Skip to main content

Full text of "Popular lectures on scientific subjects"

See other formats


POPULAR   LECTURES 


SCIENTIFIC    SUBJECTS. 


TEXT-BOOKS   OF    PHYSICS. 


GANOT'S      ELEMENTARY     TREATISE     on     PHYSICS, 

Kxnerimental  and  Applied.  Translated  and  Edited  from  GANOT'S 
EUmrmts  de  f'hysique,  by  E.  ATKINSON.  Ph.D.  F.C.S.  Fourteenth 
Edition,  Revised  and  Enlarged.  With  9  Coloured  Plates  and  1,028 
Woodcuts.  Crown  8vo.  15*. 

GANOT'S  NATURAL  PHILOSOPHY  for  GENERAL 
READERS  and  YOUNG  PERSONS  :  a  Course  of  Physics  divested  of 
Mathematical  Formulae,  expressed  in  the  langnase  of  daily  life. 
Translated  and  Edited  from  GANOT'S  Court  EUmtniaire  de  Physiquf, 
by  E.  ATKINSON,  Ph.D.  F.C.S.  Seventh  Edition.  With  37  pagps  of 
new  matter,  7  Plates,  569  Woodcuts,  and  an  Appendix  of  Questions. 
Crown  8vo.  Is.  6d. 

The  ELEMENTS  of  PHYSICS  or  NATURAL  PHILOSO- 
PHY. By  NEIL  ARNOTT,  M.D.  Edited  by  A.  BAIN.  LL.D.  and  A.  S. 
TAYLOR,  M.D.  F.R.S.  Woodcuts.  Crown  8vo.  I'ts.  6d. 

The  ELEMENTS  of  LABORATORY  WORK:  a  Course  of 

Natural  Science  By  A.  G.  EA.RL,  M.A.  F.C.S.  Science  Master  at 
Tonbridge  School.  With  57  Diagrams  and  numerous  Exercises  and 
Questions.  Crown  8vo.  4s.  6d. 

A  CLASS-BOOK  of  PRACTICAL  PHYSICS.  Molecular 
Physics  and  Sound.  By  F.  GUTHRIE,  Ph.D.  With  91  Diagrams. 
Fcp.  8vo.  Is.  6d. 

POPULAR  LECTURES  on  SCIENTIFIC  SUBJECTS.  By 
Professor  HELMHOLTZ.  With  68  Woodcuts.  2  vols.  Crown  8vo. 
3*.  Gd.  each. 

The  METHODS  of  GLASS-BLOWING.  For  the  use  of 
Physical  and  Chemical  Students.  By  W.  A.  SHBNSTONR,  Lecturer  on 
Chemistry  in  Clifton  College,  Bristol.  With  42  Illustrations.  Crown 
8vo.  1*.  6d. 

A  FIRST  COURSE  of  PHYSICAL  LABORATORY  PRAC- 
TICE. Containing  264  Experiments.  By  A.  M.  WORTHIXGTON,  M.A. 
Head  Master  of  the  Royal  Naval  Engineering  School,  Devonport. 
With  Illustrations.  Crown  8vo.  4*.  Gd. 

ELEMENTARY  PHYSICS.  By  MARK  R.  WRIGHT,  Prin- 
cipal of  the  Dav  Trai-  ing  College,  Newcastle-on-Tyne.  With  242 
Illustrations.  Crown  8vo.  2*.  6d. 


London  :  LONGMANS,  GREEN,  &  CO. 
New  York  :  15  East  16th  Street. 


POPULAR    LECTURES 


ON 


SCIENTIFIC    SUBJECTS 


BY 


HERMANN  VON  HELMHOLTZ 


TRANSLATED  BY 

E.  ATKINSON,  PH.D.,  F.C.S. 

FORMERLY  PROFESSOR  OF  EXPERIMENTAL  SCIENCE,  STAFF  COLLKOB 


FIRST    SERIES 
WITH  AS  INTRODUCTION  by  PROFESSOR   TYNDALL 


LONDON 

LONGMANS,     GREEN,     AND     CO. 

AND  NEW  YORK  :  15  EAST  16th  STREET 

1895 

All    rights    reserved 


a 


/?<?5 
TEANSLATOE'S   PBEFACE 


TO  NEW  EDITION. 


IN  1891  the  seventieth  birthday  of  Hermann  von  Helm- 
holtz,  and  the  forty-ninth  anniversary  of  his  taking  the 
degree  of  Doctor  of  Medicine,  was  celebrated  in  Berlin  in 
a  manner  which,  whether  for  its  universality  or  import- 
ance, has,  perhaps,  never  fallen  to  the  lot  of  a  Man  of 
Science  during  his  lifetime. 

The  demand  for  a  new  edition  of  the  translation  of 
the  two  volumes  of  Von  Helmholtz's  Popular  Scientific 
Lectures  suggests  that  this  is  an  appropriate  occasion  for 
a  re-issue  under  conditions  which  make  them  accessible 
to  a  larger  circle  of  readers. 

The  present  edition  is  identical  with  the  preceding 
ones ;  discussing  as  they  do,  with  the  hand  of  a  master, 
fundamental  scientific  problems,  these  Lectures  are  not 
likely  to  be  soon  out  of  date. 

To  the  second  volume  has  been  added  a  remarkable 
autobiographical  account  of  the  Author's  scientific  career 
and  development,  which  formed  the  subject  of  an  address 
given  by  Von  Helmholtz  in  reply  to  the  addresses  of 
congratulation  on  the  occasion  of  his  Jubilee.  This  is 
taken,  by  kind  permission  of  the  publisher,  M.  Hirschwald, 
from  a  collection  of  the  addresses  and  speeches  delivered 
on  that  occasion. 

E.  ATKINSON. 

March  1893. 

425182 


TRANSLATOR'S    PREFACE. 


IN  bringing  this  Translation  of  Helmholtz's  Popular 
Scientific  Lectures  before  the  public,  I  have  to  thank  Mr. 
A.  J.  Ellis  for  having  placed  at  the  disposal  of  the 
Publishers  the  translation  of  the  third  Lecture ;  and  also 
Dr.  Francis,  the  Editor  of  the  '  Philosophical  Magazine,' 
for  giving  ine  permission  to  use  the  translation  of  the  fifth 
Lecture,  which  originally  appeared  in  that  Journal. 

In  addition  to  the  Editorial  charge  of  the  book,  my 
own  task  has  been  limited  to  the  translation  of  two  of  the 
Lectures.  I  should  have  hesitated  to  undertake  the  work, 
had  I  not  from  the  outset  been  able  to  rely  upon  the  aid 
of  several  gentlemen  whose  names  are  appended  to  the 
Contents.  One  advantage  gained  from  this  division  of 
labour  is,  that  the  publication  of  the  work  has  been 
accelerated;  but  a  far  more  important  benefit  has  been 
secured  to  it,  in  the  co-operation  of  translators  who  have 
brought  to  the  execution  of  their  task  special  knowledge 
of  their  respective  subjects. 

E.  ATKINSON. 


AUTHOR'S   PBEFACE. 


IN  COMPLIANCE  with  many  requests,  I  beg  to  offer  to  the 
public  a  series  of  popular  Lectures  which  I  have  delivered 
on  various  occasions.  They  are  designed  for  readers  who, 
without  being  professionally  occupied  with  the  study  of 
Natural  Science,  are  yet  interested  in  the  scientific  results 
of  such  studies.  The  difficulty,  felt  so  strongly  in  printed 
scientific  lectures,  namely,  that  the  reader  cannot  see  the 
experiments,  has  in  the  present  case  been  materially 
lessened  by  the  numerous  illustrations  which  the  publishers 
have  liberally  furnished. 

The  first  and  second  Lectures  have  already  appeared  in 
print ;  the  first  in  a  university  programme,  which,  how- 
ever, was  not  published.  The  second  appeared  in  the 
'Kieler  Monatsschrift' for  May,  1853,  but,  owing  to  the 
restricted  circulation  of  that  journal,  became  but  little 
known;  both  have,  accordingly,  been  reprinted.  The 
third  and  fourth  Lectures  have  not  previously  appeared. 

These  Lectures,  called  forth  as  they  have  been  by 
incidental  occasions,  have  not,  of  course,  been  composed 
in  accordance  with  a  rigidly  uniform  plan.  Each  of  them 
has  been  kept  perfectly  independent  of  the  others.  Hence 


viii  AUTHOR'S  PREFACE. 

some  amount  of  repetition  has  been  unavoidable,  and  the 
first  four  may  perhaps  seem  somewhat  confusedly  thrown 
together.  If  I  may  claim  that  they  have  any  leading 
thought,  it  would  be  that  I  have  endeavoured  to  illustrate 
the  essence  and  the  import  of  Natural  laws,  and  their 
relation  to  the  mental  activity  of  man.  This  seems  to  me 
the  chief  interest  and  the  chief  need  in  Lectures  before  a 
public  whose  education  has  been  mainly  literary. 

I  have  but  little  to  remark  with  reference  to  individual 
Lectures.  The  set  of  Lectures  which  treat  of  the 
Theory  of  Vision  have  been  already  published  in  the 
*  Preussische  Jahrbiicher,'  and  have  acquired,  therefore, 
more  of  the  character  of  Eeview  articles.  As  it  was 
possible  in  this  second  reprint  to  render  many  points 
clearer  by  illustrations,  I  have  introduced  a  number  of 
woodcuts,  and  inserted  in  the  text  the  necessary  explan- 
ations. A  few  other  small  alterations  have  originated  in 
my  having  availed  myself  of  the  results  of  new  series  of 
experiments. 

The  fifth  Lecture,  on  the  Interaction  of  Natural 
Forces,  originally  published  sixteen  years  ago,  could  not 
be  left  entirely  unaltered  in  this  reprint  Yet  the  alter- 
ations have  been  as  slight  as  possible,  and  have  merely 
been  such  as  have  become  necessary  by  new  experimental 
facts,  which  partly  confirm  the  statements  originally  made, 
and  partly  modify  them. 

The  seventh  Lecture,  on  the  Conservation  of  Force, 
developes  still  further  a  portion  of  the  fifth.  Its  main 
object  is  to  elucidate  the  cardinal  physical  ideas  of  work, 
and  of  its  unalterability.  The  applications  and  conse- 


AUTHOR'S   PREFACE.  is 

quences  of  the  law  of  the  Conservation  of  Force  are  com- 
paratively more  easy  to  grasp.  They  have  in  recent  times 
been  treated  by  several  persons  in  a  vivid  and  interesting 
manner,  so  that  it  seemed  unnecessary  to  publish  the  cor- 
responding part  of  the  cycle  of  lectures  which  I  delivered 
on  this  subject;  the  more  so  as  some  of  the  more 
important  subjects  to  be  discussed  will,  perhaps  in  the 
immediate  future,  be  capable  of  more  definite  treatment 
than  is  at  present  possible. 

On  the  other  hand,  I  have  invariably  found  that  the 
fundamental  ideas  of  this  subject  always  appear  difficult 
of  comprehension  not  only  to  those  who  have  not  passed 
through  the  school  of  mathematical  mechanics ;  but  even 
to  those  who  attack  the  subject  with  diligence  and  in- 
telligence, and  who  possess  a  tolerable  acquaintance  with 
natural  science.  It  is  not  to  be  denied  that  these  ideas 
are  abstractions  of  a  quite  peculiar  kind.  Even  such  a 
mind  as  that  of  Kant  found  difficulty  in  comprehending 
them;  as  is  shown  by  his  controversy  with  Leibniiz. 
Hence  I  thought  it  worth  while  to  furnish  in  a  popular 
form  an  explanation  of  these  ideas,  by  referring  them  to 
many  of  the  better  known  mechanical  and  physical  ex- 
amples ;  and  therefore  I  have  only  for  the  present  given 
the  first  Lecture  of  that  series  which  is.  devoted  to  this 
object. 

The  last  Lecture  was  the  opening  address  for  the 
'  Naturforscher-Versammlung,'  in  Innsbruck.  It  was  not 
delivered  from  a  complete  manuscript,  but  from  brief 
notes,  and  was  not  written  out  until  a  year  after.  The 
present  form  has,  therefore,  no  claim  to  be  considered  an 


x  AUTHOR'S  PREFACE. 

accurate  reproduction  of  that  address.  I  have  added  it  to 
the  present  collection,  for  in  it  I  have  treated  briefly  what 
is  more  fully  discussed  in  the  other  articles.  Its  title  to 
the  place  which  it  occupies  lies  in  the  fact  that  it  attempts 
to  bring  the  views  enunciated  in  the  preceding  Lectures 
into  a  more  complete  and  more  comprehensive  whole. 

In  conclusion,  I  hope  that  these  Lectures  may  meet 
with  that  forbearance  which  lectures  always  require  when 
they  are  not  heard,  but  are  read  in  print. 

THE  AUTHOR. 


CONTENTS. 


LECTUBB  PAGE 

I.  ON  THE  KELATION  OF  NATURAL  SCIENCE  TO  SCIENCE  IN 
GENERAL.  Translated  by  H.  W.  EVE,  Esq.,  M.A.,  F.C.S., 
Wellington  College  .  .  .  .*•  '••'..  ...  1 

II.     ON  GOETHE'S  SCIENTIFIC  EESEARCHES.     Translated  by  H.  W. 

EVE,  Esq 29 

III.  ON  THE    PHYSIOLOGICAL    CAUSES    OF  HARMONY    or   Music. 

Translated  by  A.  J.  ELLIS,  Esq.,  M.A.,  F.K.S.       .  .53 

IV.  ICE  AND  GLACIERS.      Translated  by  Dr.  ATKINSON,  F.C.S., 

Professor  of  Experimental  Science,  Staff  College  .         .         .95 

V.   ON  THE  INTERACTION  OF  THE  NATURAL  FORCES.     Translated 

by  Professor  TYNDALL,  LL.D.,  F.R.S.  .         .        .        .        .137 

VI.   THE  EECENT  PROGRESS  OF  THE  THEORY  OF  VISION.   Translated 
by  Dr.  PYE-SMITH,  B.A.,  F.R.C.P.,  Guy's  Hospital . 

L     The  Eye  as  an  Optical  Instrument       .         .         .         .175 

n.     The  Sensation  of  Sight       .         .         .        .         .         .202 

m.     The  Perception  of  Sight     .        .        .        .        .        .237 

VII.   ON  THE  CONSERVATION  OF  FORCE.      Translated  by  Dr.   AT- 
KINSON         .         .277 

VIII.   ON  THE  AIM  AND  PROGRESS  OF  PHYSICAL  SCIENCB.    Translated 

by  Dr.  W.  FLIGHT,  F.C.S.,  British  Museum         .        .        .319 


INTRODUCTION. 


IN  the  year  1850,  -when  I  was  a  student  in  the  University  of 
Marburg,  it  was  my  privilege  to  translate  for  the  'Philosophical 
Magazine'  the  celebrated  memoirs  of  Clausius,  then  just  pub- 
lished, on  the  Moving  Force  of  Heat. 

In  1851,  through  the  liberal  courtesy  of  the  late  Professor 
Magnus,  I  was  enabled  to  pursue  my  scientific  labours  in  his 
laboratory  in  Berlin.  One  evening  during  my  residence  there 
my  friend  Dr.  Du  Bois-Raymond  put  a  pamphlet  into  my  hands, 
remarking  that  it  was  'the  production  of  the  first  head  in  Europe 
since  the  death  of  Jacobi,'  and  that  it  ought  to  be  translated 
into  English.  Soon  after  my  return  to  England  I  translated 
the  essay  and  published  it  in  the  'Scientific  Memoirs/  then 
brought  out  under  the  joint-editorship  of  Huxley,  Henfrey, 
Francis,  and  myself. 

This  essay,  which  was  communicated  in  1847  to  the  Physical 
Society  of  Berlin,  has  become  siifficiently  famous  since.  It  was 
entitled  'Die  Erhaltung  der  Kraft,'  and  its  author  was  Helmholtz, 
originally  Military  Physician  in  the  Prussian  service,  afterwards 
Professor  of  Physiology  in  the  Universities  of  Kb'nigsberg  and 
Heidelberg,  and  now  Professor  of  Physics  in  the  University  of 
Berlin. 

Brought  thus  face  to  face  with  the  great  generalisation  of 
the  Conservation  of  Energy,  I  sought,  to  the  best  of  my  ability, 
to  master  it  by  independent  thought  in  all  its  physical  details. 
I  could  not  forget  my  indebtedness  to  Helmholtz  and  Clausius, 


xiv  INTRODUCTION. 

or  fail  to  see  tlw  probable  influence  of  their  writings  on  the 
science  of  the  coming  time.  For  many  years,  therefore,  it  was 
my  habit  to  place  every  physical  paper  published  by  these 
eminent  men  within  the  reach  of  purely  English  readers. 

The  ti-anslation  of  the  lecture  on  the  '  Wechselwirkung  der 
Naturkrafte,'  printed  in  the  following  series,  had  this  origin. 
It  appears  here  with  the  latest  emendations  of  the  author 
ntroduced  by  Dr.  Atkinson. 

The  evident  aim  of  these  Lectures  is  to  give  to  those  'whose 
education  has  been  mainly  literary,'  an  intelligent  interest 
in  the  researches  of  science.  Even  among  such  persons  the 
reputation  of  Helmholtz  is  so  great  as  to  render  it  almost  super- 
fluous for  me  to  say  that  the  intellectual  nutriment  here  offered 
is  of  the  very  first  quality. 

Soon  after  the  publication  of  the  '  Tonempfindungen '  by 
Helmholtz,  I  endeavoured  to  interest  the  Messrs.  Longman  in  the 
work,  urging  that  the  publication  of  a  translation  of  it  would 
be  an  honour  to  their  house.  They  went  carefully  into  the 
question  of  expense,  took  sage  counsel  regarding  the  probable 
sale,  and  came  reluctantly  to  the  conclusion  that  it  would  not 
be  remunerative. '  I  then  recommended  the  translation  of  these 
'  Populare  Yortrage,'  and  to  this  the  eminent  publishers  imme- 
diately agreed. 

Hence  the  present  volume,  brought  out  under  the  editorship 
of  Dr.  Atkinson,  of  the  Staff  College,  Sandhurst.  The  names 
of  the  translators  are,  I  think,  a  guarantee  that  their  work  will 
be  worthy  of  their  original. 

JOHN  TYNDALL. 

ROYAL  INSTITUTION: 
March  1873. 

1  Since  the  date  of  the  foregoing  letter  from  Professor  Tyndall,  Messrs. 
Longman  &  Co.  have  made  arrangements  for  the  translation  of  Helmholtz's 
Tonempfindungen,  by  Mr.  Alexander  J.  Ellis,  F.R.S.  &c. 


ON  THE 

RELATION  OF  NATURAL  SCIENCE1 
TO  GENERAL  SCIENCE, 

Academical  Discourse  delivered  at  Heidelberg,  November  22,   1862, 
Br  DB.  H.  HELMHOLTZ,  SOJIETIMK  PKOBECTOB. 


TO-DAY  we  are  met,  according  to  annual  custom,  in  grateful 
commemoration  of  an  enlightened  sovereign  of  this  kingdom, 
Charles  Frederick,  who,  in  an  a-ge  when  the  ancient  fabric  of 
European  society  seemed  tottering  to  its  fall,  strove,  with  lofty 
purpose  and  untiring  zeal,  to  promote  the  welfare  of  his  sub- 
jects, and,  above  all,  their  moral  and  intellectual  development. 
Rightly  did  he  judge  that  by  no  means  could  he  more  effectually 
realise  this  beneficent  intention  than  by  the  revival  and  the 
encouragement  of  this  University.  Speaking,  as  I  do,  on  such 
an  occasion,  at  once  in  the  name  and  in  the  presence  of  the 
whole  University,  I  have  thought  it  well  to  try  and  take,  as  far 

1  The  German  word  Naturwissensctiaft  has  no  exact  equivalent  in  modern 
English,  including,  as  it  does,  both  the  Physical  and  the  Natural  Sciences. 
Curiously  enough,  in  the  original  charter  of  the  Royal  Society,  the  phrase 
Natural  Knowledge  covers  the  same  ground,  but  is  there  used  in  opposition 
to  supernatural  kn  OTvleclge.  (Note  in  Buckle's  Civilisation,  vol.  ii.  p.  34] .)— 
Tu. 

r.  B 


2  Oy   THE    RELATION    OK 

as  is  permitted  by  the  narrow  standpoint  of  a  single  student, 
a  general  view  of  the  connection  of  the  several  sciences,  and  of 
their  study. 

It  may,  indeed,  he  thought  that,  at  the  present  day,  those 
relations  between  the  different  sciences  which  have  led  us  to 
combine  them  under  the  name  Universitas  Litterarum,  have 
become  looser  than  ever.  We  see  scholars  and  scientific  men 
absorbed  in  specialities  of  such  vast  extent,  that  the  most 
universal  genius  cannot  hope  to  master  more  than  a  small 
section  of  our  present  range  of  knowledge.  For  instance,  the 
philologists  of  the  last  three  centuries  found  ample  occupation 
in  the  study  of  Greek  and  Latin  ;  at  best  they  added  to  it  the 
knowledge  of  two  or  three  European  languages,  acquired  for 
practical  purposes.  But  now  comparative  philology  aims  at 
nothing  less  than  an  acquaintance  with  all  the  languages  of  all 
branches  of  the  human  family,  in  order  to  deduce  from  them 
the  laws  by  which  language  itself  has  been  formed,  and  to  this 
gigantic  task  it  has  already  applied  itself  with  superhuman 
industry.  Even  classical  philology  is  no  longer  restricted  to 
the  study  of  those  works  which,  by  their  artistic  perfection 
and  precision  of  thought,  or  because  of  the  importance  of  their 
contents,  have  become  models  of  prose  and  poetry  to  all  ages. 
On  the  contrary,  we  have  learnt,  that  every  lost  fragment  of 
an  ancient  author,  every  gloss  of  a  pedantic  grammarian,  every 
allusion  of  a  Byzantine  court-poet,  every  broken  tombstone 
found  in  the  wilds  of  Hungary  or  Spain  or  Africa,  may  con- 
tribute a  fresh  fact,  or  fresh  evidence,  and  thus  serve  to  increase 
our  knowledge  of  the  past.  And  so  another  group  of  scholars  are 
busy  with  the  vast  scheme  of  collecting  and  cataloguing,  for  the 
use  of  their  successors,  every  available  relic  of  classical  antiquity. 
Add  to  this,  in  history,  the  study  of  original  documents,  the 
critical  examination  of  parchments  and  papei-s  accumulated  in 
the  archives  of  states  and  of  towns  ;  the  combination  of  details 
scattered  up  and  down  in  memoirs,  in  correspondence,  and  iu 
biographies ;  the  deciphering  of  hieroglyphics  and  cuneiform  in- 
scriptions; in  natural  history  the  more  and  more  comprehensive 
classification  of  minerals,  plants,  and  animals, as  wellliving  aa 


NATURAL   SCIENCE   TO   GENERAL   SCIENCE.  3 

extinct ;  and  there  opens  out  before  us  an  expanse  of  knowledge  the 
contemplation  of  which  may  well  bewilder  us.  In  all  these  sciences 
the  range  of  investigation  widens  as  fast  as  the  means  of  obser- 
vation improve.  The  zoologists  of  past  times  were  content  to 
have  described  the  teeth,  the  hair,  the  feet,  and  other  external 
characteristics  of  an  animal.  The  anatomist,  on  the  other  hand, 
confined  himself  to  human  anatomy,  so  far  as  he  could  make 
it  out  by  the  help  of  the  knife,  the  saw,  and  the  scalpel,  with 
the  occasional  aid  of  injections  of  the  vessels.  Human  anatomy 
then  passed  tor  an  unusually  extensive  and  difficult  study.  Now 
we  are  no  longer  satisfied  with  the  comparatively  rough  science 
which  bore  the  name  of  human  anatomy,  and  which,  though 
without  reason,  was  thought  to  be  almost  exhausted.  We 
have  added  to  it  comparative  anatomy — that  is,  the  anatomy 
of  all  animals — and  microscopic  anatomy,  both  of  them  sciences 
of  infinitely  wider  range,  which  now  absorb  the  interest  of 
students. 

The  four  elements  of  the  ancients  and  of  mediaeval  alchemy 
have  been  increased  to  sixty-four,  the  last  four  of  which  are 
due  to  a  method  invented  in  our  own  University,  which  pro- 
mises still  further  discoveries.1-  But  not  merely  is  the  number 
of  the  elements  far  greater,  the  methods  of  producing  compli- 
cated combinations  of  them  have  been  so  vastly  improved,  that 
what  is  called  organic  chemistry,  which  embraces  only  com- 
pounds of  carbon  with  oxygen,  hydrogen,  nitrogen,  and  a  few 
other  elements,  has  already  taken  iunk  as  an  independent 
science. 

'  As  the  stars  of  heaven  for  multitude '  was  in  ancient  times 
the  natural  expression  for  a  number  beyond  our  comprehension, 
Pliny  even  thinks  it  almost  presumption  ('  rem  etiam  Deo  im- 
probam ')  on  the  part  of  Hipparchus  to  have  undertaken  to 
count  the  stars  and  to  determine  their  relative  positions.  And 
yet  none  of  the  catalogues  up  to  the  seventeenth  centuiy,  con- 
structed without  the  aid  of  telescopes,  give  more  than  from 

1  That  is  the  method  of  spectrum  analysis,  duo  to  Bunsen  and  Kirchoff,  both 
of  Heidelberg.  The  elements  alluded  to  are  csesiura,  rubidium,  thallium,  and 
iridium. 


4  ON   THE   RELATION    OF 

1,000  to  1,500  stars  of  magnitudes  from  the  first  to  the  fifth. 
At  present  several  observatories  are  engaged  in  continuing  these 
catalogues  down  to  stars  of  the  tenth  magnitude ;  so  that  up- 
wards of  200,000  fixed  stai-s  are  to  be  catalogued  and  their  places 
accurately  determined.  The  immediate  result  of  these  obser- 
vations has  been  the  discovery  of  a  great  number  of  new 
planets;  so  that,  instead  of  the  six  known  in  1781,  there  are 
now  seventy-five.1 

The  contemplation  of  this  astounding  activity  in  all  branches 
of  science  may  well  make  us  stand  aghast  at  the  audacity  of 
man,  and  exclaim  with  the  Chorus  in  the  '  Antigone ' :  '  Who 
can  survey  the  whole  field  of  knowledge  1  Who  can  grasp  the 
clues,  and  then  thread  the  labyrinth  1 '  One  obvious  consequence 
of  this  vast  extension  of  the  limits  of  science  is,  that  every 
student  is  forced  to  choose  a  narrower  and  narrower  field  for 
his  own  studies,  and  can  only  keep  up  an  imperfect  acquaintance 
even  with  allied  fields  of  research.  It  almost  raises  a  smile  to 
hear  that  in  the  seventeenth  century  Kepler  was  invited  to 
Grate  as  professor  of  mathematics  and  moral  philosophy :  and 
that  at  Leyden,  in  the  beginning  of  the  eighteenth,  Boerhave 
occupied  at  the  same  time  the  chairs  of  botany,  chemistry,  and 
clinical  medicine,  and  therefore  practically  that  of  pharmacy  as 
well.  At  present  we  require  at  least  four  professors,  or,  in  an 
university  with  its  full  complement  of  teachers,  seven  or  eight, 
to  represent  all  these  branches  of  science.  And  the  same  is 
true  of  other  faculties. 

One  of  my  strongest  motives  for  discussing  to-day  the  con- 
nection of  the  different  sciences  is  that  I  am  myself  a  student 
of  natural  philosophy;  and  that  it  has  been  made  of  late  a 
reproach  against  natural  philosophy  that  it  has  struck  out  a 
path  of  its  own,  and  has  separated  itself  more  and  more  widely 
from  the  other  sciences  which  are  united  by  common  philological 
and  historical  studies.  This  opposition  has,  in  fact,  been  long 
apparent,  and  seems  to  me  to  have  grown  up  mainly  under  the 
influence  of  the  Hegelian  philosophy,  or,  at  any  rate,  to  have 

«  At  the  end  of  November  1864,  the  82nd  of  the  small  planets,  Alcmene.  WM 
discovered.  There  are  now  109. 


NATURAL   SCIENCE   TO   GENERAL   SCIENCE.  5 

been  brought  out  into  more  distinct  relief  by  that  philosophy. 
Certainly,  at  the  end  of  the  last  century,  when  the  Kantian 
philosophy  reigned  supreme,  such  a  schism  had  never  been  pro- 
claimed ;  on  the  contrary,  Kant's  philosophy  rested  on  exactly 
the  same  ground  as  the  physical  sciences,  as  is  evident  from  his 
own  scientific  works,  especially  from  his  *  Cosmogony,'  based 
upon  Newton's  Law  of  Gravitation,  which  afterwards,  under 
the  name  of  Laplace's  Nebular  Hypothesis,  came  to  be  uni- 
versally recognised.  The  sole  object  of  Kant's  'Critical  Phi- 
losophy' was  to  test  the  sources  and  the  authority  of  our 
knowledge,  and  to  fix  a  definite  scope  and  standard  for  the 
researches  of  philosophy,  as  compared  with  other  sciences. 
According  to  his  teaching,  a  principle  discovered  a  priori  by 
pure  thought  was  a  rule  applicable  to  the  method  of  pure 
thought,  and  nothing  further ;  it  could  contain  no  real,  pos  tivo 
knowledge.  The  'Philosophy  of  Identity*  l  was  bolder.  It 
started  with  the  hypothesis  that  not  only  spiritual  phenomena, 
but  even  the  actual  world — nature,  that  is,  and  man — were  the 
result  of  an  act  of  thought  on  the  part  of  a  creative  mind, 
similar,  it  was  supposed,  in  kind  to  the  human  mind.  On  this 
hypothesis  it  seemed  competent  for  the  human  mind,  even  with- 
out the  guidance  of  external  experience,  to  think  over  again  the 
thoughts  of  the  Creator,  and  to  rediscover  them  by  its  own 
inner  activity.  Such  was  the  view  with  which  the  '  Philosophy 
of  Identity'  set  to  work  to  construct  a  priori  the  results  of 
other  sciences.  The  process  might  be  more  or  loss  successful  in 
matters  of  theology,  law,  politics,  language,  art,  histoiy,  in  short, 
in  all  sciences  the  subject-matter  of  which  really  grows  out  of 
our  moral  nature,  and  which  are  therefore  properly  classed 
together  under  the  name  of  moral  sciences.  The  state,  the 
church,  art  and  language,  exist  in  order  to  satisfy  certain  moral 
needs  of  man.  Accordingly,  whatever  obstacles  nature,  or 
chance,  or  the  rivalry  of  other  men  may  interpose,  the  efforts  of 
the  human  mind  to  satisfy  its  needs,  being  systematically  directed 
to  one  end,  must  eventually  triumph  over  all  such  fortuitous 

1  So  called  because  it  proclaimed  the  identity  not  onh' of  subject  and  object, 
but  of  contradictories,  such  *w  existence  and,  non-existence.— To. 


6  ON    THE   RELATION    OF 

hindrances.  Under  these  circumstances,  it  would  not  be  a 
downright  impossibility  for  a  philosopher,  starting  from  an  exact 
knowledge  of  the  mind,  to  predict  the  general  course  of  human 
development  under  the  above-named  conditions,  especially  if 
he  has  before  his  eyes  a  basis  of  observed  facts,  on  which  to 
build  his  abstractions.  Moreover,  Hegel  was  materially  assisted, 
in  his  attempt  to  solve  this  problem,  by  the  profound  and  philo- 
sophical views  on  historical  and  scientific  subjects  with  which 
the  writings  of  his  immediate  predecessors,  both  po?ts  and  phi- 
losophers, abound.  He  had,  for  the  ruost  part,  only  to  collect 
and  combine  them,  in  order  to  produce  a  system  calculated  to 
impress  people  by  a  number  of  acute  and  original  observations. 
He  thus  succeeded  in  gaining  the  enthusiastic  approval  of  most 
of  the  educated  men  of  his  time,  and  in  raising  extravagantly 
sanguine  hopes  of  solving  the  deepest  enigma  of  human  life ;  all 
the  more  sanguine  doubtless,  as  the  connection  of  his  system 
was  disguised  under  a  strangely  abstract  phraseology,  and  was 
perhaps  really  understood  by  but  few  of  his  worshippers. 

But  even  granting  that  Hegel  was  more  or  less  successful  in 
constructing,  a  priori,  the  leading  results  of  the  moral  sciences, 
still  it  was  no  proof  of  the  correctness  of  the  hypothesis  of 
Identity,  with  which  he  started.  The  facts  of  nature  would 
have  been  the  crucial  test.  That  in  the  moral  sciences  traces  of 
the  activity  of  the  human  intellect  and  of  the  several  stages  of 
its  development  should  present  themselves,  was  a  matter  of 
course ;  but  surely,  if  nature  really  reflected  the  result  of  the 
thought  of  a  creative  mind,  the  system  ought,  without  difficulty, 
to  find  a  place  for  her  comparatively  simple  phenomena  and 
processes.  It  was  at  this  point  that  Hegel's  philosophy,  we 
venture  to  say,  utterly  broke  down.  His  system  of  nature 
eeemed,  at  least  to  natural  philosophers,  absolutely  crazy.  Of 
all  the  distinguished  scientific  men  who  were  his  contem- 
poraries, not  one  was  found  to  stand  up  for  his  ideas.  Accord- 
ingly, Hegel  himself,  convinced  of  the  importance  of  winning 
for  his  philosophy  in  the  field  of  physical  science  that  recog- 
nition which  had  been  so  freely  accorded  to  it  elsewhere, 
launched  out,  with  unusual  vehemence  and  acrimony,  against 


NATURAL   SCIENCE   TO    GENERAL   SCIENCE.  7 

the  natural  philosophers,  and  especially  against  Sir  Isaac  Newton, 
ns  the  first  and  gieatest  representative  of  physical  investigation. 
The  philosophers  accused  the  scientific  men  of  narrowness;  the 
scientific  men  retorted  that  the  philosophers  were  crazy.  And 
so  it  came  about  that  men  of  science  began  to  lay  some  stress  on 
the  banishment  of  all  philosophic  influences  from  their  work ; 
while  some  of  them,  including  men  of  the  greatest  acuteness, 
went  so  far  as  to  condemn  philosophy  altogether,  not  merely  a=? 
useless,  but  as  mi;chievous  dreaming.  Thus,  it  must  be  con- 
fessed, not  only  were  the  illegitimate  pretensions  of  the  Hegelian 
system  to  subordinate  to  itself  all  other  studies  rejected,  but  no 
regard  was  paid  to  the  rightful  claims  of  philosophy,  that  is, 
the  criticism  of  the  sources  of  cognition,  and  the  definition  of 
the  functions  of  the  intellect. 

In  the  moral  sciences  the  course  of  things  was  different, 
though  it  ultimately  led  to  almost  the  same  result.  In  all 
branches  of  those  studies,  in  theology,  politics,  jurisprudence, 
sesthetics,  philology,  there  started  up  enthusiastic  Hegelians, 
who  tried  to  reform  their  several  departments  in  accordance 
with  the  doctrines  of  their  master,  and,  by  the  royal  road  of 
speculation,  to  reach  at  once  the  promised  land  and  gather  in 
the  harvest,  which  had  hitherto  only  bean  approached  by  long 
and  laborious  study.  And  so,  for  some  time,  a  hard  and  fast 
line  was  drawn  between  the  moral  and  the  physical  sciences  ; 
in  fact,  the  very  name  of  science  was  often  denied  to  the 
latter. 

The  feud  did  not  long  subsist  in  its  original  intensity.  The 
physical  sciences  proved  conspicuously,  by  a  brilliant  series  of 
discoveries  and  practical  applications,  that  they  contained  a 
healthy  germ  of  extraordinary  fertility ;  it  was  impossible  any 
longer  to  withhold  from  them  recognition  and  respect.  And 
even  in  other  departments  of  science,  conscientious  investigators 
of  facts  soon  protested  against  the  over-bold  nights  of  specu- 
lation. Still,  it  cannot  be  overlooked  that  the  philosophy  of 
Hegel  and  Schilling  did  exercise  a  beneficial  influence ;  since  their 
time  the  attention  of  investigators  in  the  moral  sciences  had 
been  constantly  and  more  keenly  directed  to  the  scope  of  those 


8  OX  THE   RELATION   OF 

sciences,  and  to  their  intellectual  contents,  and  therefore  the 
great  amount  of  labour  bestowed  on  those  systems  has  not 
been  entirely  thrown  away. 

We  see,  then,  that  in  proportion  as  the  experimental  inves- 
tigation of  facts  has  recovered  its  importance  in  the  moral 
sciences,  the  opposition  between  them  and  the  physical  sciences 
has  become  less  and  less  marked.  Yet  we  must  not  forget 
that,  though  this  opposition  was  brought  out  in  an  unnecessarily 
exaggerated  form  by  the  Hegelian  philosophy,  it  has  its  founda- 
tion in  the  nature  of  things,  and  must,  sooner  or  later,  make 
itself  felt.  It  depends  partly  on  the  nature  of  the  intellectual 
processes  the  two  groups  of  sciences  involve,  partly,  as  their 
very  names  imply,  on  the  subjects  of  which  they  treat.  It  is 
not  easy  for  a  scientific  man  to  convey  to  a  scholar  or  a  jurist  a 
clear  idea  of  a  complicated  process  of  nature ;  he  must  demand 
of  them  a  certain  power  of  abstraction  from  the  phenomena,  as 
well  as  a  certain  skill  in  the  use  of  geometrical  and  mechanical 
conceptions,  in  which  it  is  difficult  for  them  to  follow  him.  On 
the  other  hand  an  artist  or  a  theologian  will  perhaps  find  the 
natural  philosopher  too  much  inclined  to  mechanical  and 
material  explanations,  which  seem  to  them  commonplace,  and 
chilling  to  their  feeling  and  enthusiasm.  Nor  will  the  scholar 
or  the  historian,  who  have  some  common  ground  with  the 
theologian  and  the  jurist,  fare  better  with  the  natural  philo- 
sopher. They  will  find  him  shockingly  indifferent  to  literary 
treasures,  perhaps  even  more  indifferent  than  he  ought  to  be  to 
the  history  of  his  own  science.  In  short,  there  is  no  denying 
that,  while  the  moral  sciences  deal  directly  with  the  nearest 
and  dearest  interests  of  the  human  mind,  and  with  the  insti- 
tutions it  has  brought  into  being,  the  natural  sciences  are  con- 
cerned with  dead,  indifferent  matter,  obviously  indispensable 
for  the  sake  of  its  practical  utility,  but  apparently  without  any 
immediate  bearing  on  the  cultivation  of  the  intellect. 

It  has  been  shown,  then,  that  the  sciences  have  branched 
out  into  countless  ramifications,  that  there  has  grown  up 
between  different  groups  of  them  a  real  and  deeply  felt  opposi- 
tion, that)  finally  no  single  intellect  can  embrace  the  whole  range 


NATURAL  SCIENCE  TO   GENERAL  SCIENCE.  9 

or  even  a  considerable  portion  of  it.  Is  it  still  reasonable  to 
keep  them  together  in  one  place  of  education  ?  Is  the  union 
of  the  four  faculties  to  form  one  University  a  mere  relic  of  the 
Middle  Ages?  Many  valid  arguments  have  been  adduced  for 
separating  them.  Why  not  dismiss  the  medical  faculty  to  the 
hospitals  of  our  great  towns,  the  scientific  men  to  the  Poly- 
technic Schools,  and  form  special  seminaries  for  the  theologians 
and  jurists  ?  Long  may  the  German  universities  be  preserved 
from  such  a  fate  !  Then,  indeed,  would  the  connection  between 
the  different  sciences  be  finally  broken.  How  essential  that 
connection  is,  not  only  from  an  university  point  of  view,  as 
tending  to  keep  alive  the  intellectual  energy  of  the  country,  but 
also  on  material  grounds,  to  secure  the  successful  application  of 
that  energy,  will  be  evident  from  a  few  considerations. 

First,  then,  I  would  say  that  union  of  the  different  faculties 
is  necessary  to  maintain  a  healthy  equilibrium  among  the  in- 
tellectual energies  of  students.  Each  study  tries  certain  of  our 
intellectual  faculties  more  than  the  rest,  and  strengthens  them 
accordingly  by  constant  exercise.  Bat  any  sort  of  one-sided 
development  is  attended  with  danger ;  it  disqualifies  us  for 
using  those  faculties  that  are  less  exercised,  and  so  renders  us 
less  capable  of  a  general  view ;  above  all  it  leads  us  to  overvalue 
ourselves.  Any  one  who  has  found  himself  much  more  suc- 
cessful than  others  in  some  one  department  of  intellectual  labour, 
is  apt  to  forget  that  there  are  many  other  things  which  they  can 
do  better  than  he  can :  a  mistake — I  would  have  every  student 
remember — which  is  the  worst  enemy  of  all  intellectual 
activity. 

How  many  men  of  ability  have  forgotten  to  practise  that 
criticism  of  themselves  which  is  so  essential  to  the  student,  and 
BO  hard  to  exercise,  or  have  been  completely  crippled  in  their 
progress,  because  they  have  thought  dry,  laborious  drudgery 
beneath  them,  and  have  devoted  all  their  energies  to  the  quest 
of  brilliant  theories  and  wonder-working  discoveries  !  How 
many  such  men  have  become  bitter  misanthropes,  and  put  an  end 
to  a  melancholy  existence,  because  they  have  failed  to  obtain 
among  their  fellows  that  recognition  which  must  be  won  by 


10  ON    THE   RELATION    OF 

labour  and  result?,  but  which  is  ever  withheld  from  mere  self-con- 
scious genius  !  And  the  more  isolated  a  man  is,  the  more  liable 
is  he  to  this  danger ;  while,  on  the  other  hand,  nothing  is  more 
inspiriting  than  to  feel  yourself  forced  to  strain  every  nerve  to 
win  the  admiration  of  men  whom  you,  in  your  turn,  must  admire. 

In  comparing  the  intellectual  processes  involved  in  the 
pursuit  of  the  several  branches  of  science,  we  are  struck  by 
certain  generic  differences,  dividing  one  group  of  sciences  from 
another.  At  the  same  time  it  must  not  be  forgotten  that  every 
man  of  conspicuous  ability  has  his  own  special  mental  constitution 
which  fits  him  for  one  line  of  thought  rather  than  another. 
Compare  the  work  of  two  contemporary  investigators  even 
in  closely  allied  branches  of  science,  and  you  will  generally  be 
able  to  convince  yourself  that  the  more  distinguished  the  men  are 
the  more  clearly  does  their  individuality  come  out,  and  the  less 
qualified  would  either  of  them  be  to  carry  on  the  other's  researches. 
To-day  I  cau,  of  course,  do  nothing  more  than  characterise 
some  of  the  most  general  of  these  differences. 

I  have  already  noticed  the  enormous  mass  of  the  materials 
accumulated  by  science.  It  is  obvious  that  the  organisation 
and  arrangement  of  them  must  be  proportionately  perfect,  if 
we  are  not  to  be  hopelessly  lost  in  the  maze  of  erudition. 
One  of  the  reasons  why  we  can  so  far  surpass  our  predecessors 
in  each  individual  study  is  that  they  have  shown  us  how  to 
organise  our  knowledge. 

This  organisation  consists,  in  the  first  place,  of  a  mechanical 
arrangement  of  materials,  such  as  is  to  be  found  in  our  cata- 
logues, lexicons,  registers,  indexes,  digests,  scientific  and  literary 
annuals,  systems  of  natural  history,  and  the  like.  By  these 
appliances  thus  much  at  least  is  gained,  that  such  know- 
ledge as  cannot  be  carried  about  in  the  memory  is  immedi- 
ately accessible  to  anyone  who  wants  it.  With  a  good  lexicon  u 
school-boy  of  the  present  day  can  achieve  results  in  the  inter- 
pretation of  the  classics  which  an  Erasmus,  with  the  erudition 
of  a  lifetime,  could  hardly  attain.  Works  of  this  kind  form,  so 
to  speak,  our  intellectual  principal  with  the  interest  of  which 
we  trade :  it  is,  so  to  speak,  like  capital  invested  in  land.  The 


NATURAL   SCIENCE  TO    GENERAL   SCIENCE.  11 

[earning  buried  in  catalogues,  lexicons,  and  indexes  looks  as 
bare  and  uninviting  as  the  soil  of  a  farm  ;  the  uninitiated  cannot 
Bee  or  appreciate  the  labour  and  capital  already  invested  there ; 
to  them  the  work  of  the  ploughman  seems  infinitely  dull,  weary, 
and  monotonous.  But  though  the  compiler  of  a  lexicon  or  of 
a  system  of  natural  history  must  be  prepared  to  encounter 
labour  as  weary  and  as  obstinate  as  the  ploughman's,  yet  it 
need  not  be  supposed  that  his  work  is  of  a  low  type,  or  that  it  is 
by  any  means  as  dry  and  mechanical  as  it  looks  when  we  have 
it  before  us  in  black  and  white.  In  this,  as  in  any  other  sort  of 
scientific  work,  it  is  necessary  to  discover  every  fact  by  careful 
observation,  then  to  verify  and  collate  them,  and  to  separate 
what  is  important  from  what  is  not.  All  this  requires  a 
man  with  a  thorough  grasp  both  of  the  object  of  the 
compilation  and  of  the  matter  and  methods  of  the  science; 
and  for  such  a  man  every  detail  has  its  bearing  on  the 
whole,  and  its  special  interest.  Otherwise  dictionary-making 
would  be  the  vilest  drudgery  imaginable.1  That  the  influence 
of  the  progressive  development  of  scientific  ideas  extends  to 
these  works  is  obvious  from  the  constant  demand  for  new 
lexicons,  new  natural  histories,  new  digests,  new  catalogues  of 
stars,  all  denoting  advancement  in  the  art  of  methodising  and 
organising  science. 

But  our  knowledge  is  not  to  lie  dormant  in  the  shape  of 
catalogues.  The  very  fact  that  we  must  carry  it  about  in  black 
and  white  shows  that  our  intellectual  mastery  of  it  is  incomplete. 
It  is  not  enough  to  be  acquainted  with  the  facts;  scientific 
knowledge  begins  only  when  their  laws  and  their  causes  are  un- 
veiled. Our  materials  must  be  worked  up  by  a  logical  process; 
and  the  first  step  is  to  connect  like  with  like,  and  to  elaborate  a 
general  conception  embracing  them  all.  Such  a  conception,  as 
the  name  implies,  takes  a  number  of  single  facts  together,  and 
stands  as  their  representative  in  our  mind.  We  call  it  a  general 
conception,  or  the  conception  of  a  genus,  when  it  embraces  a 
number  of  existing  objects;  we  call  it  a  law  when  it  embraces  a 
beries  of  incidents  or  occurrences.  When,  for  example,  I  havo 
1  Condendaque  lexi^a  mandat  damnatis. — TB. 


12  OX   THE   RELATION   OF 

made  out  that  all  mammals — that  is,  all  warm-blooded,  vivi- 
parous animals — breathe  through  lungs,  have  two  chambers  in 
the  heart,  and  at  least  three  tympana]  bones,  I  need  no  longer 
remember  these  anatomical  peculiarities  in  the  individual  cases 
of  the  monkey,  the  dog,  the  horse,  and  the  whale;  the  general 
rule  includes  a  vast  number  of  single  instances,  and  represents 
them  in  my  memory.  V/hen  I  enunciate  the  law  of  refraction, 
not  only  does  this  law  embrace  all  cases  of  rays  falling  at  all 
possible  angles  on  a  plane  surface  of  water,  and  inform  me  of 
the  result,  but  it  includes  all  cases  of  rays  of  any  colour  incident 
on  transparent  surfaces  of  any  form  and  any  constitution  what- 
soever. This  law,  therefore,  includes  an  infinite  number  of 
cases,  which  it  would  have  been  absolutely  impossible  to  carry 
in  one's  memory.  Moreover,  it  should  be  noticed  that  not  only 
does  this  law  include  the  cases  which  we  ourselves  or  other  men 
have  already  observed,  but  that  we  shall  not  hesitate  to  apply  it 
to  new  cases,  not  yet  observed,  with  absolute  confidence  in  the 
reliability  of  our  results.  In  the  same  way,  if  we  were  to  find 
a  new  species  of  mammal,  not  yet  dissected,  we  are  entitled  to 
assume,  with  a  confidence  bordering  on  a  certainty,  that  it  has 
lungs,  two  chambers  in  the  heart,  and  three  or  more  tympanal 
bones. 

Thus,  when  we  combine  the  results  of  experience  by  a  pro- 
cess of  thought,  and  form  conceptions,  whether  general  concep- 
tions or  laws,  we  not  only  bring  our  knowledge  into  a  form  in 
which  it  can  be  easily  used  and  easily  retained,  but  we  actually 
enlarge  it,  inasmuch  as  we  feel  ourselves  entitled  to  extend  the 
rules  and  the  laws  we  have  discovered  to  all  similar  cases  that 
may  be  hereafter  presented  to  us. 

The  above-mentioned  examples  are  of  a  class  in  which  the 
mental  process  of  combining  a  number  of  single  cases  so  as  to 
form  conceptions  is  unattended  by  farther  difficulties,  and  can  be 
distinctly  followed  in  all  its  stages.  But  in  complicated  cases  it 
is  not  so  easy  completely  to  separate  like  facts  from  unlike,  and 
to  combine  them  into  a  clear  well-defined  conception.  Assume 
that  we  know  a  man  to  be  ambitious ;  we  shall  perhaps  be  able 
to  predict  with  tolerable  certainty  that  if  he  has  to  act  under 


NATURAL  SCIENCE  TO  GENERAL  SCIENCE.  13 

certain  conditions,  he  will  follow  the  dictates  of  his  ambition, 
and  decide  on  a  certain  line  of  action.  But,  in  the  first  place, 
we  cannot  define  with  absolute  precision  what  constitutes  an 
ambitious  man,  or  by  what  standard  the  intensity  of  his  ambition 
is  to  be  measured;  nor,  again,  can  we  say  precisely  what  degree 
of  ambition  must  operate  in  order  to  impress  the  given  direction, 
on  the  actions  of  the  man  under  those  particular  circumstances. 
Accordingly,  we  institute  comparisons  between  the  actions  of 
the  man  in  question,  as  far  as  we  have  hitherto  observed  them, 
and  those  of  other  men  who  in  similar  cases  have  acted  as  he 
has  done,  and  we  draw  our  inference  respecting  his  future  actions 
without  being  able  to  express  either  the  major  or  the  minor  pre- 
miss in  a  clear,  sharply  defined  form — perhaps  even  without  hav- 
ing convinced  ourselves  that  our  anticipation  rests  on  such  an 
analogy  as  I  have  described.  In  such  cases  our  decision  proceeds 
only  from  a  certain  psychological  instinct,  not  from  conscious 
reasoning,  though  in  reality  we  have  gone  through  an  intellectual 
process  identical  with  that  which  leads  us  to  assume  that  a 
newly  discovered  mammal  has  lungs. 

This  latter  kind  of  induction,  which  can  never  be  perfectly 
assimilated  to  forms  of  logical  reasoning,  nor  pressed  so  far  as  to 
establish  universal  laws,  plays  a  most  important  part  in  human 
life.  The  whole  of  the  process  by  which  we  translate  our  sen- 
sations into  perceptions  depends  upon  it,  as  appears  especially 
from  the  investigation  of  what  are  called  illusions.  For  in- 
stance, when  the  retina  of  the  eye  is  irritated  by  a  blow,  we 
imagine  we  see  a  light  in  our  field  of  vision,  because  we  have, 
throughout  our  lives,  felt  irritation  in  the  optic  nerves  only 
when  there  was  light  in  the  field  of  vision,  and  have  become 
accustomed  to  identify  the  sensations  of  those  nerves  with  the 
presence  of  light  in  the  field  of  vision.  Moreover,  such  is  the 
complexity  of  the  influences  affecting  the  formation  both  of 
character  in  general  and  of  the  mental  condition  at  any  given 
moment,  that  this  same  kind  of  induction  necessarily  plays  a 
leading  part  in  the  investigation  of  psychological  processes.  In 
fact,  in  ascribing  to  ourselves  free-will,  that  is,  full  power  to  act 
as  we  please  without  being  subject  to  a  stern  inevitable  law  of 


14  OX   THE   RELATION   OF 

causality,  we  deny  in  toto  the  possiblity  of  referring  at  least  one 
of  the  ways  in  which  our  mental  activity  expresses  itself  to  a 
rigorous  law. 

We  might  possibly,  in  opposition  to  logical  induction  which 
reduces  a  question  to  clearly  defined  universal  propositions,  call 
this  kind  of  reasoning  (esthetic  induction,  because  it  is  most  con- 
spicuous in  the  higher  class  of  works  of  art.  It  is  an  essential 
part  of  an  artist's  talent  to  reproduce  by  words,  by  form,  by 
colour,  or  by  music,  the  external  indications  of  a  character  or  a 
state  of  mind,  and  by  a  kind  of  instinctive  intuition,  uncon- 
trolled by  any  definable  rule,  to  seize  the  necessary  steps  by 
which  we  pass  from  one  mood  to  another.  If  we  do  find  that 
the  artist  has  consciously  worked  after  general  rules  and  abstrac- 
tions, we  think  his  work  poor  and  commonplace,  and  cease  to 
admire.  On  the  contrary,  the  works  of  great  artists  bring  be- 
fore us  characters  and  moods  with  such  a  lifelikeness,  with  such 
a  wealth  of  individual  traits  and  such  an  overwhelming  con- 
viction of  truth,  that  they  almost  seem  to  be  more  real  than  the 
reality  itself,  because  all  disturbing  influences  are  eliminated. 

Now  if,  after  these  reflections,  we  proceed  to  review  the 
different  sciences,  nnd  to  classify  them  according  to  the  method 
by  which  they  must  arrive  at  their  results,  we  are  brought  face 
to  face  with  a  generic  difference  between  the  natural  and  the 
moral  sciences.  The  natural  sciences  are  for  the  most  part  in 
a  position  to  reduce  their  inductions  to  sharply  defined  general 
rules  and  principles;  the  ir  oral  sciences,  on  the  other  hand,  have, 
in  by  far  the  most  numerous  cases,  to  do  with  conclusions 
arrived  at  by  psychological  instinct.  Philology,  in  so  far  as  it 
is  concerned  with  the  interpretation  and  emendation  of  the 
texts  handed  down  to  us,  must  seek  to  feel  out,  as  it  were,  the 
meaning  which  the  author  intended  to  express,  and  the  accessory 
notions  which  he  wished  his  words  to  suggest :  and  for  that  pur- 
pose it  is  necessary  to  start  with  a  correct  insight,  both  into  the 
personality  of  the  author,  and  into  the  genius  of  the  language 
in  which  he  wrote.  All  this  affords  scope  for  aesthetic,  but 
not  for  strictly  logical,  induction.  It  is  only  possible  to  pass 
judgment,  if  you  have  ready  in  your  memory  a  great  number  of 


NATURAL   SCIENCE   TO   GENERAL   SCIENCE.  15 

similar  facts,  to  be  instantaneously  confronted  with  the  question 
you  are  trying  to  solve.  Accordingly,  one  of  the  first  requisites 
for  studies  of  this  class  ia  an  accurate  and  ready  memory. 
Many  celebrated  historians  and  philologists  have,  in  fact, 
astounded  their  contemporaries  by  their  extraordinary  strength  of 
memory.  Of  course  memory  alone  is  insufficient  without  a 
knack  of  everywhere  discovering  real  resemblance,  and  without 
a  delicately  and  fully  trained  insight  into  the  springs  of  human 
action ;  while  this  again  is  unattainable  without  a  certain 
warmth  of  sympathy  and  an  interest  in  observing  the  working 
of  other  men's  minds.  Intercourse  with  our  follow-men  in 
daily  life  must  lay  the  foundation  of  this  insight,  but  the  study 
of  history  and  art  serves  to  make  it  richer  and  completer,  for 
there  we  see  men  acting  under  comparatively  unusual  conditions, 
and  thus  come  to  appreciate  the  full  scope  of  the  energies  which 
lie  hidden  in  our  breasts. 

None  of  this  group  of  sciences,  except  grammar,  lead  us,  as  a 
rule,  to  frame  and  enunciate  general  laws,  valid  under  all  circum- 
stances. The  laws  of  grammar  are  a  product  of  the  human 
will,  though  they  can  hardly  be  said  to  have  been  framed  de- 
liberately, but  rather  to  have  grown  up  gradually,  as  they  were 
wanted.  Accordingly,  they  present  themselves  to  a  learner 
rather  in  the  form  of  commands,  that  is,  of  laws  imposed  by 
external  authority. 

With  these  sciences  theology  and  jurisprudence  are  naturally 
connected.  In  fact,  certain  branches  of  history  and  philology 
serve  both  as  stepping-stones  and  as  handmaids  to  them.  The 
general  laws  of  theology  and  jurisprudence  are  likewise  com- 
mands, laws  imposed  by  external  authority  to  regulate,  from  a 
moral  or  juridical  point  of  view,  the  actions  of  mankind;  not 
laws  which,  like  those  of  nature,  contain  generalisations  from  a 
vast  multitude  of  facts.  At  the  same  time  the  application  of  a 
grammatical,  legal,  moral,  or  theological  rule  is  couched,  like  the 
application  of  a  law  of  nature  to  a  paiticular  case,  in  the  forms  of 
logical  inference.  The  rule  forms  the  major  premiss  of  the 
syllogism,  while  the  minor  must  settle  whether  the  case  in  ques- 
tion satisfies  the  conditions  to  which  the  rule  is  intended  to 


16  ON   THE   RELATION   OF 

apply.  The  solution  of  this  latter  problem,  whether  in  gram- 
matical analysis,  where  the  meaning  of  a  sentence  is  to  be 
evolved,  or  in  the  legal  criticism  of  the  credibility  of  the  facts 
alleged,  of  the  intentions  of  the  parties,  or  of  the  meaning  of 
the  documents  they  have  put  into  court,  will,  in  most  cases,  be 
again  a  matter  of  psychological  insight.  On  the  other  hand,  it 
should  not  be  forgotten  that  both  the  syntax  of  fully  developed 
languages  and  a  system  of  jurisprudence  gradually  elaborated,  as 
ours  has  been,  by  the  practice  of  more  than  2,000  years,1  have 
reached  a  high  pitch  of  logical  completeness  and  consistency;  so 
that,  speaking  generally,  the  cases  which  do  not  obviously  fall 
under  some  one  or  other  of  the  laws  actually  laid  down  are  quite 
exceptional.  Such  exceptions  there  will  always  be,  for  the  legis- 
lation of  man  can  never  have  the  absolute  consistency  and 
perfection  of  the  laws  of  nature.  In  such  cases  there  is  no 
course  open  but  to  try  and  guess  the  intention  of  the  legislator ; 
or,  if  needs  be,  to  supplement  it  after  the  analogy  of  his  decisions 
in  similar  cases. 

Grammar  and  jurisprudence  have  a  certain  advantage  as 
means  of  training  the  intellect,  inasmuch  as  they  tax  pretty 
equally  all  the  intellectual  powers.  On  this  account  secondary 
education  among  modern  European  nations  is  based  mainly 
upon  the  grammatical  study  of  foreign  languages.  The  mother- 
tongue  and  modern  foreign  languages,  when  acquired  solely  by 
practice,  do  not  call  for  any  conscious  logical  exercise  of  thought, 
though  we  may  cultivate  by  means  of  them  an  appreciation  for 
artistic  beauty  of  expression.  The  two  classical  languages, 
Latin  and  Greek,  have,  besides  their  exquisite  logical  subtlety 
and  aesthetic  beauty,  an  additional  advantage,  which  they  seem 
to  possess  in  common  with  most  ancient  and  original  languages 
— they  indicate  accurately  the  relations  of  words  and  sentences 
to  each  other  by  numerous  and  distinct  inflexions.  Languages 
are,  as  it  were,  abraded  by  long  use ;  grammatical  distinctions 
are  cut  down  to  a  minimum  for  the  sake  of  brevity  and  rapidity 

i  It  should  be  remembered  that  the  Roman  law,  which  has  only  partially 
and  indirectly  influenced  English  practice,  is  the  recognised  basis  of  German 
jurisprudence. — TB. 


NATURAL   SCIENCE   TO   GENERAL   SCIENCE.  17 

of  expression,  and  are  thus  made  less  and  less  definite,  as  is 
obvious  from  the  comparison  of  any  modern  European  language 
with  Latin;  in  English  the  process  has  gone  further  than  in 
any  other.  This  seems  to  me  to  be  really  the  reason  why  the 
modern  languages  are  far  less  fitted  than  the  ancient  for  instru- 
ments of  education.1 

As  grammar  is  the  staple  of  school  education,  legal  studies 
are  used,  and  rightly,  as  a  means  of  training  persons  of  maturer 
age,  even  when  not  specially  required  for  professional  purposes. 

We  now  come  to  those  sciences  which,  in  respect  of  the  kind 
of  intellectual  labour  they  require,  stand  at  the  opposite  end 
of  the  series  to  philology  and  history ;  namely,  the  natural  and 
physical  sciences.  I  do  not  mean  to  say  that  in  many  branches 
even  of  these  sciences  an  instinctive  appreciation  of  analogies 
and  a  certain  artistic  sense  have  no  part  to  play.  On  the 
contrary,  in  natural  history  the  decision  which  characteristics 
are  to  be  looked  upon  as  important  for  classification,  and  which 
as  unimportant,  what  divisions  of  the  animal  and  vegetable 
kingdoms  are  more  natural  than  others,  is  really  left  to  an 
instinct  of  this  kind,  acting  without  any  strictly  definable  rule. 
And  it  is  a  very  suggestive  fact  that  it  was  an  artist,  Goethe, 
who  gave  the  first  impulse  to  the  researches  of  comparative 
anatomy  into  the  analogy  of  corresponding  organs  in  different 
animals,  and  to  the  parallel  theory  of  the  metamorphosis  of 
leaves  in  the  vegetable  kingdom;  and  thus,  in  fact,  really 
pointed  out  the  direction  which  the  science  has  followed  ever 
since.  But  even  in  those  departments  of  science  where  we 
have  to  do  with  the  least  understood  vital  processes,  it  is, 
speaking  generally,  far  easier  to  make  out  general  and  compre- 
hensive ideas  and  principles,  and  to  express  them  in  definite 
language,  than  in  cases  where  we  must  base  our  judgment  on 
the  analysis  of  the  human  mind.  It  is  only  when  we  come  to 
the  experimental  sciences  to  which  mathematics  are  applied, 
and  especially  when  we  come  to  pure  mathematics,  that  we 

1  Those  to  whom  German  is  not  a  foreign  tongue  may,  perhaps,  be  per- 
mitted to  hold  different  views  on  the  efficacy  of  modern  languages  in  educa- 
tion.—TR. 

I.  O 


18  OX   THE   RELATION   OF 

see  the  peculiar   characteristics  of  the  natural  and   physical 
sciences  fully  brought  out. 

The  essential  differentia  of  these  sciences  seems  to  me  to 
consist  in  the  comparative  ease  with  which  the  individual 
results  of  observation  and  experiment  are  combined  under 
general  laws  of  unexceptionable  validity  and  of  an  extra- 
ordinarily comprehensive  character.  In  the  moral  sciences,  on 
the  other  hand,  this  is  just  the  point  where  insuperable  diffi- 
culties are  encountered.  In  mathematics  the  general  propo- 
sitions which,  under  the  name  of  axioms,  stand  at  the  head  of 
the  reasoning,  are  so  few  in  number,  so  comprehensive,  and  so 
immediately  obvious,  that  no  proof  whatever  is  needed  for 
them.  Let  me  remind  you  that  the  whole  of  algebra  and 
aiithmetic  is  developed  out  of  the  three  axioms  : — 

'  Things  which  are  equal  to  the  same  things  are  equal  to 
one  another.' 

'  If  equals  be  added  to  equals,  the  wholes  are  equal.' 

'  If  unequals  be  added  to  equals,  the  wholes  are  unequal.' 
And  the  axioms  of  geometry  and  mechanics  are  not  more 
numerous.  The  sciences  we  have  named  are  developed  out  ot 
these  few  axioms  by  a  continual  process  of  deduction  from 
them  in  more  and  more  complicated  cases.  Algebra,  however, 
does  not  confine  itsslf  to  finding  the  sum  of  the  most  hetero- 
geneous combinations  of  a  finite  number  of  magnitudes,  but  in 
the  higher  analysis  it  teaches  us  to  sum  even  infinite  series, 
he  terms  of  which  increase  or  diminish  according  to  the  most 
various  laws ;  to  solve,  in  fact,  problems  which  could  never  be 
completed  by  direct  addition.  An  instance  of  this  kind  shows 
us  the  conscious  logical  activity  of  the  mind  in  its  purest  and 
most  perfect  form.  On  the  one  hand  we  see  the  laborious  nature 
of  the  process,  the  extreme  caution  with  which  it  is  necessary 
to  advance,  the  accuracy  required  to  determine  exactly  the 
scope  of  such  universal  principles  as  have  been  attained,  the 
difficulty  of  forming  and  understanding  abstract  conceptions. 
On  the  other  hand,  we  gain  confidence  in  the  certainty,  the 
range,  and  the  fertility  of  this  kind  of  intellectual  work. 

The  fertility  of  the  method  comes  out  moie  strikingly  in 


NATURAL   SCIENCE   TO    GENERAL   SCIENCE.  1'J 

applied  mathematics,  especially  in  mathematical  physics,  in- 
cluding, of  course,  physical  astronomy.  From  the  time  when 
Xewton  discovered,  by  analysing  the  motions  of  the  planets  on 
mechanical  principles,  that  every  particle  of  ponderable  matter 
in  the  universe  attracts  every  other  particle  with  a  force  vary- 
ing inversely  as  the  square  of  the  distance,  astronomers  have 
been  able,  in  virtue  of  that  one  law  of  gravitation,  to  calculate 
with  the  greatest  accuracy  the  movements  of  the  planets  to  the 
remotest  past  and  the  most  distant  future,  given  only  the  posi- 
tion, velocity,  and  mass  of  each  body  of  our  system  at  any  one 
time.  More  than  that,  we  recognise  the  operation  of  this  la\v 
in  the  movements  of  double  stars,  whose  distances  from  us  are 
so  great  that  their  light  takes  years  to  reach  us ;  in  some 
cases,  indeed,  so  great  that  all  attempts  to  measure  them  have 
failed. 

This  discovery  of  the  law  of  gravitation  and  its  consequences 
is  the  most  imposing  achievement  that  the  logical  power  of  the 
human  mind  has  hitherto  performed.  I  do  not  mean  to  say 
that  there  have  not  been  men  who  in  power  of  abstraction  have 
equalled  or  even  surpassed  Newton  and  the  other  astronomers, 
who  either  paved  the  way  for  his  discovery,  or  have  carried  it 
out  to  its  legitimate  consequences ;  but  there  has  never  been 
presented  to  the  human  mind  such  an  admirable  subject  as 
those  involved  and  complex  movements  of  the  planets,  which 
hitherto  had  served  merely  as  food  for  the  astrological  super- 
stitions of  ignorant  star-gazers,  and  were  now  reduced  to  a  single 
law,  capable  of  rendering  the  most  exact  account  of  the  minutest 
detail  of  their  motions. 

The  principles  of  this  magnificent  discovery  have  been  suc- 
cessfully applied  to  several  other  physical  sciences,  among  which 
physical  optics  and  the  theory  of  electricity  and  magnetism  are 
especially  worthy  of  notice.  The  experimental  sciences  have 
one  great  advantage  over  the  natural  sciences  in  the  investiga- 
tion of  general  laws  of  nature  :  they  can  change  at  pleasure  the 
conditions  under  which  a  given  result  takes  place,  and  can  thus 
confine  themselves  to  a  small  number  of  characteristic  instances, 
in  order  to  discover  the  law.  Of  course  its  validity  must  then 
c  '2 


20  ON   THE    RELATION   OF 

stand  the  test  of  application  to  more  complex  cases.  Accord- 
ingly the  physical  sciences,  when  once  the  right  methods  have 
been  discovered,  have  made  proportionately  rapid  progress. 
Not  only  have  they  allowed  us  to  look  back  into  primaeval 
chaos,  where  nebulous  masses  were  forming  themselves  into 
suns  and  planets,  and  becoming  heated  by  the  energy  of  their 
contraction;  not  only  have  they  permitted  us  to  investigate 
the  chemical  constituents  of  the  solar  atmosphere  and  of  the 
remotest  fixed  stars,  but  they  have  enabled  us  to  turn  the 
forces  of  surrounding  nature  to  our  own  uses  and  to  make  them 
the  ministers  of  our  will. 

Enough  has  been  said  to  show  how  widely  the  intellectual 
processes  involved  in  this  group  of  sciences  differ,  for  the  most 
part,  from  those  required  by  the  moral  sciences.  The  mathe- 
matician need  have  no  memory  whatever  for  detached  facts,  the 
physicist  hardly  any.  Hypotheses  based  on  the  recollection  of 
similar  cases  may,  indeed,  be  useful  to  guide  one  into  the  right 
track,  but  they  have  no  real  value  till  they  have  led  to  a  precise 
and  strictly  defined  law.  Nature  does  not  allow  us  for  a  moment 
to  doubt  that  we  have  to  do  with  a  rigid  chain  of  cause  and 
effect,  admitting  of  no  exceptions.  Therefore  to  us,  as  her 
students,  goes  forth  the  mandate  to  labour  on  till  we  have  dis- 
covered unvarying  laws ;  till  then  we  dare  not  rest  satisfied,  for 
then  only  can  our  knowledge  grapple  victoriously  with  time 
and  space  and  the  forces  of  the  universe. 

The  iron  labour  of  conscious  logical  reasoning  demands  great 
perseverance  and  great  caution ;  it  moves  on  but  slowly,  and  is 
rarely  illuminated  by  brilliant  flashes  of  genius.  It  knows 
little  of  that  facility  with  which  the  most  varied  instances  come 
thronging  into  the  memory  of  the  philologist  or  the  historian. 
Rather  is  it  an  essential  condition  of  the  methodical  progress  of 
mathematical  reasoning  that  the  mind  should  remain  concen- 
trated on  a  single  point,  undisturbed  alike  by  collateral  ideas  on 
the  one  hand,  and  by  wishes  and  hopes  on  the  other,  and  moving 
on  steadily  in  the  direction  it  has  deliberately  chosen.  A  cele- 
brated logician,  Mr.  John  Stuart  Mill,  expresses  his  conviction 
that  the  inductive  sciences  have  of  late  done  more  for  the  advance 


NATURAL   SCIENCE   TO    GENERAL   SCIENCE.  21 

of  logical  methods  than  the  labours  of  philosophers  properly  so 
called.  One  essential  ground  for  such  an  assertion  must  un- 
doubtedly be  that  in  no  department  of  knowledge  can  a  fault 
in  the  chain  of  reasoning  be  so  easily  detected  by  the  incorrect- 
ness of  the  results  as  in  those  sciences  in  which  the  results  of 
reasoning  can  be  most  directly  compared  with  the  facts  of 
nature. 

Though  I  have  maintained  that  it  is  in  the  physical  sciences, 
and  especially  in  such  branches  of  them  as  are  treated  mathe- 
matically, that  the  solution  of  scientific  problems  has  been  most 
successfully  achieved,  you  will  not,  I  trust,  imagine  that  I  wish 
to  depreciate  other  studies  in  comparison  with  them.  If  the 
natural  and  physical  sciences  have  the  advantage  of  great  per- 
fection in  form,  it  is  the  privilege  of  the  moral  sciences  to  deal 
with  a  richer  material,  with  questions  that  touch  more  nearly 
the  interests  and  the  feelings  of  men,  with  the  human  mind 
itself,  in  fact,  in  its  motives  and  the  different  branches  of  its 
activity.  They  have,  indeed,  the  loftier  and  the  more  difficult 
task,  but  yet  they  cannot  afford  to  lose  sight  of  the  example  of 
their  rivals,  which,  in  form  at  least,  have,  owing  to  the  more 
ductile  nature  of  their  materials,  made  greater  progress.  Not 
only  have  they  something  to  learn  from  them  in  point  of  method, 
but  they  may  also  draw  encouragement  from  the  greatness  of 
their  results.  And  I  do  think  that  our  age  has  learnt  many 
lessons  from  the  physical  sciences.  The  absolute,  unconditional 
reverence  for  facts,  and  the  fidelity  with  which  they  are  col- 
lected, a  certain  distrustfulness  of  appearances,  the  effort  to 
detect  in  all  cases  relations  of  cause  and  effect,  and  the  tendency 
to  assume  their  existence,  which  distinguish  our  century  from 
preceding  ones,  seem  to  me  to  point  to  such  an  influence. 

I  do  not  intend  to  go  deeply  into  the  question  how  fir 
mathematical  studies,  as  the  representatives  of  conscious  logical 
reasoning,  should  take  a  more  important  place  in  school  educa- 
tion. But  it  is,  in  reality,  one  of  the  questions  of  the  day.  ID 
proportion  as  the  range  of  science  extends,  its  system  and  or- 
ganisation must  be  improved,  and  it  must  inevitably  come  about 
that  individual  students  will  find  themselves  compelled  to  go 


22  OX  THE   RELATION   OF 

through  a  stricter  course  of  training  than  grammar  is  in  a 
position  to  supply.  What  strikes  me  in  my  own  experience 
of  students  who  pass  from  our  classical  schools  to  scientific  and 
medical  studies,  is,  first,  a  certain  laxity  in  the  application  of 
strictly  universal  laws.  The  grammatical  rules  in  which  they 
have  been  exercised  are  for  the  mcst  part  followed  by  long 
lists  of  exceptions;  accordingly  they  are  not  in  the  habit  of 
relying  implicitly  on  the  certainty  of  a  legitimate  deduction 
from  a  strictly  universal  law.  Secondly,  I  find  them  for  the 
most  part  too  much  inclined  to  trust  to  authority,  even  in  cases 
where  they  might  form  an  independent  judgment.  In  fact,  in 
philological  studies,  inasmuch  as  it  is  seldom  possible  to  take  in 
the  whole  of  the  premisses  at  a  glance,  and  inasmuch  as  the  de- 
cision of  disputed  questions  often  depends  on  an  aesthetic  feeling 
for  beauty  of  expression,  and  for  the  genius  of  the  language, 
attainable  only  by  long  training,  it  must  often  happen  that  the 
student  is  referred  to  authorities  even  by  the  best  teachers. 
Both  faults  are  traceable  to  a  certain  indolence  and  vagueness 
of  thought,  the  sad  effects  of  which  are  not  confined  to  sub- 
sequent scientific  studies.  But  certainly  the  best  remedy  for 
both  is  to  be  found  in  mathematics,  where  there  is  absolute 
certainty  in  the  reasoning,  and  no  authority  is  recognised  but 
that  of  one's  own  intelligence. 

So  much  for  the  several  branches  of  science  considered  as 
exercises  for  the  intellect,  and  as  supplementing  each  other  in 
that  respect.  But  knowledge  is  not  the  sole  object  of  man  upon 
earth.  Though  the  sciences  arouse  and  educate  the  subtlest 
powers  of  the  mind,  yet  a  man  who  should  study  simply  for  the 
sake  of  knowing,  would  assuredly  not  fulfil  the  purpose  of  his 
existence.  We  cften  see  men  of  considerable  endowments,  to 
whom  their  good  or  bad  fortune  has  secured  a  comfortable 
livelihood  or  good  social  position,  without  giving  them,  at  the 
same  time,  ambition  or  energy  enough  to  make  them  work, 
dragging  out  a  weary,  unsatisfied  existence,  while  all  the  time 
they  fancy  they  are  following  the  noblest  aim  of  life  by  constantly 
devoting  themselves  to  the  increase  of  their  knowledge,  and  the 
cultivation  of  their  minds.  Action  alone  gives  a  man  a  lifo 


NATURAL   SCIENCE   TO   GENERAL   SCIENCE.  23 

worth  living ;  and  therefore  he  must  aim  either  at  the  practical 
application  of  his  knowledge,  or  at  the  extension  of  the  limits 
of  science  itself.  For  to  extend  the  limits  of  science  is  really  to 
work  for  the  progress  of  humanity.  Thus  we  pass  to  the  second 
link,  uniting  the  different  sciences,  the  connection,  namely, 
between  the  subjects  of  which  they  treat. 

Know-ledge  is  power.  Our  age,  more  than  any  other,  is  in  a 
position  to  demonstrate  the  truth  of  this  maxim.  We  have 
taught  the  forces  of  inanimate  nature  to  minister  to  the  wants 
vrf  human  life  and  the  designs  of  the  human  intellect.  The 
application  of  steam  has  multiplied  our  physical  strength  a 
million-fold ;  weaving  and  spinning  machines  have  relieved  us 
of  labours  the  only  merit  of  which  consisted  in  a  deadening 
monotony.  The  intercourse  between  men,  with  its  far-reaching 
influence  on  material  and  intellectual  progress,  has  increased  to 
an  extent  of  which  no  one  could  have  even  dreamed  within  the 
lifetime  of  the  older  among  us.  But  it  is  not  merely  on  the 
machines  by  which  our  powers  are  multiplied ;  not  merely  on 
rifled  cannon  and  armour-plated  ships;  not  merely  on  accumu- 
lated stores  of  money  and  the  necessaries  of  life,  that  the  power  of 
a  nation  rests  :  though  these  things  have  exercised  so  unmistak- 
able an  influence  that  even  the  proudest  and  most  obstinate  des- 
j  >otisms  of  our  times  have  been  forced  to  think  of  removing  restric- 
tions on  industry,  and  of  conceding  to  the  industrious  middle  classes 
a  due  voice  in  their  councils.  But  political  organisation,  the 
administration  of  justice,  and  the  moral  discipline  of  individual 
citizens  are  no  less  important  conditions  of  the  preponderance 
of  civilised  nations ;  and  so  surely  as  a  nation  remains  in- 
accessible to  the  influences  of  civilisation  in  these  respects,  so 
surely  is  it  on  the  high  road  to  destruction.  The  several  con- 
ditions of  national  prosperity  act  and  react  on  each  other; 
where  the  administration  of  justice  is  uncertain,  where  the 
interests  of  the  majority  cannot  be  asserted  by  legitimate  means, 
the  development  of  the  national  resources,  and  of  the  power 
depending  upon  them,  is  impossible ;  nor,  again,  is  it  possible 
to  make  good  soldiers  except  out  of  men  who  have  learnt  under 
just  laws  to  educate  the  sense  of  honour  that  characterises  an 


24  OX   THE   RELATION   OF 

independent  man,  certainly  not  out  of  those  who  nave  lived  the 
submissive  slaves  of  a  capricious  tyrant. 

Accordingly  every  nation  is  interested  in  the  progress  of  know 
ledge  on  the  simple  ground  of  self-preservation,  even  were  there  no 
higher  .wants  of  an  ideal  character  to  be  satisfied;  and  not  merely 
in  the  development  of  the  physical  sciences,  and  their  technical 
application,  but  also  in  the  progress  of  legal,  political,  and  moral 
sciences,  and  of  the  accessory  historical  and  philological  studies. 
No  nation  which  would  be  independent  and  influential  can  afford 
to  be  left  behind  in  the  race.  Nor  has  this  escaped  the  notice  of  the 
cultivated  peoples  of  Europe.  Never  before  was  so  large  a  part 
of  the  public  resources  devoted  to  universities,  schools,  and 
scientific  institutions.  We  in  Heidelberg  have  this  year  occasion 
to  congratulate  ourselves  on  another  rich  endowment  granted  by 
our  government  and  our  parliament. 

I  "svas  speaking,  at  the  beginning  of  my  address,  of  the  in- 
creasing division  of  labour  and  the  improved  organisation  among 
scientific  workers.  In  fact,  men  of  science  form,  as  it  were,  an 
organised  army  labouring  on  behalf  of  the  whole  nation,  and 
generally  under  its  direction  and  at  its  expense,  to  augment  the 
stock  of  such  knowledge  as  may  serve  to  promote  industrial 
enterprise,  to  increase  wealth,  to  adorn  life,  to  improve  political  and 
social  relations,  and  to  further  the  moral  development  of  indivi- 
dual citizens.  After  the  immediate  practical  results  of  their  work 
we  forbear  to  inquire ;  that  we  leave  to  the  uninstructed.  "We 
are  convinced  that  whatever  contributes  to  the  knowledge  of 
the  forces  of  nature  or  the  powers  of  the  human  mind  is  worth 
cherishing,  and  may,  in  its  own  due  time,  bear  practical  fruit, 
very  often  where  we  should  least  have  expected  it.  Who,  when 
Galvani  touched  the  muscles  of  a  frog  with  different  metals, 
and  noticed  their  contraction,  could  have  dreamt  that  eighty 
years  afterwards,  in  virtue  of  the  self-same  process,  whose 
earliest  manifestations  attracted  his  attention  in  his  anatomical 
researches,  all  Europe  would  be  traversed  with  wires,  flashing 
intelligence  from  Madrid  to  St.  Petersburg  with  the  speed  of 
lightning?  In  the  hands  of  Galvani,  and  at  first  even  in 
Volta's,  electrical  currents  were  phenomena  capable  of  exerting 


NATURAL   SCIENCE   TO   GENERAL   SCIENCE.  25 

only  the  feeblest  forces,  and  could  not  be  detected  except  by  the 
most  delicate  apparatus.  Had  they  been  neglected,  on  the 
ground  that  the  investigation  of  them  promised  DO  immediate 
practical  result,  we  should  now  be  ignorant  of  the  most  import- 
ant and  most  interesting  of  the  links  between  the  various  forces 
of  nature.  When  young  Galileo,  then  a  student  at  Pisa,  noticed 
one  day  during  divine  service  a  chandelier  swinging  backwards 
and  forwards,  and  convinced  himself,  by  counting  his  pulse,  that 
the  duration  of  the  oscillations  was  independent  of  the  arc 
through  which  it  moved,  who  could  know  that  this  discovery 
would  eventually  put  it  in  our  power,  by  means  of  the  pendulum, 
to  attain  an  accuracy  in  the  measurement  of  time  till  then 
deemed  impossible,  and  would  enable  the  storm-tossed  seaman 
in  the  most  distant  oceans  to  determine  in  what  degree  of  longi- 
tude he  was  sailing  ? 

Whoever,  in  the  pursuit  of  science,  seeks  after  immediate 
practical  utility,  may  generally  rest  assured  that  he  will  seek  in 
vain.  All  that  science  can  achieve  is  a  perfect  knowledge  and  a 
perfect  understanding  of  the  action  of  natural  and  moral  forces. 
Each  individual  student  must  be  content  to  find  his  reward  in 
rejoicing  over  new  discoveries,  as  over  new  victories  of  mind 
over  reluctant  matter,  or  in  enjoying  the  aesthetic  beauty  of  a 
well-ordered  field  of  knowledge,  where  the  connection  and  the 
filiation  of  every  detail  is  clear  to  the  mind,  and  where  all 
denotes  the  presence  of  a  ruling  intellect ;  he  must  rest  satisfied 
with  the  consciousness  that  he  too  has  contributed  something  to 
the  increasing  fund  of  knowledge  on  which  the  dominion  of  man 
over  all  the  forces  hostile  to  intelligence  reposes.  He  will, 
indeed,  not  always  be  permitted  to  expect  from  his  fellow-men 
appreciation  and  reward  adequate  to  the  value  of  his  work.  It 
is  only  too  true  that  many  a  man  to  whom  a  monument  has 
been  erected  after  his  death  would  have  been  delighted  to  receive 
during  his  lifetime  a  tenth  part  of  the  money  spent  in  doing 
honour  to  his  memory.  At  the  same  time,  we  must  acknowledge 
that  the  value  of  scientific  discoveries  is  now  far  more  fully  recog- 
nised than  formerly  by  public  opinion,  and  that  in  stances  of  the 
authors  of  great  advance  in  science  starving  in  obscurity  have 


20  ON    THE   RELATION    OF 

become  rarer  and  rarer.  On  the  contrary,  the  governments  and 
peoples  of  Europe  have,  as  a  rule,  admitted  it  to  be  their  duty 
to  recompense  distinguished  achievements  in  science  by  appro' 
priate  appointments  or  special  rewards. 

The  sciences  have  then,  in  this  respect,  all  one  common  aim, 
to  establish  the  supremacy  of  intelligence  over  the  world: 
while  the  moral  sciences  aim  directly  at  making  the  resources  of 
intellectual  life  more  abundant  and  more  interesting,  and  seek 
to  separate  the  pure  gold  of  truth  from  alloy,  the  physical 
sciences  are  striving  indirectly  towards  the  same  goal,  inasmuch 
as  they  labour  to  make  mankind  more  and  more  independent  of 
the  material  restraints  that  fetter  their  activity.  Each  student 
works  in  his  own  department,  he  chooses  for  himself  those  tasks 
for  which  he  is  best  fitted  by  his  abilities  and  his  training. 
But  each  one  must  be  convinced  that  it  is  only  in  connection 
with  others  that  he  can  further  the  great  work,  and  that  therefore 
he  is  bound,  not  only  to  investigate,  but  to  do  his  utmost  to 
make  the  resu'ts  of  his  investigation  completely  and  easily 
accessible.  If  ho  does  this,  he  will  derive  assistance  from  others, 
and  will  in  his  turn  be  able  to  render  them  his  aid.  The  annals 
of  science  abound  in  evidence  how  such  mutual  services  have 
been  exchanged,  even  between  departments  of  science  apparently 
most  remote.  Historical  chronology  is  essentially  based  on 
astronomical  calculations  of  eclipses,  accounts  of  which  are  pre- 
Bsrved  in  ancient  histories.  Conversely,  many  of  the  important 
data  of  astronomy — for  instance,  the  invariabi'ity  of  the  length 
of  the  day,  and  the  periods  of  several  comets — rest  upon  ancient 
historical  notices.  Of  late  years,  physiologists,  especially  Briicke, 
have  actually  undertaken  to  draw  up  a  complete  system  of  all 
the  vocables  that  can  be  produced  by  the  organs  of  speech,  and  to 
base  upon  it  propositions  for  an  universal  alphabet,  adapted  to 
all  human  languages.  Thus  physiology  has  entered  the  service 
of  comparative  philology,  and  has  already  succeeded  in  account- 
ing for  many  apparently  anomalous  substitutions,  on  the  ground 
that  they  are  governed,  not  as  hitherto  supposed,  by  the  laws  of 
euphony,  but  by  similarity  between  the  movements  of  the  mouth 
that  produce  them.  Again,  comparative  philology  gives  us 


NATURAL   SCIENCE   TO   GENERAL   SCIENCE.  27 

information  about  the  relationships,  the  separations,  and  the 
migrations  of  tribes  in  pi-ehistoric  times,  and  of  the  d-::gree  of 
civilisation  which  they  had  reached  at  the  time  when  they 
parted.  For  the  names  of  objects  to  which  they  had  already 
learnt  to  give  distinctive  appellations  reappear  as  words  common 
to  their  later  languages.  So  thatthe  study  of  languages  actually 
gives  us  historical  data  for  periods  respecting  which  no  other 
historical  evidence  exists.1  Yet  again  I  may  notice  the  help 
which  not  only  the  sculptor,  but  the  archaeologist,  concerned 
with  the  investigation  of  ancient  statues,  derives  from  anatomy. 
And  if  I  may  be  permitted  to  refer  to  my  own  most  recent  studies, 
I  would  mention  that  it  is  possible,  by  reference  to  physical 
r.coustics  and  to  the  physiological  theory  of  the  sensation  of 
hearing,  to  account  for  the  elementary  principles  on  which  our 
musical  system  is  constructed,  a  problem  essentially  within  the 
sphere  of  aesthetics.  In  fact,  it  is  a  general  principle  that  the 
physiology  of  the  organs  of  sense  is  most  intimately  connected 
with  psychology,  inasmuch  as  physiology  traces  in  our  sensations 
the  results  of  mental  processes  which  do  not  fall  within  the 
sphere  of  consciousness,  and  must  therefore  have  remained  inac- 
cessible to  us. 

I  have  been  able  to  quote  only  some  of  the  most  striking 
instances  of  this  interdependence  of  different  sciences,  and  such 
as  could  be  explained  in  a  few  words.  Naturally,  too,  I  have 
tried  to  choose  them  from  the  most  widely  separated  sciences. 
But  far  wider  is  of  course  the  influence  which  allied  sciences 
exert  upon  each  other.  Of  that  I  need  not  speak,  for  each  of 
you  knows  it  from  his  own  experience. 

In  conclusion,  I  would  say,  let  each  of  us  think  of  himself, 
not  as  a  man  seeking  to  gratify  his  own  thirst  for  knowledge, 
or  to  promote  his  own  private  advantage,  or  to  shine  by  his 
own  abilities,  but  rather  as  a  fellow-labourer  in  one  great  com- 
mon work  bearing  upon  the  highest  interests  of  humanity. 
Then  assuredly  we  shall  not  fail  of  our  reward  in  the  approval 
of  our  own  conscience  and  the  esteem  of  our  fallow-citizens. 

1  See,  for  example,  Mommseu's  Rome,  Book  I.  ch.  ii. — TR. 


28  ON   THE   RELATION   OF  NATURAL   SCIENCE. 

To  keep  up  these  relations  between  all  seai-chers  after  truth  and 
all  branches  of  knowledge,  to  animate  them  all  to  vigorous  co- 
operation towards  their  common  end,  is  the  great  office  of  the 
Universities.  Therefore  is  it  necessary  that  the  four  faculties 
should 'ever  go  hand  in  hand,  and  in  this  conviction  will  we 
strive,  so  far  as  in  us  lies,  to  press  onward  to  the  fulfilment  of 
our  in-eat  mission, 


ON 

GOETHE'S   SCIENTIFIC   EESEAECHES. 

A  Lecture  delivered  before  the  German  Society  of  Kionigsberg,  in  the 
Sprinff  of  1853. 


IT  could  not  but  be  that  Goethe,  whose  comprehensive  genius 
was  most  strikingly  apparent  in  that  sober  clearness  with  which 
he  grasped  and  reproduced  with  lifelike  freshness  the  realities 
of  nature  and  human  life  in  their  minutest  details,  should,  by 
those  very  qualities  of  his  mind,  be  drawn  towards  the  study  of 
physical  science.  And  in  that  department,  he  was  not  content 
with  acquiring  what  others  could  teach  him,  but  he  soon  at- 
tempted, as  so  original  a  mind  was  sure  to  do,  to  strike  out  an  in- 
dependent and  a  very  characteristic  line  of  thought.  He  directed 
his  energies  not  only  to  the  descriptive  but  also  to  the  experi- 
mental sciences;  the  chief  results  being  his  botanical  and 
osteological  treatises  on  the  one  hand,  and  his  theory  of  colour 
on  the  other.  The  first  germs  of  these  researches  belong  for 
the  most  part  to  the  last  decade  of  the  eighteenth  century, 
though  some  of  them  were  not  completed  nor  published  till 
later.  Since  that  time  science  has  not  only  made  great  progress 
but  has  widely  extended  its  range.  It  has  assumed  in  some 
respects  an  entirely  new  aspect,  it  has  opened  out  new  fields  of 
research  and  undergone  many  changes  in  its  theoretical  views. 
I.  shall  attempt  in  the  following  Lecture  to  sketch  the  rela- 
tion of  Goethe's  researches  to  the  present  standpoint  of  science, 
and  to  bring  out  the  guiding  idea  that  is  common  to  them  all. 


30  oy  GOETHE'S  sciE?rnFic  RESEARCHES. 

The  peculiar  character  of  the  descriptive  sciences — botany, 
zoology,  anatomy,  and  the  like — is  a  necessary  result  of  tbe 
work  imposed  upon  them.  They  undertake  to  collect  and  sift 
an  enormous  mass  of  facts,  and,  above  all,  to  bring  them  into  a 
logical  order  or  system.  Up  to  this  point  their  work  is  only 
the  dry  task  of  a  lexicographer ;  their  system  is  nothing  more 
than  a  muniment-room  in  which  the  accumulation  of  papers  is 
so  arranged  that  any  one  can  find  what  he  wants  at  any  moment. 
The  more  intellectual  part  of  their  work  and  their  real  interest 
only  begins  when  they  attempt  to  feel  after  the  scattered  traces 
of  law  and  order  in  the  disjointed,  heterogeneous  mass,  and  out 
of  it  to  construct  for  themselves  an  orderly  system,  accessible  at 
a  glance,  in  which  every  detail  has  its  due  place,  and  gains 
additional  interest  from  its  connection  with  the  whole. 

In  such  studies,  both  the  organising  capacity  and  theinsighu 
of  our  poet  found  a  congenial  sphere — the  epoch  was  moreover 
propitious  to  him.  He  found  ready  to  his  hand  a  sufficieiit 
store  of  logically  arranged  materials  in  botany  and  comparative 
anatomy,  copious  and  systematic  enough  to  admit  cf  a  compre- 
hensive view,  and  to  indicate  the  way  to  some  happy  glimpse 
of  an  all-pervading  law  ;  while  his  contemporaries,  if  they  mado 
any  efforts  in  this  direction,  wandered  without  a  compass,  or 
else  they  were  so  absorbed  in  the  dry  registration  of  facts,  that 
they  scarcely  ventured  to  think  of  anything  beyond.  It  was 
reserved  for  Goethe  to  introduce  two  ideas  of  infinite  fruit- 
fulness. 

The  first  was  the  conception  that  the  differences  in  the 
anatomy  of  different  animals  are  to  be  looked  upon  as  variations 
from  a  common  phase  or  type,  induced  by  differences  of  habit, 
locality,  cr  food.  The  observation  which  led  him  to  this  fertile 
conception  was  by  no  means  a  striking  one ;  it  is  to  be  found  in 
a  monograph  on  the  intermaxillary  bone,  written  as  early  as 
1786.  It  was  known  that  in  most  vertebrate  animals  (that  is, 
mammalia,  birds,  amphibia,  and  fishes)  the  upper  jaw  consists 
of  two  bones,  the  upper  jaw-bone  and  the  intermaxillary  bone. 
The  former  always  contains  in  the  mammalia  the  molar  and 
the  canine  teeth,  the  latter  the  incisors.  Man,  who  is  dis- 


ON  GOETHE'S  SCIENTIFIC  RESEARCHES.  31 

tinguished  from  all  other  animals  by  the  absence  of  the 
projecting  snout,  has,  on  the  contrary,  on  each  side  only  one 
bone,  the  upper  jaw-bone,  containing  all  the  teeth.  This  being 
so,  Goethe  discovered  in  the  human  skull  faint  traces  of  the 
sutures  which  in  animals  unite  the  upper  and  middle  jaw-bones, 
and  concluded  from  it  that  man  had  originally  possessed  an 
intermaxillary  bone,  which  had  subsequently  coalesced  with  the 
upper  jaw-bone.  This  obscure  fact  opened  up  to  him  a  source 
of  the  most  intense  interest  in  the  field  of  osteology,  generally 
so  much  decried  as  the  driest  of  studies.  That  details  of 
structure  should  be  the  same  in  man  and  in  animals  when  the 
parts  continue  to  perform  similar  functions  had  involved 
nothing  extraordinary.  In  fact,  Camper  had  already  attempted, 
on  this  principle,  to  trace  similarities  of  structure  even  between 
man  and  fishes.  But  the  persistence  of  this  similarity,  at  least 
in  a  rudimentary  form,  even  in  a  case  when  it  evidently  does 
not  correspond  to  any  of  the  icquirements  of  the  complete 
human  structure,  and  consequently  needs  to  be  adapted  to 
them  by  the  coalescence  of  two  parts  originally  separate,  was 
what  struck  Goethe's  far-seeing  eye,  and  suggested  to  him  a 
far  more  comprehensive  view  than  had  hitherto  been  taken. 
Further  studies  soon  convinced  him  of  the  universality  of  his 
newly  discovered  principle,  so  that  in  1795  and  1796  he  was 
able  to  define  more  clearly  the  idea  that  had  struck  him  in  1786, 
and  to  commit  it  to  wi  iting  in  his  '  Sketch  of  a  General  Intrp- 
duction  to  Comparative  Anatomy.'  He  there  lays  down  with 
the  utmost  confidence  and  precision  that  all  differences  in  the 
structure  of  animals  must  be  looked  upon  as  variations  of  a 
single  primitive  type,  induced  by  the  coalescence,  the  alteration, 
the  increase,  the  diminution,  or  even  the  complete  removal  of 
single  parts  of  the  stru.ture;  the  very  principle,  in  fact,  which 
has  become  the  leading  idea  of  comparative  anatomy  in  its 
present  stage.  Nowhere  ha?  it  been  better  or  more  clearly  ex- 
pressed than  in  Goathe's  writings.  Subsequent  authorities  have 
made  but  few  essential  alterations  in  his  theory.  The  most 
important  of  these  is,  that  we  no  longer  undertake  to  construct 
a  common  type  for  the  whole  animal  kingdom,  but  are  content 


32  ON  GOETHE'S  SCIENTIFIC  RESEARCHES. 

with  one  for  each  of  Cuvier's  great  divisions.  The  industry  of 
Goethe's  successors  has  accumulated  a  well-sifted  stock  of  facts, 
infinitely  more  copious  than  what  he  could  command,  and  has 
followed  up  successfully  into  the  minutest  details  what  he  could 
only  indicate  in  a  general  way. 

The  second  leading  conception  which  science  owes  to  Goethe 
enunciated  the  existence  of  an  analogy  between  the  different 
parts  of  one  and  the  same  organic  being,  similar  to  that  which 
we  have  just  pointed  out  as  subsisting  between  corresponding 
parts  of  different  species.  In  most  organisms  we  see  a  great 
repetition  of  single  parts.  This  is  most  striking  in  the  veget- 
able kingdom  ;  each  plant  has  a  great  number  of  similar  stem 
leaves,  similar  petals,  similar  stamens,  and  so  on.  According 
to  Goethe's  own  account,  the  idea  first  occurred  to  him  while  look- 
ing at  a  fan-palm  at  Padua.  He  was  struck  by  the  immense 
variety  of  changes  of  form  which  the  successively  developed 
stem-leaves  exhibit,  by  the  way  in  which  the  first  simple  root 
leaflets  are  replaced  by  a  series  of  more  and  more  divided  leaves, 
till  we  come  to  the  most  complicated. 

He  afterwards  succeeded  in  discovering  the  transformation 
of  stem-leaves  into  sepals  and  petals,  and  of  sepals  and  petals 
into  stamens,  nectaries,  and  ovaries,  and  thus  he  was  led  to  the 
doctrine  of  the  metamorphosis  of  plants,  which  he  published  in 
1790.  Just  as  the  anterior  extremity  of  vertebrate  animals 
takes  different  forms,  becoming  in  man  and  in  apes  an  arm,  in 
other  animals  a  paw  with  claws,  or  a  forefoot  with  a  hoof,  or  a 
fin,  or  a  wing,  but  always  retains  the  same  divisions,  the  same 
position,  and  the  same  connection  with  the  trunk,  so  the  leaf 
appears  as  a  cotyledon,  stem-leaf,  sepal,  petal,  stamen,  nectary, 
ovary,  <fec.,  all  resembling  each  other  to  a  certain  extent  in  origin 
and  composition,  and  even  capable,  under  certain  unusual  con- 
ditions, of  passing  from  one  form  into  the  other,  as,  for  example, 
may  be  seen  by  any  one  who  looks  carefully  at  a  full-blown  rose, 
where  some  of  the  stamens  are  completely,  some  of  them  pai-tially, 
changed  into  petals.  This  view  of  Goethe's,  like  the  other,  is 
now  completely  adopted  into  science,  and.  enjoys  the  universal 
assent  of  botanists,  though  of  course  some  details  are  stiD 


ON   GOETHE'S   SCIENTIFIC   RESEARCHES.  33 

matters  of  controversy,  as,  for  instance,  whether  the  bud  is  a 
single  leaf  or  a  branch. 

In  the  animal  kingdom,  the  composition  of  an  individual 
out  of  several  similar  parts  is  very  striking  in  the  great  sub- 
kingdom  of  the  articulata — for  example,  in  insects  and  worms.  The 
larva  of  an  insect,  or  the  caterpillar  of  a  butterfly,  consists  of  a 
number  of  perfectly  similar  segments ;  only  the  first  and  last  of 
them  differ,  and  that  but  slightly,  from  the  others.  After  their 
transformation  into  perfect  insects,  they  furnish  clear  and  simple 
exemplifications  of  the  view  which  Goethe  had  grasped  in  his 
doctrine  of  the  metamorphosis  of  plants,  the  development, 
namely,  of  apparently  very  dissimilar  forms  from  parts '  origin- 
ally alike.  The  posterior  segments  retain  their  original  simple 
form  ;  those  of  the  breastplate  are  drawn  closely  together,  and 
develop  feet  and  wings,  while  those  of  the  head  develop  jaws 
and  feelers ;  so  that  in  the  perfect  insect,  the  original  segments 
are  recognised  only  in  the  posterior  part  of  the  body.  In  the 
vertebrata,  again,  a  repetition  of  similar  parts  is  suggested  by 
the  vertebral  column,  but  has  ceased  to  be  observable  in  the  ex- 
ternal form.  A  fortunate  glance  at  a  broken  sheep's  skull, 
which  Goethe  found  by  accident  on  the  sand  of  the  Lido  at 
Venice,  suggested  to  him  that  the  skull  itself  consisted  of  a  series 
of  very  much  altered  vertebrae.  At  first  sight,  no  two  things 
can  be  more  unlike  than  the  broad  uniform  cranial  cavity  of  the 
mammalia,  inclosed  by  smooth  plates,  and  the  narrow  cylindrical 
tube  of  the  spinal  marrow,  composed  of  short,  massy,  jagged 
bones.  It  was  a  bright  idea  to  detect  the  transformation  in 
the  skull  of  a  mammal ;  the  similarity  is  more  striking  in  the 
amphibia  and  fishes.  It  should  be  added  that  Goethe  left  this 
idea  unpublished  for  a  long  time,  apparently  because  he  was  not 
quite  sure  how  it  would  be  received.  Meantime,  in  1806,  the 
same  idea  occurred  to  Oken,  who  introduced  it  to  the  scientific 
world,  and  afterwards  disputed  with  Goethe  the  priority  of 
discovery.  In  fact,  Goethe  had  waited  till  1817,  when  the 
opinion  had  begun  to  find  adherents,  and  then  declared  that  he 
had  had  it  in  his  mind  for  thirty  years.  Up  to  the  present  day 
the  number  and  composition  of  the  vertebrae  of  the  skull  are  a 

L  2> 


34  ON  GOETHE'S  SCIENTIFIC  RESEARCHES. 

subject  of  controversy,  but  the  principle  has  maintained  ita 
ground. 

Goethe's  views,  however,  on  the  existence  of  a  common  type 
in  the  animal  kingdom  do  not  seem  to  have  exercised  any  direct 
influence  on  the  progress  of  science.  The  doctrine  of  the  meta- 
morphosis of  plants  was  introduced  into  botany  as  his  distinct 
and  recognised  property;  but  his  views  on  osteology  were  at 
first  disputed  by  anatomists,  and  only  subsequently  attracted 
attention  when  the  science  had,  apparently  on  independent 
grounds,  found  its  way  to  the  same  discovery.  He  himself  com- 
plains that  his  first  ideas  of  a  common  type  had  encountered 
nothing  but  contradiction  and  scepticism  at  the  time  when 
he  was  working  them  out  in  his  own  mind,  and  that  even 
men  of  the  freshest  and  most  original  intellect,  like  the  two 
Von  Humboldts,  had  listened  to  them  with  something  like 
impatience.  But  it  is  almost  a  matter  of  course  that  in  any 
natural  or  physical  science,  theoretical  ideas  attract  the  attention 
of  its  cultivators  only  when  they  are  advanced  in  connection 
with  the  whole  of  the  evidence  on  which  they  rest,  and  thus 
justify  their  title  to  recognition.  Be  that  as  it  may,  Goethe  is 
entitled  to  the  credit  of  having  caught  the  first  glimpse  of  the 
guiding  ideas  to  which  the  sciences  of  botany  and  anatomy  were 
tending,  and  by  which  their  present  form  is  determined. 

But  great  as  is  the  respect  which  Goethe  has  secured  by  his 
achievements  in  the  descriptive  natural  sciences,  the  denuncia- 
tion heaped  by  all  physicists  on  his  researches  in  their  depart- 
ment, and  especially  on  his '  theory  of  colour,'  is  at  least  as  uncom- 
pi'omising.  This  is  not  the  place  to  plunge  into  the  controversy 
that  raged  on  the  subject,  and  so  I  shall  only  attempt  to  state 
clearly  the  points  at  issue,  and  to  explain  what  principle  was 
involved,  and  what  is  the  latent  significance  of  the  dispute. 

To  this  end  it  is  of  some  importance  to  go  back  to  the  history 
of  the  origin  of  the  theory,  and  to  its  simplest  form,  because  at 
that  stage  of  the  controversy  the  points  at  issue  are  obvious,  and 
admit  of  easy  and  distinct  statement,  unincumbered  by  disputes 
about  the  correctness  of  detached  facts  and  complicated  theories. 

Goethe  himself  describes  very  gracefully,  in  the  confession  at 


ON  GOETHE'S  SCIENTIFIC  RESEARCHES.  35 

the  end  of  his  '  Theory  of  Colour.'  how  he  came  to  take  up  the 
subject.  Finding  himself  unable  to  grasp  the  aesthetic  principles 
involved  in  effects  of  colour,  he  resolved  to  resume  the  study  of 
the  physical  theory,  which  he  had  been  taught  at  the  university, 
and  to  repeat  for  himself  the  experiments  connected  with  it. 
With  that  view  he  borrowed  a  prism  of  Hofrath  Biitter,  of  Jena, 
but  was  prevented  by  other  occupations  from  carrying  out  his 
plan,  and  kept  it  by  him  for  a  long  time  unused.  The  owner  of 
the  prism,  a  very  orderly  man,  after  several  times  asking  in  vain, 
sent  a  messenger  with  instructions  to  bring  it  back  directly. 
Goethe  took  it  out  of  the  case,  and  thought  he  would  take  one 
more  peep  through  it.  To  make  certain  of  seeing  something,  he 
turned  it  towards  a  long  white  wall,  under  the  impression  that 
as  there  was  plenty  of  light  there  he  could  not  fail  to  see  a 
brilliant  example  of  the  resolution  of  light  into  different  colours; 
a  supposition,  by  the  way,  which  shows  how  little  Newton's 
theory  of  the  phenomena  was  then  present  to  his  mind.  Of 
course  he  was  disappointed.  On  the  white  wall  he  saw  no 
colours ;  they  only  appeared  where  it  was  bounded  by  darker 
objects.  Accordingly  he  made  the  observation — which,  it  should 
be  added,  is  fully  accounted  for  by  Newton's  theory — that 
colour  can  only  be  seen  through  a  prism  where  a  dark  object 
and  a  bright  one  have  the  same  boundary.  Struck  by  this 
observation,  which  was  quite  new  to  him,  and  convinced  that  it 
was  irreconcilable  with  Newton's  theory,  he  induced  the  owner 
of  the  prism  to  relent,  and  devoted  himself  to  the  question  with 
the  utmost  zeal  and  interest.  He  prepared  sheets  of  paper  with 
black  and  white  spaces,  and  studied  the  phenomenon  under 
every  variety  of  condition,  until  he  thought  he  had  sufficiently 
proved  his  rules.  He  next  attempted  to  explain  his  supposed 
discovery  to  a  neighbour,  who  was  a  physicist,  and  was  dis- 
agreeably surprised  to  be  assured  by  him  that  the  experiments 
were  well  known,  and  fully  accounted  for  in  Newton's  theory. 
Every  other  natural  philosopher  whom  he  consulted  told  him 
exactly  the  same,  including  even  the  brilliant  Lichtenberg, 
whom  he  tried  for  a  long  time  to  convert,  but  in  vain.  I£e 
"tudied  Newton's  writings,  and  fancied  he  had  found  some 

D2 


30  ON  GOETHE'S  SCIENTIFIC  RESEARCHES. 

fallacies  in  them  which  accounted  for  the  error.  Unable  to  con- 
vince any  of  his  acquaintances,  he  at  last  resolved  to  appear 
before  the  har  of  public  opinion,  and  in  1791  and  1792  published 
the  first  and  second  parts  of  his  'Contributions  to  Physical 
Optics.' 

In  that  work  he  describes  the  appearances  presented  by  white 
discs  on  a  black  ground,  black  discs  on  a  white  ground,  and 
coloured  discs  on  a  black  or  white  ground,  when  examined 
through  a  prism.  As  to  the  results  of  the  experiments,  there  is 
no  dispute  whatever  between  him  and  the.  physicists.  He  de- 
scribes the  phenomena  he  saw  with  great  truth  to  nature;  the 
style  is  lively,  and  the  arrangement  such  as  to  make  a  conspectus 
of  them  easy  and  inviting ;  in  short,  in  thus  as  in  all  other  cases 
where  facts  are  to  be  described,  he  proves  himself  a  master.  At 
the  same  time  he  expresses  his  conviction  that  the  facts  he  has 
adduced  are  calculated  to  refute  Newton's  theory.  There  are 
two  points  especially  which  he  considers  fatal  to  it :  first,  that 
the  centre  of  a  broad  white  surface  remains  white  when  seen 
through  a  prism;  and  secondly,  that  even  a  black  streak  on  a 
white  ground  can  be  entirely  decomposed  into  colours. 

Newton's  theory  is  based  on  the  hypothesis  that  there  exists 
light  of  different  kinds,  distinguished  from  one  another  by  the 
sensation  of  colour  which  they  produce  in  the  eye.  Thus  there 
is  red,  orange,  yellow,  green,  blue,  and  violet  light,  and  light  of 
all  intermediate  colours.  Different  kinds  of  light,  or  differently 
coloured  lights,  produce,  when  mixed,  derived  colours,  which  to 
a  certain  extent  resemble  the  original  colours  from  which  they 
are  derived ;  to  a  certain  extent  form  new  tints.  White  is  a 
mixture  of  all  the  before-named  coloiirs  in  certain  definite  pro- 
portions. But  the  primitive  colours  can  always  be  reproduced 
by  analysis  from  derived  colours,  or  from  white,  while  themselves 
incapable  of  analysis  or  change.  The  cause  of  the  colours  of 
transparent  and  opaque  bodies  is,  that  when  white  light  falls 
upon  them  they  destroy  some  of  its  constituents  and  send  to 
the  eye  other  constituents,  but  no  longer  mixed  in  the  right 
proportions  to  produce  white  light.  Thus  a  piece  of  red  glass 
looks  red  because  it  transmits  only  red  rays.  Consequently  aD 


ON  GOETHE'S  SCIENTIFIC  RESEARCHES.  37 

colour  is  derived  solely  from  a  change  in  the  proportions  in 
which  light  is  mixed,  and  is,  therefore,  a  property  of  light,  not 
of  the  coloured  bodies,  which  only  furnish  an  occasion  for  its 
manifestation. 

A  prism  refracts  transmitted  light;  that  is  to  say,  deflects  it 
BO  that  it  makes  a  certain  angle  with  its  original  direction;  the 
rays  of  simple  light  of  different  colours  have,  according  to 
Newton,  different  refrangibilities,  and  therefore,  after  refraction 
in  the  prism,  pursue  different  courses  and  separate  from  each 
other.  Accordingly  a  luminous  point  of  infinitely  small  dimen- 
sions appears,  when  seen  through  the  pi-ism,  to  be  first  displaced, 
and,  secondly,  extended  into  a  coloured  line,  the  so-called  pris^ 
matic  spectrum,  Avhich  shows  what  are  called  the  primary 
colours  in  the  order  above-named.  If,  however,  you  look  at  a 
broader  luminous  surface,  the  spectra  of  the  points  near  the 
middle  are  superposed,  as  may  be  seen  from  a  simple  geometrical 
investigation,  in  such  proportions  as  to  give  white  light,  except 
at  the  edges,  where  certain  of  the  colours  are  free.  This  white 
surface  appears  displaced,  as  the  luminous  point  did;  but  in- 
stead of  being  coloured  throughout,  it  has  on  one  side  a  margin 
of  blue  and  violet,  on  the  other  a  margin  of  red  and  yellow.  A 
black  patch  between  two  bright  surfaces  may  be  entirely  covered 
by  their  coloured  edges;  and  when  these  spectra  meet  in  the 
middle,  the  red  of  the  one  and  the  violet  of  the  other  combine 
to  form  purple.  Thus  the  colours  into  which,  at  first  sight,  it 
seems  as  if  the  black  were  analysed  are  in  reality  due,  not  to 
the  black  strip,  but  to  the  white  on  each  side  of  it. 

It  is  evident  that  at  the  first  moment  Goethe  did  not  recol- 
lect Newton's  theory  well  enough  to  be  able  to  find  out  the 
physical  explanation  of  the  facts  I  have  just  glanced  at.  It  was 
afterwards  laid  before  him  again  and  again,  and  that  in  a 
thoroughly  intelligible  form,  for  he  speaks  about  it  several  times 
in  terms  that  show  he  understood  it  quite  correctly.  But  he  is 
still  so  dissatisfied  with  it  that  he  persists  in  his  assertion  that 
the  facts  just  cited  are  of  a  nature  to  convince  any  one  who 
observes  them  of  the  absolute  incorrectness  of  Newton's  theory. 
Neither  here  nor  in  his  later  controversial  writings  does  he  ever 

425182 


38  oy  GOETEE'S  SCIENTIFIC  RESEARCHES. 

clearly  state  in  what  he  conceives  the  insufficiency  of  the  ex- 
planation to  consist.  He  merely  repeats  again  and  again  that 
it  is  quite  absurd.  And  yet  I  cannot  see  how  any  one,  whatever 
his  views  about  colour,  can  deny  that  the  theory  is  perfectly 
consistent  with  itself;  and  that  if  the  hypothesis  from  which  it 
starts  be  granted,  it  explains  the  observed  facts  completely  and 
even  simply.  Newton  himself  mentions  these  spurious  spectra 
in  several  passages  of  his  optical  works,  without  going  into 
any  special  elucidation  of  the  point,  considering,  of  course,  that 
the  explanation  follows  at  once  from  his  hypothesis.  And  he 
seems  to  have  had  good  reason  to  think  so ;  for  Goethe  no  sooner 
began  to  call  the  attention  of  his  scientific  friends  to  the  pheno- 
mena than  all  with  one  accord,  as  he  himself  tells  us,  met  his 
difficulties  with  this  explanation  from  Newton's  principles,  which, 
though  not  actually  in  his  writings,  instantly  suggested  itself  to 
every  one  who  knew  them. 

A  reader  who  tries  to  realise  attentively  and  thoroughly 
every  step  in  this  part  of  the  controversy  is  ant  to  experience  at 
this  point  an  uncomfortable,  almost  a  painful,  feeling  to  see  a  man 
of  extraordinary  abilities  persistently  declaring  that  there  is  an 
obvious  absurdity  lurking  in  a  few  inferences  appai'ently  quite 
clear  and  simple.  He  searches  and  searches,  and  at  last  unable, 
with  all  his  efforts,  to  find  any  such  absurdity,  or  even  the  ap- 
pearance of  it,  he  gets  into  a  state  of  mind  in  which  his  own 
ideas  are,  so  to  speak,  crystallisad.  But  it  is  just  this  obvious, 
flat  contradiction  that  makes  Goethe's  point  of  view  in  1792  so 
interesting  and  so  important.  At  this  point  he  has  not  as  yet 
developed  any  theory  of  his  own;  there  is  nothing  under  dis- 
cussion but  a  few  easily  grasped  facts,  as  to  the  correctness  of 
which  both  parties  are  agreed,  and  yet  both  hold  distinctly 
opposite  views;  neither  of  them  even  understands  what  his 
opponent  is  driving  at.  On  the  one  side  are  a  number  of  phy- 
sicists, who,  by  a  long  series  of  the  ablest  investigations,  the 
most  elaborate  calculations,  and  the  most  ingenious  inventions, 
have  Drought  optics  to  such  perfection  that  it,  and  it  alone, 
nmong  the  physical  sciences,  was  beginning  almost  to  rival 
astronomy  in  accuracy.  Some  of  them  have  made  the  pheno- 


ON  GOETHE'S  SCIENTIFIC  RESEARCHES.  39 

ir.ena  the  subject  of  direct  investigation ;  all  of  them,  thanks 
to  the  accuracy  with  which  it  is  possible  to  calculate  beforehand 
the  result  of  every  variety  in  the  construction  and  combination 
of  instruments,  have  had  the  opportunity  of  putting  the  infer- 
ences deduced  from  Newton's  views  to  the  test  of  experiment, 
and  all,  without  exception,  agree  in  accepting  them.  On  the  other 
aide  is  a  man  whose  remarkable  mental  endowments,  and 
AT  hose  singular  talent  for  seeing  through  whatever  obscures 
reality,  we  have  had  occasion  to  recognise,  not  only  in  poetry,  but 
also  in  the  descriptive  parts  of  the  natural  sciences ;  and  this 
man  assures  us  with  the  utmost  zeal  that  the  physicists  are 
wrong  :  he  is  so  convinced  of  the  correctness  of  his  own  view, 
that  he  cannot  explain  the  contradiction  except  by  assuming 
narrowness  or  malice  on  their  part,  and  finally  declares  that  he 
cannot  help  looking  upon  his  own  achievement  in  the  theory  of 
colour  as  far  more  valuable  than  anything  he  has  accomplished 
in  poetry.1 

So  flat  a  contradiction  leads  us  to  suspect  that  there  must 
be  behind  some  deeper  antagonism  of  principle,  some  difference 
of  organisation  between  his  mind  and  theirs,  to  prevent  them 
from  understanding  each  other.  I  will  try  to  indicate  in  the 
following  pages  what  I  conceive  to  be  the  grounds  of  this  anta- 
gonism. 

Goethe,  though  he  exercised  his  powers  in  many  spheres 
of  intellectual  activity,  is  nevertheless,  par  excellence,  a  poet. 
Now  in  poetry,  as  in  every  other  art,  the  essential  thing  is  to 
make  the  material  of  the  art,  be  it  words,  or  music,  or  colour, 
the  direct  vehicle  of  an  idea.  In  a  perfect  work  of  art,  the  idea 
must  be  present  and  dominate  the  whole,  almost  unknown  to 
the  poet  himself,  not  as  the  result  of  a  long  intellectual  process, 
but  as  inspired  by  a  direct  intuition  of  the  inner  eye,  or  by  an 
outburst  of  excited  feeling. 

An  idea  thus  embodied  in  a  work  of  art,  and  dre?sei  in  the 
garb  of  reality,  does  indeed  make  a  vivid  impression  by  appeal- 
ing directly  to  the  senses,  but  loses,  of  course,  that  universality 
and  that  intelligibility  which  it  would  have  had  if  presented  in 
1  See  Eckermann's  Conversation* 


40  ON  GOETHE'S  SCIENTIFIC  RESEARCHES. 

the  form  of  an  abstract  notion.  The  poet,  feeling  how  the 
charm  of  his  works  is  involved  in  an  intellectual  process  of  this 
type,  seeks  to  apply  it  to  other  materials.  Instead  of  trying  to 
arrange  the  phenomena  of  nature  under  definite  conceptions, 
independent  of  intuition,  he  sits  down  to  contemplate  them  as 
he  would  a  work  of  art,  complete  in  itself,  and  certain  to  yield 
up  its  central  idea,  sooner  or  later,  to  a  sufficiently  susceptible 
student.  Accordingly,  when  he  sees  the  skull  on  the  Lido, 
which  suggests  to  him  the  vertebral  theory  of  the  cranium,  he 
remarks  that  it  serves  to  revive  his  old  belief,  already  confirmed 
by  experience,  that  Nature  has  no  secrets  from  the  attentive 
observer.  So  again  in  his  first  conversation  with  Schiller  on 
the  'Metamorphosis  of  Plants.'  To  Schiller,  as  a  follower  of 
Kant,  the  idea  is  the  goal,  ever  to  be  sought,  but  ever  unattain- 
able, and  therefore  never  to  be  exhibited  as  realised  in  a  phe- 
nomenon. Goethe,  on  the  other  hand,  as  a  genuine  poet, 
conceives  that  he  finds  in  the  phenomenon  the  direct  expression 
of  the  idea.  He  himself  tells  us  that  nothing  brought  out 
more  sharply  the  separation  between  himself  and  Schiller. 
This,  too,  is  the  secret  of  his  affinity  with  the  natural  philosophy 
of  Schelling  and  Hegel,  which  likewise  proceeds  from  the 
assumption  that  Nature  shows  us  by  direct  intuition  the  several 
steps  by  which  a  conception  is  developed.  Hence  too  the  ardour 
with  which  Hegel  and  his  school  defended  Goethe's  scientific 
views.  Moreover,  this  view  of  Nature  accounts  for  the  war 
which  Goethe  continued  to  wage  against  complicated  experi- 
mental researches.  Just  as  a  genuine  work  of  art  cannot  bear 
retouching  by  a  strange  hand,  so  he  would  have  us  believe 
Nature  resists  the  interference  of  the  experimenter  who  torturea 
her  and  disturbs  her ;  and,  in  revenge,  misleads  the  impertinent 
kill-joy  by  a  distorted  image  of  herself. 

Accordingly,  in  his  attack  upon  Newton  he  often  sneers  at 
spectra,  tortured  through  a  number  of  narrow  slits  and  glasses, 
and  commends  the  experiments  that  can  be  made  in  the  open  air 
under  a  bright  sun,  not  merely  as  particularly  easy  and  parti- 
cularly enchanting,  but  also  as  particularly  convincing  !  The 
poetic  turn  of  mind  is  very  marked  even  in  his  morphological 


ON  GOETHE'S  SCIENTIFIC  RESEARCHES.  41 

researches.     If  we  only  examine  what  has  really  been  accom- 
plished by  the  help  of  the  ideas  which  he  contributed  to  science, 
we  shall  be  struck  by  the  very  singular  relation  which  they  bear 
to  it.     !No  one  will  refuse  to  be  convinced  if  you  lay  before  him 
the  series  of  transformations    by  which  a  leaf  passes   into  a 
etainen,  an  arm  into  a  fin  or  a  wing,  a  vertebra  into  the  occipital 
bone.     The  idea  that  all  the  parts  of  a  flower  are  modified  leaves 
reveals  a  connecting  law  which  surprises  us  into  acquiescence. 
But  now  try  and  define  the  leaf-like  organ,  determine  its  essential 
characteristics,  so  as  to  include  all  the  forms  that  we  have  named. 
You  will  find  yourself  in  a  difficult}-,  for  all  distinctive  marks 
vanieh,  and  you   have  nothing  left,  except  that  a  leaf  in  the 
wider  sense  of  the  term  is  a  lateral  appendage  of  the  axis  of 
a  plant.     Try  then  to  express  the  proposition  'the  parts  of  the 
flower  are  modified  leaves '  in   the  language   of  scientific  defi- 
nition, and  it  reads,  '  the  parts  of  the  flower  are  lateral  appen- 
dnges  of  the  axis.'     To  see  this  does  not  require  a  Goethe.     So 
igain  it  has  been  objected,  and  not  unjustly,  to  the  vertebral 
theory,  that  it  must  extend  the  notion  of  a  vertebra  so  much 
that  nothing  is  left  but  the  bare  fact — a  vertebra  is  a  bone.    We 
are  equally  perplexed   if  we   try  to  express  in  clear  scientific 
language  what  we  mean  by  saying  that  such  and  such  a  part  of 
one  animal  corresponds  to  such  and  such  a  part  of  another.     We 
ilo  not  mean  that  their   physiological   use  is  the  same,  for  the 
name  piece  which   in  bird  serves  as  the  lower  jaw,  becomes 
in  mammals   a  tiny  tympana!  bone.     Nor  would  the  shape,  the 
position,  or  the  connection  of  the  part  in  question  with  other 
parts  serve  to  identify  it  in  all  cases.     But  yet  it  has  been  found 
possible  in  most  cases,  by  following  the  intermediate  steps,  to 
determine   with  tolerable  certainty  which  parts  correspond  to 
each  other.     Goethe  himself  said  this  very  clearly :  he  says,  in 
speaking  of  the  vertebral  thory  of  the  sk\ill,  '  Such  an  aper^i, 
such  an   intuition,  conception,  representation,  notion,  idea,  or 
whatever    you    choose    to    call   it,  always   retains   something 
esoteric  and  indefinable,  struggle  as  you  will  against  it ;  as  a 
general  principle,  it  may  be  enunciated,  but  cannot  be  proved  ; 
in  detail  it  may  be  exhibited,  but  can  never  be  put  in  a  cut  and 


42  ON  GOETHE'S  SCIENTIFIC  RESEARCHES. 

dry  form.'  And  so,  or  nearly  so,  the  problem  stands  to  this 
day.  The  difference  may  be  brought  out  still  more  clearly  if  wo 
consider  how  physiology,  which  investigates  the  relations  of  vital 
processes  as  cause  and  effect,  would  have  to  treat  this  idea  of  a 
common  type  of  animal  structure.  The  science  might  ask,  Is 
it,  on  the  one  hand,  a  correct  view,  that  during  the  geological 
periods  that  have  passed  over  the  earth,  one  species  has  been 
developed  from  another,  so  that,  for  example,  the  breast-fin  of 
the  fish  has  gradually  changed  into  an  arm  or  a  wing  ?  Or 
again,  shall  we  say  that  the  different  species  of  animals  were 
created  equally  perfect — that  the  points  of  resemblance  between 
them  are  to  be  ascribed  to  the  fact  that  in  all  vertebrate  animals 
the  first  steps  in  development  from  the  egg  can  only  be  effected 
by  Nature  in  one  way,  almost  identical  in  all  cases,  and  that 
the  later  analogies  of  structure  are  determined  by  these  features, 
common  to  all  embryos  1  Probably  the  majority  of  observers 
incline  to  the  latter  view,1  for  the  agreement  between  the 
embryos  of  different  vertebrate  animals,  in  the  earlier  stages,  is 
very  striking.  Thus  even  young  mammals  have  occasionally 
rudimentary  gills  on  the  side  of  the  neck,  like  fishes.  It  seems, 
in  fact,  that  what  are  in  the  mature  animals  corresponding  parts 
originate  in  the  same  way  during  the  process  of  development,  so 
that  scientific  men  have  lately  begun  to  make  use  of  embryology 
as  a  sort  of  check  on  the  theoretical  views  of  comparative  ana- 
tomy. It  is  evident  that  by  the  application  of  the  physiological 
views  just  suggested,  the  idea  of  a  common  type  would  acquire 
definiteness  and  meaning  as  a  distinct  scientific  conception. 
Goethe  did  much  :  he  saw  by  a  happy  intuition  that  there  was  a 
law,  and  he  followed  up  the  indications  of  it  writh  great  shrewdness. 
But  what  law  it  was  he  did  not  see ;  nor  did  he  even  try  to 
find  it  out.  That  was  not  in  his  line.  Moreover,  even  in  the 
present  condition  of  science,  a  definite  view  on  the  question  is 
impossible ;  the  very  form  in  which  it  should  be  proposed  is 
scarcely  yet  settled.  And  therefore  we  readily  admit  that  in  this 
department  Goethe  did  all  that  was  possible  at  the  time  when  he 
lived.  I  said  just  now  that  he  treated  nature  like  a  work  of 
1  This  was  writteu  before  the  appearance  of  Darwin's  Origin  of  Species. 


ON  GOETHE'S  SCIENTIFIC  RESEARCHES.  43 

art.  In  his  studies  on  morphology,  he  reminds  one  of  a  spectator 
at  a  play,  with  strong  artistic  sympathies.  His  delicate  instinct 
makes  him  feel  how  all  the  details  fall  into  their  places,  and 
work  harmoniously  together,  and  how  some  common  purpose 
governs  the  whole ;  and  yet  while  this  exquisite  order  and  sym- 
metry give  him  intense  pleasure  he  cannot  formulate  the  dominant 
idea.  That  is  reserved  for  the  scientific  critic  of  the  drama, 
while  the  artistic  spectator  feels  perhaps,  as  Goethe  did  in  the 
presence  of  natural  phenomena,  an  antipathy  to  such  dissection, 
fearing,  though  without  reason,  that  his  pleasure  may  be  spoilt 
by  it. 

Goethe's  point  of  view  in  the  Theory  of  Colour  is  much  the 
same.  We  havo  seen  that  he  rebels  against  the  physical  theory 
just  at  the  point  where  it  gives  complete  and  consistent  expla- 
nations from  principles  once  accepted.  Evidently  it  is  not  the 
insufficiency  of  the  theory  to  explain  individual  cases  that  is  a 
stumbling-block  to  him.  He  takes  offence  at  the  assumption 
made  for  the  sake  of  explaining  the  phenomena,  which  seem  to 
him  so  absurd,  that  he  looks  upon  the  interpretation  as  no  inter- 
pretation at  all  Above  all,  the  idea  that  white  light  could  be 
composed  of  coloured  light  seems  to  have  been  quite  inconceiv- 
able to  him ;  at  the  very  beginning  of  the  controversy,  he  rails 
at  the  disgusting  Newtonian  white  of  the  natural  philosophers, 
an  expression  which  seems  to  show  that  this  was  the  assumption 
that  most  annoyed  him. 

Again,  in  his  later  attacks  on  Newton,  which  were  not 
published  till  after  his  Theory  of  Colour  was  completed,  he 
rather  strives  to  show  that  Newton's  facts  might  be  explained 
on  his  own  hypothesis,  and  that  therefore  Newton's  hypothesis 
was  not  fully  proved,  than  attempts  to  prove  that  hypothesis 
inconsistent  with  itself  or  with  the  facts.  Nay,  he  seems  to 
consider  the  obviousness  of  his  own  hypothesis  so  overwhelming, 
that  it  need  only  be  brought  forward  to  upset  Newton's  entirely. 
There  are  only  a  few  passages  where  he  disputes  the  experiments 
described  by  Newton.  Some  of  them,  apparently,  he  could  not 
succeed  in  refuting,  because  the  result  is  not  equally  easy  to 
observe  in  all  positions  of  the  lenses  used,  and  because  he  waa 


44  ON  GOETHE'S  SCIENTIFIC  RESEARCHES. 

unacquainted  with  the  geometrical  relations  by  which  the  most 
favourable  positions  of  them  are  determined.  In  other  experi- 
ments on  the  separation  of  simple  coloured  light  by  means  of 
prisms  alone,  Goethe's  objections  are  not  quite  groundless,  inas- 
much as  the  isolation  of  single  colours  cannot  by  this  means  be 
so  effectually  carried  out,  that  after  refraction  through  another 
prism  there  are  no  traces  of  other  tints  at  the  edges.  A  com- 
plete isolation  of  light  of  one  colour  can  only  be  effected  by 
very  carefully  arranged  apparatus,  consisting  of  combined 
prisms  and  lenses,  a  set  of  experiments  which  Goethe  postponed 
to  a  supplement,  and  finally  left  unnoticed.  When  he  complains 
of  the  complication  of  these  contrivances,  we  need  only  think 
of  the  laborious  and  roundabout  methods  which  chemists  must 
often  adopt  to  obtain  certain  elementary  bodies  in  a  pui-e  form ; 
and  we  need  not  be  surprised  to  find  that  it  is  impossible  to 
solve  a  similar  problem  in  the  case  of  light  in  the  open  air  in  a 
garden,  and  with  a  single  prism  in  one's  hand.1  Goethe  must, 
consistently  with  his  theory,  deny  in  toto  the  possibility  of 
isolating  pure  light  of  one  colour.  Whether  he  ever  experi- 
mented with  the  proper  apparatus  to  solve  the  problem  remains 
doubtful,  as  the  supplement  in  which  he  promised  to  detail 
these  experiments  was  never  published. 

To  give  some  idea  of  the  passionate  way  in  which  Goethe, 
usually  so  temperate  and  even  courtier-like,  attacks  Newton,  I 
quote  from  a  few  pages  of  the  controversial  part  of  his  work 
the  following  expressions,  which  he  applies  to  the  propositions 
of  this  consummate  thinker  in  physical  and  astronomical 
science — '  incredibly  impudent' ;  '  mere  twaddle' ;  '  ludicrous  ex- 
planation' ;  '  admirable  for  school-children  in  a  go-cart'  j  '  but  I 
see  nothing  will  do  but  lying,  and  plenty  of  it.'2 

1  I  venture  to  add  that  1  am  acquainted  -with  the  impossibility  of  decom- 
posing or  changing  simple  coloured  light,  the  two  principles  which  form  the 
basis  of  Newton's  theory,  not  merely  by  hearsay,  but  from  actual  observation, 
having  been  under  the  necessity  in  one  of  my  own  researches  of  obtaining  light 
of  one  colour  in  a  state  of  the  greatest  possible  purity.    (See  Poggendorff's 
Annalen,  vol.  Ixxxvi.  p.  501,  on  Sir  D.  Brewster's  New  Analysis  of  Sunlight.) 

2  Something  parallel  to  this  extraordinary  proceeding  of  Goethe's  may  be 
found  in  Hobbes's  attack  on  Wallis. — TB. 


ON  GOETHE'S  SCIENTIFIC  RESEARCHES.  45 

Thus,  in  the  theory  of  colour,  Goethe  remains  faithful  to 
his  principle,  that  Nature  must  reveal  her  secrets  of  her  own 
free  will ;  that  she  is  but  the  transparent  representation  of  the 
ideal  world.  Accordingly,  he  demands,  as  a  preliminary  to  the 
investigation  of  physical  phenomena,  that  the  observed  facts 
shall  be  so  arranged  that  one  explains  the  other,  and  that  thus 
we  may  attain  an  insight  into  their  connection  without  ever 
having  to  trust  to  anything  but  our  senses.  This  demand  of 
his  looks  most  attractive,  but  is  essentially  wrong  in  principle. 
For  a  natural  phenomenon  is  not  considered  in  physical  science 
to  be  fully  explained  until  you  have  traced  it  back  to  the 
ultimate  forces  which  are  concerned  in  its  production  and  its 
maintenance.  Now,  as  we  can  never  become  cognisant  of  forces 
qua  forces,  but  only  of  their  effects,  we  are  compelled  in  every 
explanation  of  natural  phenomena  to  leave  the  sphere  of  sense, 
and  to  pass  to  things  which  are  not  objects  of  sense,  and  are 
denned  only  by  abstract  conceptions.  When  we  find  a  stove 
warm,  and  then  observe  that  a  fire  is  burning  in  it,  we  say, 
though  somewhat  inaccurately,  that  the  former  sensation  is 
explained  by  the  latter.  But  in  reality  this  is  equivalent  to  say- 
ing, we  are  always  accustomed  to  find  heat  where  fire  is  bum- 
ing  ;  now,  a  fire  is  burning  in  the  stove,  therefore  we  shall  find 
heat  there.  Accordingly  we  bring  our  single  fact  under  a  more 
general,  better-known  fact,  rest  satisfied  with  it,  and  call  it 
falsely  an  explanation.  Evidently,  however,  the  generality  of  the 
observation  does  not  necessarily  imply  an  insight  into  causes;  such 
an  insight  is  only  obtained  when  we  can  make  out  what  forces 
are  at  work  in  the  fire,  and  how  the  effects  depend  upon  them. 

But  this  step  into  the  region  of  abstract  conceptions,  which 
must  necessarily  be  taken  if  we  wish  to  penetrate  to  the  causes 
of  phenomena,  scares  the  poet  away.  In  writing  a  poem  he 
has  been  accustomed  to  look,  as  it  were,  right  into  the  subject, 
and  to  reproduce  his  intuition  without  formulating  any  of  the 
steps  that  led  him  to  it.  And  his  success  is  proportionate  to 
the  vividness  of  the  intuition.  Such  is  the  fashion  in  which  he 
would  have  Nature  attacked.  But  the  natural  philosopher  in- 
sists on  transporting  him  into  a  world  of  invisible  atoms  and 


46  ON  GOETHE'S  SCIENTIFIC  RESEARCHES. 

movements,  of  attractive  and  repulsive  forces,  whose  intricate 
actions  and  reactions,  though  governed  by  strict  laws,  can 
scarcely  be  taken  in  ai  a  glance.  To  him  the  impiessions  of 
sense  are  not  an  irrefragable  authority ;  he  examines  what  claim 
they  have  to  be  trusted ;  he  asks  whether  things  which  they 
pronounce  alike  are  really  alike,  and  whether  things  which  they 
pronounce  different  are  really  different ;  and  often  finds  that  he 
must  answer,  no !  The  result  of  such  examination,  as  at  present 
understood,  is  that  the  organs  of  sense  do  indeed  give  us  informa- 
tion about  external  effects  produced  on  them,  but  convey  thorte 
effects  to  our  consciousness  in  a  totally  different  form,  so  that 
the  character  of  a  sensuous  perception  depends  not  so  much  on 
the  properties  of  the  object  perceived  as  on  those  of  the  organ 
by  which  we  I'eceive  the  information.  All  that  the  optic  nerve 
conveys  to  us,  it  conveys  under  the  form  of  a  sensation  of  light, 
whether  it  be  the  rays  of  the  sun,  or  a  blow  in  the  eye,  or  an 
electric  current  passing  through  it.  Again,  the  auditory  nerve 
translates  everything  into  phenomena  of  sound,  the  nerves  of  the 
skin  into  sensations  of  temperature  or  touch.  The  same  electric 
current  whose  existence  is  indicated  by  the  optic  nerve  as  a  flash 
of  light,  or  by  the  organ  of  taste  as  an  acid  flavour,  excites  in 
the  nerves  of  the  skin  the  sensation  of  burning.  The  same  ray 
of  sunshine,  which  is  called  light  when  it  falls  on  the  eye,  \re 
call  heat  when  it  falls  on  the  skin.  But  on  the  other  hand,  in 
spite  of  their  different  effects  upon  our  organisation,  the  daylight 
which  enters  through  our  windows,  and  the  heat  radiated  by  an 
iron  stove,  do  not  in  reality  differ  more  or  less  from  each  other 
than  the  red  and  blue  constituents  of  light.  In  fact,  just  as  in 
the  Undulatory  Theory  the  red  rays  are  distinguished  from  the 
blue  rays  only  by  their  longer  period  of  vibration,  and  their 
smaller  refrangibility,  so  the  dark  heat  rays  of  the  stove  have  a 
still  longer  period  and  still  smaller  refrangibility  than  the  red 
lays  of  light,  but  are  in  every  other  respect  exactly  similar  to 
them.  All  these  rays,  whether  luminous  or  non-luminous,  have 
heating  properties,  but  only  a  certain  number  of  them,  to  which 
for  that  reason  we  give  the  name  of  light,  can  penetrate  through 
the  transparent  part  of  the  eye  to  the  optic  nerve,  and  excite  a 


ox  GOETHE'S  SCIENTIFIC  RESEARCHES.  47 

sensation  of  light.  Perhaps  the  relation  between  our  senses  and 
the  external  world  may  be  best  enunciated  as  follows  :  our  sen- 
sations are  for  us  only  symbols  of  the  objects  of  the  external 
world,  and  correspond  to  them  only  in  some  such  way  as  written 
characters  or  articulate  words  to  the  things  they  denote.  They 
give  us,  it  is  true,  information  respecting  the  properties  of  things 
without  us,  but  no  better  information  than  we  give  a  blind  man 
about  colour  by  verbal  descriptions. 

We  see  that  science  has  arrived  at  an  estimate  of  the  senses 
very  different  from  that  which  was  present  to  the  poet's  mind. 
A.nd  Newton's  assertion  that  white  was  composed  of  all  the 
colours  of  the  spectrum  was  the  first  gerni  of  the  scientific  view 
which  has  subsequently  been  developed.  For  at  that  time  there 
were  none  of  those  galvanic  observations  which  paved  the  way 
to  a  knowledge  of  the  functions  of  the  nerves  in  the  production 
of  sensations.  Natural  philosophers  asserted  that  white,  to  the 
^ye  the  simplest  and  purest  of  all  our  sensations  of  colour,  was 
compounded  of  less  pure  and  complex  materials.  It  seems  to 
have  flashed  upon  the  poet's  mind  that  all  his  principles  were 
unsettled  by  the  results  of  this  assertion,  and  that  is  why  the 
hypothesis  seems  to  him  so  unthinkable,  so  ineffably  absurd. 
We  must  look  upon  his  theoiy  of  colour  as  a  forlorn  hope,  as 
a  desperate  attempt  to  rescue  from  the  attacks  of  science  the 
belief  in  the  direct  truth  of  our  sensations.  And  this  will  ac- 
count for  the  enthusiasm  with  which  he  strives  to  elaborate  and  to 
defend  his  theory,  for  the  passionate  irritability  with  which  he 
attacks  his  opponent,  for  the  overweening  importance  which  he 
attaches  to  these  researches  in  comparison  with  his  other  achieve- 
ments, and  for  his  inaccessibility  to  conviction  or  compromise. 

If  we  now  turn  to  Goethe's  own  theories  on  the  subject, 
we  must,  en  the  grounds  above  stated,  expect  to  find  that  he 
cannot,  without  being  untrue  to  his  own  principle,  give  us 
anything  deserving  to  be  called  a  scientific  explanation  of  the 
phenomena,  and  that  is  exactly  what  happens.  He  starts  with 
the  proposition  that  all  colours  are  darker  than  white,  that  they 
have  something  of  shade  in  them  (on  the  physical  theoiy,  white 
compounded  of  all  colours  must  necessarily  be  brighter  than 


48  ON  GOETHE'S  SCIENTIFIC  RESEARCHES. 

any  of  its  constituents).  The  direct  mixture  of  dark  and  light, 
of  black  and  white,  gives  grey ;  the  colours  must  therefore  owe 
their  existence  to  some  form  of  the  co-operation  of  light  and 
shade.  Goethe  imagines  he  has  discovered  it  in  the  phenomena 
presented  by  slightly  opaque  or  hazy  media.  Such  media  usually  jj 
look  blue  when  the  light  falls  on  them  and  they  are  seen  in 
front  of  a  dark  object,  but  yellow  when  a  bright  object  is  looked 
at  through  them.  Thus  in  the  daytime  the  air  looks  blue 
against  the  dark  background  of  the  sky,  and  the  sun,  when 
viewed,  as  is  the  case  at  sunset,  through  a  thick  and  hazy 
stratum  of  air,  appears  yellow.  The  physical  explanation  of 
this  phenomenon,  which,  however,  is  not  exhibited  by  all  such 
media,  as,  for  instance,  by  plates  of  unpolished  glass,  would  lead 
us  too  far  from  the  subject.  According  to  Goethe,  the  semi-opaque 
medium  imparts  to  the  light  something  corporeal,  something  of 
the  nature  of  shade,  such  as  is  requisite,  he  would  say,  for  the 
formation  of  colour.  This  conception  alone  is  enough  to  perplex 
any  one  who  looks  upon  it  as  a  physical  explanation.  Does  he 
mean  to  say  that  material  particles  mingle  with  the  light  and 
fly  away  with  it  ?  But  this  is  Goethe's  fundamental  experiment, 
this  is  the  typical  phenomenon  under  which  he  tries  to  reduce 
all  the  phenomena  of  colour,  especially  those  connected  with 
the  prismatic  spectritrn.  He  looks  upon  all  transparent  bodies 
as  slightly  hazy,  and  assumes  that  the  prism  imparts  to  the 
image  which  it  shows  to  an  observer  something  of  its  own 
opacity.  Here,  again,  it  is  hard  to  get  a  definite  conception  of 
what  is  meant.  Goethe  seems  to  have  thought  that  a  prism 
never  gives  perfectly  defined  images,  but  only  indistinct,  half- 
obliterated  ones,  for  he  puts  them  all  in  the  same  class  with  the 
double  images  which  are  exhibited  by  parallel  plates  of  glass 
and  by  Iceland  spar.  The  images  formed  by  a  prism  are,  it 
is  true,  indistinct  in  compound  light,  but  they  are  perfectly 
defined  when  simple  light  is  used.  If  you  examine,  he  says,  a 
bright  surface  on  a  dark  ground  through  a  prism,  the  image  is 
displaced  and  blurred  by  the  prism.  The  anterior  edge  is 
pushed  forward  over  the  dark  background,  and  consequently  9 
hazy  light  on  a  dark  ground  appears  blue,  while  the  other  edge 


ON  GOETHE'S  SCIENTIFIC  RESEARCHES.  49 

is  covered  by  the  image  of  the  black  surface  which  comes  after  it, 
and,  consequently,  being  a  light  image  behind  a  hazy  dark  colour, 
appears  yellowish-red.  But  why  the  anterior  edge  appears  in 
front  of  the  ground,  the  posterior  edge  behind  it,  and  not  vice 
versd,  he  does  not  explain.  Let  us  analyse  this  explanation, 
and  try  to  grasp  clearly  the  conception  of  an  optical  image. 
When  I  see  a  bright  object  reflected  in  a  mirror,  the  reason  is 
that  the  light  which  proceeds  from  it  is  thrown  back  exactly  as 
if  it  came  from  an  object  of  the  same  kind  behind  the  mirror. 
The  eye  of  the  observer  receives  the  impression  accordingly, 
and  therefore  he  imagines  he  really  sees  the  object.  Every  one 
knows  there  is  nothing  real  behind  the  mirror  to  correspond  to 
the  image — that  no  light  can  penetrate  thither,  but  that  what 
is  called  the  image  is  simply  a  geometrical  point,  in  which  the 
reflected  rays,  if  produced  backwards,  would  intersect.  And, 
accordingly,  no  one  expects  the  image  to  produce  any  real  effect 
behind  the  mirror.  In  the  same  way  the  prism  shows  us  images 
of  objects  which  occupy  a  different  position  from  the  objects 
themselves ;  that  is  to  say,  the  light  which  an  object  sends  to 
the  prism  is  refracted  by  it,  so  that  it  appears  to  come  from  an 
object  lying  to  one  side,  called  the  image.  This  image,  again; 
is  not  real ;  it  is,  as  in  the  case  of  reflection,  the  geometrical 
point  in  which  the  refracted  rays  intersect  when  produced  back- 
wards. And  yet,  according  to  Goethe,  this  image  is  to  produce 
real  effects  by  its  displacement;  the  displaced  patch  of  light 
makes,  he  says,  the  dark  space  behind  it  appear  blue,  just  as  an 
imperfectly  transparent  body  would,  and  so  again  the  displaced 
dark  patch  makes  the  bright  space  behind  appear  reddish-yellow. 
That  Goethe  really  treats  the  image  as  an  actual  object  in  the 
place  it  appears  to  occupy  is  obvious  enough,  especially  as  he  is 
compelled  to  assume,  in  the  course  of  his  explanation,  that  the 
blue  and  red  edges  of  the  bright  space  are  respectively  before 
and  behind  the  dark  image  which,  like  it,  is  displaced  by  the 
prism.  He  does,  in  fact,  remain  loyal  to  the  appearance  pre- 
sented to  the  senses,  and  treats  a  geometrical  locus  as  if  it  were 
a  material  object.  Again,  he  does  not  scruple  at  one  time  to 
make  red  and  blue  destroy  each  other,  as,  for  example,  in  the 

I.  E 


50  ON  GOETHE'S  SCIENTIFIC  RESEARCHES. 

blue  edge  of  a  red  surface  seen  through  the  prism,  and  at 
another  to  construct  out  of  them  a  beautiful  purple,  as  when 
the  blue  and  red  edges  of  two  neighbouring  white  surfaces 
meet  in  a  black  ground.  And  when  he  comes  to  Newton's 
more  complicated  experiments,  he  is  driven  to  still  more  mar- 
vellous expedients.  As  long  as  you  treat  his  explanations  as  a 
pictorial  way  of  representing  the  physical  processes,  you  may 
acquiesce  in  them,  and  even  frequently  find  them  vivid  and 
characteristic,  but  as  physical  elucidations  of  the  phenomena 
they  are  absolutely  irrational. 

In  conclusion,  it  must  be  obvious  to  evpry  one  that  the 
theoretical  part  of  the  Theory  of  Colour  is  not  natural  philo- 
sophy at  all ;  at  the  same  time  we  can,  to  a  certain  extent,  see 
that  the  poet  wanted  to  introduce  a  totally  different  method 
into  the  study  of  Nature,  and  more  or  less  understand  how  he 
rame  to  do  so.  Poetry  is  concerned  solely  with  the  '  beautiful 
show  which  makes  it  possible  to  contemplate  the  ideal ;  how 
that  show  is  produced  is  a  matter  of  indifference.  Even  nature 
is,  in  the  poet's  eyes,  but  the  sensible  expression  of  the  spiritual. 
The  natural  philosopher,  on  the  other  haud,  tries  to  discover  the 
levers,  the  cords,  and  the  pulleys  which  work  behind  the  scenes, 
and  shift  them.  Of  course  the  sight  of  the  machinery  spoils 
the  beautiful  show,  and  therefore  the  poet  would  gladly  talk  it 
out  of  existence,  and  ignoring  cords  and  pulleys  as  the  chimeras 
of  a  pedant's  brain,  he  would  have  us  believe  that  the  scenes 
shift  themselves,  or  are  governed  by  the  idea  of  the  drama. 
And  it  is  just  characteristic  of  Goethe  that  he,  and  he  alone 
among  poets,  must  needs  break  a  lance  with  natural  philosophers. 
Other  poets  are  either  so  entirely  carried  away  by  the  fire  of 
their  enthusiasm  that  they  do  not  trouble  themselves  about  the 
disturbing  influences  of  the  outer  world,  or  else  they  rejoice 
in  the  triumphs  of  mind  over  matter,  even  on  that  unpropitious 
battlefield.  But  Goethe,  whom  no  intensity  of  subjective  feeling 
could  blind  to  the  realities  around  him,  cannot  rest  satisfied 
until  he  has  stamped  reality  itself  with  the  image  and  super- 
scription of  poetry.  This  constitutes  the  peculiar  beauty  of  his 
poetry,  and  at  the  same  time  fully  accounts  for  his  resolute 


ON  GOETHE'S  SCIENTIFIC  RESEARCHES.  51 

hostility  to  the  machinery  that  every  moment  threatens  to 
disturb  his  poetic  repose,  and  for  his  determination  to  attack 
the  enemy  in  his  own  camp. 

But  we  cannot  triumph  over  the  machinery  of  matter 
by  ignoring  it;  we  can  triumph  over  it  only  by  subordinating 
it  to  the  aims  of  our  moral  intelligence.  We  must  familiarise 
ourselves  with  its  levers  and  pulleys,  fatal  though  it  be  to  poetic 
contemplation,  in  order  to  be  able  to  govern  them  after  our  own 
will,  and  therein  lies  the  complete  justification  of  physical 
investigation,  and  its  vast  importance  for  the  advance  of  human 
civilisation. 

From  what  I  have  said  it  will  be  apparent  that  Goethe  did 
follow  the  same  line  of  thought  in  all  his  contributions  to  science, 
but  that  the  problems  he  encountered  were  of  diametrically 
opposite  characters.  And,  perhaps,  when  it  is  understood  how 
the  self-same  characteristic  of  his  intellect,  which  in  one  branch 
of  science  won  for  him  immortal  renown,  entailed  upon  him 
egregious  failure  in  the  other,  it  will  tend  to  dissipate,  in  the 
minds  of  many  worshippers  of  the  great  poet,  a  lingering  pre- 
judice against  natural  philosophers,  whom  they  suspect  of  being 
blinded  by  narrow  professional  pride  to  the  loftiest  inspirations 
of  genius. 


63 


ON  THE 

PHYSIOLOGICAL  CAUSES   OF  HAEMONT 
IN    MUSIC, 

A  Lecture  delivered  in  Bonn  during  the  Winter  nf  1857. 


LADIES  AND  GENTLEMEN, — In  the  native  town  of  Beethoven,  the 
mightiest  among  the  heroes  of  harmony,  no  subject  seemed 
to  me  better  adapted  for  a  popular  audience  than  music  itself. 
Following,  therefore,  the  direction  of  my  researches  during  the 
last  few  years,  I  will  endeavour  to  explain  to  you  what  physics 
and  physiology  have  to  say  regarding  the  most  cherished  art  of 
the  Rhenish  land — music  and  musical  relations.  Music  has 
hitherto  withdrawn  itself  from  scientific  treatment  more  than 
any  other  art.  Poetry,  painting,  and  sculpture  borrow  at  least 
the  material  for  their  delineations  from  the  world  of  experience. 
They  portray  nature  and  man.  Not  only  can  their  material  be 
critically  investigated  in  respect  to  its  correctness  and  truth 
to  nature,  but  scientific  art-criticism,  however  much  enthusiasts 
may  have  disputed  its  right  to  do  so,  has  actually  succeeded  in 
making  some  progress  in  investigating  the  causes  of  that  aesthetic 
pleasure  which  it  is  the  intention  of  these  arts  to  excite.  In 
music,  on  the  other  hand,  it  seems  at  first  sight  as  if  those  were 
still  in  the  right  who  reject  all  '  anatomisation  of  pleasurable 
sensations.'  This  art,  borrowing  no  part  of  its  material  from 
the  experience  of  our  senses,  not  attempting  to  describe,  and 


54  ON   THE   PHYSIOLOGICAL   CAUSES   OF 

only  exceptionally  to  imitate  the  outer  world,  necessarily  with- 
draws from  scientific  consideration  the  chief  points  of  attack 
which  other  arts  present,  and  hence  seems  to  be  as  incompre- 
hensible and  wonderful  as  it  is  certainly  powerful  in  its  effects. 
"We  are,  therefore,  obliged,  and  we  purpose,  to  confine  ourselves, 
in  the  first  place,  to  a  consideration  of  the  material  of  the  art, 
musical  sounds  or  sensations.  It  always  struck  me  as  a  wonder- 
ful and  peculiarly  interesting  mystery,  that  in  the  theory  of 
musical  sounds,  in  the  physical  and  technical  foundations  of 
music,  which  above  all  other  arts  seems  in  its  action  on  the 
mind  as  the  most  immaterial,  evanescent,  and  tender  creator  of 
incalculable  and  indescribable  states  of  consciousness,  that  here 
in  especial  the  science  of  purest  and  strictest  thought — mathe- 
matics— .should  prove  pre-eminently  fertile.  Thorough  bass  is  a 
kind  of  applied  mathematics.  In  considering  musical  intervals, 
divisions  of  time,  and  so  forth,  numerical  fractions,  and  some- 
times even  logarithms,  play  a  prominent  part.  Mathematics 
and  music !  the  most  glaring  possible  opposite.?  of  human 
thought!  and  yet  connected,  mutually  sustained!  It  is  as 
if  they  would  demonstrate  the  hidden  consensus  of  all  the 
actions  of  our  mind,  which  in  the  revelations  of  genius  makes 
us  forefeet  unconscious  utterances  of  a  mysteriously  active 
intelligence. 

When  I  considered  physical  acoustics  from  a  physiological 
point  of  view,  and  thus  more  closely  followed  up  the  part  which 
the  ear  plays  in  the  perception  of  musical  sounds,  much  became 
clear  of  which  the  connection  had  not  been  previously  evident. 
I  will  attempt  to  inspire  you  with  some  of  the  interest  which 
these  questions  have  awakened  in  niy  own  mind,  by  endeavour- 
ing to  exhibit  a  few  of  the  results  of  physical  and  physiological 
acoustics. 

The  short  space  of  time  at  my  disposal  obliges  me  to  confine 
my  attention  to  one  particular  point;  but  I  shall  select  the 
most  important  of  all,  which  will  best  show  you  the  significance 
and  results  of  scientific  investigation  in  this  field ;  I  mean  the 
foundation  of  concord.  It  is  an  acknowledged  fact  that  the 
numbers  of  the  vibrations  of  concordant  tones  bear  to  each 


HARMONY   IX   MUSIC.  55 

other  ratios  expressible  by  small  whole  numbers.  But  why  ? 
What  have  the  ratios  of  small  whole  numbers  to  do  with  con 
cord?  This  is  an  old  lidd  e,  propounded  by  Pythagoras,  and 
hitherto  unsolved.  Let  us  see  whether  the  means  at  the  com- 
mand of  modern  science  will  furnish  the  answer. 

First  of  all,  what  is  a  musical  tone?  Common  experience 
teaches  us  that  all  sounding  bodies  are  in  a  state  of  vibration. 
This  vibration  can  be  seen  and  felt ;  and  in  the  case  of  loud 
sounds  we  feel  the  trembling  of  the  air  even  without  touching 
the  sounding  bodies.  Physical  science  has  ascertained  that  any 
series  of  impulses  which  produce  a  vibration  of  the  air  will,  if 
repeated  with  sufficient  rapidity,  generate  sound. 

This  sound  becomes  a  musical  tone,  when  such  rapid  im- 
pulses recur  with  perfect  regularity  and  in  precisely  equal  times. 
Irregular  agitation  of  the  air  generates  only  noise.  The  pitch 
of  a  musical  tone  depends  on  the  number  of  impulses  which 
take  place  in  a  given  time ;  the  more  there  are  in  the  same  time 
the  higher  or  sharper  is  the  tone.  And,  as  before  remarked, 
there  is  found  to  be  a  close  relationship  between  the  well-known 
harmonious  musical  intervals  and  the  number  of  the  vibrations 
of  the  air.  If  twice  as  many  vibrations  are  performed  in  the 
same  time  for  one  tone  as  for  another,  the  first  is  the  octave 
above  the  second.  If  the  numbers  of  vibrations  in  the  same 
time  are  as  2  to  3,  the  two  tones  form  a  fifth ;  if  they  are  as  4 
to  5,  the  two  tones  form  a  major  third. 

If  you  observe  that  the  numbers  of  the  vibrations  which 
generate  the  tones  of  the  major  chord  C  E  G  c  are  in  the  ratio 
of  the  numbers  4:5:6:8,  you  can  deduce  from  these  all 
other  relations  of  musical  tones,  by  imagining  a  new  major 
chord,  having  the  same  relations  of  the  numbers  of  vibrations, 
to  be  formed  upon  each  of  the  above-named  tones.  The  num- 
bers of  vibrations  within  the  limits  of  audible  tones  which 
would  be  obtained  by  executing  the  calculation  thus  indicated 
are  extraordinarily  different.  Since  the  octave  above  any  tone 
has  twice  as  many  vibrations  as  the  tone  itself,  the  second  octave 
above  will  have  four  times,  the  third  has  eight  times  as  many. 
Our  modern  pianofortes  have  seven  octaves.  Their  highest 


fG  ON   THE    PHYSIOLOGICAL   CAUSES   OF 

tones,  therefore,  perform  128  vibrations  in  the  time  that  theii 
lowest  tone  makes  one  single  vibration. 

The  deepest  Cj  which  our  pianos  usually  possess  answers  to 
the  sixteen-foot  open  pipe  of  the  organ — musicians  call  it  the 
'  contra-C ' — and  makes  thirty-three  vibrations  in  one  second  of 
time.  This  is  very  nearly  the  limit  of  audibility.  You  will 
have  observed  that  these  tones  have  a  dull,  bad  quality  of  sound 
on  the  piano,  and  that  it  is  difficult  to  determine  their  pitch  and 
the  accuracy  of  their  tuning.  On  the  organ  the  contra-C  is 
somewhat  more  powerful  than  on  the  piano,  but  even  here  some 
uncertainty  is  felt  in  judging  of  its  pitch.  On  larger  organs 
there  is  a  whole  octave  of  tones  below  the  contra-C,  reaching  to 
the  next  lower  C,  with  16^  vibrations  in  a  second.  But  the  ear 
can  scarcely  separate  these  tones  from  an  obscure  drone ;  and 
the  deeper  they  are  the  more  plainly  can  it  distinguish  the  sepa- 
rate impulses  of  the  air  to  which  they  are  due.  Hence  they 
are  used  solely  in  conjunction  with  the  next  higher  octaves,  to 
strengthen  their  notes,  and  produce  an  impression  of  greater 
depth. 

With  the  exception  of  the  organ,  all  musical  instruments, 
however  diverse  the  methods  in  which  their  sounds  are  pro- 
duced, have  their  limit  of  depth  at  about  the  same  point  in  the 
scale  as  the  piano ;  not  because  it  would  be  impossible  to  produce 
slower  impulses  of  the  air  of  sufficient  power,  but  because  the 
ear  refuses  its  office,  and  hears  slower  impulses  separately,  without 
gathering  them  up  into  single  tones. 

The  often-repeated  assertion  of  the  French  physicist  Savart, 
that  he  heard  tones  of  eight  vibrations  in  a  second,  upon  a 
peculiarly  constructed  instrument,  seems  due  to  an  error. 

Ascending  the  scale  from  the  contra-C,  pianofortes  usually 
have  a  compass  of  seven  octaves,  up  to  the  so-called  five-accented 
c,  which  has  4,224  vibrations  in  a  second.  Among  orchestral 
instruments  it  is  only  the  piccolo  flute  which  can  reach  as  high, 
and  this  will  give  even  one  tone  higher.  The  violin  usually 
mounts  no  higher  than  the  e  below,  which  has  2,640  vibrations 
— of  course  we  excapt  the  gymnastics  of  heaven-scaling  virtuosi, 
who  are  ever  striving  to  excruciate  their  audience  by  some  new 


HARMONY   IN    MUSIC.  57 

impossibility.  Such  performers  may  aspire  to  three  whole 
octaves  lying  above  the  five-accented  c,  and  very  painful  to  the 
ear,  for  their  existence  has  been  established  by  Despretz,  who, 
by  exciting  small  tuning-forks  with  a  violin  bow,  obtained  and 
heard  the  eight-accented  c,  having  32,770  vibrations  in  a  second. 
Here  the  sensation  of  tone  seemed  to  have  reached  its  upper 
limit,  and  the  intervals  were  really  undistinguishable  in  the 
later  octaves. 

The  musical  pitch  of  a  tone  depends  entirely  on  the  number 
of  vibrations  of  the  air  in  a  second,  and  not  at  all  upon  the 
mode  in  which  they  are  produced.  It  is  quite  indifferent  whether 
they  are  generated  by  the  vibrating  strings  of  a  piano  or  violin, 
the  vocal  chords  of  the  human  larynx,  the  metal  tongues  of  the 
harmonium,  the  reeds  of  the  clarionet,  oboe,  and  bassoon,  the 
trembling  lips  of  the  trumpeter,  or  the  air  cut  by  a  sharp  edge 
in  organ  pipes  and  flutes. 

A  tone  of  the  same  number  of  vibrations  has  always  the 
same  pitch,  by  whichever  one  of  these  instruments  it  is  pro- 
duced. That  which  distinguishes  the  note  A  of  a  piano,  for 
example,  from  the  equally  high  A  of  the  violin,  flute,  clarionet, 
or  trumpet,  is  called  the  quality  of  the  tone,  and  to  this  we  shall 
have  to  recur  presently. 

As  an  interesting  example  of  these  assertions,  I  beg  to  show  you  a 
peculiar  physical  instrument  for  producing  musical  tones,  called  the 
siren,  Fig.  1,  which  is  especially  adapted  to  establish  the  properties 
resulting  from  the  ratios  of  the  numbers  of  vibrations. 

In  order  to  produce  tones  upon  this  instrument,  the  portvents  g0 
and  gj  are  connected  by  means  of  flexible  tubes  with  a  bellows.  The 
air  enters  into  round  brass  boxes,  a0  and  a^  and  escapes  by  the  per- 
forated covers  of  these  boxes  at  c0  and  c,.  But  the  holes  for  the 
escape  of  air  are  not  perfectly  free.  Immediately  before  the  covers 
of  both  boxes  there  are  two  other  perforated  discs,  fastened  to  a  per- 
pendicular axis  k,  which  turns  with  great  readiness.  In  the  figure, 
only  the  perforated  disc  can  be  seen  at  c0,  and  immediately  below  it 
is  the  similarly  perforated  cover  of  the  box.  In  the  upper  box,  c]? 
only  the  edge  of  the  disc  is  visible.  If  then  the  holes  of  the  disc  are 
precisely  opposite  to  those  of  the  cover,  the  ah-  can  escape  freely. 
But  if  the  disc  is  made  to  revolve,  so  that  some  of  its  unperforated 


HARMONY   IN   MUSIC.  59 

portions  stand  before  the  holes  of  the  box,  the  air  cannot  escape  at 
all.  On  turning  the  disc  rapidly,  the  vent-holes  of  the  box  are  alter- 
nately opened  and  closed.  During  the  opening,  air  escapes ;  during 
the  closure,  no  air  can  pass.  Hence  the  continuous  stream  of  air  from 
the  bellows  is  converted  into  a  series  of  discontinuous  puffs,  which, 
when  they  follow  one  another  with  sufficient  rapidity,  gather  them- 
selves together  into  a  tone. 

Each  of  the  revolving  discs  of  this  instrument  (_which  is  more 
complicated  in  its  construction  than  any  one  of  the  kind  hitherto 
'uade,  and  hence  admits  of  a  much  greater  number  of  combinations 
of  tone)  has  four  concentric  circles  of  holes,  the  lower  set  having 
8, 10,  12,  18,  and  the  upper  set  9,  12,  15,  and  16  holes  respectively. 
The  series  of  holes  in  the  covers  of  the  boxes  are  precisely  the  same 
as  those  in  the  discs,  but  under  each  of  them  lies  a  perforated  ring, 
which  can  be  so  arranged,  by  means  of  the  stops  i  i  i  i,  that  the 
corresponding  holes  of  the  cover  can  either  communicate  freely  with 
the  inside  of  the  box,  or  are  entirely  cut  off  from  it;  We  are  thus 
enabled  to  use  any  one  of  the  eight  series  of  holes  singly,  or  com- 
bined two  and  two,  or  three  and  three  together,  in  any  arbitrary 
manner. 

The  round  boxes,  h0  h0  and  hj  hn  of  which  halves  only  are  drawn 
in  the  figure,  serve  by  their  resonance  to  soften  the  harshness  of  the 
tone. 

The  holes  in  the  boxes  and  discs  are  cut  obliquely,  so  that  when 
the  air  enters  the  boxes  through  one  or  more  of  the  series  of  holes, 
the  wind  itself  drives  the  discs  round  with  a  perpetually  increasing 
velocity. 

On  beginning  to  blow  the  instrument,  we  first  hear  separate  im- 
pulses of  the  air,  escaping  as  puffs,  as  often  as  the  holes  of  the  disc 
pass  in  front  of  those  of  the  box.  These  puffs  of  air  follow  one  an- 
other more  and  more  quickly,  as  the  velocity  of  the  revolving  discs 
increases,  just  like  the  puffs  of  steam  of  a  locomotive  on  beginning  to 
move  with  the  train.  They  next  produce  a  whirring  and  whizzing, 
which  constantly  becomes  more  rapid.  At  last  we  hear  a  dull  drone, 
which,  as  the  velocity  further  increases,  gradually  gains  in  pitch  and 
strength. 

Suppose  that  the  discs  have  been  brought  to  a  velocity  of  33  re- 
volutions in  a  second,  and  that  the  series  with  8  holes  has  been 
opened.  At  each  revolution  of  the  disc  all  these  8  holes  will  pass 
before  each  separate  hole  of  the  cover.  Hence  there  will  be  8  puffs 
for  each  revolution  of  the  disc,  or  S  times  33,  that  is,  20-i  pulls  in  a 


60  ON   THE   PHYSIOLOGICAL   CAUSES   OF 

second.  This  gives  us  the  once-accented  c'  of  our  musical  scale  [that 
is,  '  middle  c,'  written  on  the  leger  line  between  the  bass  and  treble 
staves].  But  on  opening  the  series  of  16  holes  instead,  we  have  twice 
as  many,  or  16  times  33,  that  is,  528  vibrations  in  a  second.  We 
hear  exactly  the  octave  above  the  first  </,  that  is,  the  twice-accented 
c''  [or  c  on  the  third  space  of  the  treble  staff].  By  opening  both  the 
series  of  8  and  16  holes  at  once,  we  have  both  c'  and  c"  at  once,  and 
can  convince  ourselves  that  we  have  the  absolutely  pure  concord  of 
the  octave.  By  taking  8  and  12  holes,  which  give  numbers  of  vibra- 
tions in  the  ratio  of  2  to  3,  we  have  the  concord  of  a  perfect  fifth. 
Similarly  12  and  16  or  9  and  12  give  fourths,  12  and  15  give  a  major 
third,  and  so  on. 

The  upper  box  is  furnished  with  a  contrivance  for  slightly  sharpen- 
ing or  flattening  the  tones  which  it  produces.  This  box  is  movable 
upon  an  axis,  and  connected  with  a  toothed  wheel,  which  is  worked 
by  the  driver  attached  to  the  handle  d.  By  turning  the  handle 
slowly  while  one  of  the  series  of  holes  in  the  upper  box  is  in  use,  the 
tone  will  be  sharper  or  natter,  according  as  the  box  moves  in  the 
opposite  direction  to  the  disc,  or  in  the  same  direction  as  the  disc. 
When  the  motion  is  in  the  opposite  direction,  the  holes  meet  those  of 
the  disc  a  little  sooner  than  they  otherwise  would,  the  time  of  vibra- 
tion of  the  tone  is  shortened,  and  the  tone  becomes  sharper.  The 
contrary  ensues  in  the  other  case. 

Now,  on  blowing  through  8  holes  below  and  16  above,  we  have  a 
perfect  octave,  as  long  as  the  upper  box  is  still ;  but  when  it  is  ic 
motion,  the  pitch  of  the  upper  tone  is  slightly  altered,  and  the  octave 
becomes  false. 

On  blowing  through  12  holes  above  and  18  below,  the  result  is  a 
perfect  fifth  as  long  as  the  upper  box  is  at  rest,  but  if  it  moves  the 
concord  is  perceptibly  injured. 

These  experiments  with  the  siren  show  us,  therefore : — 

1.  That  a  series  of  puffs  following  one  another  with  sufficient 
rapidity  produce  a  musical  tone. 

2.  That  the  more  rapidly  they  follow  one  another,  the  sharper  is 
the  tone. 

3.  That  when  the  ratio  of  the  number  of  vibrations  is  exactly  1  to 
2,  the  result  is  a  perfect  octave  ;  when  it  is  2  to  3,  a  perfect  fifth  ; 
when  it  is  3  to  4,  a  pure  fourth,  and  so  on.    The  slightest  alteration 
in  these  ratios  destroys  the  purity  of  the  concord. 

You  will  perceive,  from  what  has  been  hitherto  adduced, 


HARMOXY   IX    MUSIC.  61 

Chat  the  human  ear  is  affected  by  vibrations  of  the  air,  within 
certain  degrees  of  rapidity — viz.  from  about  20  to  about  32,000 
in  a  second — and  that  the  sensation  of  musical  tone  arises  from 
this  affection. 

That  the  sensation  thus  excited  is  a  sensation  of  musical 
tone  does  not  depend  in  any  way  upon  the  peculiar  manner  in. 
•which  the  air  is  agitated,  but  solely  on  the  peculiar  powers  of 
sensation  possessed  by  our  ears  and  auditory  nerves.  I  re- 
marked, a  little  while  ago,  that  when  the  tones  are  loud  the 
agitation  of  the  air  is  perceptible  to  the  skin.  In  this  way 
deaf  mutes  can  perceive  the  motion  of  the  air  which  we  call 
sound.  But  they  do  not  hear,  that  is,  they  have  no  sensation  of 
tone  in  the  ear.  They  feel  the  motion  by  the  nerves  of  the  skin, 
producing  that  peculiar  description  of  sensation  called  whirring. 
The  limits  of  the  rapidity  of  vibration  within  which  the  ear 
feels  an  agitation  of  the  air  to  be  sound,  depend  also  wholly 
upon  the  peculiar  constitution  of  the  ear. 

When  the  siren  is  turned  slowly,  and  hence  the  puffs  of 
air  succeed  each  other  slowly,  you  hear  no  musical  sound.  By 
the  continually  increasing  rapidity  of  its  revolution,  no  essential 
change  is  produced  in  the  kind  of  vibration  of  the  air.  Nothing 
new  happens  externally  to  the  ear.  The  only  new  result  is  the 
sensation  experienced  by  the  ear,  which  then  for  the  first  time 
begins  to  be  affected  by  the  agitation  of  the  air.  Hence  the 
more  rapid  vibrations  receive  a  new  name,  and  are  called  Sound. 
If  you  admire  paradoxes,  you  may  say  that  aerial  vibrations  do 
not  become  sound  until  they  fall  upon  a  hearing  ear. 

I  must  now  describe  the  propagation  of  sound  through  the 
atmosphere.  The  motion  of  a  mass  of  air  through  which  a 
tone  passes  belongs  to  the  so-called  wave-motions — a  class  of 
motions  of  great  importance  in  physics.  Light,  as  well  as 
sound,  is  one  of  these  motions. 

The  name  is  derived  from  the  analogy  of  waves  on  the  sur- 
face of  water,  and  these  will  best  illustrate  the  peculiarity  of 
this  description  of  motion. 

When  a  point  in  a  surface  of  still  water  is  agitated — as  by 
throwing  in  a  stone — the  motion  thus  caused  is  propagated  in 


62  ON  THE   PHYSIOLOGICAL   CAUSES  OF 

the  form  of  waves,  which  spread  in  rings  over  the  surface  of 
the  water.  The  circles  of  waves  continue  to  increase  even  after 
rest  has  been  restored  at  the  point  first  affected.  At  the  same 
time  the  waves  become  continually  lower,  the  further  they  are 
removed  from  the  centre  of  motion,  and  gradually  disappear.  On 
each  wave- ring  we  distinguish  ridges  or  crests,  and  hollows  or 
troughs. 

Crest  and  trough  together  form  a  wave,  and  we  measure  its 
length  from  one  crest  to  the  next. 

While  the  wave  passes  over  the  surface  of  the  fluid,  the 
particles  of  the  water  which  form  it  do  not  move  on  with  it. 
This  is  easily  seen,  by  floating  a  chip  of  straw  on  the  water. 
When  the  waves  reach  the  chip,  they  raise  or  depress  it,  but 
when  they  have  passed  over  it  the  position  of  the  chip  is  not 
perceptibly  changed. 

Now  a  light  floating  chip  has  no  motion  different  from  that 
of  the  adjacent  particles  of  water.  Hence  we  conclude  that 
these  particles  do  not  follow  the  wave,  but,  after  some  pitching 
up  and  down,  remain  in  their  original  position.  That  which 
really  advances  as  a  wave  is,  consequently,  not  the  particles  of 
water  themselves,  but  only  a  superficial  form,  which  continues 
to  be  built  up  by  fresh  particles  of  water.  The  paths  of  the 
separate  particles  of  water  are  more  nearly  vertical  circles,  in 
which  they  revolve  with  a  tolerably  uniform  velocity,  as  long 
as  the  waves  pass  over  them. 

In  Fig.  2  the  dark  wave-line  ABC  represents  a  section  of  the 
surface  of  the  water  over  which  waves  are  running  in  the  direction 
of  the  arrows  above  a  and  c.  The  three  circles  a,  b,  and  c  represent 
the  paths  of  particular  particles  of  water  at  the  surface  of  the  wave. 
The  particle  which  revolves  in  the  circle  b  is  supposed,  at  the  time 
that  the  surface  of  the  water  presents  the  form  A  B  C,  to  be  at  its 
highest  point  B,  and  the  particles  revolving  in  the  circles  a  and 
c  to  he  simultaneously  in  their  lowest  positions. 

The  respective  particles  of  water  revolve  in  these  circles  in  the 
direction  marked  by  the  arrows.  The  dotted  curves  represent  other 
positions  of  the  passing  waves,  at  equal  intervals  of  time,  partly 
before  the  assumption  of  the  ABC  position  (as  for  the  crests  be- 
tween a  and  b),  and  partly  after  the  same  (for  the  crests  between  b 


HARMONY  IN   MUSIC.  63 

and  c).  The  positions  of  the  crests  are  marked  with  figures.  The 
same  figures  in  the  three  circles  show  where  the  respective  revolving 
particle  would  be,  at  the  moment  the  wave  assumed  the  corresponding 
form.  It  will  be  noticed  that  the  particles  advance  by  equal  arcs  of 
the  circles,  as  the  crest  of  the  wave  advances  by  equal  distances 
parallel  to  the  water  level. 

In  the  circle  b  it  will  be  further  seen  that  the  particle  of  water  in 
its  positions  1,  2,  3  hastens  to  meet  the  approaching  wave-crests, 
] ,  2,  3,  rises  on  its  left-hand  side,  is  then  carried  on  by  the  crest  from 
4  to  7  in  the  direction  of  its  advance,  afterwards  halts  behind  it, 
sinks  down  again  on  the  right  side,  and  finally  reaches  its  original 
position  at  13.  (In  the  'Lecture  itself,  Fig.  2  was  replaced  by  a 
working  model,  in  which  the  movable  particles,  connected  by  threads, 
really  revolved  in  circles,  while  connecting  elastic  threads  represented 
the  surface  of  the  water.) 


All  particles  at  the  surface  of  the  water,  as  you  see  by  this  draw- 
ing, describe  equal  circles.  The  particles  of  water  at  different  depths 
move  in  the  same  way,  but  as  the  depths  increase,  the  diameters  of 
their  circles  of  revolution  rapidly  diminish. 

In  this  way,  then,  arises  the  appearance  of  a  progressive  motion 
along  the  surface  of  the  water,  while  in  reality  the  moving  particles 
of  water  do  not  advance  with  the  wave,  but  perpetually  revolve  in 
their  small  circular  orbits. 

To  return  from  waves  of  water  to  waves  of  sound.  Ima- 
gine an  elastic  fluid  like  air  to  replace  the  water,  and  the 
waves  of  this  replaced  water  to  be  compressed  by  an  inflexible 
plate  laid  on  their  surface,  the  fluid  being  prevented  from  escap- 
ing laterally  from  the  pressure.  Then  on  the  waves  being  thus 
flattened  out,  the  ridges  where  the  fluid  had  been  heaped  up 


64  ON  THE  PHYSIOLOGICAL  CAUSES  OF 

will  produce  much  greater  density  than  the  hollows,  from  which 
the  fluid  had  been  removed  to  form  the  ridges.  Hence  the 
ridges  are  replaced  by  condensed  strata  of  air,  and  the  hollows 
by  rarefied  strata.  Now  further  imagine  that  these  compressed 
waves  are  propagated  by  the  same  law  as  before,  and  that  also 
the  vertical  circular  orbits  of  the  several  particles  of  water 
are  compressed  into  horizontal  straight  lines.  Then  the  waves 
of  sound  will  retain  the  peculiarity  of  having  the  particles  of 
air  only  oscillating  backwards  and  forwards  in  a  straight  line, 
while  the  wave  itself  remains  merely  a  progressive  form  of 
motion,  continually  composed  of  fresh  particles  of  air.  The 
immediate  result  then  would  be  waves  of  sound  spr/eading  out 
horizontally  from  their  origin. 

But  the  expansion  of  waves  of  sound  is  not  limited,  like 
those  of  water,  to  a  horizontal  surface.  They  can  spread  out  in 
any  direction  whatsoever.  Suppose  the  circles  generated  by 
a  stone  thrown  into  the  water  to  extend  in  all  directions  of  space, 
and  you  will  have  the  spherical  waves  of  air  by  which  sound  is 
propagated. 

Hence  we  can  continue  to  illustrate  the  peculiarities  of  the 
motion  of  sound  by  the  well-known  visible  motions  of  waves 
of  water. 

The  length  of  a  wave  of  water,  measured  from  crest  to 
crest,  is  extremely  different.  A  falling  drop,  or  a  breath  of  air, 
gently  curls  the  surface  of  the  water.  The  waves  in  the  wake 
of  a  steamboat  toss  the  swimmer  or  skiff  severely.  But  the 
waves  of  a  stormy  ocean  can  find  room  in  their  hollows  for  the 
keel  of  a  ship  of  the  line,  and  their  ridges  can  scarcely  be 
overlooked  from  the  mast-head.  The  waves  of  sound  present 
similar  differences.  The  little  curls  of  water  with  short  lengths 
of  wave  correspond  to  high  tones,  the  giant  ocean  billows  to 
deep  tones.  Thus  the  contrabass  C  has  a  wave  thirty-five  feet 
long,  its  higher  octave  a  wave  of  half  the  length,  while  the 
highest  tones  of  a  piano  have  waves  of  only  three  inches  in 
length. 

1  The  exact  lengths  of  waves  corresponding  to  certain  notes,  or  symbols  of 
tone,  depend  upon  the  standard  pitch  assigned  to  one  particular  note,  and 


HARMONY   IN   MUSIC.  65 

You  perceive  that  the  pitch  of  the  tone  corresponds  to  the 
length  of  the  wave.  To  this  we  should  add  that  the  height  of 
the  ridges,  or,  transferred  to  air,  the  degree  of  alternate  con- 
densation and  rarefaction,  corresponds  to  the  loudness  and 
intensity  of  the  tone.  But  waves  of  the  same  height  may 
have  different  forms.  The  crest  of  the  ridge,  for  example,  may 
be  rounded  off  or  pointed.  Corresponding  varieties  also  occur 
in  waves  of  sound  of  the  same  pitch  and  loudness.  The  so- 
called  timbre  or  quality  of  tone  is  what  corresponds  to  the  form 
of  the  waves  of  water.  The  conception  of  form  is  transferred 
from  waves  of  water  to  waves  of  sound.  Supposing  waves  of 
water  of  different  forms  to  be  pressed  flat  as  before,  the  surface, 
having  been  levelled,  will  of  course  display  no  differences  of 
form,  but,  in  the  interior  of  the  mass  of  water,  we  shall  have 
different  distributions  of  pressure,  and  hence  of  density,  which 
exactly  correspond  to  the  differences  of  form  in  the  still  uncom- 
pressed surface.  In  this  sense  then  we  can  continue  to  speak  of 

FIG.  3, 


the  form  of  waves  of  sound,  and  can  represent  it  geometrically. 
"VVe  make  the  curve  rise  where  the  pressure,  and  hence  density, 
increases,  and  fall  where  it  diminishes — just  as  if  we  had  a 
compressed  fluid  beneath  the  curve,  which  would  expand  to 
the  height  of  the  curve  in  order  to  regain  its  natural  density. 

Unfortunately,  the  form  of  waves  of  sound,  on  which  de- 
pends the  quality  of  the  tones  produced  by  various  sounding 
bodies,  can  at  present  be  assigned  in  only  a  very  few  cases. 

Among  the  forms  of  waves  of  sound  which  we  are  able  to 
determine  with  more  exactness  is  one  of  great  importance,  here 
termed  the  simple  or  pure  wave-form,  and  represented  in  Fig.  3. 

this  differs  in  different  countries.      Hence  the  figures  of  the  author  have 
been  left  unreduced.      They  are  sufficiently  near  to  those   usually  adopted  in 
England,  to  occasion  no  difficulty  to  the  reader  in  these  general  remarks. — TB 
I.  V 


66 


ON    THE   PHYSIOLOGICAL   CAUSES   OF 


It  can  be  seen  in  waves  of  watei  only  when  their  height  is 
small  in  comparison  with  their  length,  and  they  run  over  a 
smooth  surface  without  external  disturbance,  or  without  any 
action  of  wind.  Ridge  and  hollow  are  gently  rounded,  off, 
equally  broad  and  symmetrical,  so  that,  if  we  inverted  the  carve, 
the  ridges  would  exactly  fit  into  the  hollows,  and  conversely. 
This  form  of  wave  would  be  more  precisely  defined  by  saying 

FIG.  4. 


that  the  particles  of  water  describe  exactly  circular  orbits  of 
small  diameters,  with  exactly  uniform  velocities.  To  this  simple 
wave-form  corresponds  a  peculiar  species  of  tone,  which,  from 
reasons  to  be  hereafter  assigned,  depending  upon  its  relation  to 
quality,  we  will  term  a  simple  tone.  Such  tones  are  produced 
by  striking  a  tuning-fork  and  holding  it  before  the  opening  of  a 
properly  tuned  resonance  tube.  The  tone  of  tuneful  human 


HARMONY   IN   MUSIC. 


67 


voices,  singing  the  vowel  oo  in  too,  in  the  middle  positions  of  their 
register,  appears  not  to  differ  materially  from  this  form  of  wave. 
We  also  know  the  laws  of  the  motion  of  strings  with  suffi- 
cient accuracy  to  assign  in  some  cases  the  form  of  motion  which 
they  impart  to  the  air.  Thus  Fig.  4  represents  the  forms  suc- 
cessively assumed  by  a  string  struck,  as  in  the  German  Zither, 
by  a  pointed  style  [the  plectrum  of  the  ancient  lyra,  or  the  quill 
of  the  old  harpsichord,  which  may  be  easily  imitated  on  a 
guitar].  A  a  represents  the  form  assumed  by  the  string  at  the 
moment  of  percussion.  Then,  at  equal  intervals  of  time,  follow 
the  forms  B,  C,  D,  E,  F,  G  ;  and  then,  in  inverse  order,  F,  E,  D, 
C,  B,  A,  and  so  on  in  perpetual  repetition.  The  form  of  motion 
which  such  a  string,  by  means  of  an  attached  sounding-board, 
imparts  to  the  surrounding  air,  probably  corresponds  to  the 
broken  line  in  Fig.  5,  where  h  h  indicates  the  position  of  equili- 
brium, and  the  letters  a  b  c  d  e  f  g  show  the  line  of  the  wave 
which  is  produced  by  the  action  of  several  forms  of  string 
marked  by  the  corresponding  capital  letters  in  Fig.  4.  It  is 
easily  seen  how  greatly  this  form  of  wave  (which  of  course 

FIG.  5. 


could   not  occur  in  water)  differs  from  that   of  Fig.  3  (inde- 
pendently of  magnitude),  as  the  string  only  imparts  to  the  air  a 
series  of  short  impulses,  alternately  directed  to  opposite  sides.1 
The  waves  of  air  produced  by  the  tone  of  a  violin  would,  on 

FIG.  6. 


the  same  principle,  be  represented  by  Fig.  6.     During  each 

1  It  is  here  as*nmed  that  the  sounding-board  and  air  in  contact  with  it 
immediately  obey  the  impulse  given  by  the  end  of  the  string  without  exercising 
a  perceptible  reaction  on  the  motion  of  the  string. 


C8  OX  THE   PHYSIOLOGICAL   CAUSES  OP 

period  of  vibration  the  pressure  increases  uniformly,  and  at  the 
end  falls  back  suddenly  to  its  minimum. 

It  is  to  such  differences  in  the  forms  of  the  waves  of  sound 
that  the  variety  of  quality  in  musical  tones  is  due.  "We  may 
even  carry  the  analogy  farther.  The  more  uniformly  rounded  the 
form  of  wave,  the  softer  and  milder  is  the  quality  of  tone.  The 
more  jerking  and  angular  the  wave-form,  the  more  piercing  the 
quality.  Tuning-forks,  with  their  rounded  forms  of  wave  (Fig. 
3),  have  an  extraordinarily  soft  quality;  and  the  qualities  of 
tone  generated  by  the  zither  and  violin  resemble  in  harshness 
the  angularity  of  their  wave-forms.  (Figs.  5  and  6.) 

Finally,  I  would  direct  your  attention  to  an  instructive 
spectacle,  which  I  have  never  been  able  to  view  without  a  cer- 
tain degree  of  physico-scientific  delight,  because  it  displays  to 
the  bodily  eye,  on  the  surface  of  water,  what  otherwise  could 
only  be  recognised  by  the  mind's  eye  of  the  mathematical  thinker 
in  a  mass  of  air  traversed  in  all  directions  by  waves  of  sound. 
I  allude  to  the  composition  of  many  different  systems  of  waves, 
as  they  pass  over  one  another,  each  undisturbedly  pursuing  its 
own  path.  We  can  watch  it  from  the  parapet  of  any  bridge 
spanning  a  river,  but  it  is  most  complete  and  sublime  when 
viewed  from  a  cliff  beside  the  sea.  It  is  then  rare  not  to  see 
innumerable  systems  of  waves,  of  various  length,  propagated  in 
various  directions.  The  longest  come  from  the  deep  sea  and  dash 
against  the  shore.  Where  the  boiling  breakers  burst  shorter 
waves  arise,  and  run  back  again  towards  the  sea.  Perhaps 
a  bird  of  prey  darting  after  a  fish  gives  rise  to  a  system  of 
circular  waves,  which,  rocking  over  the  undulating  surface,  are 
propagated  with  the  same  regularity  as  on  the  mirror  of  an  in- 
land lake.  And  thus,  from  the  distant  horizon,  where  white 
lines  of  foam  on  the  steel  blue  surface  betray  the  coming  trains 
of  wave,  down  to  the  sand  beneath  our  feet,  where  the  impres- 
sion of  their  arcs  remains,  there  is  unfolded  before  our  eyes  a 
sublime  image  of  immeasurable  power  and  unceasing  variety, 
which,  as  the  eye  at  once  recognises  its  pervading  order  and  law, 
enchains  and  exalts  without  confusing  the  mind. 

Now,  just  in  the  same  way  you  must  conceive  the  air  of  a 


HARMONY  IN  MUSIC.  69 

concert-hall  or  TxJl-room  traversed  in  every  direction,  and  not 
merely  on  the  surface,  by  a  variegated  crowd  of  intersecting 
wave-systems.  From  the  mouths  of  the  male  singers  proceed 
waves  of  six  to  twelve  feat  in  length  ;  from  the  lips  of  the  song- 
stresses dart  shorter  waves,  from  eighteen  to  thirty-six  inches 
long.  The  rustling  of  silken  skirts  excites  little  curls  in  the 
air,  each  instrument  in  the  orchestra  emits  its  peculiar  waves, 
and  all  these  systems  expand  spherically  from  their  respective 
centres,  dart  through  each  other,  are  reflected  from  the  walls  of 
the  room,  and  thus  rush  backwards  and  forwards,  until  they 
succumb  to  the  greater  force  of  newly  generated  tones. 

Although  this  spectacle  is  veiled  from  the  material  eye,  we 
have  another  bodily  organ,  the  ear,  specially  adapted  to  reveal 
it  to  us.  This  analyses  the  interdigitation  of  the  wavas,  which 
in  snch  cases  would  be  far  more  confused  than  the  intersection 
of  the  water  undulations,  separates  the  several  tones  which 
compose  it,  and  distinguishes  the  voices  of  men  and  women — 
nay,  even  of  individuals — the  peculiar  qualities  of  tone  given 
out  by  each  instrument,  the  rustling  of  the  dresses,  the  footfalls 
of  the  walkers,  and  so  on. 

It  is  necessary  to  examine  the  circumstances  with  greater 
minuteness.  When  a  bird  of  prey  dips  into  the  sea,  rings  of 
waves  arise,  which  are  propagated  as  slowly  and  regularly  upon 
the  moving  surface  as  upon  a  surface  at  rest.  These  rings  are 
cut  into  the  curved  surface  of  the  waves  in  precisely  the  same 
way  as  they  would  have  been  into  the  still  surface  of  a  lake. 
The  form  of  the  external  surface  of  the  water  is  determined  in 
this,  as  in  other  more  complicated  cases,  by  taking  the  height 
of  each  point  to  be  the  height  of  all  the  ridges  of  the  waves 
which  coincide  at  this  point  at  one  time,  after  deducting  the  sum 
of  all  similarly  simultaneously  coincident  hollows.  Such  a  sum  of 
positive  magnitudes  (the  ridges)  and  negative  magnitudes  (the 
hollows),  where  the  latter  have  to  be  subtracted  instead  of  being 
added,  is  called  an  algebraical  sum.  Using  this  term,  then,  we 
may  say  that  the  height  of  every  point  of  the  surface  of  t/M 
water  is  equal  to  the  algebraical  sum  of  all  the  portions  of  the 
waves  which  at  that  moment  there  concur. 


70  OX   THE   PHYSIOLOGICAL   CAUSES   OF 

It  is  the  same  with  the  waves  of  sound.  They,  too,  are 
added  together  at  every  point  of  the  mass  of  air,  as  well  as 
in  contact  with  the  listener's  ear.  For  them  also  the  degree  of 
condensation  and  the  velocity  of  the  particles  of  air  in  the 
passages  of  the  organ  of  hearing  are  equal  to  the  algebraical 
sums  of  the  separate  degrees  of  condensation  and  of  the  velo- 
cities of  the  waves  of  sound,  considered  apart.  This  single  motion 
of  the  air  produced  by  the  simultaneous  action  of  various  sound- 
ing bodies,  has  now  to  be  analysed  by  the  air  into  the  separate 
paits  which  correspond  to  their  separate  effects.  For  doing  this 
the  ear  is  much  more  unfavourably  situated  than  the  eye.  The 
latter  surveys  the  whole  und ulat  ing  surface  at  a  glance.  But  the 
ear  can,  of  course,  only  perceive  the  motion  of  the  particles  of  air 
which  impinge  upon  it.  And  yet  the  ear  solves  its  problem  with 
the  grea test  exactness,  certainty,  and  determinacy.  This  power 
of  the  ear  is  of  supreme  importance  for  hearing.  Were  it  not 
present  it  would  be  impossible  to  distinguish  different  tones. 

Some  recent  anatomical  discoveries  appear  to  give  a  clue  to 
the  explanation  of  this  important  power  of  the  ear. 

You  will  all  have  observed  the  phenomena  of  the  sym pathetic 
production  of  tones  in  musical  instruments,  especially  stringed 
instruments.  The  string  of  a  pianoforte  when  the  damper  is 
raised  begins  to  vibrata  as  soon  as  its  proper  tone  is  produced 
in  its  neighbourhood  with  sufficient  force  by  some  other  means. 
When  this  foreign  tone  ceases  the  tone  of  the  string  will  be 
heard  to  continue  some  little  time  longer.  If  we  put  little  paper 
riders  on  the  string  they  will  be  jerked  off  when  its  tone  is  thus 
produced  in  the  neighbourhood.  This  sympathetic  action  of 
the  string  depends  on  the  impact  of  the  vibrating  particles  of 
air  against  the  string  arid  its  sounding-board. 

Each  separate  wave-crest  (or  condensation)  of  air  which 
passes  by  the  string  is,  of  course,  too  weak  to  produce  a  sensible 
motion  in  it.  But  when  a  long  series  of  wave-crests  (or  con- 
densations) strike  the  string  in  such  a  manner  that  each  succeed- 
ing one  increases  the  slight  tremor  which  resulted  from  the 
action  of  its  predecessors,  the  effect  finally  becomes  sensible. 
It  is  a  process  of  exactly  the  same  nature  as  the  swinging  of  a 


HARMONY   EN   MUSIC.  71 

heavy  bell.  A  powerful  man  can  scarcely  move  it  sensibly  by 
a  single  impulse.  A  boy,  by  pulling  the  rope  at  regular  intervals 
corresponding  to  the  time  of  its  oscillations,  can  gradually  bring 
it  into  violent  motion. 

This  peculiar  reinforcement  of  vibration  depends  entirely 
on  the  rhythmical  application  of  the  impulse.  When  the  bell 
has  been  once  made  to  vibrate  as  a  pendulum  in  a  very  small 
arc,  and  the  boy  always  pulls  the  rope  as  it  falls,  and  at  a  time 
that  his  pull  augments  the  existing  velocity  of  the  bell,  this 
velocity,  increasing  slightly  at  each  pull,  will  gradually  become 
considerable.  But  if  the  boy  apply  his  power  at  irregular  in- 
tervals, sometimes  increasing  and  sometimes  diminishing  the 
motion  of  the  bell,  he  will  produce  no  sensible  effect. 

In  the  same  way  that  a  mere  boy  is  thus  enabled  to  swing 
a  heavy  bell,  the  tremors  of  light  and  mobile  air  suffice  to  set 
in  motion  the  heavy  and  solid  mass  of  steel  contained  in  a 
tuning-fork,  provided  that  the  tone  which  is  excited  in  the  air 
is  exactly  in  unison  with  that  of  the  fork,  because  in  this  case 
also  every  impact  of  a  wave  of  air  against  the  fork  increases 
the  motions  excited  by  the  like  previous  blows. 

This  experiment  is  most  conveniently  performed  on  a  fork, 
Fig.  7,  which  is  fastened  to  a  sounding-board,  the  air  being 
excited  by  a  similar  fork  of  precisely  the  same  pitch.  If  one  is 
struck,  the  other  will  be  found  after  a  fe\v  seconds  to  be  sound- 
ing also.  Then  damp  the  first  fork,  by  touching  it  for  a  moment 
with  a  finger,  and  the  second  will  continue  the  tone.  The 
second  will  then  bring  the  first  into  vibration,  and  so  on. 

But  if  a  very  small  piece  of  wax  be  attached  to  the  ends  of 
one  of  the  forks,  whereby  its  pitch  will  be  rendered  scarcely 
percept'bly  lower  than  the  other,  the  sympathetic  vibration  of 
the  second  fork  ceases,  because  the  times  of  oscillation  are  no 
longer  the  same  in  each.  The  blows  which  the  waves  of  air 
excited  by  the  first  inflict  upon  the  sounding-board  of  the  second 
fork,  are  indeed  for  a  time  in  the  same  direction  as  the  motions 
of  the  second  fork,  and  consequently  increase  the  latter,  but 
after  a  very  short  time  they  cease  to  be  so,  and  consequently 
destroy  the  slight  motion  which  they  had  previously  excited. 


72  ON  THE   PHYSIOLOGICAL   CAUSES   OF 

Lighter  and  more  mobile  elastic  bodies,  as  for  example 
strings,  can  be  set  in  motion  by  a  much  smaller  number  of 
aerial  impulses.  Hence  they  can  be  set  in  sympathetic  motion 
much  more  easily  than  tuning-forks,  and  by  means  of  a  musical 
tone  which  is  far  less  accurately  in  unison  with  themselves. 

Now,  then,  if  several  tones  are  sounded  in  the  neighbour- 
hood of  a  pianoforte,  no  string  can  be  set  in  sympathetic 
vibration  unless  it  is  in  unison  with  one  of  those  tones.  For 
example,  depress  the  forte  pedal  (thus  raising  the  dampers),  and 
put  paper  riders  on  all  the  strings.  They  will  of  course  leap 
FIG.  7. 


off  when  their  strings  are  put  in  vibration.  Then  let  several 
voices  or  instruments  sound  tones  in  the  neighbourhood.  All 
those  riders,  and  only  those,  will  leap  off  which  are  placed  upon 
strings  that  correspond  to  tones  of  the  same  pitch  as  those 
sounded.  You  perceive  that  a  pianoforte  is  also  capable  of 
analysing  the  wave  confusion  of  the  air  into  its  elementary  con- 
stituents. 

The  process  which  actually  goes  on  in  our  ear  is  probably 
very  like  that  just  described.  Deep  in  the  petrous  bone  out  of 
which  the  internal  ear  is  hollowed  lies  a  peculiar  organ,  the 
cochlea  or  snail  shell — a  cavity  filled  with  water,  and  so  called 


HARMOJfY   IN   MUSIC. 


73 


from  its  resemblance  to  the  shell  of  a  common  garden  snail. 
This  spiral  passage  is  divided  throughout  its  length  into  three 
sections,  upper,  middle,  and  lower,  by  two  membranes  stretched 
in  the  middle  of  its  height.  The  Marchese  Corti  discovered 
some  very  remarkable  formations  in  the  middle  section.  They 
FIG.  8. 

Tly^-—^ 


consist  of  innumerable  plates,  microscopically  smnll,  and 
arranged  orderly  side  by  side,  like  the  keys  of  a  piano.  They  are 
connected  at  one  end  with  the  fibres  of  the  auditory  nerve,  and 
at  the  other  with  the  stretched  membrane. 

Fig.  8  shows  this  extraordinarily  complicated  arrangement 


74  ON   TEE   PHYSIOLOGICAL  CAUSES   OF 

for  a  small  part  of  the  partition  of  the  cochlea.  The  arches 
which  leave  the  membrane  at  d  and  are  reinserted  at  e,  reach- 
ing their  greatest  height  between  m  and  o,  are  probably  the 
parts  which  are  suited  for  vibration.  They  are  spun  round 
with  innumerable  fibrils,  among  which  some  nerve  fibres  can  be 
recognised,  coming  to  them  through  the  holes  near  c.  The 
transverse  fibres  g,  h,  i,  k,  and  the  cells  o,  also  appear  to  belong 
to  the  nervous  system.  There  are  about  three  thousand  arches 
similar  to  d  e,  lying  orderly  beside  each  other,  like  the  keys  of 
a  piano  in  the  whole  length  of  the  partition  of  the  cochlea. 

In  the  so-called  vestibulum,  also,  where  the  nerves  expand 
upon  little  membranous  bags  swimming  in  water,  elastic  appen- 
dages, similar  to  stiff  hairs,  have  been  lately  discovered  at  the 
ends  of  the  nerves.  The  anatomical  arrangement  of  these 
appendages  leaves  scarcely  any  room,  to  doubt  that  they  are  set 
into  sympathetic  vibration  by  the  waves  of  sound  which  are 
conducted  through  the  ear.  Now  if  we  venture  to  conjecture 
— it  is  at  present  only  a  conjecture,  but  after  careful  considera- 
tion I  am  led  to  think  it  very  probable — that  every  such 
appendage  is  tuned  to  a  certain  tone  like  the  strings  of  a  piano, 
then  the  recent  experiment  with  a  piano  shows  you  that  when 
(and  only  when)  that  tone  is  sounded  the  corresponding  hair- 
like  appendage  may  vibrate,  and  the  corresponding  nerve-fibre 
experience  a  sensation,  so  that  the  presence  of  each  single  such 
tone  in  the  midst  of  a  whole  confusion  of  tones  must  be  in- 
dicated by  the  corresponding  sensation. 

Experience  then  shows  us  that  the  ear  really  possesses  the 
power  of  analysing  waves  of  air  into  their  elementary  forms. 

By  compound  motions  of  the  air,  we  have  hitherto  meant 
such  as  have  been  caused  by  the  simultaneous  vibration  of 
several  elastic  bodies.  Now,  since  the  forms  of  the  waves  of 
sound  of  different  musical  instniments  are  different,  there  is 
room  to  suppose  that  the  kind  of  vibration  excited  in  the  pas- 
sages of  the  ear  by  one  such  tone  will  be  exactly  the  same  as 
the  kind  of  vibration  which  in  another  case  is  there  excited  by 
two  or  more  instruments  sounded  together.  If  the  ear  analyses 
the  motion  into  its  elements  in  the  latter  case,  it  cannot  well 


HARMONY   IN   MUSIC. 


75 


avoid  doing  so  in  the  former,  where  the  tone  is  due  to  a  single 
source.     And  this  is  found  to  be  really  the  case. 

I  have  previously  mentioned  the  form  of  wave  with  gently 
rounded  crests  and  hollows,  and  termed  it  simple  or  pure  (p.  65). 
In  reference  to  this  form  the  French  mathematician  Fourier  has 
established  a  celebrated  and  important  theorem  which  may  be 
translated  from  mathematical  into  ordinary  language  thus  :  Any 
form  of  wave  whatever  can  be  compounded  of  a  number  of 
simple  waves  of  different  lengths.  The  longest  of  these  simple 
waves  has  the  same  length  as  that  of  the  given  form  of  wave, 
the  others  have  lengths  one  half,  one  third,  one  fourth,  &c.,  as 
great. 

By  the  different  modes  of  uniting  the  crests  and  hollows  of 
these  simple  waves,  an  endless  multiplicity  of  wave-forms  may 
be  produced. 

TIG.  9. 


For  example,  the  wave-curves  A  and  B,  Fi^.  9,  represent  waves 
oi  simple  tones,  13  making  twice  as  many  vibrations  as  A  in  a  second