within, its many chambers, its memories and 


associations, upon its inscribed and pictured — 


walls. Fully occupied there, as with his own 
essential business in his own home, the young 
man would become, of course, proportionately 


less interested, less meanly interested, in what 


was superficial, in the mere outsides, of other 

people and their occupations. With the true 

artist indeed, with almost every expert, all know- 

ledge, of almost every kind, tells, is attracted 

into, and duly charged with, the force of what 
120 


PLATO AND THE SOPHISTS 


may be his leading apprehension. And as the 
special function of all speech as a fine art is 
the control of minds (ψυχαγωγία) it is in general 
with knowledge of the soul of man—with a 


veritable psychology, with as much as possible 


as we can get of that—that the writer, the 
speaker, must be chiefly concerned, if he is to 
handle minds not by mere empiric routine, τριβῇ 


᾿ μόνον, καὶ ἐμπειρίᾳ ἀλλά τέχνῃ, but by the power of 


veritable fine art. Now such art, such theory, 


is not ““ἴο be caught with the left hand,” as the 
Greek phrase went; and again, χαλεπὰ τὰ καλά. 
We have no time to hear in English Plato’s 
clever specimens of the way in which people 
would write about love without success. Let 
us rather hear himself on that subject, in his 
own characteristic mood of conviction.— 


Try! she said (a certain Sibylline woman namely, from 


whose lips Socrates in the Symposium is supposed to quote what 
_ follows) Try to apply your mind as closely as possible to what 
_I am going to say. For he who has been led thus far in the 
| discipline of love, beholding beautiful objects in the right 
| order, coming now towards the end of the doctrine of love, will 
_ on a sudden behold a beauty wonderful in its nature :—that, 
| Socrates! towards which indeed the former exercises were all 
| designed; being first of all ever existent; having neither 
_ beginning nor end; neither growing or fading away; and then, 
_ not beautiful in one way, unbeautiful in another; beautiful 


now, but not then; beautiful in this relation, unlovely in 


_ that; to some, but not to others. Nor again will that 
| beauty appear to him to be beautiful as a face or hands or 
_ anything else that belongs to the body; nor as any kind of 


reasoning or science ; nor as being resident in anything else, 


as in a living creature or the earth or the sky or any other 


I2I 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


thing ; but as being itself by itself, ever in a single form with 
itself ; all other beautiful things so participating in it, that 
while they begin and cease to be, that neither becomes more 
nor less nor suffers any other change. Whenever, then, 
anyone, beginning from things here below, through a right 
practice of love, ascending, begins to discern that other beauty, 
he will almost have reached the end. For this in truth is the 
right method of proceeding towards the doctrine of love, or of 
being conducted therein by another,—beginning from these 
beautiful objects here below ever to be going up higher, with 
that other beauty in view ; using them as steps of a ladder ; 
mounting from the love of one fair person to the love of two ; 
and from the love of two to the love of all; and from the love 
of beautiful persons to the love of beautiful employments—xada 
ἐπιτηδεύματα (that means being a soldier, or a priest, or a scholar) 
and from the love of beautiful employments to the love of 


beautiful kinds of knowledge; till he passes from degrees of τ 
knowledge to that knowledge which is the knowledge of 
nothing else save the absolute Beauty itself, and knows it at 


length as in itself it really is. At this moment of life, dear 
Socrates ! said the Mantinean Sibyl, if at any moment, man 
truly lives, beholding the absolute beauty—the which, so you 
have once seen it, will appear beyond the comparison of gold, — 

or raiment, or those beautiful young persons, seeing whom 
now, like many another, you are so overcome that you are ~ 
ready, beholding those beautiful persons and associating ever 


with them, if it were possible, neither to eat nor drink but only — | 


to look into their eyes and sit beside them. What then, she 


asked, suppose we? if it were given to any one to behold the ~ 


absolute beauty, in its clearness, its pureness, its unmixed 
essence ; not repiete with flesh and blood and colours and — 
other manifold vanity of this mortal life; but if he were able 
to behold that divine beauty (μονοειδὲς) simply as it is. Do 
you think, she said, that life would be a poor thing to one 
whose eyes were fixed on that; seeing that, (ᾧ δεῖ) with the 
organ through which it must be seen, and communing with 
that? Do you not think rather, she asked, that here alone it 
will be his, seeing the beautiful with that through which it 


ε 


may be seen (namely with the imaginative reason, 6 νοῦς) to 


beget no mere phantasms of virtue, as it is no phantom he 
122 


PLATO AND THE SOPHISTS 


apprehends, but the true virtue, as he embraces what is true? 
And having begotten virtue (virtue is the child that will be 
born of this mystic intellectual commerce, or connubium, of 
the imaginative reason with ideal beauty) and reared it, he 
will become dear to God, and if any man may be immortal 
he will be. Symposium, 210. 


The essential vice of sophistry, as Plato con- 
ceived it, was that for it no real things existed. 
Real things did exist for Plato, things that were 
“an end in themselves”; and the Platonic 
Socrates was right :—Plato has written so well 
there, because he was no scholar of the Sophists 
as he understood them, but is writing of what 
he really knows. 


123 


VI 
THE GENIUS OF PLATO 


ALL true criticism of philosophic doctrine, as of 
every other product of human mind, must begin 
with an historic estimate of the conditions, ante- 
cedent and contemporary, which helped to make 
it precisely what it was. But a complete criti- 
cism does not end there. In the evolution of 
abstract doctrine as we find it written in the 
history of philosophy, if there is always, on one 
side, the fatal, irresistible, mechanic play of 
circumstance—the circumstances of a particular 
age, which may be analysed and explained ; there 
is always also, as if acting from the opposite side, 
the comparatively inexplicable force of a person- 
ality, resistant to, while it is moulded by, them. 
It might even be said that the trial-task of criti- 
cism, in regard to literature and art no less than 
to philosophy, begins exactly where the estimate 
of general conditions, of the conditions common 
to all the products of this or that particular age 
—of the ‘environment ””—leaves off, and we 
touch what is unique in the individual genius 
124 


THE GENIUS OF PLATO 


which contrived after all, by force of will, to 
have its own masterful way with that environ- 
ment. If in reading Plato, for instance, the 
philosophic student has to re-construct for 
himself, as far as possible, the general character 
of an age, he must also, so far as he may, re- 
produce the portrait of a person. The Sophists, 
the Sophistical world, around him ; his master, 
Socrates; the Pre-Socratic philosophies; the 
mechanic influence, that is to say, of past and 
present :—of course we can know nothing at all 
of the Platonic doctrine except so far as we see 
it in well-ascertained contact with all that; but 
there is also Plato himself in it. 


—A personality, we may notice at the outset, 
of a certain complication. The great masters 
of philosophy have been for the most part its 
noticeably single-minded servants. As if in 
emulation of Aristotle’s simplicity of character, 
his absorbing intellectualism—impressive cer- 
tainly, heroic enough, in its way—they have 
served science, science 7 vacuo, as if nothing 
beside, faith, imagination, love, the bodily sense, 
could detach them from it for an hour. It is 
not merely that we know little of their lives 
(there was so little to tell!) but that we know 
nothing at all of their temperaments ; of which, 
that one leading abstract or scientific force in 
_ them was in fact strictly exclusive. Little more 
_ than intellectual abstractions themselves, in them 
| 125 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


philosophy was wholly faithful to its colours, or 
its colourlessness ; rendering not grey only, as 
Hegel said of it, but all colours alike, in grey. 

With Plato it was otherwise. In him, the 
passion for truth did but bend, or take the bent 
of, certain ineradicable predispositions of his 
nature, in themselves perhaps somewhat opposed 
tothat. It is however in the blending of diverse 
elements in the mental constitution of Plato that 
the peculiar Platonic quality resides. Platonism 
is In one sense an emphatic witness to the un- 
seen, the transcendental, the non-experienced, the 
beauty, for instance, which is not for the bodily 
eye. Yet the author of this philosophy of the 
unseen was,—Who can doubt it who has read 
but a page of him? this, in fact, is what has led 
and kept to his pages many who have little or 
no turn for the sort of questions Plato actually 
discusses :—The author of this philosophy of the 
unseen was one, for whom, as was said of a very 
different French writer, “‘ the vzszb/e world really 
existed.” Austere as he seems, and on well- 
considered principle really is, his temperance or 
austerity, esthetically so winning, is attained 
only by the chastisement, the control, of a 
variously interested, a richly sensuous nature. 
Yes, the visible world, so pre-eminently worth 
eye-sight at Athens just then, really existed for 
him: exists still—there’s the point !—is active 
still everywhere, when he seems to have turned 
away from it to invisible things. 

126 


THE GENIUS OF PLATO 


To the somewhat sad-coloured school of 
Socrates, and its discipline towards apathy or 
contempt in such matters, he had brought 
capacities of bodily sense with the making in 
them of an Odyssey; or (shall we say?) of a 
poet after the order of Sappho or Catullus ; as 
_ indeed also a practical intelligence, a popular 
| management of his own powers, a skill in philo- 
_ sophic yet mundane Greek prose, which might 
_ have constituted him the most successful of 
Sophists. You cannot help seeing that his mind 
is a storehouse of all the liveliest imageries of 
men and things. Nothing, if it really arrests 
eye or ear at all, is too trivial to note. Passing 
through the crowd of human beings, he notes 
the sounds alike of their solemn hymns and of 
their pettiest handicraft. A conventional philo- 
sopher might speak of ‘dumb matter,” for 
instance; but Plato has lingered too long in 
braziers’ workshops to lapse into so stupid an 
epithet. And if the persistent hold of sensible 
things upon him thus reveals itself in trifles, it 
is manifest no less in the way in which he can 
_ tell a long story,—no one more effectively! and 
again, in his graphic presentment of whole scenes 
_ from actual life, like that with which The Re- 
_ public opens. His Socrates, like other people, 
1s curious to witness a new religious function : 
_ how they will do it. As in modern times, it 
_ would be a pleasant occasion also for meeting 
_ the acquaintance one likes best—Huveodue0a πολλοῖς 
127 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


τῶν νέων αὐτόθ. ‘ We shall meet a number of @ 


our youth there: we shall have a dialogue: 
there will be a torchlight procession in honour 
of the goddess, an equestrian procession : a novel 
feature !—What? Torches in their hands, passed 
on as they race? Aye, and an illumination, 
through the entire night. It will be worth 
seeing |” —that old midnight hour, as Carlyle 
says of another vivid scene, “shining yet on us, 
ruddy-bright through the centuries.” Put along- 
side of that, and, for life-like charm, side by side 
with Murillo’s Beggar-boys (you catch them, 
if you look at his canvas on the sudden, actually 
moving their mouths, to laugh and speak and 
munch their crusts, all at once) the scene in 
the Lysis of the dice-players. There the boys 
are! in full dress, to take part in a religious 
ceremony. It is scarcely over; but they are 
already busy with the knuckle-bones, some just 
outside the door, others in a corner. Though 
Plato never tells one without due motive, 
yet he loves a story for its own sake, can 
make one of fact or fancy at a moment’s notice, 
or re-tell other people’s better: how those dear 
skinny grasshoppers of Attica, for instance, 
had once been human creatures, who, when 
the Muses first came on earth, were so ab- 
sorbed by their music that they forgot even 
to eat and drink, till they died of it. And 
then the story of Gyges in The Republic, and 
the ring that can make its wearer invisible: 
128 


THE GENIUS OF PLATO 


—it goes as easily, as the ring itself round the 
finger. 

Like all masters of literature, Plato has of 

course varied excellences; but perhaps none 
of them has won for him a larger number of 
friendly readers than this impress of visible reality. 
For him, truly (as he supposed the highest sort 
οὗ knowledge must of necessity be) all knowledge 
_was like knowing a person. The Dialogue itself, 
being, as it is, the special creation of his literary 
art, becomes in his hands, and by his masterly 
conduct of it, like a single living person; so 
comprehensive a sense does he bring to bear 
upon it of the slowly-developing physiognomy 
of the thing—its organic structure, its symmetry 
and expression—combining all the various, dis- 
parate subjects of The Republic, for example, 
into a manageable whole, so entirely that, look- 
ing back, one fancies this long dialogue of at 
least three hundred pages might have occupied, 
perhaps an afternoon. 
_ And those who take part in it! If Plato 
did not create the “Socrates” of his Dialogues, 
he has created other characters hardly less life- 
like. The young Charmides, the incarnation 
of natural, as the aged Cephalus of acquired, 
temperance ; his Sophoclean amenity as he sits 
there pontifically at the altar, in the court of his 
peaceful house; the large company, of varied 
character and of every age, which moves in 
those Dialogues, though still oftenest the young 
aa. VI 129 K 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


in all their youthful liveliness :—-who that knows : 
them at all can doubt Plato’s hold on persons, ~ 
that of persons on him? Sometimes, even when — ὕ 
they are not formally introduced into his work, ; 
characters that had interested, impressed, or ἱ 
touched. him, inform and eulidtir it, as if with Ὁ 
their personal influence, showing through what 
purports to be the wholly abstract analysis of 
some wholly abstract moral situation. Thus, ᾿ 
the form of the dying Socrates himself is visible 
I 
{| 


pathetically in the description of the suffering” 
righteous man, actually put into his own mouth” 
in the second book of The Republic ; as the | 
winning brilliancy of the lost spirit of Alcibiades — 
infuses those pages of the sixth, which discuss 
the nature of one by birth and cide an | 
aristocrat, amid the dangers to which it is ex- 
posed in the Athens of that day—the qualities | 
which must make him, if not the saviour, the — 
destroyer, of a society which cannot remain if 
unaffected by his showy presence. ἐόν 
optim pessima! Yet even here, when Plato is 
dealing with the inmost clements of personality, - 
his eye is still on its object, on character as seen 
in characteristics, through those details, which 
make character a sensible fact, the changes of 
colour in the face as of tone in the voice, the 
gestures, the really physiognomic value, or the | 
mere tricks, of gesture and glance and speech, — 
‘What is visibly expressive in, or upon, persons ; 
those flashes of temper which check yet sive | 

130 | 


THE GENIUS OF PLATO 


renewed interest to the course of a conversation ; 
the delicate touches of intercourse, which convey 
to the very senses all the subtleties of the heart 
or of the intelligence :—it is always more than 
worth his while to make note of these. 

We see, for instance, the sharp little pygmy 


bit of a soul that catches sight of any little 


thing so keenly, and makes a very proper lawyer. 
We see, as well as hear, the “‘ rhapsodist,” whose 


sensitive performance of his part is nothing less 


than an “interpretation” of it, artist and critic 
at once: the personal vanities of the various 


speakers in his Dialogues, as though Plato had 
observed, or overheard them, alone; and the 
inevitable prominence of youth wherever it is 


present at all, nothwithstanding the real sweet- 


'ness of manner and modesty of soul he records 
οὗ it so affectionately. It is this he loves best 


to linger by; to feel himself in contact with a 
condition of life, which translates all it is, so 
immediately, into delightful colour, and move- 
ment, and sound. The eighth and ninth books 
of The Republic are a grave contribution, as you 


_know, to abstract moral and political theory, a 


generalisation of weighty changes of character 
in men and states. But his observations on the 
concrete traits of individuals, young or old, which 
enliven us on the way; the difference in same- 
ness of sons and fathers, for instance; the in- 


fluence of servants on their masters; how the 
minute ambiguities of rank, as a family becomes 


[31 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


impoverished, tell on manners, on temper ; all 
the play of moral colour in the reflex of mere 
circumstance on what men really are :—the 
characterisation of all this has with Plato a 
touch of the peculiar fineness of Thackeray, one 
might say. Plato enjoys it for its own sake, 
and would have been an excellent writer of 
fiction. 

There is plenty of humour in him also of 
course, and something of irony—salt, to keep 
the exceeding richness and sweetness of his dis- 
course from cloying the palate. The affectations 


of sophists, or professors, their staginess or their — 
inelegance, the harsh laugh, the swaggering © 
ways, of Thrasymachus, whose determination to — 
make the general company share in a private © 
conversation, is significant of his whole char- 
acter, he notes with a finely-pointed pencil, with © 
something of the fineness of malice,—malin, as — 
the French say. Once Thrasymachus had been ~ 
actually seen to blush. It is with a very differ- — 
ent sort of fineness Plato notes the blushes of the — 
young ; of Hippocrates, for instance, in the Prota- _ 
goras. The great Sophist was said to be in ~ 
Athens, at the house of Callicles, and the diligent — 
young scholar is up betimes, eager to hear him. | 
He rouses Socrates before daylight. As they — 


linger in the court, the lad speaks of his own 


intellectual aspirations ; blushes at his confidence, — 
It was just then that the morning sun blushed — 
with his first beam, as if to reveal the lad’s 


132 


THE GENIUS OF PLATO 


blushing face.—Ka) ὃς εἶπεν ἐρυθριάσας, ἤδη γὰρ 
ὑπέφαινέ τι ἡμέρας ὥστε καταφανῆ αὐτὸν γενέσθα. He 
who noted that so precisely had, surely, the 
delicacy of the artist, a fastidious eye for the 


subtleties of colour as soul made visibly ex- 


pressive. ‘‘ Poor creature as I am,” says the 
Platonic Socrates, in the Lysis, concerning an- 


| other youthful blush, “ Poor creature as I am, I 
_ have one talent : I can recognise, at first sight, the 


lover and the beloved.” 
So it is with the audible world also. The 


| exquisite monotony of the voice of the great 
_ sophist, for example, “once set in motion, goes 
_ ringing on like a brazen pot, which if you strike 
_ it continues to sound till some one lays his hand 


upon it.” And if the delicacy of eye and ear, so 


also the keenness and constancy of his observa- 
tion, are manifest in those elaborately wrought 
images for which the careful reader lies in wait : 
the mutiny of the sailors in the ship—ship of 


the state, or of one’s own soul: the echoes and 


_beams and shadows of that half-illuminated 
_ cavern, the human mind: the caged birds in the 
_ Theetetus, which are like the flighty, half- 
contained notions of an imperfectly educated 
understanding. Rea/ notions are to be ingrained 
_ by persistent thoroughness of the “dialectic” 
_ method, as if by conscientious dyers. He makes 
us stay to watch such dyers busy with their 
_ purple stuff, as he had done; adding as it were 
ethic colour to what he sees with the eye, and 


133 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


painting while he goes, as if on the margin of 
his high philosophical discourse, himself scarcely 
aware ; as the monkish scribe set bird or flower, 
with so much truth of earth, in the blank spaces 
of his heavenly meditation. 

Now Plato is one for whom the visible world 
thus “‘ really exists”’ because he is by nature and 
before all things, from first to last, unalterably a 
lover. In that, precisely, lies the secret of the 


susceptible and diligent eye, the so sensitive ear. ᾿ 
The central interest of his own youth—of his © 
profoundly impressible youth—as happens always ~ 


with natures of real capacity, gives law and 
pattern to all that succeeds it. Ta ἐρωτικά, as he 


says, the experience, the discipline, of love, 


had been that for Plato; and, as love must of | 


necessity deal above all with visible persons, this 


discipline involved an exquisite culture of the 
senses. It is “‘as lovers use,” that he is ever on 
the watch for those dainty messages, those finer — 
intimations, to eye and ear. If in the later 


development of his philosophy the highest sort — 


of knowledge comes to seem like the knowledge 
of a person, the relation of the reason to truth 
like the commerce of one person with another, 
the peculiarities of personal relationship thus 
moulding his conception of the properly in- 
visible world of ideas, this is partly because, for 
a lover, the entire visible world, its hues and 
outline, its attractiveness, its power and bloom, 
must have associated themselves pre-eminently 
134 


THE GENIUS OF PLATO 


with the power and bloom of visible living 
persons. With these, as they made themselves 
known by word and glance and touch, through 
the medium of the senses, lay the forces, which, 
in that inexplicable tyranny of one person over 
| another, shaped the soul. 
Just there, then, is the secret of Plato’s inti- 
mate concern with, his power over, the sensible 
_ world, the apprehensions of the sensuous faculty : 
he is a lover, a great lover, somewhat after the - 
| manner of Dante. For him, as for Dante, in the 
_ impassioned glow of his conceptions, the material 
and the spiritual are blent and fused together. 
_ While, in that fire and heat, what is spiritual 
attains the definite visibility of a crystal, what is 
| material, on the other hand, will lose its earthi- 
ness and impurity. It is of the amorous temper, 
| therefore, you must think in connexion with 
_ Plato’s youth—of this, amid all the strength of 
_ the genius in which it is so large a constituent, 
_ —indulging, developing, refining, the sensuous 
capacities, the powers of eye and ear, of the fancy 
_ also which can re-fashion, of the speech which 
_ can best respond to and reproduce, their liveliest 
| presentments. That is why when Plato speaks 
of visible things it is as if you saw them. He 
who in the Sympostum describes so vividly the 
pathway, the ladder, of love, its joyful ascent 
towards a more perfect beauty than we have 
ever yet actually seen, by way of a parallel to 
_ the gradual elevation of mind towards perfect 
135 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


knowledge, knew all that, we may be sure— 
τὰ épwtixd—all the ways of lovers, in the literal 
sense. He speaks of them retrospectively indeed, 
but knows well what he is talking about. Plato 
himself had not been always a mere Platonic 
lover ; was rather, naturally, as he makes Socrates 
say of himself, ἥττων τῶν xarav—subject to the 
influence of fair persons. A certain penitential 
colour amid that glow of fancy and expression, 
hints that the final harmony of his nature had 
been but gradually beaten out, and invests the 
temperance, actually so conspicuous in his own 
nature, with the charms of a patiently elaborated 
effect of art. 

For we must remind ourselves just here, that, 
quite naturally also, instinctively, and apart from 
the austere influences which claimed and kept 
his allegiance later, Plato, with a kind of unim- 


passioned passion, was a lover in particular of 


temperance ; of temperance too, as it may be seen, 
as a visible thing—seen in Charmides, say! in 
that subdued and grey-eyed loveliness, “clad in 
sober grey”; or in those youthful athletes 
which, in ancient marble, reproduce him and 
the like of him with sound, firm outlines, such 
as temperance secures. Still, that some more 
luxurious sense of physical beauty had at one 
time greatly disturbed him, divided him against 
himself, we may judge from his own words in a 
famous passage of the Phedrus concerning the 
management, the so difficult management, of 
36 


Se 


THE GENIUS OF PLATO 


those winged steeds of the body, which is the 
chariot of the soul. 

Puzzled, in some degree, Plato seems to 
remain, not merely in regard to the higher love 


and the lower, Aphrodite Urania and Aphrodite 


_Pandemus, as he distinguishes them in the 


Symposium; nor merely with the difficulty of 


_arbitrating between some inward beauty, and 
_ that which is outward; with the odd mixture 
_ everywhere, save in its still unapprehended but 
_ eternal essence, of the beautiful with what is 
_ otherwise ; but he is yet more harassed by the 
_ experience (it is in this shape that the world-old 
| puzzle of the existence of evil comes to him) 
_ that even to the truest eyesight, to the best trained 
faculty of soul, the beautiful would never come 
_ to seem strictly concentric with the good. That 


seems to have taxed his understanding as gravely 


as it had tried his will, and he was glad when in 
_the mere natural course of years he was become 
_ at all events less ardent a lover. ’*Tis he isthe 
_authority for what Sophocles had said on the 
happy decay of the passions as age advanced : 
_ it was “like being set free from service to a band 
of madmen.” His own distinguishing note is 


tranquil afterthought upon this conflict, with a 


_kind of envy of the almost disembodied old age 


of Cephalus, who quotes that saying of Sophocles 
amid his placid sacrificial doings. Connect with 


this quiet scene, and contrast with the luxuriant 
power of the Phedrus and the Symposium, what, 


137 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


for a certain touch of later mysticism in it, we 
might call Plato’s evening prayer, in the ninth 
book of The Republic.— 


When any one, being healthfully and temperately disposed 
towards himself, turns to sleep, having stirred the reasonable 
part of him with a feast of fair thoughts and high problems, 
being come to full consciousness, himself with himself; and 
has, on the other hand, committed the element of desire 
neither to appetite, nor to surfeiting, to the end that this may 
slumber well, and, by its pain or pleasure, cause no trouble to 


that part which is best in him, but may suffer it, alone by © | 


itself, in its pure essence, to behold and aspire towards some 
object, and apprehend what it knows not—some event, of the 
past, it may be, or something that now is, or will be hereafter ; 
and in like manner has soothed hostile impulse, so that, falling 
to no angry thoughts against any, he goes not to rest with a 
troubled spirit, but with those two parts at peace within, and 
with that third part, wherein reason is engendered, on the move: 


—you know, I think, that in sleep of this sort he lays special — | 


hold on truth, and then least of all is there lawlessness in the 
visions of his dreams. Republic, 571. 


For Plato, being then about twenty-eight 


years old, had listened to the “ Apology” of | 


Socrates; had heard from them all that others 


had heard or seen of his last hours; himself 
perhaps actually witnessed those last hours. 


“Justice itself "—the “absolute” Justice —had 


then become almost a visible object, and had 
greatly solemnised him. The rich young man, 


rich also in intellectual gifts, who might have 


become (we see this in the adroit management of — 
his written work) the most brilliant and effective — 
of Sophists ; who might have developed dialogues — 


into plays, tragedy, perhaps comedy, as he cared ; 
138 


\ 
| 


| 
Ϊ 


THE GENIUS OF PLATO 


whose sensuous or graphic capacity might have 
made him the poet of an Odyssey, a Sappho, or a 
Catullus, or, say! just such a poet as, just because 
he was so attractive, would have been disfran- 
chised in the Perfect City; was become the 
creature of an immense seriousness, of a fully 
adult sense, unusual in Greek perhaps even more 
than in Roman writers, “of the weightiness of 
the matters concerning which he has to discourse, 
and of the frailty of man.” He inherits, alien 
as they might be to certain powerful influences 
in his own temper, alike the sympathies and the 
antipathies of that strange, delightful teacher, 
who had given him (most precious of gifts !) an 
inexhaustible interest in himself. It is in this 
way he inherits a preference for those trying 
_ severities of thought which are characteristic of 
the Eleatic school; an antagonism to the suc- 
cessful Sophists of the day, in whom the old 
_ sceptical “‘ philosophy of motion” seemed to be 
renewed as a theory of morals ; and henceforth, 
in short, this master of visible things, this so 
_ ardent lover, will be a lover of the invisible, with 
_— Yes! there it is constantly, in the Platonic dia- 
_logues, not to be explained away—with a certain 
asceticism, amid all the varied opulence, of sense, 
of speech and fancy, natural to Plato’s genius. 
| The lover, who is become a lover of the 
invisible, but still a lover, and therefore, literally, 
_aseer, of it, carrying an elaborate cultivation of 
the bodily senses, of eye and ear, their natural 
139 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


force and acquired fineness—gifts akin properly to 
τὰ ἐρωτικά, aS he says, to the discipline of sensuous 
love—into the world of intellectual abstractions ; 
seeing and hearing there too, associating for 
ever all the imagery of things seen with the 
conditions of what primarily exists only for the 
mind, filling that “‘ hollow land” with delightful 
colour and form, as if now at last the mind were 
veritably dealing with living people there, living _ 
people who play upon us through the affinities, 
the repulsion and attraction, of persons towards _ 
one another, all the magnetism, as we call it, of 
actual human friendship or love :—There, is the 
formula of Plato’s genius, the essential condition 
of the specially Platonic temper, of Platonism. 
And his style, because it really is Plato’s style, — 
conforms to, and in its turn promotes in others, | 
that mental situation. He breaks as it were 
visible colour into the very texture of his work : 
his vocabulary, the very stuff he manipulates, 
has its delightful esthetic qualities ; almost every 
word, one might say, its figurative value. And 
yet no one perhaps has with equal power literally — 
sounded the unseen depths of thought, and, — 
with what may be truly called “substantial” | 
word and phrase, given locality there to the © 
mere adumbrations, the dim hints and surmise, © 
of the speculative mind. For him, all gifts of 
sense and intelligence converge in one supreme 
faculty of theoretic vision, θεωρία, the imaginative 
reason. 
140 


THE GENIUS OF PLATO 


To trace that thread of physical colour, en- 
twined throughout, and multiplied sometimes 
into large tapestried figures, is the business, the 
| enjoyment, of the student of the Dialogues, as he 
reads them. For this or that special literary 
_ quality indeed we may go safely by preference to 
this or that particular Dialogue ; to the Gorgias, 
_ for instance, for the readiest Attic wit, and a 
manly practical sense in the handling of philo- 
_ sophy ; to the Charmides, for something like the 
_ effect of sculpture in modelling a person ; to the 
_ Timezus, for certain brilliant chromatic effects. 
| Yet who that reads the Theetetus, or the Phedrus, 
or the seventh book of The Republic, can doubt 
_ Plato’s gift in precisely the opposite direction ; 
that gift of sounding by words the depths of 
_ thought, a plastic power literally, moulding to 
_ term and phrase what might have seemed in its 
very nature too impalpable and abstruse to lend 
itself, in any case, to language? He gives names 
to the invisible acts, processes, creations, of 
_ abstract mind, as masterly, as efficiently, as Adam 
_ himself to the visible living creations of old. As 
Plato speaks of them, we might say, those 
abstractions too become visible living creatures. 
_ We read the speculative poetry of Wordsworth, 
or Tennyson ; and we may observe that a great 
_ metaphysical force has come into language which 
is by no means purely technical or scholastic ; 
what a help such language is to the understanding, 
toa real hold over the things, the thoughts, the 
[41 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


mental processes, those words denote ; a vocabu- 
lary to which thought freely commits itself, 
trained, stimulated, raised, thereby, towards a 
high level of abstract conception, surely to the 
increase of our general intellectual powers. ‘That, 
of course, is largely due to Plato’s successor, to 
Aristotle’s life-long labour of analysis and defini- 
tion, and to his successors the Schoolmen, with 
their systematic culture of a precise instrument 


for the registration, by the analytic intellect, οὐ 
its own subtlest movements. But then, Aristotle, — 


himself the first of the Schoolmen, had succeeded 
Plato, and did but formulate, as a terminology 
“‘of art,” as technical language, what for Plato 
is still vernacular, original, personal, the product 
in him of an instinctive imaginative power—a 
sort of visual power, but causing others also to 
see what is matter of original intuition for him. 


From first to last our faculty of thinking is 
limited by our command of speech. Now it is 
straight from Plato’s lips, as if in natural con- 


versation, that the language came, in which 


the mind has ever since been discoursing with 
itself concerning itself, in that inward dialogue, 
which is the ‘active principle” of the dialectic 
method as an instrument for the attainment of 
truth. For, the essential, or dynamic, dialogue, 


is ever that dialogue of the mind with itself, — 


which any converse with Socrates or Plato does 
but promote. The very words of Plato, then, 
142 


THE GENIUS OF PLATO 


challenge us straightway to larger and finer appre- 
hension of the processess of our own minds; are 
themselves a discovery in the sphere of mind. 
It was he made us freemen of those solitary 
places, so trying yet so attractive : so remote and 
high, they seem, yet are naturally so close to us: 
he peopled them with intelligible forms. Nay 
more! By his peculiar gift of verbal articulation 
he divined the mere hollow spaces which a 
knowledge, then merely potential, and an ex- 
perience still to come, would one day occupy. 
And so, those who cannot admit his actual 
speculative results, precisely Azs report on the 
invisible theoretic world, have been to the point 
sometimes, in their objection, that by sheer 
effectiveness of abstract language, he gave an 
illusive air of reality or substance to the mere 
nonentities of metaphysic hypothesis—of a mind 
trying to feed itself on its own emptiness. 

Just there—in the situation of one, shaped, 
_ by combining nature and cian metasien! into a 
seer who has a sort of sensuous love of the un- 
seen—is the paradox of Plato’s genius, and 
therefore, always, of Platonism, of the Platonic 
temper. His aptitude for things visible, with 
the gift of words, empowers him to express, as 
if for the eyes, what except to the eye of the 
mind is strictly invisible, what an acquired 
asceticism induces him to rank above, and some- 
times, in terms of harshest dualism, oppose to, 
the sensible world. Plato is to be interpreted 
143 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


not merely by his antecedents, by the influence 
upon him of those who preceded him, but by 
his successors, by the temper, the intellectual 
alliances, of those who directly or indirectly 
have been sympathetic with him. Now it is 
noticeable that, at first sight somewhat incon- 
gruously, a certain number of Manicheans have 
always been of his company; people who held 
that matter was evil. Pointing significantly to 
an unmistakable vein of Manichean, or Puritan 
sentiment actually there in the Platonic Dia- 
logues, these rude companions or successors of 
his, carry us back to his great predecessor, to 
Socrates, whose personal influence had so strongly 
enforced on Plato the severities, moral and in- 
tellectual, alike of Parmenides and of the Pytha- 
goreans. ‘The cold breath of a harshly abstract, 
a too incorporeal philosophy, had blown, like 
an east wind, on that last depressing day in 
the prison-cell of Socrates; and the venerable 
commonplaces then put forth, in which an over- 
strained pagan sensuality seems to be reacting, 
to be taking vengeance, on itself, turned now 
sick and suicidal, will lose none of their weight | 
with Plato:—That “all who rightly touch | 
philosophy, study nothing else than to die, and © 
to be dead,”—that “the soul reasons best, when, 
as much as possible, it comes to be alone with 
itself, bidding good-bye to the body, and, to the | 
utmost of its power, rejecting communion with | 
it, with the very touch of it, aiming at what zs.” 
144 


THE GENIUS OF PLATO 


It was, in short, as if for the soul to have come into 
a human body at all, had been the seed of disease 
in it, the beginning of its own proper death. 

As for any adornments or provision for this 
body, the master had declared that a true philo- 
sopher as such would make as little of them 
as possible. To those young hearers, the words 
of Socrates may well have seemed to anticipate, 


not the visible world he had then delineated in 


glowing colour as if for the bodily eye, but only 


the chilling influence of the hemlock ; and it 
_ was because Plato was only half convinced of the 
_Manichean or Puritan element in his master’s 


doctrine, or rather was in contact with it on one 
side only of his complex and genial nature, that 
Platonism became possible, as a temper for 
which, in strictness, the opposition of matter to 
spirit has no ultimate or real existence. Not to 


be “pure” from the body, but to identify it, in 


its utmost fairness, with the fair soul, by a 


gymnastic “ fused in music.”’ became, from first 
3 3 


to last, the aim of education as he conceived it. 


That the body is but “a hindrance to the attain- 


ment of philosophy, if one takes it along with 
one as a companion in one’s search” (a notion 
which Christianity, at least in its later though 
wholly legitimate developments, will correct) 


can hardly have been the last thought of Plato 
himself on quitting it. He opens his door 
indeed to those austere monitors. They correct 
the sensuous richness of his genius, but could 


Ρ. VI 145 L 


PLATO AND PLATONISM ᾿ 


not suppress it. The sensuous lover becomes ἃ 
lover of the invisible, but still a lover, after his — 
earlier pattern, carrying into the world of intel- _ 
lectual vision, of θεωρία, all the associations of the © 
actual world of sight. Some of its invisible © 
realities he can all but see with the bodily eye: the _ 
absolute Temperance, in the person of the youth- — 
ful Charmides ; the absolute Righteousness, in © 
the person of the dying Socrates. Yes, truly! — 
all true knowledge will be like the know- 4 
ledge of a person, of living persons, and — 
truth, for Plato, in spite of his Socratic asceti- Ϊ 
cism, to the last, something to /ook at. The © 
eyes which had noted physical things, so — 
finely, vividly, continuously, would be still δὲ 
work ; and, Plato thus qualifying the Manichean ~ 
or Puritan element in Socrates by his own 
capacity for the world of sense, Platonism has — 
contributed largely, has been an immense en- — 
couragement towards, the redemption of matter, | 
of the world of sense, by art, by all nigh 
education, by the creeds and worship of the 
Christian Church—towards the vindication off ἢ 
the dignity of the body. 


It was doubtless because Plato was an excellent 
scholar that he did not begin to teach others till © 
he was more than forty years old—one of the | 
great scholars of the world, with Virgil and © 
Milton : by which is implied that, possessed of | 


the inborn genius, of those natural powers, ! 
146 | 


THE GENIUS OF PLATO 


which sometimes bring with them a certain 
defiance of rule, of the intellectual habits of 
others, he acquires, by way of habit and rule, 
all that can be taught and learned ; and what 
is thus derived from others by docility and 
discipline, what is rangé, comes to have in him, 
and in his work, an equivalent weight with 
what is unique, impulsive, underivable. Raphael 
—Raphael, as you see him in the Blenheim 
Madonna, is a supreme example of such scholar- 
ship in the sphere of art. Born of a romantically 
ancient family, understood to be the descendant 
of Solon himself, Plato had been in early youth 
‘a writer of verse. That he turned to a more 
vigorous, though pedestrian mode of writing, was 
perhaps an effect of his corrective intercourse with 
Socrates, through some of the most important 
years of his life.—from twenty to twenty-eight. 
He belonged to what was just then the 
discontented class, and might well have taken 
tefuge from active political life in political ideals, 
or in a kind of self-imposed exile. A traveller, 
adventurous for that age, he certainly became. 
‘After the Lehr-jahre, the Wander-jahre !—all 
round the Mediterranean coasts as far west as 
Sicily. Think of what all that must have meant 
just then, for eyes which could see. If those 
journeys had begun in angry flight from home, 
it was for purposes of self-improvement they 
were continued: the delightful fruit of them 
is evident in what he writes; and finding him 
147 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


in friendly intercourse with Dionysius the elder, _ 
with Dio, and Dionysius the younger, at the 
polished court of Syracuse, we may understand — 
that they were a search also for “ the philosophic | 
king,” perhaps for the opportune moment οὗ 
realising “‘the ideal state.” In that case, his — 
quarrels with those capricious tyrants show that 
he was disappointed. For the future he sought no 
more to pass beyond the charmed theoretic circle, _ 
“‘speaking wisdom,” as was said of Pythagoras, 
only ‘“‘ among the perfect.” Hereturns finally to 
Athens ; and there, in the quiet precincts of the - 
Académus, which has left a somewhat dubious — 
name to places where people come to be taught | 
or to teach, founds, not a state, nor even a. 
brotherhood, but only the first college, with 
something of a common life, of communism on > 
that small scale, with Aristotle for one of its — 
scholars, with its chapel, its gardens, its library 
with the authentic text of his Dia/ogues upon the — 
shelves: we may just discern the sort of place 
through the scantiest notices. His reign was 
after all to be in his writings. Plato himself does — 
nothing in them to retard the effacement which © 
mere time brings to persons and their abodes ; 
and there had been that, moreover, in his own 
temper, which promotes self-effacement. Yet as - 
he left it, the place remained for centuries, — 
according to his will, to its original use. What 
he taught through the remaining forty years of | 
his life, the method of that teaching, whether it 

148 | 


THE GENIUS OF PLATO 


was less or more esoteric than the teaching of 

the extant Dia/ogues, is but matter of surmise. 
Writers, who in their day might still have said 
much we should have liked to hear, give us 
little but old, quasi-supernatural stories, told as 
if they had been new ones, about him. The 
year of his birth fell, according to some, in the 
very year of the death of Pericles (a significant 
date !) but is not precisely ascertainable: nor is 
the year of his death, nor its manner. Scribens 
est mortuus, says Cicero :—after the manner of a 
true scholar, “he died pen in hand.” 


149 


Vil 


THE DOCTRINE OF PLATO 


I. The Theory of Ideas 


PLATONISM is not a formal theory or body of — 
theories, but a tendency, a group of tendencies— 
a tendency to think or feel, and to speak, abou | 
certain things in a particular way, discernible ir 

Plato’s dialogues as reflecting the peculiarities, : 
the marked peculiarities, of himself and his 
own mental complexion. Those tendencies | 
combine and find their complete expression 1 
what Plato’s commentators, rather than Plato, 
have called the “theory of ideas,” itself indesa ' 
not so much a doctrine or theory, as a way of 
regarding and speaking of general terms, such as 
Useful or Fust ; of abstract notions, like Ἐμοί ἢ 
of ideals, such as Beauty, or The Perfect City; 
of all those terms or notions, in short, whic 
represent under general forms the particular pre- 
sentations of our individual experience ; or, to. 
use Plato’s own frequent expression, borrowec 

150 


THE DOCTRINE OF PLATO 


from his old Eleatic teachers, which reduce “ the 
Many to the One.” 

What the nature of such representative terms 
and notions, genus and species, class-word, and 
abstract idea or ideal, may be; what their rela- 
tionship to the individual, the unit, the par- 
ticulars which they include ; is, as we know, one 
of the constant problems of logic. Realism, 
which supposes the abstraction, Amal for 
instance, or The “fust, to be not a mere name, 
nomen, as with the nominalists, nor a mere 
subjective thought as with the conceptualists, but 
to be ves, a thing in itself, independent of the 
particular instances which come into and pass out 
of it, as also of the particular mind which enter- 
tains it :—that is one of the fixed and formal 
answers to this question ; and Plato is the father 
of all realists. Realism, as such, in the sense just 
indicated, is not in itself a very difficult or tran- 
scendental theory ; but rises, again and again, at 
least in a particular class of minds, quite naturally, 
as the answer to a natural question. ‘Taking our 
own stand as to this matter somewhere between 
the realist and the conceptualist :—See! we 
might say, there is a general consciousness, a 
permanent common sense, independent indeed of 
each one of us, but with which we are, each one 
of us, in communication. It is in that, those 
common or general ideas really reside. And we 
might add just here (giving his due to the 
nominalist also) that those abstract or common 

IS! 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


notions come to the individual mind through 
language, through common or general names, 
Animal, “fustice, Equality, into which one’s in- 
dividual experience, little by little, drop by drop, 
conveys their full meaning or content ; and, by the 
instrumentality of such terms and notions, thus 
locating the particular in the general, mediating 
between general and particular, between our in- 
dividual experience and the common experience of 
our kind, we come to understand each other, and 
to assist each other’s thoughts, as in a common 
mental atmosphere, an “intellectual world,” as 
Plato calls it, a true νοητὸς τόπος. So much for the 
modern view ; for what common sense might now 
suggest as to the nature of logical “ universals.” 


Plato’s realism however—what is called 
“The Theory of Ideas” —his way of regarding 
abstract term and general notion, what Plato has 
to say about “the Many and the One,” is often 
very difficult; though of various degrees of 
difficulty, it must be observed, to various minds. 
From the simple and easily intelligible sort 
of realism attributed by Aristotle to Socrates, 
seeking in “universal definitions,’ or ideas, only 
a serviceable instrument for the distinguishing of 
what is essential from what is unessential in the 
actual things about him, Plato passes by successive 
stages, which we should try to keep distinct as 
we read him, to what may be rightly called 
a ‘transcendental,’ what to many minds has 

152 


THE DOCTRINE OF PLATO 


seemed a fantastic and unintelligible habit of 
thought, regarding those abstractions, which 
indeed seem to become for him not merely 
substantial things-in-themselves, but little short 
of living persons, to be known as persons are 
made known to each other, by a system of 
affinities, on the old Eleatic rule, ὅμοιον ὁμοίῳ, like 
to like—these persons constituting together that 
common, eternal, intellectual world, a sort of 
divine family or hierarchy, with which _ the 
mind of the individual, so far as it is reasonable, 
or really knows, is in communion or corre- 
spondence. And here certainly is a theory, a 
tendency to think or feel, and to speak, about 
which the difficulties are many. 


Yet as happens always with the metaphysical 
questions, or answers, which from age to age pre- 
occupy acuter minds, those difficulties about the 
Many and the One actually had their attractive- 
ness for some in the days of Plato.— 


Our doctrine (says the Platonic Socrates in the Philebus) is, 
_ that one and the same thing (the one common notion, namely, 
_ embodied in one general term) which—timd Adéywv—under the 
_ influence of our thoughts and words, of thought and language, 
_ become one and many, circulates everywhere, in regard to every- 
| thing of which existence is asserted from time to time. ‘This 
| law neither will cease to be, nor has it just now begun ; but 
| something of the kind is, I think, an eternal and ineradicable 
| affection of our reason itself in us. And whenever a young 
man gets his first taste of this he is delighted as having found 
_ the priceless pearl of philosophy ; he becomes an enthusiast in 
| his delight ; and eagerly sets in motion—xivei—every definition 


153 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


—éyos—every conception or mental definition (it looked so 
fixed and firm till then!) at one time winding things round 
each other and welding them into one (that is, he drops all 
particularities out of view, and thinks only of the one common 
form) and then again unwinding them, and dividing them into 
parts (he becomes intent now upon the particularities of the 
particular, till the one common term seems _ inapplicable) 
puzzling first, and most of all, himself ; and then any one who 
comes nigh him, older or younger, or of whatever age he may 
be ; sparing neither father nor mother, nor any one else who 
will listen ; scarcely even the dumb creatures, to say nothing of 
men ; for he would hardly spare a barbarian, could he but find 
an interpreter. Philebus, 15. 


The Platonic doctrine of “the Many and the 


One ”—the problem with which we are brought 
face to face in this choice specimen of the humour 
as well as of the metaphysical power of Plato— 
is not precisely the question with which the 
speculative young man of our own day is likely 
to puzzle himself, or exercise the patience of his 
neighbour in a railway carriage, of his dog, or 


even of a Chinese ; though the questions we are © 


apt to tear to pieces, organism and environment, 
or protoplasm perhaps, or evolution, or the Zezt- 
geist and its doings, may, in their turn, come to 
seem quite as lifeless and unendurable. As the 
theological heresy of one age sometimes becomes 
the mere commonplace of the next, so, in matters 
of philosophic enquiry, it might appear that the 


all-absorbing novelty of one generation becomes 


nothing less than the standard of what is un- 
interesting, as such, to its successor. Still in the ~ 
discussion even of abstract truths it is not so much — 


154 


THE DOCTRINE OF PLATO 


what he thinks as the person who is thinking, 
that after all really tells. Plato and Platonism 
we shall never understand unless we are patient 
with him in what he has to tell us about “the 
Many and the One.” 

Plato’s peculiar view of the matter, then, 
passes with him into a phase of poetic thought ; 
as indeed all that Plato’s genius touched came 
in contact with poetry. Of course we are not 
naturally formed to love, or be interested in, or 
attracted towards, the abstract as such ; to notions, 
we might think, carefully deprived of all the 
incident, the colour and variety, which fits things 
—this or that—to the constitution and natural 
habit of our minds, fits them for attachment to 
what we really are. We cannot love or live 
upon genus and species, accident or substance, but 
for our minds, as for our bodies, need an orchard 
or a garden, with fruit and roses. Take a seed 
from the garden. What interest it has for us all 
lies in our sense of potential differentiation to 
come: the leaves, leaf upon leaf, the flowers, a 
thousand new seeds in turn. It is so with 
animal seed; and with humanity, individually, 
or as a whole, its expansion into a detailed, ever- 
changing, parti-coloured history of particular 
facts and persons. Abstraction, the introduction 
of general ideas, seems to close it up again; to 
reduce flower and fruit, odour and savour, back 
again into the dry and worthless seed. We 
might as well be colour-blind at once, and there 

155 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


is not a proper name left! We may contrast 
generally the mental world we actually live in, 
where classification, the reduction of all things 
to common types, has come so far, and where the 
particular, to a great extent, is known only as the 
member of a class, with that other world, on the 
other side of the generalising movement to which 
Plato and his master so largely contributed—a 
world we might describe as being under Homeric 
conditions, such as we picture to ourselves with 
regret, for which experience was intuition, and 
life a continuous surprise, and every object unique, 
where all knowledge was still of the concrete and 
the particular, face to face delightfully. 

To that gaudy tangle of what gardens, after 
all, are meant to produce, in the decay of time, 
as we may think at first sight, the systematic, 
logical gardener put his meddlesome hand, and 
straightway all ran to seed; to genus and species 
and differentia, into formal classes, under general 
notions, and with—yes! with written labels 
fluttering on the stalks, instead of blossoms—a 
botanic or “‘ physic” garden, as they used to say, 
instead of our flower-garden and orchard. And 
yet (it must be confessed on the other hand) 
what we actually see, see and hear, 1s more 
interesting than ever; the nineteenth century as 
compared with the first, with Plato’s days or 
Homer’s; the faces, the persons behind those 
masks which yet express so much, the flowers, or 
whatever it may happen to be they carry or 

156 


THE DOCTRINE OF PLATO 


touch. The concrete, and that even as a visible 
thing, has gained immeasurably in richness and 
compass, in fineness, and interest towards us, by 
the process, of which those acts of generalisation, 
of reduction to class and generic type, have 
certainly been a part. And holding still to the 
concrete, the particular, to the visible or sensuous, 
if you will, last as first, thinking of that as 
essentially the one vital and lively thing, really 
worth our while in a short life, we may recognise 
sincerely what generalisation and abstraction have 
done or may do, are defensible as doing, just for 
that—for the particular gem or flower—what its 
proper service is to a mind in search, precisely, 
of a concrete and intuitive knowledge such as 
that. 

Think, for a moment, of the difference, as 
regards mental attitude, between the naturalist 
who deals with things through ideas, and the 
layman (so to call him) in picking up a shell on 
the sea-shore ; what it is that the subsumption 
of the individual into the species, its subsequent 
alliance to and co-ordination with other species, 
really does for the furnishing of the mind of 
the former. The layman, though we need not 
suppose him inattentive, or unapt to retain im- 
pressions, is in fact still but a child; and the 
shell, its colours and convolution, no more than 
a dainty, very easily destructible toy to him. 
Let him become a schoolboy about it, so to 
speak, The toy he puts aside; his mind is 

157 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


drilled perforce, to learn about it ; and thereby is 
exercised, he may think, with everything except 
just the thing itself, as he cares for it; with 
other shells, with some general laws of life, and 
for a while it might seem that, turning away his 
eyes from the “ vanity ” of the particular, he has 
been made to sacrifice the concrete, the real and 
living product of nature, to a mere dry and abstract 
product of the mind. But when he comes out 
of school, and on the sea-shore again finds a 
fellow to his toy, perhaps a finer specimen of it, 
he may see what the service of that converse 
with the general has really been towards the 
concrete, towards what he sees—in regard to the 
particular thing he actually sees. By its juxta- 
position and co-ordination with what is ever 
more and more not 7, by the contrast of its very 
imperfection, at this point or that, with its 
own proper and perfect type, this concrete and 
particular thing has, in fact, been enriched by 
the whole colour and expression of the whole 
circumjacent world, concentrated upon, or as it 
were at focus in, it. By a kind of short-hand 
now, and as if in a single moment of vision, all 
that, which only a long experience, moving 
atiently from part to part, could exhaust, its 
manifold alliance with the entire world of 
nature, is legible upon it, as it lies there in one’s 
hand. 
So it is with the shell, the gem, with a glance 
of the eye; so it may be with the moral act, © 
158 


THE DOCTRINE OF PLATO 


with a condition of the mind, or a feeling. You 


_may draw, by use of this coinage (it is Hobbes’s 
figure) this coinage of representative words and 


thoughts, at your pleasure, upon the accumula- 


_ tive capital of the whole experience of humanity. 
_ Generalisation, whatever Platonists, or Plato him- 


self at mistaken moments, may have to say 


about it, is a method, not of obliterating the 
concrete phenomenon, but of enriching it, with 
the joint perspective, the significance, the ex- 


_pressiveness, of all other things beside. What 
_broad-cast light he enjoys !—that scholar, con- 
fronted with the sea-shell, for instance, or with 
some enigma of heredity in himself or another, 


with some condition of a particular soul, in 


circumstances which may never precisely so 


occur again ; in the contemplation of that single 
phenomenon, or object, or situation. He not 
only sees, but understands (thereby only seeing 


the more) and will, therefore, also remember. 


The significance of the particular object he will 


retain, by use of his intellectual apparatus of 
notion and general law, as, to use Plato’s own 


figure, fluid matter may be retained in vessels, 
not indeed of unbaked clay, but of alabaster or 
bronze. So much by way of apology for 
general ideas—abstruse, or intangible, or dry and 
seedy and wooden, as we may sometimes think 
them. 

“Two things,” says Aristotle, “ might rightly 
be attributed to Socrates: inductive reasoning, 

159 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


and universal definitions.” Now when Aristotle © 
says this of Socrates, he is recording the institu-— 
tion of a method, which might be applied in the — 
way just indicated, to natural objects, to such ἃ 
substance as carbon, or to such natural processes © 
as heat or motion ; but which, by Socrates him- © 
self, as by Plato after him, was applied almost — 
exclusively to moral phenomena, to the general- © 
isation of esthetic, political, ethical ideas, of © 
the laws of operation (for the essence of every © 
true conception, or definition, or idea, is a law of © 
operation) of the feelings and the will. To get — 
a notion, a definition, or idea, of motion, for | 
example, which shall not exclude the subtler — 
forms of it, heat for instance—to get a notion of © 
i 
; 
. 


carbon, which shall include not common charcoal 


only, but the diamond, a thing superficially so 
unlike it, and which shall also exclude, perhaps, — 
some other substance, superficially almost indis- — 
tinguishable from it: such is the business of | 
ΓΝ science, in obedience to rules, outlined , 


by Bacon in the first book of the Novum 
Organum, for securing those acts of “inclusion” 
and “exclusion,” ic/usiones, exclusiones, natura, 
debite, as he says, “ which Hie nature of things 
requires,” if our thoughts are not to misrepresent 
them. 


It was a parallel process, a process of in- 


clusion, that one’s resultant idea should be 


adequate, of rejection or exclusion, that this idea 


should be not redundant, which Socrates applied — 
160 


THE DOCTRINE OF PLATO 


to practice ; exercising, as we see in the Platonic 
Dialogues, the two opposed functions of συναγωγή 
and διαίρεσις, for the formation of just ideas of 
Temperance, Wisdom, Bravery, Justice itself—a 
classification of the phenomena of the entire 
world of feeling and action. Ideas, if they fulfil 
their proper purpose, represent to the mind such 
phenomena, for its convenience, but may easily 
also misrepresent them. In the transition from 
the particulars to the general, and again in the 
transition from the general idea, the mental 
word, to the spoken or written word, to what 
we call the definition, a door lies open, both for 
the adulteration and the diminution of the 
proper content, of our conception, our definition. 
The first growth of the Platonic “ideas,” as we 
see it in Socrates, according to the report of 
Aristotle, provided against this twofold mis- 
representation. Its aim is to secure, in the 
terms of our discourse with others and with 
ourselves, precise equivalence to what the 
denote. It was a“ mission” to go about Athens 
and challenge people to guard the inlets of error, 
in the passage from facts to their thoughts about 
them, in the passage from thoughts to words. 
It was an intellectual gymnastic, to test, more 
exactly than they were in the habit of doing, 
the equivalence of words they.used so constantly 
as ‘fust, Brave, Beautiful, to the thoughts they 
had; of those thoughts to the facts of ex- 
perience, which it was the business of those 
P. VI 161 M 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


thoughts precisely to represent; to clear the 
mental air; to arrange the littered work- 
chamber of the mind. 

In many of Plato’s Dialogues we see no more 
than the ordered reflex of this process, informal — 
as it was in the actual practice of Socrates. Out — 
of the accidents of a conversation, as from the © 
confused currents of life and action, the typical 
forms of the vices and virtues emerge in definite — 
outline. The first contention of The Republic, 
for instance, is to establish in regard to the 
nature of Justice, terms as exactly conterminous — 
with thoughts, thoughts as exactly conterminous _ 
with moral facts, as the notion of carbon is for 
the naturalist, when it has come to include both — 
charcoal and the diamond, on the basis of the 
essential law of their operation as experience 
reveals it. Show us, not merely accidental 
truths about it; but, by the doing of what (Τί 
ποιοῦσα) In the very soul of its possessor, itself by 
itself, Justice is a good, and Injustice a bad thing, 
That illustrates exactly what is meant by “an 
idea,” the force of “knowledge through ideas,” 
in the particular instance of Justice. It will 
include perhaps, on the one hand, forms of 
Justice so remote from the Justice of our every- 
day experience as to seem inversions of it; it 
will clearly exclude, on the other hand, acts and’ 
thoughts, not it, yet, phenomenally, so like it, as) 
to deceive the very gods; and its area will be 
expanded sufficiently to include, not the indi- 

162 | 


THE DOCTRINE OF PLATO 


vidual only, but the state. And you, the philo- 
sophic student, were to do that, not for one 
virtue only, but for Piety, and Beauty, and the 
State itself, and Knowledge, and Opinion, and 
the Good. Nay, you might go on and do the 
same thing for the physical, when you came to 
the end of the moral, world, were life long 
enough, and if you had the humour for it :—for 
Motion, Number, Colour, Sound. That, then, 
was the first growth of the Platonic ideas, as 
derived immediately from Socrates, whose formal 
contribution to philosophy had been “ universal 
definitions,” developed “inductively,” by the 
twofold method of “ inclusion ” and “ exclusion.” 
_ Aristotle adds, however, that Socrates had 
stopped at the point here indicated: he had not 
gone on, like some others, to make those universal 
notions or definitions ‘separable ”—separable, 
that is to say, from the particular and concrete 
instances, from which he had gathered them. 
Separable : χωριστός (famous word !) that is pre- 
tisely what general notions become in what is 
specially called “the Platonic Theory of Ideas.” 
The “Ideas” of Plato are, in truth, neither more 
ior less than those universal icGhitions: those 
iniversal conceptions, as they look, as they could 
10t but look, amid the peculiar lights and 
hadows, in the singularly constituted atmosphere, 
inder the strange laws of refraction, and in the 
roper perspective, of Plato’s house of thought. 
y its peculiarities, subsequent thought—philo- 
163 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


sophic, poetic, theological—has been greatly 
influenced; by the intense subjectivities, the 
accidents, so to speak, of Plato’s genius, of Plato 
himself; the ways constitutional with him, the 
magic or trick of his personality, in regarding: 
the intellectual material he was occupied with— 
by Plato’s psychology. And it is characteristic 
of him, again, that those peculiarities of his 
mental weitude are evidenced informally ; by a) 
tendency, as we said, by the mere general tone 
in which he speaks of Beauty, for instance, “as 
it really is,” of all that “really is,” under its 
various forms ; a manner of speaking, not explicit, 
but veiled, in various degrees, under figures, as 
at the end of the sixth book of The Republic, or 
under mythological fantasies, like those of the 
Phedrus. He seems to have no inclination for 
the responsibilities of definite theory; for ἃ 
system such as that of the Neo-Platonists for 
instance, his own later followers, who, in a kind 
of prosaic and cold-blooded transcendentalism 
developed as definite philosophic dogma, hard 
enough in more senses than one, what in Plate 
is to the last rather poetry than metaphysica 
reasoning—the irrepressible because almost un- 
conscious poetry, which never deserts him, ever 
when treating of what is neither more nor les 
than a chapter in the rudiments of logic. | 


The peculiar development of the Socratic 
realism by Plato can then only be understoot 
164 


ἑ 
| THE DOCTRINE OF PLATO 

. 

by a consideration of the peculiarities of Plato’s 
genius ; how it reacted upon those abstractions ; 
what they came to seem in its peculiar atmo- 
sphere. The Platonic doctrine of “Ideas,” as 
was said, is not so much a doctrine, as a way of 
speaking or feeling about certain elements of the 
mind; and this temper, this peculiar way of 
feeling, of speaking, which for most of us will 
have many difficulties, is not uniformly notice- 
ible in Plato’s Dialogues, but is to be found 
more especially in the Phado, the Symposium, 
> in certain books of The Republic, above all 
nthe Phedrus. Here is a famous passage from 
| :-- 


There (that is to say, at a particular point in a sort of 
ythagorean mental pilgrimage through time and _ space) 
here, at last, its utmost travail and contest awaits the 
oul. For the immortal souls, so-called, when they were 
1pon the highest point, passed out and stood (as you might 
itand upon the outside of a great hollow sphere) upon the back 
ἢ the sky. And as they stand there, the revolution of the 
pheres carries them round; and they behold the things that 
ire beyond the sky. ‘That supercelestial place none of our 
yoets on earth has ever yet sung of, nor will ever sing, 
worthily. And thus it is: for 1 must make bold to state the 
ruth, at any rate, especially as it is about truth, that I am 
jpeaking. For the colourless, and formless, and impalpable 
3eing, being in very truth of (that is, relative to) the soul, is 
nsible by reason alone as one’s guide. Centered about that, 
he generation, or seed, yévos—the people, of true knowledge 
nhabits this place. As, then, the intelligence of God, which 
8 nourished by pure or unmixed reason and knowlege (dxn- 
νάτῳ, unmixed with sense) so, the intelligence of every other 
joul also, which is about to receive that which properly be- 
‘ongs to it, beholding, after long interval, that which is, ves 
| 165 


~ 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


it (that’s the point!) and by the vision of truth is fed; and 
fares well; until, in cycle, the revolving movement brings it 
round again to the same place. And in that journey round it 
looks upon Justice itself; it looks upon ‘Temperance, upon 
Knowledge; not that knowledge to which the process of 
becoming (the law of change, namely, of birth and death and 
decay) attaches; nor that which is, as it were, one in one 
thing, another in another, of those things which now we 
speak of as being; but the knowledge which is in that 
which in very deed is (τὴν ἐν ty 6 ἐστιν ὃν ὄντως ἐπιστήμην 
οὖσαν) and having beheld, after the same manner, all other 
things that really are, and feasted upon them, being passed 
back again to the interior of the sky, the soul returned home, 
Phedrus, 247. 


Only, as Plato thinks, that return was, in fact, 
an exile. 

There, in that attractive, but perhaps not 
wholly acceptable, sort of discourse, in some 
other passages like it, Plato has gone beyond 
his master Socrates, on two planes or levels, so 
to speak, of speculative ascent, which we may 
distinguish from each other, by way of making 
a little clearer what is in itself certainly so 
difficult. ' 

For Plato, then, not by way of formal theory, 
we must remember, but by a turn of thought 
and speech (while he speaks of them, in fact) 
the Socratic “‘ universals,” the notions of Justice 
and the like, are become, first, things in them- 
selves—the real things ; and secondly, persons, 
to be known as persons must be; and to be 
loved, for the perfections, the visible perfec- 
tions, we might say—intellectually visible—of 

166 | 


THE DOCTRINE OF PLATO 


their being. “It looks upon Justice itself; it 
looks upon Temperance ; upon Knowledge.” 
Hitherto, in the Socratic disputations, the 
ideas had been creations, serviceable creations, 
' of men’s thought, of our reason. With Plato, 
they are the creators of our reason—those 
_ treasures of experience, stacked and _ stored, 
_which, to each one of us, come as by inherit- 
_ ance, or with no proportionate effort on our part, 
to direct, to enlarge and rationalise, from the 
first use of language by us, our manner of tak- 
ing things. For Plato, they are no longer, as 
with Socrates, the instruments by which we 
_ tabulate and classify and record our experience 
—mere “marks” of the real things of experi- 
ence, of what is essential in this or that, and 
common to every particular that goes by a 
_ certain common name; but are themselves 
rather the proper objects of all true know- 
ledge, and a passage from all merely relative 
experience to the “absolute.” In proportion 
as they lend themselves to the individual, in 
his effort to think, they create reason in him ; 
they reproduce the eternal reason for him. For 
Socrates, as Aristotle understands him, they were 
still in service to, and valid only in and by, the 
experience they recorded, with no /ocus standi 
beyond. For Plato, for Platonists, they are 
_become—Justice and Beauty, and the perfect 
State, or again Equality (that which we must 
bring with us, if we are to apprehend sensible 
167 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


instances thereof, but which no two equal 
things here, two coins, ever really attain) nay, 
Couch, or Tree, every general thought, or 
name of a thing, whatever—separate (χωριστός) 
separable from, as being essentially independent 
of, the individual mind which conceives them ; 
as also of the particular temporary instances 
which come under them, come and go, while 
they remain for ever—those eternal “forms,” of 
Tree, Equality, Justice, and so forth. 


That, then, is the first stage, or plane, of 
Platonic transcendentalism. Our common ideas, 
without which, in fact, we none of us could 
think at all, are not the consequence, not the 
products, but the cause of our reason in us: we 
did not make them ; but they make us what we 
are, as reasonable beings. The eternal Being, 
of Parmenides, one and indivisible, has been dif- 
fused, divided, resolved, refracted, differentiated, 
into the eternal Ideas, a multiple, numerous, 
stellar world, so to call it—abstract light into — 
stars: Justice, Temperance as it is, Bravery as 
it is. Permanence, independency, indefectible 
identity with itself—all those qualities which 
Parmenides supposed in the one and indivisible 
reality —belong to every one of those ideas 
severally. 

It was like a recrudescence of polytheism in 
that abstract world; a return of the many gods 
of Homer, veiled now as abstract notions, Love, 

168 


THE DOCTRINE OF PLATO 


Fear, Confidence, and the like; and as such, 
the modern anthropologist, our student of the 
natural history of man, would rank the Platonic 
theory as but a form of what he calls “animism.” 
Animism, that tendency to locate the movements 
of a soul like our own in every object, almost in 
every circumstance, which impresses one with a 
sense of power, is a condition of mind, of which 
the simplest illustration is primitive man ador- 
ing, as a divine being endowed with will, the 
meteoric stone that came rushing from the sky. 
That condition “survives” however, in the 
negro, who thinks the discharging gun a liv- 
ing creature; as it survives also, more subtly, 
in the cnlare of Wordsworth and Shelley, aie 
whom clouds and peaks are kindred spirits ; in 
the pantheism of Goethe; and in Schelling, 
who formulates that pantheism as a philosophic, 
a Platonic, theory. Such “animistic” instinct 
was, certainly, a natural element in Plato’s 
mental constitution,—the instinctive effort to 
find anima, the conditions of personality, in 
whatever pre-occupied his mind, a mind, be it 
remembered, of which the various functions, as 
we reckon them, imagination, reason, intuition, 
were still by no means clearly analysed and 
differentiated from each other, but participated, 
all alike and all together, in every single act of 
mind. 

_ And here is the second stage of the Platonic 
idealism, the second grade of Plato’s departure 
| 169 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


from the simpler realism of his master, as noted | 
by Aristotle, towards that “intelligible world,” — 
opposed by him so constantly to the visible © 
world, into which many find it so hard to follow 
him at all, and in which the ‘‘ideas” become | 
veritable persons. ΤῸ speak, to think, to feel, — 
about abstract ideas as if they were living | 
persons; that, is the second stage of Plato’s — 
speculative ascent. With the lover, who had | 
graduated, was become a master, in the school | 
of love, but had turned now to the love οὗ 
intellectual and strictly invisible things, it was — 
as if the faculty of physical vision, of the bodily 
eye, were still at work at the very centre of — 
intellectual abstraction. Abstract ideas them- — 
selves became animated, living persons, almost 
corporeal, as if with hands and eyes. And it is, © 
as a consequence, but partly also as a secondary 
reinforcing cause, of this mental condition, that — 
the idea of Beauty becomes for Plato the central — 
idea ; the permanently typical instance of what — 
an idea means; of its relation to particular — 
things, and to the action of our thoughts upon — 
them. It was to the lover dealing with physi- — 
cal beauty, a thing seen, yet unseen—seen by _ 
all, in some sense, and yet, truly, by one and | 
not by another, as if through some capricious, _ 
personal self-discovery, by some law of affinity — 
between the seer and what is seen, the knowing | 
and the known—that the nature and function οὐ 
an idea, as such, would come home most clearly. 
170 


THE DOCTRINE OF PLATO 


And then, while visible beauty is the clearest, 
the most certain thing, in the world (lovers will 
always tell you so) real with the reality of some- 
thing hot or cold in one’s hand, it also comes 
nearest of all things, so Plato assures us, to its 
eternal pattern or prototype. For some reason, 
the eternal idea of beauty had left visible copies 
of itself, shadows, antitypes, out of all propor- 
tion, in their truthfulness and adequacy, to any 
copy, left here with us, of Justice, for instance, 
or Equality, or the Perfect State. The typical 
instance of an abstract idea, yet pre-occupying 
the mind with all the colour and circumstance 
of the relationship of person to person, the idea 
of Beauty, conveyed into the entire theory of 
ideas, the associations which belong properly to 
such relationships only. A certain measure of 
caprice, of capricious preference or repulsion, 
would thus be naturally incidental to the 
commerce of men’s minds with what really 
is, with the world in which things really are, 
only so far as they are truly known. “ Philo- 
sophers are /overs of truth and of that which zs 
—impassioned lovers”: Tod ὄντος τε καὶ ἀληθείας 
ἐραστὰς, τοὺς φιλοσόφου. They are the corner- 
stone, as readers of The Republic know, of the 
ideal state—those impassioned lovers, ἐραστάς, of 
that which really is, and in comparison where- 
with, office, wealth, honour, the love of which 
has rent Athens, the world, to pieces, will be of 
no more than secondary importance. 
171 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


He is in truth, in the power, in the hands, of 
another, of another will—this lover of the Ideas 
—attracted, corrected, guided, rewarded, satiated, 
in a long discipline, that “ascent of the soul into 
the intelligible world,” of which the ways of 
earthly love (τὰ ἐρωτικά) are a true parallel. His 
enthusiasm of knowledge is literally an enthust- 
asm: has about it that character of possession of 
one person by another, by which those “ani- 
mistic” old Greeks explained natural madness. 
That philosophic enthusiasm, that impassioned 
desire for true knowledge, is a kind of madness 
(μανία) the madness to which some have declared 
great wit, all great gifts, to be always allied— 
the fourth species of mania, as Plato himself 
explains in the Phedrus. ΤῸ natural madness, to 
poetry and the other gifts allied to it, to prophecy 
like that of the Delphic pythoness, he has to 
add, fourthly, the “‘ enthusiasm of the ideas.” 

The whole course of our theory hitherto (he there tells us) 
relates to that fourth form of madness; wherein, when any 
one, seeing the beauty that is here below, and having a remi- 
niscence of the true, feels, or finds, his wings (πτερῶται) flutter- 
ing upwards, in his eagerness to soar above, but unable, like a 
bird looking towards the sky, heedless of things below, he is 
charged with unsoundness of mind. I have told how this is 
the most excellent of all forms of enthusiasm (or possession) 
both to its possessor and to him who participates in it; how 
it comes of the noblest causes ; and that the lover who has a 
share of this madness is called a lover of the beautiful. For, 
as has been said, every soul of man, by its very nature, has seen 
the things that really are, otherwise it would not have come 
into this form of life (into a human body). But to rise from 
things here to the recollection of those, is not an easy matter 

172 


THE DOCTRINE OF PLATO 


for every soul ; neither for those which then had but a brief 
view of things there; nor for such as were unlucky in their 
descent hither, so that, through the influence of certain associa- 
tions, turning themselves to what is not right, they have for- 
gotten the sacred forms which then they saw. Few souls, in 
truth, remain, to which the gift of reminiscence adequately 
pertains. ‘These, when they see some likeness of things there, 
are lost in amazement, and belong no longer to themselves ; 
only, they understand not the true nature of their affection, be- 
cause they lack discernment. Now, of Justice, and of T’emper- 
ance, and of all those other qualities which are precious to souls, 
there is no clear light in their semblances here below ; but, 
through obscure organs, with difficulty, very few, coming to 
their figures, behold the generation (γένος, the people) of that 
which is figured. At that moment it was possible to behold 
Beauty in its clearness, when, with the choir of the blessed 
following on, ourselves with Zeus, some with one, some with 
another, of the gods, they looked upon a blissful vision and 
view, and were made partakers in what it is meet and right to 
call the most blessed of all mysteries ; the which we celebrated, 
sound and whole then, and untouched by the evil things that 
awaited us in time to come, as being admitted to mystic sights, 
whole and sound and at unity with themselves, in pure light 
gazing on them, being ourselves pure, and unimpressed by this 
we carry about now and call our body, imprisoned like a fish 
in its shell. 

Let memory be indulged thus far ; for whose sake, in regret 
for what was then, I have now spoken somewhat at length. 
As regards Beauty, as 1 said, it both shone out, in its true 
being, among those other eternal forms ; and when we came 
down hither we apprehended it through the clearest of all our 
bodily senses, gleaming with utmost brightness. For sight 
comes to us keenest of all our bodily senses, though Wisdom 
is not seen by it. Marvellous loves, in truth, would that 
(namely, Wisdom) have afforded, had it presented any mani- 
fest image of itself, such as that of Beauty, had it reached our 
bodily vision—that, and all those other amiable forms. But 
now Beauty alone has had this fortune; so that it is the 
clearest, the most certain, of all things ; and the most lovable. 
Phedrus, 2.49. 


173 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


II. Dialectic 


Three different forms of composition have, 
under the intellectual conditions of different 
ages, prevailed—three distinct literary methods, 
in the presentation of philosophic thought ; the 
metrical form earliest, when philosophy was 
still a matter of intuition, imaginative, sanguine, 
often turbid or obscure, and became a Poem, 
Περὶ Φύσεως, “Concerning Nature”; according to 
the manner of Pythagoras, “‘his golden verses,” 
of Parmenides or Empedokles, after whom 
Lucretius in his turn modelled the finest extant 
illustration of that manner of writing, of 
thinking. 

It was succeeded by precisely the opposite 
manner, when native intuition had shrunk into 
dogmatic system, the dry bones of which rattle 
in one’s ears, with Aristotle, or Aquinas, or 
Spinoza, as a formal treatise; the perfected 
philosophic temper being situate midway be- 
tween those opposites, in the third essential 
form of the literature of philosophy, namely 
the essay; that characteristic literary type of 
our own time, a time so rich and various in 
special apprehensions of truth, so tentative and 
dubious in its sense of their ensemb/e, and issues. 
Strictly appropriate form of our modern phil- 
osophic literature, the essay came into use at 
what was really the invention of the relative, 

174 


| 
| 


} 


THE DOCTRINE OF PLATO 


or “modern” spirit, in the Renaissance of the 
sixteenth century.’ 


The poem, the treatise, the essay: you see 
already that these three methods of writing are 


no mere literary accidents, dependent on the 
personal choice of this or that particular writer, 
but necessities of literary form, determined 
directly by matter, as corresponding to three 
essentially different ways in which the human 


mind relates itself to truth. If oracular verse, 


stimulant but enigmatic, is the proper vehicle 
_of enthusiastic intuitions ; if the treatise, with its 


ambitious array of premiss and conclusion, is the 
natural out-put of scholastic all-sufficiency ; so, 
the form of the essay, as we have it towards the 
end of the sixteenth century, most significantly 
in Montaigne, representative essayist because the 
representative doubter, inventor of the name as, 
in essence, of the thing—of the essay, in its 
seemingly modest aim, its really large and adven- 
turous possibilities—is indicative of Montaigne’s 
peculiar function in regard to his age, as in truth 
the commencement of our own. It provided 
him with precisely the literary form necessary 
to a mind for which truth itself is but a possi- 
bility, realisable not as general conclusion, but 
rather as the elusive effect of a particular 
personal experience; to a mind which, noting 


1 Essay— A loose sally of the mind,” says Johnson’s Diction- 
ary. Bailey’s earlier Dictionary gives another suggestive use of 
the word “among miners ”—4 Jittle trench or hole, which they dig to 
search for ore. 


175 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


faithfully those random lights that meet it by © 
the way, must needs content itself with suspen- | 
sion of judgment, at the end of the intellectual | 
journey, to the very last asking: Que scais-je? | 


Who knows ?—in the very spirit of that old 


Socratic contention, that all true philosophy is | 


but a refined sense of one’s ignorance. 


And as Aristotle is the inventor of the ‘| 


treatise, so the Platonic Dialogue, in its con- 


ception, its peculiar opportunities, is essentially | 
an essay—an essay, now and then passing into — 
the earlier form of philosophic poetry, the | 
prose-poem of Heraclitus. ‘There have been ~ 
effective writers of dialogue since, Bruno, for | 
instance, Berkeley, Landor, with whom, how- 
ever, that literary form has had no strictly — 
constitutional propriety to the kind of matter ἡ 
it conveyed, as lending itself (that is to say) © 
structurally to a many-sided but hesitant con- | 
sciousness of the truth. Thus, with Berkeley, © 
its purpose is but to give a popular turn to | 
certain very dogmatic opinions, about which © 
there is no diffidence, there are no half-lights, — 
in the writer’s own mind. With Plato, on the 
other hand, with Plato least of all is the 
dialogue—that peculiar modification of the 
essay—anything less than essential, necessary, — 
organic: the very form belongs to, is of the 
organism of, the matter which it embodies. 
For Plato’s Dialogues, in fact, reflect, they refine | 


176 


3 Se >= 
Te Er i 


THE DOCTRINE OF PLATO 


upon while they fulfil, they idealise, the actual 
ethod, in which, by preference to anything 
ike formal lecturing (the lecture being, so to 
peak, a treatise in embryo) Socrates conveyed 
is doctrine to others. We see him in those 
Dialogues of Plato, still loitering in the public 
places, the open L citiaeg the suburban roads, of 
Athens, as if seeking πα from others ; seeking 
it, doubtless, from himself, but along with, and 
y the help of, his supposed scholars, for whom, 
ndeed, he can but bring their own native con- 
eptions of truth to the birth ; but always faith- 
ully registering just so much light as is given, 
d, so to speak, never concluding. 

The Platonic Dialogue is the literary trans- 
ormation, in a word, of what was the inti- 
ately home-grown method of Socrates, not only 
f conveying truth to others, but of coming by 
for himself. The essence of that method, of 
dialectic” in all its forms, as its very name 
enotes, is dialogue, the habit of seeking truth 
y means of question and answer, primarily with 
ne’s self. Just there, lies the validity of the 
ethod—in a dialogue, an endless dialogue, 
ith one’s self; a dialogue concerning those first 
rinciples, or “universal definitions,” or notions, 
ose “ideas,” which, according to Plato, are 
€ proper objects of all real knowledge ; con- 
ting the adequacy of one’s hold upon them; 
e relationship to them of other notions; the 
lausible conjectures in our own or other minds, 
P. VI 177 N 


=~ δὴ 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


which come short of them; the elimination, by 
their mere presence in the mind, of positive 
ignorance or error. Justice, Beauty, Perfect 
Polity, and the like, in outlines of eternal and 
absolute certainty: —they were to be appre- 
hended by “dialectic,” literally, by a method 
(μέθοδος) a Circuitous journey, presented by the 
Platonic dialogues in its most accomplished 
literary form. 

For the certainty, the absolute and eternal 
character, of such ideas involved, with much 
labour and scruple, repeated acts of qualification 
and correction; many readjustments to experi- 
ence ; expansion, by larger lights from it ; those 
exclusions and inclusions, debite nature (to repeat 
Bacon’s phrase) demanded, that is to say, by the 
_ veritable nature of the facts which those ideas are | 
designed to represent. ‘‘ Representation ”’ was, in 
fact, twofold, and comprehended many successive 
steps under each of its divisions. The thought 
was to be adjusted, first, to the phenomena, to 
the facts, daintily, to she end that the said 
thought might just cover those facts, and no more, | 
To the thought, secondly, to the conception, thus 
articulated, it was necessary to adjust the term; 
the term, or “ definition,” by which it might be 
conveyed into the mind of another. The 
dialogue—the freedom, the variety and elasticity, 
of dialogue, informal, easy, natural, alone afforded 
the room necessary for that long and complex: 
process. If one, if Socrates, seemed to become 

178 


THE DOCTRINE OF PLATO 


the teacher of another, it was but by thinking 
aloud for a few moments over his own lesson, or 
leaning upon that other as he went along that 
difficult way which each one must really prose- 
cute for himself, however full such comradeship 
might be of happy occasions for the awakening of 
the latent knowledge, with which mind is by 
nature so richly stored. The Platonic Socrates, 
in fact, does not propose to teach anything : is 
but willing, “along with you,” and if you concur, 
“to consider, to seek out, what the thing may be. 
Perchance using our eyes in common, rubbing 
away, we might cause Justice, for instance, to 
glint forth, as from fire-sticks.” ἢ 

*< And, » again, “is not the road to Athens 
‘made for conversation?” Yes! It might seem 
that movement, after all, and any habit that pro- 
moted movement, promoted the power, the 
successes, the fortunate parturition, of the mind. 
A method such as this, a process (processus) a 
movement of thought, which is the very converse 
of mathematical or demonstrative reasoning, and 
incapable therefore of conventional or scholastic 
form, of ‘‘ exactness,” in fact; which proceeded 
to truth, not by the analysis and application of an 
axiom, but by a gradual suppression of error, of 
error in the form of partial or exaggerated truths 
on the subject-matter proposed, found its proper 


1 Σκέψασθαι. καὶ συζητῆσαι ὅτι πότε ἔστιν" καί, (Tax ἄν, Tap 
ἄλληλα σκοποῦντες, καὶ τρίβοντες, ὥσπερ ἐκ πυρείων, ἐκλάμψαι 
ποιήσαιμεν τὴν δικαιοσύνην. 


179 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


literary vehicle in a dialogue, the more flexible 


the better. It was like a journey indeed, that 
essay towards Justice, for example, or the true 
Polity ; a journey, not along the simple road to 


Athens, but to a mountain’s top. The propor-_ 
tions, the outline, the relation of the thing to. 
its neighbours,—how do the inexperienced in such — 
journeys mistake them, as they climb! What > 


repeated misconceptions, embodying, one by one, — 
some mere particularity of view, the perspective 


of this or that point of view, forthwith abandoned, _ 


some apprehension of mountain form and structure, 


just a little short, or, it may be, immeasurably 


short, of what Plato would call the “synoptic " 
view of the mountain as a whole. From this or 


that point, some insignificant peak presented itself 


as the mountain’s veritable crest: inexperience 


would have sworn to the truth of a wholly illusive - 


perspective, as the next turn in the journey 
assured one. It is only upon the final step, with 
free view at last on every side, uniting together 
and justifying all those various, successive, partial 
apprehensions of the difficult way—only on the 


summit, comes the intuitive comprehension of 


what the true form of the mountain really is ; 


with a mental, or rather an imaginative hold upon 


which, for the future, we can find our way 
securely about it; observing perhaps that, next 


to that final intuition, the first view, the first 
impression, had been truest about it. 


180 


δι Σ.»- 


THE DOCTRINE OF PLATO 


Such, in its full scope, is the journey or 
pilgrimage, the method (ὁδός, κίνησις, μέθοδος) Of 
the Socratic, of the perfected Platonic dialectic, 
towards the truth, the true knowledge, of Bravery 
or Friendship, for instance ; of Space or Motion, 
again, as suggested in the seventh book of The 
Republic ; of the ideal City, of the immaculate 
Beauty. You are going about Justice, for ex- 
ample—that great complex elevation on the level 
surface of life, whose top, it may be, reaches to 
heaven. You fancy you have grasped its outline. 
᾿Αλλὰ μεταθώμεθα. You are forced on, perhaps by 
your companion, a step further, and the view has 
already changed. ‘“‘ Persevere,”’ Plato might say, 
“and a step may be made, upon which, again, 
a whole world around may change, the entire 
horizon and its relation to the point you stand 
on—a change from the half-light of conjecture 
to the full light of indefectible certitude. That, 
of course, can only happen by a summary act of 
intuition upon the entire perspective, wherein 
all those partial apprehensions, which one by 
one may have seemed inconsistent with each 
other, find their due place, or (to return to the 
Platonic Dialogue again, to the actual process of 
dialectic as there exposed) by that final impression 
of a subject, a theorem, in which the mind attains 
a hold, as if by a single imaginative act, through 
all the transitions of a long conversation, upon 
all the seemingly opposite contentions of all the 
various speakers at once. We see already why 
181 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


Platonic dialectic—the ladder, as Plato thinks, | 


by which alone we can ascend into the entirely 
reasonable world (νοητὸς τόπος) beginning with 
the boyish difficulties and crudities of Meno, 
for instance, is a process which may go on, at 


least with those gifted by nature and opportunity, — 


as in the Perfect City,—may go on to the close 
of life, and, as Pythagorean theory suggests, 
perhaps does not end even then. 


The process of dialectic, as represented in the 
Platonic Dialogues, may seem, therefore, incon-_ 
sistent with itself, if you isolate this or that 


particular movement, in what is a very complex 


process, with many phases of development. It 


is certainly difficult, and that not merely on a 
first reading, to grasp the unity of the various 
statements Plato has made about it. Now it 


may seem to differ from ordinary reasoning by 


a certain plausibility only : it is logic, p/us per- 
suasion ; helping, gently enticing, a child out οὗ, 
his natural errors ; ; carefully explaining difficulties 
by the way, as one can best do, by question and 
answer with him; above all, never falling into 


the mistake of the obscurum per obscurius. At 
another time it may seem to aim at plausibility 
of another sort; at mutual complaisance, as 
Thrasymachus complains. It would be possible, 


of course, to present an insincere dialogue, in 
which certain of the disputants shall be mere 
men of straw. In the PAz/ebus again, dialectic 


is only the name of the process (described there 
182 


one 


THE DOCTRINE OF PLATO 


as exactly, almost as technically, as Aristotle, or 
-‘'some modern master of applied logic, might 
describe it) of the resolution of a genus into 
its species. Or it lapses into “eristic’’—into 
an argument for its own sake; or sinks into 
logomachy,a mere dispute about words. Or yet 
again, an immense, a boundless promise is made 
for it, as in the seventh book of The Republi. 
It is a life, a systematised, but comprehensive 
and far-reaching, intellectual life, in which the 
reason, nay, the whole nature of man, realises all 
it was designed to be, by the beatific “ vision of 
all time and all existence.” 

Now all these varying senses of the word 
“ dialectic” fall within compass, if we remember 
that for Plato, as for every other really philo- 
sophic thinker, method must be ome; that it 
must cover, or be understood to cover, the entire 
process, all the various processes, of the mind, 
in pursuit of properly representative ideas, of a 
reasoned reflex of experience ; and that for Plato, 
this process is essentially a long discourse or 
reasoning of the mind with itself. It is that 
dynamic, or essential, dialogue of the mind with 
itself, which lends, or imputes, its active principle 
to the written or spoken dialogue, which, in 
return, lends its name to the method it figures— 
“dialectic.” Well! in that long and complex 
dialogue of the mind with itself, many persons, 
so to speak, will necessarily take part ; so many 
persons as there are possible contrasts or shades 

183 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


in the apprehension of some complex subject. — 


The advocatus diaboli will be heard from time 
to time. The dog also, or, as the Greeks said, 
the wolf, will out with his story against the 


man; and one of the interlocutors will always — 
be a child, turning round upon us innocently, — 
candidly, with our own admissions, or surprising | 


us, perhaps at the last moment, by what seems 


his invincible ignorance, when we thought it © 
rooted out of him. There will be a youth, in- © 
experienced in the capacities of language, who © 
will compel us to allow much time to the dis- | 


cussion of words and phrases, though not always 
unprofitably. And to the last, let us hope, re- 
freshing with his enthusiasm, the weary or dis- 
heartened enquirer (who is always also of the 
company) the rightly sanguine youth, ingenuous 
and docile, to whom, surely, those friendly living 
ideas will be willing, longing, to come, after that 
Platonic law of affinity, so effectual in these 
matters—opoioy ὁμοίῳ. 

With such a nature above all, bringing with 
it its felicities of temperament, with the sort of 


natures (as we may think) which intellectually — 


can but thrive, a method like that, the dialectic 


method, will also have its felicities, its singular — 


good fortunes. A voyage of discovery, prosecuted 
almost as if at random, the Socratic or Platonic 
‘dialogue of enquiry,” seems at times to be in 


charge of a kind of “ Providence.” Or again, — 
it will be as when hunters or bird-catchers “* beat — 


184 


| 


THE DOCTRINE OF PLATO 


the bush,” as we say: Plato elaborates that figure 
in The Republic. Only, if they be knowing in 
the process, a fair percentage of birds will be 
found and taken. All the chances, or graces, of 
such a method, as actually followed in a whole 
life of free enquiry, The Republic, for a watchful 
reader, represents in little. And when, using 
still another figure, Socrates says: “I do not 
yet know, myself; but, we must just go where 
the argument carries us, as a vessel runs before 
the wind,” he breathes the very soul of the 
(ἐς dialectic method” :—Omn ἂν ὁ λόγος, ὥσπερ πνεῦμα, 


] / im | ΑΨ. 
φέρῃ, ταύτῃ LTEOV. 


This dialectic method, this continuous dis- 
course with one’s self, being, for those who 
prosecute it with thoroughness, co-extensive 
with life itself—a part of the continuous com- 
pany we keep with ourselves through life—will 
have its inequalities ; its infelicities ; above all, 
its final insecurity. ‘‘ We argue rashly and ad- 
-venturously,” writes Plato, most truly, in the 
Timeus—aye, we, the Platonists, as such, some- 
times—‘“ by reason that, like ourselves, our dis- 
courses (our Platonic discourses, as such) have 
much participation in the temerity of chance.” 
Of course, as in any other occasional conversation, 
with its dependence on the hour and the scene, 
the persons we are with, the humours of the 
moment, there will always be much of accident 
in this essentially informal, this un-methodical, 

185 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


method; and, therefore, opportunities for misuse, 
sometimes consciously. ‘The candid reader notes 
instances of such, even in The Republic, not 
always on the part of Thrasymachus :—in this 
“new game of chess,” played, as Plato puts it, 
not with counters, but with words, and not 
necessarily for the prize of truth, but, it may 
be, for the mere enjoyment of move and counter- 
move, of check-mating. 

Since Zeno’s paradoxes, in fact, the very air 
of Athens was become sophisticated, infected with 
questionings, often vain enough; and the Platonic 


method had been, in its measure, determined : 
by (the unfriendly might say, was in truth only — 


a deposit from) that infected air. ‘‘ Socrates,” as 


he admits, “is easily refuted. Say rather, dear — 
Agathon, that you cannot refute the truth.” — 


That is reassuring, certainly! For you might 
think sometimes, uneasily, of the Platonic 


ἡ 


i 


Socrates, that, as he says of the Sophist, or οὔ. 


himself perhaps ez caricature, in the Euthydemus, — 


“Such is his skill in the war of words, that he ' 


can refute any proposition whatever, whether 
true or false” ; that, in short, there is a danger- 
ous facility abroad for proving all things what- 
ever, equally well, of which Socrates, and his 
presumable allotment of truth, has but the general 
allotment. 


The friendly, on the other hand, might rejoin 


even then, that, as Lessing suggests, the search 
for truth is a better thing for us than its possessiony 
186 


THE DOCTRINE OF PLATO 


Plato, who supposes any knowledge worth the 
name to be “absolute and eternal”; whose 
constant contention it is, to separate /ongo inter- 
vallo, by the longest possible interval, science 
(ἐπιστήμη) as the possession of irresistible truth, 
from any and every sort of knowledge which 
falls short of that; would hardly have accepted 
the suggestion of Lessing. Yet, in spite of all 
that, in spite of the demand he makes for certainty 
and exactness and what is absolute, in all real 
knowledge, he does think, or inclines his reader 
to think, that truth, precisely because it resembles 
some high kind of relationship of persons to 
persons, depends a good deal on the receiver; 
and must be, in that degree, elusive, provisional, 
contingent, a matter of various approximation, 
and of an “economy,” as is said; that it is 
partly a subjective attitude of mind :—that philo- 
sophic truth consists in the philosophic temper. 
*‘ Socrates in Plato,” remarks Montaigne acutely, 
“disputes, rather to the profit of the disputants, 
than of the dispute. He takes hold of the first 
subject, like one who has a more profitable end 
in view than to explain it; namely, to clear the 
understandings that he takes upon him to instruct 
and exercise.” 

Just there, in fact, is the justification of Plato’s 
peculiar dialectical method, of its inexactness, its 
hesitancy, its scruples and reserve, as if he feared 
to obtrude knowledge on an unworthy receiver. 
The treatise, as the proper instrument of dogma 

187 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


—the Ethics of Aristotle, the Ethics of Spinoza 
—begins with a truth, or with a clear conviction 
of truth, in the axiom or definition, which it does 
but propose further to explain and apply.—The 
treatise, as the instrument of a dogmatic philo- 
sophy 4egis with an axiom or definition: the 
essay or dialogue, on the other hand, as the 
instrument of dialectic, does not necessarily so 
much as conclude in one; like that long dialogue 
with oneself, that dialectic process, which may 
be co-extensive with life. It does in truth 
little more than clear the ground, as we say, 
or the atmosphere, or the mental tablet, that one 
may have a fair chance of knowing, or seeing, 
perhaps: it does but put one into a duly receptive 
attitude towards such possible truth, discovery, 
or revelation, as may one day occupy the ground, 
the tablet,—shed itself on the purified air; it 
does not provide a proposition, nor a system of 
propositions, but forms a temper. 


What Plato presents to his readers is then, 
again, a paradox, or a reconciliation of opposed 
tendencies: on one side, the largest possible 
demand for infallible certainty in knowledge (it 


was he fixed that ideal of absolute truth, to which, ~ | 


vainly perhaps, the human mind, as such, aspires) 

yet, on the other side, the utmost possible inex- 

actness, or contingency, in the method by which 

actually he proposes to attain it. It has been 

said that the humour of Socrates, of which the 
188 


THE DOCTRINE OF PLATO 


famous Socratic irony—the pretence to have a 
bad memory, to dislike or distrust long and formal 
discourse, to have taught nothing, to be but a 
mid-wife in relation to other people’s thoughts— 
was an element, is more than a mere personal 
trait; that it was welcome as affording a means 
of escape from the full responsibilities of his 
teaching. It belonged, in truth, to the tentative 
character of dialectic, of question and answer as 
the method of discovery, of teaching and learning, 
_to the position, in a word, of the philosophic 
essayist. That it was thus, might be illustrated 
abundantly from the Platonic dialogues. The 
irony, the Socratic humour, so serviceable to a 
diffident teacher, are, in fact, Plato’s own. Kuw- 
᾿ δυνεύει, “it may chance to be,” is, we may notice, 
a favourite catchword of his. The philosopher 
of Being, or, of the verb “To be,” is after all 
afraid of saying, “It is.” 
For, again, person dealing with person—with 
_ possible caprice, therefore, at least on one side— 
or intelligence with intelligence, is what Plato 
supposes in the reception of truth :—that, and 
mot an exact mechanism, a precise machine, 
operating on, or with, an exactly ponderable 
matter. He has fears for truth, however care- 
fully considered. To the very last falsehood 
will lurk, if not about truth itself, about this or 
that assent to it. The receiver may add the 
falsities of his own nature to the truth he re- 
ceives. ‘The proposition which embodies it very 
| 189 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


imperfectly, may not look to him, in those dark 
chambers of his individuality, of himself, into 
which none but he can ever get, to test the 
matter, what it looks to me, or to you. We 
may not even be thinking of, not looking at, 
the same thing, when we talk of Beauty, and 
the like; objects which, after all, to the Platonist 
are matters of θεωρία, of immediate intuition, of 
immediate vision, or, as Plato sometimes fancied, 
of an earlier personal experience; and which, as 
matter of such intuition, are incapable of analysis, 
and therefore, properly, incommunicable by words. 
Place, then, must be left to the last in any legiti- 
mate dialectic process for possible after-thoughts ; 
for the introduction, so to speak, of yet another 
interlocutor in the dialogue, which has, in fact, 
no necessary conclusion, and leaves off only because 
time is up, or when, as he says, one leaves off 
seeking through weariness (dsoxduvov). ‘S What 
thought can think, another thought can mend.” 
Another turn in the endless road may change the 
whole character of the perspective. You cannot, 
as the Sophist proposed to do (that was part of 
his foolishness) take and put truth into the soul. 
If you could, it might be established there, only 
as an “inward lie,” as a mistake. ‘ Must I take 
the argument, and literally insert it into your 
mind?” asks Thrasymachus. ‘ Heaven forbid”: 
answers Socrates. ‘That is precisely what he fears 
most, for himself, and for others; and from first 
to last, demands, as the first condition of comrade- 
190 


THE DOCTRINE OF PLATO 


ship in that long journey in which he conceives 
teacher and learner to be but fellow-travellers, 
pilgrims side by side, sincerity, above all sincerity 
with one’s self—that, and also freedom in reply. 
“ Answer what you think, peyadorperds—liber- 
ally.”” For it is impossible to make way other- 
wise, in a method which consists essentially in 
the development of knowledge by question and 
answer. 

Misuse, again, is of course possible in a method 
which admits of no objective sanction or standard ; 
the success of which depends on a loyalty to one’s 
self, in the prosecution of it, of which no one 
else can be cognisant. And if we can misuse it 
with ourselves, how much more certainly can 
the expert abuse it with another. At every turn 
of the conversation, a door lies open to sophistry. 
Sophistry, logomachy, eristic: we may learn 
what these are, sometimes, from Plato’s own 
practice. That justice is only useful as applied 
to things useless; that the just man is a kind 
of thief; and the like; is hardly so much as 
sophistry. And this too was possible in a 
method, which, with all its large outlook, has 
something of the irregularity, the accident, the 
heats and confusion, of life itself—a method of 
reasoning which can only in a certain measure 
be reasoned upon. How different the exactness 
which Aristotle supposes, and does his best to 
secure, in scientific procedure! For him, dialectic, 
Platonic dialectic, is, at best, a part of “ eristic” 

19! 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


—of the art, or trick, of merely popular and 
approximate debate, in matters where science is 
out of the question, and rhetoric has its office, 
not in providing for the intelligence, but in 
moulding the sentiments and the will. Con- 
versely to that absoluteness and necessity which 
Plato himself supposes in all real knowledge, as 
“the spectacle of all time and all existence,” it 
might seem that the only sort of truth attain- 
able by his actual method, must be the truth 
of a particular time and place, for one and not 
for another. δΔιάλογος πειραστικός, “a Dialogue of 
search” :—every one of Plato’s Dialogues is in 
essence such like that whole, life-long, endless 
dialogue which dialectic, in its largest scope, 
does but formulate, and in which truly the last, 
the infallible word, after all, never gets spoken. 
Our pilgrimage is meant indeed to end in nothing 
less than the vision of what we seek. But can 
we ever be quite sure that we are really come 
to that? By what sign or test ? 


Now oppose all this, all these peculiarities of 
the Platonic method, as we find it, to the exact 
and formal method of Aristotle, of Aquinas, of 
Spinoza, or Hegel; and then suppose one trained 
exclusively on Plato’s dialogues. Is it the eternal 
certainty, after all, the immutable and absolute 
character of truth, as Plato conceived it, that he 
would be likely to apprehend? We have here 
another of those contrasts of tendency, consti- 

192 


THE DOCTRINE OF PLATO 


tutional in the genius of Plato, and which may 
add to our interest in him. Plato is to be ex- 
_ plained, as we say, or interpreted, partly through 
his predecessors, and his contemporaries; but in 
part also by his followers, by the light his later 
mental kinsmen throw back on the conscious or 
unconscious drift of his teaching. Now there 
are in the history of philosophy two opposite 
_ Platonic traditions; two legitimate yet divergent 
streams of influence from him. Two very differ- 
ent yet equally representative scholars we may 
see in thought emerging from his school. The 
“theory of the Ideas,” the high ideal, the un- 
compromising demand for absolute certainty, in 
any truth or knowledge worthy of the name ; 
the immediate or intuitive character of the 
highest acts of knowledge; that all true theory 
15 indeed “ vision” :—for the maintenance of that 
side of the Platonic position we must look onward 
to Aristotle, and the Schoolmen of all ages, to 
Spinoza, to Hegel; to those mystic aspirants to 
“vision” also, the so-called Neo-Platonists of 
all ages, from Proclus to Schelling. From the 
abstract, metaphysical systems of those, the ecstasy 
and illuminism of these, we may mount up to 
the actual words of Plato in the Symposium, the 
fifth book of The Republic, the Phedrus. 

But it is in quite different company we must 
look for the tradition, the development, of Plato’s 
actual method of learning and teaching. The 
Academy of Plato, the established seat of his 


P. VI 193 ο 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


philosophy, gave name to a school, of which 
Lucian, in Greek, and in Latin, Cicero, are the 
proper representatives,—Cicero, the perfect em- 
bodiment of what is still sometimes understood 
to be the “academic spirit,” surveying all sides, 
arraying evidence, ascertaining, measuring, bal- 
ancing, tendencies, but ending in suspension of 
judgment. If Platonism from age to age has 
meant, for some, ontology, a doctrine of “ being,” 
or the nearest attainable approach to or substi- 
tution for that; for others, Platonism has been 
in fact only another name for scepticism, in a 
recognisable philosophic tradition. Thus, in the 
Middle Age, it qualifies in the Sic et Non the 
confident scholasticism of Abelard. It is like 
the very trick and impress of the Platonic Socrates - 
himself again, in those endless conversations of : 
Montaigne—that typical sceptic of the age of 
the Renaissance—coversations with himself, with 
the living, with the dead through their writings, | 
which his Essays do but reflect. Typical Platonist : 
or sceptic, he is therefore also the typical essayist. - 
And the sceptical philosopher of Bordeaux does 
but commence the modern world, which, side 
by side with its metaphysical reassertions, from 
Descartes to Hegel, side by side also with a. 
constant accumulation of the sort of certainty 
which is afforded by empirical science, has had 
assuredly, to check wholesomely the pretensions — 
of one and of the other alike, its doubts.—“ Their + 
name is legion,” says a modern writer. Reverent | 
194 | 


“ἀπ 


——  — i 


| THE DOCTRINE OF PLATO 


and irreverent, reasonable and unreasonable, manly 
and unmanly, morbid and healthy, guilty and 
honest, wilful, inevitable—they have been called, 
indifferently, in an age which thirsts for intel- 
lectual security, but cannot make up its mind. 
Que scais-je ? it cries, in the words of Montaigne ; 
but in the spirit also of the Platonic Socrates, 
with whom such dubitation had been nothing 
less than a religious duty or service. 

Sanguine about any form of absolute know- 
ledge, of eternal, or indefectible, or immutable 
truth, with our modern temperament as it is, we 
shall hardly become, even under the direction 
of Plato, and by the reading of the Platonic 
Dialogues. But if we are little likely to realise 
in his school, the promise of “ontological ” 
science, of a “doctrine of Being,” or any increase 
in our consciousness of metaphysical security, are 
likely, rather, to acquire there that other sort of 
Platonism, a habit, namely, of tentative thinking 
nd suspended judgment, if we are not likely to 
enjoy the vision of his “eternal and immutable 
ideas,” Plato may yet promote in us what we 
call “ideals”—the aspiration towards a more 
perfect Justice, a more perfect Beauty, physical 
and intellectual, a more perfect condition of 
Shuman affairs, than any one has ever yet seen ; 
that κόσμος, in which things are only as they are 
Vthought by a perfect mind, to which experience 
is constantly approximating us, but which it 
‘does not provide. There they stand, the two 
195 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


great landmarks of the intellectual or spiritual 
life as Plato conceived it: the ideal, the world 
of ‘‘ideas,” “the great perhaps,” for which it is 
his merit so effectively to have opened room in 
the mental scheme, to be known by us, if at all, 
through our affinities of nature with it, which, 
however, in our dealings with ourselves and others 
we may assume to be objective or real :—and 
then, over against our imperfect realisation of 
that ideal, in ourselves, in nature and history, 
amid the personal caprices (it might almost seem) 
of its discovery of itself to us, as the appropriate. 
attitude on our part, the dialectical spirit, which 
to the last will have its diffidence and reserve, 
its scruples and second thoughts. Such condition 
of suspended judgment indeed, in its more genial 
development and under felicitous culture, is but 
the expectation, the receptivity, of the faithful 
scholar, determined not to foreclose what is still 
a question—the “philosophic temper,” in short, 
for which a survival of query will be still the 
salt of truth, even in the most absolutely ascer- 
tained knowledge. 


196 


Vill 


LACED/EMON 


| Amonc the Greeks, philosophy has flourished longest, and is 
_ still most abundant, at Crete and Lacedemon ; and there there 
_ are more teachers of philosophy than anywhere else in the world. 
_ But the Lacedemonians deny this, and pretend to be unlearned 
| people, lest it should become manifest that it is through philo- 
_ sophy they are supreme in Greece ; that they may be thought 
| to owe their supremacy to their fighting and manly spirit, for 
\ they think that if the means of their superiority were made 
known all the Greeks would practise this. But now, by keep- 
| ing it a secret, they have succeeded in misleading the Laconisers 
‘in the various cities of Greece ; and in imitation of them these 
| people buffet themselves, and practise gymnastics, and put on 
_ boxing-gloves, and wear short cloaks, as if it were by such 
\things that the Lacedzmonians excel all other Greeks. But 
‘the Lacedzemonians, when they wish to have intercourse with 
) their philosophers without reserve, and are weary of going to 
_ them by stealth, make legal proclamation that those Laconisers 
should depart, with any other aliens who may be sojourning 
_ among them, and thereupon betake themselves to their sophists 
unobserved by strangers. And you may know that what I say 
is true, and that the Lacedemonians are better instructed than 
_all other people in philosophy and the art of discussion in this 
way. If any one will converse with even the most insignificant 
of the Lacedemonians, he may find him indeed in the greater 
| part of what he says seemingly but a poor creature ; but then 
at some chance point in the conversation he will throw in some 
brief compact saying, worthy of remark, like a clever archer, 
80 that his interlocutor shall seem no better than a child Of 


197 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


this fact some both of those now living and of the ancients — 
have been aware, and that to Laconise consists in the study of | 


philosophy far rather than in the pursuit of gymnastic, for they 
saw that to utter such sayings as those was only possible for 
a perfectly educated man. Of these was Thales of Miletus, 
Pittacus of Mytilene, Bias the Prienean, and our own Solon, 
Cleobulus the Lindian, and Myson of Chen, and the seventh 


among them was called Chilon, a Lacedemonian. ‘These were 


all zealous lovers and disciples of the culture of the Lacedz- 
monians. And any one may understand that their philosophy 
was something of this kind, short rememberable sayings uttered 
by each of them. ‘They met together and offered these in 


| 


common, as the first fruits of philosophy, to Apollo in his — 
temple at Delphi, and they wrote upon the walls these sayings © 
known and read of all men: Γνῶθι σαυτόν and Μηδὲν ἄγαν. 


Protagoras, 343. 


Of course there is something in that of the 
romance to which the genius of Plato readily 
inclined him; something also of the Platonic — 


humour or irony, which suggests, for example, 
to Meno, so anxious to be instructed in the 
theory of virtue, that the philosophic temper 
must be departed from Attica, its natural home, 
to Thessaly—to the rude northern capital whence 
that ingenuous youth was freshly arrived. Partly 
romantic, partly humorous, in his Laconism, 
Plato is however quite serious in locating a 
certain spirit at Lacedemon of which his own 
ideal Republic would have been the completer 
development ; while the picture he draws of 
it presents many a detail taken straight from 
Lacedemon as it really was, as if by an admiring 
visitor, who had in person paced the streets of 
the Dorian metropolis it was so difficult for any 
198 


LACEDA MON 


| alien to enter. What was actually known of 
) that stern place, of the Lacedemonians at home, 
at school, had charmed into fancies about it 


) other philosophic theorists; Xenophon for in- 


} stance, who had little or nothing of romantic 
) tendency about them. 

| And there was another sort of romancing also, 
quite opposite to this of Plato, concerning the 
hard ways among themselves of those Lacede- 
_monians who were so invincible in the field. 
_ “The Lacedemonians,” says Pausanias, “ appear 
to have admired least of all people poetry and 
| the praise which it bestows.” “Αἱ Lacedemon 
there is more philosophy than anywhere else 
in the world,” is what Plato, or the Platonic 
Socrates, had said. Yet, on the contrary, there 
were some who alleged that true Lacedemonians 
—Lacedemonian nobles—for their protection 
against the “effeminacies”’ of culture, were denied 
all knowledge of reading and writing. But 
then we know that written books are properly a 
mere assistant, sometimes, as Plato himself sug- 
gests, a treacherous assistant, to memory; those 
conservative Lacedemonians being, so to speak, 
the people of memory pre-eminently, and very 
appropriately, for, whether or not they were 
taught to read and write, they were acknow- 
ledged adepts in the Pythagorean philosophy, 
a philosophy which attributes to memory so 
preponderating a function in the mental life. 
“Writing,” says K. O. Miiller in his laborious, 

199 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


yet, in spite of its air of coldness, passably romantic 
work on The Dorians—an author whose quiet 
enthusiasm for his subject resulted indeed in a 
patient scholarship which well befits it : “ Writ- 
ing,” he says, “was not essential in a nation 
where laws, hymns, and the praises of illustrious 
men—that is, jurisprudence and history—were 
taught in their schools of music.” Music, which 
is or ought to be, as we know, according to those 
Pythagorean doctrines, itself the essence of all 
things, was everywhere in the Perfect City of 
Plato ; and among the Lacedemonians also, who 
may be thought to have come within measurable 
distance of that Perfect City, though with no 
conscious theories about it, music (μουσική) in the 
larger sense of the word, was everywhere, not 
to alleviate only but actually to promote and 
inform, to be the very substance of their so 
strenuous and taxing habit of life. What was 
this “‘music,” this service or culture of the 
Muses, this harmony, partly moral, doubtless, 
but also throughout a matter of elaborate move- 
ment of the voice, of musical instruments, of all 
beside that could in any way be associated to 
such things—this music, for the maintenance, 
the perpetual sense of which those vigorous 
souls were ready to sacrifice so many opportunities, 
privileges, enjoyments of a different sort, so much 
of their ease, of themselves, of one another ? 


Platonism is a highly conscious reassertion 
200 


5. Ἃ Φ' 


‘of one of the two constituent elements in’ the 
Hellenic genius, of the spirit of the highlands 
namely in which the early Dorian forefathers of 
the Lacedemonians had secreted their peculiar 
disposition, in contrast with the mobile, the 
marine and fluid temper of the littoral Ionian 
people. The Republic of Plato is an embodiment 
of that Platonic reassertion or preference, of 
Platonism, as the principle of a society, ideal 
enough indeed, yet in various degrees practicable. 
It is not understood by Plato to be an erection 
_de novo, and therefore only on paper. Its founda- 
tions might be laid in certain practicable changes 
to be enforced in the old schools, in a certain 
reformed music which must be taught there, and 
would float thence into the existing homes of 
Greece, under the shadow of its old temples, the 
sanction of its old religion, its old memories, the 
old names of things. Given the central idea, 
with its essentially renovating power, the well- 
worn elements of society as it is would rebuild 
‘themselves, and a new colour come gradually 
over all things as the proper expression of a 
certain new mind in them. 

And in fact such embodiments of the specially 
Hellenic element in Hellenism, compacted in 
the natural course of political development, there 
had been, though in a less ideal form, in those 
many Dorian constitutions to which Aristotle 
tefers. To Lacedemon, in The Republic itself, 
admiring allusions abound, covert, yet bold 
201 


LACEDEMON ΘΑ 


% 
τ 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


enough, if we remember the existing rivalry | 
between Athens and her neighbour; and it 
becomes therefore a help in the study of Plato’s — 
political ideal to approach as near as we may to | 
that earlier actual embodiment of its principles, — 
which is also very interesting in itself. The 
Platonic City of the Perfect would not have > 
been cut clean away from the old roots of 
national life: would have had many links with © 
the beautiful and venerable Greek cities of past 
and present. ‘The ideal, poetic or romantic as it 
might seem, would but have begun where they | 
had left off, where Lacedemon, in particular, had | 
left off. Let us then, by way of realising the — 
better the physiognomy of Plato’s theoretic build- _ 
ing, suppose some contemporary student of The 
Republic, a pupil, say! in the Athenian Academy, — 
determined to gaze on the actual face of what has _ 
so strong a family likeness to it. Stimulated by | 
his master’s unconcealed Laconism, his approval — 
of contemporary Lacedemon, he is at the pains 
to journey thither, and make personal inspection 
of a place, in Plato’s general commendations of 
which he may suspect some humour or irony, 
but which has unmistakably lent many a detail 
to his ideal Republic, on paper, or in thought. 

He would have found it, this youthful 
Anacharsis, hard to get there, partly through the 
nature of the country, in part because the people 
of Lacedemon (it was a point of system with 
them, as we heard just now) were suspicious of 

202 


LACEDA MON 


foreigners. Romantic dealers in political theory 
at Athens were safe in saying pretty much what 
they pleased about its domestic doings. Still, 
not so far away, made, not in idea and by 
the movements of an abstract argument, the 
mere strokes of a philosophic pen, but solidified 
by constancy of character, fortified anew on 
emergency by heroic deeds, for itself, for the 
whole of Greece, though with such persistent 
hold throughout on an idea, or system of ideas, 
that it might seem actually to have come 
ready-made from the mind of some half-divine 
_Lycurgus, or through him from Apollo himself, 
creator of that music of which it was an example: 
—there, in the hidden valley of the Eurotas, it 
was to be found, as a visible centre of actual 
human life, the place which was alleged to have 
come, harsh paradox as it might sound to Athenian 
ears, within measurable distance of civic per- 
fection, of the political and social ideal. 

Our youthful academic adventurer then, mak- 
ing his way along those difficult roads, between 
the ridges of the Eastern Acadian Mountains, 
and emerging at last into “hollow” Laconia, 
would have found himself in a country carefully 
made the most of by the labour of serfs; a land 
of slavery, far more relentlessly organised accord- 
ing to law than anywhere else in Greece, where, 
in truth, for the most part slavery was a kind 
of accident. But whatever rigours these slaves 
of Laconia were otherwise subjected to, they 
| 203 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


enjoyed certainly that kind of well-being which 
does come of organisation, from the order and 
regularity of system, living under central military 
authority, and bound themselves to military 
service ; to furnish (as under later feudal institu- 
tions) so many efficient men-at-arms on demand, 
and maintain themselves in readiness for war as 
they laboured in those distantly-scattered farms, 
seldom visited by their true masters from Lace- 
demon, whither year by year they sent in kind 
their heavy tribute of oil, barley and wine. The © 
very genius of conservatism here enthroned, — 
secured, we may be sure, to this old-fashioned 
country life something of the personal dignity, 
of the enjoyments also, natural to it ; somewhat 
livelier religious feasts, for example, than their 
lords allowed themselves. Stray echoes of their 
boisterous plebeian mirth on such occasions have 
reached us in Greek literature. 

But if the traveller had penetrated a little 
more closely he would have been told certain 
startling stories, with at least a basis of truth in 
them, even as regards the age of Plato. These 
slaves were Greeks : no rude Scythians, nor crouch- 
ing, decrepit Asiatics, like ordinary prisoners of 
war, the sort of slaves you could buy, but genuine 
Greeks, speaking their native tongue, if with less 
of muscular tension and energy, yet probably with 
pleasanter voice and accent than their essentially 
highland masters. Physically they throve, under 
something of the same discipline which had made 

204 


LACEDAMON 


those masters the masters also of all Greece. 
_ They saw them now and then—their younger 
lords, brought, under strict tutelage, on those 
long hunting expeditions, one of their so rare 
enjoyments, prescribed for them, as was believed, 
_ by the founder of their polity. But sometimes 
_ (here was the report which made one shudder 
even in broad daylight, in those seemingly 
_reposeful places) sometimes those young nobles 
_ of Lacedemon reached them on a different kind 
of pursuit: came by night, secretly, though by 
no means contrarily to the laws of a state crafty 
as it was determined, to murder them at home, 
or a certain moiety of them; one here or there 
_ perhaps who, with good Achzan blood in his 
| veins, and under a wholesome mode of life, was 
_ grown too tall, or too handsome, or too fruitful 
a father, to feel quite like a slave. Under a sort 
of slavery that makes him strong and beautiful, 
where personal beauty was so greatly prized, his 
_ masters are in fact jealous of him. 


But masters thus hard to others, these Lace- 
demonians, as we know, were the reverse of 
indulgent to themselves. While, as a matter of 
_ theory, power and privilege belonged exclusively 
to the old, to the seniors (οἱ γέροντες, ἡ γερουσία) 
ruling by a council wherein no question might be 
_ discussed, one might only deliver one’s Aye! or 
No! Lacedemon was in truth before all things 
an organised place of discipline, an organised 
205 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


opportunity also, for youth, for the sort of youth 
that knew how to command by serving—a con- 
stant exhibition of youthful courage, youthful 
self-respect, yet above all of true youthful docility; 
youth thus committing itself absolutely, soul and 
body, to a corporate sentiment in its very sports. 
There was a third sort of regulation visits the 
lads of Lacedemon were driven to pay to those 
country places, the vales, the uplands, when, to 
brace youthful stomachs and develope resource, 
they came at stated intervals as a kind of mendi- 
cants or thieves, feet and head uncovered through 
frost and heat, to steal their sustenance, under 


penalties if detected—“a survival,” as anthro- — 


pologists would doubtless prove, pointing out 
collateral illustrations of the same, from a world 
of purely animal courage and keenness. Whips 
and rods used in a kind of monitorial system by 
themselves had a great part in the education of 
these young aristocrats, and, as pain surely must 
do, pain not of bodily disease or wretched accidents, 
but as it were by dignified rules of art, seem to 
have refined them, to have made them observant 
of the minutest direction in those musical exer- 
cises, wherein eye and ear and voice and foot 
all alike combined. There could be nothing 
παραλειπόμενον, aS Plato says, no “oversights,” here. 
No! every one, at every moment, quite at his 
best ; and, observe especially, with no superfluities ; 
seeing that when we have to do with music of 
any kind, with matters of art, in stone, in words, 
206 


Beet δώ τῳ: 


LACEDAMON 


‘in the actions of life, all superfluities are in 
very truth “ superfluities of naughtiness,” such as 
annihilate music. 

_ The country through which our young 
traveller from his laxer school of Athens seeks 
his way to Lacedemon, this land of a noble 
slavery, so peacefully occupied but for those 
irregular nocturnal terrors, was perhaps the 
loveliest in Greece, with that peculiarly blent 
loveliness, in which, as at Florence, the expression 
of a luxurious lowland is duly checked by the 
severity of its mountain barriers. It was a type 
of the Dorian purpose in life—sternness, like sea- 
water infused into wine, overtaking a matter 
naturally rich, at the moment when fulness may 
lose its savour and expression. Amid the corn 
and oleanders—corn “‘so tall, close, and luxuriant,” 
as the modern traveller there still finds—it was 
visible at last, Lacedemon, κοίλη Σπάρτη, “ hollow 
Sparta,” under the sheltering walls of Taygetus, 
'the broken and rugged forms of which were 
attributed to earthquake, but without proper 
walls of itsown. In that natural fastness, or trap, 
or falcon’s nest, it had no need of them, the falcon 
| of the land, with the hamlets (πολίχνια) a hundred 
_and more, dispersed over it, in jealously enforced 
~ seclusion from one another. 

From the first he notes “the antiquated ap- 
pearance” of Lacedemon, by no means a “ grow- 
ing” place, always rebuilding, remodelling itself, 
after the newest fashion, with shapeless suburbs 
207 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


; 
stretching farther and farther on every side of it, : 


grown too large perhaps, as Plato threatens, to 


be a body, a corporate unity, at all: not that, but 
still, and to the last, itself only a great village, aq 


solemn, ancient, mountain village. Even here 


of course there had been movement, some sort οὗ 


progress, if so it is to be called, linking limb to 
limb; but long ago. Originally a union, after 
the manner of early Rome, of perhaps three or four 


neighbouring villages which had never lost their — 
physiognomy, like Rome it occupied a group οὗ 


irregular heights, the outermost roots of Taygetus, 
on the bank of a river or mountain torrent, 


impetuous enough in winter, a series of wide — 
shallows and deep pools in the blazing summer. © 


It was every day however, all the year round, 


that Lacedemonian youth plunged itself in the — 
Eurotas. Hence, from this circumstance of the — 
union there of originally disparate parts, the — 
picturesque and expressive irregularity, had they — 
had time to think it such, of the “city” properly — 
so termed, the one open place or street, High — 
Street, or Corso—Aphetais by name, lined, irregu- — 
larly again, with various religious and other 


monuments. It radiated on all sides into a maz 


coil, an ambush, of narrow crooked lanes, up 
and down, in which attack and defence would 
necessarily be a matter of hand-to-hand fighting. 
In the outskirts lay the citizens’ houses, roomier — 


far than those of Athens, with spacious, walled 
courts, almost in the country. Here, in contrast 
208 


ee ee 


BS Pe ae OP eee, PS 


4 


LACEDAMON 


to the homes of Athens, the legitimate wife had 
ἃ real dignity, the unmarried woman a singular 
freedom. There were no door-knockers: you 
shouted at the outer gate to be let in. Between 
the high walls lanes passed into country roads, 
‘sacred ways to ancient sacro-sanct localities, 
Therapne, Amycle, on this side or that, under 
the shade of mighty plane-trees. 

Plato, as you may remember, gives a hint 
that, like all other visible things, the very trees 
—how they grow—exercise an esthetic influence 
on character. The diligent legislator therefore 
would have his preferences, even in this matter 
‘of the trees under which the citizens of the 
‘Perfect City might sit down to rest. What 
‘trees? you wonder. The olive? the laurel, as if 
wrought in grandiose metal? the cypress? that 
‘came to a wonderful height in Dorian Crete: 
‘the oak? we think it very expressive of strenuous 
‘national character. Well! certainly the plane- 
‘tree for one, characteristic tree of Lacedemon 
‘then and now; a very tranquil and tranquillising 
jobject, spreading its level or gravely curved 
masses on the air as regally as the tree of Lebanon 
itself. A vast grove of such was the distinguish- 
ling mark of Lacedemon in any distant view of 
it; that, and, as at Athens, a colossal image, 
older than the days of Phidias—the Demos of 
Lacedemon, it would seem, towering visibly 
Lbove the people it protected. Below those 
}mighty trees, on an island in their national river, 
P. VI 209 P 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


were the “ playing-fields,” where Lacedemonian 
youth after sacrifice in the Ephebeum delighted 
others rather than itself (no “shirking” was 
allowed) with a sort of football, under rigorous 
self-imposed rules——tearing, biting —a_ sport, 
rougher even than our own, ef méme tres dangereux, 
as our Attic neighbours, the French, say of the 
English game. 

They were orderly enough perforce, the boys, 
the young men, within the city—-seen, but not 
heard, except under regulations, when they made 
the best music in the world. Our visitor from 
Athens when he saw those youthful soldiers, or 
military students, as Xenophon in his pretty 
treatise on the polity of Lacedemon describes, 
walking with downcast eyes, their hands meekly 
hidden in their cloaks, might have thought them 
young monks, had he known of such. 


A little mountain town, however ambitious, 


| 


however successful in its ambition, would hardly | 


be expected to compete with Athens, or Corinth, 
itself a Dorian state, in art-production, yet had 
not only its characteristic preferences in this 
matter, in plastic and literary art, but had also 
many venerable and beautiful buildings to show. 
The Athenian visitor, who is standing now in 
the central space of Lacedemon, notes here, as 
being a trait also of the “Perfect City” of 


academic theory, that precisely because these — 
people find themselves very susceptible to the — 


210 


LACEDA MON 


influences of form and colour and sound, to 
external esthetic influence, but have withal a 
special purpose, a certain strongly conceived dis- 
ciplinary or ethic ideal, that therefore a peculiar 
humour prevails among them, a self-denying 
humour, in regard to these things. Those ancient 
Pelopid princes, from whom the hereditary kings 
of historic Lacedemon, come back from exile into 
their old home, claim to be descended, had had 
their palaces, with a certain Homeric, Asiatic 
splendour, of wrought metal and the like; con- 
siderable relics of which still remained, but as 
public or sacred property now. At the time 
when Plato’s scholar stands before them, the 
houses of these later historic kings—two kings, 
as you remember, always reigning together, in 
some not quite clearly evolved differentiation of 
_ the temporal and spiritual functions—were plain 
_ enough ; the royal doors, when beggar or courtier 
_ approached them, no daintier than Lycurgus had 
prescribed for all true Lacedemonian citizens ; 
' rude, strange things to look at, fashioned only, 
like the ceilings within, with axe and saw, of old 
mountain oak or pine from those great Taygetan 
forests, whence came also the abundant iron, 
which this stern people of iron and steel had 
_ super-induced on that earlier dreamy age of silver 
and gold—steel, however, admirably tempered 
and wrought in its application to military use, 
_and much sought after throughout Greece. 
Layer upon layer, the relics of those earlier 

21ῚΙι 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


generations, a whole succession of remarkable 
races, lay beneath the strenuous footsteps of the 
present occupants, as there was old poetic legend 
in the depths of their seemingly so practical or 
prosaic souls. Nor beneath their feet only : the 
relics of their worship, their sanctuaries, their 
tombs, their very houses, were part of the scenery 
of actual life. Our young Platonic visitor from 
Athens, climbing through those narrow winding 
lanes, and standing at length on the open platform 
of the Aphetais, finds himself surrounded by 
treasures, modest treasures of ancient architecture, — 
dotted irregularly here and there about him, as 
if with conscious design upon picturesque effect, 
such irregularities sometimes carrying in them the 
secret of expression, an accent. Old Alcman for 
one had been alive to the poetic opportunities of 
the place; boasts that he belongs to Lacedemon, 
“‘abounding in sacred tripods” ; that it was here 
the Heliconian Muses had revealed themselves 
to him. If the private abodes even of royalty 
were rude it was only that the splendour of places 
dedicated to religion and the state might the more 
abound. Most splendid of them all, the Stoa 
Pehile, a cloister or portico with painted walls, 
to which the spoils of the Persian war had been ~ 
devoted, ranged its pillars of white marble on one 
side of the central space: on the other, connecting 
those high memories with the task of the living, 
lay the Choros, where, at the Gymnopedia, the 
Spartan youth danced in honour of Apollo. 
212 


LACEDAMON 


Scattered up and down among the monuments 
of victory in battle were the 4eroa, tombs or 
_ chapels of the heroes who had purchased it with 
their blood—Pausanias, Leonidas, brought home 
_ from Thermopyle forty years after his death. 
“A pillar too,” says Pausanias, “‘is erected here, 
| on which the paternal names are inscribed of 
_ those who at Thermopyle sustained the attack of 
_the Medes.” Here in truth all deities put on a 
| martial habit—Aphrodite, the Muses, Eros him- 
self, Athene Chalcicecus, Athene of the Brazen 
_ House, an antique temple towering above the 
rest, built from the spoils of some victory long 
since forgotten. The name of the artist who 
made the image of the tutelary goddess was 
remembered in the annals of early Greek art, 
| Gitiades, a native of Lacedemon. He had com- 
_ posed a hymn also in her praise. Could we have 
seen the place he had restored rather than con- 
| structed, with its covering of mythological reliefs 
in brass or bronze, perhaps Homer’s descriptions 
_ of a seemingly impossible sort of metallic archi- 
_ tecture would have been less taxing to his reader’s 
imagination. Those who in other places had 
lost their taste amid the facile splendours of a 
_ later day, might here go to school again. 

| Throughout Greece, in fact, it was the Doric 
_ style which came to prevail as the religious or 
_hieratic manner, never to be surpassed for that 
| purpose, as the Gothic style seems likely to do 
with us. Though it is not exclusively the in- 
213 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


vention of Dorian men, yet, says Miller, “the 
Dorian character created the Doric architecture,” 
and he notes in it, especially, the severity of the 
perfectly straight, smartly tapering line of its 
column ; the bold projection of the capital; the 
alternation of long unornamented plain surfaces 
with narrower bands of decorated work; the 
profound shadows ; the expression of security, of 
harmony, infused throughout; the magnificent 
pediment crowning the whole, like the cornice 
of mountain wall beyond, around, and above it. 
Standing there in the Aphetais, amid these vener- 
able works of art, the visitor could not forget the 
natural architecture about him. As the Dorian 
genius had differentiated itself from the common 
Hellenic type in the heart of the mountains of 
Epirus, so here at last, in its final and most 
characteristic home, it was still surrounded by 
them ἱ---ὐὀφρυᾷ τε καὶ κοιλαίνεται. 

We know, some of us, what such mountain 
neighbourhood means. ‘The wholesome vigour, 
the clearness and purity they maintain in matters 
such as air, light, water; how their presence 
multiplies the contrasts, the element of light and 
shadow, in things; the untouched perfection of 
the minuter ornament, flower or crystal, they 
permit one sparingly ; their reproachful aloof- 
ness, though so close to us, keeping sensitive 
minds at least in a sort of moral alliance with 
their remoter solitudes. ‘The whole life of 
the Lacedemonian community,” says Miller, 

214 


LACEDAMON 


_ “had a secluded, impenetrable, and secret char- 
acter.” You couldn’t really know it unless you 
were of it. 
| A system which conceived the whole of life 
as matter of attention, patience, a fidelity to 
᾿ς detail, like that of good soldiers and musicians, 
_ could not but tell also on the merest handicrafts, 
_ constituting them in the fullest sense of a cra/Z. 
If the money of Sparta was, or had recently 
been, of cumbrous iron, that was because its 
trade had a sufficient variety of stock to be 
mainly by barter, and we may suppose the 
market (into which, like our own academic 
| youth at Oxford, young Spartans were forbidden 
to go) full enough of business—many a busy 
workshop in those winding lanes. The lower 
arts certainly no true Spartan might practise ; 
but even Helots, artisan Helots, would have 
_ more than was usual elsewhere of that sharpened 
| intelligence and the disciplined hand in such 
- labour which really dignify those who follow it. 
In Athens itself certain Lacedemonian com- 
_ modities were much in demand, things of military 
service or for every-day use, turned out with 
| flawless adaptation to their purpose. 
| The Helots, then, to whom this business 
exclusively belonged, a race of slaves, dis- 
) tinguishable however from the slaves or serfs 
' who tilled the land, handing on their mastery 


) in those matters in a kind of guild, father to 


son, through old-established families of flute- 
| 215 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


players, wine-mixers, bakers, and the like, thus 


left their hereditary lords, Les Gens Fleur-de-lses 
(to borrow an expression from French feudalism) 
in unbroken leisure, to perfect themselves for 
the proper functions of gentlemen—cyors, leisure, 
in the two senses of the word, which in truth 
involve one another—their whole time free, to 
be told out in austere schools. Long easeful 
nights, with more than enough to eat and drink, 
the “‘illiberal” pleasures of appetite, as Aristotle 
and Plato agree in thinking them, are of course 
the appropriate reward or remedy of those who 
work painfully with their hands, and seem to 
have been freely conceded to those Helots, who 
by concession of the State, from first to last their 
legal owner, were in domestic service, and some- 
times much petted in the house, though by no 
means freely conceded to the “ golden youth” of 
Lacedemon—youth of gold, or gilded steel. 
The traditional Helot, drunk perforce to disgust 
his young master with the coarseness of vice, is 
probably a fable; and there are other stories 
full of a touching spirit of natural service, of 
submissiveness, of an instinctively loyal admira- 
tion for the brilliant qualities of one trained 
perhaps to despise him, by which the servitor 


must have become, in his measure, actually a : 


sharer in them. Just here, for once, we see that 

slavish ἦθος, the servile range of sentiment, which 

ought to accompany the condition of slavery, if 

it be indeed, as Aristotle supposes, one of the 
216 


LACEDAMON 


natural relationships between man and man, 
idealised, or esthetically right, pleasant and 
proper; the ἀρετή, or “best possible condition,” 
οὗ the young servitor as such, including a sort of 
bodily worship, and a willingness to share the 
keen discipline which had developed the so 
attractive gallantry of his youthful lords. 


A great wave, successive waves, of invasion, 
sufficiently remote to have lost already all 
historic truth of detail, had left them—these 
_Helots, and the Pericci, in the country round 
_about—thus to serve among their own kinsmen, 
though so close to them in lineage, so much on 
a level with their masters in essential physical 
qualities that to the last they could never be 
entirely subdued in spirit. Patient modern 
research, following the track of a deep-rooted 
national tradition veiled in the mythological 
figments which centre in what is called “ The 
Return of the Heraclidz,” reveals those northern 
immigrants or invaders, at various points on 
their way, dominant all along it, from a certain 
deep vale in the heart of the mountains of 
Epirus southwards, gradually through zone after 
zone of more temperate lowland, to reach their 
perfection, highlanders from first to last, in this 
mountain “ hollow ” of Lacedemon. They claim 
supremacy, not as Dorian invaders, but as kins- 
men of the old Achzan princes of the land; yet 
it was to the fact of conquest, to the necessity of 
217 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


maintaining a position so strained, like that, as 
Aristotle expressly pointed out, of a beleaguered 
encampment in an enemy’s territory, that the 
singular institutions of Lacedemon, the half- 
military, half-monastic spirit, which prevailed 
in this so gravely beautiful place, had been 
originally due. But observe !—Its moral and 
political system, in which that slavery was so 
significant a factor, its discipline, its esthetic and 
other scruples, its peculiar moral ἦθος, having 
long before our Platonic student comes thither 
attained its original and proper ends, survived,— 
there is the point! survived as an end in itself, 
as a matter of sentiment, of public and perhaps 
still more of personal pride, though of the finer, 
the very finest sort, in one word as an ddeal. 
Pericles, as you remember, in his famous vindi- 
cation of the Athenian system, makes his hearers 
understand that the ends of the Lacedemonian 
people might have been attained with less self- 
sacrifice than theirs. But still, there it remained, 
ἡ δίαιτα Awpixj—the genuine Laconism of the 
Lacedzmonians themselves, their traditional con- 
ception of life, with its earnestness, its precision 
and strength, its loyalty to its own type, its 
impassioned completeness ; a spectacle, zesthetic- 
ally, at least, very interesting, like some perfect 
instrument shaping to what they visibly were, 
the most beautiful of all people, in Greece, in 
the world. 

Gymnastic, “ bodily exercise,” of course, does 

218 


LACEDAMON 


not always and necessarily effect the like of that. 
A certain perfectly preserved old Roman mosaic 
pavement in the Lateran Museum, presents a 
terribly fresh picture of the results of another 
sort of “training,” the monstrous development 
_by a cruel art, by exercise, of this or that muscle, 
changing boy or man into a merely mechanic 
instrument with which his breeders might make 
money by amusing the Roman people. Victor 
-Hugo’s odius dream of L’ homme qui rit, must have 
had something of a prototype among those old 
Roman gladiators. The Lacedemonians, says 
Xenophon on the other hand, ὁμοίως ἀπό τε τῶν 
σκελῶν Kal ἀπὸ χειρῶν Kal ἀπὸ τραχήλου γυμνάζονται. 
Here too, that is to say, they aimed at, they 
found, proportion, Pythagorean symmetry or 
‘music, and bold as they could be in their 
exercises (it was a Lacedemonian who, at 
Olympia, for the first time threw aside the 
heavy girdle and ran naked to the goal) forbade 
all that was likely to disfigure the body. 
Though we must not suppose all ties of nature 
rent asunder, nor all connexion between parents 
and children in those genial, retired houses at an 
end in very early life, it was yet a strictly public 
education which began with them betimes, and 
with a very clearly defined programme, con- 
servative of ancient traditional and unwritten 
rules, an aristocratic education for the few, the 
liberales—* liberals,” as we may say, in that the 
‘proper sense of the word. It made them, in 
| 219 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


very deed, the lords, the masters, of those they 
were meant by-and-by to rule ; masters, of their 
very souls, of their imagination, enforcing on 
them an ideal, by a sort of spiritual authority, 
thus backing, or backed by, a very effective 
organisation of “the power of the sword.” In 
speaking of Lacedemon, you see, it comes 
naturally to speak out of proportion, it might 
seem, of its youth, and of the education of its 
outh. But in fact if you enter into the spirit 
of Lacedemonian youth, you may conceive 
Lacedemonian manhood for yourselves. You — 
divine already what the boy, the youth, so late — 
in obtaining his majority, in becoming a man, 
came to be in the action of life, and on the 
battle-field. “In a Doric state,” says Muller, © 
“ education was, on the whole, a matter of more — 
importance than government.” 
A young Lacedemonian, then, of the privi- 
leged class left his home, his tender nurses in 
those large, quiet old suburban houses early, for — 
a public school, a schooling all the stricter as 
years went on, to be followed, even so, by a 
peculiar kind of barrack-life, the temper of which, ~ 
a sort of military monasticism (it must be re- — 
peated) would beset him to the end. Though — 
in the gymnasia of Lacedemon no idle by- 
standers, no—well! Platonic loungers after truth — 
or what not—were permitted, yet we are told, 
neither there nor in Sparta generally, neither 
there nor anywhere else, were the boys permitted — 
220 


LACEDAMON 


to be alone. If a certain love of reserve, of 
seclusion, characterised the Spartan citizen as 
such, it was perhaps the cicatrice of that wrench 
from a soft home into the imperative, inevitable 
_gaze of his fellows, broad, searching, minute, his 
regret for, his desire to regain, moral and mental 
even more than physical ease. And his educa- 
tion continued late; he could seldom think of 
| marriage till the age of thirty. Ethically it 
aimed at the reality, esthetically at the expres- 
sion, of reserved power, and from the first set its 
subject on the thought of his personal dignity, 
οὗ self-command, in the artistic way of a good 
musician, a good soldier. It is noted that “the 
general accent of the Doric dialect has itself the 
character not of question or entreaty, but of 
command or dictation.” The place of deference, 
of obedience, was large in the education of 
_Lacedeamonian youth; and they never com- 
plained. It involved however for the most part, 
/as with ourselves, the government of youth by 
itself; an implicit subordination of the younger 
} to the older, in many degrees. Quite early in 
life, at school, they found that superiors and 
} inferiors, ὅμοιοι and ὑπομείονες, there really were ; 
and their education proceeded with systematic 
boldness on that fact. Eipny, μελλείρην, σιδεύνης, 
and the like—words, titles, which indicate an 
unflinching elaboration of the attitudes of youth- 
ful subordination and command with respon- 
-sibility—-remain as a part of what we might 
221 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


call their “public-school slang.” They ate 
together “‘in their divisions” (ἀγέλαι) on much | 
the same fare every day at a sort of messes; not 
reclined, like Ionians or Asiatics, but like heroes, 
the princely males, in Homer, sitting upright on | 
their wooden benches; were “inspected” fre- 
quently, and by free use of wud voce examination 
“became adepts in presence of mind,” in mental 
readiness and vigour, in the brief mode of speech | 
Plato commends, which took and has kept its — 
name from them; with no warm baths allowed; © 
a daily plunge in their river required. Yes! 
The beauty of these most beautiful of all people 
was a male beauty, far remote from feminine 
tenderness; had the expression of a certain 
ascésis in it; was like un-sweetened wine. In 
comparison with it, beauty of another type 
might seem to be wanting in edge or accent. 
And they could be silent. Of the positive 
uses of the negation of speech, like genuine 
scholars of Pythagoras, the Lacedemonians 
were well aware, gaining strength and intensity 
by repression. Long spaces of enforced silence 
had doubtless something to do with that expres- 
sive brevity of utterance, which could be also, 
when they cared, so inexpressive of what their 
intentions really were—something to do with 
the habit of mind to which such speaking would ~ 
come naturally. In contrast with the ceaseless — 
prattle of Athens, Lacedemonian assemblies lasted 
as short a time as possible, all standing. A 
222 


LACEDAMON 


_Lacedemonian ambassador being asked in whose 
name he was come, replies: “In the name of 
the State, if I succeed; if I fail, in my own.” 
What they lost in extension they gained in 
_ depth. 


Had our traveller been tempted to ask a 
young Lacedemonian to return his visit at Athens, _ 


permission would have been refused him. He 
belonged to a community bent above all things 


on keeping indelibly its own proper colour. Its 


more strictly mental education centered, in fact, 
upon a faithful training of the memory, again in 


the spirit of Pythagoras, in regard to what seemed 
best worth remembering. Hard and practical as 
Lacedemonians might seem, they lived neverthe- 
less very much by imagination ; and to train the 
memory, to preoccupy their minds with the past, 
as in our own classic or historic culture of youth, 


_ was in reality to develope a vigorous imagination. 


In music (μουσική) as they conceived it, there 


would be no strictly selfish reading, writing or 


listening ; and if there was little a Lacedemonian 
lad had to read or write at all, he had much to 
learn, like a true conservative, by heart: those 
unwritten laws of which the Council of Elders 
was the authorised depositary, and on which the 
whole public procedure of the state depended ; 
the archaic forms of religious worship; the 
names of their kings, of victors in their games or 
in battle ; the brief record of great events ; the 
oracles they had received; the rhetrai, from 
223 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


Lycurgus downwards, composed in metrical Lace- 
demonian Greek ; their history and law, in short, 
actually set to music, by Terpander and others, as 
was said. What the Lacedemonian learned by 
heart he was for the most part to sing, and we 
catch a glimpse, an echo, of their boys in school 
chanting ; one of the things in old Greece one 
would have liked best to see and hear—youth- 
ful beauty and strength in perfect service —a 
manifestation of the true and genuine Hellenism, 
though it may make one think of the novices 
at school in some Gothic cloister, of our own 
old English schools, nay, of the young Lace- 
dzmonian’s cousins at Sion, singing there the law 
and its praises. 

The Platonic student of the ways of the Lace- 
dzemonians observes then, is interested in observ- 
ing, that their education, which indeed makes no 
sharp distinction between mental and _ bodily 
exercise, results as it had begun in “ music ”— 
ends with body, mind, memory above all, at their 
finest, on great show-days, in the dance. Austere, 
self-denying Lacedemon had in fact one of the 
largest theatres in Greece, in part scooped out 
boldly on the hill-side, built partly of enormous 
blocks of stone, the foundations of which may 
still be seen. We read what Plato says in The 
Republic of “imitations,” of the imitative arts, 
imitation reaching of course its largest develop- 
ment on the stage, and are perhaps surprised at 
the importance he assigns, in every department of 

224 


LACEDAMON 


human culture, to a matter of that kind. But 
here as elsewhere to see was to understand. We 
| should have understood Plato’s drift in his long 
criticism and defence of imitative art, his careful 
“system of rules concerning it, caiitd we have 
seen the famous dramatic Lacedemonian dancing. 
They danced a theme, a subject. A complex and 
elaborate art this must necessarily have been, but, 
as we may gather, as concise, direct, economically 
expressive, in all its varied sound and motion, as 
those swift, lightly girt, zmpromptu Lacedemonian 
‘sayings. With no movement of voice or hand or 
foot, παραλειπόμενον, unconsidered, as Plato forbids, 
it was the perfect flower of their correction, of 
that minute patience and care which ends in a 
perfect expressiveness; not a note, a glance, a 
touch, but told obediently in the promotion of a 
firmly grasped mental conception, as in that 
perfect poetry or sculpture or painting, in which 
“the finger of the master is on every part of his 
work.” We have nothing really like it, and to 
comprehend it must remember that, though it 
took place in part at least on the stage of a theatre 
—was in fact a ballet-dance, it had also the 
character both of a liturgical service and of a 
military inspection; and yet, in spite of its 
severity of rule, was a natural expression of the 


delight of all who took part in it. 


So perfect a spectacle the gods themselves 
might be thought pleased to witness; were in 
im P. VI 225 Q 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


consequence presented with it as an important 
element in the religious worship of the Lace- 
demonians, in whose life religion had even a 
larger part than with the other Greeks, con- 
spicuously religious, δεισιδαίμονες, involved in reli-- 
gion or superstition, as the Greeks generally were, 
More closely even than their so scrupulous 
neighbours they associated the state, its acts and 
officers, with a religious sanction, religious usages, 
apa ES traditions. While the responsibilities of 
secular government lay upon the Ephors, those. 
mysteriously dual, at first sight useless, and yet 80. 
sanctimoniously observed kings, “οἵ the house of 
Heracles,” with something of the splendour of the 
old Achzan or Homeric kings, in life as also in 
death, the splendid funerals, the passionate archaic 
laments which then followed them, were in fact 
of spiritual or priestly rank, the living and active 
centre of a poetic religious system, binding them: 
‘“‘in a beneficent connexion” to the past, and in 
the present with special closeness to the oracle of 
Delphi. 

Of that catholic or general centre of Greell 
religion the Lacedemonians were the hereditary 
and privileged guardians, as also the peculiar 
people of Apollo, the god of Delphi; but, 
observe ! of Apollo in a peculiar development of 
his deity. In the dramatic business of Lace- 
demon, centering in these almost liturgical 
dances, there was little comic acting. The 
fondness of the slaves for buffoonery and loud 

226 


LACEDAMON 


laughter, was to their master, who had no taste 
for the like, a reassuring note of his superiority. 
He therefore indulged them in it on occasion, 
and you might fancy that the religion of a people 
‘so strenuous, ever so full of their dignity, must 
) have been a religion of gloom. It was otherwise. 
‘The Lacedemonians, like those monastic persons 
of whom they so often remind one, as a matter 
᾿ of fact however surprising, were a very cheerful 
Hpeople; and the religion of which they had 
}so much, deeply imbued everywhere with an 
Foptimism as of hopeful youth, encouraged that 
disposition, was above all a religion of sanity. 
} The observant Platonic visitor might have taken 
note that something of that purgation of religious 
Hthought and sentiment, of its expression in 
literature, recommended in Plato’s Repub/ic, had 
been already quietly effected here, towards the 
establishment of a kind of cheerful daylight in 
‘men’s tempers. 

_ In furtherance then of such a religion of sanity, 
of that harmony of functions, which is the 
§ Aristotelian definition of health, Apollo, sanest of 
ithe national gods, became also the tribal or home 
Mgod of Lacedemon. That common Greek 
worship of Apollo they made especially their own, 
Pbut (just here is the noticeable point) with a 
marked preference for the human element in him, 
for the mental powers of his being over those 
elemental or physical forces of production, which 
she also mystically represents, and which resulted 
227 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


sometimes in an orgiastic, an unintellectual, or | 
even an immoral service. He remains youthful 
and unmarried. In congruitv with this, it is 
observed that, in a quasi-Roman worship, abstract 
qualities and relationships, ideals, become sub- 
sidiary objects of religious consideration around 
him, such as sleep, death, fear, fortune, laughter 
even. Nay, other gods also are, so to speak, 
Apollinised, adapted to the Apolline presence ; 
Aphrodite armed, Enyalius in fetters, perhaps 
that he may never depart thence. Amateurs 
everywhere of the virile element in life, the 
Lacedemonians, in truth, impart to all things an 
intellectual character. Adding a vigorous logic 
to seemingly animal instincts, for them courage 
itself becomes, as for the strictly philosophic mind 
at Athens, with Plato and Aristotle, an intel- 
lectual condition, a form of right knowledge. 


Such assertion of the consciously human 
interest in a religion based originally on a pre- 
occupation with the unconscious forces of nature, 
was exemplified in the great religious festival of 
Lacedemon. Asa spectator of the Hyacithia, our 
Platonic student would have found himself one of 
a large body of strangers, gathered together from 
Lacedemon and its dependent towns and villages, 
within the ancient precincts of Amycle, at the 
season between spring and summer when under 
the first fierce heat of the year the abundant 
hyacinths fade from the fields. Blue flowers, 


228 


LACEDHAMON 


you remember, are the rarest, to many eyes the 
loveliest; and the Lacedemonians with their guests 
‘were met together to celebrate the death of the 
hapless lad who had lent his name to them, 
Hyacinthus, son of Apollo, or son of an ancient 
mortal king who had reigned in this very place ; 
in either case, greatly beloved of the god, who 
had slain him by sad accident as they played at 
quoits together delightfully, to his immense 
sorrow. That Boreas (the north-wind) had 
maliciously miscarried the discus, is a circum- 
‘stance we hardly need to remind us that we have 
here, of course, only one of many transparent, 
unmistakable, parables or symbols of the great 
solar change, so sudden in the south, like the 
story of Proserpine, Adonis, and the like. But 
here, more completely perhaps than in any other 
of those stories, the primary elemental sense had 
obscured itself behind its really tragic analogue in 
human life, behind the figure of the dying youth. 
We know little of the details of the feast; 
incidentally, that Apollo was vested on the 
occasion in a purple robe, brought in ceremony 
from Lacedemon, woven there, Pausanias tells us, 
in a certain house called from that circumstance 
Chiton. You may remember how sparing these 
Lacedemonians were of such dyed raiment, of any 
but the natural and virgin colouring of the fleece ; 
that purple or red, however, was the colour of 
their royal funerals, as indeed Amycle itself was 
famous for purple stuffs—<Amyclee vesies. As 
229 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


the general order of the feast, we discern clearly 
a single day of somewhat shrill gaiety, between 
two days of significant mourning after the manner 
of All Souls’ Day, directed from mimic grief for 
a mythic object, to a really sorrowful com- 
memoration by the whole Lacedemonian people 
—each separate family for its own deceased 
members. 

It was so again with those other youthful 
demi-gods, the Dioscuri, themselves also, in old 
heroic time, resident in this venerable place: 
Amycle@i fratres, fraternal leaders of the Lace- 
demonian people. Their statues at this date were 
numerous in Laconia, or the docana, primitive 
symbols of them, those two upright beams of 
wood, carried to battle before the two kings, 
until it happened that through their secret enmity 
a certain battle was lost, after which one king 
only proceeded to the field, and one part only of 
that token of fraternity, the other remaining at 
Sparta. Well! they were two stars, you know, 
at their original birth in men’s minds, Gemum, 
virginal fresh stars of dawn, rising and setting 
alternately—those two half-earthly, half-celestial 
brothers, one of whom, Polydeuces, was immortal. 
The other, Castor, the younger, subject to old 
age and death, had fallen in battle, was found 
breathing his last. Polydeuces thereupon, at his 
own prayer, was permitted to die: with undying 
fraternal affection, had forgone one moiety of his 
privilege, and lay in the grave for a day in his 

230 


LACEDAMON 


brother’s stead, but shone out again on the 
morrow; the brothers thus ever coming and 
_ going, interchangeably, but both alike gifted now 
_ with immortal youth. 

In their origin, then, very obviously elemental 
deities, they were thus become almost wholly 
humanised, fraternised with the Lacedemonian 
_ people, their closest friends of the whole celestial 
company, visitors, as fond legend told, at their 
_very hearths, found warming themselves in the 
half-light at their rude fire-sides. ‘Themselves 
_ thus visible on occasion, at all times in devout art, 
_ they were the starry patrons of all that youth was 
proud of, delighted in, horsemanship, games, 
battle ; and always with that profound fraternal 
sentiment. Brothers, comrades, who could not 
live without each other, they were the most 
fitting patrons of a place in which friendship, 
comradeship, like theirs, came to so much. 
Lovers of youth they remained, those enstarred 
types of it, arrested thus at that moment of 
_ miraculous good fortune as a consecration of the 
clean, youthful friendship, “‘ passing even the love 
of woman,” which, by system, and under the 
sanction of their founder’s name, elaborated into 
a kind of art, became an elementary part of 
education. A part of their duty and discipline, 
it was also their great solace and encouragement. 
_ The beloved and the lover, side by side through 
their long days of eager labour, and above all on 
_ the battlefield, became respectively, dirns, the 

231 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


hearer, and εἰσπνήλας, the inspirer; the elder 


inspiring the younger with his own strength and 
noble taste in things. 


What, it has been asked, what was there to — 
occupy persons of the privileged class in Lace-_ 
demon from morning to night, thus cut off as __ 
they were from politics and business, and many — 
of the common interests of men’s lives? Our | 
Platonic visitor would have asked rather, Why © 
this strenuous task-work, day after day ; why this — 
loyalty to a system, so costly to you individually, — 


though it may be thought to have survived its 
original purpose; this laborious, endless, educa- 
tion, which does not propose to give you anything 


very useful or enjoyable in itself? An intelligent — 


young Spartan might have replied: “Τὸ the end 
that I myself may be a perfect work of art, issu- 
ing thus into the eyes of all Greece.” He might 
have observed—we may safely observe for him— 
that the institutions of his country, whose he was, 
had a beauty in themselves, as we may observe 
also of some at least of our own institutions, 
educational or religious: that they bring out, 


for instance, the lights and shadows of human — 


character, and relieve the present by maintaining 
in it an ideal sense of the past. He might have 
added that he had his friendships to solace him ; 
and to encourage him, the sense of honour. 


Honour, friendship, loyalty to the ideal of the 


232 


LACEDAMON 


past, himself as a work of art! There was 
much of course in his answer. Yet still, after 
all, to understand, to be capable of, such motives, 
was itself but a result of that exacting discipline 
of character we are trying to account for; and 
the question still recurs, To what purpose ? 
Why, with no prospect of Israel’s reward, are 
_ you as scrupulous, minute, self-taxing, as he? 
_A tincture of asceticism in the Lacedemonian 
rule may remind us again of the monasticism of 
the Middle Ages. But then, monastic severity 
_ was for the purging of a troubled conscience, or 
for the hope of an immense prize, neither of 
which conditions is to be supposed here. In 
fact the surprise of Saint Paul, as a practical 
man, at the slightness of the reward for which 
a Greek spent himself, natural as it is about all 
pagan perfection, is especially applicable about 
_ these Lacedemonians, who indeed had actually 
invented that so “corruptible” and essentially 
_ worthless parsley crown in place of the more 
tangible prizes of an earlier age. Strange 
people! Where, precisely, may be the spring 
of action in you, who are so severe to yourselves ; 
you who, in the words of Plato’s supposed 
objector that the rulers of the ideal state are not 
to be envied, have nothing you can really call 
your own, but are like hired servants in your 
own houses,—gui manducatis panem doloris ὃ 


Another day-dream, you may say, about those 
233 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


obscure ancient people, it was ever so difficult — 
really to know, who had hidden their actual life 
with so much success; but certainly a quite 
natural dream upon the paradoxical things we © 
are told of them, on good authority. It is — 
because they make us ask that question ; puzzle — 
us by a paradoxical idealism in life; are thus — 
distinguished from their neighbours ; that, like — 
some of our old English places of education, — 
though we might not care to live always αἴ 
school there, it is good to visit them on occasion ; _ 
as some philosophic Athenians, as we have now — 
seen, loved to do, at least in thought. 


234 


IX 


THE REPUBLIC 


“THE Republic,” as we may realise it mentally 
within the limited proportions of some quite 
imaginable Greek city, is the protest of Plato, in 
enduring stone, in law and custom more im- 
perishable still, against the principle of flam- 
boyancy or fluidity in things, and in men’s 
thoughts about them. Political “ideals” may 
provide not only types for new states, but also, 
in humbler function, a due corrective of the 
errors, thus renewing the life, of old ones. But 
like other medicines the corrective or critical 
ideal may come too late, too near the natural 
end of things. The theoretic attempt made by 
Plato to arrest the process of disintegration in 
the life of Athens, of Greece, by forcing it back 
upon a simpler and more strictly Hellenic type, 
ended, so far as they were concerned, in theory. 


It comes of Plato’s literary skill, his really 
dramatic handling of a conversation, that one 
subject rises naturally out of another in the 

235 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


course of it, that in the lengthy span of The q 
Republic, though they are linked together after — 
all with a true logical coherency, now justice, 
now the ideal state, now the analysis of the 
individual soul, or the nature of a true philo- 


sopher, or his right education, or the law of i | 
political change, may seem to emerge as the _ 


proper subject of the whole book. It is thus 
incidentally, and by way of setting forth the 
definition of Justice or Rightness, as if in big © 
letters, that the constitution of the typically 
Right State is introduced into what, according — 


to one of its traditional titles—tIep) Δικαιοσύνης--- ὦ 


might actually have figured as a dialogue on the © 


nature of Justice. But τόδ᾽ ἣν ὡς ἔοικε προοίμιον---- 


the discussion of the theory of the abstract and 1 
invisible rightness was but to introduce the — 
practical architect, the creator of the right state. 


\ Plato then assumes rather than demonstrates that Ι β 
‘so facile parallel between the individual con- — 
' sciousness and the social aggregate, passes lightly 


| backwards and forwards from the rightness or — 
_wrongness, the normal or abnormal conditions, — 
of the one to those of the other, from you and ᾿ 
_me to the “colossal man,’ > whose good or bad — 
| qualities, being written up there on a larger © 
Beas, are easier to read, and if one may Say 80, 
“once in bricks and mortar,” though but on — 
‘paper, is lavish of a world as it should be. A 
strange world in some ways! Let us look from ~ 
the small type of the individual to the monu- 
236 


THE REPUBLIC 


mental inscription on those high walls, as he 
proposes; while his fancy wandering further 
and further, over tower and temple, its streets 
and the people in them, as if forgetful of his 
original purpose he tells us all he sees in thought 
of the City of the Perfect. 

᾿ To the view of Plato, as of all other Greek 
_ citizens, the state, in its local habitation here or 
there, had been in all cases the gift or ordinance 
_ of one or another real though half-divine founder, 
some Solon or Lycurgus, thereafter a proper 
object of piety, of filial piety, for ever, among 
_ those to whom he had bequeathed the blessings 
of civilised life. Himself actually of Solon’s 
lineage, Plato certainly is less aware than those 
_ who study these matters in the “ historic spirit ” 
_ of the modern world that for the most part, like , 
other more purely physical things, states “are 
/ not made, but grow.” Yet his own work as δ᾽ 
designer or architect of what shall be new is 
| developed quite naturally out of the question 
_ how an already existing state, such as the actual 
_ Athens of the day, might secure its pre-eminence, 
or its very existence. Close always, by the 
| concrete turn of his genius, to the facts of the 
_ place and the hour, his first thought is to suggest 
| a remedy for the peculiar evils of the Athenians 
αἵ that moment; and in his delineation of the 
_ ideal state he does but elevate what Athens in 
| particular, a ship so early going to pieces, might 
_ well be forced to become for her salvation, were 
237 


DO oe) 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


it still possible, into the eternal type of veritable 


statecraft, of a city as such, “a city at unity in © 
itself,” defiant of time. He seems to be seeking 
in the first instance a remedy for the sick, a 


desperate political remedy; and thereupon, as — 
happens with really philosophic enquirers, the 
view enlarges on all sides around him. 

Those evils of Athens then, which were — 


found in very deed somewhat later to be the ~ 


infirmity of Greece as a whole, when, though its — 
versatile gifts of intellect might constitute it the © 
teacher of its eventual masters, it was found too © 
incoherent politically to hold its own against — 
Rome :—those evils of Athens, of Greece, came — 
from an exaggerated assertion of the fluxional, — 
flamboyant, centrifugal Ionian element in the — 
Hellenic character. They could be cured only 
by a counter-assertion of the centripetal Dorian — 
ideal, as actually seen best at Lacedemon; by 
the way of simplification, of a rigorous imitation 
of all things, of art and life, of the souls, aye, — 
and of the very bodies of men, as being the 
integral factors of all beside. It is in those ~ 


‘simpler, corrected outlines of a reformed Athens — 


that Plato finds the “eternal form” of the State, — 


toe 


_ of a city as such, like a well-knit athlete, or one — 
_of those perfectly disciplined Spartan dancers. 
᾿ His actual purpose therefore is at once reforming 


and conservative. The drift of his charge is, in 
his own words, that no political constitution then 
existing is suitable to the philosophic, that is to 

238 | 


THE REPUBLIC 


say, as he conceives it, to the aristocratic or 
_ kingly nature. How much that means we shall 
866 by and bye, when he maintains that in the 
City of the Perfect the kings will be philo- 
-sophers. It means that those called, like the 
gifted, lost Alcibiades, to be the saviours of the 
state, as a matter of fact become instead its 
destroyers. The proper soil in which alone that 
| precious exotic seed, the kingly or aristocratic 
seed, will attain its proper qualities, in which 
alone it will not yield wine inferior to its best, 
or rather, instead of bearing any wine at all, 
_ become a deadly poison, is still to be laid down 
according to rules of art, the ethic or political 
art; but once provided must be jealously kept 
from innovation. Organic unity with one’s self, 
body and soul, is the well-being, the rightness, 
or righteousness, or justice of the individual, of 
the microcosm ; but is the ideal also, it supplies 
the true definition, of the well-being of the 
macrocosm, of the social organism, the state. 
On this Plato has to insist, to the disadvantage 
of what we actually see in Greece, in Athens, 
with all its intricacies of disunion, faction against 
faction, as displayed in the later books of Thucy- 
dides. Remember ! the question Plato is asking 
throughout The Republic, with a touch perhaps 
of the narrowness, the fanaticism, or “ fixed idea,” 
of Machiavel himself, is, not how shall the state, 
the place we must live in, be gay or rich or 
populous, but strong—strong enough to remain 
239 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


itself, to resist solvent influences within or from 
without, such as would deprive it not merely of 
the accidental notes of prosperity but of its own 
very being. 


Now what hinders this strengthening macro- 
cosmic unity, the oneness of the political 
organism with itself, is that the unit, the indi- 
vidual, the microcosm, fancies itself, or would 
fain be, a rival macrocosm, independent, many- 
sided, all-sufficient. To make him that, as 
you know, had been the conscious aim of the 
Athenian system in the education of its youth, 
as also in its later indirect education of the 
citizen by the way of political life. It was the 
ideal of one side of the Greek character in 
general, of much that was brilliant in it and 
seductive to others. In this sense, Pericles 
himself interprets the educational function of the 
city towards the citizen :—to take him as he is, 
and develope him to the utmost on all his 
various sides, with a variety in those parts how- 
ever, as Plato thinks, by no means likely to 
promote the unity of the whole, of the state as 
such, which must move all together if it is to 
move at all, at least against its foes. With this 
at first sight quite limited purpose then, para- 
doxical as it might seem to those whose very 
ideal lay precisely in such manifold development, 
to Plato himself perhaps, manifold as his own 
genius and culture conspicuously were—para- 

240 


THE REPUBLIC 


doxical as it might seem, Plato’s demand is for the 
limitation, the simplifying, of those constituent 
parts or units; that the unit should be indeed 
no more than a part, it might be a very small 
part, in a community, which needs, if it is still 
to subsist, the wholeness of an army in motion, 
of the stars in their courses, of well-concerted 
music, if you prefer that figure, or, as the 
modern reader might perhaps object, of a 
machine. The design of Plato is to bring back 
{δε Athenian people, the Greeks, to thoughts of 
order, to disinterestedness in their functions, to 
_ that self-concentration of soul on one’s own part, 
that loyal concession of their proper parts to 
others, on which such order depends, to a love 
of it, a sense of its extreme esthetic beauty and 
fitness, according to that indefectible definition 
of Justice, of what is right, TO ἕν πράττειν, TO τὰ 
αὑτοῦ πράττειν, in Opposition, as he thinks, to those 
so fascinating conditions of Injustice, ποικιλία, 
πλεονεξία, πολυπραγμοσύνη, figuring away, as they 
do sometimes, so brilliantly. . 

For Plato would have us understand that men 
are in truth after all naturally much simpler, | 
much more limited in character and capacity, — 
than they seem. Such diversity of parts and Ὁ 
function as is presupposed in his definition of © 
Justice has been fixed by nature itself on human — 
life. The individual, as such, humble as his 
_ proper function may be, is unique in fitness for, 
in a consequent “call” to, that function. We 
P. VI 241 R 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


know how much has been done to educate the 
world, under the supposition that man is a 
creature of very malleable substance, indifferent 
in himself, pretty much what influences may 
make of him. Plato, on the other hand, assures 
us that no one of us “is like another all in all.” — 
Πρῶτον μὲν φύεται ἕκαστος ob πάνυ ὅμοιος ἑκάστῳ, ἀλλὰ 
διαφέρων τὴν φύσιν, ἄλλος ἐπ ἄλλου ἔργου πρᾶξιν.---Βαῖ 
for this, social Justice, according to its eternal 
form or definition, would in fact be nowhere 
applicable. Once for all he formulates clearly 
that important notion of the function, (ἔργον) of a 
thing, or of a person. It is that which he alone 
can do, or he better than any one else. 

That Plato should exaggerate this definiteness 
in men’s natural vocations, thus to be read as it 
were in “ plain figures” upon each, is one of the 


necessities of his position. Effect of nature itself, — 


such inequality between men, this differentiation 
of one from another, is to be further promoted 


by all the cunning of the political art. The — 


counter-assertion of the natural indifference of — 


men, their pliability to circumstance, while it is 
certainly truer to our modern experience, is also 
in itself more hopeful, more congruous with all 


the processes of education. But for Plato the 


natural inequality of men, if it is the natural 


ground of that versatility, (ποικιλία), of the wrong- — 
ness or Injustice he must needs correct, will be 
the natural ground of Justice also, as essentially — 


a unity or harmony enforced on disparate 
242 


THE REPUBLIC 


elements, unity as of an army, or an order of 
-monks, organic, mechanic, liturgical, whichever 
you please to call it; but a kind of music 
certainly, if the founder, the master, of the state, 
for his proper part, can but compose the scattered 
notes. 

Just here then is the original basis of society— 
᾿ γίγνεται τοίνυν ὡς ἐγῴμαι πόλις ἐπειδὴ τυγχάνει ἡμῶν 
ἕκαστος οὐκ αὐτάρκης---αἴ first in its humblest form ; 
simply because one can dig and another spin ; 
yet already with anticipations of The Republic, 
_ of the City of the Perfect, as developed by Plato, 
as indeed also, beyond it, of some still more 
distant system “of the services of angels and 
men in a wonderful order”; for the somewhat 
visionary towers of Plato’s Republic blend of 
course with those of the Cruitas Dez of Augustine. 
Only, though its top may one day “reach 
unto heaven,” it by no means came down 
thence ; but, as Plato conceives, arises out of the 
earth, out of the humblest natural wants. Grote 
was right.—There is a very shrewd matter-of- 
fact utilitarian among the dramatis persone which 
together make up the complex genius of Plato. 
Ποιήσει ὡς ἐγῴώμαι τὴν πόλιν ἡμετέρα xpela.—Society 15 
produced by our physical necessities, our in- 
equality in regard to them :—an inequality in 
three broad divisions of unalterable, incom- 
municable type, of natural species, among men, 
with corresponding differentiation of political 
and social functions: three firmly outlined orders 

243 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


in the state, like three primitive castes, propagat- 
ing, reinforcing, their peculiarities of condition, 
as Plato will propose, by exclusive intermarriage, 
each within itself. As in the class of the artisans 
(of δημιουργοί) Some can make swords best, others 
pitchers, so, on the larger survey, there will be 
found those who can use those swords, or, again, 
think, teach, pray, or lead an army, a whole 
body of swordsmen, best, thus defining within 
impassable barriers three essential species of 
citizenship—the productive class, the military 
order, the governing class thirdly, or spiritual 
order. 

The social system is in fact like the constitu- 
tion of a human being. There are those who 
have capacity, a vocation, to conceive thoughts, 
and rule their brethren by intellectual power. 
Collectively of course they are the mind or 
brain, the mental element, in the social organism. 
There are those secondly, who have by nature 
executive force, who will naturally wear arms, 
the sword in the sheath perhaps, but who will 
also on occasion most certainly draw it. Well, 
these are like the active passions and the ulti- 
mately decisive will in the bosom of man, most 
conspicuous as anger—anger, it may be, resent- 
ment, against known wrong in another or in one’s 
self, the champion of conscience, flinging away 
the scabbard, setting the spear against the foe, 


like a soldier of spirit. They are in a word the © 
conscience, the armed conscience, of the state, © 


244 


THE REPUBLIC 


| nobly bred, sensitive for others and for them- 
selves, informed by the light of reason in their 
natural kings. And then, thirdly, protected, 
controlled, by the thought, the will, above them, 
} like those appetites in you and me, hunger, 
_ thirst, desire, which have been the motive, the 
actual creators, of the material order all around 
us, there will be the “ productive” class, labour- 
ing perfectly in the cornfields, in the vineyards, 
or on the vessels which are to contain corn and 
_ wine, at a thousand handicrafts, every one still 
exquisitely differentiated, according to Plato’s 
rule of right—eis ἕν κατὰ φύσιν; aS within the 
military class also there will be those who com- 
mand and those who can but obey, and within 
the true princely class again those who know all 
things and others who have still much to learn ; 
those also who can learn and teach one sort of 
knowledge better than another. 

Plato however, in the first steps of the evolu- 
tion of the State, had lighted quite naturally on 
what turns out to be a mistaken or inadequate 
ideal of it, in an idyll pretty enough, indeed, 
from “The Golden Age.”—How sufficient it 
seems for a moment, that innocent world ! is, 
nevertheless, actually but a false ideal of human 
society, allowing in fact no place at all for 
Justice; the very terms of which, precisely 
because they involve differentiation of life and 
its functions, are inapplicable to a society, if so 
it may be called, still essentially inorganic. In 

, 245 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


a condition, so rudimentary as to possess no 
opposed parts at all, of course there will be no 
place for disturbance of parts, for proportion or 
disproportion of faculty and function. It is, in 
truth, to a city which has lost its first innocence 
(πόλις ἤδη τρυφῶσα) that we must look for the 
consciousness of Justice and Injustice ; as some 
theologians or philosophers have held that it 
was by the “Fall” man first became a really 
moral being. 

Now in such a city, in the πόλις ἤδη τρυφῶσα, 
there will be an increase of population :--καὶ ἡ 


χώρα που ἡ τότε ἱκανὴ σμικρὰ ἐξ ἱκανῆς ἔστα. And in © 


an age which perhaps had the military spirit in 
excess Plato’s thoughts pass on immediately to 
wars of aggression :—otxow τῆς τῶν πλησίον χώρας 
ἡμῖν ἀποτμητέννδὺ We must take something, if 
we can, from Megara or from Sparta; which 
doubtless in its turn would do the same by us. 
As a measure of relief however that was not 
necessarily the next step. The needs of an out- 
pushing population might have suggested to 
Plato what is perhaps the most brilliant and 
animating episode in the entire history of Greece, 
its early colonisation, with all the bright stories, 
full of the piety, the generosity of a youthful 
people, that had gathered about it. No, the 
next step in social development was not neces- 
sarily going to war. In either case however, 
aggressive action against our neighbours, or 
defence of our distant brethren beyond the seas 
246 


Mii δε σον δες 


THE REPUBLIC 


at Cyrene or Syracuse against rival adventurers, 
we shall require a new class of persons, men 
of the sword, to fight for us if need be. Ah! 
You hear the notes of the trumpet, and there- 
with already the stir of an enlarging human 
life, its passions, its manifold interests. Φύλακες 
Or ἐπίκουροι, Watchmen or auxiliaries, our new 
servants comprehend at first our masters to be, 
whom a further act of differentiation will dis- 
tinguish as philosophers and kings from the 
strictly military order. Plato nevertheless in 
his search for the true idea of Justice, of right- 
ness in things, may be said now to have seen 
land. Organic relationship is come into the 
rude social elements and made of them a body, 
a society. Rudimentary though it may still be, 
the definition of Justice, as also of Injustice, is 
now applicable to its processes. There is a 
music in the affairs of men, in which one may 
take one’s due part, which one may spoil. 
Criticising mythology Plato speaks of certain 
fables, to be made by those who are apt at such 
things, under proper spiritual authority, so to 
term it, ὡς ἐν φαρμάκου εἴδει τὰ ψευδῆ τὰ ἐν δέοντι 
γενόμενα, Medicinable lies or fictions, with ἃ pro- 
visional or economised truth in them, set forth 
under such terms as simple souls could best 
receive. Just here, at the end of the third book 
of The Republic he introduces such a fable: 
φοινικικὸν ψεῦδος, he calls it, a miner’s story, about 
copper and silver and gold, such as may really 
247 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


have been current among the primitive inhabit- 
ants of the island from which metal and the 
art of working it had been introduced into 
Greece.— 


And I shall try first of all to persuade the rulers themselves 
and our soldiers, and afterwards the rest of the community, as 
to the matter of the rearing and the education we gave them, 
that in fact it did but seem to happen with them, they seemed 
to experience all that, only as in dreams. ‘They were then in 
very truth nourished and fashioned beneath the earth within, 
and the armour upon them and their equipment put together ; 
and when they were perfectly wrought out the earth even their 
mother put them forth. Now, therefore, it is their duty to 
think concerning the land-in-which they are as of a mother, or 
foster-mother, and to protect it if any foe come against it, and 
to think of their fellow-citizens as being their brothers, born 
of the earth as they. All ye in the city, therefore, are brothers, 
we shall say to them proceeding with our story 5 but God, 
when he made you, mixed gold in the generation of those 
among you fit to be our kings, for which cause they are the 
most precious of all; and silver in those fit to be our guards ; 
and in the husbandmen and all other handicraftsmen iron and 
brass. Forasmuch then as ye are all of one kindred, for the 
most part ye would beget offspring like to yourselves ; but at 
times a silver child will come of one golden, and from the silver 
a child of gold, and so forth, interchangeably. ‘To those who 
rule, then, first and above all God enjoins that of nothing shall 
they be so careful guardians, nothing shall they so earnestly 
regard, as the young children—what metal has been mixed to 
their hands in the souls of these. And if a child of their own 
be born with an alloy of iron or brass, they shall by no means 
have pity upon it, but, allotting unto it the value which befits 
its nature, they shall thrust it into the class of husbandmen or 
artisans. And if, again, of these a child be born with gold or 
silver in him, with due estimate they shall promote such to 
wardenship or to arms, inasmuch as an oracular saying declares 
that the city is perished already when it has iron or brass to 
guard it. Can you suggest a way of getting them to believe 
this mythus? Republic, 414. 

248 


Se ee ae Ὁ 


THE REPUBLIC 


Its application certainly is on the surface: 
the Lacedemonian details also—the military turn 
_ taken, the disinterestedness of the powerful, their 
monastic renunciation of what the world prizes 
_ most, above all the doctrine of a natural aristocracy 
with its “ privileges and also its duties.””’ Men 
_are of simpler structure and capacities than you 
have fancied, Plato would assure us, and more 
decisively appointed to this rather than to that 
order of service. Nay, with the boldness proper 
to an idealist, he does not hesitate to represent 
them (that is the force of the mythus) as actually 
made of different stuff; and society, assuming a 
certain aristocratic humour in the nature of 
things, has for its business to sanction, safeguard, 
further promote it, by law. 


The state therefore, if it is to be really a living 
creature, will have, like the individual soul, those 
sensuous appetites which call the productive 
powers into action, and its armed conscience, and 
its far-reaching intellectual light: its industrial 
class, that is to say, its soldiers, its kings—the 
last, a kind of military monks, as you might 
think, on a distant view, their minds full of a 
‘kind of heavenly effulgence, yet superintending 
the labours of a large body of work-people in the 
town and the fields about it. Of the industrial 
or productive class, the artists and artisans, Plato 
speaks only in outline, but is significant in what 
he says; and enough remains of the actual fruits 

249 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


of Greek industry to enable us to complete his — 
outline for ourselves, as we may also, by aid of 
Greek art, together with the words of Homer ~ 
and Pindar, equip and realise the full character of 
the true Platonic “‘war-man” or knight; and Ἶ 
again, through some later approximate instances, — 
discern something of those extraordinary, half-_ 
divine, philosophic kings. 

We must let industry then mean for Plato all 
it meant, would naturally mean, for a Greek, © 
amid the busy spectacle of Athenian handicrafts. — 
The “rule” of Plato, its precepts of temperance, — 
proportion, economy, though designed primarily — 
for its soldiers, and its kings or archons, for the © 
military and spiritual orders, would probably ᾿ 
have been incumbent also in relaxed degree upon ~ 
those who work with their hands ; and we have © 
but to walk through the classical department ~ 
of the Louvre or the British Museum to be — 
reminded how those qualities of temperance and ~ 
the like did but enhance, could not chill or im-_ 
poverish, the artistic genius of Greek workmen. — 
In proportion to what we know of the minor ~ 
handicrafts of Greece we shall find ourselves able — 
to fill up, as the condition of everyday life in the 
streets of Plato’s City of the Perfect, a picture of — 
happy protected labour, “skilled” to the utmost — 
degree in all its applications. ‘Those who pro-— 
secute it will be allowed, as we may gather, in © 
larger proportion than those who “watch,” in ~ 
silent thought or sword in hand, such animal — 

250 ᾿ 


-- 


THE REPUBLIC 


liberties as seem natural and right, and are not 
really “‘illiberal,” for those who labour all day 
with their bodies, though they too will have on 
them in their service some measure of the com- 
pulsion which shapes the action of our kings and 
soldiers to such effective music. With more or 
less of asceticism, of a “common life,” among 
themselves, they will be the peculiar sphere of 
the virtue of temperance in the State, as being 
the entirely willing subjects of wholesome rule. 

hey represent, as we saw, in the social organism, 
the bodily appetites of the individual, its converse 
with matter, in a perfect correspondence, if all be 
right there, with the conscience and with the 


\reasonable soul in it. Labouring by system at 


the production of perfect swords, perfect lamps, 
perfect poems too, and a perfect coinage, such as 
we know, to enable them the more readily to 
exchange their produce (νόμισμα τῆς ἀλλαγῆς ἕνεκα) 
working perhaps~in guilds and under rules to 
insure perfection in-each. specific..craft, refining 
matter to the last degree, they would.constitute 
the beautiful body of the State, in rightful service, 
like the copper and iron, the bronze and the steel, 
they manipulate so finely, to its beautiful soul— 
to its natural though hereditary aristocracy, its 
*‘ golden” humanity, its kings, in whom Wisdom, 
the light, of a comprehensive Synopsis, indefectibly 
resides, and who, as being not merely its dis- 
cursive or practical reason, but its faculty of con- 
templation likewise, will be also its priests, the 
251 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


medium of its worship, of its intercourse with 


the gods. 


Between them, between that intellectual or 
spiritual order, those novel philosophic kings, 
and the productive class of the artists and artisans, 
moves the military order, as the sensitive armed 
conscience, the -armed—will,..of.the—State, its 
executive power in the fullest.sense of that term 

“standing army,” as Plato supposes, recruited 
sa a great hereditary caste born and -bred.t 


such functions, and certainly very different from i 
the mere “militia” of actual Greek states, @ 


hastily summoned at need to military service 
from the fields and workshops. Remember that 
the veritable bravery also, as the philosopher 
sees it, is a form of that “ knowledge,” which in 


truth includes in itself all other virtues, all good i 


things whatever ; that it is a form of “ right _ 
opinion,” and has a kind of insight in it, a real 
apprehension of the occasion and its claims 
on one’s courage, whether it is worth while to 
fight, and to what point. Platonic knighthood 
then will have in it something of the philosophy 
which resides in plenitude in the class above it, 


by which indeed this armed conscience of the 


State, the military order, is continuously en- 

lightened, as we know the conscience of each one 

of us severally needs to be. And though Plato 

will not expect his fighting-men, like the 

Christian knight, like Saint Ranieri Gualberto, 
252 


THE REPUBLIC 


_ to forgive their enemies, yet, moving one degree 
out of the narrower circle of Greek habits, he 
_ does require them, in conformity with a certain 
_ Pan-Hellenic, a now fully realised national sense, 
_ which fills himself, to love the whole Greek race, 
_ to spare the foe, if he be Greek, the last horrors 
οὗ war, to think of the soil, of the dead, of the 
arms and armour taken from them, with certain 
_ scruples of a natural piety. 

_ Asthe knights share the dignity of the regal 
_ order, are in fact ultimately distinguished from 
it by degree rather than in kind, so they will 
be sharers also in its self-denying‘‘rule.” In 
common with it, they will observe a singular 
precept which forbids them so much as to come 
under the same roof with vessels-or-other-objects 
wrought of_gold—or-silver—they “who are most 
worthy of it,” precisely because while “many 
iniquities have come from the world’s coinage, 
they have gold in them undefiled.” Yet again 
we are not to suppose in Platonic Greece—how 
could we indeed anywhere within the range of 
Greek conceptions '—anything rude, uncomely, 
or unadorned. No one who reads carefully in 
this very book of The Republic those pages of 
criticism which concern art quite as much as 
poetry, a criticism which drives everywhere at a 
conscientious nicety of workmanship, will suppose 
that. If kings and knights never drink from 
vessels of silver or gold, their earthen cups and 
platters, we may be sure, would be what we can 

253 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


still see; and the iron armour on their bodies 
exquisitely fitted to them, to its purpose, with 
that peculiar beauty which such fitness secures. 
See them, then, moving, in perfect “‘ Justice” or 
“Rightness,” to their Dorian music, their so 
expressive plain-song, under the guidance of their 
natural leaders, those who can see and fore-see— 
of those who know. 

That they may be one !—TIf, like an individual 
soul, the state has attained its normal differentia- 


tion of parts, as with that also its vitality and — 
_ effectiveness will be proportionate to the unity οὗ 


those parts in their various single operations. 
~The productive, the executive, the contemplative 
orders, respectively, like their psychological 
analogues, the senses, the will, and the intelli- 
gence, will be susceptible each of its own proper 
virtue or excellence, temperance, bravery, spiritual 
illumination. Only, let each work aright in its 
own order, and a fourth virtue will supervene 
upon their united perfections, the virtue or 
perfection of the organic whole as such. The 
Justice which Plato has been so long in search of 
will be manifest at last—that perfect οἰκειοπραγία, 


which will be also perfect co-operation. One- 


ness, unity, community, an absolute communit 
of interests among fellow-citizens, phi/ade/phia, 
over against the selfish ambition of those natur- 
ally ascendant, like Alcibiades or Crito, in that 


competition for office, for wealth and honours, — 


which has rent Athens into factions ever breeding 
254 


THE REPUBLIC 


on themselves, the centripetal force versus all 
centrifugal forces :—on this situation, Plato, in 
the central books of The Republic, dwells untired, 
in all its variety of synonym and epithet, the 
_ conditions, the hazard and difficulty of its realisa- 
tion, its analogies in art, in music; in practical 
life, like three strings ‘of a lyre, or like one 
colossal person, the painted δῆμος or civic genius 
on the walls of a Greek town-house, or, again, 
like the consummate athlete whose body, with 
no superfluities, is the precise, the perfectly 
finished, instrument of his will. Hence, at once 
cause and effect of such “seamless” unity, his 
paradoxical new law of property in the City of 
the Perfect—mandatum novum, a“ new command- 
ment,” we might fairly call it—7ra τῶν φίλων κοινά. 
“ And no one said that aught of the things he 
possessed was his own but they had all things 
common.” Ah, you see! Put yourself in 
Plato’s company, and inevitably, from time to 
time, he will seem to pass with you beyond the 
utmost horizon actually opened to him. 

Upon the aristocratic class therefore, in its two 
divisions, the army and the church or hierarchy, 
so to speak, the “rule” of Plato— poverty, 
obedience, contemplation, will be incumbent in 
its fullest rigour. ‘‘ Like hired servants in their 
own house,” they may not seem very enviable 
persons, on first thoughts. But remember again 
that Plato’s charge against things as they are is 
partly in a theoretic interest—the philosopher, 

255 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


the philosophic soul, loves unity, but finds it 


nowhere, neither in the State nor in its individual 
members: it is partly also practical, and of the 


hour. Divided Athens, divided Greece, like 


some big, lax, self-neglectful person would be an 


easy prey to any well-knit adversary really at — 
unity in himself. It is by way of introducing a — 
constringent principal into a mass of amorphic © 
particles, that Plato proclaims that these friends — 
will have-all things in common ; and, challenged — 

P his companions in the dialogue 
to say how far he will be ready to go in the _ 
application of so paradoxical a rule, he braces | 
himself to a surprising degree of consistency. © 
How far then will Plato, a somewhat Machia- © 
velian theorist, as you saw, and with something 
of “fixed” ideas about practical things, taking — 
desperate means towards a somewhat exclusively © 
conceived ideal of social well-being, be ready — 


by the questions o 


to go? 


256 


Now we have seen that the genuine citizens of — 
his Perfect City will have much of monasticism, — 
of the character of military monks, about them ~ 
already, with their poverty, their obedience, their — 
contemplative habit. And there is yet another — 
indispensable condition of the monastic life. The — 
great Pope Hildebrand, by the rule of celibacy, ~ 
by making “regulars” to that extent of the — 
secular clergy, succeeded, as many have thought, — 
in his design of making them in very deed, soul — 
and body, but parts of the corporate order they 


ἃ 2 a oe ϑς 2S ὧν δον 


ona 


petite te IS 


ee π᾿ 
ee δος, 


eee Pa 


THE REPUBLIC 


belonged to; and what Plato is going to add to 
his rule of life, for the ἄρχοντες, who are to be 
φιλοπόλιδες, to love the corporate body they 
belong to better than themselves, is in its actual 
Jeffects something very like a law of celibacy. 
Difficult, paradoxical, as he admits it to be, he is 
pressed on by his hearers, and by the natural 
force of his argument, reluctantly to declare that 
the rule of communism~-will-apply~to~a man’s 
ownership of his wife and children. 


Observe ! Plato proposes this singular modifica- 
tion of married life as an elevatron-or_expansion 
of the family, but, it may be rightly objected, is, 
in truth, only colouring with names exclusively 
appropriate to the family, arrangements which 
will be a suppression of all those sentiments that 
naturally pertain to it. The wisdom of Plato 
would certainly deprive mothers of that privacy 
of affection, regarding which the wisdom of 
Solomon beamed forth, by sending all infants 
soon after birth to be reared-in..a common 
nursery, where the facts of their actual parentage 
would be carefully obliterated. The result, as he 
supposes, will be a common and universal parent- 
age, sonship, brotherhood ; but surely with but 
ΓΑ shadowy realisation of the affections, the claims, 
of these relationships. It will involve a loss of 
) differentiation in life, and be, as such, a movement 
backward, to a barbarous or merely animal grade 
of existence. 

P. VI 257 5 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


Ta τῶν φίλων xowd.—With this soft phrase, 
then, Plato would take away all those precious 
differences that come of our having a little space — 
in things to do what one will or can with. The — 
Platonic state in fact, with its extraordinary 
common marriages, would be dealing precisely — 
after the manner of those who breed birds or — 
dogs. A strange forbidding experiment, it seems, — 
or should seem, to us, looking back on it in the — 
light of laws now irrevocably fixed on these 
subjects by the judgment of the Christian 
church. We must remember however, in fair- " 
ness, that Plato in this matter of the relation of — 
the sexes especially, found himself in a world 
very different from ours, regulated and refined, as Ἶ 
it already is in some degree, by Christian ideas i 
about women and children. A loose law of 
marriage, beyond it concubinage in some degree 
sanctioned by religion, beyond that again morbid — 
vice : such was the condition of the Greek world. © 
What Christian marriage, in harmonious action 
with man’s true nature, has done to counteract — 
this condition, that Plato tried to do by a some- — 
what forced legislation, which was altogether out 
of harmony with the facts of man’s πατοῦν 
Neither the church nor the world has endorsed 
his theories about it. Think, in contrast, of the ] 

᾿ 
| 
. 
‘ 


te ge στ ξὺν» τὸ 


place occupied in Christian art by the mother 
and her child. What that represents in life Plato 
wishes to take from us, though, as he would have 
us think, in our own behalf, 

258 


THE REPUBLIC 


And his views of the community of male and 
female education, and of the functions of men 
and women in the State, do but come of the 
relief of women in large measure from home- 
duties. Such duties becoming a carefully 
economised department of the State, the women 
will have leisure to share the-werk-of-men ; and 
will need a corresponding education. ‘The details 
of their commen-tifé in peace and war he 
certainly makes effective and bright. But if we 
think of his proposal as a reinstatement of the 
Amazon we have in effect condemned it. For 
the Amazon of mythology and art is but a 
survival from a _ half-animal world, which 
Theseus, the embodiment of adult reason, had 
long since overcome. 

Plato himself divides this confessedly so 
difficult question into two: Is the thing good? 
and in the second place, Is it possible? Let us 
admit that at that particular crisis, or even 
generally, what he proposes is for the best. 
Thereupon the question which suggested itself 
in regard to the community of goods recurs with 
double force: Where may lie the secret of the 
magnanimity (that is the term to hold by) which 
will make wealth and office, with all their 
opportunities for puissant wills, no motive in life 
at all? Is it possible, and under what conditions 
—this disinterestedness on the part of those who 
might do what they will as with their own, this 
indifference, this surrender, not of one’s goods and 

259 


| 
| 


PLATO AND PLATONISM | 


time only, but of one’s last resource, one’s very — 
home, for “the greatest happiness of the greatest — 
number.”—Those are almost the exact words of 
Plato. How shall those who might be egotists 
on the scale of an Alcibiades or an Alexander be 
kept to this strange “new mandate” of altruism ? 
How shall a paradox so bold be brought within the © 
range of possibilities? Well! by the realisation - 
of another paradox,—if we make philosophers our _ 
kings or our kings philosophers. It is the last 
“wave of paradox,” from the advancing crest of 
which Plato still shrinks back, oddly reluctant, — 
as we may think, to utter his whole mind. But, 
concede his position, and all beside, in the 
strange, paradoxical new world he is constructing, 
its extraordinary reaches of philadelphia, will be 
found practicable. 

Our kings must be philosophers. But not, we 
must carefully note, because, as people are apt to 
fancy, philosophers as such necessarily despise or 
are unable to feel what is fascinating in the world 
of action, are un-formed or withered on one side, 
and, as regards the allurements of the world of 
sense, are but “corpses.” For Plato certainly 
they are no starvelings. The philosophic, or 
aristocratic, or kingly, nature, as he conceives it, 
will be the perfect flower of the whole compass 
of natural endowments, promoted to the utmost 
by the artificial influences of society-—xaroxayabds 
—capable therefore in the extreme degree of 
success in a purely “self-regarding ” policy, of an 

260 


THE REPUBLIC 


exploitation, in their own interests, of all that 
‘men in general value most, to the surfeiting, if 
they cared, of their ambition, their vanity, their 
love of liberty or license. 


Nor again must our kings be philosophers 


| mainly because in such case the world will be 
_very wisely, very knowingly, governed. Of 


course it would be well that wise men should 
rule. Even a Greek, still “a youth in the youth 
of the world,” who indeed was not very far gone 


_ from an essentially youthful evaluation of things, 
_ was still apt to think with Croesus that the richest 
_ must of course be the happiest of men, and to 
have a head-ache when compelled to think, even 


he would have taken so much for granted. That 
it would be well that wise men should govern, 
wise after the Platonic standard, bringing, that is 
to say, particular details under coherent general 


rules, able to foresee and influence the future by 


their knowledge of the past :—there is no paradox 


in that: it belongs rather, you might complain, 


to the range of platitudes. But, remember ! the 
hinge of Plato’s whole political argument is, that 


the ruinous divisions of Athens, of Greece, of the 


entire social community, is the want of dis- 
interestedness in its rulers; not that they are 
unfit to rule; rather, that they have often, it 
may be, a natural call to office—those exceptional 


high natures—but that they “abound” therein 


exclusively “in their own sense.” And the 
precise point of paradox in philosophic kingship, 
261 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


as Plato takes it, is this, that if we have 
philosophers for our kings, our archons, we shall 
be under a sort of rulers who as such have made 
sacrifice of themselves, and in coming to office at 
all must have taken upon them “the form of a 
servant.” — 


For thus it is—If you can find out a life better than being 

a king, for those who shall be kings, a well-governed city will 
become possible, and not otherwise. For in that city alone 
will those be kings who are in very deed rich. But if poor 
men, hungering after their private good, proceed to public 
offices, it is not possible ; for, the kingly office becoming an — 
object of contention, the sort of battle which results, being at 
home and internal, destroys them, along with the common- 
wealth.—Most truly, he replied—Have you then, I asked, any 
kind of life which can despise political offices, other than the 
life of true philosophers ?—Certainly not.—Yet still it is 
necessary that those who come to office should not be lovers of 
it ; otherwise the rival lovers will fight.—That must be so.— 
Whom then will you compel to proceed to the guardianship of 
the city save those, who, being wisest of all in regard to the 
conditions of her highest welfare, are themselves possessed of 
privileges of another order, and a life better than the politician’s? 
Republic, 520. 


More capable than others of an adroit applica- 
tion of all that power usually means in the way 
of personal advantage, your “legitimate,” and 
really elect royalty or aristocracy must be secured 
from the love of it; you must insure their 
magnanimity in office by a counter-charm. But 
where is such a charm, or counter-charm, to be 
found? Throughout, as usual in so provident a 
writer as Plato, the answer to that leading 

262 


THE REPUBLIC 


question has had its prelude, even in the first 
book.— 


Therefore it was, for my part, friend Thrasymachus, I was 
saying just now that no one would be willing of his own motion 
to rule, and take in hand the ills of other people to set them 
right, but that he would ask a reward; because he who will 
do fairly by his art, or prosper by his art, never does what is 
best for himself, nor ordains that, in ordaining what is proper 
to his art, but what is best for the subject of his rule. By 
reason of which indeed, as it seems, there must needs be a 
reward for those who shall be willing to rule, either money, or 
honour, or a penalty unless he will rule—How do you mean 
this Socrates? said Glaucon: for the two rewards I understand ; 
but the penalty, of which you speak, and have named as 
in the place of a reward, I do not understand.—Then you do 
not understand, I said, the reward of the best, for the sake of 
which the most virtuous rule, when they are willing to rule. 
Or do you not know that the being fond of honours, fond of 
money, is said to be, and is, a disgrace ?—-For my part, Yes ! 
he said.—On this ground then, neither for money are the good 
willing to rule, nor for honour; for they choose neither, in 
openly exacting hire as a return for their rule, to be called hire- 
lings, nor, in taking secretly therefrom, thieves. Nor again is 
it for honour they will rule; for they are not ambitious. 
Therefore it is, that necessity must be on them, and a penalty, 
if they are to be willing to rule: whence perhaps it has come, 
that to proceed with ready will to the office of ruler, and not 
to await compulsion, is accounted indecent. As for the penalty, 
—the greatest penalty is to be ruled by one worse than oneself, 
unless one will rule. And it is through fear of that, the good 
seem to me to rule, when they rule: and then they proceed 
to the office of ruler, not as coming to some good thing, nor 
as to profit therein, but as to something unavoidable, and as 
having none better than themselves to whom to entrust it, nor 
even as good. Since it seems likely that if a city of good men 
came to be, not to rule would be the matter of contention, as 
nowadays to rule; and here it would become manifest that a 
ruler in very deed, in the nature of things, considers not what 
is profitable for himself, but for the subject of his rule. So 

263 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


that every intelligent person would choose rather to be benefited 
by another, than by benefiting another to have trouble himself. 
Republic, 346. 


Now if philosophy really is where Plato con- 
sistently puts it, and is all he claims for it, then, 
for those capable of it, who are capable also in 
the region of practice, it will be precisely “that 
better thing than being a king for those who 
must be our kings, our archons.” You see that 
the various elements of Platonism are inter- 
dependent ; that they really cohere. 

Just at this point then you must call to 
memory the greatness of the claim Plato makes 
for philosophy—a promise, you may perhaps 
think, larger than anything he has actually 
presented to his readers in the way of a 
philosophic revelation justifies. He seems, in 
fact, to promise all, or almost all, that in a later 
age natures great and high have certainly found 
in the Christian religion. If philosophy is only 
star-gazing, or only a condition of doubt, if what 
the sophist or the philistine says of it is all that 
can be said, it could hardly compete with the 
rewards which the vulgar world holds out to its 
servants. But for Plato, on the other hand, if 
philosophy is anything at all, it is nothing less. 
than an “escape from the evils of the world,” 
and ὁμοίωσις τῷ θεῷ, a being made like to God. It: 
provides a satisfaction not for the intelligence 
only but for the whole nature of man, his 
imagination and faith, his affections, his capacity 

264 


| 


THE REPUBLIC 


for religious devotion, and for some still un- 
imagined development of the capacities of sense. 

How could anything which belongs to the 
world of mere phenomenal change seem great 
to him who is “the spectator of all time and 
all existence”? ‘For the excellency” of such 
knowledge as that, we might say, he must “count 
all things but loss.” By fear of punishment in 
some roundabout way, he might indeed be com- 
pelled to descend into “the cave,” “to take in 
hand the wrongs of other people to set them 
right”; but of course the part he will take in 
your sorry exhibition of passing shadows, and 
dreamy echoes concerning them, will not be for 
himself. You may think him, that philosophic 
archon or king, who in consenting to be your 
master has really taken upon himself “the form 
of a servant”—you may think him, in our late 
age of philosophic disillusion, a wholly chimerical 
being. Yet history records one instance in which 
such a figure actually found his way to an imperial 
throne, and with a certain approach to the result 
Plato promises. It was precisely because his whole 
being was filled with philosophic vision, that the 
Emperor Marcus Aurelius, that fond student of 
philosophy, of this very philosophy of Plato, served 
the Roman people so well in peace and war—with 
so much disinterestedness, because, in fact, so 
reluctantly. Look onward, and what is strange 
and inexplicable in his realisation of the Platonic 
scheme—strange, if we consider how cold and 

265 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


feeble after all were the rays of light on which he 
waited so devoutly—becomes clear in the person 
of Saint Louis, who, again, precisely because his 
whole being was full of heavenly vision, in self- 
banishment from it for a while, led and ruled the 
French people so magnanimously alike in peace 
and war. The presence, then, the ascendancy amid 
actual things, of the royal or philosophic nature, 
as Plato thus conceives it—that, and nothing else, 
will be the generating force, the seed, of the City 
of the Perfect, as he conceives it: this place, in 
which the great things of existence, known or 
divined, really fill the soul. Only, he for one 
would not be surprised if no eyes actually see it. 
Like his master Socrates, as you know, he is 
something of a humorist ; and if he sometimes 
surprises us with paradox or hazardous theory, 
will sometimes also give us to understand that 
he is after all not quite serious. So about this 
vision of the City of the Perfect, The Republic, 
Καλλίπολις, Uranopolis, Utopia, Civitas Dei, The 
Kingdom of Heaven— 


Suffer me, he says, to entertain myself as men of listless 
minds are wont to do when they journey alone. Such persons, 
I fancy, before they have found out in what way ought of what 
they desire may come to be, pass that question by lest they 
grow weary in considering whether the thing be possible or no; 
and supposing what they wish already achieved, they proceed at 
once to arrange all the rest, pleasing themselves in the tracing 
out all they will do, when that shall have come to pass—: 
making a mind already idle idler still. Republic, 144. 


266 


᾿ 
£ 
d 
ἤ 
Ἷ 
A 
ἶ 


““.“4 »ἱἶἷἱἽ. ee τ αν 


ρος. > 
~~ wr 


pet = eS et 


να 
PLATO'S AESTHETICS 


WHEN we remember Plato as the great lover, 
what the visible world was to him, what a large 
place the idea of Beauty, with its almost adequate 
realisation in that visible world, holds in his most 
abstract speculations as the clearest instance of 
the relation of the human mind to reality and 
truth, we might think that art also, the fine arts, 
would have been much for him ; that the esthetic 
element would be a significant one in his theory 
of morals and education. Ta τερπνὰ ἐν “Ελλάδι (to 
use Pindar’s phrase) all the delightful things in 
Hellas :—Plato least of all could have been un- 
affected by their presence around him. And 
so it is. Think what perfection of handicraft, 
what a subtle enjoyment therein, is involved in 
that specially Platonic rule, to mind one’s busi- 
Ness (τὸ τὰ αὑτοῦ πράττειν) that he who, like Fra 
Damiano of Bergamo, has a gift for ποικιλία, 
intarsia or marqueterie, for example, should con- 
fine himself exclusively to that. Before him, 
267 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


you know, there had been no theorising about 
the beautiful, its place in life, and the like; and 
as a matter of fact he is the earliest critic of the 
fine arts. He anticipates the modern notion 
that art as such has no end but its own perfec- 
tion,—‘“‘art for art’s sake.” ‘Ap’ οὖν καὶ ἑκάστῃ 
TOV τεχνῶν ἔστι TL συμφέρον ἄλλο ἢ ὅτε μάλιστα τελέαν 
εἶναι; We have seen again that not in theory 
only, by the large place he assigns to our 
experiences regarding visible beauty in the 
formation of his doctrine of ideas, but that in 
the practical sphere also, this great fact of 
experience, the reality of beauty, has its im- 
portance with him. The loveliness of virtue as 
a harmony, the winning aspect of those “‘images” 
of the absolute and unseen Temperance, Bravery, 
Justice, shed around us in the visible world for 
eyes that can see, the claim of the virtues as a 
visible representation by human persons and 
their acts of the eternal qualities of ‘the 
eternal,” after all far out-weigh, as he thinks, 
the claitn of their mere utility. And accordingly, 
‘\in education, all will begin and end in “ music,’ 
fin the promotion of qualities to which no truer 
-name can be given than symmetry, zsthetic fit- 
‘ness, tone. Philosophy itself indeed, as he con- 
ceives it, is but the sympathetic appreciation of 
a kind of music in the very nature of things. 
There have been Platonists without Plato, 
and a kind of traditional Platonism in the world, 
independent of, yet true in spirit to, the Platonism 
268 


PLATO’S ASTHETICS 


of the Platonic Dialogues. Now such a piece of 
traditional Platonism we find in the hypothesis 
of some close connexion between what may be 
called the esthetic qualities of the world about 
us and the formation of moral character, between 
esthetics and ethics. Wherever people have 
been inclined to lay stress on the colouring, for 
instance, cheerful or otherwise, of the walls of 
the room where children learn to read, as though 
that had something to do with the colouring of 
their minds ; on the possible moral effect of the 
beautiful ancient buildings of some of our own 
schools and colleges ; on the building of character, 
in any way, through the eye and ear; there the 
spirit of Plato has been understood to be, and 
rightly, even by those who have perhaps never 
read Plato’s Republic, in which however we do 
find the connexion between moral character and 
matters of poetry and art strongly asserted. 
This is to be observed especially in the third 
and tenth books of The Republic. The main 
interest of those books lies in the fact, that in 
them we read what Plato actually said on a 
subject concerning which people have been so 
ready to put themselves under his authority. 


It is said with immediate reference to metre 
and its various forms in verse, as an element in 
the general treatment of style or manner (λέξις) 
as opposed to the matter (λόγοι) in the imaginative 
literature, with which as in time past the 

269 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


education of the citizens of the Perfect City 
will begin. It is however at his own express 
suggestion that we may apply what he says, in 
the first instance, about metre and verse, to all 
forms of art whatever, to music (μουσική) generally, 
to all those matters over which the Muses of 
Greek mythology preside, to all productions in 
which the form counts equally with, or for more 
than, the matter. Assuming therefore that we 
have here, in outline and tendency at least, the 
mind of Plato in regard to the ethical influence 
of esthetic qualities, let us try to distinguish 
clearly the central lines of that tendency, of 
Platonism in art, as it is really to be found in 
Plato. 

“You have perceived have you not,” observes 
_the Platonic Socrates, ‘that acts of imitation, if 
they begin in early life, and continue, establish 
themselves in one’s nature and habits, alike as to 
the body, the tones of one’s voice, the ways of 
one’s mind.” 

Yes, that might seem a matter of common 
observation ; and what is strictly Platonic here 
and in what follows is but the emphasis of the 
statement. Let us set it however, for the sake 
of decisive effect, in immediate connexion with 
certain other points of Plato’s esthetic doctrine. 
Imitation then, imitation through the eye and 
ear, is irresistible in its influence over human 
nature. And secondly, we, the founders, the 
people, of the Republic, of the city that shall be 


270 


ΒΡ τ ανοναν.. 


erage 


PLATO’S ASTHETICS 


perfect, have for our peculiar purpose the simpli- 
fication of human nature: a purpose somewhat 
costly, for it follows, thirdly, that the only kind 
of music, of art and poetry, we shall permit 
ourselves, our citizens, will be of a very austere 
character, under a sort of “self-denying ordin- 
ance.” We shall be a fervently esthetic com- 
munity, if you will; but therewith also very 
fervent ‘‘ renunciants,” or ascetics. 

In the first place, men’s souls are, according 
to Plato’s view, the creatures of what men see 
and hear. What would probably be found in a 
limited number only of sensitive people,- a 
constant susceptibility to the aspects and other 
sensible qualities of things and persons, to the 
element of expression or form in them and their 
movements, to phenomena as such—this suscepti- 
bility Plato supposes in men generally. It is 
not so much the matter of a work of art, what is 
conveyed in and by colour and form and sound, 
that tells upon us educationally—the subject, for 
instance, developed by the words and scenery of 
a play—as the form, and its qualities, concision, 
simplicity, rhythm, or, contrariwise, abundance, 
variety, discord. Such “esthetic” qualities, by 
what we might call in logical phrase, μετάβασις εἰς 
ἄλλο γένος, a derivation into another kind of 
matter, transform themselves, in the temper of 
the patient the hearer or spectator, into terms 
of ethics, into the sphere of the desires and the 
will, of the mora/ taste, engendering, nursing 

271 


Ν 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


there, strictly moral effects, such conditions of 
sentiment and the will as Plato requires in his ~ 
City of the Perfect, or quite the opposite, but 
hardly in any case indifferent, conditions. 

Imitation :—it enters into the very fastnesses 
of character; and we, our souls, ourselves, are 
for ever imitating what we see and hear, the 
forms, the sounds which haunt our memories, 
our imagination. We imitate not only if we 
play a part on the stage but when we sit as 
spectators, while our thoughts follow the acting 
of another, when we read Homer and put our- 
selves, lightly, fluently, into the place of those 
he describes : we imitate unconsciously the line 
and colour of the walls around us, the trees by 
the wayside, the animals we pet or make use of, 
the very dress we wear. Only, Ἵνα μὴ ἐκ τῆς 
μιμήσεως τοῦ εἶναι amodkatcwow.—Let us beware 
how men attain the very truth of what they 
imitate. 

That then is the first principle of Plato’s 
esthetics, his first consideration regarding the 
art of the City of the Perfect. Men, children, 
are susceptible beings, in great measure condi- 
tioned by the mere look of their ‘“‘ medium.” 
Like those insects, we might fancy, of which 
naturalists tell us, taking colour from the plants 
they lodge on, they will come to match with 
much servility the aspects of the world about 
them. 

But the people of the Perfect City would not 


272 


PLATO’S ASTHETICS 


be there at all except by way of a refuge, an 
experiment, or our de force, in moral and social 
philosophy ; and this circumstance determines 
the second constituent principle of Plato’s 
esthetic scheme. We, then, the founders, the 
᾿ς citizens, of the Republic have a peculiar purpose. 
We are here to escape from, to resist, a certain 
vicious centrifugal tendency in life, in Greek 
and especially in Athenian life, which does but 
propagate a like vicious tendency in ourselves. 
We are to become—like little pieces in a 
machine ! you may complain.—No, like per- 
formers rather, individually, it may be, of more 
or less importance, but each with a necessary 
and inalienable part, in a perfect musical exercise 
which is well worth while, or in some sacred 
liturgy ; or like soldiers in an invincible army, 
invincible because it moves as one man. We 
are to find, or be put into, and keep, every one 
his natural place; to cultivate those qualities 
which will secure mastery over ourselves, the 
subordination of the parts to the whole, musical 
proportion. To this end, as we saw, Plato, a 
remorseless idealist, is ready even to suppress the 
differences of male and female character, to 
merge, to lose the family in the social aggregate. 

Imitation then, we may resume, imitation 
through the eye and ear, is irresistible in its 
influence on human nature. Secondly, the 
founders of the Republic are by its very purpose 
bound to the simplification of human nature: 

P. VI 273 T 


av 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


and our practical conclusion follows in logical 
order. We shall make, and sternly keep, a 
‘self-denying ” ordinance in this matter, in the 
matter of art, of poetry, of taste in all its 
varieties ; a rule, of which Plato’s own words, 
applied by him in the first instance to rhythm 
or metre, but like all he says on that subject 
fairly applicable to the whole range of musical 
or esthetic effects, will be the brief summary : 
Alternations will be few and far between :—-how 
differently from the methods of the poetry, 
the art, the choruses, we most of us love so 
much, not necessarily because our senses are 
inapt or untrained : — Σμικραὶ ai μεταβολαί. We 
shall allow no musical innovations, no Aristo- 
phanic cries, no imitations however clever of 
“the sounds of the flute or the lyre,” no free 
imitation by the human voice of bestial or 
mechanical sounds, no such artists as are 
“like a mirror turning all about.” ‘There were 
vulgarities of nature, you see, in the youth of 
ideal Athens even. ‘Time, of course, as such, 
is itself a kind of artist, trimming pleasantly for 
us what survives of the rude world of the past. 
Now Plato’s method would promote or anticipate 
the work of time in that matter of vulgarities of 
taste. Yes, when you read his precautionary 
rules, you become fully aware that even in 
Athens there were young men who affected what 
was least fortunate in the habits, the pleasures, 
the sordid business of the class below them. 
274 


le amie Rial lhe I ER RIE Se -.5 5 


PLATO’S ASTHETICS 


But they would not be allowed quite their own 
way in the streets or elsewhere in a reformed 
world, to whose chosen imperial youth (βασιλικὴ 
φυλή) it would not be permitted even to think of 
any of those things—otSeri προσέχειν τὸν νοῦν. ΤῸ 
them, what was illiberal, the illiberal crafts, 
would be (thanks to their well-trained power of 
intellectual abstraction !) as though it were not. 
And if art, like law, be, as Plato thinks, “a 
creation of mind, in accordance with right 
reason,” we shall not wish our boys to sing like 
mere birds. 

Yet what price would not the musical 
connoisseur pay to handle the instruments we 
may see in fancy passing out through the gates 
of the City of the Perfect, banished, not because 
there is no one within its walls who knows the 
use of, or would receive pleasure from, them (a 
delicate susceptibility in these matters Plato, as 
was said, presupposes) but precisely because they 
are so seductive, must be conveyed therefore to 
some other essentially less favoured neighbour- 
hood, like poison, say! moral poison, for one’s 
enemies’ water-springs. A whole class of 
painters, sculptors, skilled workmen of various 
kinds go into like banishment—they and their 
very tools ; not, observe again carefully, because 
they are bad artists, but very good ones.—’Anra 
μήν, ὦ ᾿Αδείμαντε, ἡδύς ye καὶ ὁ Kexpayévos. Art, as 
such, as Plato knows, has no purpose but itself, 
its own perfection. The proper art of the 

P. VI 275 T2 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


Perfect City is in fact the art of discipline. 
Music (μουσική) all the various forms of fine art, 
will be but the instruments of its one over- 
mastering social or political purpose, irresistibly 
conforming its so imitative subject units to type : 
they will be neither more nor less than so many 
variations, so to speak, of the trumpet-call. 

Or suppose again that a poet finds his way to 
us, “Sable by his genius, as he chooses, or as his 
audience chooses, to become all things, or all 
persons, in turn, and able to transform us too 
into all things and persons in turn, as we listen 
or read, with a fluidity, a versatility of humour 
almost equal to his own, a poet myriad-minded, 
as we say, almost in Plato’s precise words, as 
our finest touch of praise, of Shakespeare for 
instance, or of Homer, of whom he was thinking : 
—Well! we shall have been set on our guard. 
We have no room for him. Divine, delightful, 
being, “if he came to our city with his works, 
his poems, wishing to make an exhibition of 
them, we should certainly do him reverence as 
an object, sacred, wonderful, delightful, but we 
should not let him stay. We should tell him 
that there neither is, nor may be, any one like 
that among us, and so send him on his way to 
some other city, having anointed his head with 
myrrh and crowned him with a garland of wool, 
as something in himself half-divine, and for our- 
selves should make use of some more austere 
and less pleasing sort of poet, for his practical 

276 


age ἐῶν 


PLATO’S ASTHETICS 


uses.” —T@ αὐστηροτέρῳ καὶ ἀηδεστέρῳ ποιητῇ, ὠφελίας 
ἕνεκα. Not, as I said, that the Republic any 
more than Lacedezmon will be an artless place. 
Plato’s esthetic scheme is actually based on a 
high degree of sensibility to such influences in 
the people he is dealing with.— 


Right speech, then, and rightness of harmony and form 
and rhythm minister to goodness of nature; not that good- 
nature which we so call with a soft name, being really silli- 
ness, but the frame of mind which in very truth is rightly and 
fairly ordered in regard to the moral habit.—Most certainly he 
said.— Must not these qualities, then, be everywhere pursued 
by the young men if they are to do each his own business ?— 
Pursued, certainly.—Now painting, 1 suppose, is full of them 
(those qualities which are partly ethical, partly esthetic) and 
all handicraft such as that ; the weaver’s art is full of them, and 
the inlayer’s art and the building of houses, and the working 
of all the other apparatus of life; moreover the nature of our 
own bodies, and of all other living things. For in all these, 
rightness or wrongness of form is inherent. And wrongness 
of form, and the lack of rhythm, the lack of harmony, are 
fraternal to faultiness of mind and character, and the opposite 
qualities to the opposite condition—the temperate and good 
character :—fraternal, aye! and copies of them.—Yes, entirely 
so: he said.— 

Must our poets, then, alone be under control, and compelled 
to work the image of the good into their poetic works, or not 
to work among us at all; or must the other craftsmen too be 
controlled, and restrained from working this faultiness and 
intemperance and illiberality and formlessness of character 
whether into the images of living creatures, or the houses they 
build, or any other product of their craft whatever ; or must 
he who is unable so to do be forbidden to practise his art 
among us, to the end that our guardians may not, nurtured in 
images of vice as in a vicious pasture, cropping and culling 
much every day little by little from many sources, composing 
together some one great evil in their own souls, go undetected ? 
Must we not rather seek for those craftsmen who have the 


277 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


power, by way of their own natural virtue, to track out the 
nature of the beautiful and seemly, to the end that, living as in 
some wholesome place, the young men may receive good from 
every side, whencesoever, from fair works of art, either upon 
sight or upon hearing anything may strike, as it were a 
breeze bearing health from kindly places, and from childhood 
straightway bring them unaware to likeness and friendship and 
harmony with fair reason '—Yes: he answered: in this way 
they would be by far best educated.—Well then, I said, 
Glaucon, on these grounds is not education in music of the 
greatest importance—because, more than anything else, rhythm 
and harmony make their way down into the inmost part of 
the soul, and take hold upon it with the utmost force, bringing 
with them rightness of form, and rendering its form right, if 
one be correctly trained; if not, the opposite? and again 
because he who has been trained in that department duly, 
would have the sharpest sense of oversights (τῶν παραλειπομένων) 
and of things not fairly turned out, whether by art or nature 
(μὴ καλῶς δημιουργηθέντων ἢ μὴ καλῶς φύντων) and disliking 
them, as he should, would commend things beautiful, and, by 
reason of his delight in these, receiving them into his soul, be 
nurtured of them, and become καλοκαγαθός, while he blamed 
the base, as he should, and hated it, while still young, before 
he was able to apprehend a reason, and when reason comes 
would welcome it, recognising it by its kinship to himself— 
most of all one thus taught '—Yes: he answered: it seems 
to me that for reasons such as these their education should be 
in music. Republic, 400. 


Understand, then, the poetry and music, the 
arts and crafts, of the City of the Perfect—what 
is left of them there, and remember how the 
Greeks themselves were used to say that “the 
half is more than the whole.” Liken its music, 
if you will, to Gregorian music, and call to mind 
the kind of architecture, military or monastic 
again, that must be built to such music, and 
then the kind of colouring that will fill its 

278 


PLATO’S ASTHETICS 


_ jealously allotted space upon the walls, the sort of 
carving that will venture to display itself on 
cornice or capital. The walls, the pillars, the 
streets—you see them in thought ! nay, the very 
trees and animals, the attire of those who move 
along the streets, their looks and voices, their 
style—the hieratic Dorian architecture, to speak 
precisely, the Dorian manner everywhere, in 
possession of the whole of life. Compare it, for 
further vividness of effect, to Gothic building, 
to the Cistercian Gothic, if you will, when 
Saint Bernard had purged it of a still barbaric 
superfluity of ornament. It seems a long way 
from the Parthenon to Saint Ouen ‘of the 
aisles and arches,” or Notre-Dame de Bourges ; yet 
they illustrate almost equally the direction of 
the Platonic esthetics. ‘Those churches of the 
Middle Age have, as we all feel, their loveliness, 
yet of astern sort, which fascinates while perhaps 
it repels us. We may try hard to like as well 
or better architecture of a more or less different 
kind, but coming back to them again find that 
the secret of final success is theirs. The rigid 
logic of their charm controls our taste, as logic 
proper binds the intelligence: we would have 
something of that quality, if we might, for our- 
selves, in what we do or make; feel, under its 
influence, very difident of our own loose, or 
gaudy, or literally insignificant, decorations. 
“Stay then,” says the Platonist, too sanguine 
perhaps,—“ Abide,” he says to youth, “in these 
279 


) 


Ι γί 
: 

y ca 
lf 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


places, and the like of them, and mechanically, 
irresistibly, the soul of them will impregnate 
yours. With whatever beside is in congruity 
with them in the order of hearing and sight, 
they will tell (despite, it may be, of unkindly 
nature at your first making) upon your very coun- 
tenance, your walk and gestures, in the course 
and concatenation of your inmost thoughts.” 


And equation being duly made of what is 
merely personal and temporary in Plato’s view 
of the arts, it may be salutary to return from 
time to time to the Platonic esthetics, to find 
ourselves under the more exclusive influence of 
those qualities in the Hellenic genius he has 
thus emphasised. What he would promote, 
then, is the art, the literature, of which among 
other things it may be said that it solicits a 
certain effort from the reader or spectator, who 
is promised a great expressiveness on the part of 
the writer, the artist, if he for his part will bring 
with him a great attentiveness) And how 
satisfying, how reassuring, how flattering to 
himself after all, such work really is—the work 
which deals with one as a scholar, formed, 
mature and manly. Bravery—dvdpe‘a or manliness 
—manliness and temperance, as we know, were 
the two characteristic virtues of that old pagan 
world; and inart certainly they seem to be involved 
inoneanother. Manliness in art, what can it be, 
as distinct from that which in opposition to it 

280 


τ ee se eS τα 


PLATO’S ASTHETICS 


must be called the feminine quality there,— 
what but a full conciousness of what one does, of 
art itself in the work of art, tenacity of intuition 
and of consequent purpose, the spirit of con- 
struction as opposed to what is literally incoherent 
or ready to fall to pieces, and, in opposition to 
what is hysteric or works at random, the main- 
tenance of a standard. Of such art ἦθος rather 
than πάθος will be the predominant mood. To 
use Plato’s own expression there will be here 
NO παραλευπόμενα, NO “ negligences,” no feminine 
forgetfulness of one’s self, nothing in the work 
of art unconformed to the leading intention of 
the artist, who will but increase his power by 
reserve. An artist of that kind will be apt, of 
course, to express more than he seems actually 
to say. He economises. He will not spoil 
good things by exaggeration. The rough, pro- 
miscuous wealth of nature he reduces to grace 
and order: reduces, it may be, lax verse to 
staid and temperate prose. With him, the 
rhythm, the music, the notes, will be felt to 
follow, or rather literally accompany as ministers, 
the sense,—dxorovbeiv τὸν λόγον. 

We may fairly prefer the broad daylight of 
Veronese to the contrasted light and shade of 
Rembrandt even; and a painter will tell you 
that the former is actually more difficult to 
attain. Temperance, the temperance of the 
youthful Charmides, super-induced on a nature 
originally rich and impassioned,—Plato’s own 

281 


PLATO AND PLATONISM 


native preference for that is only reinforced by 
the special needs of his time, and the very 
conditions of the ideal state. ‘The diamond, we 
are told, if it be a fine one, may gain in value 
by what is cut away. It was after such fashion 
that the manly youth of Lacedemon had been 
cut and carved. Lenten or monastic colours, 
brown and black, white and grey, give their 
utmost value for the eye (so much is obvious) to 
the scarlet flower, the lighted candle, the cloth 
of gold. And Platonic esthetics, remember ! as 
such, are ever in close connexion with Plato’s 
ethics. It is life itself, action and character, he 
proposes to colour; to get something of that 
irrepressible conscience of art, that spirit of 
control, into the general course of life, above all 
into its energetic or impassioned acts. 

Such Platonic quality you may trace of course 
not only in work of Doric, or, more largely, of 
Hellenic lineage, but at all times, as the very 
conscience of art, its saving salt, even in ages of 
decadence. You may analyse it, as a condition 
of literary style, in historic narrative, for in- 
stance ; and then you have the stringent, short- 
hand art of Thucydides at his best, his masterly 
feeling for master-facts, and the half as so much 
more than the whole. Pindar is in a certain 
sense his analogue in verse. Think of the 
amount of attention he must have looked for, 
in those who were, not to read, but to sing him, 
or to listen while he was sung, and to under- 

282 


PLATO’S ASSTHETICS 


stand. With those fine, sharp-cut gems or 
chasings of his, so sparely set, how much he 
leaves for a well-drilled intelligence to supply in 
the way of connecting thought. 

And you may look for the correlative of that 
in Greek clay, in Greek marble, as you walk 
through the British Museum. But observe it, 
above all, at work, checking yet reinforcing his 
naturally fluent and luxuriant genius, in Plato 
himself. His prose is a practical illustration 
of the value of that capacity for correction, of 
the effort, the intellectual astringency, which he 
demands of the poet also, the musician, of all 
true citizens of the ideal Republic, enhancing 
the sense of power in one’s self, and its effect 
upon others, by a certain crafty reserve in its 
exercise, after the manner of a true expert. 
Χαλεπὰ τὰ xata—he is faithful to the old Greek 
saying. Patience, “infinite patience,” may or 
may not be, as was said, of the very essence of 
genius ; but is certainly, quite ‘as much as fire, 
of the mood of all true lovers. Ἴσως τὸ λεγόμενον 
ἀληθές, ὅτε χαλεπὰ τὰ καλά. Heraclitus had pre- 
ferred the “dry soul,” or the “dry light” in it, 
as Bacon after him the siccum lumen. And the 
dry beauty,—let Plato teach us, to love that 
also, duly. 


1891-1892. 


Printed by Ἐ. & R. Ciark, Limirep, Edinburgh. 


are 0} 
Δ A Le , 


geen ih 5 


wet 
— 
7 } 


ry 


i ἌΡ ᾿ 
a βρνς οὐ ψο] τα νιν ὟΝ ti Mt tate a a Ἂν 


NEW LIBRARY EDITION OF 
ΔΗ 


OF 


WALIER FAITE 


In Ten Volumes. With decorated backs. ὅνο. 


I, 


Il. 


ΙΧ, 
Χ, 


7s. 6d. net each. ᾿ 


THE RENAISSANCE: STUDIES IN ART 
AND POETRY. 


AND III. MARIUS THE EPICUREAN. In 
Two Vols. 


. IMAGINARY PORTRAITS. 
. APPRECIATIONS. With an Essay on “ Style.” 
. PLATO AND PLATONISM. A Series of 


Lectures. 


. GREEK STUDIES. A Series of Essays. 


MISCELLANEOUS STUDIES. A Series of 
Essays. 


GASTON DELATOUR. An unfinished Romance. 
ESSAYS FROM “THE GUARDIAN.” 


MACMILLAN AND CO., Ltp., LONDON. 


Νᾳ 


Ph re " ω 
ΝΠ Τὴ 


"Δι σὺ 


Wi Coe ey yi i oe | 


ἔν 


,᾿ 
i 
4 
᾿ 
4 
‘ 
’ fa ¥ 
i ] 
4 
; ee 
i 
ΔΑ 


- 
7 
~ ral 
y 
; 
aos 
i 
ἢ ΕἾ 
ny 
f Wes 
“ie ‘ 7, 
Ϊ é 
‘ 
+4 “Fe 
a -* .f 
ite 
‘ 
᾿ 
ΩΣ 
ou 
at? a rh δὰ 
. Ὺ Ἠν 
ht ae | 
i = | hue 6 


x - -Ὄ 


ἐς ὁ ΝΣ ve 


9, 


, 
= ed 
Ὡς ἃ τ 
ς . ζ 
6 ΞΕ. 
ae 
ν . 
if 
. 
͵ 
᾿ 
- 
‘ wa 
> 7 
᾿ at 
»-- 
Ἀν To 
: 
’ 
Never 
“ ᾿ > 
ἘΣ 


JAN 2 1984 


PLEASE DO NOT REMOVE 
CARDS OR SLIPS FROM THIS POCKET 


UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO LIBRARY 


ut 
wom 
᾿ 
i 


"