Skip to main content

Full text of "The principles of Descartes' philosophy"

See other formats


BHB         m  fflmm     BBS 

mm 
m    m  HH  Wm 

■■  wwHiSW  HI    w 

■  Km 

HHH 

H 

'HnmfrW  HH  Hi  DU 

HH 

H 

HSH  Hi 

■HUH  ^HnflH        iMBIfldl  Hfl 

HHH     H  m 
H  H      H 

m     HI 

Hi       me  HI  HH   BSH 

B  IHWH 

w     H  ra      HHH 


mm        HS 

ffl 

59      H 

mmoh 


^  v? 


^. 

V* 

x° 

3* 

*  ,-.■ 

V 

<h 


oN 


^ 
^ 


V 

V  "* 


\ 


Co 


•A 


3 


V 


■ 


,*x 


a 


\ 


Oa 


vV 


' 


^ 


/\ 


\ 


_ 

.0  o  ^  -si     ^/- 


^0^ 

i*      ^ 


A^  ^  X> 


*. 
*, 


\ 


\ 


a?     *•" '  9*  v   -N 

*  TV  -  ■         *P  a. 


,\ 


/ 


A> 


'/ 


A  *%,  ''  s  x  ^ 

*6.  av    - 


c5>  ^ 


,\V       V'. 

cv        ^  'B  *       < 


*^>. 


s>\V 

A°  v 


A  A.  ^N 

<1 


\ 


0  o 


-> 


^s 


e, 


■ 


<*       O  A  . 


J 


\ 


^v  ^ 


^f    %*         a\  °     < 


$  "^ 


sX     ^  "    /  O  V 


1  o      > 


A  ' 


HKXEDICTTS    SPINOZA 


K-KOM    A    PORTRAIT  IN   THK   COLLECTION   OF   HON.    MAYER   SULZBERGER 

OF  PHILADELPHIA 
nv  COURTIS'S  OF  MESSRS.  kink   a  WAONALLS 


THE   PRINCIPLES  OF 


Descartes'  Philosophy 


BY 

BENEDICTUS  DE  SPINOZA 


(the  philosopher's  earliest  work) 


TRANSLATED  FROM  THE  LATIN, 

WITH  AN  INTRODUCTION 

BY 

HALBERT  HAINS   BRITAN,   Ph.D. 


CHICAGO 
THE  OPEN  COURT  PUBLISHING  COMPANY 

LONDON  AGENTS 

Kegan  Paul,  Trench,  Trubner  &  Co.,  L/td. 

1905 


LIBRARY  of  CONGRESS 

Two  Copies  Received 

NOV  18  1905 

Copyright  Entry 

*)t*.s;  lyes 

CLASS    Ox     XXc.  No. 
COPY    B. 


~7wir 


Copyright  1905 

by 
THE  OPEN  COURT  PUBLISHING  CO. 


CHICAGO 


As  a  token  of  gratitude  for  his  kindness  and 
for  his  help,  I  dedicate  this  book 

TO 

Professor  George  M.  Duncan,  LL.D. 


TABLE  OF  CONTENTS 


INTRODUCTION. 


PAGK 

The  Significance  of  Spinoza's  Early  Writings     .  i 
The  Publication  of  "  The  Principles  of  Descartes' 

Philosophy  " iii 

The  Geometrical  Method,  its   Purpose     ....  ix 

The  Geometrical  Method  the  Outcome  of  Deduction  xiii 

Deduction  and  the  Concept  of  God xix 

Spinoza's  Idea  of  God,  influenced  by  His  Early  Life  xx 

The  Early  Influence  of  Descartes'  Philosophy     .  xxiii 
An  Analysis  of  the  Concept  of  God  found  in  the 

Cogitata  Metaphysical 

The  Eternity  of  God xxv 

There  is  but  One  God xxviii 

The  Greatness  of  God xxix 

The  Immutability  of  God xxx 

The  Simplicity  and  Life  of  God xxxi 

The  Omniscience  of  God xxxii 

The  Will  of  God xxxv 

The  Power  of  God xxxviii 

/  ... 

The  Concurrence  of  God xxxvm 

God's  Attributes  identified xl 

The  Necessity  under  which  God  Acts       ....  xli 

God's  Determinism  leads  to  Pantheism     ....  xlvi 

Spinoza   a   "  Rationalist  " Iii 

Descartes'    Dualism                   . Hv 

Three  Factors  turning  Spinoza  to  Pantheism:     .  fix 
(i)  His  Allegiance  to  Deduction, 

(2)  His  Idea  of  God, 

(3)  The  Influence  of  Descartes'  Philosophy. 
Deduction,  the  Source  of  the  Weakness  of  Spino- 
za's System Ixvi 

Problem  of  Evil lxvii 


TABLE  OF  CONTENTS 

PAGE 

Determinism lxviii 

Was    Kant   influenced   by    This    Early    Work   of 

Spinoza? Ixxi 

The  Principal  Truth  in  Spinoza's  Pantheism     .     .  lxxv 
Its  Influence  in  the  Main  Current  of  Philosoph- 
ical Truth Ixxvi 

Its  Influence  on  Art lxxyiii 

Preface  of  Dr.  Meyer i 

the  principles  of  descartes'  philosophy 

part   i. 

Prolegomenon ti 

Definitions  :     Thought,  Idea,   Substance,  Mind,   Body, 

God,  etc 20 

Axioms 22 

The  Fundamental  Principle  of  All  Knowledge     .      .  23 

Axioms  taken  from  Descartes 25 

God's  Existence  demonstrated   ...         30 

The  Attributes  of  God 41 

Whatever  is  clearly  conceived  is  True 46 

Other  Attributes  of  God 51 

Extended  Substance 54 

part  11. 

concerning  the  physical  world. 

Definitions 57 

Axioms  and  Lemmata 60 

The  Essential  Nature  of  Matter 63 

Concerning  Motion 69 

God  the  Cause  of  Motion 79 

Moving  Bodies  tend  to  move  in  Straight  Lines     ...  81 

The  impact  of  Moving  Bodies 87 

part  hi. 

Introduction 107 

A  Postulate 109 

Definitions  and  Axioms 111 

The  First  Division  of  Matter 112 


TABLE  OF  CONTENTS 


APPENDIX. 


THE   COGITATA    METAPHYSICA. 


PART   I. 

PAGE 

Chapter  I.     Division  of  Being 115 

Chapter  II.     Essence,  Existence,  Idea  and  Power  Ex- 
plained     120 

Chapter  III.     The  Terms   Necessary,  Contingent,  Im- 
possible and  Possible  Explained 124 

Chapter  IV.  Concerning  Duration  and  Time  .  .  .  129 
Chapter  V.  Concerning  Opposition,  Order,  etc.  .  .  .  130 
Chapter  VI.     Concerning  Unity,  Truth  and  Goodness  131 


part  11. 


Chapter  I.  Concerning  the  Eternity  of  God 
Chapter  II.  Concerning  the  Unity  of  God  . 
Chapter  III.  Concerning  the  Greatness  of  God 
Chapter  IV.  Concerning  God's  Immutability 
Chapter  V.  Concerning  the  Simplicity  of  God 
Chapter  VI.  Concerning  the  Life  of  God 
Chapter  VII.  Concerning  the  Understanding  of 
Chapter  VIII.  Concerning  God's  Will 
Chapter  IX.  Concerning  the  Power  of  God  . 
Chapter  X.  Concerning  Creation  .... 
Chapter  XL  Concerning  the  Concurrence  of  God 
Chapter  XII.     Concerning  the  Human  Mind 


God 


139 
142 

143 
146 
148 
150 
152 
156 

159 
161 
168 
170 


PREFACE 

This  translation,  undertaken  at  the  suggestion  of 
Professor  George  M.  Duncan  of  Yale  University,  has 
been  made  from  the  Latin  text  of  Vloten's  and  Land's 
Benedict  de  Spinoza  Opera,  1895.  A  careful  study  of 
this  work  such  as  a  translator  must  needs  make  has 
convinced  me  that  more  attention  should  be  given  to 
the  early  writings  of  Spinoza  for  the  help  they  give 
in  understanding  his  Pantheism.  By  this  means,  by 
seeing  how  his  ideas  followed  naturally  if  not  always 
quite  logically,  from  personal  factors,  and  from  Des- 
cartes' philosophy,  some  of  the  most  obscure  points 
in  his  system  of  philosophy  are  materially  elucidated 
and  explained.  But  a  historical  or  genetic  study  of 
any  subject  today  needs  no  apology.  The  only  re- 
markable thing  about  this  is  that  so  little  attention 
has  been  given  to  this  method  of  clearing  up  the  ob- 
scurities of  Spinoza's  thought. 

In  my  introduction  I  have  not  attempted  to  make 
an  exhaustive  analysis  of  the  work  translated  so  much 
as  I  have  endeavored  to  fasten  the  attention  upon  some 
of  the  points  which  throw  light  upon  Spinoza's  Pan- 
theism. Little  reference  is  made  to  Part  II.  or  to 
Part  III.  of  the  Principles  because  they  treat  of  mat- 
ter that  has  but  little  importance  in  understanding  the 
Ethics.  And  the  contents  of  Part  I.  being  better  pre- 
sented in  the  Cogitata  Metaphysica,  we  have  confined 
our  analysis  mainly  to  the  appendix.  If  some  added 
light  is  thrown  upon  the  two  or  three  points  to  which 


PREFACE 

we  have  especially  directed  our  attention,  and  the  pos- 
sibilities of  this  method  of  studying  Spinoza's  thought 
are  made  clear,  the  main  purpose  of  this  book  will  have 
been  attained.  In  obtaining  a  better  translation  for 
certain  passages  help  has  sometimes  been  found  by 
consulting  the  standard  Histories  of  Philosophy  such 
as  Erdmann's,  Kuno  Fisher's,  and  Ueberwig's  as  well 
as  Torrey's  and  Veitch's  translation  of  Descartes' 
works,  and  Elwes'  translation  of  the  earlier 
works  of  Spinoza.  My  thanks  are  also  due  to  Pro- 
fessor Duncan  for  his  suggestion  upon  some  points, 
and  to  Professor  C.  R.  Melcher  of  Hanover  College 
for  reading  over  a  portion  of  my  MSS. 

HALBERT   HAINS   BRITAN. 
Hanover,  Indiana,  January,  1905. 


INTRODUCTION 

§  I.  In  Histories  of  Philosophy  Spinoza's  name 
stands  inseparably  associated  with  Pantheism  if  it  has 
not  become  practically  synonymous  with  that  term. 
His  earlier  writings,  therefore,  are  of  value  primarily 
for  the  light  they  throw  upon  his  later  thought.  While 
it  is  true  that  some  of  them  have  intrinsic  worth,  for 
the  most  part  it  is  because  they  illumine  the  mysteries 
of  his  mystical  Pantheism  that  these  early  writings 
are  preserved  and  read.  We  need  not  hesitate  to  say 
that  this  is  pre-eminently  true  of  the  Principles  of 
Descartes'  Philosophy  translated  below.  At  the  very 
beginning  of  this  work  we  are  confronted  with  the 
assertion  that  this  professes  to  be  only  a  new,  a  more 
logical  presentation  of  the  truth  which  Descartes  had 
already  set  forth  with  such  admirable  clearness. 
Nevertheless,  as  we  hope  will  appear,  while  the  con- 
tent of  this  work  may  not  be  absolutely  essential  for 
understanding  Spinoza's  Ethics,  it  is  still  far  too  im- 
portant to  be  neglected. 

It  has  long  been  a  tacit  assumption  that  Spinoza's 
system  of  philosophy  is  found  complete  in  the  Ethics, 
that  since  this  was  the  latest,  most  mature  product  of 
his  thought  there  is  little  need  to  refer  to  anything  out- 
side of  this  work  in  order  to  understand  his  svstem  of 
Pantheism.  Such  an  assumption,  however,  would  be 
very  difficult  to  justify,  for,  while  it  is  true  that  the 
Ethics  contains  the  outline  of  a  theory  of  reality  and  of 
human  experience,  it  is  not  in  mastering  the  outline 
that  the  trouble  appears.  The  chief  difficulty  in  under- 
standing the  Ethics  is  not  in  mastering  the  broad  out- 


ii  INTRODUCTIOX 

lines  of  its  doctrines,  but  in  gaining  clear  and  adequate 
conceptions  of  the  terms  in  which  the  thought  is  ex- 
pressed.    This,  together  with  the  unusual  method  of 
treatment,  are  the  cruces  which  the  average  student 
of  Spinoza  finds  hardest  to  overcome.     As  far  as  the 
general  plan  of  the  work  is  concerned,  the  one  all  inclu- 
sive idea  first,  and  then  the  descent  to  particular  ideas 
and  objects,  this  need  offer  no  serious  occasion   for 
stumbling,  if  it  is  but  remembered  that  this  work  is 
the  product  of  a  deductive  age  and  of  a  deductive  logic. 
The  difficulties  of  Spinoza's  terminology  and  the  ap- 
parent grotesque  inaptitude  of  the  geometrical  method, 
can  largely  be  removed  by  a  genetic  or  historical  study 
of  his   system.   The    fundamental   conceptions   of   the 
Ethics  were  the  outcome  of  years  of  earnest,  patient, 
careful  study  and  their  full  content  cannot  be  appre- 
ciated by  reading  over  the  terse  language   in  which 
they   are   defined   in   their   mathematical   setting.     To 
appreciate   them   we   must   know   something   of   their 
actual  development  and  of  the  ideas  with  which  they 
were   habitually   associated.     Unless   we   can   by   this 
historical  investigation  get  into  the  atmosphere  of  his 
thought,  as  it  were,  his  .main  tenets  must  of  necessity 
seem  artificial  and  remain  obscure. 

So,  also,  by  such  a  study  we  will  derive  the  most 
important  aid  in  understanding  and  even  in  appre- 
ciating that  most  generally  reprehended  feature  of  the 
Ethics,  the  method  in  which  it  is  expressed. 

The  importance  of  this  historical  study  of  Spinoza 
is  recognized  in  some  of  the  more  recent  writers  on 
this  ethical  system.  Joachim  hints  at  it  while  Pro- 
fessor Duff  gives  this  as  one  of  three  essentials  for 
the  mastery  of  Spinoza's  Pantheism.1     The  soundness 

1  Joachim,  A  Study  of  The  Ethics  of  Spinoza.  Duff.  Spino- 
za's Political  and  Ethical  Philosophy. 


INTRODUCTION  iii 

of  such  an  opinion  cannot  be  questioned ;  concepts  that 
require  years  to  form  cannot  be  fully  contained  in  any 
brief  and  formal  definition.  The  more  radical  the 
idea  (and  some  of  Spinoza's  possess  this  attribute  in 
no  small  degree)  the  more  important  this  historical 
study  becomes  for  understanding  its  full  significance, 
and  the  more  fundamental  the  concept,  the  more  es- 
sential it  is  that  we  do  not  neglect  any  help  that  we 
may  have  in  fully  understanding  that  on  which  so 
much  depends. 

§  2.  The  work  on  Descartes'  philosophy  translated 
below,  the  earliest  of  all  his  writings,  was  published 
in  1663  under  rather  unusual  circumstances.     It  was 

\  the  only  work  to  which  Spinoza  ever  subscribed  his 
name,  and  yet  he  warns  us  that  we  must  not  accept  this 
as  an  expression  of  his  own  belief.     The  story  of  its 

)  composition  and  publication  is  as  follows :  Spinoza 
about  the  year  1662-3  had  a  pupil  to  whom  he  was 
teaching  Descartes'  philosophy,  being  at  that  time 
unwilling  to  impart  his  own  opinions  to  any  one  ex- 
cept to  a  few  of  his  special  friends  with  whom  he 
was  accustomed  to  discuss  his  philosophical  views. 
Well  founded  conjecture  makes  this  pupil  to  be  Albert 
Burgh,  who,  being  in  later  years  converted  to  the 
Roman  Catholic  faith,  takes  his  former  instructor  se- 
verely to  task  for  his  heresies.  Be  this  as  it  may,  the 
fact  remains  that  the  "  Principles  of  Descartes'  Philoso- 
phy "  was  not  meant  to  be  an  expression  of  Spinoza's 
own  belief  at  the  time  it  was  written.  Not  wishing 
his  own  opinions  to  be  known  at  that  time  he  con- 
ceives the  plan  of  teaching  his  pupil  the  philosophy 
of  Descartes,  which  he  could  do  conscientiously  and 
without  any  unpleasant  results  to  himself.  This  work 
was  written,  therefore,  more  to   conceal  than  to  ex- 


iv  INTRODUCTION 

press  his  own  belief.  Spinoza,  as  it  seems,  solely  for 
the  benefit  of  his  pupil,  had  put  the  second  part  of  the 
Principles  in  geometrical  form.  Some  of  his  phil- 
osophical friends,  seeing  this,  and  being  impressed 
with  the  method  in  which  it  was  expressed  asked  him 
to  put  the  first  and  third  parts  in  the  same  form, 
and,  appending  the  Cogitata  Metaphysial,  to  permit 
the  whole  to  be  published.  This  Spinoza  readily  con- 
sented to  do,  if  some  one  of  them  would  go  over  the 
work  perfecting  the  phraseology,  and  would  write  a 
preface  explaining  that  this  work  was  not  meant  to 
be  an  expression  of  his  own  belief,  but  that  it  was  a 
faithful  presentation  of  the  philosophy  of  Descartes, 
either  what  he  had  said  explicitly  or  that  which  could 
logically  be  inferred  from  his  premises. 

Thus  we  are  forewarned  lest  we  should  accept  the 
propositions  given  below  as  an  expression  of  Spinoza's 
own  thought.  Some  of  the  positions  taken,  we  are 
told  in  this  Preface,  do  express  his  own  belief,  but 
there  are  others  to  which  he  holds  exactly  the  contrary 
opinion.  We  are  not  at  liberty,  therefore,  to  subscribe 
Spinoza's  name  to  all  that  is  said  in  this  work  but 
must  sift  out  as  best  we  can  that  with  which  he  agreed 
from  that  which  he  rejected. 

Dr.  Ludwig  Meyer,  a  physician  in  Amsterdam,  and 
a  man  intimately  acquainted  with  Spinoza's  opinions, 
gladly  agreed  to  write  such  a  preface  as  Spinoza  de- 
sired, and  this  is  given  as  an  introduction  to  the  work 
in  question.  Spinoza  immediately  set  to  work  and  in 
two  weeks'  time  had  the  first  part  also  in  geometrical 
form  and  sent  it  to  be  published  with  the  rest.  Another 
reason  why  he  entrusted  its  publication  to  his  friend 
was  that  he  had  left  Amsterdam  in  1660  on  account 
of  persecution  and  was  at  this  time  dwelling  in  Rheins- 


INTRODUCTION  v 

burgh,  near  Leyden.  The  following  letter  to  Olden- 
burgh  gives  us  his  own  version  of  the  publication  of 
the  work : 

Distinguished  Sir:— 

I  have  at  length  received  your  long  wished  for 
letter,  and  am  at  liberty  to  answer  it.  But  before  I 
do,  I  will  briefly  tell  you  what  has  prevented  my  re- 
plying before.  When  I  removed  my  household  goods 
here  in  April,  I  set  out  for  Amsterdam.  While 
there  certain  friends  asked  me  to  impart  to 
them  a  treatise  containing,  in  brief,  the  second 
part  of  the  principles  of  Descartes  treated  geo- 
metrically, together  with  some  of  the  chief  points 
treated  in  metaphysics,  which  I  had  formerly 
dictated  to  a  youth,  to  whom  I  did  not  wish 
to  teach  my  own  opinions  openly.  They  further  re- 
quested me,  at  the  first  opportunity,  to  compose  a 
similar  treatise  on  the  first  part.  Wishing  to  oblige 
my  friends  I  at  once  set  myself  to  the  task,  which  I 
accomplished  in  a  fortnight,  and  handed  over  to  them. 
They  then  asked  leave  to  print  it,  which  I  readily 
granted  on  the  condition  that  one  of  them  should, 
under  my  supervision,  clothe  it  in  more  elegant  phrase- 
ology, and  add  a  little  preface  warning  readers  that 
I  do  not  acknowledge  all  the  opinions  there  set  forth 
as  my  own,  in  as  much  as  I  hold  the  exact  contrary  to 
much  that  is  there  written,  illustrating  the  fact  by  one 
or  two  examples.  All  this  the  friend  who  took  charge 
of  the  treatise  promised  to  do,  and  this  is  the  cause  for 
my  prolonged  stay  in  Amsterdam.  Since  I  returned 
to  this  village  I  have  hardly  been  able  to  call  my  time 
my  own,  because  of  the  friends  who  have  been  kind 
enough  to  visit  me.    At  last,  my  dear  friend,  a  moment 


vi  ■  INTRODUCTION 

has  come  when  I  can  relate  these  occurrences  to  you, 
and  inform  you  why  I  allow  this  treatise  to  see  the 
light.  It  may  be  that  on  this  occasion  some  of  those 
who  hold  the  foremost  positions  in  my  country  will  be 
found  desirous  of  seeing  the  rest  of  my  writings, 
which  I  acknowledge  to  be  my  own,  they  will  thus  take 
care  that  I  am  enabled  to  publish  them  without  any 
danger  of  infringing  the  laws  of  the  land.  If  this  be 
as  I  think,  I  shall  doubtless  publish  at  once ;  if  things 
fall  out  otherwise,  I  would  rather  be  silent  than  ob- 
trude my  opinions  on  men,  in  defiance  of  my  country, 
and  thus  render  them  hostile  to  me.  I  therefore  hope, 
my  friend,  that  you  will  not  chafe  at  having  to  wait  a 
short  time  longer ;  you  shall  then  receive  from  me  the 
treatise  printed,  or  the  summary  of  it  you  ask  for. 
If  meanwhile  you  would  like  to  have  one  or  two  copies 
of  the  work  now  in  the  press  I  will  satisfy  your  wish 
as  soon  as  I  know  of  it  and  of  means  to  send  the  book 
conveniently.1 


Thus  by  Spinoza's  own  words  we  are  told  that  this 
work  is  not  meant  for  an  expression  of  his  own  be- 
lief. It  was  written,  ostensibly,  for  the  benefit  of  his 
pupil,  but  really  that  he  might  not  be  required  to 
teach  him  his  own  opinions.  His  reticence  in  express- 
ing his  own  belief  can  be  readily  understood  if  we  re- 
member what  sacrifices  he  was  willing  to  make  for  the 
sake  of  undisturbed  meditation  and  how  his  opinions 
only  a  few  years  before,  when  but  verbally  expressed, 
had  brought  down  upon  him  the  wrath  and  curses  of 
the  Jewish  synagogue,  and  a  persecution  that  drove 
him  from  Amsterdam  to  the  little  village  of  Rheins- 
burgh.     In   order  that  he  might  not  be  compelled  to 

1  Letter  XIII.   Elwes'  Trans.    Spinoza's   Works. 


INTRODUCTION  vii 

express  his  own  belief  he  resorts  to  the  expedient  of 
teaching  his  pupil  not  his  own  but  Descartes'  phil- 
osophy. 

From  this  hesitancy  in  expressing  his  own  opinions 
we  infer  that  even  at  this  early  period  Spinoza  had 
already  departed  from  the  philosophy  of  Descartes, 
which  as  far  as  the  concept  of  God  was  concerned, 
was  comparatively  orthodox.  It  is  doubtful  if  Spinoza 
ever  followed  Descartes  very  far  in  his  opinions.  The 
great  service  of  Descartes  in  the  development  of  phil- 
osophy was  to  establish  the  firm  basis  of  epistemo- 
logical  truth,  while  Spinoza's  interests  were  along  an 
entirely  different  line.  When  we  remember  that  pre- 
vious to  his  study  of  Descartes  Spinoza  had  already 
spent  some  time  in  the  study  of  Theology,  and  that 
his  main  interest  was  always  in  the  concept  of  God, 
it  is  a  question  whether  he  ever  followed  the  teachings 
of  his  illustrious  predecessor  further  than  to  accept 
certain  metaphysical  distinctions  which  Descartes  had 
pointed  out  with  his  usual  perspicuity.  Spinoza's 
earliest  reflection  was  upon  the  nature  of  God.  Both 
his  early  training  and  taste  and  the  ultra  deductive 
nature  of  his  thinking  demanded  that  it  should  be  so. 
Just  what  the  specific  nature  of  his  reflections  were 
we  can  infer  from  the  second  of  his  published  works, 
the  Theologico-Political  Treatise.  He  well  knew  that 
the  conclusions  to  which  he  was  coming  would  hardly 
receive  a  kind  reception  in  a  world  where  religious 
toleration  either  in  act  or  thought  was  scarcely  known. 
Therefore  he  preferred,  as  he  told  Oldenburgh  in  the 
letter  quoted  above,  to  remain  forever  silent  rather 
than  to  obtrude  his  opinions  upon  men  not  willing  to 
receive  them. 

For  the  purposes   of  our  consideration  two  points 


viii  INTRODUCTION 

stand  out  above  all  others  in  importance  in  the  work 
which  it  is  our  purpose  to  examine.  These  are  the 
form  in  which  Spinoza  chooses  to  remold  Descartes' 
philosophy,  and  the  constant  and  emphatic  stress  laid 
upon  the  concept  of  God.  It  is  not  too  much  to  say 
that  in  these  two  thoughts  which  appear  in  definite 
form  in  this  the  earliest  of  Spinoza's  works,  we  find 
the  principal  causes  which  led  him  to  accept  Panthe- 
ism as  the  most  satisfactory  theory  of  God  and  of  the 
World.  Though  the  opinions  expressed  in  the  Prin- 
ciples, as  we  have  seen,  are  not  always  Spinoza's  own 
belief,  the  significance  of  this  work  is  by  no  means 
destroyed.  More  significant  than  any  new  item  of 
truth  in  this  presentation  of  the  Cartesian  philosophy 
is  the  method  employed  in  presenting  it ;  and  more 
significant  than  any  novelty  in  the  discussion  of  the 
attributes  of  God  is  the  constant  stress  laid  upon  this 
idea  as  the  fundamental  concept  of  Philosophy.  More 
than  any  other  factor,  and  possibly  more  than  all  other 
factors  combined,  these  two  facts,  the  geometrical 
method  and  this  concept  of  God,  explain  his  Panthe- 
ism. Let  it  be  granted,  then,  that  this  work,  the 
Principles  of  Descartes'  Philosophy,  is  an  expression 
of  Descartes'  thought  rather  than  of  his  own,  still  we 
have  by  no  means  destroyed  nor  hardly  impaired  its 
usefulness  as  a  means  to  a  fuller  understanding  of 
Spinoza's  philosophy.  The  purpose  of  his  employment 
of  the  geometrical  method,  and  its  general  significance, 
is  not  at  all  changed  by  the  fact  that  he  used  it  first  to 
present  not  his  own  but  Descartes'  philosophy.  The 
important  thing  is  that  he  did  actually  employ  at  this 
early  period,  the  method  of  geometry  to  express  not 
mathematical  but  philosophical  truth.  What  we  are 
interested  in  discovering-  is  not  the  demonstrable  cer- 


INTRODUCTION  ix 

tainty  of  his  propositions,  this  we  have  given  over 
long  ago,  but  his  purpose  in  using  this  method,  how 
he  justified  his  action  and  whither  its  employment 
logically  leads.  In  our  consideration  of  the  geomet- 
rical method,  therefore,  no  restrictions  whatever  are 
imposed  by  the  apparently  disconcerting  fact  that  the 
Principles  is  primarily  an  expression  of  Descartes' 
philosophy. 

And  yet,  while  this  work  is  so  truly  an  expression  of 
the  Cartesian  philosophy,  we  shall  find  both  in  the 
Principles  and  more  especially  in  the  Co  git  at  a  ample 
expression  of  Spinoza's  own  belief  to  enable  us  to  see 
his  point  of  departure  from  the  philosophy  of  Descar- 
tes, and  to  understand  why  he  turned  not  to  Theism 
but  to  Pantheism  as  a  conception  of  the  World- 
Ground.  As  we  proceed  we  shall  find  elements  which, 
taken  in  connection  with  some  of  the  metaphysical  ten- 
ets of  Spinoza's  early  reflections,  led  him  logically 
and,  as  it  seems,  almost  necessarily  to  a  pantheistic 
conception  of  God.  Sufficient  data  will  also  be  found 
to  throw  much  light  upon  the  content  of  this,  the  most 
fundamental  as  well  as  the  most  difficult  concept  of 
his  philosophy,  the  idea  or  concept  of  God. 

§  3.  The  geometrical  method  in  Spinoza's  Ethics 
has  long  been  to  students  of  that  work  both  a  stumb- 
ling-block and  foolishness.  To  the  modern  mind  in- 
grained with  scientific  principles  and  prejudices  the 
method  of  geometry  seems  utterly  inapt  and  unfitted 
for  the  presentation  of  philosophical  truth.  It  can  but 
be  of  the  greatest  importance,  therefore,  if  we  can 
learn  from  this  early  work,  our  only  precedent  in 
Spinoza's  writings  for  the  method  used  in  the  Ethics, 
just  why  Spinoza  used  the  geometrical  method  in  the 
Principles.     And  this  is  our  sole  chance  for  learning 


x  INTRODUCTION 

why  he  employed  this  method ;  there  is  little  help  to  be 
gained  by  even  the  most  careful  study  of  the  Ethics 
alone.  When  he  wrote  that  work,  Spinoza's  opinions 
and  habits  of  thought  had  so  far  become  crystalized 
that  he  did  not  introduce  any  comment  that  would 
serve  to  make  this  point  clear.  Our  answer  to  this 
question,  therefore,  must  be  found  in  the  work  below 
or  it  will  not  be  found  at  all. 

When  we  turn,  now,  to  the  Principles  to  consider 
the  method  in  which  it  is  presented  we  are  soon  forced 
to  the  conclusion  that  this  geometrical  method  was 
not  employed  because  Spinoza  thought  he  could  thus 
present  an  irrefragable  body  of  truth.  He  did  not  use 
this  method-  because  of  the  apodeictic  character  of  its 
proof.  This  is  conclusively  shown  by  the  fact  that  he 
used  the  method  alike  to  present  propositions  in  which 
he  believed  and  those  to  which  as  he  said  he  held  the 
exactly  opposite  opinion.  In  the  latter  cases  the  proof 
is  no  less  rigid,  the  argument  no  less  logical  than  when 
he  has  given  propositions  which  held  his  hearty  as- 
sent. Let  us  then  get  this  idea  firmly  fixed  in  our 
minds,  that  Spinoza  did  not  regard  the  geometrical 
method,  either  in  the  work  translated  below  or  in  the 
Ethics,  as  an  apodeictic  demonstration  of  the  opinions 
he  thus  expresses.  Such  an  opinion  is  flatly  contra- 
dicted in  his  first  use  of  this  method,  and  we  have  no 
reason  for  believing  that  it  was  in  any  way  different  in 
the  case  of  its  later  use.  Whatever  his  purpose  may 
have  been,  it  was  not  to  present  by  its  use  a  philosoph- 
ical system  that  would  not  win,  but  compel  assent.  Not 
a  little  of  the  difficulty  in  understanding  the  Ethics 
arises  from  the  failure  to  properly  comprehend  the 
purpose  of  the  method  in  which  it  is  presented.  So 
long  as  we  think  of  it  as  a  presentation  of  truth  as  in- 


INTRODUCTION  xi 

dubitable  as  geometry,  and  yet  as  general  as  philo- 
sophical principles  must  needs  be,  so  long  will  we  be- 
come entangled  in  the  meshes  and  fail  to  see  the  true 
significance  of  the  matter  contained  in  these  unyielding 
forms. 

But  if  it  is  true  as  we  have  said  that  Spinoza  did 
not  employ  the  geometrical  method  for  the  sake  of  its 
unassailable  cogency,  wherein  was  its  virtue?  If  it 
could  be  used,  as  was  indisputably  the  case,  to  prove 
error  as  well  as  truth,  propositions  which  were  directly 
opposed  to  his  belief,  as  well  as  propositions  in  which 
he  firmly  believed,  why  was  it  used  at  all?  And  why 
did  Spinoza's  friends  see  such  virtue  in  it  that  they 
requested  the  immediate  publication  of  every  frag- 
ment of  Descartes'  philosophy  which  Spinoza  had  put 
in  this  form?  The  answer  to  these  questions  which 
apply  primarily  to  the  Principles  will  throw  a  flood 
of  light  upon  the  Ethics. 

To  state  it  briefly,  Spinoza's  purpose  in  employing 
the  geometrical  method  was  pedagogical  not  philo- 
sophical. That  is,  he  put  the  Principles  of  Descartes 
in  this  close  form  of  Proposition  and  Demonstration 
not  to  establish  the  truth  of  the  conclusions  but  that 
the  pupil  whom  he  was  instructing  in  that  system 
might  more  readily  and  more  clearly  comprehend  what 
Descartes  was  endeavoring  to  establish.  Truth  and 
error  did  not  enter  into  his  consideration  at  all,  for  he 
used  the  same  form  and  the  same  kind  of  proof  to 
express  what  he  disbelieved  as  well  as  what  he  re- 
garded as  true.  The  circumstances  under  which 
the  "  Principles  of  Descartes'  Philosophy  "  was  written 
absolutely  preclude  any  other  conclusion.  When 
Spinoza  began  this  work  he  apparently  had  no  idea 
of  publication,  but  it  was  done  solely  for  the  benefit  of 


xii  INTRODUCTION 

his  pupil  to  whom  he  was  teaching  the  Cartesian  phi- 
losophy. So  far  as  there  was  any  justification  for  a 
new  presentation  of  the  truth  which  Descartes  had  al- 
ready so  well  expressed  it  was  in  the  method  alone. 
What  advantage  could  it  be  to  repeat  the  same  con- 
clusions, relying  always  upon  the  same  argument  if 
it  was  not  to  present  in  a  clearer  way  what  were  not 
otherwise  so  easily  comprehended?  Spinoza  put  Des- 
cartes' Principles  in  geometrical  form  because  he 
believed  that  was  the  form  best  adapted  to  the  re- 
quirements of  his  pupil's  mind.  His  purpose  was  to 
present  the  conclusions  of  Descartes  in  their  most  log- 
ical form  so  that  they  might  be  easiest  learned  and 
most  thoroughly  understood.  This  method,  therefore, 
was  not  employed  as  a  method  of  proof,  for  Spinoza,  at 
that  time,  was  not  interested  in  that,  but  in  order  that 
he  might  be  in  his  presentation  strictly  logical  and  con- 
sistently pedagogical.  Considered  in  this  way  the 
difficulty  in  reconciling  the  discrepancy  between  the 
method  Spinoza  employed,  and  his  position  upon  some 
of  the  propositions  given,  disappears.  The  method  is 
true  and  sound  but  the  premises  upon  which  the 
conclusions  are  grounded  were  not  well  taken.  This 
fact,  however,  does  not  destroy  the  value  of  this 
method  in  presenting  logically  and  pedagogically  a 
conclusion  be  it  never  so  weak  when  judged  upon  the 
grounds  of  belief  and  well  reasoned  judgment.  There 
is  a  clear  and  a  forceful  way  to  present  a  seeming 
truth  as  well  as  that  which  is  indubitable.  Hence,  we 
affirm  that  the  only  possible  virtue  in  the  geometrical 
method  was  its  conformity  to  the  demands  of  the  think- 
ing mind.  It  was  pedagogically  a  superior  method  of 
presenting  conclusions  logically  to  the  mind.  That 
this  same  purpose  was  the  chief  one  that  led  Spinoza 


INTRODUCTION  xiii 

to  employ  this  method  in  the  Ethics  is  the  logical  in-  - 
ference.  Although  his  other  works  had  not  been 
written  under  this  form,  when  he  comes  to  write  what 
he  regarded  as  his  last  and  master  work  he  returns  to 
this  method.  This  time  he  is  to  express  only  what  he 
firmly  believed,  but  can  we  think  that  he  was  dogmatic 
enough  to  think  that  his  conclusions  must  forever  re- 
main indisputable?  Such  a  conclusion  is  not  in  har- 
mony with  his  catholic  sympathies  and  even  temper. 
But  here  as  in  the  former  case  the  most  satisfactory 
conclusion  is,  that  this  was  the  most  direct  method  of 
expressing  his  opinions,  and  above  all  it  was  in  accord 
with  the  great  principles  of  Mediaeval  Logic. 

§  4.  In  order  to  appreciate  Spinoza's  motives  in 
using  the  geometrical  method,  and  to  see  its  cogency 
we  must  remember  that  this  was  an  age  of  deduction.  « 
If  we  are  seeking  the  real  causes  that  led  Spinoza  to 
believe  in  this  method  and  to  accept  it  as  the  best  form 
in  which  to  express  not  only  mathematical  but  philo- 
sophical truth,  we  will  find  it  in  the  fact  that  at  this 
time  the  old  Aristotelian  Logic  dominated  his  mind 
completely.  The  leaven  which  Bacon  had  introduced 
into  the  world  of  reflective  thought  had  not  leavened 
the  whole,  but  Spinoza  still  held  to  Deduction  as  the 
great  Organon  of  truth.  For  him  the  warrant  for 
truth  was  rational  not  empirical.  Explanations  of 
phenomena  were  deductive  not  inductive.  The  proof 
of  any  proposition  did  not  consist  in  an  appeal  to  facts 
empirically  obtained,  but  in  a  syllogistic  deduction  from 
premises  previously,  and  better  known.  The  whole 
tenor  of  thought  on  the  continent  was  still  deductive, 
and  whatever  did  not  conform  to  this  method  was 
illogical   and  untrue. 

In  confirming  Spinoza  in  this  belief  the  influence  of 


xiv  INTRODUCTION 

Descartes  was  important.  He  had  proven  that  in- 
dubitable truth  does  not  lie  in  the  field  of  objective 
experience  but  in  the  subjective  assertion  that  I,  a 
thinking  being,  exist.  Philosophy  must  begin  with 
an  assertion  that  cannot  be  doubted  and  then  proceed 
to  build  a  system  founded  upon  this  truth.  According 
to  his  formula  Epistemology  must  precede  Meta- 
physics. The  next  step  was  to  establish  the  verity 
of  God  in  order  that  we  might  be  justified  in  our  be- 
lief in  the  external  world.  Such  was  the  position  of 
philosophic  thought  when  Spinoza  began  to  reflect 
upon  the  problems  of  human  experience.  There  was 
no  serious  attention  paid  to  the  Novum  Organum  of 
Bacon  but  Spinoza  took  his  problem  from  the  old 
scholastics  and  with  this,  their  ideas  of  logical,  me- 
thodical proof. 

Instead  of  accepting  the  conclusions  of  Descartes 
as  the  starting  point,  viz.,  his  cogito  ergo  sum,  and 
his  proof  of  God's  veracity,  by  which  empirical  knowl- 
edge is  made  credible,  and  employing  the  method  of 
Bacon  to  build  upon  this  foundation  already  laid, 
Spinoza  turns  back  a  step  and  begins  anew  the 
impossible  task  of  deducing  the  world  in  thought. 
Instead  of  following  the  role  of  an  humble  learner  in 
a  world  whose  mysteries  are  unfathomable  he  aspired 
to  be  a  system  maker  in  the  most  didactic  way.  The 
task  he  imposed  upon  himself  was  the  old  task  of  de- 
ductive thought.  Individual  facts  of  human  experi- 
ence were  not  data  on  which  conclusions  could  be 
based,  but  phenomena  to  be  explained  by  deducing 
them  from  some  primary,  and  fundamental  principle. 
The  world  was  not  something  to  be  taken  as  it  is  and 
studied  empirically,  but  it  was  regarded  as  a  problem 
to  be  explained  dialectically.     Spinoza  was  dominated 


INTRODUCTION  xv 

completely  by  this  deductive  ideal  of  truth.  His  idea 
of  philosophical  explanation  was  deductive,  his  logic 
was  deductive,  his  proof  was  deductive,  hence  his 
method  also  was  deductive.  When  this  fact  is  suffici- 
ently emphasized  and  consistently  remembered  we 
may  still  regret  the  method  Spinoza  used  in  the  Ethics, 
but  we  must  commend  his  strict  adherence  to  the  prin- 
ciples of  Mediaeval  Logic.  In  this  dry,  stilted  form  of 
Axiom,  Definition,  Proposition,  Demonstration,  and 
Corollary,  deductive  logic  reaches  the  height  of  con- 
sistency. 

From  the  standpoint  of  deductive  thought,  therefore, 
and  this  is  the  point  of  view  from  which  it  was  used, 
the  geometrical  method,  we  venture  to  affirm,  was  the 
most  logical  presentation  of  truth,  mathematical  or 
philosophical,  that  could  be  made.  It  was  wellnigh  if 
not  perfectly  in  accord  with  the  strictest  demands  of 
Deduction  and  seemed  so  at  first  sight  to  those  accus- 
tomed to  the  logic  of  that  time.  It  seems  stiff  and  un- 
natural to  us  because  we  are  so  inured  to  the  modern 
method  of  science  that  anything  out  of  harmony  with 
this  seems  artificial  and  unreal.  With  our  eyes  fastened 
upon  individual  facts  as  the  starting  point  and  general 
principles  as  the  goal,  to  follow  Spinoza  we  must  run 
with  our  eyes  behind  us.  What  he  saw  ahead  we 
see  behind,  and  what  we  look  forward  to  as  the  goal 
of  philosophical  explanation  he  had  accepted  as  the 
starring  point  of  reflection.  So  complete  is  the  in- 
version that  there  is  no  way  to  harmonize  his  method 
with  present  ideas  of  proof  and  logical  procedure. 
Reconciliation  is  impossible ;  either  we  must  give  up 
one  and  cling  to  the  other,  or  we  must  reject  the  one 
in  toto  and  rely  wholly  upon  the  other.  While  he  ac- 
cepts the  most  fundamental  principles  as  true  and  tries 


xvi  INTRODUCTION 

to  show  how  the  phenomena  of  experience  result  from 
these,  we  accept  the  facts  of  experience  as  the  primary 
truths,  and  correlating  and  analyzing  these,  seek  for 
more  general  conclusions.  The  rigidity  of  deductive 
logic,  therefore,  gave  rise  to  this  method  and  instead  of 
being  censured  for  his  application  of  this  method  of 
geometry  in  philosophy  Spinoza  should  be  commended, 
for  his  close  conformity  to  the  principles  of  the  thought 
of  his  time.  If  Deduction  is  the  correct  Organon  of 
truth,  and  we  must  ground  our  belief  not  on  observa- 
tion and  experiment  but  upon  some  rational  principle, 
then  the  geometrical  method  is  the  most  logical  and 
consistent  form  in  which  to  present  philosophical  truth. 
Mathematics,  a  deductive  science,  has  not  discarded 
this  method  and  never  will.  And  just  as  soon  as  we 
can  get  the  deductive  point  of  view,  Spinoza's  method 
will  not  seem  artificial  nor  inapt,  but  perfectly  logical 
and  perfectly  suited  to  the  purposes  for  which  it  was 
employed.  But  from  the  modern  standpoint  it  will 
always  be  regarded  as  an  attempt  to  commensurate 
what  is  incommensurable. 

To  Spinoza's  associates,  however,  men  accustomed 
to  the  deductive  point  of  view  the  geometrical  method 
used  in  this  early  work  did  not  seem  strange  or  inapt. 
On  the  other  hand,  to  them  this  method,  as  soon  as 
it  appeared,  appealed  as  a  great  improvement  even 
over  the  sunclear  method  of  Descartes,  and  they  at 
once  sought  to  have  him  put  the  remainder  of  Des- 
cartes' Principles  in  this  form  and  allow  it  to  be  pub- 
lished. From  the  Preface  of  Dr.  Meyer  we  might  in- 
fer that  they  considered  this  an  infallible  method  of 
presenting  truths ;  but  this  is  not  essential.  All  that 
we  now  wish  to  show  is  that  to  minds  whose  thoughts 
were  habitually  deductive,  the  geometrical  method  ap- 


INTRODUCTION  xvii 

plied  to  philosophy  did  not  seem  artificial  nor  inappro- 
priate, but  well  devised  and  the  best  possible  method 
of  presenting  any  truth  logically  and  forcibly. 

We  thus  come  to  the  real  causes  that  led  Spinoza 
to  make  use  of  the  geometrical  method  in  his  philo- 
sophical system.  He  believed  that  this  method  was 
pedagogically  the  correct  one  because  he  believed  de- 
duction was  the  correct  way  to  establish  truth.  It 
matters  but  little  whether  we  say  that  Spinoza  believed 
the  method  of  geometry  was  the  best  method  to  pre- 
sent truth  to  the  learning  mind,  because  it  conformed 
so  perfectly  to  the  principles  of  deduction,  or  whether 
we  say  because  Deduction  is  the  Organon  of  truth 
the  geometrical  method  is  the  acme  of  logical  consist- 
ency. The  truth  that  we  wish  to  make  clear  is  that  the 
geometrical  method  had  its  real  causes  in  Deduction, 
and  the  immediate  occasion  of  its  use  in  a  desire  to 
conform  strictly  to  the  requirements  of  the  mental 
processes  of  the  student.  Spinoza  was  correct  in  his 
reasoning,  therefore,  and  abundantly  justified  in  his 
use  of  this  method.  It  was  the  climax  of  logical  pur- 
pose and  failed  to  receive  the  approval  of  succeeding 
ages  not  from  any  weakness  in  itself  nor  because  it  was 
ill  applied,  but  because  the  whole  process  of  thought 
has  been  reversed.  Had  Deduction  retained  its  hold 
upon  the  minds  of  the  thinking  few,  Spinoza's  inno- 
vation would  have  been  praised  as  it  has  since  been 
censured. 

Reference  to  this  early  work  of  Spinoza,  then,  offers 
a  very  considerable  aid  in  understanding  the  method 
of  the  Ethics.  We  have  found  the  purpose,  I  believe, 
he  had  in  view  when  he  employed  it  both  in  his  earliest 
and  in  his  latest  works.  As  we  have  seen  he  certainly 
did  not  regard  this  method  in  the  nature  of  a  proof  of 


xviii  INTRODUCTION 

the  positions  taken  in  the  Principles,  and  we  find  no 
reason  for  believing  that  he  did  in  the  Ethics.  Be- 
sides, in  this  last  work  his  purpose  was  practical  rather 
than  speculative-  or  theoretical.  He  did  not  give  his 
life  to  meditation  like  Descartes,  primarily  for  the 
sake  of  truth,  but  ultimately  that  he  might  point  out 
to  man  the  way  of  blessedness  and  peace.  His  purpose 
was,  as  the  title  of  the  work  indicates,  ethical  not 
metaphysical.  He  uses  demonstration  in  his  work  and 
yet  not  for  the  sake  of  the  demonstration  but  that  he 
might  convince.  With  his  logical  mind,  so  little  in- 
fluenced  by  prejudice  of  any  kind,  conviction  followed 
demonstration,  and  he  thought  that  it  was  always  so. 
However,  Spinoza  did  not  depend  upon  this  method  to 
produce  conviction  in  his  readers  but  upon  the  truth  in 
the  premises  from  which  he  started.  The  geometrical 
method  would  enable  others  to  see  clearly  what  he  had 
learned  through  years  of  reflection.  If  once  we  under- 
stand why  it  was  used,  that  it  rested  upon  an  implicit 
faith  in  scholastic  logic,  and  that  it  was  the  crowning 
attempt  of  a  logical  mind  to  conform  absolutely  to  the 
strictest  demand  of  this  iron-clad  reason,  there  need 
be  but  little  difficulty  in  following  his  argument  and 
to  some  degree  at  least  in  appreciating  his  presenta- 
tion. But  to  do  this  the  essential  thing  is  to  get  rid  just 
as  far  as  we  can  of  our  scientific  prejudices,  and  grasp 
the  problem  as  it  was  envisaged  by  Spinoza,  with  its 
mediaeval  atmosphere.  Otherwise  the  method  will  re- 
main, as  it  seems  at  first,  an  incomprehensible  appli- 
cation of  geometrical  method  to  subject  matter  which 
has  no  relation  at  all  to  the  form  into  which  it  is  put. 
But  remembering  that  that  was  a  deductive  age,  even 
philosophical  truth,  we  see,  was  thought  to  be  not  dis- 
similar to  the  mathematical  truth  which  geometry  ade- 


INTRODUCTION  xix 

quately  demonstrates.  Back  of  Spinoza's  attempt  to 
apply  the  geometrical  method  to  philosophy  was  the 
more  fundamental  attempt  to  make  philosophy  as  truly 
deductive  as  geometry.  This  method,  therefore,  was 
the  logical  method,  the  method  best  adapted  to  the 
thought  of  the  age,  or  as  we  have  expressed  it  above, 
it  was  used  because  of  its  pedagogical  correctness. 

§  5.     Spinoza's  complete  reliance  upon  Deduction  as 
the  true  order  of  all  methodical  thought  and  of  proof, 
calls  attention  to  another  thought  of  fundamental  im- 
portance in  understanding  his  philosophy.     Instead  of 
building  upon  the  great  conclusion  of  Descartes  ac- 
cording to  the  method  of  the  Novum  Organum  he 
turns  back  to  the  long  tried  logic  of  the  Scholastics  and 
seeks  by  a  more  perfect  adherence  to  the  principles 
of  their  logic  to  deduce  a  system  and  explain  experi- 
ence,  and,   Pantheism   is   the   result.     To   be   true   to 
Deduction,  and  it  was   Spinoza's  purpose  to  be  per- 
fectly so,  the  starting  point  for  reflective  thought  must 
be  a  concept  which  includes  all  that  is  to  be  deduced. 
The  logical  starting  point  of  Spinoza's  system,  there- 
fore, is  with  the  concept  of  God.    Since  the  attempt  is 
to  be  made  to  follow  in  thought  the  plan  of  creation 
the  first  step  will  be  to  learn  everything  possible  of  the 
Creator.     So  in  the  Ethics  we  find  Spinoza,  true  to  the 
demands  of  deductive  thought,  dividing  his  work  ex- 
actly the  reverse  of  what  modern  philosophical  treat- 
ment demands.    In  Part  I.  he  treats  of  God,  in  Part  II. 
of  the  Origin  and  then  the  nature  of  mind  and  then  in 
Part  III.  of  its  affects,  etc.     Before  we  study  the  mind 
we  must  study  God,  before  we  study  its  nature  we 
must  study  its  origin.    In  every  way  the  order  is  just 
the  reverse  of  that  followed  today  in  attempts  to  solve 
the  mysteries  of  Reality  or  to  understand  Experience. 


xx  INTRODUCTION 

And  yet  from  his  point  of  view  his  order  is  the  only 
logical  one.  Attention  has  been  called  to  these  facts 
to  show  the  supreme  logical  importance  of  this  concept 
of  God,  in  Spinoza's  philosophical  system.  His  thought 
so  hinges  upon  this  idea  for  the  reasons  we  have  just 
mentioned,  that  its  mastery  is  the  prerequisite  for  an 
intelligent  comprehension  of  the  main  tenets  of  his 
Pantheism.  If  we  wish  to  understand  why  Spinoza's 
reflection  led  him  from  a  Deistic  conception  of  God 
to  Pantheism  rather  than  to  Theism,  or  if  we  wish  to 
adequately  appreciate  the  truth  in  Pantheism  we  must 
preface  our  study  with  the  closest  investigation  pos- 
sible of  the  idea  of  God.  The  key  that  has  not  yet 
been  used  for  such  study  is  the  historical  develop- 
ment of  that  idea.  We  cannot  appreciate  Spinoza's 
definition  of  God,  for  example,  unless  we  are  ac- 
quainted with  some  of  the  prior  conceptions  of  sub- 
stance and  with  the  various  attempts  to  explain  Des- 
cartes' Dualism.  Nor  can  we  —  and  this  is  the  region 
in  which  our  inquiry  lies  —  appreciate  or  rightly  com- 
prehend the  attributes  of  Spinoza's  God  unless  we  see 
how  his  ideas  on  this  subject  developed  from  the  more 
orthodox  theology  of  a  previous  period. 

§  6.  In  order  to  get  the  true  starting  point  of 
Spinoza's  ideas  concerning  God  we  should  remember 
that  he  had  in  his  veins  five  thousand  years  of  Mon- 
otheism. A  Jew  by  birth  and  early  training,  the  pure 
Monotheism  of  the  Hebrew  people  would  be  his  ear- 
liest conception  of  God.  Soon  after  completing  the 
usual  Jewish  course  of  study,  with  its  emphasis  upon 
this  idea,  he  turned  his  attention  to  Jewish  theology 
and  for  some  time  was  a  diligent  student  of  that  branch 
of  study.  His  opinions,  therefore,  were  more  than  in- 
cidently  influenced  by  the  theology  of  the  Jewish  re- 


INTRODUCTION  xxi 

ligion.  The  influence  of  this  study,  however,  did  not 
seem  to  confirm  him  in  his  earlier,  filial  acceptance  of 
the  religion  of  his  fathers.  On  the  other  hand  we 
know  that  for  his  opinions,  when  still  at  an  early  age, 
he  was  excommunicated  for  heresy  from  the  syna- 
gogue and  anathematized  with  all  the  opprobrious 
epithets  of  that  body.  The  ground  of  his  dissent  is 
not  hard  to  see.  His  philosophic  mind,  so  free  at  all 
times  from  passion  or  prejudice,  demanded  a  broader 
conception  of  God  than  the  Jewish  religion  as  ordinar- 
ily interpreted  supplied.  The  limited  love  of  God, 
the  unsympathetic,  uncharitable  pride  that  led  the  Jews 
to  regard  themselves  as  the  chosen  people  of  God 
would  repel  a  mind  of  Spinoza's  temperament.  The 
very  exclusiveness  in  which  the  Hebrews  so  delighted, 
the  special  favor  which  they  claimed  as  their  peculiar 
birthright  from  God,  was  opposed  to  unprejudiced,  re- 
flective thought,  as  it  was  also  to  the  principles  of 
Christian  truth.  Philosophy  demands  a  human  broth- 
erhood that  includes  both  Jew  and  Gentile,  Barbarian 
and  Greek.  But  such  a  brotherhood  presupposes  the 
Fatherhood  of  God.  Such  a  conception,  however,  was 
opposed  to  the  traditions  of  the  Hebrew  people ;  while 
they  might  acknowledge  Jehovah  as  the  creator  of  all 
people,  His  love  and  special  care  were  for  their  nation 
alone.  The  history  of  this  people  is  one  long  story 
where  the  safety  and  welfare  of  the  Hebrews  was 
placed  above  every  humanitarian  consideration.  In 
the  Thcolo gico-P olitical  Treatise,  published  only  a  few 
years  later  than  The  Principles  of  Descartes'  Philos- 
ophy, etc.,  we  see  how  strongly  this  exclusiveness  of 
the  Jews  affected  his  thought.  In  the  opening  words 
of  Chapter  III.  we  have  these  words :  "  Every  man's 
true  happiness  and  blessedness  consists  solely  in  the 


xxii  INTRODUCTION 

enjoyment  of  what  is  good,  not  in  the  pride  that  he 
alone  is  enjoying  it  to  the  exclusion  of  others.  He 
who  thinks  himself  the  more  blessed  because  he  is 
enjoying  benefits  which  others  are  not,  or  because  he 
is  more  blessed  or  more  fortunate  than  his  fellows, 
is  ignorant  of  true  happiness  and  blessedness,  and  the 
joy  which  he  feels  is  either  childish  or  envious  and 
malicious.  For  instance,  a  man's  true  happiness  con- 
sists only  in  wisdom  and  the  knowledge  of  the  truth, 
not  at  all  in  the  fact  that  he  is  wiser  than  others  or  that 
others  lack  such  knowledge ;  such  considerations  do  not 
increase  his  wisdom  or  true  happiness. 

Whoever,  therefore,  rejoices  for  such  reasons,  re- 
joices in  another's  misfortune,  and  is,  so  far  malicious 
and  bad,  knowing  neither  true  happiness  nor  the  peace 
of  the  true  life."  x 

Beneath  this  trenchant  criticism  of  the  Jewish  re- 
ligion there  is  an  implied  stricture  upon  the  Jewish 
idea  of  God.  A  God  who  would  answer  to  their  de- 
mands for  special  favor  at  the  expense  of  other  nations, 
was  not  a  God  in  whom  Spinoza  could  believe.  The 
philosophical  and  rationalistic  bias  of  his  mind  de- 
manded a  God  in  every  attribute,  perfect,  and  in  every 
expression  of  his  power  infinite.  Thus  he  was  early 
led  to  see  the  inconsistencies  of  the  traditional  Jewish 
conception  of  God  and  to  seek  an  idea  of  Him  free 
from  personal  or  national  prejudices  and  in  closer  ac- 
cord with  the  highest  demands  of  his  rational  nature. 
And  as  he  understood  these  demands,  they  required  a 
God  of  more  universal  providence  than  the  ordinary 
conception  of  Jehovah.  With  this  dissent  from  the 
Jewish  idea  of  God  we  find  also  an  attitude  of  mind 
which  we  know  today  under  the  term  "higher  criti- 
1  Spinoza's  Works,  Elwes'  Translation,  Vol.  I. 


INTRODUCTION  xxiii 

cism."  The  influence  of  this  spirit,  best  seen  in  the 
treatise  mentioned  before,  was  to  lead  Spinoza  away 
from  the  Jehovah  of  the  Jewish  belief  to  a  more  ra- 
tionalistic conception  of  His  nature.  In  the  study  of 
theology  Spinoza  had  been  led  to  examine  this  belief 
closely  and  critically,  with  the  consequent  separation 
from  much  of  their  most  cherished  belief.  Through- 
out his  early  study  of  Jewish  theology  he  was  actuated 
by  the  most  liberal  interpretation  of  scriptural  dogma. 
Thus  while  in  that  theology  there  were  elements  of 
monotheism,  which  we  know  Spinoza  thus  far  accepted, 
there  were  also  in  the  traditional  side  of  that  teaching 
ground  for  a  most  determined  dissent. 

We  know,  too,  that  Spinoza  was  also  more  or  less 
influenced  by  the  Christian  concept  of  God ;  in  all  his 
published  work  the  New  Testament  is  accorded  an 
equal  place  with  the  Old  as  an  expression  of  the  Word 
and  Will  of  God. 

However,  since  the  Jewish  and  the  Christian  con- 
cepts of  God  are  practically  the  same,  judged  from  the 
philosophical  point  of  view,  we  need  not  pause  to  em- 
phasize this  fact.  All  that  we  need  to  note  is  that  it 
was  from  this  concept  that  his  later  ideas  developed. 

§  J.  The  other  element  in  Spinoza's  early  life  that 
shaped  his  thought  and  determined  the  character  of 
his  philosophy,  was  the  widely  prevalent  doctrines  of 
Descartes.  So  far,  almost  all  that  we  have  seen  has 
been  a  spirited  dissent  from  the  current  ideas  of  his 
time  without  any  very  definite  constructive  tenets  to 
replace  those  he  was  so  rapidly  rejecting.  But  this 
was  but  a  clearing  away  of  the  debris  preparatory  to 
the  structure  soon  to  be  begun.  In  giving  positive 
character  to  his  new  ideas  and  in  turning  his  thoughts 
from  a  purely  theological  to  a  constructive  philosoph- 


xxiv  INTRODUCTION 

ical  character  the  Cartesian  philosophy  has  its  place. 
It  was  to  this  work  that  he  turned  after  his  reflection 
led  him  to  part  with  the  synagogue  and  so  give  over 
his  special  work  in  theology.  Much  has  already  been 
written  upon  Descartes'  influence  upon  Spinoza,  and 
yet  there  is  one  aspect  of  it  that  has  not  been  suffi- 
ciently noted.  This,  however,  is  hardly  to  be  won- 
dered at  for  it  is  an  aspect  which  the  study  of  Spinoza's 
earliest  writings  alone  reveals.  It  was  not  the  Dualism 
of  Descartes  that  had  the  earliest  influence  upon  Spin- 
oza ;  neither  was  it  any  other  of  the  ontological  tenets  or 
conclusions  of  the  system  that  first  interested  him. 
But  as  we  see  by  reference  to  the  main  theme  in  his 
early  discussion  of  Descartes'  philosophy,  the  thought 
that  first  appealed  to  him  and  stamped  itself  upon  his 
thought  indelibly,  was  Descartes'  concept  of  God. 
Whether  this  continued  to  be  of  prime  importance  or 
not  in  moulding  his  opinions  it  was  the  first  great 
factor  to  gain  his  serious  attention.  This  was  made 
all  but  inevitable  by  Spinoza's  previous  interests  and 
study,  which,  we  have  seen,  were  from  the  first  con- 
cerned with  questions  relating  to  God.  His  earliest 
interest,  therefore,  would  be  to  get  the  opinions  of 
Descartes  upon  those  topics  in  which  he  was  already 
interested.  And  not  only  would  his  interests  be  cen- 
tered in  this  subject,  but  it  would  be  along  this  line 
that  he  could  be  most  directly  and  most  potently  in- 
fluenced. It  is  important,  therefore,  that  we  get 
clearly  before  us  Descartes'  idea  of  God,  in  order  that 
we  may  see  how  Spinoza's  opinions  were  influenced 
by  contact  with  his  theory  of  the  Absolute  Being. 
The  question  for  us  to  answer,  if  we  wish  to  under- 
stand his  Pantheism,  is,  how  did  he  pass  logically  from 
these  earlier  views  to  the  more  radical,  and  heterodox 


INTRODUCTION  xxv 

opinions  found  in  the  Ethics?  We  must  turn,  then, 
to  a  consideration  of  Descartes'  ideas  concerning  God 
as  they  were  understood  by  Spinoza. 

§  8.  Descartes'  conception  of  God,  as  Spinoza  un- 
derstood it,  we  find  most  clearly  expressed  in  the  Cogi- 
tata  Metaphysica,  an  essay  upon  certain  metaphysical 
subjects,  given  as  an  appendix  to  the  "  Principles  of 
Descartes'  Philosophy."  The  essay  itself  suggests 
the  importance  of  the  concept  of  God  in  Spinoza's 
mind,  for  the  whole  of  the  second  part  is  given  up 
entirely  to  this  one  idea  and  a  good  part  of  Part  I.  is 
really  a  prolegomenon  to  these  thoughts.  So  while 
this  discussion  is  far  more  independent  of  Descartes' 
order  than  is  the  "  Principles,"  we  know  that  Spinoza 
wrote  it  more  as  an  expression  of  Descartes'  belief 
than  as  his  own  at  the  time  it  was  written.  Still  we 
might  say  for  the  most  part  there  is  in  Spinoza's  lan- 
guage the  ring  of  conviction,  and  in  his  earlier  years 
he  would  probably  have  accepted  even  a  greater  pro- 
portion of  it  as  his  own  belief.  But  be  this  as  it  may, 
we  find  in  it  a  wealth  of  suggestive  matter  upon  the 
idea  of  God.  And  this  matter  if  used  aright  will 
throw  much  light  upon  Spinoza's  later  thought.  In 
order  to  get  as  much  help  as  possible  in  understanding 
Spinoza's  concept  of  God,  we  shall  notice  this  essay 
rather  carefully. 

In  Part  II.  of  the  Cogitata,  the  part  that  treats 
more  specifically  of  God  and  his  attributes,  there  are 
twelve  chapters  and  all  except  one  discuss  some  char- 
acteristic of  His  being.  The  first  chapter  discusses 
the  eternity  of  God.  What  is  said  concerning  this 
attribute  depends  upon  the  distinction,  that  must  first 
be  made  clear,  between  essence  and  existence,  and  be- 
tween the  essence  of  created  objects  and  the  essence  of 


xxvi  INTRODUCTION 

God  Himself.  "  Essence,"  he  says,  "  is  nothing  else 
than  the  mode  by  which  created  objects  are  compre- 
hended in  the  attributes  of  God.  *  *  *  Exist- 
ence is  the  essence  of  things  considered  in  themselves 
apart  from  God,  and  is  attributed  to  things  after 
they  have  been  created  by  God."  1  The  difference  be- 
tween essence  and  existence  in  created  or  finite  objects 
then  is  this:  The  essence  of  an  object  concerns  its 
reality,  not  merely  as  an  individual  thing,  but  as  it 
stands  related  to  its  primary  or  efficient  cause.  This 
term  lays  the  emphasis  upon  the  ontological  nexus  be- 
tween an  object  and  the  Absolute  Being,  and,  does  not, 
therefore,  consist  in  any  sensible  quality  or  attribute. 
The  term  existence  is  not  so  fundamentally  ontological. 
When  using  this  term  no  question  is  raised  as  to  the 
connection  between  an  object  and  God,  but  it  is  re- 
garded simply  as  an  object  of  our  cognitive  experience. 
I  do  not  regard  it  in  its  relation  to  Nature,  but  in  its 
relations  to  me  as  an  intelligent  subject.  The  first 
term  regards  its  ontological  reality,  the  second  its 
sensuous  nature ;  the  former  expresses  its  relation  to 
and  dependence  upon  the  Absolute,  the  latter  its  re- 
lation to  me  a  cognitive,  knowing  subject. 

The  other  point  necessary  to  understand  the  Eternity 
of  God  is  the  distinction  between  the  essence  and  ex- 
istence of  created  objects  and  the  essence  and  exist- 
ence of  uncreated  substance  or  of  God.  As  appears 
from  the  definitions  just  given,  in  created  objects  or 
in  all  things  except  God  these  terms  must  be  distin- 
guished. But  in  God  this*  ground  of  difference  disap- 
pears and  His  essence,  His  existence,  and,  indeed.  His 
understanding,  His  will,  His  decrees,  etc.,  are  one. 
There  is  not  one  fact  that  can  be  used  to  support  our 

1  Cogitata  Metaphysial,  Pt.   I.,  Chap.   II. 


INTRODUCTION  xxvli 

belief  in  the  existence  of  God,  that  does  not  have  an 
equal  importance  as  an  expression  of  some  truth  con- 
cerning His  essence.  In  a  Being  absolutely  infinite 
each  attribute  enfolds  all  the  others  so  that  as  objective 
facts  they  are  indistinguishable.  This  is  a  proposition 
to  which  we  may  well  give  the  most  serious  attention 
for  it  not  only  serves  to  make  clear  what  is  said  con- 
cerning the  eternity  of  God,  but  it  is  a  principle  which, 
we  shall  see,  led  Spinoza  toward  his  conception  of  an 
impersonal  God. 

With  this  distinction  between  essence  and  existence 
kept  in  mind  we  find  no  difficulty  in  understanding  the 
eternity  of  God.  Duration  pertains  only  to  the  exist- 
ence of  objects,  not  to  their  essence.  It  relates  to  the 
sensible  qualities  of  objects  and  is  cognized  by  our 
powers  of  sense  perception.  Eternity,  on  the  other 
hand,  belongs  to  the  infinite  essence  of  things,  and 
therefore  can  belong  properly  but  to  God.  Duration 
and  eternity  are  wholly  distinct,  and  each  sni  generis. 
Duration  applies  only  to  created  objects,  i.  e.  to  ob- 
jects, the  essence  of  which  is  not  in  themselves  but  in 
God,  while  the  latter  term  applies  only  to  a  Being 
whose  essence  is  wholly  self-contained.  The  temporal 
idea,  the  essential  one  in  duration,  is  not  so  funda- 
mental in  the  term  eternity.  The  latter  term  since  it 
relates  to  an  attribute  of  God,  embraces  by  implication 
all  the  attributes  of  God.  Therefore,  though  created 
objects  should  have  existed  from  the  beginning,  coeval 
with  God,  we  could  not  ascribe  eternity  to  them  unless 
their  existence  was  self-contained  and  necessary. 
The  real  ground  of  distinction,  is  not  temporal  there- 
fore, but  an  essential,  ontological  differentiation  be- 
tween substance  that  is  self-contained,  necessary,  and 
absolute,  and  substance  that  is  contingent  and  depend- 


xxviii  INTRODUCTION 

ent.  Eternity  can  be  predicated  of  God  alone,  not, 
however,  merely  because  He  has  existed  for  an  in- 
finite time,  but  because  He  is  the  one  necessary,  abso- 
lute, self-contained,  eternal  Being. 

From  what  has  been  said  it  follows  that  the  present 
existence  of  an  object  does  not  insure  or  even  imply 
its  future  being.  This  depends  upon  its  essence,  and 
its  essence  in  turn  depends  upon  God.  We  today  are 
wont  to  assume  that  having  the  bare  "stuff"  of  the 
world  once  given  the  rest  is  easily  explainable  by  nat- 
ural physical  law.  As  both  Descartes  and  Spinoza 
saw  the  problem  it  was  not  so  simple.  But  back  of 
every  object  and  of  every  event  stands  the  power  of 
God.  His  concurrence  is  necessary  in  order  that  these 
objects  may  exist  even  for  a  moment.  In  every  case 
there  is  a  submerging  of  the  finite  in  the  infinite,  an 
absolute  dependence  of  every  created  object  upon  the 
power  and  will  of  God.  So  dependent  becomes  the 
finite,  and  so  absolute  the  infinite  that  we  may  well 
ask  ourselves  if  this  did  not  help  to  turn  Spinoza  to- 
ward his  later  conception  of  God  and  the  world.  But 
this  thought  will  appear  again  before  we  finish  our  in- 
vestigation into  Descartes'  idea  of  God. 

The  other  point  of  interest  to  us  in  this  discussion  of 
duration  and  eternity  is,  that  it  is  one  step  toward 
a  complete  identification  of  the  attributes  of  God,  which 
leads  finally  to  the  necessary  or  determined  character  of 
all  of  God's  acts  and  decrees.  But  this,  too,  will  be- 
come clearer  further  on,  so  we  need  do  no  more  than 
call  attention  to  it  here. 

In  Chapter  II.  of  the  second  part  of  the  Cogitata 
Metaphysial  the  following  argument  is  given  to  prove 
that  there  is  but  one  God.  Since  omniscience  is  a  nec- 
essarv  attribute  of  God,  if  there  were  many  Gods  each 


INTRODUCTION  xxix 

one  must  have  a  perfect  understanding  of  all  things. 
Each  god,  therefore,  must  understand  perfectly  him- 
self and  all  the  other  gods  besides.  But  under  such 
conditions  the  cause  of  all  perfection  would  not  be 
self-contained  in  God,  but  would  exist  partly  in  Him- 
self and  partly  in  another.  This,  however,  is  contrary 
to  the  concept  of  God.  Therefore,  there  is  but  one 
God. 

The  significance  of  this  proof  does  not  lie  in  the 
truth  it  professes  to  establish ;  to  one  who  did  not  al- 
ready believe  in  monotheism  this  argument  would  not 
be  convincing.  Nor  does  any  cogency  appear  unless 
we  accept  the  method  of  deductive  logic,  and  acknowl- 
edge the  power  of  the  mind  to  form  a  priori,  a  concept 
of  God  which  must  be  true.  It  is  interesting  to  us 
here  because  it  is  so  strictly  in  accord  with  the  deduc- 
tive character  of  thought  at  that  time  and  because  it 
shows  how  all  philosophy  and  all  truth  is  contained  in 
this  one  central  idea  of  God.  It  foreshadows  Spinoza's 
attempt  to  derive  a  whole  system  of  philosophy,  and  to 
explain  a  world  of  experimentive  facts,  by  drawing 
upon  this  concept  of  God.  Besides  this,  there  is  the  im- 
plied truth,  more  positively  affirmed  in  another  place, 
that  God's  omniscience  is  nothing  but  self  knowledge. 
He  does  not  know  an  objective  world  as  we  do,  but  His 
knowledge  is  simply  knowledge  of  His  own  will,  and 
of  His  decrees.  From  this  one  idea  all  things  are  to 
be  deduced,  and  it  is  not  hard  to  pass  from  this  knowl- 
edge of  things  in  God,  to  their  existence  in  Him,  which 
is  the  usual  formula  for  Pantheism. 

The  next  attribute  of  God  discussed  is  His  greatness. 
This  cannot  be  predicted  of  God  so  far  as  we  regard 
Him  as  an  absolutely  perfect  or  infinite  Being,  but  only 
as  He  is  regarded  as  the  efficient  cause  of  the  world 


xxx  IXTRODUCTION 

around  us.  It  is  hardly  correct  to  assign  magnitude 
at  all  to  infinity,  for  any  assignable  magnitude  what- 
ever before  infinity  pales  to  insignificance  and  is  lost. 
However,  the  world  is  a  manifestation  of  the  power  of 
God,  hence  since  He  appears  in  the  effect  we  may  in- 
fer His  nature  as  "  first  "  cause.  The  cause  must  be 
adequate  for  the  effect.  Since,  therefore,  there  is  no 
object  by  which  He  may  be  limited  or  determined,  in  ' 
this  respect  we  may  properly  apply  this  term  to  His 
being.  When  we  use  this  term  to  describe  His  being, 
however,  we  are  regarding  the  objects  in  which  His 
power  is  manifested  more  than  His  own  true  character. 
As  a  "first"  cause  He  is  great  but  per  se  He  is  in- 
finite. 

The  fourth  attribute  discussed  is  the  immutability 
of  God.  In  this  chapter  we  are  told  that  God  is  un- 
changeable and  absolutely  so.  All  changes  arise 
either  from  some  external  cause,  the  subject  being 
either  willing  or  unwilling,  or  from  some  internal 
cause.  God  is  not  changed  by  an  external  cause  for 
He  is  Himself  the  cause  of  all  things  and  can  be 
changed  by  none  of  them.  Neither  is  there  in  God 
any  self-caused  change,  for  all  changes  that  depend 
upon  the  will  of  the  subject  arise  from  an  attempt  to 
pass  to  a  more  perfect  state  of  being.  But  this  is  im- 
possible in  God  who  is  in  every  way  absolutely  per- 
fect.    God,  therefore,  is  immutable. 

The  inferences  to  be  drawn  from  this  conclusion 
are  far  reaching  and  for  our  purposes  exceedingly  im- 
portant. Practically,  there  is  little  difference  between 
an  unchangeable  God,  and  a  God  whose  acts  are  all 
determined ;  as  far  as  the  external  world  is  concerned 
there  is  no  difference  at  all.  There  is  no  more  direct 
way  to  universal   Determinism   than   to  affirm,   as   is 


INTRODUCTION  xxxi 

r 

done  in  this  discussion,  that  God  is  the  sole  cause  of 
all  being,  both  that  it  is,  and  what  it  is,  and  that  He 
is  unchangeable,  that  His  decrees  are  eternal.  If 
God  is  the  efficient  cause  of  all  being,  not  in  a  general 
way  being  simply  its  creator,  but  in  a  concrete,  re- 
sponsible way  determining  the  act  of  every  object,  we 
have  granted  all  the  determinism  in  Nature  that 
Spinoza's  system  demands.  And  if  we  agree  with 
this  Cartesian  philosophy  so  far  as  to  say  that  God's 
understanding,  and  power,  and  will,  and  decrees,  are 
one,  and  that  He  is  unchangeable  we  have  little  more 
to  admit  to  be  in  agreement  with  Spinoza's  teaching 
concerning  the  determined  nature  of  all  of  God's  de- 
crees. The  ground  for  distinguishing  between  an  ab- 
solute, unchangeable  God,  and  a  God  whose  thoughts 
and  acts  are  necessarily  what  they  are,  is  hard-  to  de- 
fine. In  the  first  case  the  sequence  of  events  is  fixed 
because  God  in  His  infinite  wisdom  has  foreseen  all 
contingencies  and  foreordained  those  changes  which 
best  accord  with  His  will ;  in  the  latter  case  the  result 
is  the  same,  but  God's  decrees  and  the  changes  in  na- 
ture are  conceived  to  be  determined,  as  it  were,  by 
some  hypostasized  necessity. 

The  matter  given  in  Chapters  V.  and  VI.  is  so  purely 
of  scholastic  interest  that  we  will  do  no  more  than 
note  it,  for  the  sake  of  completeness,  in  the  briefest 
possible  way.  In  the  first  of  these  two  chapters  we 
are  told  that  God  is  not  a  composite  but  a  simple  Be- 
ing. This  conclusion  rests  upon  the  distinction  intro- 
duced in  the  first  paragraph  between  "  real "  and 
"  modal  "  and  "  rational  "  being.  All  composite  being' 
must  be  composed  of  some  one  combination  of  these 
three  forms.  But  God  is  not  thus  composite,  there- 
fore, etc. 


xxxii  ,  INTRODUCTION 

The  sixth  chapter  speaks  of  the  life  of  God,  and  the 
prime  object  is  to  secure  a  definition  broad  enough  to 
include  the  life  of  plants  and  animals  as  well  as  the 
life  of  men  and  the  life  of  God.  After  showing  that 
two  from  Aristotle  are  unsatisfactory  he  gives  the 
following:  "Life  is  the  force  by  which  objects  pre- 
serve their  own  being."  * 

In  striking  contrast  to  the  two  chapters  just  noted 
the  contents  of  the  following  three  are  replete  with 
suggestion  and  worthy  of  the  most  careful  considera- 
tion :  Omniscience,  the  first  attribute  of  God  dis- 
cussed, throughout  the  whole  development  of  the 
monotheistic  idea  of  God  has  always  been  regarded  as 
one  of  His  most  Godlike  attributes.  From  the  re- 
flective or  philosophical  point  of  view  well  may  it  be 
given  this  place  of  prime  importance.  Upon  this  at- 
tribute all  the  other  attributes  depend.  Without  om- 
niscience omnipotence  is  nerveless,  His  will  and  His 
decrees  are  blind  and  even  His  love  has  lost  half  its 
virtue.  For  philosophy,  therefore,  God's  omniscience 
assumes  the  importance  of  a  postulate.  Correlated 
with  this  in  importance  follows  a  discussion  of  the 
will  of  God.  For  its  bearing,  therefore,  upon 
Spinoza's  universal  Determinism  it  yields  in  impor- 
tance to  no  other  attribute. 

His  remarks  in  this  chapter  upon  the  problem  of 
good  and  evil,  another  vital  question  in  Pantheism, 
also  call  for  consideration  for  we  find  here  in  this 
chapter  the  germs  of  Spinoza's  later  position  in  the 
Ethics.  But  we  turn  now  to  notice  these  points  more 
specifically. 

God's  omniscience,  as  we  are  now  almost  ready 
to  infer,  is   not  a  conclusion  warranted  by  induction 

1  Cogitata  Metaphysial.  Pt.  II.,  Ch.  VI. 


INTRODUCTION  xxxiii 

but  a  truth  deduced  from  the  idea  of  an  absolutely 
perfect  God.  God  is  a  being  absolutely  and  infinitely 
perfect.  Omniscience  is  a  mark  of  such  perfection. 
Therefore,  God  is  omniscient.  This  attribute  is  thus 
established  as  are  all  His  others,  purely  deductively. 
God's  knowledge,  however,  is  not  like  ours,  derived 
through  logical  processes  of  thought,  either  inductive 
or  deductive,  but  is  direct,  immediate  and  infallible. 
Human  knowledge  is  of  two  kinds,  knowledge  of  ob- 
jective facts  and  knowledge  of  subjective  states.  Des- 
cartes had  shown  that  our  knowledge  of  the  external 
world  depends  upon  the  veracity  of  God;  that  He  is 
by  nature  so  true  that  it  would  be  contrary  to  His 
character  to  create  us  so  that  our  senses  are  constantly 
deceiving  us  in  their  account  of  the  objective  world. 
Knowledge  of  self,  on  the  other  hand,  is  true  and  cer- 
tain whether  God  be  a  deceiver  or  not.  Indeed,  so 
certain  is  the  starting  point  of  his  philosophy,  his 
cogito  ergo  sum  that  God  Himself,  we  are  told,  could 
not  deceive  me  in  this  one  thing.  So  long  as  I  do 
not  go  beyond  my  own  conscious  states  therefore,  my 
knowledge  is  indubitable  and  sure.  God's  knowledge, 
as  far  as  it  is  comparable  to  finite,  human  understand- 
ing, is  like  this  latter  kind.  God  even  in  His  om- 
niscience does  not  pass  from  His  own  being,  but  His 
knowledge  is  all  knowledge  of  Self.  As  Spinoza  says 
in  the  second  paragraph  of  this  Chapter  VII :  "  Porro 
ex  perfectione  Dei  etiam  sequitur,  ejus  ideas  non 
terminari,  sicuti  nostrae,  ab  objectis  extra  Deum  po- 
sitis."  Based  upon  this  distinction  of  Descartes  be- 
tween the  character  of  knowledge  of  one's  own  sub- 
jective states,  and  a  knowledge  of  the  external  world, 
God's  knowledge  is  wholly  of  His  own  being.  It 
therefore  has  the  directness,  the  completeness,  and  the 


xxxiv  INTRODUCTIOX 

certainty  of  self-consciousness.  He  is  the  "  first ' 
and  sole  cause  of  all  things,  therefore,  the  world  is 
contained  in  His  understanding.  The  world  of  cre- 
ated things  is  but  a  visible  expression  of  His  thought, 
or  as  it  is  forcibly  stated,  "  He  is  Himself  the  object 
of  His  knowledge,  indeed  He  is  that  knowledge."  * 

This  conclusion,  logically  developed,  leads  us  far 
toward  Pantheism.  There  is  a  great  deal  more  than 
a  mere  epistemological  truth,  implicated  in  its  terse  as- 
sertion. Besides  this,  it  contains  a  whole  system  of 
ontology.  If  God's  knowledge  is  of  Himself  alone 
and  not  of  the  external  world,  either  His  understand- 
ing is  imperfect  or  all  things  are  in  some  way  con- 
tained in  Him.  The  latter  alternative  is,  of  course, 
the  one  Spinoza  accepts.  But  this  connection  between 
God  and  the  world  cannot  be  simply  that  between  an 
object  and  its  creator  unless  it  is  assumed  that  crea- 
tion is  always  in  progress  but  never  complete.  In 
other  words,  this  conception  of  the  understanding  of 
God  requires  that  the  power  and  the  presence  of  God 
in  nature  today  be  just  as  real  and  just  as  vital  as  it 
was  when  Nature  was  being  created.  We  need  not  be 
content,  however,  with  our  own  inference,  for  this  is 
exactly  the  position  we  will  find  maintained  when  we 
come  to  notice  the  chapter  on  the  concurrence  of  God. 
This  conclusion,  therefore,  if  consistently  maintained 
is  the  death-knell  to  all  deistic  conceptions  of  God, 
and  leads  either  to  Theism  or  to  the  more  literal  doc- 
trines of  Pantheism.  It  demands  a  relation  between 
God  and  the  world  so  close  that  Deism  utterly  fails 
to  supply  it.  The  world  does  not  perdure  by  virtue  of 
some  property  of  inert  stuff  and  God  is  not  a  Dcus  ex 
machina.  To  satisfy  this  conclusion,  therefore,  we 
1  Cogitata  Mctaphysica,  Pt.  II.,  Chap.  VII. 


INTRODUCTION  xxxv 

must  turn  either  to  the  idealistic  conception  of  Theism 
or  to  the  mystical,  materialistic  identification  of  God 
and  the  world  in  Pantheism.  Just  which  of  these  it 
will  be,  or  why  it  was  the  latter,  we  will  see  depend- 
ed upon  factors  to  be  noted  later  on. 

It  will  be  worth  while  to  mention,  since  the  subject 
occurs  in  this  chapter,  God's  knowledge  of  good  and 
evil.  God,  we  are  told,  must  know  these  since  He  is 
the  cause  of  their  being  and  since  they  could  not  ex- 
ist even  for  a  moment  without  His  concurrence. 
These  terms,  however,  are  not  distinctions  grounded 
in  reality,  but  they  arise  as  the  mind  consciously  com- 
pares one  object  with  another.  The  ground  of  their 
reality,  therefore,  is  not  in  God  but  in  the  human  mind. 
Thus  the  ontological  character  of  these  terms  is  de- 
stroyed, and  the  way  is  paved  for  Spinoza's  doctrine 
of  the  relativity  of  good  and  evil  as  it  is  taught  in  his 
latest  work. 

God's  will,  by  which  He  chooses  to  love  Himself, 
follows  from  His  infinite  understanding  of  His  own 
being.  But  how  this  will  differ  from  His  understand- 
ing or  His  essence  we  cannot  say.  This  distinction 
which  we  recognize  in  the  attributes  of  God  is  not  a 
distinction  in  God  Himself,  but  arises  from  the  char- 
acter of  the  human  mind.  It  is,  as  it  is  called  else- 
where, a  distinction  of  reason.  Objectively  or  in  God 
Himself,  His  understanding,  His  power,  His  essence, 
and  His  will  are  one. 

It  is  interesting,  too,  that  Spinoza,  in  this  connec- 
tion, makes  special  mention  of  the  word  personality 
which  theologians  had  introduced  to  make  this  dis- 
tinction clear.  But,  he  says,  while  he  was  not  ig- 
norant of  the  term  itself  he  was  wholly  unable  to  get 
its  meaning  or  to  give  it  any  connection  that  would 


xxxvi  INTRODUCTIOX 

help  to  explain  the  difficulty.  From  the  later  devel- 
opment of  his  thought  we  are  compelled  to  agree  with 
him  in  this  and  to  admit  that  he  was  unable  to  har- 
monize the  term  with  his  thought.  The  subject  is 
worthy  of  consideration,  for  it  perhaps  will  help  us 
somewhat  to  understand  his  impersonal  God.  The 
essential  element  in  personality  is  intelligent  agency, 
or  rational  free  will.  But  Spinoza,  for  the  reasons 
we  have  already  mentioned  and  others  which  we  shall 
find  as  we  proceed,  could  recognize  but  one  agency, 
that  is  God.  One  of  the  signal  defects  of  Pantheism 
is  just  this,  that  it  fails  to  recognize  this  fundamental 
truth  concerning  man's  nature,  the  fact  of  his  free 
agency.  It  is  easy  to  understand  why  this  was  so ; 
Spinoza's  reflection  we  must  remember  began  not 
with  the  direct  testimony  of  all  our  conscious  experi- 
ence, but  with  the  concept  of  God,  a  being  whose  at- 
tributes were  swallowed  up  in  His  infinity.  Wrapped 
up  as  he  was  in  this  concept  of  God,  God  considered 
primarily  as  a  "  first  cause,"  he  was  never  able  to 
descend  logically  to  the  idea  of  free  finite  beings.  A 
God  whose  power  and  decrees  could  be  hampered  in 
the  least  by  the  action  of  moral  agents  was  not  a  God 
absolute  in  the  way  Deduction  demanded  that  its  Ab- 
solute should  be.  This  absoluteness  of  God,  insisted 
upon  from  first  to  last,  excluded  from  his  system  the 
existence  of  free,  rational,  beings.  Such  an  idea  was 
not  included  in  the  concept  of  God,  hence  it  could  not 
be  derived  through  deduction  nor  reconciled  with  this 
concept  when  found  externally.  His  strict  adherence 
to  deductive  logic  did  not  in  this  case  at  least  allow 
him  to  surreptitiously  introduce  into  his  philosophy 
what  was  not  logically  deduced  from  his  premises. 
Nor  can  we  wonder  at  his  dilemma.     One  of  the  most 


INTRODUCTION  xxxvii 

difficult  problems  theology  or  philosophy  has  ever 
known  is  just  upon  this  point.  It  is  the  problem  of  evil ; 
it  is  the  mystery  of  freedom  ;  it  is  the  problem  of  the  one 
and  many ;  it  is  the  sphinx  of  philosophy.  Spinoza 
encountered  it  and  solved  it  logically,  but  merely  shift- 
ed the  contradiction  to  another  place  where  it  has  since 
been  speedily  found  and  shifted  again  and  again.  We 
have  an  example,  therefore,  in  connection  with  this 
word  of  the  drift  of  all  his  thought,  how  in  everything 
he  was  urged  on  by  his  logical  consistency  and  his 
early  opinions,  to  the  system  of  his  mature  age. 

Another  significant  feature  of  this  early  chapter  on 
the  wTill  of  God  is  found  in  some  further  remarks  upon 
the  problem  of  evil.  It  is,  as  we  have  learned  now  to 
expect,  in  accordance  with  the  eternal,  absolute,  char- 
acter of  God  that  this  problem  is  solved.  As  was  seen 
in  the  chapter  upon  the  understanding  of  God,  good 
and  evil  are  terms  relative  to  human  thought.  We 
might,  perhaps,  reconcile  in  some  way  this  statement 
with  the  ethical  character  of  God,  but  when  we  are 
told  as  we  are  now  that  it  is  only  in  a  very  figurative 
sense  that  we  can  say  that  God  approves  of  some  acts 
and  disapproves  of  others,  our  last  hope  of  regarding 
God  as  an  ethical  being  is  destroyed  and  we  are  on  the 
verge  of  Pantheism.  Destroy  the  ground  of  the  dis- 
tinction of  good  and  evil  in  the  Absolute,  making  it 
purely  relative  to  human  thought,  and  there  is  left  to 
God  only  those  attributes  which  Pantheism  emphasizes, 
His  understanding,  and  His  power.  If  it  be  true  that 
all  things  good  and  evil  alike  express  God's  infinite 
understanding,  that  they  are  determined  by  His  will 
and  preserved  by  His  power,  and  above  all  that  no 
moral  distinctions  are  made  by  God,  we  must  radically 
change  our  concept  of  His  being.     With  these  propo- 


xxxviii  INTRODUCTION 

sitions  granted  the  change  must  almost  necessarily  be 
toward  the  concept  Spinoza  gives  us  in  the  Ethics. 

The  purport  of  Chapter  IX.  concerning  the  power 
of  God,  is  to  show  that  His  power  is  commensurate 
with  His  understanding,  and  that  in  respect  to  His 
decrees,  all  things  are  necessary.  It  cannot  be  said 
that  some  things  are  contingent  and  others  necessary, 
but  if  God  is  in  all  things  absolute  and,  if  by  His 
power  and  by  His  decrees  the  world  is  what  it  is,  then 
all  things  without  any  exception  are  forever  deter- 
mined to  be  as  they  are.  Nothing  can  be  except  as 
God  has  willed  that  it  should  be.  If  now  it  be  asked 
whether  God  has  determined  that  the  world  should 
be  as  it  is  from  free  choice,  Descartes  answers  this 
question  in  the  affirmative.  This  position,  however,  is 
plainly  one  with  which  Spinoza  would  not  and  could 
not  agree.  It  is  a  statement  out  of  harmony  with  his 
belief  and  even  hardly  reconcilable  with  the  conclusions 
to  which  these  chapters  are  leading  us.  The  identifica- 
tions of  God's  attributes  as  it  is  insisted  upon  makes 
this  impossible.  If  God's  understanding,  and  His 
power,  and  His  essence  and  His  will  are  one.  His 
decrees  are  as  absolute,  and  as  necessary  as  His  under- 
standing or  His  power. 

The  next  chapter  (Chapter  X.),  since  it  presents  no 
new  facts  concerning  the  nature  of  God,  need  not  delay 
us  here.  Merely  referring  the  reader  to  the  transla- 
tion of  the  chapter  given  below,  we  pass  on  to  the  last 
attribute  of  God  discussed  in  the  Cogitata. 

This  attribute  Spinoza,  using  a  Cartesian  term,  calls 
the  concurrence  (concursits)  of  God.  This  term  he 
uses  to  express  the  conserving  power  which  God  at  all 
times  manifests  in  the  world.  With  this  attribute  the 
chain  which  establishes  an  indissoluble  connection  be- 


INTRODUCTION  xxxix 

tween  God  and  nature  both  in  its  manifestations  of 
mind,  and  in  its  manifestations  of  matter,  is  complete. 

So  vital  is  this  connection  that  the  world  is,  as  it 
were,  created  anew  every  single  moment  of  its  exist- 
ence. Or,  to  express  the  thought  in  another  way, 
God's  power  and  His  presence  in  the  world  at  all  times 
is  no  whit  less  real  or  less  powerful  than  it  was  in  the 
act  of  the  first  creation.  Created  objects  do  not  have 
in  themselves  the  power  of  existence,  or  of  determining 
any  of  their  actions.  But  all  things  depend,  and 
depend  absolutely  upon  the  power  and  the  presence  of 
God  for  their  reality  and  for  their  continuance  of 
being.  Thus,  as  Spinoza  restates  the  philosophy  of 
Descartes  we  encounter  propositions  that  are  almost  if 
not  quite  pantheistic.  They  are,  to  say  the  least,  so 
anti-deistic  that  Deism  can  no  longer  in  the  face  of  so 
powerful  a  refutation,  be  maintained.  This  conception 
of  God  must  yield  place  to  a  concept  that  lays  more 
stress  upon  the  vital  necessity  of  God's  constant  pres- 
ence in  the  world.  Theism,  or  Pantheism,  therefore, 
becomes  the  only  tenable  hypothesis  of  the  World 
Ground.  Why  Spinoza  rejected  Theism  and  accepted 
Pantheism  as  the  more  rational  conception  we  shall 
now  proceed  to  inquire. 

Although  at  the  time  this  work  was  written  Spinoza 
had  doubtlessly  advanced  further  toward  Pantheism 
than  this  discussion  indicates,  still,  we  have  every  rea- 
son to  believe  that  only  a  few  years  earlier  than  this 
he  held  essentially  the  position  we  have  outlined.  The 
conception  of  God  we  have  given  was  Spinoza's  view 
of  the  Cartesian  philosophy,  which  system  he  studied 
and  at  an  early  date  partially  accepted.  It  is  our 
purpose  to  see,  so  far  as  we  can,  why  he  rejected  his 
earlier   concept   of   God,   and   accepted   Pantheism   as 


xl  INTRODUCTION 

a  more  logical,  more  satisfactory  conception.  It  is  of 
but  little  moment,  therefore,  whether  it  was  a  few 
months  earlier  or  a  few  months  later  that  his  mind 
left  the  opinions  we  have  presented  and  started  on  an 
independent  course.  The  essential  thing  is  that  he  at 
one  time  accepted  the  opinions  here  expressed,  and,  as 
we  believe  and  hope  to  show,  found  in  them  elements 
that  led  him  finally  to  the  conception  of  God  found  in 
the  Ethics.  Beside  this,  there  is,  in  the  different  points 
presented,  in  the  order  in  which  they  are  arranged  as 
well  as  in  the  general  method  of  treatment,  a  reflection 
of  Spinoza's  own  thought  showing  through  his  at- 
tempted concealment. 

Especially  is  this  true  in  the  Cogitata  Metaphysica 
which  is  a  less  formal  treatment  than  the  first  Part  of 
the  "  Principles  "  where  the  same  subject  is  discussed. 
Although  there  are  cases,  even  here,  where  Spinoza's 
opinions  are  directly  opposed  to  the  view  presented, 
there  are  others  where  he  is  expressing  his  own  con- 
viction. 

Recalling,  then,  the  points  we  have  noted  in  this 
brief  review  of  the  concept  of  God  we  ask,  are  there 
any  general  principles  involved  that  will  help  us  to 
understand  Spinoza's  Pantheism ;  why  he  came  to  ac- 
cept that  idea  of  God,  and  what  its  essential  doc- 
trines are?  In  answer  to  this  inquiry  we  at  once 
assert  that  there  are.  Throughout  our  examination  of 
this  essay,  point  after  point  has  appeared,  all  converg- 
ing toward  Pantheism.  In  connection  with  almost 
every  attribute  of  God  discussed  some  truth  has  been 
found  which  plainly  suggested,  if  it  did  not  demand, 
a  pantheistic  idea  of  God. 

§  9.  One  of  the  things  that  was  insisted  upon  from 
the  beginning,  was  the  identification  of  all  divine  attri- 


INTRODUCTION  xli 

butes  in  God.  Although  for  human  thought  it  is  nec- 
essary for  us  to  speak  of  God's  understanding,  or  of 
His  power,  or  of  His  decrees,  or  of  His  will,  this  is  a 
necessity  arising  from  the  modes  of  finite  thought  not 
from  the  true  character  of  God.  In  Himself  God 
knows  no  such  distinctions.  His  understanding  is  His 
will,  and  His  power  is  identical  with  his  decrees.  In 
God  as  He  really  is,  His  attributes  are  one  and  indis- 
tinguishable. The  perfection  of  the  one  implies  the 
presence  and  perfection  of  all  the  others,  so  that  any 
attempt  to  conceive  of  the  existence  of  one  apart  from 
all  the  others  is  hopelessly  futile.  We  may  note,  too, 
in  this  connection,  that  this  idea  of  the  indistinguishable 
unity  of  God's  attributes  is  Spinoza's  idea,  not  Des- 
cartes's.  We  are  told  in  the  Preface  of  Dr.  Meyer 
that  Spinoza  did  not  believe  with  Descartes  that  the 
will  is  something  distinct  from  the  understanding, 
much  less  that  it  has  the  freedom  which  Descartes 
maintained  that  it  possesses.1  The  logical  inferences 
that  follow  from  this  identification,  therefore,  may  be 
accepted  without  reserve,  and  we  may  point  to  it  as  a 
factor  that  helped  to  determine  Spinoza's  later  thought. 
§  10.  The  most  important  deduction  to  be  drawn 
from  this  identification  of  God's  attributes,  is  the  de- 
termined or  necessary  character  of  all  His  decrees  and 
acts,  and  the  consequent  impersonal  nature  of  His 
being.  If  it  be  true,  as  Spinoza  constantly  assumes, 
that  God  is  in  every  attribute  absolutely  perfect,  does 
this  complete  perfection  involve  a  greater  freedom  or 
a  greater  necessity  ?  Is  a  king  by  virtue  of  his  power 
more  free  in  his  acts,  or  more  constrained  by  the  ac- 
companying necessities  of  his  position  ?  Descartes  held 
that  God's  perfection  brought  infinite  freedom,  that  He 

1  See   Preface,  p.  7. 


xlii  INTRODUCTION 

was  not  determined  by  His  infinite  understanding  or 
by  His  infinite  will.  Spinoza,  on  the  other  hand,  holds 
that  if  God's  understanding  is  absolute,  and  His  under- 
standing and  His  decrees  are  one,  this  complete  knowl- 
edge of  every  contingency  binds  Him  to  one  course  of 
action.  For  as  there  can  be  but  one  absolutely  per- 
fect Being,  so  His  perfection  must  be  of  just  one  kind. 
It  is  just  as  necessary  that  the  attributes  of  such  a 
Being  should  be  just  what  they  are,  as  that  they  should 
be  contained  in  His  nature.  Intelligence  does  impose 
obligations,  and  a  perfect  understanding  of  every  cause, 
and  every  factor  involved,  if  all  nature  is  one,  demands 
that  in  every  case  the  result  shall  be  just  that  one 
thing. 

This  necessity,  however,  is  not  external.  The  nature 
of  God  is  absolute,  and  He  cannot  be  changed  or  even 
influenced  except  by  His  own  understanding.  But  be- 
cause He  is  determined  not  by  an  external  force,  but  by 
His  own  nature,  it  does  not  follow  that  He  is  less 
determined  or  that  His  actions  are  less  necessary.  On 
the  other  hand,  there  is  no  compulsion  so  absolute  as 
that  coming  from  within.  From  the  nature  of  the  case 
this  is  the  only  compulsion  that  God  can  know.  Com- 
ing as  it  does,  then,  from  God's  nature,  it  is  so  far  a 
perfectly  harmless  tenet,  for  it  only  affirms  that  God 
is  God,  and  that  Nature  is  a  faithful,  a  necessary  ex- 
pression of  His  being. 

It  will  be  worth  our  while  at  this  point  to  inquire 
a  little  further  into  the  nature  of  the  compulsion  under 
which  God  acts  as  it  follows  from  this  early  discussion 
of  Spinoza.  Our  conclusions  on  this  subject,  it  is  evi- 
dent, must  rest  upon  the  attributes  assigned  to  God,  so 
we  need  but  to  recall  what  has  been  said  to  make  this 
point  clear.     Good  and  evil   we  were  told  are  terms 


INTRODUCTION  xliii 

relative  to  human  thought,  and  God  knows  them  only 
in  this  connection.1  The  same  thought  is  further  em- 
phasized when  we  hear  that  God  does  not  regard  some 
acts  with  favor  and  others  with  disfavor.2  These 
terms  arise  as  we,  comparing  one  object  with  another, 
find  one  adapted  to  our  welfare,  and  another  opposed 
to  our  interests.  All  things  alike,  whether  we  regard 
them  as  good  or  evil,  express  God's  infinite  understand- 
ing and  His  will,  for  they  could  not  exist  for  a  single 
moment  without  His  concurrence.  It  follows,  there-, 
fore,  that  God  does  not  know  good  and  evil  apart  from 
the  human  mind,  that  they  are  not  real  but  rational 
distinctions.  These  are  not  terms  that  are  connected 
with  the  essence  of  objects,  but  are  merely  forms  of 
human  thought.  God,  therefore,  is  not  constrained  by 
considerations  of  this  kind,  and  the  necessity  under 
which  he  acts  is  not  a  moral  necessity.  God  does  not 
know  the  force  of  moral  obligation.  While  He  is  de- 
termined  by  His  nature,  it  is  not  His  nature  considered 
as  a  moral  Being. 

Excluded  from  obedience  to  supreme  moral  princi- 
ples as  the  guiding  motive  in  God's  government  of  the 
world,  we  turn  to  intellectual  considerations  to  see  if 
there  can  be  such  a  thing  as  intellectual  or  logical  com- 
pulsion. A  previous  knowledge  of  the  Ethics  leads 
us  to  expect  that  it  will  be  in  this  attribute  of  God 
that  we  shall  find  the  necessity  that  makes  all  of  His 
acts  determined.  Not  only  do  we  find  intellectual  ele- 
ments regarded  as  the  highest  expression  of  God's  per- 
fection the  source  of  His  blessedness,  but  it  was  a  fa- 
vorite tenet  of  Descartes  accepted  by  Spinoza  that 
whatever  is  clearly  and  distinctly  perceived  must  be 


1  Vid.   supra,  p.  xxxv. 

2  Ibid  p.  xxxvii. 


xliv  INTRODUCTION 

true.  In  some  way  the  connection  between  clear  logi- 
cal thought  and  Reality  is  so  vital  that  what  is  thus 
clearly  understood  must  exist.  This,  too,  not  with 
God's  thought,  but  with  finite  human  thought.  If 
such  a  statement  can  be  made  of  our  fallible  human 
thought,  how  much  greater  the  necessity  between  God's 
infinite  understanding  and  the  real  sequence  of  Na- 
ture's changes.  We  are  often  told  today  and  with  a 
good  measure  of  truth,  that  it  is  only  because  of  our 
ignorance  of  causes  that  we  regard  some  things  as 
necessary  and  some  as  contingent.  Spinoza  antici- 
pated this  argument  of  modern  Materialism  and  car- 
ried this  thought  years  ago  to  its  logical  conclusion : 
with  God  there  is  perfect,  absolute  understanding  of  all 
things,  and  this  understanding  determines  His  decrees, 
which  are  not  less  absolute  than  is  His  foreknowledge. 
So  far  as  God's  knowledge  is  absolute,  it  will  determine 
what  all  things  shall  be,  nay,  what  they  must  be,  if 
God  is  to  retain  His  absolute  character.  Any  devia- 
tion from  this  prescribed  cause,  or  any  failure  in  the 
least  part  of  the  fore-ordained  sequence  destroys  the 
whole  order  of  Nature.  In  a  universe  where  there  are 
so  many  factors,  where  action  and  reaction  assume 
such  a  multitude  of  directions  and  inter-relations,  noth- 
ing less  than  infinite  understanding  could  have  planned 
it  all,  and  nothing  less  than  absolute  conformity  to  that 
knowledge  could  preserve  it.  Just  as  it  has  been 
shown  that  there  can  exist  but  one  absolutely  perfect 
being,  so  it  might  be  shown  that  there  is  but  one  abso- 
lutely perfect  plan  for  nature.  Perfection  of  knowl- 
edge is  just  as  singular  as  perfection  of  being,  and 
there  could  no  more  be  two  perfect  plans  for  nature 
Jhan  there  could  be  two  absolute  divinities. 

Such  would  be  the  logical  inferences  by  which  Spin- 


INTRODUCTION  xlv 

oza  might  pass  from  the  premises  of  Descartes  to  the 
deterministic  idea  of  God  found  in  his  own  mature 
thought.  There  are  elements  in  the  Cartesian  phil- 
osophy, which,  harmless  though  they  seem,  lead  us  at 
once  and  directly  to  some  of  the  tenets  of  Pantheism. 
Of  this  nature  are  the  inferences  that  follow  from  this 
identification  of  the  attributes  of  God.  And  there  can 
be  but  little  doubt  that  Spinoza  when  he  wrote  the 
Cogitata  Metaphysica  recognized  these  truths  and  was 
deeply  influenced  by  them.  Though  he  gives  us  a  very 
faithful  presentation  of  Descartes'  thought  still  he  has 
presented  the  argument  whether  consciously  or  not,  so 
that  it  shows  us  the  nature  of  his  own  reflection  and 
forecasts  his  later  thought.  If  we  allow  our  minds  to 
move  at  all  from  the  positions  as  they  are  given  we 
must  reject  Descartes'  assertion  that  God  is  absolutely 
free  and  believe  with  Spinoza  that  He  is  determined 
by  the  absolute  character  of  His  being. 

We  need  not,  however,  stand  aghast  at  this  proposi- 
tion, for  when  it  is  said  that  God's  acts  are  all  deter- 
mined, since  they  are  determined  not  by  an  external 
force,  but  by  the  necessities  of  His  infinite  understand- 
ing, we  only  in  this  assert  that  God  is  true  to  His 
nature  and  that  His  decrees  are  the  decrees  of  infinite 
wisdom.  Far  from  being  a  confession  of  fatalism, 
therefore,  this  proposition,  strange  as  it  may  sound,  is 
intellectual  opinionism  of  the  strongest  type.  God's 
acts  are  necessary,  not,  however,  because  of  any  exter- 
nal compulsion,  but  because  the  requirements  of  His 
intelligence  demand  an  unchanging  invariable  se- 
quence of  events.  However,  a  God  who  acts,  nay,  is 
compelled  to  act  in  accordance  with  His  infinite  under- 
standing, may  be  a  God  who  can  justly  claim  our 
adoration  and  love.     I  say  may  be,  for  while  this  con- 


xlvi  INTRODUCTION 

fortuity  to  the  requirements  of  an  absolute  intelligence 
is  one  of  the  demands  of  Godhood,  there  are  others 
which  are  considered  by  the  human  mind  to  be  not  less 
but  even  more  important.  And  if  these  are  not  present 
as  guiding  principles  of  His  decrees  there  will  be 
wanting  in  His  nature  that  which  the  human  soul  re- 
quires in  its  God. 

§  ii.  Having  seen  the  nature  of  the  Determinism 
under  which  God  rests,  we  are  now  at  the  point  where 
we  may  raise  the  question  whether  this  Determinism 
by  destroying  the  personal  nature  of  God  is  a  direct 
step  toward  the  God  of  Spinoza's  Pantheism.  Since 
God  is  determined  not  by  an  external  force,  but  by  the 
necessities  of  such  a  fundamental  mental  requirement 
as  intelligence,  it  seems  possible  to  entertain  the  hope 
that  under  this  kind  of  necessity  we  may  yet  maintain 
the  Personality  of  God.  For  surely  to  act  always  in 
accord  with  the  demands  of  intelligence  is  a  personal 
trait  devoutly  to  be  hoped  for.  Our  hope,  however, 
will  be  short  lived,  for  as  we  have  suggested  above 
intelligence  though  it  be  absolutely  perfect  and  com- 
plete, is  not  the  sole  attribute  of  God ;  and  a  doctrine 
of  the  Absolute  that  is  based  upon  this  attribute  alone 
cannot  satisfy  the  more  exacting  requirements  of  a 
philosophical  conception  of  God.  It  is  a  truth  estab- 
lished by  all  historical  investigation  and  by  psycholog- 
ical analysis,  that  a  people's  conception  of  God  reflect 
their  best  ideals  of  culture  and  of  growth.  God  is,  in 
some  general  way,  the  sum  total  of  their  ideals,  of 
mental  and  moral  virtue.  To  limit  the  attributes  of. 
God  to  intellectual  elements  merely,  or  even  to  make 
this  the  matter  of  prime  importance  at  once  circum- 
scribes our  ideas  of  virtue,  and  limits  human  endeavor 
and  human  attainment  to  this  kind  of  development. 


INTRODUCTION  xlvii 

We  need  no  better  illustration  of  this  point  than  that 
furnished  by  Spinoza's  own  system.  For  there  the 
fundamental  attribute  of  God,  if  we  may  use  that  term 
where  each  attribute  is  infinite  and  all  are  one,  is  His 
infinite  understanding.  Perfectly  logically,  therefore, 
he  makes  the  end  of  human  endeavor,  the  highest  eth- 
ical good,  the  Summum  Bonum,  to  be  this  intellectual 
comprehension  of  Nature  as  of  God.  Spinoza's  sys- 
tem might  be  judged,  therefore,  and  judged  rightly  by 
showing  how  meagerly  or  how  completely  it  contains 
those  elements  which  are  included  under  the  term  "  per- 
sonality." For  we  may  rest  assured  that  a  people  will 
not  transcend,  in  their  general  plane  of  living,  the  ideals 
they  have  included  in  their  best  conception  of  God. 
We  do  not  need,  however,  to  resort  to  indirect  methods 
to  get  Spinoza's  view  concerning  God's  ethical  nature. 
For  we  have  already  seen  that  according  to  the  "  Cogi- 
tata ''  good  and  evil  are  terms  relative  to  human 
thought,  and  in  no  way  connected  with  the  essence 
of  things.  Thus  by  a  word  we  are  prohibited  from 
attributing  to  God  any  of  those  qualities  which  are 
almost  universally  regarded  as  the  foundation  of  char- 
acter and  of  true  personality.  Good  and  evil  do  not 
exist  apart  from  finite  thought,  and  have  no  foundation 
in  Reality  or  God.  The  attributes  of  personality  that 
arise  from  ethical  elements  must,  therefore,  be  denied. 
God's  decrees  are  not  determined  or  even  influenced 
by  these  considerations. 

Another  line  of  thought  will  further  show  us  how 
the  personal  character  of  God  is  lost  and  how  Spinoza 
was  turned  to  the  impersonal  God  of  Pantheism.  We 
have  noted  above  how  the  different  attributes  of  God 
are  identified  and  become,  in  Him,  indistinguishable. 
As  far  as  its  effect  upon  His  personal  nature  is  con- 


xlviii  INTRODUCTION 

cerned  it  is  a  matter  of  little  importance  whether  these 
attributes  be  identified  or  be  denied.  In  the  latter 
case  they  are  destroyed  through  denial,  in  the  former 
they  are  swallowed  up  in  God's  infinity.  In  either 
case  all  similarity  to  our  best  conceptions  of  Personal- 
ity are  destroyed.  However  much  we  dislike  the 
charge  of  "  anthropomorphism  "  we  have  no  other  way 
in  which  to  interpret  phenomena  philosophically. 
Hence  while  it  may  be  perfectly  true  that  these  attri- 
butes are  closer  related  to  one  another  than  in  man, 
each  one  necessarily  implying  all  the  others  to  their 
full  perfection,  still  when  it  is  said  that  they  are  all 
identified  and  indistinguishable,  our  language  is  either 
meaningless  or  it  affirms  that  God  has  lost  all  those 
attributes  connoted  by  the  term  "  personal."  If  God's 
understanding,  His  essence,  His  will,  His  power  and 
His  decrees  are  one,  what,  we  may  well  ask,  is  the  char- 
acter of  God.  Eliminating  as  far  as  possible  the  non- 
common  elements  we  come  finally  to  the  absoluteness  of 
each  attribute  as  the  one  common  factor.  His  under- 
standing is  absolute,  His  power  is  absolute,  his  decrees 
are  absolute;  the  logicalresult  of  this  absolute  charac- 
ter of  God's  attributes  is  Absolutism  or  Determinism 
that  includes  in  an  unvarying  sequence,  every  event  in 
nature,  whether  it  be  physical  or  whether  it  be  mental 
or  moral.  So  absolute  is  His  nature  that  God  Himself 
is  bound  by  the  necessity  of  His  attributes. 

This  absoluteness  in  God's  nature,  this  Determinism 
in  the  heart  of  Reality  is  not  the  less  impersonal  be- 
cause it  rests  upon  an  infinite  intelligence.  It  is  true 
that  understanding  is  an  attribute  of  Personality,  but 
all  materialistic  philosophers  will  admit  that  there  is 
intelligence  in  nature's  laws.  Otherwise  the  world 
were  no  cosmos,  and  all  philosophy  were  futile  and 


INTRODUCTION  xlix 

vain.  The  question  at  issue  between  Theism  and 
Materialism  is  not  whether  intelligence  is  manifested 
in  nature,  whether  nature  is  not  everywhere  and  al- 
ways conformable  to  Law.  This  fact  is,  especially  in 
our  day  of  Science,  accepted  without  one  dissenting 
voice.  For  if  there  is  no  reason  in  the  world  it  is  use- 
less to  attempt  rational  explanations  of  the  world's 
phenomena.  Mere  chance  is  by  hypothesis  inexplic- 
able. And  to  contend  that  the  universe  is  a  mere  con- 
course of  atoms  without  Law  is  an  absurdity  that  no 
one  would  have  the  mental  bravado  to  assert.  There 
are  laws  in  nature,  laws  that  can  be  expressed  in 
rational  terms  and  understood  by  rational  beings. 
The  only  question  is,  how  shall  we  explain  the  pres- 
ence of  mental  regulations  in  matter?  How  shall 
we  interpret  this  complete  obedience  of  matter  to 
laws  that  can  only  be  expressed  or  understood  in 
the  light  of  intelligence?  For  so  entirely  is  matter 
amenable  to  law  that  not  one  atom  in  all  nature  ever 
mistakes  its  duty,  or  ever  refuses,  however  unusual 
the  position  in  which  it  is  placed,  to  comply  instantly 
with  the  demands  of  the  laws  under  which  it  acts. 
That  this  is  true,  the  Materialist  will  affirm  even  more 
vehemently  than  the  Theist.  For,  while  the  latter  may 
believe  that  miraculous  manifestations  of  God's  power 
are  not  incompatible  with  the  world  order,  the  Mate- 
rialist guards  the  sanctity  of  "  Natural  Law  "  with  the 
jealousy  of  desperation.  In  his  case,  if  it  is  once 
even  in  the  most  trivial  way  inoperative  the  chain  is 
broken  and  the  whole  order  is  destroyed.  The  differ- 
ence between  Theism  and  Materialism  is  found  in  the 
explanation  offered  for  these  facts.  Theism  maintains 
that  this  Natural  Law  arises  from  the  Creator  of  the 
world,   a   Personal   Being.     Materialism   would   show 


1  INTRODUCTIOX 

and  have  us  believe  that  this  rational  element  in  nature 
does  not  originate  in  a  personal  Agent  or  God,  but  is 
somehow  included  in  the  very  constitution  of  inani- 
mate matter.  Materialism  recognizes  the  element  of 
law  in  nature,  the  guiding  power  of  certain  rational 
principles,  and  yet  does  not  feel  constrained  by  this  fact 
to  assert  that  it  comes  from  a  personal  Absolute.  It  is 
not  sufficient,  therefore,  to  establish  the  personal  char- 
acter of  God,  to  say  that  His  acts  and  His  decrees  are 
an  expression  of  absolute  intelligence.  If  God  is  a 
personal  being,  something  more  than  an  infinite  under- 
standing must  be  attributed  to  Him  as  principles  which 
influence  Him  in  His  government  of  the  world. 

Should  we  inquire  more  specifically  what  these  prin- 
ciples must  needs  be,  we  would  soon  come  to  the  con- 
clusion that  what  is  demanded  is  that  God  should  be 
an  ethical  as  well  as  intellectual  Being.  I  can  respect 
or  stand  in  awe  of  a  Being  whose  understanding  and 
whose  power  are  infinite,  but  I  cannot  love  a  God  who 
is  not  Love,  and  I  cannot  adore  a  Being  insensible  to 
considerations  of  such  vital  importance  to  me  as  good 
and  evil.  The  highest  demand  of  the  religious  mind  is 
that  its  God  should  be  an  ethical  Spirit ;  and  the  phil- 
osophical conception  of  Personality  requires  that  this 
concept  should  include  all  of  those  factors  which,  by 
reflective  thought  are  held  to  constitute  the  essential 
nature  of  the  human  mind.  It  is  impossible,  therefore, 
to  have  any  adequate  conception  of  Personality  with- 
out including  in  it,  as  one  of  its  most  essential  factors, 
a  supreme  regard  for  ethical  elements.  Hence  the  few 
remarks  made  concerning  good  and  evil  in  Chapters 
VII.  and  VIII.  of  the  Cogitata  Metaphystca  are  ex- 
tremely significant.  The  position  there  taken  helps  us 
to  understand  how  Spinoza  was  led  to  reject  the  more 


INTRODUCTION  li 

orthodox  conception  of  God  and  to  find  the  only  satis- 
factory Absolute  in  the  God  of  his  Pantheism.  By  this 
denial  of  the  ethical  attributes  of  God,  by  making  good 
and  evil  wholly  relative  to  human  thought  and  human 
desire,  all  moral  qualities  in  God  are  destroyed,  and 
we  have  then,  as  the  highest  determining  force  in  God's 
nature,  this  intellectual  understanding  of  cause  and  ef- 
fect which,  we  have  seen,  does  not  in  any  true  sense 
demand  that  He  should  be  a  personal  Being.  Hence, 
even  in  this  early  discussion  of  God,  we  find  the  way 
open  for  the  impersonal  Absolute,  which  is  the  basis  of 
Spinoza's  Pantheism.  We  have  given  here  a  thought, 
which  alone  logically  developed  and  its  implied  infer- 
ences regarded,  precludes  Theism,  and  consequently 
supports  the  conception  of  God  found  in  the  Ethics. 

The  full  import  of  what  has  just  been  said  concern- 
ing the  necessary  or  determined  character  of  God's  de- 
crees, and  the  consequent  impersonal  nature  of  the  Ab- 
solute escapes  us  unless  it  is  taken  in  connection  with 
the  deductive  character  of  Spinoza's  thought.  We 
have  already  shown  that  from  the  earliest  period  of  his 
reflection  Spinoza's  interest  centered  in  the  concept  of 
God.  Not,  however,  altogether  for  the  intrinsic  inter- 
est of  that  subject,  but  partly  as  the  starting  point  of 
his  constructive  system.  A  deductive  philosophy  re- 
quires as  its  starting  point  a  concept  which  includes  all 
that  is  to  appear  in  the  system.  But  why  or  how  ap- 
pear? From  logical  or  intellectual  necessity.  It  de- 
mands first  an  absolute  God.  And  if  the  system  is  log- 
ically carried  out  no  truth  will  be  recognized  which 
does  not  follow  in  this  necessary  way  from  the  prem- 
ises previously  laid  down.  If  the  premises  are  once 
fixed,  determined,  the  inferences  at  once  follow  by  in- 
tellectual necessity  and  are  as  necessary  as  the  princi- 


Hi  INTRODUCTION 

pies  from  which  they  are  deduced.  Thus  when  Spin- 
oza accepted  Deduction  as  the  great  Organon  of  truth 
and  the  geometrical  method  as  the  most  consistent 
method  of  presentation,  his  philosophy  is  at  once  strait- 
ened to  the  requirements  of  that  method.  As  the  con- 
clusions in  geometry  follow  from  a  logical  or  rational 
necessity,  so  nature  is  just  what  it  is  because  of  a 
similar  intellectual  necessity.  Spinoza  was  dominated 
through  and  through  with  this  deductive  nature  of 
thought  so  that  he  believed  it  was  the  image  of  reality. 
What  was  necessary  logically,  was  necessary  in  reality. 
To  follow  Spinoza  in  his  reasoning  this  truth  must  be 
always  kept  in  mind. 

Having  shown  how  the  conception  of  God  given  in 
the  "  Cogitata "  was  such  as  to  turn  Spinoza's  mind 
toward  Pantheism,  and  how  also  it  prepared  the  way 
for  the  impersonal  Absolute  of  that  system,  we  turn 
now  to  notice  some  of  the  more  particular  factors,  that 
had  part  in  this  result.  A  consideration  of  these  will 
further  show  us  how  Spinoza,  when  his  ideas  of  the 
absolute  supremacy  of  God  in  nature  had  made  im- 
possible his  acceptance  of  any  deistic  theory  of  God, 
turned  not  to  Theism  but  to  the  more  radical,  more 
materialistic  absolute  of  Pantheism. 

§  12.  Spinoza  seems  to  have  been  from  the  begin- 
ning a  rationalist.  The  universal  doubt  of  Descartes 
had  probably  some  influence  in  this  direction,  at  least 
so  far  as  to  make  Spinoza  wary  of  accepting  as  true 
that  which  could  not  be  supported  by  the  logic  on  which 
he  relied.  Deduction,  depending  as  it  does  not  upon 
empirical  verification  but  upon  rational  premises  and 
logical  inference,  prepares  the  way  for  the  rejection  of 
everything  that  does  not  admit  of  this  kind  of  proof. 
To  establish  the  truth  of  any  proposition,  therefore,  his 


INTRODUCTION  liii 

sole  reliance  was  upon  reason.  This  early  rationalism 
was  in  all  probability  the  immediate  cause  of  his  breach 
with  the  Jewish  synagogue.  In  the  "  Theologico-Po- 
litical  Treatise  '  written  only  a  few  years  after  the 
Principles  the  result  of  this  critical  spirit  is  manifest 
and  we  see  how  he  was  led  away  from  the  more  ortho- 
dox conception  of  God.  With  a  spirit  akin  to  the 
ultra  critical  spirit  of  our  present  day,  he  proceeds 
to  sift  all  the  claims  of  the  supernatural  in  the  Scrip- 
tures, and  in  the  end  rejects  everything  that  shows  the 
touch  of  a  hand  other  than  nature.  In  the  chapter 
on  miracles,  he  thus  states  his  purpose :  "  I  will  show," 
he  says, 

I.  '  That  nature  cannot  be  contravened,  but  that 
she  preserves  a  fixed  and  immutable  order,  and  at  the 
same  time  I  will  explain  what  is  meant  by  a  miracle. 

II.  c  That  God's  nature  and  existence,  and  conse- 
quently His  providence  cannot  be  known  from  mira- 
cles, but  that  they  can  all  be  much  better  perceived 
from  the  fixed  and  immutable  order  of  nature. 

III.  "  That  by  the  decrees  and  volitions,  and  conse- 
quently the  providence  of  God,  Scripture  (as  I  will 
prove  by  Scriptural  examples)  means  nothing  but  na- 
ture's order  following  necessarily  from  her  eternal 
laws."  1 

These  statements,  the  result  of  a  few  added  years  of 
reflection  upon  the  nature  of  God,  reveal  the  character 
of  Spinoza's  early  thought.  His  critical,  rationalistic 
mind  had  not  only  led  him  to  reject  the  Jewish  and  the 
Christian  doctrine  of  Inspiration  and  of  Miracles,  but 
had  now  caused  him  to  give  up  his  belief  in  a  personal 
God.  The  import  of  these  words  is  deep  and  unmis- 
takable.    There  is  a  complete  surrender  of  all  Liber- 

1  Spinoza's    Works,    Elwes'    Trans.,   p.   82. 


liv  INTRODUCTION 

tarianism  and  an  unqualified  acceptance  of  Determin- 
ism. His  early  anthropomorphic  conception  of  God 
was  now  supplanted  by  the  conception  that  appears 
later  in  the  Ethics.  God's  providence  and  care  appear 
not  in  special  manifestations  of  His  power,  but  in  the 
presence  of  universal,  invisible  laws.  The  very  per- 
sonal fact  of  a  special  display  of  wisdom  or  of  power,  is 
made  impossible  by  the  sway  of  principles  that  know 
no  exception  to  their  uniform  control.  All  things  are 
determined,  following  from  an  absolute  necessity. 
And  instead  of  a  God  whose  attitude  toward  men  and 
whose  character  permits  of  miraculous  expressions  of 
His  love  and  His  wisdom,  God  has  'become  a  being 
impossible  to  know  except  through  a  study  of  His 
eternal  decrees,  the  laws  of  Nature,  and  impossible  to 
love  except  with  a  purely  intellectual  love.  When 
Spinoza  published  this  Treatise,  therefore,  in  1670, 
but  seven  years  after  the  first  appearance  of  the  Prin- 
ciples, his  conception  of  God  and  of  God's  relation  to 
the  world  were  essentially  pantheistic. 

§  13.  Another  reason  why  Spinoza's  thought  turned 
not  to  Theism  but  to  Pantheism,  is  the  fact  that  Theism 
is  by  nature  idealistic,  while  Pantheism  is  half,  if  not 
entirely  materialistic.  Theism  regards  God  as  a  spirit- 
ual, personal  Being  immanent  in  nature  and  yet  tran- 
scending her  every  form.  While  every  object  and 
every  action  have  their  cause  in  God,  His  presence  is 
not  a  sensible  but  a  metaphysical  fact.  This  doctrine 
is  the  doctrine  of  mind  in  matter,  of  the  ideal  in  the 
real,  of  the  spiritual  in  the  corporeal.  It  is  evident  that 
we  have  come  face  to  face  with  the  great  problem 
which  Descartes  so  clearly  stated  for  subsequent  phil- 
osophy, the  relation  of  the  physical  and  the  psychical. 
In  order  to  effect  the  close  relation  between  God  and 


INTRODUCTION  lv 

the  world,  Pantheism  is  distinctly  opposed  to  the 
idealism  of  Theism.  It  is  impossible  to  assert  the 
primacy  of  spirit  and  remain  in  Pantheism.  On  the 
other  hand  this  doctrine  so  far  does  away  with  the  dis- 
tinction between  body  and  spirit  as  to  make  them  co- 
relative  attributes  of  one  and  the  same  substance,  name- 
ly God.  The  extended  world,  Pantheism  asserts,  is  as 
truly  and  as  essentially  a  part  of  God  as  the  world  of 
thought.  But  this  will  be  better  seen  if  we  turn  back 
for  a  few  minutes  to  see  the  condition  of  the  problem 
as  it  was  handed  down  to  Spinoza. 

Since  the  time  of  Descartes,  if  never  before,  one  of 
the  fundamental  problems  of  philosophy  has  been  to 
explain  the  relation  between  mind  and  matter.  Des- 
cartes stated  this  problem  so  clearly  that  those  who 
immediately  followed  him  had  their  whole  philosophy 
characterized  largely  by  the  position  they  held  upon 
this  subject.  How  are  mind  and  matter  related? 
How  do  they  react  upon  one  another  when  apparently 
there  are  no  grounds  of  inter-relation?  The  starting 
point  of  Descartes'  system,  his  Cogito  ergo  sum  is  the 
primal  truth  of  Epistemology  because  in  it  all  traces  of 
this  question  have  been  eliminated,  and  it  is  an  assertion 
that  applies  wholly  to  the  realm  of  thought.  This 
predication,  therefore,  was  untainted  by  any  of  the 
doubts  that  gather  round  the  still  unsolved  problem  of 
the  relation  between  the  psychical  and  the  physical. 
However,  the  whole  problem  of  philosophy  is  not  episte- 
mological,  but  there  are  metaphysical  problems  as  well. 
And  the  fact  that  by  eliminating  all  sensuous  elements 
Descartes  had  gained  a  foothold  on  Reality,  but  served 
to  emphasize  the  contrast  between  the  world  of  mind 
and  the  world  of  matter.  To  put  the  matter  succinctly, 
Descartes  found  an  antithesis  between  mind  and  matter 


lvi  INTRODUCTION 

which  came  to  be  not  only  a  fundamental  problem  in 
his  philosophy,  but  a  distinction  that  served  as  a 
ground  of  separation  for  those  who  immediately  fol- 
lowed him.  In  endeavoring  to  formulate  a  rational 
theory  concerning  the  relation  of  mind  and  matter  Des- 
cartes, Geulincx,  Malebranche,  and  Spinoza,  each  takes 
a  characteristic  position  which  is  the  key  to  his  system 
of  philosophy.  So  vital  did  this  point  continue  to  be 
after  Descartes  had  once  stated  it,  that  these  four  men 
gave  their  best  efforts  to  find  a  satisfactory  solution 
for  its  perplexities.  Descartes  taught  that  God  is  in- 
finite thought,  and  that  the  human  mind  participates  in 
His  absolute  character.  He  is  not,  however,  infinite 
extension  of  which  finite  objects  are  but  modes,  but  His 
essential  nature  is  mental,  not  corporeal.  Geulincx 
held  that  thought  and  extension  are  both  modes  of  two 
disparate  substances.  The  distinction  between  his  phil- 
osophy and  the  philosophy  of  Spinoza,  therefore,  lies 
in  the  fact  that  mind  and  matter  are  not  modifications 
of  the  same  substance  but  of  two  separate  substances. 
Malebranche  was  in  accord  with  Descartes  and  Geu- 
lincx so  far  as  to  affirm  that  bodies  are  modes  of  in- 
finite extension,  but  minds,  on  the  other  hand,  instead 
of  being  modes  of  infinite  thought,  have  a  substantial 
existence.1 

Spinoza,  too,  accepted  this  dualism  of  Descartes  as  a 
fundamental  philosophical  truth  and  embodied  it  as  one 
of  the  cardinal  principles  of  his  system.  One  of  his 
purposes  also  was  to  find  a  theory  of  Reality  that 
would  explain  the  interaction  of  such  disparate  sub- 
stances as  mind  and  matter.  He  recognized  a  world 
of  mental  phenomena  and  an  extended  world.  His  ex- 
planation of  their  interaction,  however,  was  not  that 

1  Cf.  Erdmann's  History  of  Phil.,  Vol.  TI,  p.  31. 


INTRODUCTION  lvfi 

of  any  of  the  three  men  whose  position  we  have  just 
stated.  Neither  Descartes,  who  was  in  this  an  idealist, 
nor  Geulincx,  nor  Malebranche,  dared  to  maintain  an 
equality  of  importance  between  these  two  aspects  of 
substance,  but  primacy  was  with  them  uniformly 
ascribed  to  mind.  Spinoza,  of  them  all,  maintained 
that  thought  and  extension  are  two  correlated  attri- 
butes of  one  and  the  same  infinite  substance,  *.  e., 
God.  His  position  upon  this  point,  the  solution  of 
Cartesian  Dualism  by  thus  making  mind  and  matter 
not  two  substances  but  two  attributes  of  one  substance, 
not  only  differentiates  his  philosophy  from  that  of  the 
men  whose  position  we  have  noted,  but  it  states  a  fun- 
damental truth  of  Pantheism.  While  the  others,  as  we 
have  already  seen,  one  in  one  way,  one  in  another,  at- 
tributed a  certain  primacy  to  mind,  Spinoza  boldly  cor- 
relates these  two  worlds  and  makes  them  equally  an 
expression  of  the  power  and  presence  of  the  one  abso- 
lute God.  With  him  the  physical  world  is  just  as  truly 
and  just  as  profoundly  a  manifestation  of  God's  being 
as  the  most  idealistic  principles  of  the  rational  world. 
There  is  but  one  true  Substance,  whose  attributes  as 
modes  are  thought  and  extension.  The  former  attri- 
bute is  no  more  essential  to  God's  being  than  the  latter, 
for  both  are  infinite  attributes  and  both  express  funda- 
mental truth  concerning  His  nature.  Spinoza's  ex- 
planation of  Cartesian  Dualism,  therefore,  was  a  direct 
step  toward  Pantheism.  He  accepts  the  distinction  but 
interprets  it  so  that  it  harmonizes  perfectly  with  the 
demands  of  the  logic  he  had  already  adopted,  and  with 
his  belief  concerning  the  supreme  importance  of  the 
concept  of  God.  Thus  Spinoza  accepted  the  only  ex- 
planation of  the  Cartesian  Dualism  that  would  make 
his    Pantheism    possible.     The    supremacy    of    mind 


lviii  INTRODUCTION 

over  matter  means  some  form  of  Deism  or  Theism. 
The  primacy  of  matter  means  Materialism.  The  cor- 
relation of  the  two  as  attributes  or  modes  of  one  Sub- 
stance is  Pantheism. 

Thus  while  Descartes  established  the  basis  for  a 
sound  Epistemology,  his  Dualism,  the  antithesis  be- 
tween thought  and  extension,  opened  the  way  for 
Pantheism  or  even  for  Materialism.  Of  course  these 
beliefs  were  never  favored  in  his  own  mind,  but  the 
metaphysical  principles  involved,  variously  interpreted, 
did  lead  to  these  more  radical  conceptions  of  Reality. 
Had  Spinoza  merely  reversed  the  assertion  of  his  pred- 
ecessors and  affirmed  that  not  mind  but  matter  is  the 
cause  of  all  phenomena,  he  would  have  become  a 
materialist.  But  this  he  could  not  do ;  he  was  too  firm 
a  believer  in  the  substantial  nature  of  thought,  and  in 
the  power  of  logic,  to  ever  make  this  of  secondary  im- 
portance. On  the  other  hand  this  supreme  confidence 
in  reason,  this  natural  inclination  toward  rationalism, 
led  him  to  deny  all  manifestations  of  supernatural 
power,  and  to  rely  exclusively  upon  the  natural 
sequence  of  events  for  all  knowledge  of  God's  nature 
and  of  His  decrees.  Nature,  therefore,  in  all  her 
physical  forms,  and  especially  in  her  laws,  becomes  a 
matter  of  the  highest  importance  to  philosophy. 
Spinoza,  therefore,  influenced  on  the  one  hand  by  his 
belief  in  the  absolute  character  of  logic,  and  on  the 
other  by  his  belief  in  the  uniformity  of  natural 
sequence,  could  affirm  the  primacy  of  neither  mind  nor 
matter,  but  must  make  them  necessarily  correlated 
forms  of  Reality.  The  person  who  refuses,  as  Spinoza 
did,  all  miraculous  expressions  of  divine  power  as 
highly  improbable  if  not  actually  impossible,  must  sup- 
port his  philosophy  by  showing  some  very  close  con- 


INTRODUCTION  lix 

nection  between  physical  phenomena  and  God.  For 
this,  the  rather  artificial  explanation  of  Deism  will  not 
suffice.  But,  on  the  other  hand,  the  person  who 
accepts  the  invariable  sequence  of  nature  without  pos- 
sibility of  intervention  by  any  cause  whatever,  as  the 
fundamental  postulate  of  philosophy,  must  deny  the 
ideality  of  God's  being  as  it  is  represented  in  Theism. 
For  in  whatever  form  antitheistic  theories  may  appear 
in  the  last  analysis  they  will  be  found  to  base  their 
argument  upon  this  unyielding  sequence  in  the  natural 
world,  upon  the  necessity  of  all  physical  acts.  So  it 
has  always  been,  and  so  it  will  doubtless  remain. 
Hence,  because  Spinoza  could  not  accept  exclusively 
either  the  interpretation  of  Theism  or  of  Materialism, 
he  could  do  nothing  else  than  combine  the  essential 
features  of  both  in  his  theory  of  a  pantheistic  Ontology. 
§14.  We  have  found  in  our  investigation,  therefore, 
three  factors  which  have  concurred  to  turn  Spinoza's 
thought  from  a  deistic  conception  of  God  to  Pantheism. 
.No  one  of  them  alone,  perhaps,  would  have  been  suf- 
ficient to  produce  his  radical  departure  from  the 
philosophy  of  his  time ;  but  the  three  taken  together 
with  cumulative  force  make  any  other  cosmic  theory 
than  Pantheism  almost  impossible.  He  gave  as  we 
have  seen  an  unqualified  allegiance  to  the  old  Aris- 
totelian Logic,  as  the  true  Organon  of  truth.  Deduc- 
tion is  the  only  true  method  of  determining  truth. 
Some  concept  must  needs  be  found,  therefore,  which 
connects  all  being.  Since  from  it  all  things  are  to  be 
deduced,  in  it  all  things  must  be  contained.  Such  a 
concept  as  this  Spinoza  found  in  his  pantheistic  con- 
cept of  God.  Far  from  being  criticised  for  his  attempt 
to  find  one  idea  in  which  the  whole  world  is  contained, 
he  deserves  praise  for  the  clear  insight  into  the  demands 


Ix  INTRODUCTION 

of  this  method  and  for  his  attempt  to  satisfy  them. 
If  criticised  at  all  it  should  be  for  the  vanity  of  his 
attempt  and  for  the  failure  to  see  the  value  of  the 
Novum  Organum  which  for  forty  years  had  been  be- 
fore the  world.  Deduction  demanded  this  concept  of 
God,  not  as  its  goal,  but  as  the  very  starting  point  of  its 
functioning,  the  postulate  of  its  truth.  And  in  no 
small  degree  Spinoza  by  the  iron-bound  apodeictic  char- 
acter of  this  logic,  was  led  to  a  belief  in  a  God  of  sim- 
ilar character.  As  induction  permeates  and  influences 
all  our  ideas  to-day,  so  deduction  then  cast  its  influence 
over  every  concept  of  philosophy. 

The  second  point  we  have  noted  in  our  discussion 
which  gave  shape  to  Spinoza's  thought  is  this  concept 
of  God.  So  close  is  the  connection  between  deduction 
and  this  idea  that  it  is  almost  impossible  to  conceive 
of  the  former,  when  it  is  to  be  used  to  establish  a 
philosophic  system,  without  the  latter.  In  this  con- 
nection they  are  true  complements  of  one  another.  We 
have  already  seen  that  this  idea  of  God,  was  historic- 
ally considered  a  fundamental  idea  in  Spinoza's  reflec- 
tion ;  we  can  now  see  that  it  was  made  so  necessarily 
by  his  close  allegiance  to  deduction  and  by  his  strict 
conformity  to  scholastic  logic.  This  concept  of  God, 
however,  was  not  discovered  out  of  hand,  ready- 
made,  but  was  the  product  of  years  of  careful 
thought,  and  of  definite,  though  little  investigated 
causes.  Logically  this  concept  was  prior  to  Pantheism 
as  a  system,  and  largely  determined  just  what  the 
main  tenets  of  that  philosophy  must  be.  To  under- 
stand fully  just  what  Pantheism  is,  therefore,  we 
have  had  recourse  to  the  historical  development  of 
the  idea  of  God,  and  sought  to  show  how  certain 
ideas   in   the   more   orthodox   conception,    with   but   a 


INTRODUCTION  lxi 

slight  modification  may  become  quite  pantheistic. 
God's  absolute  power  makes  Him  the  sole  cause  of  all 
being,  and  the  absolute  character  of  His  decrees  is 
Determinism.  So  absolute  is  the  character  of  God, 
and  so  vital  the  connection  between  His  being,  and 
the  existence  and  essence  of  all  objects  that  Deism  is 
at  once  declared  insufficient.  Since  in  effect  the 
world  is  created  anew  every  moment,  God's  presence 
and  His  power  in  nature  must  be  as  real  as  the  objects 
themselves.  It  is  not  so,  however,  according  to  the 
deistic  hypothesis,  so  that  theory  of  God's  being  is  at 
once  rejected,  and  Theism,  Materialism  or  Panthe- 
ism must  be  the  true  conception  of  His  being. 

It  was  just  at  this  critical  point,  when  Spinoza's 
beliefs  were  in  the  plastic  state,  that  the  influence  of 
Descartes'  philosophy  came  in  to  give  them  definite 
character  and  to  throw  his  mind  irrevocably  toward 
Pantheism.  This  effect  is,  as  we  have  suggested, 
prepared  for  by  his  rationalism,  and  yet  this  alone 
might  as  well  have  led  to  Materialism  as  to  Theism. 
But  as  the  Dualism  of  Descartes  was  interpreted  and 
explained  by  Spinoza,  there  was  no  other  concept  of 
God  that  could  so  well  satisfy  the  logical  demands  of 
this  explanation  as  Pantheism.  Spinoza  retained  the 
dualistic  distinction  of  Descartes  and  this  made 
urgent  some  theory  that  would  recognize  the  rights 
of  both  of  these  phases  of  reality.  Since  from  the 
rationalistic  character  of  his  early  thought  Spinoza 
was  led  to  reject  all  supernatural  expressions  of  God's 
power,  he  could  find  the  power  of  God  only  in  the 
laws  of  nature.  God  is  present  in  every  form  of  the 
objective  world,  and  not  one  change  can  be  found  in 
nature  that  is  not  determined  by  His  eternal  decrees. 
This   is   but   another   way   to   say   that    Spinoza   was 


Ixii  INTRODUCTION 

through  and  through  a  strict  determinist.  But  the 
root  of  Determinism  is  found  in  the  observed  sequence 
of  physical  change  and  in  the  belief  in  the  inviolable 
character  of  nature's  laws.  Our  knowledge  of  the 
Absolute,  therefore,  he  would  maintain,  cannot  rest 
upon  miraculous  manifestations  of  God's  power,  but 
must  be  gained  through  an  investigation  of  the  laws 
that  are  uniformly  governing  the  natural  world. 
God  is  revealed  in  every  object  and  in  every  act  of 
nature,  not  merely  in  special  cases  when  the  laws  of 
the  physical  world  seem  to  be  controverted  and  for 
the  time  of  none  effect.  If  we  would  know  the  nature 
of  God,  therefore,  we  must  turn  to  the  laws  of  the 
physical  and  the  mental  world  and  find  there  an  ex- 
pression of  His  wisdom  and  His  power.  There  is 
more  truth,  he  would  say,  revealed  concerning  the 
nature  of  God  in  the  law  of  gravitation  than  in  any 
special  manifestation  of  His  presence  in  which  men 
have  ever  believed.  And  so  far  as  mere  intelligence 
is  concerned  he  would  unquestionably  be  correct.  If 
we  would  know  of  God's  wisdom  and  of  His  power 
and  of  His  decrees  we  must  study  the  works  of  His 
creation ;  these  are  the  visible,  the  tangible  expression 
of  the  wisdom  and  the  power  we  seek.  Such  are  the 
claims  of  the  natural  world ;  a  world  where  physical 
law  stands  thus  far  upon  an  equality  with  the  laws  of 
thought.  While  they  are  not  strong  enough  to  estab- 
lish a  materialistic  conception  of  God,  they  are  far 
too  cogent  to  be  ignored  or  made  of  little  effect.  Ma- 
terialism would  in  many  respects  fulfill  most  perfectly 
the  demands  of  these  considerations.  For  not  only 
does  it  recognize  these  laws  of  the  physical  world  as 
the  direct  expression  of  the  Absolute,  but  it  affirms 
that  they  are  the  one  source  of  all.     This,  however, 


INTRODUCTION  lxiii 

was  further  than  Spinoza  could  go ;  he  could  not  sub- 
scribe to  this  and  retain  his  belief  in  the  Dualism 
which  Descartes  had  so  clearly  established.  Instead 
of  mind  being  merely  an  epiphenomenon  of  matter  as 
Materialism  affirms,  Descartes  and  Spinoza  both  held 
that  it  is  one  of  the  attributes  of  Substance.  Material- 
ism expressed  but  one  phase  of  the  truth.  Substance 
is  not  merely  Extension,  but  Thought  as  well.  All 
that  was  essential  in  Materialism  Spinoza  found  as 
well  provided  for  in  Pantheism.  And  the  idealism  of 
Theism,  the  spiritual  nature  of  God,  is  also  included 
in  this  pantheistic  concept.  Thus  the  Dualism  of 
Nature  is  maintained,  although  as  Deduction  demands, 
and  as  the  logical  requirements  of  thought  importune, 
the  absolute  unity  of  Nature  is  provided  for.  Mind 
and  matter  are  two  attributes  of  the  same  Substance, 
namely  God.  Pantheism  alone  of  all  philosophies  can 
maintain  this  literal  unity  and  still  recognize  this 
duality. 

§  15.  It  is  time  that  we  attempt  now,  in  concluding 
our  argument,  to  gather  up  the  threads  to  see  whether 
when  woven  together  they  support  our  contention,  and 
help  to  make  clear  Spinoza's  Pantheism.  Was  this 
philosophy  a  true  development  somewhat  sporadic  per- 
haps but  still  a  development  from  definite,  definable 
antecedents,  or  did  it  Pallas-like  spring  from  the 
troubled  brain  of  Spinoza  fully  ordered  and  complete? 
If  the  latter  our  work  has  been  useless  and  we  should 
commend  students  of  Spinoza  to  a  study  of  his  Ethics 
alone.  But  if  it  is  a  development,  a  logical  growth 
from  premises  Spinoza  did  not  formulate  and  from 
personal  factors  not  wholly  under  his  control  then  we 
can  still  affirm  however  inadequate  our  analysis  has 
been,  that  some  such  method  as  this  is  essential  for  a 


lxiv  INTRODUCTION 

sympathetic  or  even  for  a  just  appreciation  of 
Spinoza's  philosophy. 

In  the  first  place  we  undertook  to  show  that  the 
geometrical  method,  first  used  in  the  work  that  has 
called  for  this  discussion,  was  not  considered  an  in- 
fallible method  of  argumentation.  It  does  not  follow 
that  everything  that  can  be  put  in  mathematical 
form  is  true.  But  Spinoza  believed,  and  here  we  get 
to  the  root  of  the  matter,  that  all  logical  thought  and 
all  proof  is  identical  in  character  to  the  mental 
processes  of  geometry.  It  follows,  therefore,  that  the 
most  logical  presentation  of  truth  will  be  the  accepted 
presentation  of  geometry.  But  the  truth  of  geometry 
does  not  depend  upon  this  form,  it  is  used  merely 
because  of  its  logical  consistency.  So  the  geometrical 
method  as  used  in  the  Ethics  does  not  insure  certainty 
of  argument ;  it  is  used  simply  because  of  its  peda- 
gogical soundness,  just  as  some  use  the  Socratic,  some 
the  kindergarten  method.  They  seem  to  be  justified 
by  the  general  character  of  the  processes  of  thought. 

The  second  point  was  the  extremely  broad,  the 
extremely  important  idea  of  God.  Here  we  have  en- 
deavored to  show  how  Spinoza's  peculiar  ideas  de- 
veloped more  or  less  logically  from  causes  easily 
ascertainable  but  not  on  that  account  less  potent.  His 
first  idea  of  God  was  the  Jewish  conception,  the  ordi- 
nary Deism  of  Scholasticism.  But  there  was  in 
Spinoza  beside  this  deep  never  dying  interest  in  this 
idea  of  God,  what  we  have  called  a  rationalistic  ele- 
ment, that  soon  led  him  to  reject  not  only  the  Jewish 
conception  of  Jehovah  but  also  the  deistic  conception 
of  mediaeval  philosophy. 

But  underneath  all  this,  as  the  ultimate  source  of  his 
heresy,  the  real  cause  of  his  heterodoxy  was  his  un- 


INTRODUCTION  lxv 

shaken  faith  in  Deduction  as  the  true  method  of  proof 
and  the  right  method  of  thought.  His  fault,  if  fault 
it  was,  was  that  he  accepted  completely  the  logic  of 
his  times ;  his  sin  if  sin  it  was,  was  that  he  carried  out 
more  logically  than  had  ever  been  done  before  the 
principles  of  this  logic,  never  hesitating  to  draw  his 
conclusions,  never  blanching  at  the  outcome.  Even 
if  his  system  is  doomed  to  philosophical  disapproba- 
tion the  man  himself  stands  out  a  hero  in  intellectual 
prowess  and  in  his  devotion  to  the  truth.  He  was  not 
simply  a  disciple  of  deductive  reasoning  but  by  his 
logical  consistency,  by  carrying  out  the  principles  of 
such  thought  as  they  had  never  been  carried  out  before, 
by  a  devotion  to  the  syllogism  that  never  faltered  from 
fear  nor  weakened  in  warmth,  he  deserves  the  title, 
the  saint  of  Deduction. 

The  next  problem  to  which  we  directed  our  atten- 
tion was  to  show  that  the  fundamental  tenets  of  Pan- 
theism are  the  logical  outcome  of  the  principles  that 
underlie  Spinoza's  thought.  The  two  points  we 
singled  out  for  special  remark  were  the  impersonal 
character  of  the  Absolute  and  the  Determinism  which 
stands  over  all  things.  So  absolute  is  the  conception 
of  God  which  a  consistent  Deduction  demands  that 
all  His  ethical  attributes  are  lost  sight  of  in  the  su- 
perior importance  (superior  from  the  logical  stand- 
point) of  the  more  dynamic  attributes  of  cause  and 
effect,  and  logical  coherency.  The  concept  of  God, 
the  ultimate  source  of  the  world  of  experience,  does 
not  contain  in  any  available  form  the  idea  of  free 
finite  wills,  so  the  essential  idea  of  personality  is  de- 
stroyed. But  on  the  other  hand  the  demands  of  strict 
logic  such  as  Spinoza  used,  necessitate  a  Determinism 
just  as  universal,  just  as  invariable  as  the  Determin- 


Ixvi  INTRODUCTION 

ism  of  the  Ethics.  When  we  sought  for  the  character 
of  this  Determinism  we  saw  that  it  could  not  be  an 
external  force,  or  hypostasized  necessity,  but  must, 
therefore,  arise  from  the  attribute  of  God  Himself. 
Physical  necessity  it  could  not  be,  and  moral  necessity 
God  does  not  know,  hence  it  could  only  be  the  logical 
necessity  of  self  expression.  Thus  we  have  bridged 
over  as  it  seemed  to  us  the  gap  between  Spinoza's 
thought  and  the  current  philosophy  of  his  time,  at  least 
far  enough  to  see  that  his  Pantheism  has  its  roots 
deeply  seated  in  the  thought  of  preceding  years,  and 
needs  this  connection  clearly  pointed  out  for  an  ade- 
quate appreciation  of  the  obscure  points  in  this  system. 
The  definitions  are  clearer  and  richer,  his  ideas  more 
easily  understood,  and  their  arrangement  more  logical 
than  if  we  study  the  system  merely  content-wise. 
The  sources  of  strength  and  the  causes  of  error,  when 
the  system  is  thus  envisaged,  both  stand  out  in  clearer 
perspective,  and  with  a  different  emphasis,  than  if  in- 
vestigated in  the  usual  way.  In  conclusion  we  shall 
pause  to  point  out  some  of  the  points  of  weakness  and 
some  of  the  profound  truth  to  which  this  historical 
method  calls  special  attention. 

§  1 6.  Turning  first  to  the  weaknesses  to  which  this 
genetic  study  specially  directs  our  thought  we  find 
them  to  cluster  around  the  term  Deduction.  This  we 
have  seen  above  is  the  great  underlying  principle,  the 
true  cause  of  the  use  of  the  geometrical  method,  and 
inferentially  implies  if  it  does  not  absolutely  demand 
a  determined  sequence  of  events  in  nature.  More 
than  any  one  thing,  therefore,  this  word  exposes  and 
explains  the  vulnerable  points  of  Spinoza's  Pantheism. 
His  purpose,  which  he  in  large  measure  accomplished, 
was  to  remain   always  true  to  the  principles  of  De- 


INTRODUCTION  lxvii 

duction.  And  his  close  adherence  to  this  kind  of  logic, 
and  to  the  scholastic  idea  of  truth  and  valid  proof 
led  him  to  embrace  in  his  system  much  that  is  artificial 
and  unreal.  The  particular  tenets  that  have  excited  the 
vituperative  and  cutting  criticism  of  his  opponents 
very  largely  arose  from  this  cause.  The  reasons  for 
this  are  not  hard  to  see :  in  the  first  place  Deduction 
if  logically  carried  out  sets  before  philosophy  an  ideal 
which  is  by  nature  impossible  for  finite  intelligence. 
The  human  mind  cannot  formulate  a  system  a  priori 
which  must  be  true.  Human  reason  even  in  its  most 
absolute  claims  cannot  thus  set  the  bounds  of  Reality. 
However  true  it  may  be  that  there  is  "  logic  in  nature/' 
and  that  the  world  is  "  hung  on  principles,"  this  does 
not  guarantee  that  what  is  clearly  conceived  must  be 
true.  To  assert  this  is  to  claim  for  the  human  mind 
creative  power.  The  bare  logical  necessities  of 
thought  are  too  abstract,  too  general  to  serve  as  a  cer- 
tain basis  upon  which  to  construct  a  theory  of  Reality. 
Dialectics  as  a  method  of  system  building  always  leads 
to  hopeless  confusion  and  to  contradiction  of  empir- 
ical truth.  Of  this  truth  the  history  of  thought  fur- 
nishes abundant  illustration.  On  the  other  hand 
there  are  certain  questions,  which,  while  they  are 
known  only  too  well,  cannot  be  explained  satisfactorily 
to  reason.  Such  for  example  are  the  problems  of  Evil 
and  of  Freedom.  Before  these  questions  the  human 
mind  realizes  its  impotency  and  stands  humbly  before 
that  which  transcends  its  mightiest  endeavors. 

§  17.  Spinoza's  position  upon  these  two  questions, 
the  problem  of  evil  and  the  problem  of  human  free- 
dom, was  profoundly  influenced  if  it  was  not  wholly 
determined  by  the  deductive  character  of  the  time  in 
which  he  lived.     As  we  have  already  shown,  Deduc- 


lxviii  INTRODUCTION 

tion  demands,  as  its  starting  point,  a  concept  that 
includes  in  itself  a  complete  system  of  thought. 
Nothing  can  logically  be  deduced  which  is  not  poten- 
tially contained.  And  truth  is  established  when  it  is 
shown  that  the  given  proposition  follows  logically 
from  the  premises  previously  laid  down.  Spinoza 
with  his  idea  of  one,  perfectly  absolute  God  could  not 
reconcile  with  this  concept,  either  the  current  concep- 
tion of  evil,  or  of  human  freedom.  If  God  is  abso- 
lute, and  if  everything  is  determined  by  His  under- 
standing and  His  will,  then  good  and  evil  are  alike 
expressions  of  His  wisdom  and  His  power.  What 
we  know  as  evil  is  just  as  truly  an  expression  of  God's 
will  as  that  which  we  regard  as  good.  Reasoned  out 
in  this  way,  beginning  not  with  the  facts  of  experience 
but  with  the  idea  of  an  absolute  God,  and  establishing 
each  proposition  by  deductive  proof,  there  is  little 
chance  to  come  to  any  other  conception  concerning 
the  true  character  of  evil.  If  evil  as  well  as  good 
exists  by  God's  concurrence  and  by  express  decrees  of 
His  will,  the  ontological  basis  for  a  distinction  be- 
tween them  is  destroyed,  and  their  relativity  to  human 
thought  it  established.  But  if  it  be  true  that  God  has 
no  regard  for  ethical  distinctions  He  is  not  an  ethical 
being.  In  this  way  we  find  the  significance  of  Panthe- 
ism as  a  religion  reduced  to  a  minimum,  and  its  logical 
superiority  its  sole  claim  to  consideration. 

§  1 8.  Spinoza's  Determinism,  also,  was  made  neces- 
sary by  his  strict  adherence  to  the  deductive  method  of 
his  time.  Induction  begins  with  isolated  facts,  and 
theoretically,  at  least,  with  no  preconceived  theory  to 
account  for  them.  The  mind  is  as  open  to  one  conclu- 
sion as  to  another.  It  is  in  this  way,  as  Positivism 
affirms,   that   we   may   establish    a   system    of   certain 


INTRODUCTION  lxix 

truth,  and  free  ourselves  from  all  prejudices  and  as- 
sumptions. But  with  Deduction,  especially  when  such 
demands  are  made  upon  it  as  must  be  made  for  the 
accomplishment  of  the  purpose  to  which  Spinoza  set 
himself,  we  must  postulate  that  nature  and  thought 
are  in  the  closest  allegiance  with  one  another.  It  is 
absolutely  required  before  we  begin,  that  we  believe 
that  "  what  is  clearly  and  distinctly  conceived  is  true." 
It  were  folly  to  construct  a  system  of  thought,  and 
to  assert  that  this  is  an  explanation  of  experience 
unless,  in  some  way,  we  are  confident  that  our  system 
constructed  upon  logic,  is  a  faithful  presentation  of 
the  actual  facts  in  nature.  Thus,  while  from  the 
standpoint  of  Epistemology  there  is  no  incompatibility 
between  Induction  and  Determinism,  in  Deduction 
there  is  an  implicit  demand  for  that  fixed  sequence 
in  nature  which  is  the  ground  of  all  deterministic  phi- 
losophy. Unless  Nature  is  herself  logical  it  is  useless 
to  offer  a  logical  explanation  of  her  phenomena.  If 
Deduction  is  to  be  the  measure  of  truth  it  is  imperative 
that  nature  should  be  a  closed  series  with  no  possible 
intervention  from  without.  This  Spinoza  provided 
for  by  the  absolute  nature  which  he  ascribed  to  God. 
In  every  change  in  the  physical  world  no  matter  how 
trivial  or  apparently  commonplace,  and  in  every 
thought  and  deed  of  men,  whatever  its  ethical  nature, 
God's  hand  is  seen  supreme ;  they  are  both  what  they 
are  solely  by  His  will  and  through  His  power.  Thus, 
in  nature  as  Deduction  would  envisage  it,  there  is  no 
place  left  for  human  Freedom.  To  leave  anything  to 
the  arbitrament  of  the  human  will,  as  irrational  and  as 
wilful  as  it  often  is,  is  to  introduce  into  the  world 
causes  whose  effects  if  not  counterbalanced  might 
wreck  the  universe. 


lxx  INTRODUCTION 

Beside  this,  Freedom  is  not  primarily  a  rational  in- 
ference, but  a  datum  of  experience.  We  do  not  reason 
ourselves  into  a  belief  in  this  attribute  of  the  human 
mind,  but  we  experience  it  in  the  constant  selection  of 
elements  in  our  intellectual  processes  as  well  as  in  the 
more  debated  field  of  moral  choice.  The  man  who 
takes  life  as  it  comes  with  but  little  reflection  upon 
his  experience  accepts  the  postulate  of  moral  Freedom 
as  he  accepts  the  fact  that  he  can  think  of  this  thing 
or  of  that,  or  that  he  can  go  to  his  usual  work  to-day 
or  remain  at  home.  The  reason  that  Freedom  vs. 
Determinism  has  been,  throughout  the  history  of  re- 
flective thought,  one  of  the  most  debated  of  questions, 
and  the  question  on  which  the  final  word  has  never 
been  said,  is  not  alone  because  it  is  of  such  importance 
for  morality,  but  because  it  is  also  a  question  that  im- 
plicates the  whole  problem  of  empirical  and  a  priori 
factors  in  experience.  This  does  not  mean,  however, 
that  there  is  a  necessary  opposition  or  incompatibility 
between  them,  but  it  does  imply  that  before  the  prob- 
lem of  Freedom  can  be  solved  we  must  find  some 
satisfactory  hypothesis  concerning  the  relation  of  em- 
pirical and  a  priori  elements  in  experience.  Spinoza 
not  appreciating  the  force  of  empirical  facts,  but  seek- 
ing constantly  for  the  ignis  fatuus  of  deductive  proof, 
would  not  accept  this  testimony  of  consciousness,  un- 
less it  were  confirmed  in  the  manner  he  thought  neces- 
sary. But  thus  envisaged  there  was  but  one  solution 
of  the  problem.  Beginning  as  he  did  with  the  abso- 
lute character  of  God  as  the  postulate  of  further  reflec- 
tion, he  could  not  bridge  over  the  chasm  to  freedom  in 
the  human  mind.  Indeed,  when  the  question  was  con- 
sidered in  the  light  in  which  he  saw  it  there  was  little 
desirability  and  no  imperative  need  that  man  should 


INTRODUCTION  lxxi 

be  free.  Determinism  unifies  the  world  better,  it  helps 
us  to  believe  in  the  power  of  logic  more,  and  it  pre- 
pares the  way  for  a  deductive  philosophy  more  directly 
than  to  grant  to  finite  beings  this  attribute  of  infinity. 
Hence,  we  see  that  the  two  points  most  criticised  in 
Spinoza's  Ethics,  his  doctrine  of  evil  and  the  fatalistic 
Determinism  that  he  championed,  have  their  origin  in 
the  deductive  logic  which  he  accepted  as  the  true 
Organon  of  truth,  and  which  he  upheld,  be  it  said  to 
his  credit,  in  such  a  strict  consistent  way.  We  have 
already  spoken  of  the  geometrical  method  which 
Spinoza  used  and  shown  how  it,  too,  was  used  in  the 
interest  of  Deduction.  We  only  name  it  again  to  call 
attention  to  the  fact  that  so  far  as  it  was  the  result 
of  this  way  of  considering  truth  its  weaknesses,  too, 
arose  from  this  same  source  of  error  that  we  have 
found  at  the  root  of  the  two  concepts  just  discussed. 

§  19.  Turning  now  from  the  weaknesses  to  which 
our  historical  study  of  Spinoza  has  called  special  atten- 
tion, we  pass  on  to  consider  some  of  the  significant 
truths  that  are  found  when  his  system  is  thus  envis- 
aged. And  first,  we  shall  raise  the  question  whether 
Kant  himself  may  not  have  been  influenced  by  this 
early  work  of  Spinoza.  In  the  first  part  of  the 
Cogitata  Metaphysica  there  are  some  distinctions 
clearly  made  of  such  a  character  that  it  leads  us  to 
ask  whether  it  is  not  probable  that  Kant  had  read 
this  essay  and  received  from  it  suggestions  for  his 
Transcendental  Philosophy.  While  there  is  no  direct 
or  positive  evidence  that  such  is  the  case,  some  of  the 
positions  which  Spinoza  here  maintains  are  so  palp- 
ably the  logical  antecedents  of  the  Kantian  Transcen- 
dentalism that  they  awaken  interest  in  the  question, 
and  provoke  a  further  inquiry  into  the  justice  of  the 


lxxii  INTRODUCTION 

comparison.  It  may  be  worth  our  while,  therefore, 
to  point  out  the  main  points  of  similarity  between 
these  two  men,  in  almost  every  point  so  dissimilar  to 
one  another. 

Spinoza  begins  this  essay,  the  Cogitata,  by  a  chapter 
in  which  he  seeks  to  make  clear  the  difference  between 
real  being  (ens  reale) ,  fictitious  being  (ens  Hctuin), 
and  being  of  the  reason  (ens  rationis)}  Being  is  de- 
fined as  "  all  that  which,  when  it  is  clearly  and  dis- 
tinctly conceived,  we  find  to  exist  or  at  least  to  be  able 
to  exist."  Under  this  definition  chimera,  fictitious 
being,  and  being  of  reason  are  not  real.  Being  of 
reason  is  "nothing  but  a  mode  of  thinking  which  is 
of  service  in  retaining,  or  explaining,  or  in  imaging 
out  ideas."  To  enable  us  to  retain  our  ideas  we  have 
such  terms  or  beings  of  reason  as  genus,  species,  etc. ; 
for  explaining  our  ideas  we  have  time,  number,  meas- 
ure, and  others ;  those  that  help  us  to  image  out  our 
ideas  are  such  terms  of  negation  as  blindness,  extrem- 
ity, limit,  shades,  etc. 

But  before  we  affirm  a  similarity  between  these 
terms  and  the  transcendental  elements  of  the  "  Aes- 
thetic "  and  of  the  "  Analytic,"  it  will  be  well  to  see 
just  how  closely  these  modes  of  thinking  correspond 
to  the  a  priori  elements  in  the  Kantian  philosophy. 
The  distinction  which  Kant  made  in  the  elements  of 
phenomena  was  between  its  matter,  that  part  which 
comes  through  the  senses,  and  its  form,  that  part 
which  causes  the  manifold  of  empirical  elements  to 
be  perceived  in  a  certain  order.  The  matter  of  any 
phenomenon  is  given  a  posteriori,  but  its  form  is 
a  priori.     Kant  recognized  these  two  elements  in  every 

1This    last    is    a    somewhat    awkward    phrase,    but    rational 
being,  the  only  smooth   translation,  would  he  ambiguous. 


INTRODUCTION  Ixxiii 

phenomenon,  the  empirical  factors  derived  from  ex- 
tramental  objects  through  the  mind's  sensibility,  and 
the  subjective  factors  that  make  experience  possible 
by  referring  this  manifold  of  sense  to  these  forms  of 
thought.  Spinoza's  terminology  was  widely  different; 
that  which  comes  from  the  external  world  he  calls 
real,  that  which  the  mind  creates  in  order  to  further 
its  intellectual  demands  is  called  modes  of  thinking 
{modi  cogitandi).  Spinoza  did  not  analyse  this  dis- 
tinction at  all,  but  he  did  set  forth  the  distinction  upon 
which  Kant  later  founded  his  system  of  Transcen- 
dentalism. Spinoza  did  not  even  use  this  distinction 
in  his  later  thought,  but  in  the  Cogitata  it  is  found,  a 
vein  just  noted  and  then  neglected  until  it  was  redis- 
covered by  Kant  and  astonished  the  whole  philosophic 
world  by  the  wealth  its  working  revealed.  All  that 
we  desire  to  do  is  to  show  that  Spinoza  recognized  the 
fact  that  there  are  certain  fundamental  ideas  derived 
not  from  the  external  world  but  forms  of  the  mind's 
own  making.  But  even  this  would  not  be  worth  men- 
tion were  it  not  for  the  further  significant  fact  that 
there  is  apparently  more  than  an  accidental  coincidence 
between  the  particular  ideas  Spinoza  thus  enumerates 
and  the  Kantian  categories. 

The  first  object  to  which  Kant  addresses  himself  in 
the  "  Critique  of  Pure  Reason  "  was  to  prove  the  sub- 
jectivity of  Time  and  Space.  Though  Spinoza's  argu- 
ment is  not  similar  his  conclusion  is  identical  with 
that  of  Kant.  Time  is  a  concept  necessary,  not  for 
every  single  intuition  as  Kant  would  say,  but  for 
understanding  the  whole  sequence  of  intuitions.  But 
whether  for  the  one  reason  or  the  other  the  result  is 
the  same ;  time  is  not  an  "  affect  "  of  being  but  a  form 
or  mode  of  thought.    Measure  another  one  of  Spinoza's 


lxxiv  INTRODUCTION 

ideas  of  reason  used  to  explain  experience  by  a  sim- 
ilar argument  to  that  used  in  connection  with  time, 
would  provide  for  the  subjectivity  of  time.  Thus  we 
would  have  in  this  essay  the  "  Transcendental  Aes- 
thetic "  complete.  Time  and  Space  by  implication  are 
not  something  externally  real,  but  forms  of  thought 
necessary  to  explain  experience. 

Beside  these  elements  of  the  "  Transcendental  Aes- 
thetic "  there  are  several  of  the  categories  of  Kant 
placed  in  the  list  of  being  of  reason.  Number,  the 
third  one  of  the  ideas  Spinoza  names  in  his  enumera- 
tion, is  practically  identical  with  the  Kantian  categories 
of  quantity. .  The  terms  "  possible  "  and  "  contingent  ' 
though  not  given  with  the  others  are  plainly  regarded 
as  subjective  and  suggest  the  categories  of  relation. 
Besides  all  this  we  find  also  that  Spinoza  in  this  dis- 
cussion makes  use  of  that  most  distinctly  Kantian  of  all 
Kantian  terms  "  transcendental."1  In  popular  usage, 
we  are  told,  unity,  the  true  and  the  good,  the  examples 
he  gives  of  transcendental  terms,  are  considered  to  be 
attributes  inherent  in  the  objects  themselves.  Spinoza's 
purpose  is  to  show  that  these  are  not  real  affects  of  be- 
ing but  ideas  of  reason.  Taking  each  one  up  separate- 
ey  he  would  show  that  they  arise  from  subjective 
causes.  In  other  words  Spinoza  would  show  that 
those  attributes  usually  called  transcendental  are  not 
noumenal  or  real  but  of  a  subjective  origin,  a  use  of 
the  term  that  suggests  very  powerfully  the  Kantian 
use  of  the  word.  So  far  as  the  distinction  between 
the  manifold  of  sense  and  the  subjective  elements  of 
experience  are  concerned,  therefore,  Spinoza  seems  in 
these  passages  to  insist  upon  it  in  such  a  way  that  we 
may  well  raise  the  inquiry  we  have  suggested.     It  is 

1  Vid.  Cogilata  Mctaphysica.  Pt.  I.,  Chaps.  V.  and  VI. 


INTRODUCTION  lxxv 

far  from  an  improbability,  therefore,  that  Kant  who 
seemed  by  his  keen  criticism  of  Pantheism  well  ac- 
quainted with  Spinoza's  system  may  have  received 
some  valuable  suggestions  from  this  early  work. 

In  the  Ethics  Spinoza  apparently  made  little  use  of 
this  distinction  between  subjective  necessities  of 
thought  and  ideas  having  origin  in  the  attributes  of 
external  objects.  In  no  part  of  this  work  is  the  dis- 
tinction set  forth  in  such  clear-cut  terms  as  in  this  early 
essay.  But  on  the  other  hand,  the  later  work  con- 
tains as  one  of  its  most  essential  truths  this  antithesis 
between  thought  and  extension.  And  more  specifically 
one  of  the  prime  tenets  of  Pantheism  rests  upon  this 
distinction  between  what  is  externally  real  and  what 
is  mentally  required.  His  doctrine  of  good  and  evil 
we  have  seen  depends  upon  this  distinction.  Good 
and  evil  have  their  causa  essendi,  not  in  the  external 
world  but  in  the  way  the  human  mind  regards  them. 
Apart  from  this,  however,  there  is  little  in  the  Ethics 
to  illustrate  the  importance  of  the  distinction  made  in 
the  Cogitata. 

§  20.  But  the  most  important  truth  of  Spinoza's 
system,  the  truth  which  Pantheism  emphasized  with 
such  commendable  persistency  is  not  one  upon  which 
questions  and  doubts  can  arise.  It  is  a  truth  which, 
in  the  development  of.  philosophical  belief,  stands  out 
in  bold  relief;  it  marks  a  well  defined  stage  in  philo- 
sophic thought,  and  did  not  merely  suggest,  but  it 
determined  the  trend  of  succeeding  opinion.  The 
thought  to  which  we  refer  is  the  closer  bond  that 
Spinoza  established  between  God  and  the  world.  As 
we  have  already  pointed  out,  even  in  his  early  thinking, 
Spinoza  assigned  such  a  supreme  value  to  the  concept 
of  God,  and  made  the  world  so  completely  dependent 


lxxvi  INTRODUCTION 

upon  His  power  and  presence,  that  Deism  was 
doomed.  We  have  seen,  too,  why  it  was  that  Spinoza's 
ideas  assumed  this  particular  form.  From  the  earliest 
times  he  accepted  Deduction  as  the  true  method  of 
determining  truth,  and  looked  to  the  concept  of  God 
as  the  source  of  all  being  and  all  truth.  Thus  this 
vital  connection  between  God  and  nature  becomes  a 
dominant  thought  throughout  Spinoza's  reflections. 
Since  to  the  end  he  was  the  devoted  champion  of  De- 
duction, and  since  the  idea  of  God  increased  rather  than 
decreased  in  importance,  in  the  Ethics  as  well  as  in  the 
Cogitata  this  thought  remains  the  greatest,  grandest 
truth  of  his  philosophy.  It  only  remains  to  see  how  it 
has  appeared  and  reappeared  in  different  forms  in  suc- 
ceeding years. 

In  the  main  current  of  philosophic  thought  since 
Spinoza's  time  the  influence  of  this  truth  of  God's 
immanence  in  nature  has  been  uninterrupted.  Phi- 
losophy soon  saw  how  vital  was  this  truth,  and  though 
it  has  been  modified  in  form,  it  has  never  been  rejected. 
The  German  Rationalistic  School  accepted  it  boldly, 
and  the  followers  of  Kant  incorporated  it  in  various 
ways  in  their  teachings.  Even  the  recent  tendencies 
toward  Materialism  are  manifestations  which  show 
most  forcibly,  if  illogically,  that  Nature  cannot  be 
divorced  from  God.  The  place  which  nature  holds  in 
human  experience  is  far  too  important  to  allow  it  to  be 
treated  in  the  unreflective  manner  of  Deism.  However 
radical  some  of  the  theories  of  the  Absolute  which  have 
arisen  since  Spinoza's  chief  work  was  published,  they 
have  not  sinned  against  the  principal  truth  he  wished  to 
emphasize  and  returned  to  a  deistic  conception  of  God. 
And  as  our  knowledge  of  the  world  and  of  its  wonder- 
ful   laws   is   increasing   through   the   giant   strides   of 


INTRODUCTION  lxxvii 

science,  we  can  but  reaffirm  this  same  truth.  God  is 
in  the  world  and  His  presence  is  just  as  necessary  and 
just  as  real  in  the  world  to-day  as  when  the  heavens 
and  the  earth  were  first  created.  Science  is  not  out- 
growing this  idea,  but  growing  into  it  more  and  more. 
The  fact  that  there  is  sometimes  an  atheistic  tendency 
in  those  who  devote  their  lives  to  this  work  is  not  due 
to  the  nature  of  that  work,  but  to  a  failure  to  compre- 
hend the  full  significance  of  the  study  in  which  they 
are  engaged.  So  wonderful,  so  universal,  so  mighty 
are  the  truths  that  thus  stand  revealed,  that  they  im- 
agine there  is  no  greater  grander  truth  than  that  which 
they  have  found.  They  would  feign  assert  that  those 
Laws  are  the  highest  work  of  the  Divine,  nay,  that 
they  are  themselves  the  only  Absolute. 

This  thought  that  God  is.  in  the  world,  not  merely 
over  it  or  above  it,  therefore,  by  determining  our  con- 
ception of  God  and  of  Nature,  leads  us  to  the  very 
heart  of  Ontology.  But  more  than  this,  it  has  opened 
our  eyes  to  see  the  true  significance  of  the  cosmological 
argument  for  the  existence  of  God.  If  this  thought 
is  true,  God  is  not  far  away  but  even  nigh  to  every 
one  of  us ;  His  spirit  is  in  the  world  on  every  hand 
sustaining  and  directing  it,  and  in  the  development  or 
evolution  of  material  forms  and  psychical  powers  we 
have  a  direct  manifestation  of  His  presence,  and  His 
power.  Until  this  truth  was  recognized,  and  Spinoza 
deserves  the  credit  for  making  it  evident,  Philosophy 
must  needs  rely,  as  we  know  it  actually  did,  upon  some- 
form  of  ontological  argument  for  the  being  and  at- 
tributes of  God.  The  proof  for  His  being  and  the 
argument  for  His  attributes,  until  this  truth  is  accepted, 
had  to  be  found  in  the  a  priori  deductive  method  of 
which  Spinoza  was  a  consummate  master.     But  when 


lxxviii  INTRODUCTION 

it  is  known  that  God  stands  as  the  eminent  cause  of 
every  act,  the  soul  of  every  form  of  nature,  nature 
acquires  a  new  dignity  and  a  new  worth.  Under  this 
conception  the  intelligence  here  shown  becomes 
the  wisdom  of  God,  the  purposes  and  teleology  of  the 
external  wrorld  become  the  purposes  and  teleology  of 
God,  and  the  evolution  of  nature  in  her  various  stages 
of  development  becomes  the  unfolding  of  the  great 
World  Plan  of  God.  It  is  only  as  we  believe  this 
truth,  only  as  we  rely  upon  the  truth  which  Spinoza 
presented  in  his  bold  formal  way  that  we  can  put  confi- 
dence in  this  cosmological  argument  for  God's  being. 
But  when  it  is  known  that  God  stands  each  moment 
as  the  cause,  the  real  soul  of  every  form  of  nature, 
nature  is  filled  with  meaning,  and  becomes  the  great 
source  book  for  Philosophy  as  well  as  the  text-book 
for  Science.  Henceforth,  all  the  truth  which  the  sci- 
ences discover,  as  well  as  the  no  less  significant,  though 
less  demonstrable  truths  which  the  poet  and  the  artist 
find,  and  the  reflections  of  the  philosopher,  all  conspire 
to  reveal  the  real  nature  of  the  world  and  of  God 
Henceforth,  Philosophy  as  well  as  Science  must  be 
thus  far  inductive.  We  learn  of  God  as  we  study  His 
works. 

§  21.  But  there  is  another  field  beside  that  of  Phi- 
losophy in  which  Spinoza's  influence  has  been  pro- 
foundly felt.  Strange  as  it  may  seem  at  first  sight 
there  was  something  in  Spinoza's  cold,  calculating, 
almost  fatalistic  philosophy  that  appealed  strongly  to 
the  poetic  mind  since  his  time.  Goethe  and  Lessing.  in 
Germany,  and  Coleridge  and  Wordsworth  in  England 
are  but  the  most  striking  examples  of  an  influence  in 
this  field  of  art,  that  has  extended  even  clown  to  the 
present  time.     In  some  way  they  found,  in  his  system. 


INTRODUCTION  lxxix 

more  than  the  chaste  beauty  of  a  philosophic  truth ;  un- 
der the  forbidding  exterior  of  his  method,  and  the  more 
formidable  tenets  of  the  fatalism  the  system  suggested, 
they  found  a  truth  pulsating  with  all  the  warmth  and 
color  and  life  of  an  artistic  thought.  It  is  needless  to 
say  that  this  truth  was  the  one  we  have  just  seen  was 
so  powerful  in  shaping  later  Philosophy.  God's  actual 
presence  in  nature,  His  immanence  in  the  forms  of  life 
He  has  created,  and  is  continually  preserving,  is  a 
truth  not  less  important  for  the  Philosophy  of  the 
Beautiful  than  for  Ontology. 

Spinoza,  then,  unknowingly  emphasized  a  vital 
aesthetic  truth ;  or  rather,  the  truth  for  which  he  de- 
serves the  credit  of  first  making  emphatic,  is  capable 
of  an  aesthetic  envisagement.  Pantheism,  notwith- 
standing its  formality  and  the  radical  character  of  some 
of  its  tenets,  furnishes  to  Philosophy  a  conception  that 
not  only  converts  the  world  from  Deism  to  Theism, 
but  a  conception  that  also  animates  nature  and  gives 
its  every  form  a  significance  and  an  ideal  beauty  that 
could  never  be  found  under  the  older  conception  of 
God,  and  of  His  relation  to  the  world.  Without  the 
acceptance  and  appreciation  of  this  truth,  viz.,  the 
presence  of  the  ideal  in  the  real,  the  universal  in  the 
particular,  the  divine  in  the  human,  the  infinite  in  the 
finite,  the  richest  and  the  real  significance  of  nature  is 
not  seen.  But  with  an  appreciation  of  the  truth  im- 
plicated in  Spinoza's  Pantheism,  there  comes  an  en- 
largement of  the  world  aesthetically,  that  has  by  no 
means  been  compassed  in  the  last  hundred  years,  either 
poetically  or  from  the  standpoint  of  the  artist.  Under 
this  conception  of  nature  the  world  around  us  on  every 
side  and  in  every  form  is  filled  with  possibilities  for 
artistic  charm  and  beauty  as  various  and  as  deep  as 


lxxx  INTRODUCTION 

the  emotions  of  the  soul  itself.  Indeed,  nature  thus 
becomes  a  direct  expression  of  the  mind  and  soul  of 
God  Himself.  Beauty  no  longer  consists,  as  the  Greeks 
believed,  in  a  harmonious  relation  of  parts,  mere  form, 
nor  must  we  rely  entirely  upon  the  human  form  as 
the  mediaeval  painters  thought,  for  an  expression  of 
emotional  elements.  But  now,  when  we  believe  as 
Spinoza  taught,  that  God  is  in  these  forms  of  nature, 
landscape,  some  little  scene  of  water  or  of  wood,  may 
represent  some  truth  of  life,  and  picture  some  deep 
emotion  of  the  heart  of  man.  With  our  feet  planted 
upon  this  truth  as  a  ground  rock  of  our  philosophy 
we  have  an  outlook  upon  beauties  never  before  pic- 
tured so  vividly  nor  so  truly.  The  world  which  was 
before  conceived  as  a  mechanism  —  not  without  beauty 
it  is  true  but  still  a  mechanism  —  now  throbs  with  the 
life  and  the  emotions  of  the  mind  it  represents.  Man 
does  not  descend,  to  become  a  brother  to  the  insensible 
clod,  but  the  world  in  its  organic  and  in  its  inorganic 
forms  is  raised  up  to  man.  Nature  is  no  longer  merely 
what  we  see  and  hear  and  touch,  the  mere  sequence 
of  cause  and  effect,  but  under  this  new  conception  it 
is  all  we  feci  and  love  and  enjoy.  Nature  becomes  a 
mine  of  aesthetic  truth  as  inexhaustible  as  infinity ;  the 
world  becomes  a  grand  picture  that  reflects  in  a  divine 
way  the  deepest  emotions  and  aspirations  of  the  soul 
itself.  It  was  for  this  reason  that  Spinoza's  system, 
though  set  forth  in  the  most  abstract  formal  way,  ap- 
pealed to  the  poetic  mind.  It  was  not  because  Panthe- 
ism was  wholly  satisfactory,  because  none  of  its  tenets 
do  violence  to  truth,  that  it  was  so  heartily  accepted 
by  the  men  whose  names  we  have  mentioned  above. 
They  probably  did  not  appreciate  or  even  care  for  his 
logic,  but  they  did  perceive  or  feel  that  down  beneath 


INTRODUCTION  lxxxi 

this  forbidding  exterior  there  was  the  warm  glow  of  a 
vital  aesthetic  truth.  It  was  only  as  Wordsworth  ap- 
preciated this  truth,  only  as  he  realized  the  indwelling 
in  nature  of  the  divine  spirit,  that  he  could  write : 

"  To  me  the  meanest  flower  that  blows  can  give 
Thoughts  that  do  often  lie  too  deep  for  tears." 

In  Literature  we  have  examples  of  immortal  pictures 
taken  from  regions  supernal.  Virgil  and  Dante  and 
Milton  have  each  found  in  that  realm  and  painted  with 
their  poetic  art,  pictures  that  bid  fair  to  defy  oblivion. 
Spinoza  sketched  with  a  few  bold  strokes  a  picture 
even  more  impressively  sublime  in  the  immensity  of  its 
conception.  Pantheism  or  God  become  visible  is  per- 
haps the  most  stupendous,  the  most  daring  picture  that 
man  has  yet  conceived.  Its  depth  has  by  no  means 
yet  been  fathomed  or  its  possibilities  appreciated  by  the 
Art  of  the  past.  But  the  truth  of  God's  presence  in  the 
world,  the  lasting  fruit  of  Spinoza's  reflection,  in  a 
more  refined,  conservative  form  remains  to-day  a 
thought  necessary  for  the  highest  interpretation  of  Art 
as  well  as  essential  truth  of  Ontology.  It  was  this 
idea  of  God's  immanence  in  nature  and  its  rich  accom- 
paniment of  aesthetic  suggestion  that  explains  Spinoza's 
influence  over  much  of  the  world's  poetry  since  his 
time.  Lessing  and  Goethe,  and  Coleridge  and  Words- 
worth, and  poets  and  artists  even  to  the  present  have 
appreciated  this  aesthetic  truth  and  incorporated  much 
of  it  in  their  more  refined  expressions.  But  they  are 
only  producing  in  the  concrete  that  which  Spinoza 
conceived  abstractly,  or  toning  down  to  milder  shades 
that  which  he  had  sketched  in  boldest  form. 


LUDWIG  MEYER 

TO 

THE   WORTHY   READER. 

S.    P.    D. 

It  is  admitted  by  all  who  have  any  claims  to  superior 
intelligence  that  the  method  of  mathematics,  viz.,  the 
method  by  which  conclusions  are  demonstrated  from 
definitions,  postulates,  and  axioms  is  the  best  method 
of  obtaining  and  imparting  truth.  And  rightly  so ;  for 
as  certain  knowledge  of  an  unknown  object  can  only 
be  obtained  through  facts  previously  known,  there 
must  of  necessity  be  certain  premises  on  which  the 
whole  superstructure  of  human  knowledge  rests,  pro- 
vided it  does  not  fall  of  its  own  weight,  or  succumb 
to  some  slight  attack  from  without.  No  one  who  has 
paid  any  attention  to  the  noble  study  of  mathematics 
can  doubt  its  definitions  or  postulates  or  axioms.  For 
definitions  are  but  a  very  open  explanation  of  the  terms 
and  names  under  which  the  subject  is  discussed,  and 
the  postulates  and  axioms  of  mathematics,  or  the  gen- 
eral ideas  of  the  mind,  cannot  be  denied  by  any  one 
who  understands  the  use  of  his  vocabulary. 

Nevertheless  mathematicians  are  almost  the  only 
ones  committed  to  such  a  method.  Others  employ  a 
method  radically  different  from  this,  namely,  a  method 
where   the    end    is    attained    through    definitions    and 


2       PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

logical  division  interspersed  with  numerous  questions 
and  explanations.  For  almost  all  believe,  and  many 
well  informed  persons  have  asserted  that  this  method 
is  peculiar  to  mathematics  and  should  be  abjured  in 
all  other  branches  of  study.  Therefore  they,  in  their 
discussions,  are  unable  to  offer  apodeictic  proof,  but 
are  compelled  to  reason  by  analogy  and  from  probable 
evidence.  They  produce  a  whole  medley  of  ponderous 
volumes  in  which  nothing  is  established  with  certainty, 
but  which  are  full  of  contending  views ;  what  is  in  one 
place  asserted  is  presently,  and  for  a  similar  reason, 
denied.  So  much  so  that  the  mind  eager  for  eternal 
truth,  when  it  had  hoped  to  find  the  tranquil  expanse 
of  its  own  desire,  and  crossing  this  with  propitious 
speed  to  gain  the  haven  of  true  cognition,  finds  itself 
on  a  tempestuous  sea  of  thought  tossed  about  and 
overcome,  surrounded  by  storms  of  contending  belief, 
and  lost  amid  waves  of  uncertainty,  without  hope  of 
rescue. 

There  are  some,  however,  who,  regretting  this 
wretched  plight  of  Philosophy,  in  order  that  they  may 
leave  to  posterity  some  studies  beside  mathematics 
established  with  absolute  certainty,  have  departed  from 
the  ancient  method  to  this  new  path,  arduous  though 
it  be.  Some  of  these  have  put  into  literary  form  the 
philosophy  now  accepted  and  accustomed  to  be  taught 
in  the  schools ;  others  have  set  in  order  new  systems 
elaborated  through  their  own  reflection.  Although  for 
years  the  task  was  undertaken  in  vain,  at  length  that 
splendid  star  of  our  century  Rene  Descartes  arose, 
who,  after  he  had  made  clear  the  mathematical  truth 
that  was  inaccessible  to  the  ancients,  and  everything 
desired  by  his  contemporaries,  also  discovered  this  fun- 
damental  principle   of  all   knowledge.     By   means   of 


PREFACE  3 

this  truth  he  was  able  to  elaborate  and  establish  many 
things  with  mathematical  certainty.  To  any  one  who 
attends  to  his  writings,  which  cannot  be  too  highly 
praised,  this  will  be  as  evident  as  the  midday  sun. 

Although  the  philosophical  writings  of  this  incom- 
parable man  contain  a  method  of  demonstrating  mathe- 
matics, it  is  not  the  method  found  in  Euclid  and  in 
other  geometries.  Descartes'  method,  which  he  called 
Analysis  and  maintained  was  the  best  way  to  discover 
truth,  was  widely  different  from  this.  In  the  end  of 
his  '  Response  to  the  Second  Objection,"  he  recog- 
nizes two  kinds  of  apodeictic  demonstration.  The  one, 
Analysis,  which  he  showed  to  be  the  true  method,  by 
which  truth  is  discovered  methodically  and  as  it  were 
a  'priori;  the  other  by  Synthesis,  the  method  in  which 
a  long  series  of  definitions,  and  premises  and  axioms, 
and  theorems,  and  problems  is  used  so  that  if  anything 
is  denied  in  the  conclusion,  it  is  immediately  shown  to 
have  been  contained  in  the  premises.  By  this  means 
assent  is  extorted  from  the  reader  however  unwilling 
or  unyielding  he  may  be. 

Granted,  however,  that  truth  may  be  established 
beyond  all  chance  of  doubt  by  these  two  methods,  still 
they  do  not  have  an  equal  value.  For  many  plainly 
unlearned  in  mathematical  knowledge  and  so  wholly 
ignorant  of  the  method  by  which  such  truth  is  discov- 
ered (analysis),  and  by  which  it  is  set  in  order  (syn- 
thesis), are  not  only  unable  to  teach  this  truth  to  others 
but  are  unable  to  follow  it  for  themselves.  Whence  it 
happens  that  many  who  have  made  his  opinions  and 
dogmas  only  a  matter  of  memory,  carried  away  by 
some  thoughtless  attack  or  influenced  by  the  authority 
of  others,  have  defamed  the  name  of  Descartes,  and, 
when  a  discussion  of  these  things  arises,  since  they 


PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 


cannot  demonstrate  anything,  garrulously  repeat  what 
has  always  been  ascribed  to  the  Peripatetic  Philosophy. 
Wherefore,  in  order  that  this  state  of  affairs  might  be 
improved,  I  have  often  desired  that  some  one,  alike 
skilful  in  Analysis  and  Synthesis,  well  versed  in  the 
writings  of  Descartes,  and  thoroughly  master  of  his 
philosophy,  might  give  his  attention  to  this  work  and 
what  he  has  put  in  analytic  form  remold  in  synthetic 
order  and  demonstrate  in  the  more  familiar  forms  of 
geometry.  I  myself,  although  fully  conscious  of  my 
unfitness  for  that  task,  have  often  been  inclined  to 
undertake  it.  Other  occupations,  however,  have  filled 
my  time  and  prevented  me  from  acting  on  my  desire. 

I  was  very  glad  to  know,  therefore,  that  our  author 
had  put  into  geometrical  form,  for  a  pupil  whom  he 
was  teaching  Descartes'  philosophy,  the  entire  second 
Part  of  the  Principles  and  a  part  of  the  third,  together 
with  some  important  questions  and  difficulties  usually 
discussed  in  Metaphysics,  and  not  yet  discussed  by 
Descartes ;  and  that  he  had  consented,  at  the  urgent 
request  of  his  friends,  that  these,  corrected  and  revised 
by  himself,  should  be  published.  I,  therefore,  approv- 
ing this  purpose,  offered  my  services,  if  he  had  any 
need  of  them,  in  helping  to  publish  the  work.  I  asked 
and  even  urged  him  that  he  should  put  the  first  Part 
into  similar  form  and  let  it  precede  the  two  already 
done,  in  order  that  the  work  might  be  complete  and 
therefore  more  intelligible.  Although  for  good  reasons 
he  did  not  wish  to  do  this,  he  was  unwilling  to  refuse 
his  friends  or  to  neglect  anything  which  might  be  done 
for  the  benefit  of  the  reader.  He  entrusted  to  my  care 
the  entire  management  of  the  publication  since  he  had 
departed  from  the  city  into  the  country  and  was  unable 
to  be  present. 


PREFACE  5 

This  is  what  we  offer  you,  therefore,  dear  reader,  in 
this  little  volume :  viz.,  the  first  and  second  Parts  of 
Descartes'  Principles  of  Philosophy,  together  with  a 
fragment  of  the  third,  to  which  we  have  added  under 
the  name  of  an  appendix  the  Cogitata  Metaphysica  of 
our  author.  But  when  we  speak  of  the  first  Part  of 
the  Principles,  and  the  title  of  the  book  suggests  the 
same  thought,  we  do  not  wish  it  understood  that  all 
that  Descartes  has  said  in  this  is  here  presented  demon- 
strated in  geometrical  order,  but  only  that  preferable 
terms  have  been  selected  and  those  principles  which 
Descartes  treated  in  his  Meditations,  which  relate  more 
particularly  to  Metaphysics.  Those  matters  which  are 
only  of  logical  interest,  however,  or  which  Descartes 
expressed  for  their  historical  value,  he  has  omitted. 
That  he  might  the  more  easily  effect  this  end  our 
author,  so  far  as  the  order  is  concerned,  has  trans- 
posed almost  all  that  Descartes  had  put  into  geometrical 
form  in  the  end  of  his  "  Response  to  the  Second 
Objection."  This  he  did  by  placing  all  of  Descartes* 
definitions  first  and  by  inserting  propositions  of  his 
own ;  by  placing  the  axioms  not  together  with  his 
definitions,  but  a  part  of  them  after  the  fourth  propo- 
sition ;  finally  by  omitting  those  not  needed  and  by 
changing  the  order  so  that  they  might  more  easily  be 
understood.  It  did  not  escape  the  notice  of  our  author 
that  these  axioms  might  be  demonstrated  in  the  manner 
of  theorems  (as  Descartes  also  held,  Postulate  7.)  and 
might  even  properly  be  classed  as  propositions.  We, 
indeed,  urged  him  to  do  this,  but  the  amount  of  work 
with  which  he  was  employed  only  left  him  two  short 
weeks  in  which  to  complete  the  work.  For  this  reason 
he  was  unable  to  satisfy  his  own  and  our  desire,  but 
merely   adding   a   brief    explanation   in    place   of   the 


6       PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

demonstration,  he  postponed  until  another  time  the 
complete  and  perfected  volume,  if  perchance  after  this 
imperfect  edition  a  new  one  should  be  demanded.  To 
this  end  we  shall  urge  him  to  complete  the  third  Part 
concerning  the  visible  world.  (Of  this  we  have  added 
the  fragment  our  author  had  completed,  for  we  were 
unwilling  that  the  reader  should  be  deprived  of  any 
part  of  his  work,  however  small.)  To  better  accom- 
plish his  purpose,  certain  propositions  concerning  the 
nature  of  fluid  bodies  had  to  be  inserted  in  Part  II. 
For  my  part,  I  shall  urge  him  to  speedily  complete 
the  work. 

Not  only  in  regard  to  the  axioms,  but  also  in 
demonstrating  the  propositions  and  in  other  conclu- 
sions our  author  often  differs  from  Descartes ;  for 
example,  the  term  apodeictic  is  used  in  a  widely  dif- 
ferent sense.  However,  let  no  one  think  that  he 
wished  to  correct  that  most  illustrious  man  in  these 
things,  but  only  that  he  did  this  in  order  to  retain  the 
current  order  and  not  increase  the  number  of  axioms 
unduly.  For  this  and  for  many  reasons  he  was  com- 
pelled to  demonstrate  many  things  which  Descartes 
had  stated  without  demonstration  and  to  add  much 
that  he  had  omitted. 

Nevertheless,  I  wish  it  to  be  noted  first  of  all  that 
in  all  of  these  Parts,  viz.,  in  the  first  and  second 
Parts  of  the  Principles  and  in  the  fragment  of  the 
third,  as  well  as  in  the  Cogitata  Metaphysica,  our 
author  is  merely  expressing  the  opinions  of  Descartes 
with  their  demonstrations  so  far  as  they  are  found  in 
his  writings  or  as  they  logically  follow  from  his 
premises.  For  when  he  promised  to  teach  a  pupil 
the  philosophy  of  Descartes  it  was  a  matter  of  prin- 
ciple  with   him   not   to   depart   in   the   least   from   his 


PREFACE  7 

opinions  or  to  teach  anything  that  did  not  follow  from 
his  dogmas,  or  was  contrary  to  them.  Wherefore, 
let  no  one  think  that  he  is  teaching  here  his  own 
opinions  or  only  what  he  approves.  Although  he  ad- 
judges certain  things  to  be  true,  he  affirms  that  others 
are  opposed  to  his  belief.  Many  things  he  rejects  as 
false,  from  which  he  holds  a  far  different  opinion. 
Of  this  nature,  to  mention  only  one  from  many,  are 
those  conclusions  concerning  the  Will,  Schol.  Prop. 
15,  Part  I.,  and  Chapter  12,  Part  II.  of  the  Appendix, 
although  they  seem  to  be  proved  with  painstaking 
care.  For  he  did  not  think  that  the  Will  was  some- 
thing distinct  from  Intellect,  much  less  endowed  with 
such  freedom.  For  in  these  assertions,  as  is  evident 
from  his  dissertation  concerning  method  Part  4, 
Meditation  2,  and  in  other  places,  Descartes  merely 
affirms  and  does  not  prove  that  the  human  mind  is 
an  absolute  thinking  substance.  Although  our  author 
indeed  admits  that  there  is  a  thinking  substance  in 
Nature,  he  denies  that  this  constitutes  the  essence  of 
the  human  mind.  He  believed  that  in  the  same  way 
that  there  are  no  limits  to  Extension,  so  Thought  is 
in  no  way  determined.  And  as  the  human  body  is 
not  absolute,  but  its  extension  is  determined  accord- 
ing to  natural  laws  of  motion  and  of  rest,  so  also  the 
mind  or  human  spirit  is  not  absolute  but  is  determined 
through  ideas  by  natural  laws  of  thought.  These,  we 
ought  to  conclude  are  given  when  the  body  begins  to 
exist.  From  this  definition  it  is  easy  to  show  that 
the  Will  and  the  Intellect  cannot  be  distinguished, 
much  less,  as  Descartes  affirmed,  can  we  say  that  the 
Will  is  endowed  with  liberty.  To  say  that  it  is  the 
faculty  of  affirming  or  of  denying  is  wrong,  for  to 
affirm  or  to  deny  is  only  a  form  of  idea.     Indeed,  those 


8       PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

faculties,  as  Intellect,  Desire,  etc.,  ought  to  be  placed 
in  the  list  ,of  fictitious  thoughts,  or  at  least  of  those 
ideas  which  men  have  because  of  their  powers  of  ab- 
straction, as  for  example,  with  humanity,  lapidity,  etc. 

Reference  must  also  be  made  to  another  point  which 
was  prominent  in  the  mind  of  Descartes,  namely, 
that  this  or  that  surpasses  human  knowledge.  For  it 
must  not  be  thought  that  our  author  states  this  as  his 
own  opinion.  He  believed  that  all  these  things,  and 
even  many  things  more- subtle  and  more  sublime,  could 
not  only  be  clearly  and  distinctly  conceived  by  us,  but 
even  readily  explained  if  only  the  human  mind  were 
led  in  the  way  which  Descartes  opened  up  and  made 
possible  for  investigating  truth  and  for  acquiring 
knowledge.  Therefore  the  principles  of  knowledge 
which  Descartes  set  forth  and  the  philosophy  based 
upon  these  do  not  suffice  for  solving  all  those  extreme- 
ly difficult  problems  which  relate  to  metaphysics,  but 
others  are  required  if  we  desire  the  intellect  to  sound 
the  depths  of  cognition. 

And  finally,  to  bring  our  preface  to  an  end,  we  wish 
the  reader  to  know  that  these  papers  are  published  for 
no  other  purpose  than  to  discover  and  to  impart  truth, 
and  to  incite  in  men  a  desire  for  a  true  and  a  sincere 
philosophy.  So  let  every  one,  having  been  diligently 
warned,  before  he  undertakes  to  read  this  work,  deter- 
mine to  correct  as  far  as  possible  certain  typographical 
errors  which  have  crept  in,  and  to  insert  the  omissions 
in  order  that  he  may  receive  the  full  benefit  which  we 
earnestly  desire  for  every  reader.  For  these  obstacles, 
as  any  one  can  readily  see,  may  easily  prevent  the  force 
of  the  demonstration  and  the  thought  of  the  author 
from  being  easily  seen. 


AD  LIBRUM.     ■ 

Ingenio  seu  te  natum  meliore  vocemus, 

Seu  de  Cartesii  fonte  renatus  eas, 
Parve  Liber,  quidquid  pandas,  id  solus  habere 
Dignus,  ab  exemplo  laus  tibi  nulla  venit. 
Sive  tuum  spectem  genium,  seu  dogmata,  cogor 

Laudibus  Auctorem  tollere  ad  astra  tuum. 
Hactenus  exemplo  caruit,  quod  praestitit ;  at  tu 

Exemplo  haud  careas,  obsecro,  parve  Liber ; 

Spinozae  at  quantum  debet  Cartesius  uni, 

Spinoza  ut  tantum  debeat  ipse  sibi. 

—J.  B.,  M.D.1 

1  Probably  by  J.  Bresser,  M.  D. 


The  Principles  of  Philosophy  Demonstrated 
by  the  Method  of  Geometry. 


Part  I. 


PROLEGOMENON. 


Before  giving  these  propositions  and  their  demon- 
stration it  seems  best  to  recall  briefly  why  Descartes 
came  to  doubt  all  things,  how  he  discovered  the 
fundamental  principle  of  all  knowledge,  and  finally  how 
he  liberated  himself  from  this  universal  doubt.  All  of 
this  we  would  have  put  in  mathematical  order  if  we 
had  not  thought  that  such  prolixity  would  have  im- 
peded our  understanding  of  these  things  which 
should  be  seen  as  clearly  as  though  presented  in  a 
picture. 

In  order  to  proceed  with  his  investigation  with  the 
utmost  caution  Descartes  was  compelled : 

i.     To  lay  aside  all  prejudices. 

2.  To  find  the  fundamental  truth  on  which  all 
knowledge  rests. 

3.  To  discover  the  cause  of  error. 

4.  To  understand  everything  clearly  and  distinctly. 

In  order  to  accomplish  the  first  three  points  he 
doubted  all  things,  not,  however,  as  a  sceptic  who 
doubts  merely  for  the  sake  of  doubting,  but  in  order 
to  free  his  mind  of  all  prejudices,  so  that  he  might 
find  at  length  the  firm  and  certain  truth  on  which 
all  knowledge  rests.     By   using  this   method,   such   a 

11 


12     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

truth,  if  any  such  existed,  could  not  escape  him.  For 
this  principle  must  he  so  clear  that  it  needs  no  proof, 
and  cannot  under  any  circumstances  be  doubted ;  every 
demonstration  must  presuppose  it.  Such  a  truth  he 
found  after  a  long  period  of  doubt.  And  after  he 
had  once  gained  this  truth  it  was  not  difficult  to  dis- 
tinguish the  true  from  the  false,  or  to  detect  the  cause 
of  error.  And  thus  he  could  be  on  his  guard  lest  he 
accept  anything  doubtful  and  false  for  what  is  certain 
and  true. 

To  accomplish  the  last  point,  viz.,  to  understand 
everything  clearly  and  distinctly,  his  principal  rule  was 
to  examine  separately  all  the  simple  ideas  from  which 
all  others  are  composed.  For  when  he  clearly  and  dis- 
tinctly understood  these  simple  ideas,  he  was  enabled 
to  understand  m  the  same  thorough  way,  all  others  into 
which  they  entered  as  component  parts.  Having 
prefaced  our  remarks  with  these  few  words  we  shall 
proceed  with  our  purpose  as  stated  above,  namely,  to 
explain  why  he  doubted  everything,  how  he  found 
the  fundamental  truth  of  all  knowledge,  and  how  he 
extricated  himself  from  the  difficulties  of  these  doubts. 
r  , .       .       In  the  first  place  he  calls  attention  to 

Concerning  his   tint-  r 

versai  doubt.  z\\  0f  those  things  perceived  through 
the  senses,  the  heavens,  the  earth  and  all  external  ob- 
jects. So  also,  even  concerning  those  things  which 
he  thought  to  be  most  certain  he  doubted,  because  he 
knew  that  his  senses  had  sometimes  deceived  him, 
and  in  sleep  he  had  often  persuaded  himself  that  many 
things  existed  in  which  he  later  found  he  had  been 
deceived.  And  finally  because  he  had  heard  com- 
petent witnesses  affirm  that  they  sometimes  felt  pain  in 
limbs  recently  lost.  It  was  not  without  reason,  there- 
fore, that  he  doubted  everything  even  the  existence  of 


PART  I  13 

his  own  body.  Hence  from  all  these  reasons  he  was 
able  to  conclude  that  sense  perception  is  not  a  certain 
foundation  for  knowledge  (all  that  the  senses  give  may 
well  be  called  in  doubt),  but  certainty  rests  upon  some 
more  indubitable  principle  than  this.  To  investigate 
further  he  next  notices  the  universal  attributes  of  cor- 
poreal matter,  as  extension,  form,  quantity,  etc.,  as  well 
as  all  mathematical  truth.  Although  these  seem  more 
certain  than  the  objects  of  sense  perception,  neverthe- 
less, he  finds  a  cause  for  doubting  them  as  well.  Some 
err  even  in  these,  and  beside  there  is  an  old  idea  that 
God,  who  is  omnipotent,  and  has  created  us  with  our 
present  faculties,  has  perhaps  so  made  us  that  we  are 
deceived  even  in  those  things  which  seem  most  certain. 
These  are  the  causes  that  led  him  to' doubt  all  things. 

In    order    to    find    the    fundamental 
The  discovery  of     truth  in  knowledge,  he  afterward  in- 

the     fundamental  .  .  . 

principle  of  all  quired  whether  all  things  which  are 
subjects  of  cognition  could  be  doubted, 
if  perchance  there  wTas  anything  which  he  had  not  yet 
called  in  question.  Doubting  in  this  way  he  believed 
that  if  anything  was  found,  which,  for  none  of  the 
reasons  given  above,  should  be  doubted,  this  might 
be  considered  the  foundation  on  which  all  knowledge 
rests.  And  although,  as  it  now  seemed  he  had  doubted 
everything  (for  he  had  called  in  question  all  that  the 
senses  give,  and  all  that  comes  from  the  understand- 
ing), there  was  something  left  the  certainty  of  which 
had  not  been  doubted,  namely,  he  himself  who  was 
doubting.  Not,  however,  so  far  as  he  consisted  of 
head  or  hands  or  other  bodily  members,  for  he  had 
doubted  the  existence  of  these,  but  even  while  he  was 
doubting  he  was  thinking,  etc.  Carefully  examining 
this  fact  he  found  that  for  no  reason  whatever  could  it 


i4     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES-  PHILOSOPHY 

be  doubted,  for,  whether  waking  or  sleeping^  if  think- 
ing at  all  he  must  therefore  exist.  And  even  though  he 
and  others  might  fall  into  error,  since  they  were  in 
error  they  must  exist.  Nor  could  he  conceive  of  a 
creator  so  skilful  in  deceit  that  he  could  deceive  him 
about  this  truth.  For  if  it  is  supposed  that  he  is  de- 
ceived, it  must  also  be  supposed  that  he  exists.  Fin- 
ally, whatever  reason  for  doubt  may  be  conceived,  there 
is  none  which  does  not  at  the  same  time  make  one  more 
certain  of  his  own  existence.  Indeed  the  more  argu- 
ments that  can  be  assigned  as  cause  for  doubt  the  more 
there  are  which  convince  him  of  his  own  existence. 
So  true  is  this  that  whoever  begins  to  doubt  will  never- 
theless exclaim,  "I  doubt,  I  think,  therefore  I  am" 

In  this  truth  he  finds  the  ground  of  all  knowledge 
as  well  as  the  measure  of  all  other  truth,  viz..  What- 
ever is  as  el  early  and  distinctly  perceived  as  this  is  true. 

That  nothing  but  this  Cogito  ergo  sum  can  be  the 
fundamental  truth  in  all  knowledge  is  evident  from 
what  has  already  been  said.  Concerning  this  it  should 
be  noted  in  the  first  place,  that  it  is  not  a  syllogism 
in  which  the  major  premise  is  omitted.  If  it  were, 
the  premise  cogito  ought  to  be  better  known  than  the 
conclusion,  ergo  sum.  And  if  this  were  so  the  ergo 
sum  would  not  be  the  foundation  of  all  knowledge. 
Beside  it  would  not  be  a  certain  conclusion,  for  its 
truth  depends  upon  universal  premises  which  the 
author  had  called  in  question.  Therefore  Cogito  ergo 
sum  is  one  proposition  equivalent  to  the  statement 
ego  sum  cogitans. 

To  avoid  confusion  hereafter  (for  the  matter  ought 
to  be  thoroughly  understood),  we  must  know  what 
we  are.     For  if  I  clearly  understand  this  our  essence 


PART  I  15 

will  not  be  confused  with  other  things.     To  deduce 
this  from  what  precedes  our  author  thus  proceeds : 

He  now  recalled  all  those  opinions  formerly  held, 
as  for  example,  that  his  mind  was  something  very 
fine  in  texture,  like  the  wind,  or  fire,  or  air,  interplaced 
with  the  coarser  particles  of  the  body ;  and  that  his 
body  was  better  known  than  his  mind  and  could  be 
more  clearly  perceived.  These  opinions  he  now  saw 
were  at  variance  with  what  he  had  discovered.  For 
he  could  doubt  the  existence  of  his  body,  but  not  his 
reality  so  far  as  he  was  a  thinking  being.  Beside 
this,  the  body  could  not  be  clearly  and  distinctly  known 
and  therefore,  according  to  his  own  dictum,  should 
be  rejected  as  non-existent.  Therefore,  since  the  body 
cannot  be  accepted  as  pertaining  to  his  essence,  so 
far  as  it  is  known,  he  further  inquires  what  there  is 
about  his  being  which  compels  him  to  believe  in  his 
own  existence.  Such  things  were  these :  that  he  had 
determined  to  be  on  his  guard  lest  he  be  deceived; 
that  he  had  desired  to  understand  so  many  things; 
that  he  had  doubted  everything  he  was  not  able  to 
know;  that  he  had  affirmed  only  one  thing  at  a  time ; 
that  he  had  denied  all  else,  and  even  rejected  it  as  false ; 
that  he  had  conceived  many  things  though  reluctantly ; 
and  finally  that  he  had  considered  many  things  as 
though  derived  from  the  senses.  Since  his  existence 
was  so  evidently  bound  up  with  each  one  of  these 
actions,  and  since  none  of  them  belonged  to  the  things 
which  he  had  doubted,  and  finally  since  they  all  may 
be  considered  as  forms  of  thought,  it  follows  that  these 
are  all  true  and  pertain  to  his  nature.  So  when  he 
said  cogito  these  modes  of  thought  were  all  implied, 
viz.,  to  doubt,  to  understand,  to  affirm,  to  deny,  to  zirish, 
to  be  unwilling,  to  imagine,  and  to  feel. 


16      PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

Some  distinctions  must  here  be  noted  that  will  have 
importance  when  we  come  to  discuss  the  distinction 
between  mind  and  body,  (i)  That  modes  of  clear 
and  distinct  thought  may  be  known  even  when  some 
things  are  still  in  doubt.  (2)  That  we  render  a  clear 
and  a  distinct  concept  obscure  and  confused  when  we 
ascribe  to  it  something  concerning  which  we  are  still 
in  doubt. 

Finally,  in  order  that  he  might  be 
His  liberation  from  certain    and    remove    all    doubt    from 

doubt. 

those  things  he  had  called  in  question, 
he  further  proceeds  to  inquire  into  the  nature  of  a 
perfect  Being  and  whether  such  a  Being  exists.  For 
when  he  has  discovered  that  this  Being,  by  whose 
power  all  things  are  created  and  preserved  and  to 
whose  nature  it  would  be  repugnant  to  be  a  deceiver, 
exists,  then  he  has  removed  that  reason  for  doubt 
which  is  found  in  the  fact  that  he  was  ignorant  of 
the  cause  of  his  existence.  For  he  knew  that  the 
power  of  discerning  the  true  from  the  false  would 
not  have  been  given  to  him  by  a  God  of  perfect  good- 
ness and  truth  in  order  that  he  might  be  deceived. 
Mathematical  truth,  therefore,  and  all  other  of  like 
certainty  cannot  be  doubted.  To  remove  other  causes 
for  doubt  he  inquires  next  why  it  is  we  sometimes 
fall  into  error.  For  when  he  discovered  how  error 
arose,  and  that  we  use  our  free  will  to  assert  what  we 
perceive  only  confusedly,  he  concluded  straightway 
that  we  could  avoid  error  by  withholding  assent  from 
that  which  is  seen  only  indistinctly. 

As  every  one  has  the  power  of  inhibiting  the  will 
he  can  easily  restrain  it  to  the  limits  of  the  understand- 
ing. And  since  in  youth  we  form  many  prejudices 
from  which  we  free  ourselves  only  with  difficulty,  he 


PART  I  17 

enumerates  and  examines  separately  all  of  our  simple 
ideas  to  assist  us  in  casting  these  prejudices  aside. 
His  object  was  to  determine  what  was  clear  and  what 
was  obscure  in  each.  Thus  he  was  able  to  distinguish 
the  clear  from  the  obscure  and  to  form  clear  and  dis- 
tinct ideas.  By  this  means  he  easily  found  the  real 
distinction  between  mind  and  body ;  what  was  clear 
and  what  obscure  in  those  ideas  derived  from  the 
senses ;  and  finally  how  sleep  differs  from  waking. 
When  this  was  done  he  could  doubt  no  longer  concern- 
ing the  waking  life,  nor  could  he  be  deceived  by  his 
senses.  In  this  way  he  was  able  to  free  himself  from 
all  his  recent  doubt. 

Before  I  close  this  part  of  the  discussion  it  seems 
that  some  satisfaction  should  be  given  to  those  who 
argue,  that  since  it  is  not  known  that  God  exists  per  se 
it  is  impossible  for  us  ever  to  know  that  God  does  exist. 
For  from  uncertain  premises  (and  we  have  said  that 
all  things  are  uncertain  so  long  as  we  are  ignorant  of 
our  origin),  nothing  can  be  concluded  with  certainty. 

In  order  to  remove  this  difficulty  Descartes  re- 
sponded in  this  fashion ;  although  we  do  not  know 
whether  the  creator  of  our  nature  has  created  us  so 
that  we  are  deceived  in  those  things  which  seem  most 
certain,  nevertheless,  we  cannot  doubt  those  things 
we  understand  clearly  and  distinctly,  so  long  as  we 
attend  merely  to  them.  But  we  only  doubt  those 
things  previously  demonstrated,  and  now  recalled  to 
memory,  when  we  no  longer  attend  closely  to  the 
reasons  from  which  they  were  deduced,  v/hich  per- 
chance are  even  forgotten.  Therefore,  though  we 
cannot  know  directly  that  God  exists,  but  must  learn 
this  by  deduction,  still,  we  are  able  to  know  this  cer- 
tainly, provided  we  attend  very  accurately  to  the  prem- 


18     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

ises  from  which  the  conclusion  is  deduced.  Vid.  Prin. 
Pt.  I.  Art.  13,  and  Response  to  Second,  Obj.  No.  3, 
and  end  of  Med.  5. 

But  since  this  reply  is  not  sufficient  we  will  offer 
another.  We  saw  above,  when  speaking  of  the  evi- 
dence and  certainty  of  our  existence,  that  this  was 
found  in  the  fact  that,  consider  what  we  will,  we 
meet  no  argument  for  doubt  which  does  not  at  the 
same  time  convince  us  of  the  certainty  of  our  exist- 
ence. This  is  true  whether  we  consider  our  own 
nature,  or  conceive  of  God  as  a  skilful  deceiver,  or 
adduce  some  extraneous  reason  for  doubt.  For  ex- 
ample, considering  the  nature  of  a  triangle,  though 
we  are  now  compelled  to  believe  that  its  three  angles 
are  equal  to  two  right  angles  we  are  not  forced  to 
the  conclusion  that  this  is  really  true  if  perchance  we 
are  deceived  by  our  Creator.  In  the  same  'way  we 
deduce  the  certainty  of  our  existence.  We  are  not 
compelled  to  believe  that  under  any  conditions  the 
three  angles  of  a  triangle  are  equal  to  two  right  angles. 
On  the  contrary  we  find  reason  for  doubt,  for  we  have 
no  idea  of  God  which  compels  us  to  believe  that  it  is 
impossible  for  God  to  deceive  us.  It  is  equally  easy 
for  one  who  has  no  true  conception  of  God  to  think 
that  he  is  a  deceiver  or  that  he  is  not.  So  for  those 
who  have  no  right  conception  of  a  triangle  it  is  equally 
easy  for  them  to  think  that  the  sum  of  the  angles  is 
equal  to  two  right  angles,  or  that  it  is  not.  There- 
fore, we  grant  that  we  cannot  be  absolutely  certain 
of  anything  except  of  our  own  existence,  however 
closely  we  attend  to  the  proof,  until  we  have  a  clear 
concept  of  God  which  compels  us  to  affirm  (in  the  same 
way  that  the  concept  of  a  triangle  compels  us  to  affirm 
that   the    sum    of    its    angles    is    equal    to    two    right 


PART  I  19 

angles)  that  he  is  perfectly  true  in  His  being.  But 
we  deny  that  we  are  unable  to  come  to  any  certain 
knowledge  of  the  external  world.  For,  as  now  ap- 
pears, the  whole  matter  hinges  upon  this,  viz.,  whether 
we  can  form  such  a  concept  of  God  that  it  is  not  as 
easy  for  us  to  think  of  Him  as  a  deceiver  as  to  believe 
that  He  is  perfectly  true  in  His  being.  When  we 
obtain  such  a  concept  as  this,  all  cause  for  doubting 
mathematical  truth  is  removed.  For,  when  we  con- 
sider how  the  doubt  of  this  affects  our  own  existence, 
if  we  doubt  this  still  we  ought  not  to  even  affirm  our 
own  existence.  If  now  having  obtained  this  concept 
of  God  we  consider  the  nature  of  a  triangle  we  are 
compelled  to  affirm  that  the  sum  of  its  three  angles  is 
equal  to  two  right  angles ;  or  if  we  consider  the  nature 
of  God,  and  this  also  compels  us  to  affirm  that  He  is 
perfectly  true  and  the  author  and  continual  preserver 
of  our  being,  we  are  not  deceived.  Nor  is  it  less  im- 
possible for  us  to  think  when  we  once  have  obtained 
this  idea  of  God  (which  we  suppose  to  be  already 
found),  that  He  is  a  deceiver,  then  when  we  consider 
the  nature  of  a  triangle  to  think  that  the  sum  of  its 
angles  is  not  equal  to  two  right  angles.  As  we  can 
form  such  an  idea  of  a  triangle  although  we  are  not 
certain  that  God  is  not  deceiving  us,  so  we  can  form 
this  idea  of  God,  although  we  do  not.  know  whether 
or  not  He  is  deceiving  us.  And,  provided  only  that 
we  have  such  an  idea  of  God,  however  it  may  have 
been  obtained,  it  is  sufficient  to  remove  all  doubt. 

This  point  having  been  made  clear  I  shall  remark 
upon  this  difficult  proposition :  we  can  be  certain  of 
nothing  not  merely  as  long  as  we  are  ignorant  of  God's 
existence  (for  I  have  not  yet  spoken  of  this),  but  as 
long  as  we  do  not  have  a  clear  and  a  distinct  idea  of 


20     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

His  being.  Hence  if  any  one  should  desire  to  oppose 
our  conclusions,  his  argument  should  be  as  follows : 
We  cannot  be  certain  of  anything  so  long  as  we  have 
no  clear  and  distinct  idea  of  God.  But  we  cannot 
have  a  clear  and  a  distinct  idea  of  God  as  long  as  we 
do  not  know  whether  or  not  he  is  deceiving  us. 
Therefore  we  cannot  be  certain  of  anything  as  long 
as  we  do  not  know  whether  or  not  our  Creator  is 
deceiving  us,  etc.  To  this  I  reply  by  conceding  the 
major  premise  but,  denying  the  minor.  For  we  have 
a  clear  and  a  distinct  idea  of  a  triangle  although  we 
do  not  know  whether  or  not  God  is  deceiving  us. 
And  in  the  same  way  we  have  a  clear  and  a  distinct 
idea  of  God  as  I  have  already  shown,  and,  therefore, 
cannot  doubt  His  existence,  nor  any  mathematical 
truth. 

Our  prefatory  remarks  being  thus  completed  we 
proceed  now  to  the  main  pr6blem. 

DEFINITIONS. 

I.  Under  the  term  thought  (cogitatio)  I  compre- 
hend all  mental  phenomena  of  which  we  are  imme- 
diately conscious. 

Thus  volition,  understanding,  imagination  and  sense 
perception  are  all  forms  of  thought.  I  have  added 
the  term  immediately  to  exclude  phenomena  which 
directly  depend  upon  and  follow  from  these  mental 
states.  Thus  voluntary  motion  arises  as  the  direct 
result  of  some  form  of  thought  but  is  not  itself  a 
mental  state. 

II.  By  the  term  idea  (idea)  I  understand  any 
form  of  thought  of  which  we  are  conscious  through 
immediate  perception. 

I  cannot  express  anything  in  words,  therefore,  with- 


PART  I  21 

out  thus  making  it  certain  that  I  have  some  idea  which 
these  words  are  meant  to  signify.  Therefore  I  would 
even  call  the  images  depfcted  in  phantasy,  ideas,  not, 
however,  so  far  as  they  are  corporeal,  i.  e.?  as  they 
affect  some  portion  of  the  brain,  but  only  so  far  as 
they  affect  the  mind  in  that  portion  of  the  brain. 

III.  By  the  objective  reality  of  an  idea,  /  under- 
stand  the  object  represented  by  the  idea. 

In  the  same  manner  I  may  speak  of  objective  per- 
fection, or  of  an  objective  art,  etc.  For  whatever  we 
perceive  in  the  objects  of  our  ideas  are  objective  in 
the  ideas  themselves. 

IV.  These  characteristics  are  said  to  be  formally 
(formaliter)  contained  in  the  objects  of  our  ideas 
when  they  really  are  just  as  we  perceive  them-.  They 
are  said  to  be  eminently  (eminenter)  contained  when 
they  are  not  just  as  zee  perceive  them  but  so  great  that 
they  can  easily  supply  what  we  perceive. 

Note  that  when  I  say  a  cause  eminently  contains  the 
perfection  of  its  own  effect,  I  mean  that  the  cause 
contains  the  perfection  of  the  effect  more  completely 
than  the  effect  itself.     Vid.  Ax.  8. 

V.  Every  object  to  zvhich  belongs  as  to  a  subject, 
some  property,  or  quality,  or  attribute,  or  through 
zvhich  some  things  which  we  perceive  exist,  or  of  which 
we  have  some  real  idea  is  called  substance. 

Properly  speaking,  indeed  we  have  no  other  idea 
of  substance  than  that  it  is  an  object  in  which  either 
formally  or  eminently  something  else  exists  which  we 
perceive,  or  that  it  is  objective  in  something  apart 
from  our  ideas. 

VI.  Substance  in  which  thoughts  are  immediately 
present,  is  called  mind. 

I   use   the   term   mind    (mens),    rather   than   spirit 


22     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

(animus),  for  the  latter  term  is  equivocal,  often  being 
used  to  mean  a  corporeal  object. 

VII.  Substance,  which  is  the  immediate  subject  of 
extension,  and  of  accidents,  which  presupposes  forms  of 
extension  as  figure,  position,  and  motion,  etc.,  is  called 
body  (corpus). 

Whether  mind  and  body  are  one  and  the  same  sub- 
stance will  be  inquired  into  later. 

VIII.  Substance  which  we  know  to  be  perfect  in 
the  highest  degree,  and  in  which  nothing  can  be  con- 
ceived implying  a  defect  or  limitation,  is  called  God. 

IX.  When  we  say  that  something  is  contained  in 
the  nature  of  the  thing  itself  or  in  its  concept,  it  is  the 
same  as  to  affirm  that  this  is  true. 

X.  Substances  are  said  to  be  distinct  when  the  one 
can  exist  alone  and  apart  from  others. 

We  have  here  omitted  the  Postulates  of  Descartes  be- 
cause we  were  unable  to  deduce  any  conclusions  from 
them  in  what  is  to  follow.  Nevertheless,  we  earnestly 
ask  the  reader  that  he  does  not  fail  to  carefully  read 
them  over  and  give  them  his  earnest  attention. 

AXIOMS. 

I.  The  knowledge  and  certainty  of  an  unknown 
object  depends  upon  the  cognition  of  objects  pre- 
viously known. 

II.  There  are  reasons  for  doubting  the  existence 
of  our  own  bodies. 

(This  was  shown  in  the  Prolegomenon,  so  may  be 
placed  here  as  an  axiom.) 

III.  If  our  being  comprises  anything  beside  mind 
and- body  it  is  not  so  well  known  as  these. 

(These  axioms,   it  should  be  noted,   do  not  affirm 


PART  I  23 

objective  existence,  but  only  deal  with  objects  as  a  part 
of  our  mental  life.) 

Proposition  I. 

We  cannot  be  absolutely  certain  of  anything  until 
we  know  that  we  really  exist. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

This  proposition  is  self-evident.  For  he  who  does 
not  know  that  he  exists,  cannot  know  that  he  is  affirm- 
ing or  denying.  It  should  be  noted,  too,  that  although 
we  affirm  and  deny  many  things  that  have  no  refer- 
ence to  our  existence,  nevertheless  unless  this  fact  is 
accepted  as  indubitable  all  things  are  in  doubt. — Q. 
E.  D. 

Proposition  II, 
The  proposition  ego  sum  is  self-evident. 

demonstration. 

If  you  deny  that  it  is  self-evident,  it  can  be  known 
only  through  some  truth,  prior  to  the  proposition  ego 
sum  (per.  Ax.  1),  which  is  absurd  (per  Ibid.). 
Therefore  it  is  self-evident. —  Q.  E.  D. 

Proposition  III. 

The  primary  truth  is  not  that  I  am  a  corporeal  being, 
neither  is  this  fact  self-evident. 

demonstration. 
There  are  some  reasons  for  doubting  the  existence 
of   our   bodies    (Vid.   Ax.    2).     Hence    (per   Ax.    1) 


-4     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

we  must  derive  this  truth  through  something  pre- 
viously and  more  indubitably  known.  Therefore,  the 
primary  truth  is  not  that  I  am  a  corporeal  being  nor 
is  this  fact  self-evident. —  O.  E.  D. 


Proposition  IV. 

Ego  sum  is  the  primary  fact  in  cognition  only  so 
far  as  I  am  a  thinking  being. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

The  assertion  that  I  am  a  corporeal  being  is  not  the 
primary  fact  in  cognition  (per  Prop.  III.)  ;  neither  am 
I  certain  of  my  existence  except  as  I  am  mind  and 
body.  For  if  I  comprise  in  my  being  any  thing  beside 
mind  and  body,  it  is  not  so  well  known  to  me  as  body 
(per  Ax.  3).  Therefore  ego  sum  is  the  primary  fact 
of  cognition  only  so  far  as  I  am  a  thinking  being. 
-Q.  E.  D. 

COROLLARY. 

From  the  last  proposition  it  is  evident  that  the  mind 
is  better  known  than  the  body.  (For  a  fuller  explana- 
tion, see  Art.  11  and  12,  Part  I.  of  the  Principles.) 

SCHOLIUM. 

Every  one  is  certain  that  he  affirms,  he  denies,  he 
doubts,  he  understands,  he  imagines,  etc.,  or  that  he  is 
a  doubting,  an  understanding,  an  affirming  —  in  a 
word  —  a  thinking  being.  This  truth  no  one  can 
doubt.  Therefore  the  proposition  cogito,  or  sum 
cogitans,  is  the  fundamental  truth  of  all  Philosophy. 
And,  since  for  certain  knowledge  nothing  more  can  be 
demanded  or  desired  than  that  we  deduce  all  things 


PART  I  25 

from  certain  premises  so  that  all  our  conclusions  are 
as  certain  as  our  premises,  it  follows  that  all  that  we 
deduce  from  our  principle  so  that  if  we  doubt  the 
conclusion  we  must  also  doubt  the  premises,  must  be 
held  to  be  perfectly  true.  In  order  to  proceed  as 
cautiously  as  possible,  in  the  beginning  I  shall  admit 
to  be  of  equal  certainty  only  those  things  which  we 
perceive  in  ourselves  so  far  as  we  are  thinking  beings. 
As,  for  example,  that  one  desires  this  or  that,  that  one 
has  certain  ideas,  and  that  one  thing  contains  more  per- 
fection than  another ;  namely,  that  which  contains  ob- 
jective perfection  of  substance  is  far  more  perfect 
than  that  which  contains  only  objective  perfection  of 
some  accident.  Finally,  that  that  is  the  most  perfect 
substance  which  contains  the  highest  degree  of  perfect 
being.  These  things,  I  say,  are  not  only  all  as  clear 
as  our  first  principle  but,  perhaps,  are  even  more  cer- 
tain. For  they  not  only  affirm  that  we  think  but  that 
we  think  in  this  particular  way.  And  we  shall  find, 
when  we  come  to  test  them,  that  they  are  not  only 
indubitable,  but  that  we  cannot  doubt  their  verity 
without  doubting  the  fundamental  truth  of  all  knowl- 
edge. For  example,  if  some  one  should  say  he  is  in 
doubt  whether  something  can  arise  from  nothing,  he 
might  also  doubt  his  own  existence  even  when  he  is 
thinking.  For  if  I  can  affirm  that  something  can  exist 
without  a  cause  I  can,  by  the  same  right,  affirm  that 
thought  may  exist  without  a  cause  and  that  I  think 
although  I  am  nothing.  Since  this  is  impossible  I 
cannot  believe  that  something  can  arise  from  nothing. 
Leaving  these  matters  for  the  present,  it  seems  neces- 
sary, in  order  to  proceed,  to  add  to  the  number  of 
Axioms  we  have  already  given.  In  the  end  of  his 
"  Response  to  the  Second  Objection,"  Descartes  has 


26     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

given  certain  truths  as  axioms,  and  I  could  not  wish 
to  be  more  accurate  than  he.  Nevertheless,  in  order 
to  preserve  the  order  now  begun,  and  to  render  them 
a  little  clearer,  I  shall  attempt  to  show  how  they  de- 
pend one  upon  the  other  and  all  upon  the  principle 
Ego  sum  cogitans,  or  that  they  are  all  as  certain  as 
this  truth. 


axioms 
Taken   from-  Descartes. 

IV.  There  are  different  degrees  of  reality  or  being. 
For  substance  has  more  reality  than  accidents  or  mode ; 
and  infinite  substance  than  finite.  So,  too,  there  is 
more  objective  reality  in  the  idea  of  substance  than  in 
the  idea  of  accident ;  and  in  the  idea  of  infinite  sub- 
stance than  in  the  idea  of  finite  substance. 

This  axiom  is  known  as  true  from  a  consideration 
of  those  ideas  of  which  we  are  certain  because  they 
are  modes  of  thought.  For  we  know  how  much 
reality  or  perfection  the  idea  of  substance  affirms  of 
substance  and  how  much  the  idea  of  mode  affirms  of 
mode.  And  since  this  is  true  we  know  that  the  idea 
of  substance  contains  more  objective  reality  than  the 
idea  of  its  accidents,  etc.  (Vid.  Schol.  Prop.  4). 

V.  A  thinking  being,  if  it  were  possible,  would 
immediately  add  to  itself  any  attribute  of  perfection  in 
which  it  was  lacking. 

Every  one  observes  this  in  himself  so  far  as  he  is 
a  thinking  being;  therefore  (per  Schol.  Prop.  4)  we 
know  that  this  is  true.  And  for  the  same  reason  we 
are  equally  certain   of  the  inference. 

VI.  In  the  idea  or  concept  of  everything,  existence 


PART  I  27 

either    as    possible    or    necessary    is    contained    (Vid. 
Axioms  of  Descartes,  No.  10). 

In  the  concept  of  God  or  an  absolutely  perfect  being, 
existence  is  necessary.  For  otherwise  it  would  be  im- 
perfect which  is  contrary  to  the  hypothesis. 

VII.  No  object  or  quality  of  an  object  already 
existing  can  exist  without  some  existing  object  as  the 
cause  of  its  existence. 

In  the  Scholium  to  Prop.  4.  I  have  shown  that  this 
axiom  is  equal  in  truth  to  the  proposition  Ego  sum 
cogitans. 

VIII.  Whatever  reality  or  perfection  an  object  con- 
tains, this  exists  either  formally  (formaliter)  or  emi- 
nently (eminenter)  in  its  primary  or  adequate  cause.1 

By  the  term  eminently  I  mean  that  the  cause  con- 
tains the  perfection  of  the  effect  more  fully  than  the 
effect  itself.  By  the  term  formally  I  mean  that  the 
cause  and  the  effect  contain  the  perfection  to  a  like 
degree. 

This  axiom  depends  upon  the  previous  ones.  For 
if  it  is  supposed  that  there  is  less  perfection  in  the 
cause  than  in  the  effect  we  have  a  result  without  a 
cause,  and  this  is  absurd  (per  Ax.  7). 

Therefore  nothing  can  be  the  cause  of  a  given  effect 
except  that  in  which  is  contained  eminently  or  at  least 
formally,  all  the  perfection  found  in  the  effect. 

IX.  The  objective  reality  of  our  ideas  requires  a 
cause  in  which  this  same  reality  is  not  only  objectively 
contained,  but  one  in  which  it  is  found  formally,,  or 
eminently. 

Although  this  axiom  is  evident  to  all,  many  misuse 
it.  For  when  some  one  forms  some  new  idea  every- 
one wishes  to  know  why  he  did  so.     When  they  can 

1  Cf.  Veitch's  Descartes,  p.  268,  and  Note  p.  281. 


28     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

assign  some  cause  that  contains  formally  or  eminently 
all  the  perfection  found  in  the  concept  they  are  content. 
Descartes  has  sufficiently  explained  this  in  his  example 
of  a  machine  (Vid.  Prin.  of  Phil,  Pt.  L,  Art.  iy).  So 
also  if  one  inquires  from  whence  man  derives  the  ideas 
of  his  own  thought  and  body,  he  finds  that  they  are  de- 
rived from  himself.  He  discovers  that  he  formally  or 
at  least  constantly  contains  all  that  these  ideas  objec- 
tively contain.  Therefore  if  one  has  some  idea  which 
contains  more  objective  reality  than  he  himself  contains, 
impelled  by  reason  he  would  seek  some  other  cause 
outside  of  himself  which  formally  or  eminently  con- 
tains all  the  perfection  he  is  seeking  to  understand. 
Nor  would  any  one  ever  assign  any  other  reason  for 
doing  this  than  that  he  had  conceived  this  with  equal 
clearness  and  distinctness  and  that  he  had  compre- 
hended the  truth  of  this  axiom  as  it  depends  directly 
upon  those  preceding  it.  Namely  (per  Ax.  4),  dif- 
ferent degrees  of  reality  or  being  are  given  in  our 
ideas;  and  (per  Ax.  8)  for  these  degrees  of  perfec- 
tion, some  cause  with  equal  perfection  is  required. 
But  since  these  degrees  of  reality  in  our  ideas  are  not 
merely  in  thought,  but  represent  something  in  sub- 
stance and  its  modes,  in  a  word,  so  far  as  they  arc 
considered  as  images  of  things,  it  clearly  follozcs  that 
no  other  cause  for  this  can  be  assigned  than  that  all 
the  reality  they  objectively  contain  is  contained  either 
formally  or  eminently  in  reason.  This  we  have  shown 
above  and  it  is  evident  to  all. 

I11  order  to  make  this  perfectly  clear  I  will  illustrate 
with  one  or  two  examples.  If  one  should  see  two 
books  (for  example,  one  written  by  a  great  philosopher 
and  another  by  an  uncultured  man)  writ! en  in  the 
same  hand,  and  should  consider  not  the  meaning  of  the 


PART  I  29 

words,  i.  e.,  the  mental  images  they  represent,  but  only 
the  delineation  of  the  characters  in  which  the  thoughts 
are  expressed,  he  would  discover  no  dissimilarity.  So 
he  would  not  be  led  to  look  for  different  authors  for 
the  books  but  would  believe  they  were  written  by 
the  same  person  and  with  a  common  end  in  view. 
But  attending  not  to  this  but  to  the  meaning  of  the 
words  and  of  the  discussions  he  woidd  Hud  great  dif- 
ferences, and  would  conclude  that  they  certainly  had 
a  different  origin.  He  would  find  that  the  sense  of 
the  words  being  considered,  that  is,  the  concepts  they 
represent,  the  one  is  far  more  perfect  than  the  other. 
I  speak  here  of  the  first  cause  of  the  books.  Although 
as  is  evident  the  one  might  even  have  been  derived 
from  the  other. 

We  may  illustrate  further  by  the  statue  of  some 
leader.  Here,  if  we  attend  only  to  the  material  used 
we  will  find  no  cause  for  seeking  a  different  sculptor  for 
this,  and  for  some  copy.  Indeed,  nothing  hinders  us 
from  thinking  that  the  first  is  a  copy  of  the  second, 
this  again  of  a  third  and  so  on  ad  infinitum.  //  the 
material  alone  is  considered  we  do  not  need  a  separ- 
ate cause  for  each.  But  if  we  consider  the  statue  as 
a  statue  we  are  immediately  compelled  to  seek  a  first 
cause  which  contained  cither  formally  or  eminently 
all  that  is  presented  to  us.  I  do  not  see  that  this 
axiom  requires  any  further  elucidation  or  confirma- 
tion. 

X.  No  lesser  cause  is  required  for  the  conservation 
of  an  object  than  for  its  first  creation. 

Because  at  the  present  time  we  are  thinking  it  does 
not  at  all  follow  that  we  must  continue  to  think.  Our 
concept  of  thought  does  not  contain  nor  involve  neces- 
sary existence.     For  I  can  clearly  conceive  of  thought 


30     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

although  I  suppose  that  it  docs  not  exist.  (This  every 
one  knows  from  his  own  experience  so  far  as  he  is 
a  thinking  being).  But  since  the  nature  of  any  cause 
ought  to  contain  and  involve  in  itself  the  perfection 
of  its  effect  (per  Ax.  8),  it  follows  that  there  is  some- 
thing in  ourselves  or  without  us  (as  yet  we  do  not 
know  which)  zvhose  nature  involves  necessary  exist- 
ence. And  this  something  is  the  primary  cause  of 
our  thought  both  of  its  beginning  and  its  continuance. 
For,  although  our  thought  began  to  exist,  its  nature 
and  essence  does  not  imply  a  necessary  existence  any 
more  than  it  did  before  it  began  to  be.  It  is  there- 
fore preserved  in  its  existence  by  the  same  force  that 
determined  that  it  should  exist.  What  we  here  affirm 
of  thought  is  true  also  for  every  thing  whose  essence 
does  not  involve  a  necessary  existence. 

XL  Nothing  exists  of  which  we  may  not  ask,  what 
is  the  cause  (or  reason)  of  its  existence.  (Vid.  Ax.  I. 
of  Descartes). 

If  anything  positive  exists  we  cannot  say  that  it 
exists  without  a  cause  (per  Ax.  y).  Therefore  zee 
must  assign  some  positive  cause  for  its  existence.  This 
may  be  external,  i.  e.,  some  cause  outside  of  the  object 
itself,  or  internal,  i.  c,  something  comprel\endcd  in 
the  nature  and  definition  of  the  object. 

Four  Propositions  Taken  From  Descartes. 

Proposition  V. 

God's  existence  is  known  merely  from  the  consid- 
eration of  his  nature. 

demonstration. 

It  is  equivalent  to  saying-  that  a  thing  is  true  to  say 
that   it   is   contained   in   its   nature   or   in   its   concept. 


PART  I  31 

(per  Def.  9).  The  concept  of  God  includes  necessary 
existence.  Therefore  it  is  true  to  say  that  he  has  a 
necessary  existence  in  Himself,  or  that  He  exists. 
-  Q.  E.  D. 

SCHOLIUM. 

Many  important  truths  follow  from  this  proposition. 
Indeed  upon  this  truth  alone,  namely,  that  existence 
belongs  to  the  nature  of  God,  or  that  the  concept  of 
God  involves  a  necessary  existence  as  that  of  a  triangle 
that  the  sum  of  its  angles  is  equal  to  two  right 
angles,  or  again  that  His  existence  and  His  essence 
are  eternal  truth,  depends  almost  all  our  knowledge 
of  God's  attributes  by  which  we  are  led  to  a  love  of 
God  (or  to  the  highest  blessedness).  Therefore  it  is 
extremely  desirable  that  the  human  race  should  some- 
time consider  this.  I  confess  that  there  are  certain 
prejudices  which  make  this  truth  hard  to  see.  But  if 
any  one  with  earnest  purpose,  impelled  by  the  love  of 
truth  and  its  utility,  wishes  to  examine  into  this,  we 
recommend  that  he  consider  what  is  given  in  Medita- 
tion V.  and  in  the  end  of  his  "  Response  to  the  Sec. 
Obj.,"  and  also,  what  we  have  said  of  Eternity  in 
Ch.  I.  Pt.  II.  of  our  Appendix.  He  would  then  under- 
stand very  clearly,  nor  could  he  doubt  that  we  do 
have  an  idea  of  God  which  is  indeed  the  foundation 
of  human  blessedness ;  he  would  see  clearly  that  the 
idea  of  God  differs  greatly  from  that  of  other  objects; 
He  would  see,  when  he  understands  the  essence  and 
existence  of  God,  that  he  differs  toto  genere  from  all 
other  things.  But  there  is  no  need  to  detain  the  reader 
longer. 


32    PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

Proposition  VI. 

The  existence  of  God  may  be  demonstrated  a  pos- 
teriori from  this,  viz.,  that  we  possess  this  idea  of 
such  a  Being. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

The  objective  reality  of  anything  requires  a  cause 
apart  from  our  ideas,  in  which  cause  this  reality  is 
not  only  objective,  but  in  which  it  is  contained  either 
formally,  or  eminently  (per.  Ax.  8).  We  have  the 
idea  of  God,  and  the  objective  reality  of  this  idea 
as  it  is  not  in  our  minds  either  formally  or  eminently 
cannot  be  anywhere  but  in  God  himself.  Therefore 
this  idea  of  God  as  we  have  it  requires  God  for  its 
cause  and  He,  therefore,  exists. 

SCHOLIUM. 

There  are  certain  ones  who  say  they  have  no  idea 
of  God,  although,  as  they  affirm,  they  love  and  worship 
him.  And  although  you  place  before  their  eyes  the 
definition  and  attributes  of  God,  you  have  accom- 
plished nothing.  No  more,  by  Hercules,  than  if  you 
should  attempt  to  teach  a  man  blind  from  birth  the 
different  colors  as  we  see  them.  Indeed,  we  ought 
to  give  their  words  very  little  attention  unless  we  wish 
to  consider  them  as  a  new  species  of  animal  half  way 
between  man  and  the  lower  beasts.  In  what  way 
do  I  attempt  to  set  forth  the  idea  of  anything  except 
by  giving  a  definition  and  explaining  its  attributes? 
Indeed  when  we  are  discussing  the  idea  of  God,  it  is 
not  so  much  that  men  deny  the  words  as  that  they 
are  unable  to  form  some  image  corresponding  to  these 
words. 


PART  I  33 

Then  it  should  be  noted  that  Descartes  when  he 
cites  Axiom  4  to  show  that  the  objective  reality  of 
the  idea  of  God  is  not  in  us  either  formally  or  emi- 
nently, supposes  that  every  one  knows  that  he  is  not 
infinite  substance  nor  perfect  in  knowledge  or  power, 
etc.  This  he  was  justified  in  doing,  for  whoever 
thinks  at  all  knows  that  there  are  many  things-  he  does 
not  understand  clearly  and  distinctly,  and  that  he  is 
even  in  doubt  in  regard  to  much  that  he  sees. 

Finally  it  should  be  noted  that  there  are  not  many 
gods,  as  clearly  follows  from  Axiom  8,  but  only  one 
as  we  have  shown  in  Proposition  II.  of  this  part  and 
in  Pt.  II.,  Chapter  II.,  of  our  Appendix. 

Proposition  VII. 
The  existence  of  God  is  demonstrated  in  the  fact 
that  we,  having  the  idea  of  existence,  also  exist. 

SCHOLIUM. 

To  prove  this  proposition  Descartes  laid  down  two 
axioms,  viz.,  (1)  "Whatever  is  able  to  do  that  which 
is  more  difficult  is  able  to  do  that  which  is  less  so. 
(2)  It  is  greater  to  create  or  (per  Ax.  10)  conserve 
substance  than  attributes  or  properties  of  substance." 
What  he  meant  by  these  I  do  not  know.  For  these 
terms  are  not  used  absolutely  but  only  in  respect  to  a 
definite  cause.1 

So  one  and  the  same  thing  at  the  same  time,  in 
respect  to  different  causes  may  be  easy  or  difficult. 
If  you  call  that  difficult  which  requires  more  exertion, 


1  If  you  wish  an  example,  consider  the  spider  which  easily 
spins  its  web,  but  for  man  this  would  be  almost  impossible. 
On  the  other  hand,  men  easily  do  many  things  which  perhaps 
are  impossible  for  angels. 


34     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

and  that  easy  which  requires  less  in  the  same  case,  as 
for  example,  the  force  which  sustains  fifty  pounds 
could  sustain  twenty-five  with  double  ease,  clearly  the 
axiom  would  not  be  true ;  neither  does  it  demonstrate 
what  he  intended  it  should.  For  when  he  said,  'If 
I  have  the  power  of  preserving  myself  I  have  the 
power  also  of  giving  to  myself  all  the  works  of  per- 
fection which  I  lack'  (for  that  would  require  only  as 
great  power)  ;  I  would  concede  that  this  energy  used 
for  self-preservation  might  be  able  to  do  many  other 
things  far  more  easily  if  I  did  not  need  it  for  conserv- 
ing myself.  But  so  long  as  I  use  this  energy  for 
self-preservation,  I  deny  that  it  is  possible  to  use  it 
for  accomplishing  other  things,  though  they  be  never 
so  easy.  This  is  clearly  evident  from  our  example. 
Nor  does  he  take  away  the  difficulty  by  saying,  that 
as  I  am  a  thinking  being  I  shall  know  this  necessarily, 
for  I  employ  all  my  strength  in  preserving  myself 
which  is  the  reason  I  do  not  give  myself  the  attributes 
of  perfection  which  I  lack.  For  (although  we  are 
not  now  discussing  this,  but  only  how  the  necessity 
of  this  proposition  follows  from  this  axiom)  if  I  know 
this  I  would  be  greater  and  perhaps  would  require,  for 
preserving  myself  in  such  perfection,  greater  power 
than  I  now  possess.  And  then  I  do  not  know  that 
it  is  any  greater  task  to  create  (or  to  conserve)  sub- 
stance than  attributes,  i.  e.,  to  speak  clearly  and  more 
philosophically,  I  do  not  know  but  that  substance  re- 
quires all  the  virtue  and  essence  by  which  it  conserves 
itself,  to  conserve  its  attributes.  But  we  leave  this  and 
will  inquire,  as  this  worthy  author  intended  we  should, 
into  what  is  meant  by  the  terms  "easy"  and  "  diffi- 
cult." I  clo  not  think  that  by  any  means  1  could  per- 
suade myself  that  he  understood  bv  the  term  "  diffi- 


PART  I  35 

cult"  that  which  is  impossible  (and  so  could  not  be 
conceived  as  existing),  and  by  the  term  "easy"  that 
which  implies  no  contradiction  (and  so  is  easily  con- 
ceivable). Although  in  the  Third  Meditation  and  in 
the  observation  he  seems  to  mean  that  when  "he  says : 
"  Nor  ought  I  to  think  that  those  things  which  are 
wanting  in  my  nature  are  more  difficult  to  acquire  than 
the  powers  which  I  now  possess.  For,  on  the  con- 
trary, it  is  manifestly  far  more  difficult  for  me  as  a 
being  or  a  thinking  substance  to  arise  from  nothing 
than,  etc."  For  this  is  not  in  keeping  with  the  words 
of  the  author  nor  consonant  with  his  ability.  And, 
indeed,  though  for  the  present  I  shall  overlook  it, 
between  the  possible  and  the  impossible,  or  between 
that  which  is  conceivable  and  inconceivable  there  is  no 
relation,  just  as  there  is  none  between  something  and 
nothing.  Power  does  not  quadrate  better  with  that 
which  is  impossible  than  creation  and  generation  with 
non-being;  such  terms  are  not  capable  of  relationship. 
Beside  this  it  should  be  remembered  that  I  can  compare 
and  understand  only  those  things  of  which  I  have  a 
clear  and  a  distinct  concept.  I  cannot  conclude,  there- 
fore, that  one  who  is  able  to  do  impossible  things  is 
able  also  to  do  that  which  is  possible.  I  ask  what 
conclusion  is  this?  If  any  one  can  square  a  circle  he 
can  also  make  a  circle  whose  radii  are  not  equal ;  or 
if  one  can  endue  nothing  with  the  qualities  of  matter 
he  can  also  produce  something  from  nothing.  As  I 
have  said  there  is  no  analogy,  or  relation,  or  means 
of  comparison  between  such  terms.  Any  one  who 
reflects  upon  this  even  a  little  can  clearly  see  that  this 
is  true.  Therefore  I  believe  that  something  else  was 
meant  by  the  ingenious  Descartes.  Considering  the 
second  axiom  given  above,  Descartes  seemed  to  mean 


36     PRINCIPLES  OP  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

by  the  terms  greater  and  more  difficult  that  which  was 
more  perfect,  and  by  the  opposite  terms  that  which 
was  less  perfect.  This  also  certainly  seems  obscure. 
It  is  the  same  difficulty  found  above,  and  I  deny  here, 
as  there,  that  he  who  has  power  to  do  the  greater 
thing  has  power  also  at  the  same  time  to  do  the  lesser. 
According  to  the  above  proposition  this  must  be 
granted.  Then  when  he  says  "it  is  greater  to  create 
or  conserve  substance  than  its  attributes,"  we  cannot 
understand  by  attributes  that  which  is  formally  con- 
tained in  substance  and  only  distinguished  from  it  by 
reason.  For  then  it  would  be  the  same  thing  to  create 
substance  as  to  create  attributes.  For  the  same  reason 
we  cannot  think  that  he  meant  the  properties  of  sub- 
stance. This  follows  necessarily  from  its  essence  and 
definition,  much  less  can  we  understand  by  this,  how- 
ever, as  he  seemed  to  wish,  the  properties  and  at- 
tributes of  some  other  substance ;  as  for  example,  if  I 
say  that  because  I  have  the  power  of  conserving  my- 
self, a  thinking,  finite  substance,  so  I  have  the  power 
of  giving  to  myself  all  the  perfection  of  infinite  sub- 
stance which  differs  by  its  whole  essence  from  me. 
For  the  power  or  essence  by  which  I  conserve  my 
being  differs  toto  genere  from  the  power  and  essence 
by  which  absolute  or  infinite  substance  conserves 
itself.  The  power  and  properties  of  infinite  substance 
are  not  differentiated  per  se  but  only  by  reason ; 2  so 
(while  I  may  concede  that  I  conserve  myself),  if  I 
wish  to  think  that  I  have  the  power  to  give  to  myself 
all  the  perfection  of  infinite  substance  I  suppose  noth- 
ing else  than  that  I  have  the  power  to  annihilate  my 

2  It  may  be  noted  here  that  the  power  by  which  substance 
conserves  itself  is  nothing  but  its  essence  and  only  differs 
from  that  in  name.  Which  we  will  clearly  show  when  in  the 
Appendix  we  discuss  the  nature  of  God. 


PART  I  37 

being  and  to  create  infinite  substance  anew.  Which 
clearly  presupposes  more  than  that  I  am  able  to  con- 
serve the  finite  substance  of  my  being.  If  then  none 
of  these  interpretations  can  be  given  to  the  terms 
attributes  or  properties,  nothing  remains  but  the  qual- 
ities which  are  eminently  contained  in  the  substance 
(as  this  or  that  thought  which  I  clearly  see  are  want- 
ing in  me).  Not,  however,  what  some  other  substance 
eminently  contains ;  for  these  attributes  even  though 
wanting  in  me  are  not  imperfections  so  far  as  I  am  con- 
sidered to  be  a  thinking  being.  This,  then,  which 
Descartes  wished"  to  infer  from  his  axioms  does  not 
logically  follow;  namely,  that  if  I  have  the  power  to 
conserve  myself,  I  have  the  power  also  of  giving  to 
myself  all  the  marks  of  perfection  of  the  Absolute 
Being.  This  is  evident  from  what  has  been  said.  But 
to  avoid  confusion,  and  to  make  the  matter  more  cer- 
tain, it  seems  best  to  demonstrate  the  following  Lem- 
mata first  and  give  the  demonstration  of  the  seventh 
proposition   afterward. 

Lemma  I. 

An  object  of  a  higher  degree  of  perfection,  by  virtue 
of  this  fact  involves  a  fuller  existence  and  a  greater 
necessity  of  existence.  Conversely,  that  which  by 
nature  involves  a  greater  necessity  of  existence,  is 
more  perfect. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

Existence  is  contained  in  the  idea  or  concept  of 
every  object  (per  Ax.  6).  Let  us  suppose  A  to  be 
an  object  with  ten  degrees  of  perfection.  I  say  that 
this  object  involves  more  existence  than  if  it  is  sup- 


38     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

posed  to  contain  but  five.  For,  as  we  cannot  affirm 
existence  of  nothing  (Vid.  Schol.  Prop.  4),  as  we 
detract  from  the  perfection  of  a  concept  and  conceive 
its  content  to  approach  zero  as  its  limit,  so  much*  do 
we  detract  from  its  possible  existence.  If  we  conceive 
this  degree  of  perfection  to  be  infinitely  diminished, 
even  to  zero,  it  will  contain  no  existence,  or  but  an 
"absolutely  impossible  one.  On  the  other  hand  if  we 
increase  this  degree  of  perfection  to  infinity  we  con- 
ceive that  it  has  the  highest  possible  existence  and  so 
to  be  absolutely  necessary.  This  was  the  first  point 
to  be  proven.  Then,  as  I  am  by  no  means  able  to 
separate  these  two  (as  appears  from  Ax.  6  and  the 
whole  of  Pt.  I.)  it  clearly  follows  that  the  other  is 
likewise  true. 

Note  I.  Although  many  things  are  said  to  exist 
necessarily  simply  because  the  cause  producing  them 
is  given  we  do  not  now  speak  of  such  objects;  but 
only  of  that  necessity  and  possibility  which  follows 
from  the  mere  consideration  of  the  nature  and  essence 
of  the  thing  itself,  no  reason  being  held  as  to  its  cause. 

Note  II.  We  do  not  here  speak  of  beauty  and  other 
marks  of  perfection  which  men  from  ignorance  and 
tradition  are  accustomed  to  esteem  as  such.  But  by 
perfection  I  understand  only  so  much  reality  or  being. 
As  for  example,  I  perceive  that  there  is  more  reality 
in  substance  than  in  modes  or  qualities.  And  so  far, 
I  know  clearly  that  there  is  necessity,  and  a  more  per- 
fect existence  in  the  first  than  in  the  latter  tzvo,  as  is 
evident  from  Axioms  4  and  6. 

COROLLARY. 

Hence  it  follows  that  that  which  absolutely  involves 
a  necessary  existence  is  perfect  Being,  or  God. 


PART  I  39 

Lemma  II. 

He  who  has  the  power  of  conserving  himself,  in- 
volves, by  his  nature,  a  necessary  existence. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

Whoever  has  the  power  of  conserving  himself  has 
also  the  power  of  self-creation  (per  Ax.  10),  that  is, 
(as  all  will  readily  concede),  he  needs  no  external 
cause  of  his  existence,  but  his  own  nature  is  sufficient 
cause  that  he  should  exist,  either  problematically  or 
necessarily.  But  not  problematically;  for  (according 
to  what  I  have  shown  in.  Ax.  10)  from  the  mere  fact 
of  existence  it  does  not  follow  that  an  object  will  con- 
tinue to  exist ;  this  being  contrary  to  the  hypothesis. 
Therefore  necessarily :  that  is,  his  nature  involves 
existence.     Q.  E.  D. 

DEMONSTRATION 

Of  Proposition  VII. 

If  I  had  in  myself  the  power  of  self-conservation 
I  would  by  nature  have  a  necessary  existence  (per 
Lemma  II.),  and  (per  Co-roll.  Lemm.  I.)  ;  my  nature 
would  contain  all  the  attributes  of  perfection.  But  as 
a  thinking  being  I  am  certain  that  there  are  many  im- 
perfections in  me  (per  Schol.  Prop.  4)  as  that  I  doubt, 
I  desire,  etc.  Therefore  I  do  not  have  the  power  of 
self-conservation,  nor  can  I  say  that  I  choose  thus 
to  limit  my  being  for  this  is  clearly  opposed  to  Lemma 
I.  and  to  what  I  actually  experience  in  myself.  (Per 
Ax.5). 

Since  then  it  is  impossible  for  me  to  exist  ex- 
cept as  I  am  conserved,  as  long  as  I  exist,  I  must 
exist  either  by  my  own  power  (provided  I  possess  such 


40     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

power),  or  by  the  power  of  another.  But  I  exist  (per 
Schol.  Prop.  4)  and  yet  have  not  the  power  of  self- 
conservation  as  is  now  positively  proven.  Therefore 
I  am  conserved  by  another ;  but  not  by  a  being  who 
does  not  possess  the  power  of  self-conservation  (for 
the  same  reason  that  I  myself  do  not  possess  this 
power)  ;  therefore  by  some  being  who  has  this  power, 
i.  e.  (per  Coroll.  Lemm.  I.)  by  one  whose  nature 
involves  a  necessary  existence,  and  contains  all  per- 
fection which  I  recognize  as  belonging  to  an  absolutely 
perfect  being.  Therefore  this  perfect  being,  i.  e.,  God, 
exists.     Q.  E.  D. 

COROLLARY. 

God  is  able  to  do  all  that  we  clearly  understand, 
just  as  we  so  understand  it. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

This  all  follows  from  the  preceding  Proposition. 
For  it  was  proven  that  God  does  exist  from  this,  viz., 
that  it  is  necessary  for  some  being  to  exist  in  whom 
is  found  all  the  perfection  we  can  clearly  conceive. 
Moreover,  there  is  in  us  the  idea  of  some  power  so 
great  that  by  it  alone  all  things  exist  which  are  under- 
stood by  me  as  possible,  the  heavens,  the  earth  and 
all  other  things.  Therefore  with  God's  existence  all 
of  these  statements  are  likewise  proven. 

Proposition  VIII. 
Mind  and  body  are  essentially  different. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

Whatever  wc  clearly  conceive,  can  be  realized  by 
God  just  as  we  so  conceive  it  (per  Coroll.  of  the  pre- 


PART  I  41 

ceding).  But  we  clearly  conceive  of  mind,  a  thinking 
substance  (per  Def.  6)  apart  from  body,  i.  e.  (per 
Def.  7),  apart  from  extended  substance  (per  Props. 
3  and  4)  ;  and  vice  versa  body  apart  from  mind  (as 
all  will  concede).  Therefore,  through  divine  power 
mind  can  exist  apart  from  body  and  body  apart  from 
mind. 

Substances  which  can  exist  the  one  apart  from  the 
other  are  essentially  different  (per  Def.  10)  ;  body 
and  mind  are  substances  (per  Defs.  5,  6,  7)  which 
can  so  exist ;  therefore  they  are  essentially  different. 

See  Prop.  4  of  Descartes  in  the  end  of  his  Response 
to  the  Second  Objection;  and  also  what  is  found  in 
Pt.  I.  of  the  Principles,  Arts.  22-29.  F°r  I  consider 
that  these  things  here  do  not  give  the  value  of  the 
work. 

Proposition  IX. 
God  is  omniscient. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

If  you  deny  it,  then  God  either  knows  nothing  or 
only  a  certain  limited  amount.  But  to  understand 
some  things  and  be  ignorant  of  others  implies  a  lim- 
itation to  God's  perfection,  which  is  absurd  (per  Def. 
8).  If  God  understands  nothing,  it  either  indicates 
in  God  a  want  of  intelligence  and  involves  in  Him,  as 
in  men  who  understand  nothing,  an  imperfection, 
which  is  impossible  with  God  (Ibid.),  or  it  indicates, 
which  is  also  repugnant  to  the  idea  of  His  being,  that 
He  understands  only  some  things.  But  if  intelligence 
is  so  denied  to  Him  it  is  impossible  for  Him  to  create 
intellect  (per  Ax.  8).  Since  intellect  is  clearly  and 
distinctlv  conceived  bv  us,  God  is  able  to  be  its  cause 


42     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

(per  Coroll.  Prop.  7).  Therefore,  it  is  far  from 
being  the  case  that  He  understands  only  some  things, 
this  being  opposed  to  God's  perfection.  Therefore, 
God  is  omniscient.     Q.  E.  D. 

SCHOLIUM. 

Although  it  must  be  conceded  that  God  is  incor- 
poreal, as  will  be  proven  in  Proposition  i67  this  does 
not  mean  only  that  all  perfection  of  extension  is  want- 
ing in  Him,  but  only  that  the  imperfections  of  exten- 
sion must  not  be  attributed  to  Him.  The  same  is  true 
of  God's  intelligence,  as  all,  who  wish  to  be  above  the 
rank  and  file  of  philosophers,  will  readily  admit.  This 
will  be  further  explained  in  our  Appendix,  Pt.  II., 
ch.  7. 

Proposition  X. 

Whatever  perfection  is  found  in  God  arises  from 
His  own  being. 


i«^' 


If  you  deny  it,  let  it  be  supposed  that  there  is  some 
perfection  in  God  which  does  not  have  its  source  in 
Himself.  Either  it  would  be  in  God  by  virtue  of  itself 
or  by  virtue  of  something  apart  from  God.  But  if  its 
cause  was  in  itself  it  would  have  a  necessary,  or  at 
least  a  problematical  existence  (per  Lemma  TI.  Prop. 
7),  and  so  far  (per  Coroll.  Lemma  I.  Ibid.),  have  some 
absolute  perfection  and  (per  Def.  8)  thus  be  God. 
If,  therefore,  we  say  that  there  is  some  perfection  in 
God  whose  cause  is  itself,  we  affirm  that  it  arises  from 
God  O.  E.  D.  Put  if  it  has  arisen  from  some  other 
source  than  God,  then  He  is  not  an  absolutely  perfect 
hciner,  which  is  contrary  to  Def.  8.     Therefore  what- 


PART  I  43 

ever  perfection  is  found  in  God  arises  from  His  own 
being.     Q.  E.  D. 

Proposition  XL 
There  are  not  many  gods. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

If  you  deny  this,  conceive,  if  possible,  that  there  are 
many  gods,  for  example  A  and  B.  Then  necessarily 
(per  Prop.  9)  A  as  well  as  B  wTill  be  omniscient;  that 
is,  A  will  understand  all  things  himself  and  B,  and 
likewise  B  will  understand  himself  and  A.  But  since 
A  and  B  exist  necessarily  (per  Prop.  5),  the  cause  of 
the  truth  and  the  necessity  of  the  idea  of  B  which  A 
has  is  B  himself;  and  likewise  the  cause  of  the  truth 
and  the  necessity  of  the  idea  of  A  in  B  is  in  A  him- 
self. Therefore  there  will  be  some  perfection  in  A 
that  is  not  self-caused,  and  likewise  with  B.  And  so 
far  A  and  B  would  not  be  gods.  Therefore  there  is 
only  one  God.     Q.  E.  D. 

It  should  be  noted  here  that  because  there  is  some- 
thing which  in  itself  involves  a  necessary  existence  as 
does  God's  being,  He  is  the  only  being  of  whom  this 
is  true,  as  any  one  who  reflects  carefully  will  clearly 
see.  I  might  also  demonstrate  this,  but  it  is  evident 
in  all  that  I  have  shown  in  this  Proposition. 

Proposition  XII. 

All  existing  things  are  conserved  by  God's  power 
alone. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

If  you  deny  this,  let  it  be  supposed  that  something 
conserves  itself.     Then   (per  Lemma  II.  Prop.  7)   its 


44     PRINCIPLES  OP  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

nature  involves  necessary  existence.  And  so  (per 
Coroll.  Lemma  I.  Prop.  7),  it  would  be  God,  and  there 
would  be  more  than  one  God,  which  is  absurd  (per 
Prop,  supra).  Therefore,  nothing  exists  which  is  not 
conserved  by  God's  power  alone.     Q.  E.  D. 

COROLLARY    I. 

God  is  the  Creator  of  all  things. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

God  (per  the  preceding)  conserves  all  things,  i.  e. 
(per  Axiom  10),  he  has  created  all  things  and  is 
continually  creating  them. 

COROLLARY    II. 

Objects  have  in  themselves  no  essence  which  is  the 
cause  of  God's  knowledge  of  them. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

Since  God's  perfection  is  self-derived  (per  Prop. 
10),  objects  can  have  no  self-caused  essence  which 
could  be  the  cause  of  God's  knowledge  of  them.  On 
the  other  hand,  since  God  has  created  all  things,  not 
from  other  objects,  but  by  the  mere  fiat  of  His  will, 
(per  Prop.  12  with  Coroll.),  and  since  He  knows  no 
other  power  beside  His  own  (for  so  I  define  creation), 
it  follows  that  before  creation  nothing  existed,  and  that 
God  is  the  cause  of  the  essence  of  all  things.     0.  E.  D. 

It  may  be  noted,  also,  that  this  corollary  is  evident 
from  the  fact  that  God  is  the  cause  or  creator  of  all 
things  (per  Coroll.  T.),  and  that  the  cause  must  con- 
tain in  itself  all  the  perfection  of  the  effect  (per  Ax- 
iom 8). 


PART  I  45 


COROLLARY    III. 

It  clearly  follows,  therefore,  that  God  does  not,  prop- 
erly speaking,  perceive  or  form  precepts,  for  His  un- 
derstanding is  not  determined  by  any  external  object, 
but  all  things  arise  from  Himself. 

COROLLARY    IV. 

God's  causality  is  prior  to  the  essence  and  existence 
of  things.  This  clearly  follows  from  Corollaries  I. 
and  II.  above. 

Proposition  XIII. 

God  is  never  a  deceiver,  but  in  all  things  is  perfectly 
true. 

demonstration. 

We  can  attribute  nothing  to  God  in  which  we  find 
any  imperfection  (per  Ax.  8).1  All  deception  (as  is 
evident)  or  desire  of  deceiving,  arises  either  from 
malice  or  fear.  Fear,  moreover,  presupposes  a  limited 
power ;  malice  a  privation  of  some  good.  No  decep- 
tion, therefore,  can  be  ascribed  to  God,  a  being  omnipo- 
tent and  of  perfect  goodness,  but  on  the  contrary,  it 
must  be  agreed  that  He  is  in  no  way  a  deceiver.  Q. 
E.  D.  See  "  Response  to  Second  Objection,"  num- 
ber 4. 

1 1  have  not  put  this  down  as  an  Axiom  with  the  others,  as 
I  could  not  see  the  need  of  so  doing.  I  do  not  use  it  except 
in  demonstrating  this  proposition,  and  also,  while  we  have  not 
yet  proved  God's  existence  I  did  not  wish  to  assume  anything 
as  true  which  I  could  not  deduce  from  the  primary  truth  Ego 
sum  as  I  said  in  Scholium  Prop.  4.  Further,  I  have  not 
given  among  the  others  the  definitions  of  malice  and  fear  for 
no  one  is  ignorant  of  them,  and  I  do  not  use  them  except  in 
this  place. 


46     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 


Proposition  XIY. 
Whatever  we  clearly  and  distinctly  conceive,  is  true. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

The  faculty  we  possess  of  discerning  the  true  from 
the  false  (as  every  one  finds  in  himself  and  is  evident 
from  all  that  has  been  said)  has  been  created  by  God 
and  is  continually  conserved  by  Him  (per  Prop.  12 
and  Coroll.),  that  is  (per  the  above),  by  a  Being  of 
absolute  truth  and  not  a  deceiver.  Neither  has  He 
given  to  us  (as  every  one  knows)  any  power  of  with- 
holding assent  to  what  we  thus  clearly  conceive. 
Wherefore  if  we  are  deceived  in  this,  we  are  deceived 
in  everything  by  God,  and  He  is  a  deceiver,  which,  by 
the  above,  is  absurd.  Therefore,  whatever  we  clearly 
and  distinctly  conceive  is  true.     Q.  E.  D. 

SCHOLIUM. 

Since  those  things  to  which  we  are  constrained  to 
assent  when  we  clearly  and  distinctly  conceive  them 
are  necessarily  true ;  and  since  we  have  the  power  of 
withholding  assent  from  those  things  which  are  ob- 
scure and  doubtful,  and  not  derived  from  certain  prem- 
ises (as  every  one  understands  from  his  own  experi- 
ence), it  clearly  follows  that  we  are  able  to  be  on  our 
guard  lest  we  fall  into  error  and  are  deceived  (which 
will  be  made  clearer  as  we  proceed).  We  may.  in 
this  manner,  determine  in  ourselves  to  affirm  nothing 
which  we  do  not  clearly  and  distinctly  conceive,  or 
which  is  not  deduced  from  certain  premises. 


PART  I  47 


Proposition  XV. 
Error  is  nothing  positive. 


DEMONSTRATION. 

If  error  were  something  positive,  God  would  be  its 
cause,  and  by  Him  it  would  continually  be  procreated 
(per  Prop.  12).  But  this  is  absurd  (per  Prop.  13). 
Therefore  error  is  nothing  positive.     Q.  E.  D. 

SCHOLIUM. 

Since  error  is  nothing  positive  in  man,  its  cause  will 
be  merely  the  lack  of  a  correct  use  of  our  freedom 
(per  Schol.  Prop.  14).  We  cannot  say,  therefore, 
that  God  is  the  cause  of  error  in  any  sense,  except  as 
we  say  the  absence  of  the  sun  is  the  cause  of  dark- 
ness, or  as  we  say  that  God  is  the  cause  of  blindness 
in  a  child  having  all  his  faculties  except  sight.  For 
He  has  given  to  us  understanding  for  a  few  things 
only.  In  order  that  it  may  be  clearly  understood  how 
error  depends  entirely  upon  the  misuse  of  the  will, 
and  how  we  may  be  able  to  avoid  all  error,  we  will 
call  to  mind  the  different  modes  of  thought  which  we 
have,  viz. :  All  modes  of  conception  (as  sensation, 
imagination,  and  pure  cognition)  and  of  volition  (as 
desire,  aversion,  affirming,  denying,  and  doubt)  ;  for 
all  forms  of  thought  may  be  referred  to  these  two 
classes. 

Concerning  these  things  it  may  be  noted:  1.  That 
so  far  as  mind  knows  objects  clearly  and  distinctly 
and  assents  to  them,  it  cannot  be  deceived  (per  Prop. 
14)  ;  and  also  so  far  as  it  knows  things  and  does  not 
assent  to  them.     For,  although   I  can  conceive  of  a 


48     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

winged  horse,  it  is  certain  that  I  do  not  fall  into  error 
as  long  as  I  do  not  assent  to  the  proposition  that  such 
a  creature  exists,  or  even  while  I  am  in  doubt  about 
it.  And  since  to  assent  is  nothing  else  than  to  deter- 
mine the  will,  it  follows  that  error  depends  entirely 
upon  the  use  of  the  will. 

As  now  more  evidently  appears,  it  should  be  noted : 
2.  That  we  not  only  have  the  power  of  assenting  to 
those  things  which  we  clearly  and  distinctly  conceive, 
but  also  of  assenting  to  things  conceived  in  some  other 
way.  For  our  will  is  determined  by  no  limits.  If 
one  but  consider  for  a  moment  it  will  be  evident  that 
if  God  should  choose  to  give  us  infinite  knowledge 
there  would  be  no  necessity  for  bestowing  upon  us  a 
more  ample  power  of  volition  in  order  that  we  might 
approve  all  that  would  be  known  under  such  condi- 
tions. But  the  power  we  now  possess  would  be  suffi- 
cient for  assenting  to  infinite  things.  From  this  we 
learn  that  we  give  our  assent  to  many  things  not  de- 
duced from  certain  principles.  And  further,  it  is  evi- 
dent that  if  knowledge  extended  as  far  as  the  power  of 
volition,  or  if  we  could  not  exercise  our  power  of  vo- 
lition beyond  the  limits  of  understanding,  or  finally, 
if  we  could  but  keep  volition  within  the  bounds  of 
knowledge,  we  should  never  fall  into  error  (per  Prop. 

14). 

We  do  not  have  the  power  of  attaining-  the  first  two 
conditions,  however,  for  that  would  imply  that  the 
will  was  not  created  infinite  in  its  nature  and  the  under- 
standing finite.  The  third  condition  alone  remains, 
viz.,  whether  we  have  the  power  of  limiting  the  action 
of  volition  to  the  limits  of  the  understanding.  Since 
the  will  is  free  to  determine  itself,  it  follows  that  we 
have  the  power  of   restricting  this   faculty   of   assent 


PART  I  49 

within  the  limits  of  understanding.  So,  also,  we  can 
prevent  ourselves  from  falling  into  error.  Whence 
it  is  perfectly  evident  that  whether  or  not  we  fall  into 
error  depends  entirely  upon  the  use  we  make  of  our 
free  will.  That  our  will  is  free  is  demonstrated  in 
Art.  39,  Pt.  I.  of  the  Principles,  and  in  Meditation  4, 
and  in  our  Appendix,  the  last  chapter,  it  is  also  clearly 
shown.  Although  it  is  true  that  when  we  clearly  and 
distinctly  conceive  something  we  cannot  withhold  as- 
sent, this  necessity  of  assent  does  not  depend  upon 
some  defect  in  the  will,  but  upon  its  freedom  and  per- 
fection. For  to  assent  to  the  truth  is  a  mark  of  per- 
fection in  us,  as  is  sufficiently  evident  in  itself;  neither 
is  the  will  ever  more  perfect  or  more  free  than  when 
it  directly  determines  itself.  If  it  were  possible  for 
the  mind  so  to  do,  it  would  give  to  itself  this  same 
perfection,  viz.,  to  assent  necessarily  to  what  is  clearly 
and  distinctly  conceived.  Wherefore  it  is  far  from 
being  the  case,  that  because  we  are  not  indifferent  in 
comprehending  truth,  we  know  we  are  less  free.  On 
the  other  hand,  we  know  that  the  more  indifferent  we 
are  under  such  conditions  the  less  freedom  we  possess. 
It  only  remains  to  show  how,  in  regard  to  man, 
error  is  privation,  and  in  regard  to  God  mere  nega- 
tion. This  we  will  easily  see  if  we  consider  first,  that 
seeing  many  things  beside  those  which  we  understand 
clearly,  we  are  more  perfect  than  if  we  did  not  perceive 
them.  This  is  evident  because,  if  it  be  supposed  that 
we  are  able  to  conceive  nothing  clearly  and  distinctly, 
but  only  confusedly,  we  would  have  nothing  more 
perfect  than  these  confused  concepts,  neither  would 
anything  further  be  desired.  Under  such  conditions, 
to  assent  to  what  we  perceive  only  in  a  confused  way, 
so  far  as  the  act  is  concerned,  would  be  the  perfect 


50     PRINCIPLES  OP  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

thing  to  do.  This  will  be  evident  to  any  one,  if,  as 
above,  he  supposes  that  it  is  repugnant  to  human  na- 
ture to  know  anything  clearly  or  distinctly.  For 
though  he  does  not  attain  to  clearness  in  his  knowl- 
edge, it  is  far  better  to  assent  to  what  is  perceived 
only  confusedly,  and  thus  to  exercise  his  freedom, 
than  to  remain  indifferent,  that  is,  as  will  be  shown, 
to  remain  in  a  lower  degree  of  freedom.  If  we  wish 
to  appeal  to  experience  and  utility,  we  will  find  that 
daily  experience  teaches  this  same  truth. 

Since,  therefore,  all  our  modes  of  thought,  consid- 
ered in  themselves,  are  perfect,  the  source  of  error  is 
not  in  the  understanding.  But  if  we  consider  the 
different  forms  of  volition  as  they  differ  from  one 
another,  some  are  found  to  be  more  perfect  than 
others,  for  there  are  some  that  show  less  indifference 
of  will,  that  is,  are  more  free.  We  know,  also,  that 
as  long  as  we  give  our  assent  to  what  is  not  clearly 
and  distinctly  known,  we  are  rendering  ourselves  the 
more  unfit  to  discern  the  true  from  the  false.  And 
thus  we  do  not  possess  the  highest  liberty.  There- 
fore, to  assent  to  what  is  only  obscurely  perceived,  so 
far  as  it  is  anything  positive,  is  not  in  itself  an  imper- 
fection or  error.  But  it  deprives  us  of  the  highest 
freedom  for  which  we  are  fitted.  All  imperfection  of 
error,  therefore,  consists  in  the  privation  of  the  high- 
est form  of  liberty  and  is  called  error.  It  is  called 
privation  because  it  deprives  us  of  some  perfection 
which  is  consonant  with  our  nature.  It  is  called  error 
because,  from  our  own  fault,  we  are  without  that  per- 
fection which  we  might  possess,  did  we  but  keep,  as 
far  as  possible,  volition  within  the  bounds  of  knowl- 
edge. Since  error  in  men,  therefore,  is  nothing  else 
than  a  privation  of  the  perfect  use  of  freedom,  it  fol- 


PART  I  51 

lows  that  this  freedom  is  not  connected  with  any  fac- 
ulty which  man  has  obtained  from  God,  nor  even  in 
the  operation  of  a  faculty  so  far  as  it  depends  upon 
God.  Nor  can  we  say  that  He  has  deprived  us  of  a 
more  perfect  knowledge  with  which,  in  order  that  we 
should  not  fall  into  error,  He  might  have  endowed 
us.  For  no  one  has  a  right  to  demand  anything  of 
God,  nor  has  an  object  any  properties  except  those 
which  God  of  His  own  free  will  has  given  it.  Noth- 
ing existed  before  the  will  of  God,  nor,  as  we  will 
clearly  show  in  chaps.  7  and  8  of  our  Appendix,  can 
anything  be  conceived  to  have  existed.  God,  there- 
fore, has  no  more  deprived  us  of  a  fuller  understand- 
ing, or  of  the  faculty  of  a  more  perfect  knowledge, 
than  He  has  deprived  the  circle  of  the  properties  of 
the  globe  or  its  periphery  of  the  properties  of  the 
sphere. 

Since,  then,  nothing  in  our  powers,  however  con- 
sidered, reveals  any  imperfection  in  God,  it  clearly 
follows  that  error  in  man  is  nothing  but  privation; 
but  relative  to  God  as  its  cause,  it  is  not  privation, 
but  negation. 

Proposition  XVI. 
God  is  incorporeal. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

Matter  is  the  immediate  subject  of  motion  (per 
Def.  7)  ;  therefore,  if  God  is  corporeal,  He  may  be 
divided  into  parts.  This,  however,  since  it  involves 
an  imperfection,  it  is  absurd  to  affirm. 


52     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 


ANOTHER   PROOF. 

If  God  were  corporeal,  He  might  be  divided  into 
parts  (per  Def.  7).  Now,  either  each  part  would  be 
able  to  subsist  per  se  or  it  would  not.  If  the  former, 
each  part  would  be  similar  to  other  things  erected  by 
God  and  constantly  conserved  by  His  power  (per 
Prop.  10  and  Ax.  11).  These  parts  would  then  per- 
tain no  more  to  the  nature  of  God  than  do  other 
created  objects,  as  is  evident  from  Prop.  5.  But  if 
each  part  exists  by  its  own  power,  they  would  each 
involve  a  necessary  existence  (per  Lemma  II.  Prop. 
7),  and  consequently  would  be  a  perfect  being  (per 
Coroll.  Lemma  II.  Prop.  7).  But  this  also  is  absurd 
(per  Prop.  II.).  Therefore  God  is  incorporeal.  Q. 
E.  D. 

Proposition  XVII. 
God  is  simple  being  (ens  simplissimum). 

DEMONSTRATION. 

If  God  were  composite  in  His  nature,  these  parts, 
as  all  will  readily  concede,  should  be  prior,  even  down 
to  the  most  insignificant  one,  to  the  nature  of  God, 
which  is  absurd  (per  Coroll.  4,  Prop.  12).  There- 
fore God  is  simple  being.     O.  E.  D. 

COROLLARY. 

Hence  it  follows  that  God's  understanding,  His  vo- 
lition, His  decrees  and  His  power  are  only  distinctions 
of  reason. 


PART  I  53 

Proposition  XVIII. 
God  is  unchangeable. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

If  God  were  changeable,  He  would  not  change  in 
part,  but  His  whole  essence  would  change  (per  Prop. 
7).  But  God's  essence  is  necessarily  what  it  is  (per 
Props.  5,  6  and  7)  ;  therefore  God  is  unchangeable. 
Q.  E.  D. 

Proposition  XIX. 
God  is  eternal. 

demonstration. 

God  is  a  perfect  being  (Def.  8),  and  therefore  nec- 
essarily exists.  If  we  attribute  only  a  limited  exist- 
ence to  Him  these  limits  must  be  known,  if  not  by  us, 
by  God  Himself  (per  Prop.  9),  who  is  omniscient. 
But  then  God  who  is  omniscient  (per  Def.  8),  would 
know  no  existence  beyond  these  limits,  which  is  ab- 
surd (per  Prop.  5).  Therefore  God  does  not  have  a 
limited  but  an  infinite  existence,  which  we  call  eter- 
nity. (Via*.  Chap.  I.,  Fart  II.,  of  our  App'cndix.) 
God,  therefore,  is  eternal.     0.  E.  D. 

Proposition   XX. 
God  has  preordained  everything  from  eternity. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

Since  God  is  eternal  (per  Prop.  19),  His  under- 
standing is  eternal  because  it  pertains  to  His  eternal 


54     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES   PHILOSOPHY 

essence  (per  Coroll.  Prop.  7).  Hence  His  under- 
standing, and  His  will,  and  His  decrees  are  one  (Ibid.) 
Therefore  when  we  say  God  knows  all  things  from 
eternity,  we  say  also  that  He  has  willed,  and  decreed 
them  from  eternity.     Q.  E.  D. 

COROLLARY. 

From  this  proposition  it  follows  that  God  is  un- 
changeable in  all  His  works. 

Proposition  XXI. 

Extended  substance  has  three  dimensions,  length, 
breadth  and  depth.  We  are  united  with  each  of  these 
three. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

Extended  substance,  so  far  as  we  clearly  understand 
it,  does  not  pertain  to  the  nature  of  God  (per  Prop. 
10).  It  can,  however,  be  created  by  God  (per  Coroll. 
Prop.  7,  and  per  Prop.  8).  Then  we  clearly  and  dis- 
tinctly perceive  (as  every  thinking  person  knows)  that 
extended  substance  produces  in  us  titulations  or  pain 
and  other  similar  sensations  or  ideas,  at  times  even 
contrary  to  our  desires.  If  we  attempt  to  find  some 
other  cause  of  our  sensations,  as  for  example  God  or 
an  angel,  we  immediately  destroy  the  clear  concept 
which  we  had  before.  Therefore  (Vid.  demonstration 
Prop.  14  and  Schol.  Prop.  15),  as  long  as  we  properly 
attend  to  our  perceptions  and  do  not  admit  what  is  not 
clearly  and  distinctly  known,  we  lose  our  indifference 
and  are  led  to  admit  that  extended  substance  alone  is 
the  cause  of  our  sensations.  So,  also,  we  will  see  and 
admit  that  extended  things  were  created  and  exist  by 


PART  I  55 

God's  power.  In  this  we  are  clearly  not  deceived 
(per  Prop.  14  with  Schol.).  Therefore  it  is  truly 
affirmed  that  extended  substance  has  length,  and 
breadth,  and  depth,  which  was  the  first  point. 

And  further,  as  I  have  already  proven,  we  observe 
great  differences  between  our  various  sensations,  as 
for  example,  when  I  say  I  perceive  or  see  a  tree;  or 
when  I  say  I  am  thirsty,  or  suffer,  etc.  It  is  evident 
that  I  cannot  see  or  understand  the  reasons  for  these 
differences,  unless  I  know  that  as  a  being,  I  am  united 
to  certain  portions  of  matter  and  not  to  others.  When 
I  understand  this  clearly,  and  there  is  no  other  way 
to  know  it,  it  is  evident  that  I  am  united  to  a  certain 
part  of  matter.  This  was  the  second  point,  and  it  is 
now  proven.     Q.  E.  D. 

Note. —  Unless  the  reader  considers  himself  merely 
as  a  thinking  being  and  free  from  his  body,  and  lays 
aside  as  (prejudices  all  the  reasons  he  has  heretofore 
held  as  proving  the  existence  of  the  body,  he  will  a/- 
tempt  in  vain  to  understand  this  demonstration.. 


The  Principles  of  Philosophy  Demonstrated 
by  the  Method  of  Geometry. 

Part  II. 

A  Postulate. 

It  is  only  asked  here  that  each  one  attend  as  accu- 
rately as  possible  to  his  concepts  in  order  to  be  able 
to  distinguish  the  clear  from  the  obscure. 

DEFINITIONS. 

I.  Extension  is  that  which  consists  of  three  dimen- 
sions. We  do  not  understand  by  the  term  the  act  of 
extending  or  anything  else  distinct  from  quantity. 

II.  By  substance  we  understand  that  which  de- 
pends only  upon  the  concurrence  of  God  for  its  exist- 
ence. 

III.  An  Atom  as  a  part  of  matter,  by  nature  is  in- 
divisible. 

IV.  That  is  indefinite,  the  limits  of  which,  if  it 
has  any,  cannot  be  investigated  by  the  human  mind. 

V.  A  vacuum  is  extension  without  corporeal  sub- 
stance. 

VI.  Space  is  distinguished  from  extension  only 
by  the  reason ;  in  reality  they  are  one  and  the  same 
thing.     See  Art.  10,  Pt.  II.  of  the  Principles. 

VII.  That  which  we  understand  to  be  divisible,  is 
divisible,  at  least  potentially. 

57 


58     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

VIII.  Local  motion  is  the  transference  of  a  particle 
of  matter  or  of  a  body  from  the  vicinity  of  other  con- 
tiguous bodies  considered  as  in  a  state  of  rest,  to  the 
vicinity  of  others. 

This  definition  Descartes  used  to  explain  local  mo- 
tion. In  order  to  understand  this  rightly  it  should  be 
noted : 

1.  That  by  a  particle  of  matter  he  understood  all 
that  which  is  transferred  at  the  same  time,  although 
it  may  itself  be  composed  of  many  parts. 

2.  That  to  avoid  confusion  in  this  definition  he 
spoke  only  of  that  which  is  always  in  moving  bodies, 
viz.,  transference,  lest,  as  has  often  happened,  this  be 
confused  with  the  force  or  action  which  transfers 
them.  This  force  or  action,  it  is  generally  believed, 
is  required  only  for  motion  and  not  for  rest,  which 
belief  is  plainly  wrong.  For,  as  is  self-evident,  the 
same  force  is  required  to  give  to  a  body  at  rest  a  cer- 
tain velocity  as  is  required  to  bring  the  same  body 
with  that  given  velocity  to  rest.  This  is  proved  also 
by  experience.  Almost  the  same  force  is  used  in 
starting  a  ship  at  rest  in  quiet  water  as  in  suddenly 
stopping  it  when  in  motion.  Plainly  this  force  would 
be  the  same  except  that  we  are  assisted  in  retarding 
the  motion  of  the  ship  by  the  weight  and  viscosity  of 
the  retarding  water. 

3.  That,  he  says,  the  transference  is  made  from 
the  vicinity  of  contiguous  bodies  to  the  vicinity  of 
others  and  not  from  one  place  to  another.  For  place 
(as  he  himself  explained  Art.  13,  Pt.  2)  is  not  some- 
thing in  the  object,  but  it  depends  upon  our  thought, 
so  much  so  that  the  same  body  may  be  said  at  the  same 
time  to  change  its  place  and  not  to  change  it ;  but  not 
at  the  same  time  to  be  transferred  from  the  vicinity  of 


m 


PART  II  59 

contiguous  bodies  and  not  to  be  transferred.  For 
only  one  body  at  the  same  moment  of  time  can  be 
contiguous  to  the  same  moving  body. 

4.  That  he  did  not  say  absolutely  that  a  transfer- 
ence was  made  from  the  vicinity  of  contiguous  bodies, 
but  only  so  far  as  they  were  considered  to  be  at  rest. 

For  in  order  that  the  body  A  be 
transferred  from  the  body  B  at  rest, 
the  same  force  is  required  whether 
in  this  direction  or  in  that.  This  is 
evident  from  the  example  of  a  boat  aground  or  on 
the  sand  in  shallow  water.  For  in  order  that  the 
boat  may  be  moved  an  equal  force  must  be  exerted 
against  the  boat  and  against  the  ground.  Therefore 
the  force  by  which  bodies  are  moved  is  expended 
equally  on  the  moving  body  and  on  the  one  at  rest. 
The  action  and  the  reaction  are  equal.  If  the  boat  is 
moved  from  the  sand,  the  sand  is  likewise  moved  from 
the  boat.  If,  of  bodies  which  are  mutually  separated, 
the  one  to  this  place,  the  other  to  that,  we  attribute 
equal  motion,  then  regard  one  of  them  as  at  rest,  it  is 
because  the  same  action  is  in  one  as  in  the  other. 
Then  also  even  to  bodies  which  are  regarded  by  all 
as  at  rest,  e.  g.,  the  sand  from  which  the  boat  is  sep- 
arated, we  are  compelled  to  attribute  to  this  a  motion 
equal  to  the  motion  of  the  boat ;  for,  as  we  have  shown, 
the  same  action  is  required  in  the  one  part  as  in  the 
other,  and  the  transposition  is  reciprocal.  But  this 
is  too  much  at  variance  with  the  common  way  of 
speaking.  In  truth,  although,  those  bodies  from 
which  others  are  separated  are  regarded  as  at  rest 
and  are  also  said  to  be  so,  nevertheless  we  affirm  that 
everything  in  the  moving  body  on  account  of  which 
it  is  said  to  be  moving  is  also  in  the  body  at  rest. 


oo     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

5.  Finally,  from  the  definition  it  is  evident  that 
every  body  has  for  itself  its  own  one  proper  motion, 
since  only  in  regard  to  contiguous  quiet  bodies  is  it 
said  to  recede.  Nevertheless,  if  a  moving  body  is  a 
part  of  other  bodies  having  other  motions,  we  clearly 
see  that  it  is  also  able  to  participate  in  these  as  well. 
But  because  so  many  things  can  not  easily  be  under- 
stood, nor  will  all  recognize  this,  it  will  suffice  to  con- 
sider that  alone  which  is  peculiar  to  each  body.  See 
Art.  31,  Pt.  2,  Principles. 

IX.  By  a  circle  of  moving  bodies  we  understand 
such  an  arrangement  that  when  one  is  impelled  by  the 

impulse  of  another  the  last  imme- 
diately touches  the  first  one  of  the 
series ;  although  the  line  described 
by  the  motion  of  these  bodies  may 
plainly  be  contorted. 

AXIOMS. 

To  non-being  there  are  no  properties. 

II.  Whatever  can  be  detracted  from  an  object, 
without  destroying  the  completeness  of  that  object, 
does  not  constitute  its  essence ;  that  which,  when 
taken  away,  destroys  the  object  does  constitute  its  es- 
sence. 

III.  As  to  hardness  sense  indicates  nothing  else, 
nor  do  we  clearly  and  distinctly  know  more  than  that 
the  parts  of  hard  bodies  resist  the  motion  of  our 
hands. 

IV.  Whether  two  bodies  are  mutually  approaching 
one  another,  or  whether  receding,  they  occupy  the 
same  amount  of  space. 

V.  A  particle  of  matter,  whether  it  gives  way  to 
or  resists  another,  does  not  lose  its  character. 


PART  II  61 

VI.  Motion,  rest,  form,  and  similar  ideas  cannot 
be  conceived  without  the  concept  of  extension. 

VII.  Beside  the  sensible  qualities  of  bodies,  noth- 
ing remains  except  extension  and  its  affects  as  given 
in  Part  I.  of  the  Principles. 

VIII.  One  space  or  portion  of  extension  is  no 
greater  than  another. 

IX.  All  extension  can  be  divided,  at  least,  in 
thought.  Concerning  the  truth  of  this  axiom  no  one 
can  doubt  who  has  learned  even  the  elements  of  math- 
ematics. For  the  space  between  a  given  circle  and 
its  tangent  can  always  be  divided  by  an  infinite  num- 
ber of  greater  circles.  Which  is  also  true  as  regards 
the  asymptote  of  the  hyperbole. 

X.  No  ends  of  extension  or  space  can  be  con- 
ceived except  as  another  space  is  conceived  to  imme- 
diately follow  such  limits. 

XL  If  matter  were  manifold  and  one  part  did  not 
immediately  touch  the  other,  each  part  would  neces- 
sarily be  comprehended  under  limits  beyond  which  no 
matter  is  given. 

XII.  A  very  minute  body  easily  recedes  before  the 
motion  of  our  hands. 

XIII.  One  space  does  not  penetrate  another,  nor  is 
the  one  greater  than  the  other. 

XIV.  If  the  tube  A  is  of  equal  length  with  C,  but 
^IfiSSCSE}         C  is  twice  as   large  as  A,   then   if 

-^==^====5^,  some  liquid  flows  through  A  with 
C^^^msS^s?  double  the  velocity  of  that  which 
passes  through  C,  in  the  same  time  an  equal  amount 
will  have  passed  through  each.  And  if,  in  an  equal 
time,  an  equal  quantity  has  passed  through  each,  the 
velocity  through  A  will  be  double  that  of  C. 

XV.  Things  which  agree  in  a  third  part  agree  in 


62     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

the  whole.  And  things  which  are  each  double  a  third 
part  are  equal  to  one  another. 

XVI.  Matter  which  is  moved  in  different  ways 
has  at  least  as  many  divided  parts  as  there  were  degrees 
of  swiftness  observed  at  any  given  time. 

XVTI.  A  straight  line  is  the  shortest  distance  be- 
tween two  points. 

XVIII.  A  body  A  moving  from  C  toward  B,  if  re- 
q  g        pelled   by   a  contrary   impulse,   will 

^-y  move  along  the  same  line  toward  C. 

XIX.  Bodies  having  motions  in  opposite  direc- 
tions, when  they  come  in  contact,  undergo  some 
change. 

XX.  Variation  in  any  object  proceeds  from  a 
stronger  force. 

XXI.  If  when  body  i  is  moved  toward  body  2  and 
impels  it,  and  body  8  from  this  im- 

^  pulse  is  moved  toward   1,  bodies  1, 
2,   3,   etc.,   cannot   be   in   a   straight 
line.     But  all  of  them  from  1  to  8 
compose  a  complete  circle   (Vid.  Def.  9). 

lemma  1. 

Where  there  is  extension  or  space,  there  from  neces- 
sity substance  also  exists. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

Extension  or  space  (per  Ax.  1)  cannot  be  pure 
nothing;  therefore  it  is  an  attribute  which  must  be 
attributed  to  something.  But  not  to  God  (per  Prop. 
16,  Part  I.)  ;  therefore  to  some  object  which  needs 
only  God's  concurrence  for  its  existence  (per  Prop.  12, 
Part  I.),  that  is  (per  Def.  2),  to  substance.     O.  E.  D. 


PART  II 


LEMMA  II. 


We  clearly  and  distinctly  conceive  of  rarefaction 
and  condensation.  We  would  not  concede,  however, 
that  a  body  occupies  more  space  under  rarefaction 
than  tinder  condensation. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

We  can  have  a  clear  and  a  distinct  concept  of  these 
because  we  can  conceive  that  the  parts  of  a  body  mu- 
tually recede,  or  mutually  approach  one  another. 
Therefore  (per  Ax.  4),  they  will  not  occupy  more  or 
less  space.  If  the  parts  of  some  body,  for  example 
a  sponge,  are  compressed  the  bodies  between  the  parts 
will  be  occupied.  What  we  can  thus  clearly  perceive 
occupy  less  space  than  before  (per  Ax.  4).  And  if, 
again,  the  body  expands  and  the  pores  are  filled  by 
some  body,  there  is  a  rarefaction,  but  no  more  space 
will  be  occupied.  What  we  can  thus  clearly  perceive 
by  the  senses  in  the  case  of  the  sponge,  we  can  con- 
ceive by  the  understanding  to  be  true  with  all  bodies, 
although  the  pores  of  these  cannot  be  perceived  by  our 
senses.  Therefore,  rarefaction  and  condensation  are 
clearly  conceived,  etc.     Q.  E.  D. 

It  seemed  best  to  give  this  at  this  place  in  order  to 
overcome  these  prejudices  concerning  space,  rarefac* 
tion,  etc.,  and  in  order  that  the  mind  may  be  ready  to 
understand  what  follows. 

» 

Proposition  I. 


Although  hardness,  weight,  and  the  other  sensible 
qualities  of  a  body  be  removed,  the  whole  nature  of 
that  body  will  nevertheless  remain. 


64     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 


DEMONSTRATION. 

In  the  hardness  of  this  stone,  for  example,  sense 
indicates  nothing  to  us,  nor  can  we  clearly  and  dis- 
tinctly conceive  anything,  except  that  its  parts  resist 
the  movements  of  our  hands  (per  Ax.  3).  There- 
fore (per  Prop.  14,  Part  I.),  hardness  is  nothing  but 
this.  If  that  body  were  pulverized  into  very  small 
particles,  these  parts  would  easily  give  way  (per  Ax. 
12)  ;  nevertheless,  they  do  not  lose  the  nature  of  the 
body  (per  Ax.  5).     Q.  E.  D. 

In  regard  to  weight  and  to  other  sensible  qualities, 
the  same  demonstration  is  valid. 

Proposition  II. 

The  nature  of  body  or  matter  (corporis  sive  mate- 
riae)  consists  in  extension  alone. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

The  nature  of  body  is  not  destroyed  by  the  loss  of 
sensible  qualities  (per  Prop.  1  above)  ;  therefore 
these  do  not  constitute  its  essence  (per  Ax.  2).  Noth- 
ing remains  except  extension  and  its  affects  (per  Ax. 
7).  Therefore,  if  extension  is  destroyed,  nothing  will 
remain  which  pertains  to  the  nature  of  body,  but  it 
is  destroyed;  therefore  (per  Ax.  2),  the  nature  of 
body  consists  in  extension  alone.     0.  E.  D. 

COROLLA RY. 

Space  and  Body  are  the  same. 


PART  II  65 

DEMONSTRATION. 

Body  and  extension  are  the  same  (per  the  preced- 
ing) ;  space  and  extension  are  the  same  thing  (per 
Def.  6)  ;  therefore  (per  Ax.  15),  space  and  body  are 
the  same.     Q.  E.  D. 

SCHOLIUM. 

Although  we  have  said  1  that  God  is  omnipresent 
we  do  not  believe  that  God  is  extension,  that  is,  (per 
the  preceding)  body.  His  omnipotence  pertains 
only  to  his  power  and  his  concurrence  by  which  all 
things  are  conserved.  So  far,  therefore,  His  om- 
nipresence refers  no  more  to  extension  or  body  than 
to  angels  or  to  the  human  mind.  It  should  be  noted, 
too,  that  when  we  say  His  power  is  everywhere  we 
do  not  exclude  His  essence :  for  where  His  power  is, 
there  His  essence  is  also  (Coroll.  Prop.  17,  Part  I.). 
We  would  exclude  corporeality,  that  is,  God  is  not 
everywhere  in  some  corporeal  power,  but  in  divine 
essence,  which  is  common  in  the  preservation  of  ex- 
tension and  in  thinking  being  (Prop.  17,  Part  I.). 
These  He  would  not  be  able  to  perfectly  conserve  if 
His  power  or  essence  were  corporeal. 

Proposition  III. 
It  is  a  contradiction  to  say  that  a  vacuum  exists. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

By  a  vacuum  is  meant  extension  without  corporeal 
substance  (per  Def.  5),  that  is  (per  Prop.  2),  body 
without  body,  which  is  absurd. 

*Vid.  Appendix,  Pt.  II.,  Chaps.  III.  and  IX. 


06     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

For  a  fuller  explanation  of  this  proposition,  and  to 
correct  the  prejudices  men  have  concerning  a 
vacuum,  Articles  17  and  18,  Part  II.  of  the  "  Princi- 
ples," should  be  read.  In  these  it  is  noted  more  espe- 
cially that  bodies  between  which  nothing  intervenes 
necessarily  touch  one  another,  and,  also,  that  there  are 
no  properties  to  non-being. 

Proposition  IV. 

One  particle  of  a  body  occupies  at  one  time  no  more 
space  than  a'nother ;  conversely,  the  same  space  at  a 
given  time  will  contain  no  more  of  one  body  than  of 
another. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

Space  and  body  are  the  same  thing  (per  Coroll. 
Prop.  2)  :  therefore  when  we  say  that  one  portion  of 
space  is  no  larger  than  another  (per  Ax.  13)  we 
affirm  that  a  body  cannot  occupy  more  space  in  one 
place  than  in  another,  which  was  the  first  point  to 
be  proved. 

Further,  from  the  fact  that  space  does  not  differ 
from  body,  it  follows,  that  when  we  say  that  a  body 
cannot  occupy  more  space  in  one  place  than  in  another, 
we  likewise  affirm  that  the  same  space  cannot  contain 
more  of  one  body  than  another.     Q.  E.  D. 

COROLLARY. 

Bodies  which  occupy  an  equal  amount  of  space,  as 
for  example  some  gold  and  some  brass,  have  an  equal 
amount  of  matter  or  of  corporeal  substance. 


PART  II  67 

DEMONSTRATION. 

Corporeal  substance  does  not  consist  in  hardness, 
e.  g.  of  gold,  nor  in  softness,  e.  g.  of  brass,  nor  in 
any  sensible  quality  (per  Prop.  1,  above),  but-  in  ex- 
tension alone  (per  Prop.  2  above).  Moreover,  since 
by  hypothesis  there  is  an  equal  amount  of  space  or 
(per  Def.  6)  of  extension  in  the  one  as  in  the  other, 
there  is  a  like  amount  of  corporeal  substance. 
Q.  E.  D. 

Proposition  V 
There  are  no  Atoms. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

By  their  nature  atoms  are  indivisible  parts  of  mat- 
ter (per  Def.  3).  But  since  the  nature  qf  matter 
consists  in  extension  (per  Prop.  2  above),  which  by 
nature  is  divisible,  however  small  the  part  (per  Ax. 
9  and  Def.  7),  it  follows  that  any  part  of  matter, 
however  small,  is  divisible.  That  is,  there  are  no 
atoms  or  indivisible  parts  of  matter.     Q.  E.  D. 

SCHOLIUM. 

The  question  of  atoms  has  always  been  a  great  and 
an  intricate  one.  Some  affirm  that  atoms  must  exist 
because  one  infinity  cannot  be  greater  than  another ; 
and  if  two  bodies,  A  and  one  double  the  size  of  A, 
are  divisible  to  infinity  by  the  power  of  God,  who 
understands  their  infinite  parts  in  one  intuition,  they 
can  actually  be  so  divided.  Therefore,  as  it  is  said, 
since  one  infinity  is  no  greater  than  another,  one  part 
of  A  will  be  equal  to  one  double  its  size,  which  is 


68     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

absurd.  Then  they  ask  also,  whether  a  part  divided 
half  way  to  infinity  would  still  be  infinite,  and 
whether  it  would  be  equal  or  unequal,  and  other 
things  of  this  kind.  To  this  question  Descartes  re- 
plied that  we  ought  not  to  reject  what  we  properly 
understand  on  account  of  other  things  which  surpass 
our  understanding,  and  which  consequently  cannot 
adequately  be  conceived.  Infinity  and  its  properties 
are  beyond  the  power  of  the  human  intellect,  which 
is  by  nature  finite.  It  would,  then,  be  improper  to 
reject  as  false  what  we  clearly  and  distinctly  con- 
ceive, or  to  doubt  this  because  we  do  not  understand 
the  infinite.  Hence,  Descartes  held  that  those  things 
which  have  no  limits,  such  as  the  extension  of  the 
world  or  the  divisibility  of  a  part  of  matter,  should 
be  called  indefinite.     See  Art.  26,  Part  I.  Principles. 

Proposition  VI. 

Matter  is  indefinitely  extended,  and  is  the  same 
throughout  the  heavens  and  the  earth. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

Point  I.  No  limit  to  extension  or  matter  can  be 
conceived  (per  Prop.  2  above)  except  as  we  conceive 
of  another  space,  that  is  (per  Def.  6),  extension  or 
matter  immediately  following  this  (per  Ax.  10),  and 
so  on  indefinitely ;  which  was  the  first  point  to  be 
proved. 

Point  II.  The  essence  of  matter  consists  in  ex- 
tension   (per   Prop.    2   above),   and   this   is   indefinite 

(per  Point  I.).     That  is   (per  Def.  4),  it  cannot  be 
conceived    to    be    bounded    by    any    limits;    therefore 

(per  Ax.  1  1 "),  it  is  not  manifold  in  its  nature  but  every- 


PART  II  69 

where  one  and  the  same ;  which  was  the  second  point 
to  be  proved. 

SCHOLIUM. 

We  have  already  discussed  the  nature  and  essence 
of  matter.  In  the  last  Proposition  to  Part  I.  we 
showed  that  matter  created  by  God's  power  exists,  as 
it  is  conceived  by  us,  and  from  Proposition  12  of  the 
same  part  it  follows  that  it  is  conserved  by  the  same 
power  that  created  it.  Also,  in  the  last  Proposition  to 
Part  I.  we  showed  that  so  far  as  we  are  thinking 
beings,  we  are  united  to  some  part  of  matter.  Hence, 
we  are  certain  that  all  the  changes  in  matter  are  real, 
which  we,  by  the  contemplation  of  matter,  perceive 
as  possible.  As,  for  example,  that  matter  is  divisible 
or  capable  of  motion,  that  there  may  be  a  transfer- 
ence of  some  parts  of  matter  from  one  place  to  an- 
other, which,  indeed,  we  clearly  and  distinctly  know, 
provided  we  understand  that  other  parts  take  the  place 
of  those  which  are  moved.  This  division  and  motion 
is  conceived  by  us  in  infinite  modes,  hence  an  infinite 
variation  of  matter  is  conceived  as  possible.  I  say  that 
these  things  are  clearly  and  distinctly  conceived  by  us 
(as  was  clearly  explained  in  Part  I.  of  the  Principles) 
so  long  as  they  are  regarded  as  modes  of  extension,  and 
not  as  objects  apart  from  extension.  And  although 
some  philosophers  conceive  of  many  forms  of  motion, 
we  only  admit  that  there  is  local  motion.  For  it  is  evi- 
dent to  us,  who  admit  only  what  is  clearly  and  distinctly 
perceived,  that  extension  is  capable  only  of  local  mo- 
tion, neither  can  any  other  form  be  imagined. 

Zeno,  indeed,  it  is  said,  for  various  reasons  denied 
that  there  was  motion  in  space  (motum  localum), 
which  assertion  the  cynic  Diogenes  refuted  in  a  char- 


70     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 


acteristic  way,  namely,  by  walking  about  in  the  school 
where    Zeno   was   teaching,    and   thus    disturbing   his 
pupils.     When    he   was    asked   by    a   certain   listener 
to  stop  his  walking  he  began  to  find  fault  with  him 
by   saying :   "  Why   do   you   thus   dare   to   refute   the 
teaching  of   your  master?"     But  lest  any   one,   per- 
chance,  deceived  by   this   argument  of  Zeno,   should 
think  that  the  senses  show  anything  to  us,  as  for  ex- 
ample motion,   which  is  at  variance  with  the  under- 
standing,  so   that  the   mind   is   deceived   about  those 
things,  which,  by  the  help  of  the  intellect  are  perceived 
clearly  and  distinctly,  I  shall  give  his  principal  rea- 
sons, and  show  that  these  are  only  supported  by  false 
prejudices;  namely,  because  he  had  no  true  concept  of 
matter. 

In  the  first  place  it  is  said  that  he  argued  that  if 
there  is  motion  in  space,  the  motion  of  a  body  moving 
in  a  circle  with  the  greatest  possible  speed  does  not 
differ  from  a  body  at  rest ;  and  this  is  absurd,  there- 
fore, that  also.  Consequently,  he  affirmed  this. 
That  body  is  at  rest,  all  of  whose  parts  constantly  re- 
main in  the  same  place ;  but  all  the  parts  of  a  body 
moving  in  a  circle  with  the  greatest  possible  velocity 
constantly  remain  in  the  same  place.     Therefore,  etc., 

This,  it  is  said,  he  explained  by  the 
example  of  a  wheel,  for  example 
A,  B,  C.  Which,  if  it  moves  with 
a  certain  velocity  about  its  center, 
the  point  A  will  move  more  rapidly 
through  the  points  B  and  C  than 
if  it  rotated  more  slowly.  Let  it  be 
supposed  for  example,  that  when  moving  slowly  for  an 
hour,  the  point  A  occupies  the  same  point  as  when  it 
began.     Tf  it  moves  with  double  this  velocity,  in  a  half- 


PART  II  71 

hour  it  will  occupy  the  same  point,  and  if  with  a  ve- 
locity four  times  as  great,  then  in  a  quarter  of  an  hour. 
If,  now,  we  conceive  that  the  velocity  is  increased  to  in- 
finity, and  the  time  to  be  diminished  even  to  a  mo- 
ment, then  the  point  A,  moving  with  this  infinite 
velocity  every  moment,  or  continually,  will  be  in  the 
place  from  which  it  began  to  move.  So  far  it  will 
always  remain  in  the  same  place.  And  this,  which  is 
true  of  the  point  A,  is  also  true  of  every  other  point 
of  the  wheel.  Therefore,  all  points  of  a  body  moving 
with  the  highest  velocity  remain  in  the  same  place. 

Indeed,  as  I  would  reply,  it  should  be  noted  that  this 
is  more  an  argument  against  infinite  motion  than 
against  motion  itself.  We  shall  not,  however,  inquire 
whether  Zeno  argued  rightly,  but  rather  would  detect 
those  prejudices  on  which  the  whole  argument  rests 
so  far  as  he  thought  this  to  annul  the  idea  of  motion. 
In  the  first  place  it  is  supposed  that  a  body  may  be 
conceived  to  be  moving  so  fast  that  a  greater  velocity 
is  impossible.  Then,  again,  it  is  supposed  that  time 
is  composed  of  moments,  as  some  think  that  quantity 
is  made  up  of  indivisible  points.  Both  suppositions 
are  false.  For  we  are  not  able  to  conceive  of  a  motion 
than  which  there  can  be  no  greater.  It  is  contrary  to 
reason  to  think  there  is  a  motion,  however  small  the 
line  it  describes,  so  rapid  that  no  more  rapid  one  can 
be  given.  The  same  thing  holds  true  in  regard  to 
slowness.  For  it  implies  that  we  can  conceive  of  a 
motion  so  slow  that  a  slower  one  can  not  be  given. 
Concerning  time  also,  which  is  a  measure  of  motion, 
we  affirm  that  the  same  thing  is  true,  and  that  it  is 
contrary  to  reason  to  think  of  a  time  so  short  that  no 
shorter  can  be  given.  All  of  which,  as  we  will  prove, 
follows  from  the  words  of  Zeno.     Let  it  be  supposed, 


72    PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

therefore,  as  he  said,  that  the  wheel  A,  B,  C,  rotates 
with  such  speed  that  the  point  A  at  all  moments  is 
in  the  point  A  from  which  it  moves.  I  say  that  I  can 
clearly  conceive  that  this  swiftness  is  indefinitely  in- 
creased and  these  moments  of  time  to  be  diminished 
in  inverse  ratio.  For  let  it  be  supposed  that  while 
the  wheel  A,  B,  C,  is  rotating,  another  wheel,  D,  E, 
F,  (which  I  suppose  half  as  large  as  the  other),  is 
made  to  rotate  by  the  chord  H.  Since  the  wheel  D, 
E,  F  is  only  half  the  size  of  A,  B,  C,  it  is  evident 
that  the  first  one  will  rotate  twice  as  fast  as  the  latter. 
Then  if  the  wheel  A,  B,  C  is  supposed  to  have  the 
motion  of  D,  E,  F,  the  movement  of  D,  E,  F  will  be 


C 

four  times  the  original  motion  of  A,  B,  C.  And  if 
we  suppose  this  motion  of  D,  E,  F  to  be  given  to  A, 
B,  C,  the  motion  of  D,  E,  F  will  be  eight  times  the 
motion  of  our  original  wheel.  And  so  on  to  infinity. 
This  is  perfectly  evident  from  the  very  concept  of 
matter.  For  as  we  have  proven  the  essence  of  mat- 
ter consists  in  extension  or  in  space  always  divisible. 
There  is  no  motion  except-  in  space.  We  showed  also 
that  the  same  part  of  matter  cannot  occupy  two  points 
of  space  at  the  same  time.  This  would  be  equal  to 
saying  that  one  part  of  matter  is  equal  to  another  pari 
twice  its  size.  Therefore,  if  a  particle  of  matter  is 
moved  it  is  moved  through  some  space.  This  space, 
and  the  time  that  serves  to  measure  this  as  well,  how- 


PART  II  73 

ever  small  they  be  conceived  to  be,  will  always  be 
divisible.     Q.  E.  D. 

We  turn  now  to  another  argument  of  the  same 
nature.  If  a  body  is  moved,  does  it  move  in  the  place 
in  which  it  is,  or  in  some  other?  It  does  not  move 
in  the  place  where  it  is,  for  if  it  is  any  where  it  is 
necessarily  at  rest.  Neither  can  it  move  in  a  place 
where  it  is  not.  Therefore,  a  body  does  not  move. 
This  argument  is  plainly  similar  to  the  first,  for  it 
also  supposes  that  there  is  a  time  given  than  which 
there  can  be  no  smaller.  For  if  you  reply  that  a  body 
does  not  move  in  the  place  it  is,  but  from  that  place  to 
another,  he  will  ask  whether  it  does  not  also  move 
through  the  intervening  places.  We  reply  by  mak- 
ing a  distinction  —  if  through  the  term  was  we  un- 
derstand to  be  at  rest  then  we  deny  that  the  body  was 
at  any  of  the  places  through  which  it  moved :  but  if  by 
was  existence  is  meant,  then  we  say  that  it  necessarily 
existed  in  that  point  although  it  was  moving.  But  he 
would  also  ask  whether  it  existed  any  where  while 
it  was  moving.  We  reply,  if  he  meant  to  ask  whether 
the  body  remained  in  any  one  place,  that  it  did  not; 
but  if  he  wished  to  ask  whether  it  changed  its  position, 
we  reply  that  it  has,  through  all  the  points  in  the  given 
distance.  Then  he  would  inquire  whether  it  could 
occupy,  and  move  from  a  point  at  the  same  moment 
of  time.  To  this  we  reply  by  making  another  dis- 
tinction. If  by  a  moment  of  time  he  understands  a 
duration  so  short  that  no  shorter  is  conceivable,  as 
was  shown  above,  he  asks  a  question  that  is  not  in- 
telligible, and  hence  unworthy  of  reply. 

But  if  he  take  time  in  the  true  sense  explained 
above,  however  small  the  duration  assigned,  it  will 
never  be  so  small  that  a  body  may  not  both  occupy  it 


74     PRINCIPLES  OP  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

and  be  moving  at  the  same  time.  This  is  evident  to 
any  one  who  considers  the  matter.  For  it  is  evident, 
as  we  said  above,  that  he  supposes  a  time  given  than 
which  no  smaller  is  possible.  Hence,  he  proves 
nothing. 

Beside  these  two  there  is  another  argument  of  Zeno 
which,  together  with  its  refutation,  is  given  in 
Descartes   (Vol.  I.  "  Epis./5  last  letter  but  one). 

I  wish  here  to  remind  the  reader  that  my  argument 
is  opposed  to  the  reasonings  of  Zeno ;  and  that  as  far 
as  he  argued  from  reason  not  from  sense,  he  followed 
the  argument  of  Diogenes.  Nor  does  sense  ever  give 
any  truth  to  the  inquirer,  except  the  mere  phenomena 
of  Nature,  whose  causes  he  is  impelled  to  investigate ; 
never  does  it  show  anything  to  be  false  which  the 
understanding  clearly  comprehends  as  true.  So  we 
believe,  and  so  far  this  is  our  Method : — to  demon- 
strate the  things  we  set  forth,  by  reasons  clearly  and 
distinctly  perceived  by  the  understanding ;  holding 
to  these,  whatever  the  senses  may  give  that  seems 
contrary  to  this ;  which,  as  we  have  said,  can  only  de- 
termine the  understanding  as  it  inquires  about  this  or 
that,  but  cannot  prove  the  falsity  of  anything  which 
is  clearly  and  distinctly  perceived. 

Proposition  VII. 

No  body  moves  to  the  place  of  another,  except  as 
that  other  moves  into  the  position  of  some  other. 

DEMONSTRATION.1 

If  you  deny  this,  let  it  be  supposed,  if  possible,  that 
a  body  A  take  the  position  of  a  body  B,  and  is  equal 

1  Vid.  Fig-.  Prop.  seq. 


PART  II 


75 


to  it,  and  also  that  B  does  not  recede  from  its  place. 
Then  the  space  which  before  only  contained  B  (by 
hypothesis)  will  contain  A  and  B,  and  so  twice  as 
much  corporeal  substance  as  it  before  contained. 
Which  (per  Prop.  4  of  this  Part)  is  absurd.  There- 
fore, no  body  can  take  the  place  of  another,  etc. 
Q.  E.  D. 

Proposition  VIII. 

When  some  body  takes  the  place  of  another,  at  the 
same  moment  the  place  left  by  the  one  is  occupied  by 
another  which  is  immediately  contiguous  to  it. 


SB= 


wm. 


DEMONSTRATION. 

If  the  body  B  moves  toward  D,  either  the  bodies 
A  and  C  mutually  approach  and  touch  one  another, 
or  they  do  not.  If  they  mutually  approach  and  are 
contiguous  the  question  is  conceded.  If  they  do  not 
approach  one   another,   but  the   space  left  by   B   lies 

between  them,  then  (per  Coroll. 
Prop.  2  supra,  and  Coroll.  Prop. 
4)  some  body  equal  to  B  lies  be- 
tween. But  (per  hypothesis)  not 
B :  therefore,  some  other  body, 
which  at  the  same  moment  takes 
its  place.  But  since  it  is  at  the 
same  moment  it  is  no  other  than  the  one  immediately 
contiguous  (per  Schol.,  Prop.  6).  There  it  was 
shown  that  there  can  not  be  motion  from  one  place 
to  another  which  does  not  require  a  duration  than 
which  a  shorter  may  always  be  conceived.  Hence, 
it  follows  that  the  space  of  the  body  B  cannot  be 
occupied  at  the  same  moment  by  a  body  which  must 


B 


D 


76    PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

be  moved  from  some  other  position.  Therefore,  only 
the  body  immediately  contiguous  to  B  can  occupy  this 
space  at  the  given  moment.     0.  E.  D 

SCHOLIUM. 

Since  the  parts  of  matter  are  really  distinct  from 
one  another  (per  Art.  6i,  Part  I.  Principles),  one 
part  can  exist  apart  from  the  other  (per  Coroll. 
Prop.  7,  Part  I.)  and  they  are  not  dependent  upon  one 
another.  Therefore,  all  the  fancies  about  sympathy 
and  antipathy  should  be  rejected  as  false.  And 
further,  since  the  cause  of  an  effect  must  be  positive 
(per  Ax.  8,  Part  I.)  we  can  not  say  that  the  cause 
of  motion  is  a  vacuum,  but  that  it  is  due  to  the  im- 
pulse of  some  other  body. 

COROLLARY. 

In  all  motion  the  zvholc  circle  of  bodies  is  moved. 

DEMONSTRATION 

At  the  moment  when  body  i  takes  the  place  of  body 
2,  this  one  must  move  into  place  of  body  3,  etc.  (per 
Prop.  7).     Then  at  the  moment  when  1  is  occupying 

the  place  of  2,  the  place  it  formerly 
held  must  (per  Prop.  8)  be  filled 
by  some  other  body,  for  example 
by  8,  or  some  other  body  contigu- 
ous to  I.  But  since  this  can  only  come  from  the  im- 
pulse of  another  body  (per  Schol.  sup.)  which  is  here 
supposed  to  be  1,  the  series  cannot  lie  in  a  straight 
line  (per  Ax.  2t)  but  (per  Def.  9)  describes  a  com- 
plete circle.     O.  E.  D. 


PART  II 


77 


Proposition  IX. 

//  a  circular  canal,  A,  B,  C,  is  filled  with  water  or 
with  some  other  fluid,  and  at  A  the  canal  is  four  times 
as  broad  as  at  B,  when  the  water  (or  liquid)  at  A 
begins  to  move  toward  B,  the  water  at  B  will  move 
four  times  as  fast  as  the  water  at  A. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

When  the  water  at  A  moves 
toward  B,  the  water  at  C,  which 
is    contiguous    to    A,    takes    its 
place   (per  Prop.  8)  ;  then  from 
B  an  equal  quantity  must  replace 
that  at  C.  (per  eanclem).     There- 
fore (per  Ax.  14),  it  will  move 
four  times  as  fast.     Q.  E.  D. 
What  we  have  just  said  concerning  circular  chan- 
nels is  also  true  of  all  unequal  spaces  through  which 
water  is  forced.     For  the  proof  would  be  the  same  in 
all  such  cases. 


Lemma. 

If  two  semicircles  are  described  from  the  same  cen- 
ter, as  for  example  A  and  B,  the  distance  between 
them  is  equal  at  all  points.     But  if  they  are  described 


from  different  centers  as  are  C  and  D.  the  distance 
between  them  is  unequal  at  all  points.  This  is  evident 
from  the  definition  of  the  circle. 


78     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

Proposition  X. 

A  fluid  body  moving  through  the  channel  A,  B,  C, 
changes  its  velocity  by  indefinite  degrees. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

(Vid.  Figure  to  Prop.  IX).  The  space  between  A 
and  B  is  unequal  at  all  points  (per  Lemm.  sup.)  ; 
therefore  (per  Prop.  9)  the  velocity  with  which  a  fluid 
moves  through  this  channel  is  everywhere  unequal. 
And  since  we  can  conceive  that  the  space  between  A 
and  B  to  be  indefinitely  divided  (per  Prop.  5),  the 
inequalities  also  will  be  indefinitely  changing  and  also 
(per  Prop.  9)  the  motion  by  indefinite  degrees.  Q. 
E.  D. 

Proposition  XL 

In  the  matter  which  passes  through  the  channel  A, 
B,  C,  there  is  a  division  into  indefinitely  small  parts. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

(Vid.  Fig.  Prop.  9).  The  matter  flowing  through 
A,  B,  C,  has  a  motion  changing  by  indefinite  degrees 
(per  Prop.  10)  ;  therefore  (per  Ax.  16)  its  parts  must 
be  indefinitely  divided  O.  E.  D.  See  also  Articles  34 
and  35,  Part  II.  "  Principles." 

SCHOLIUM. 

We  have  already  spoken  of  the  nature  of  motion. 
Tt  behooves  us  here  to  inquire  into  its  cause,  which 
is  twofold :  the  primary  or  general  cause,  which  is  the 
cause  of  all  the  motion  in  the  world,  and  then  more 
specifically,  how  does  it  happen  that  particular  objects 


PART  II  79 

which  have  no  motion,  acquire  it.  Regarding  the  gen- 
eral cause  of  motion  it  is  clear,  since  we  ought  not  to 
admit  anything  except  what  is  clearly  and  distinctly 
perceived  (per  Prop.  14,  Pt.  I.  and  Schol.  Prop.  17, 
Pt.  II.),  and  since  we  understand  no  other  cause  except 
God  (the  creator  of  matter),  that  no  other  general 
cause  of  motion  can  be  admitted  except  God.  And 
what  we  have  said  of  motion  is  also  true  of  rest. 

Proposition  XII. 
God  is  the  'principal  cause  of  motion. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

See  the  Scholium  just  given. 

Proposition  XIII. 

God  by  his  pozver  conserves  the  same  quantity  of 
motion  and  rest  which  he  once  gave  to  matter. 

demonstration. 

Since  God  is  the  cause  of  motion  and  of  rest  (per 
Prop.  12),  he  conserves  these  by  the  same  power  by 
which  he  also  created  them  (per  Ax.  10  Pt.  I.),  and 
indeed  with  the  same  amount  of  power  (per  Coroll. 
Prop.  20,  Pt.  I.)  Q.  E.  D. 

SCHOLIUM. 

I.  Although,  in  Theology,  it  is  said  that  God  does 
many  things  because  He  is  pleased  to  do  so,  and  to 
show  His  power  to  man,  since  these  acts  are  known 
only  through  divine  revelation,  they  should  not  be 
admitted  into  the  body  of  philosophical  truth  where 


80    PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

reason   is   the   criterion   of  truth,   lest   Theology   and 
Philosophy  become  confused. 

II.  Although  motion  is  nothing  but  a  mode  of  a 
moving  body,  nevertheless,  it  has  a  certain  definite 
quantity.  How  this  is  possible  will  appear  below. 
See  Art.  36,  Pt.  II.  of  the  "  Principles." 

Proposition  XIV. 

Every  object,  so  far  as  it  is  simple  and  individual 
considered  in  itself  alone,  has  a  certain  unchanging 
quantity. 

To  many  this  proposition  is,  as  it  were,  an  axiom ; 
nevertheless  we  will  give  a  demonstration  of  its  truth. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

Since  an  object  can  exist  in  a  certain  state  only  by 
the  concurrence  of  God  (per  Prop.  12,  Pt.  I.),  and 
since  God  is  unchanging  in  all  His  works  (per  Coroll. 
Prop.  20,  Pt.  I.),  if  we  consider  no  external  causes 
(i.  e.,  particular  ones)  but  consider  the  object  in  itself, 
it  must  be  admitted  that  its  quantity  always  remains 
the  same.     O.  E.  D. 

COROLLARY. 

A  body  when  once  in  motion  will  continue  to  mo:'c 
unless  hindered  by  some  external  forces. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

This  is  evident  from  the  preceding  Proposition. 
Nevertheless  for  correcting  certain  prejudices  concern- 
ing motion  read  Articles  37  and  38,  Part  IT.  "  Prin- 
ciples." 


PART  II  81 

Proposition  XV. 

Every  moving  body,  in  itself,  tends  to  move  in  a 
straight  line  not  in  a  curved  one.  This  proposition 
might  be  given  as  an  axiom  but  I  will  demonstrate  it 
from  the  preceding  ones. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

Motion  since  it  has  God  alone  as  its  cause  (per  Prop. 
12,  Pt.  II.)  has  in  itself  no  power  of  existence  (per 
Ax.  10,  Pt.  I.),  but  is,  as  it  were,  procreated  every 
single  moment  by  God  (per  that  which  was  demon- 
strated with  the  axiom  just  cited).  Therefore,  as  long 
as  we  consider  the  mere  nature  of  motion  we  cannot 
attribute  to  it,  as  pertaining  to  its  nature,  a  duration 
so  great  that  a  greater  may  not  be  conceived.  But 
if  it  is  said  that  it  pertains  to  the  nature  of  a  mov- 
ing body  to  move  in  a  curved  line,  a  longer  duration  is 
attributed  to  the  nature  of  motion  than  if  it  is  sup- 
posed to  be  the  nature  of  motion  to  move  in  a  straight 
line  (per  Ax.  8).  Since  (as  we  have  already  demon- 
strated) we  cannot  assign  such  a  duration  to  the 
nature  of  motion,  we  cannot  suppose  that  it  is  in  the 
nature  of  a  moving  body  to  move  in  a  curved  line 
but  it  must  tend  to  move  in  a  straight  line.     O.  E.  D. 

SCHOLIUM. 

To  many,  perhaps,  this  demonstration  will  not  seem 
to  prove  that  a  moving  body  tends  to  describe  a  straight 
line  rather  than  a  curved  one,  for  no  straight  line  can 
be  assigned  so  small  that  there  may  not  be  a  smaller 
either  curved  or  straight,  neither  is  there  any  curved 
line  so  small  that  there  may  not  also  be  another  curved 


82     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

one  still  smaller.  Although  I  have  considered  these 
objections  I  do  not  consider  them  to  be  valid.  For 
we  have  based  our  conclusion  upon  the  universal 
essence  of  these  lines,  not  upon  the  quantity  of  each 
or  accidental  differences.  But  that  I  may  not  in  this 
demonstration  render  obscure  what  is  clear,  I  refer  the 
reader  to  the  definition  of  motion,  which  affirms  nothing 
of  motion  except  a  transference  of  one  part  of  matter 
from  one  vicinity  to  the  position  of  others,  etc.  This 
is  true  so  far  as  we  conceive  of  a  simple  trans- 
ference, that  is,  that  this  is  made  in  a  straight  line. 
So  far  as  we  go  beyond  this  we  assign  something  to 
motion  which  is  not  in  the  definition  and  so  far  does 
not  pertain  to  its  nature. 

Corollary. 

From  this  it  follows  that  every  body  moving  in  a 
curved  line  is  continually  deflected  from  the  line  which 
it  tends  to  follow.  This  is  done  by  some  external 
force  (per  Prop.  14,  Pt.  II.). 

Proposition  XVI. 

Every  body  moving  in  a  circular  orbit,  as  for  ex- 
ample a  stone  in  a  sling,  tends  constantly  to  move  off 
at  a  tangent. 


DEMONSTRATION. 

A  body  moving  in  a  circumference  is  continuously 
restrained  by  some  external  force  from  moving  in  a 
straight  line  (per  Coroll.,  Prop.  XV.  Pt.  II.).  When 
this  ceases  to  act  the  body  at  once  moves  off  in  a 
straight  line  (per  Prop.  15).  T  say  also,  that  a  body 
describing  a  circle  continually  tends  to  move  off  at  a 


PART  II 


8; 


tangent.     For,  if  you  deny  it  let  it  be  supposed  that 

the  stone,  for  example,  in 
the  sling  at  B,  does  not 
tend  to  follow  the  line 
BD,  but  some  other  line, 
either  within  or  without 
the  circle,  for  example, 
BF.  Or  the  line  BG 
(which  I  understand  inter- 
sects the  line  BH,  drawn 
from  the  center  of  the  circle  at  B  and  makes 
with  it  an  angle  equal  to  the  angle  FBFI),  if  it  is 
supposed  that  the  sling  is  moving  from  C  toward  B. 
But  if  the  stone  moving  from  L  to  B  at  B,  tends  to 
move  in  the  line  BF,  then  (per  Axiom  18)  when  the 
sling  moves  from  C  toward  B,  it  should  tend  to  move 
toward  K,  not  toward  G,  which  is  contrary  to  the 
hypothesis.  And  since  there  is  no  line  that  can  be 
drawn  through  the  point  B  except  the  tangent  AD, 
which  keeps  the  angles  DBH,  and  ABH  equal,  there 
is  no  line  except  this  tangent  able  to  fulfil  the  hypo- 
thesis, when  the  sling  is  moving  either  from  L  to  B 
or  from  C  to  B.  Therefore  no  other  line  except  the 
tangent  can  be  drawn  on  which  the  body  tends  to  move. 
Q.  E.  D. 

ANOTHER  DEMONSTRATION.1 

In  place  of  a  circle  let  the  hexagon  A,  B,  H,  be 
inscribed  in  a  circle  and  a  body  C  be  at  rest  on  one 
side  AB.  Then  let  the  ruler  DBE  (one  end  fixed  at 
D  and  the  other  end  free)  be  moved  about  the  center 
D,  continually  intersecting  the  line  AB.  It  is  evident 
that    if    the    ruler   DBE,    while   it    is    thus    conceived 

1  The  letter  A  at  the  intersection  of  the  circle  and  the  hexa- 
gon between  B  and  G  is  omitted  in  the  Latin  text. 


84     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 


to  move  meet  some  body  at  C,  when  the  ruler  inter- 
sects  the   line   AB   at   a   right  angle   it   will   tend   to 

move  C  in  the  line  FBAG 
toward  G,  that  is,  along  the 
line  AB  produced  indefinite- 
ly. Indeed,  since  we  can  con- 
sider the  number  of  sides  of 
the  polygon  to  be  increased  ad 
libitum,  it  can  be  affirmed  of 
any  figure  whatever  that  can 
be  inscribed  in  a  circle  that 
when  a  body  C  at  rest  on  one 
of  its  sides,  is  impelled  by  a  ruler  fixed  at  the  center, 
when  the  angle  found  by  the  side  of  the  polygon  and 
the  ruler  is  a  right  angle,  the  body  will  tend  to  move 
in  the  line  of  that  side  indefinitely  produced. 

Let  us  conceive  instead  of  the  hexagon  a  polygon 
of  an  infinite  number  of  sides  (that  is,  the  circle  ac- 
cording to  the  definition  of  Archimedes)  ;  then  it  is 
clear  that  wherever  the  ruler  shall  come  in  contact 
with  the  body  C,  it  would  always  meet  it  at  a  right 
angle.  Hence  it  would  never  come  in  contact  with  C, 
without  C  at  the  same  time  tending-  to  move  in  the 
line  of  that  side  produced.  Any  side  whatever  when 
produced  will  lie  wholly  outside  the  figure,  and  this 
side  indefinitely  produced  is  the  tangent  of  one  side 
of  the  figure  of  an  infinite  number  of  sides,  that  is,  of 
a  circle.  Therefore  if  we  think  of  sling  moving  in  a 
circle  in  place  of  the  ruler  the  stone  will  constantly 
tend  to  move  in  a  tangent  to  that  circle.     Q.  E.  D. 

77  should  be  noted  that  this  demonstration  ean  be  ap- 
plied to  any  curved  figure. 


PART  II 


85 


Proposition  XVII. 

Every  body  moving  in  a  circle  tends  to  move  from 
the  center  of  the  circle  it  describes. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

As  long  as  a  body  is  moving  in  a  circular  path,  so 
long  is  it  held  in  its  course  by  some  external  force ; 
this  force  being  removed  it  at  once  begins  to  move 

off  at  a  tangent  (per  the 
above)  all  of  whose  points 
except  that  which  touches  the 
circle  fall  outside  of  the  circle 
(per  Prop.  16,  Lib.  3,  Ele- 
ments), and  so  are  further 
removed  from  the  center  of 
its  path.  Therefore,  when 
the  stone  in  the  sling  EA,  is  at  the  point  A  it  will 
tend  to  move  along  a  straight  line  whose  points  are 
all  further  from  the  center  E  than  those  of  the  circum- 
ference LAB.  This  is  to  do  nothing  else  than  to 
recede  from  the  circle  which  it  is  describing.  O. 
E.  D. 


Proposition  XVIII. 

//  some  body  A  is  moved  against  another  body  B  at 
rest,  and  B  acquires  no  motion  from  the  impact,  then 
A  has  lost  none  of  its  motion  but  retains  all  it  had 
before. 


demonstration. 

If  you  deny  it,  let  it  be  supposed 
that  A  has  lost  some  of  its  motion 
but  has  not  transferred  it  to  another 
body  as,  for  example,  B.  If  this  happens  there  will  be 
less  motion  in  Nature  than  before  which  is  absurd  (per 


86     PRINCIPLES  OP  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

Prop.  13).  The  demonstration  in  respect  to  the  rest  in 
B  is  the  same.1  Therefore  if  no  motion  is  transferred 
B  will  be  in  the  same  state  of  rest  and  A  will  retain 
the  same  amount  of  motion.     Q.  E.  D. 

Proposition  XIX. 

Motion,  considered  in  itself,  by  its  own  determina- 
tion moves  in  a  given  direction;  nor  is  there  any  need 
for  a  moment  of  rest  before  it  can  change  its  direction 
or  be  repelled. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

Let  it  be  supposed  as  in  the  preceding  proposition 
that  a  body  A  is  moved  directly  against  B  and  im- 
peded by  B  but  that  B  is  not  moved.  Therefore  (by 
the  above)  A  will  retain  all  of  its  motion,  nor  does  it 
remain  at  rest  even  for  a  moment.  Nevertheless  when 
it  moves  it  does  not  move  in  the  same  direction  as 
before,  for  it  is  supposed  to  be  impeded  by  the  body 
B.  Therefore  its  motion  remaining  entire  and  its 
prior  determination  being  lost  it  will  move  in  some 
other  direction  (per  what  was  said  in  Chap.  2, 
Diopt.)  ;  and  so  far  (per  Ax.  2)  determination  does 
not  pertain  to  the  essence  of  motion,  nor  is  a  moving 
body  when  repelled  at  rest  at  any  time.     Q.  E.  D 

COROLLARY. 

Hence  it  follows  that  motion  is  not  the  opposite  of 
motion. 

1  Spinoza  throughout  this  work  attributes  quantity  to  rest 
or  quietude  just  as  he  docs  to  motion;  a  body  may  have  a 
certain  amount  of  rest  as  well  as  a  certain  amount  of  motion. 


PART  II  87 

Proposition  XX. 

//  a  body  A  meet  a  body  B  and  they  move  on  to- 
gether the  gain  of  motion  in  B  and  the  loss  of  motion 
in  A  are  equal. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

If  you  deny  it,  let  it  be  supposed 
that  B  acquires  less  motion  from  A 
than  A  loses.  Then  that  quantity  of 
motion  must  be  added  or  substracted  from  the  total 
motion  in  Nature,  which  is  absurd  (per  Prop.  13 
above).  Since  therefore,  B  can  acquire  neither  more 
nor  less  motion  than  A  loses  it  must  receive  just  what 
is  lost  by  A.     Q.  E.  D. 

Proposition  XXL 

//  a  body  A  is  twice  as  great  as  B  and  moves  with 
an  equal  velocity,  it  will  have  twice  the  motion  of  B 
or  a  force  for  retaining  a  motion  equal  to  that  of  B. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

Let  it  be  supposed,  for  example,  that  in  place  of  A 
there  are  two  Bs  that  is  (by  hypothesis)  A  is  divided 
into  two  equal  parts.  Each  one  then  has  the  same 
inertia  and  (by  hypothesis)  the  force  in  each  is  equal. 
If  now  these  two  parts  are  joined  together  their 
velocity  remaining  the  same  there  will  be  a  body  A 
whose  force  and  quantity  will  be  equal  to  two  Bs  or 
double  that  of  one  B.     Q.  E.  D. 

This  follows  also  from  the  definition  of  motion,  for 
zvhen  a  larger  body  is  moved  there  is  more  matter 
separated    from    the    surrounding    matter.     There    is, 


88     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

therefore,  more  of  a  separation,  that  is  (per  Def.  8) 
more  motion.     See  also  Def.  VIII. 

Proposition  XXII. 

If  a  body  A  is  equal  to  another  body  B  and  moves 
with  twice  the  velocity  of  B,  the  force  or  motion  in  A 
is  also  double  that  of  B.  (Vid.  Fig.  Prop.  20). 

DEMONSTRATION. 

Let  it  be  supposed  that  B,  when  it  first  received  a 
certain  force  acquired  a  velocity  of  four  degrees.  If 
it  is  not  acted  upon  by  some  external  force  it  will  con- 
tinue to  move  with  the  same  velocity  (per  Prop.  14). 
Suppose  now,  that  by  a  new  impulse  it  receives  a  new 
force  equal  to  that  which  it  first  received.  It  will 
thus  acquire  four  other  degrees  of  velocity  beside 
those  that  it  had  before,  which  (per  the  same  Prop.) 
it  will  retain.  Thus  it  will  be  moving  with  twice 
its  former  velocity,  or  with  the  velocity  of  A,  and 
have  double  its  former  force  or  a  force  equal  to  that 
of  A.  Therefore  the  motion  in  A  is  double  that  in  B. 
Q.  E.  D. 

It  should  be  noted  here,  that  by  force  (vis)  we 
understand  the  quantity  of  motion.  This,  in  bodies  of 
equal  size,  will  vary  according  to  the  velocity,  for  in  a 
given  time  the  distance  by  which  equal  bodies  arc 
separated  from  those  tangent  to  them  varies  with  the 
velocity.  Therefore  those  moving  more  swiftly  have 
more  motion  (per  Def.  8).  In  bodies  at  rest  by  the 
force  of  resistance  we  understand  the  quantity  of  rest. 
From  which  follow: 


PART  II  89 

Corollary  I. 

The  more  slowly  bodies  move,  the  more  they  par- 
take of  rest,  for  bodies  having  a  greater  velocity 
meeting  those  which  have  less  force,  resist  more  and 
are  not  separated  so  far  from  bodies  immediately  con- 
tiguous to  them. 

Corollary  II. 

//  a  body  A  moves  with  double  the  velocity  of  a 
body  B  which  is  twice  as  large  as  A,  they  contain  an 
equal  amount  of  motion  and  force. 

demonstration. 

If  B  is  twice  as  large  as  A,  but  A  moves  with  twice 
the  velocity  of  B,  and  C  is  only  half  as  large  as  B  and 
moves  only  half  as  fast  as  A  (per  Prop.  21),  B  will 
have  twice  the  force  of  C  and  A  will  have  twice  the 
motion  of  C  (per  Prop.  22).  Therefore  (per  Ax.  15) 
B  and  A  have  an  equal  motion,  for  the  motion  of  each 
is  double  that  of  the  third  body  C.     Q.  E.  D. 

Corollary  III. 

From  these  corollaries  it  follows  that  motion  must 
be  distinguished  from  velocity.  For  we  can  conceive 
of  bodies  which  have  an  equal  velocity,  but  one  of 
them  having  more  motion  than  the  other  (per  Prop. 
21).  And  on  the  other  hand,  bodies  with  an  unequal 
velocity  may  have  an  equal  motion  (per  Coroll. 
II.  above).  This,  also,  is  evident  from  the  definition 
of  motion  which  is  nothing  but  the  transference  of 
one  body  from  the  vicinity,  etc. 

It  should  be  noted  that  this  corollary  is  not  at  vari- 


90     PRINCIPLES  OP  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

ancc  with  the  first.  For  velocity  is  conceived  in  two 
ways:  Either  so  far  as  a  body  in  a  given  time  is 
further  or  nearer  removed  from  those  bodies  imme- 
diately contiguous  to  it,  and  so  far  partakes  more  or 
less  of  rest,  or  so  far  as  in  a  given  time  it  describes 
a  longer  or  a  shorter  line  and  so  far  is  distinguished 
from  motion. 

I  might  add  other  propositions  to  explain  more  fully 
Proposition  14,  in  regard  to  other  points,  as  we  have 
done  in  regard  to  motion.  But  it  is  sufficient  to  read 
Art.  43,  Part  II.  of  the  Principles,  and  to  add  one 
Proposition  only  in  order  to  understand  what  follows. 

Proposition  XXIII. 

When  the  modes  of  a  body  arc  forced  to  suffer 
change,  this  change  is  always,  under  the  circumstances, 
a  minimum  one. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

This  proposition  follows  sufficiently  clearly  from 
Prop.  14. 

Proposition  XXIV — Rule    1. 

//  tzvo  bodies,  for  example  A  and  B  (vid.  Fig.  Prop. 
20)  are  equal,  and  are  moving  toward  one  another 
with  equal  velocity,  when  they  meet  each  will  be  re- 
flected in  an  opposite  direction  without  any  loss  of 
velocity. 

In  this  hypothesis  it  is  evident  that  in  order  that 
this  opposition  may  be  removed,  either  they  must  both 
be  reflected  in  opposite  directions  or  one  must  take  the 
other  on  with  it.  For  they  are  opposed  (inly  in  regard 
to  their  determination,  not  as  to  their  motion. 


PART  II  91 

DEMONSTRATION. 

Since  A  and  B  are  mutually  approaching  one  an- 
other they  must  suffer  some  change  (per  Ax.  19). 
But  since  the  motion  of  the  one  is  not  opposed  to  the 
motion  of  the  other  (per  Coroll.  Prop.  19)  they  do 
not  necessarily  lose  any  of  their  motion  (per  Ax.  19). 
Therefore,  the  change  is  in  their  determination  alone. 
But  we  can  not  say  that  the  determination  of  only 
one,  e.  g.  B,  is  changed  unless  A,  by  which  it  was 
changed,  is  supposed  tx>  be  stronger  (per  Ax.  20). 
This,  however,  is  contrary  to  the  hypothesis.  There- 
fore, since  a  change  in  the  determination  of  only  one 
is  impossible,  it  will  be  in  both,  A  and  B  being  de- 
flected in  opposition  directions  (per  what  was  said  in 
ch.  2,  Dioptric),  each  retaining  its  original  motion. 
Q.  E.  D. 

Proposition  XXV — Rule  2. 

If  they  are  unequal  in  mass,  namely,  B  being  greater 
than  A  {yid.  Fig.  Prop.  20)  other  things  being  as 
before,  then  A  alone  will  be  deflected  and  each  will 
move  with  its  former  velocity. 

demonstration. 

Since  it  is  supposed  that  A  is  less  than  B,  it  will 
have  less  force  than  B.  And,  since  in  this  hypothesis 
as  in  the  last,  the  opposition  is  only  in  their  deter- 
mination, as  we  showed  above,  the  variation  therefore 
will  be  in  their  determination  alone.  It  will  be  merely 
in  A  and  not  in  B  (per  Ax.  20).  Therefore,  A  alone 
will  be  reflected  in  an  opposite  direction  by  the  greater 
body  B,  its  former  velocity  being  returned.     Q.  E.  D. 


92    PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

Proposition  XXVI. 

//  the  mass  and  velocity  are  unequal,  for  example 
B  twice  as  large  as  A  (via7.  Fig.  Prop.  20),  but  A 
moving  with  double  the  velocity  of  B,  other  things 
being  as  before,  both  will  be  reflected  in  opposite  di- 
rections, and  each  will  retain  its  former  velocity. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

Since  A  and  B  are  moving  toward  one  another,  and 
according  to  hypothesis  the  motion  in  one  is  equal  to 
that  in  the  other  (per  Coroll.  2,  Prop.  22)  ;  therefore, 
the  motion  of  the  one  is  not  opposed  to  the  motion  of 
the  other  (per  Coroll.,  Prop.  19).  This  hypothesis, 
therefore,  is  so  far  similar  to  the  hypothesis  of  Propo- 
sition 24,  and  by  the  same  demonstration  A  and  B  will 
be  reflected  in  opposite  directions  by  retaining  each  its 
former  motion.     Q.  E.  D. 

COROLLARY. 

From  the  three  preceding  Propositions  it  is  evident 
that  in  order  that  a  body  be  moved  the  determination 
of  that  body  requires  a  force  equal  to  its  motion. 
Whence,  it  follows  that  a  body  which  has  lost  more 
than  half  of  its  determination  and  more  than  half  of 
its  motion  suffers  more  change  than  one  which  has 
lost  all  of  its  determination. 

Proposition  XXVII — Rule  3. 

//  A  and  B  arc  equal  in  mass,  but  B  moves  a  little 
more  rapidly  than  A,  not  only  is  A  reflected  back  in 
an  opposite  direction,  but  B  gives  to  it  one-half  of  its 


PART  II  93 

excess  of  motion,  and  both  move  in  the  same  direction 
with  an  equal  velocity. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

A  (by  hypothesis)  is  opposed  to  B  not  only  by  its 
determination,  but  also  by  its  slowness,  so  far  as  it 
partakes  of  the  nature  of  rest  (per  CorolL,  Prop.  22). 
Whence,  although  it  is  reflected  in  an  opposite  direc- 
tion and  its  determination  is  changed,  all  of  its  oppo- 
sition (contrarietas)  is  not  destroyed.  Therefore  (per 
Ax.  19),  there  ought  to  be  a  variation  both  in  its  de- 
termination and  in  its  motion.  But  since  by  hypo- 
thesis, B  moves  faster  than  A,  B  will  have  a  greater 
force  than  A  (per  Prop.  22).  Therefore,  the  change 
proceeds  from  B  to  A,  which  will  be  reflected  in  an 
opposite  direction,  which  was  the  first  point  to  be 
proved. 

Then,  so  long  as  A  moves  more  slowly  than  B,  it 
will  be  opposed  to  B  (per  CorolL  1,  Prop.  22).  Conse- 
quently there  ought  to  be  a  variation  in  A  until  it 
moves  with  a  velocity  equal  to  B's  (per  Ax.  19).  But 
in  this  hypothesis  it  is  not  impelled  by  some  stronger 
force  so  that  it  should  move  more  rapidly  than  B. 
Since  it  is  impelled  by  B,  it  can  not  move  slower  than 
that  body,  nor  can  it  move  faster :  therefore,  it  must 
move  with  a  velocity  equal  to  B's. 

Further,  if  B  gave  less  than  one-half  of  its  excess 
of  velocity  to  A,  A  would  move  slower  than  B ;  if 
more  than  one-half,  then  faster,  which  as  we  have 
shown,  is  absurd.  Therefore,  the  variation  will  con- 
tinue until  B  has  given  one  half  of  its  excess  of 
velocity  to  A,  which  B  would  therefore  lose.  So,  also, 
they  will  both  move  without  any  opposition  with  an 
equal  velocity  in  the  same  direction.     Q.  E.  D. 


94     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

COROLLARY. 

It  follows,  that  a  body  moving  with  a  greater 
velocity  has  the  more  determination,  so  that  it  tends 
the  more  to  move  in  a  straight  line ;  and,  on  the 
other  hand,  a  body  moving  more  slowly  has  less  de- 
termination. 

SCHOLIUM. 

Lest  the  reader  confuse  the  force  of  determination 
(vim  determinationis)  with  the  force  of  motion 
(vi  motus),  it  seems  best  to  explain  these  terms.  If 
now  the  bodies  A  and  C  are  equal,  and  are  moving 
toward  one  another  with  an  equal  velocity,  they  will 

be     deflected     back      (per 
£\  Prop.   24),   each   retaining 
/        its      former      velocity.     If 
there  is  a  body  C  at  B  and 
it  moves   obliquely  toward 
A  its  determination  is  less 
than    its    motion    equaling 
^~^  the  line  B  D  or  the  line  C 

JL  A.     Therefore,       although 

L4'i  the  motion  in  the  two  cases 

is  the  same,  the  force  of 
determination  of  C  moving  directly  toward  A  is 
greater  than  the  force  of  determination  of  C  mov- 
ing obliquely  from  B  toward  A  in  the  ratio  of  AB  to 
CA.  Since  it  is  here  supposed  that  A  and  B  move 
with  an  equal  velocity,  the  time  B  consumes  in  moving 
from  B  to  A  or  A  C,  which  measures  its  opposition  to 
A,  will  be  to  A's  time  as  B  A  to  A  C.  When  the  body 
C,  moving  from  B  along  the  line  B  A,  strikes  A,  it  will 
be  deflected  along  the  line  of  A  B/  B'  being  on  B  C 


PART  II  95 

produced  so  that  B'  C  is  equal  to  B  C.  And  since  the 
motion  of  the  two  bodies  is  equal  the  time  B  consumes 
in  traversing  the  perpendicular  distance  A  C  is  greater 
than  the  time  of  A  in  moving  an  equal  distance  or,  to 
such  a  degree  it  is  opposed  to  the  determination  of  A, 
which  is  the  stronger.  In  order  that  the  determination 
of  C  moving  from  B  toward  A,  may  be  equal  to  the  de- 
termination of  C  (or  from  the  hypothesis,  to  A),  it  is 
necessary  that  the  motion  from  B  be  to  the  motion 
from  C  as  B  A  is  to  C  A.  Then  when  it  strikes  the 
body  A  obliquely,  A  will  be  reflected  back  to  A'  and 
B  toward  B',  each  retaining  its  former  velocity.  But 
if  B  is  as  much  greater  than  A  as  the  line  B  A  than 
C  A,  then  B  will  repel  A  toward  A'  and  give  of  its 
motion  until  the  motion  of  B  is  to  the  motion  of  A  as 
the  line  B  A  is  to  C  A,  and  by  losing  the  motion  which 
it  has  transferred  to  A  it  will  proceed  in  the  direction 
it  was  first  moving.  For  example,  if  the  line  A  C  is 
to  the  -line  A  B  as  I  to  2,  and  the  motion  of  A  to  the 
motion  of  B  as  1  to  5,  then  B  will  give  to  A  one  de- 
gree of  motion,  and  will  repell  it  in  an  opposite  direc- 
tion, while  B,  having  lost  one-fifth  of  its  motion,  will 
move  on  in  the  same  direction  as  before. 

Proposition  XXVIII — Rule  4. 

If  a  body  A  (vid.  Fig.,  Prop.  2/),  a  little  larger 
than  B,  is  at  rest,  it  will  not  be  moved  however  great 
the  velocity  of  B,  but  B  will  be  deflected  at  an  angle 
retaining  its  former  motion. 

Note. —  Of  these  bodies  there  is  opposition  of  three 
kinds :  One  when  the  one  meets  the  other  and  they 
both  move  on  with  an  equal  velocity ;  the  second  when 
one  is  reflected  in  an  opposite  direction  the  other  re- 


96     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

maining  at  rest ;  the  third  when  one  is  deflected  from 
its  course  and  gives  some  part  of  its  motion  to  the 
body  at  rest.  There  is  no  fourth  kind  as  is  seen  from 
Prop.  13.  Therefore  it  will  be  evident  (per  Prop. 
23)  that  conformable  to  our  hypothesis  the  least  pos- 
sible change  occurs  in  these  bodies. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

If  B  moves  A,  until  both  move  with  the  same 
velocity,  it  must  give  from  its  own  motion  (per  Prop. 
20)  all  that  A  acquires  and  consequently  would  lose 
more  than  half  of  its  motion  (per  Prop.  21)  as  well 
as  more  than  half  of  its  determination  (per  Coroll., 
Prop.  27).  So  far  (per  Coroll.,  Prop.  26)  it  under- 
goes more  change  than  if  it  lost  all  of  its  determina- 
tion. And  if  A  loses  a  part  of  its  rest,  but  not  so 
much  that  it  moves  with  a  velocity  equal  to  B's,  then 
the  opposition  of  the  two  bodies  is  not  destroyed.  For 
A,  so  far  as  it  partakes  of  rest,  will  be  opposed  to  the 
motion  of  B,  and  so  far  B  will  be  deflected  from  its 
course  and  will  lose  all  of  its  determination  and  that 
part  of  its  motion  which  it  has  given  to  A.  And  this 
also  is  a  greater  change  than  if  it  had  lost  its  deter- 
mination alone.  The  change,  therefore,  under  our 
hypothesis,  since  it  is  in  the  determination  alone,  is 
the  least  possible  that  can  come  in  these  bodies,  and 
therefore  (per  Prop.  23)  the  only  possible  one.  O. 
E.  D. 

It  should  be  noted  that  in  the  demonstration  of  this 
Proposition,  and  it  holds  true  likewise  in  other  places, 
that  we  have  not  cited  Prop.  19,  where  it  was  dem- 
onstrated, that  the  entire  determination  of  a  body  may 
change,  the  motion  remaining  the  same.  Neverthe- 
less this  should  be  remembered  in  order  that  the  force 


PART  II  97 

of  this  argument  may  be  seen.  For  in  Prop.  23  we 
do  not  say  that  the  variation  is  the  least  absolutely, 
but  the  least  possible  under  the  given  conditions. 
That  such  a  change  as  this  is  possible,  that  is,  a  change 
in  the  determination  alone,  is  evident  from  Props.  18 
and  19  with  the  Corollary. 

Proposition  XXIX — Rule  5. 

If  there  is  a  body  A,  less  than  B,  at  rest  (vid.  Fig. 
Prop.  30.),  then,  however  slowly  B  moves  toward  A, 
B  will  give  such  a  portion  of  its  motion  to  A  that  they 
will  move  on  together  (Read  Art.  50,  Part  II. 
Principles) . 

In  this  rule,  as  in  the  preceding,  there  are  three 
possible  cases  by  which  their  opposition  may  be 
destroyed.  We  will  show  that  under  this  hypothesis 
there  is  the  least  possible  change  in  these  bodies,  and 
so  (per  Prop.  23)  this  is  the  only  variation. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

By  hypothesis,  B  transfers  to  A  (per  Prop.  21)  less 
than  half  of  its  motion,  and  (per  Coroll.,  Prop.  17) 
less  than  half  of  its  determination.  But  if  B  did  not 
carry  A  on  with  it,  but  should  be  reflected  in  an  oppo- 
site direction,  it  would  lose  all  of  its  determination 
and  there  would  be  a  greater  variation  (per  Coroll., 
Prop.  26).  And  much  greater  even,  if  it  should  lose 
all  of  its  determination,  and  at  the  same  time  a  part 
of  its  motion,  as  is  supposed  in  the  third  case. 
Therefore,  the  change  under  our  hypothesis  is  the 
least  possible.     Q.  E.  D. 


q8     PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

Proposition  XXX-t-Rule  6. 

If  a  body  A,  at  rest,  is  exactly  equal  to  B,  a  body 
moving  toward  it,  zvhen  B  strikes  A,  A  will  be  im- 
pelled and  B  repelled. 

Here,  as  in  the  preceding,  there  are  three  possible 
cases,  and  we  will  show  that  the  resulting  change  is 
the  least  possible. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

If  the  body  B  should  take  A  with  it  until  both  move 
with  an  equal  velocity,  then  the  motion  in  each  would 
be  the  same   (per  Prop.  22)   and   (per  Coroll.,  Prop. 

2j)  B  would  lose  half  of  its  de- 
termination and  half  of  its  motion 
(per  Prop.  20).  If  B  is  repelled  in 
an  opposite  direction  it  will  lose  all 
of  its  determination  but  retain  all  its  motion  (per 
Prop.  18).  In  the  latter  case  the  change  is 
equal  to  that  of  the  former  (per  Coroll.,  Prop. 
26).  But  neither  of  these  is  possible,  for  if 
A  remains  at  rest  and  still  changes  the  determina- 
tion of  B,  it  must  needs  (per  Ax.  20)  be  greater 
than  B,  which  is  contrary  to  the  hypothesis.  And  if 
B  act  on  A  until  both  move  together  with  an  equal 
velocity,  B  is  greater  than  A,  which  is  also  contrary 
to  the  hypothesis.  Since  neither  of  these  results  is 
possible,  the  third  case  must  be  the  result,  namely,  that 
B  impels  A  a  little,  and  is  repelled  by  A.  O.  E.  D. 
Read  Art.  51,  Part  II.  of  the  Principles. 


PART  II  99 

Proposition  XXXI — Rule  7. 

//  B  and  A  {yid.  Fig.  above)  are  moving  in  the 
same  direction,  A  a  little  more  slozvly  than  B,  which 
is  following,  so  that  it  will  impinge  on  A,  and  if  A 
is  greater  than  B,  but  the  excess  in  magnitude  is  not 
equal  to  B's  excess  of  velocity,  then  B  will  give  a 
part  of  its  velocity  to  A,  so  that  they  will  move  on 
together.  But  if  the  excess  of  motion  in  B  does  not 
equal  the  excess  of  magnitude  in  A,  then  B  will  be 
reflected  back,  each  retaining  its  former  velocity. 

See  Art.  52,  Part  of  II.  of  the  Principles.  Here,  as 
above,  there  are  three  possible  cases. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

Point  one :  B,  which  is  supposed  to  be  stronger 
than  A,  cannot  be  reflected  in  an  opposite  direction 
(per  Props.  21  and  22,  and  Ax.  20).  Therefore,  since 
B  is  stronger  than  A  it  will  move  A  on  with  it  so  that 
the  two  advance  together,  for  as  appears  from  the  pre- 
vious proposition,  there  is  less  change  in  this  way  than 
in  any  other. 

Point  two :  Since  here  B  is  not  so  strong  as  A  it 
can  not  move  A  (per  Props.  21  and  22),  neither  (per 
Ax.  20)  can  it  give  it  any  of  its  motion.  Therefore 
(per  Coroll.,  Prop.  14),  it  will  retain  its  former  mo- 
tion. Not,  however,  in  the  same  direction,  for  it  is 
supposed  to  be  impeded  by  A.  Therefore  (per  what 
was  said  in  Chap  2,  Diopt.),  it  will  be  reflected  in 
an  opposite  direction,  each  body  retaining  its  former 
motion  (per  Prop.  18).     O.  E.  D. 

It  should  be  noted  that  here,  as  in  the  preceding- 
propositions,  we  have  assumed  as  proven  that  every 


'.'  VI 


ioo  PRINCIPLES  OP  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

body  meeting  another  by  which  it  is  absolutely  im- 
peded, advances  no  further  in  its  former  direction, 
but  on  the  contrary,  is  reflected  in  an  opposite  direc- 
tion.    To  understand  this  read  Chapter  2  of  the  Diopts. 

SCHOLIUM. 

For  explaining  the  changes  of  bodies  which  are 
mutually  impelled  we  have  so  far  considered  two 
bodies  as  though  separated  from  all  others,  no  account 
being  taken  of  other  impinging  bodies.  For  we  will 
consider  the  state  and  changes  of  those  in  place  of  the 
bodies  by  which  they  are  impinged  on  all  sides. 

Proposition  XXXII. 

If  a  body  B  is  impinged  on  all  sides  by  moving 
particles  which  tend  to  move  it  in  all  directions,  as 
long  as  there  is  no  other  cause  it  will  remain  un- 
moved. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

This  proposition  is  self-evident :  for  if  a  body  is 
moving  from  the  impulse  of  corpuscles  coming  from 
a  certain  direction,  the  corpuscles  which  move  it  im- 
pel it  with  greater  force  than  others  coming  from 
other  parts,  and  striking  it  are  unable  to  produce  a 
sensible  effect  (per  Ax.  20).  But  this  is  contrary  to 
the  hypothesis. 

Proposition  XXXIII. 

Conditions  being  as  in  the  last  Proposition,  a  body 
B  can  be  moved  in  a  certain  direction  by  a  force  how- 
ever small. 


PART  II  101 

DEMONSTRATION. 

Since,  by  hypothesis,  B  is  at  rest,  and  the  particles 
contiguous  to  it  are  in  motion,  these  particles  (per 
Prop.  28)  in  touching  B  are  repelled,  each  one  re- 
taining its  former  velocity.  B,  therefore,  is  being 
continually  left  by  those  particles  contiguous  to  it,  and 
no  action  is  required  for  separating  it  from  those 
particles  which  come  in  contact  with  it  (according  to 
what  was  remarked  concerning  Def.  8).  Therefore, 
however  small  the  external  force  impinging  on  B,  it 
is  still  greater  than  that  required  to  retain  B  in  its 
position  (for  we  have  shown  that  there  is  no  force 
in  the  bodies  immediately  tangent  to  B),  and  which, 
added  to  the  impact  of  the  particles  moving  in  the  same 
direction,  is  not  greater  than  the  impact  of  particles 
moving  in  an  opposite  direction  (for  we  suppose  that 
these  particles  are  acting  equally  on  all  sides.) 
Therefore  (per  Ax.  20),  any  external  force,  however 
small,  will  move  B  in  a  certain  direction.     O.  E.  D. 

Proposition  XXXIV. 

A  body  B,  the  conditions  being  as  above,  can  not 
be  moved  with  a  velocity  greater  than  the  velocity  of 
the  body  impelling  it,  although  the  particles  of  that 
body  may   be   moving  much  more  rapidly. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

The  corpuscles  which,  together  with  the  external 
force,  impel  B  in  a  certain  direction,  although  they 
move  much  more  rapidly  than  the  external  force  is 
able  to  move,  nevertheless,  since  (by  hypothesis)  they 
hive  no  greater  force  than  those  particles  which  tend 


102  PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

to  drive  B  in  another  direction,  all  strength  of  their 
determination  is  used  in  resisting  these,  and  hence 
(per  Prop.  32)  they  give  no  acceleration  to  the  body. 
Therefore,  since  there  are,  according  to  supposition, 
no  other  elements  or  causes  except  this  external  force, 
nor  does  it  receive  acceleration  from  any  other  bodies 
except  this  external  force,  it  can  not  be  moved  with 
a  greater  velocity  than  the  impulse  of  this  body. 
O.  E.  D. 

Proposition  XXXV. 

When  a  body  B  is  so  moved  by  an  external  force, 
it  receives  the  greater  part  of  its  motion  from  those 
bodies  which  immediately  surround  it,  and  not  from 
an  external  force. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

The  body  B,  however  large  it  is  supposed  to  be, 
will  be  moved  by  the  continued  impulse  of  a  body 
however  small  (per  Prop.  33).  Let  us  suppose  that 
B  is  four  times  as  large  as  an  external  body  by  which 
it  is  moved.  Since  (by  the  preceding  Proposition) 
both  will  move  with  an  equal  velocity  there  will  be 
four  times  as  much  motion  in  B  as  in  the  body  by 
which  it  is  impelled  (per  Prop.  21).  Therefore  (per 
Ax.  8,  Part  I.),  it  does  not  receive  the  principal  part 
of  its  motion  from  this  external  force.  And  since 
no  other  factors  are  present  except  those  bodies  by 
which  it  is  continually  being  impelled  (for  B  is  sup- 
posed to  be  at  rest),  it  receives  the  greater  part  of  its 
motion  from  these  bodies  continually  acting  upon  it 
and  not  from  some  external  force,  O.  E.  D. 

Let  it  be  noted  here  that  we  cannot  say,  as  above, 


PART  II  103 

that  the  motion  of  particles  coming  from  one  direc- 
tion is  needed  to  counterbalance  the  motion  of  parts 
coming  from  an  opposite  direction.  For  bodies  mov- 
ing toward  one  another  (as  is  here  supposed)  with 
an  equal  motion  are  opposed  to  one  another  in  their 
determination  alone  and  not  in  their  motion1  (per 
Coroll.  Prop.  19)  ;  hence  when  resisting  one  another 
they  are  opposed  only  in  their  determination  and  not 
in  their  motion.  Beside  B  cannot  receive  from 
circumjacent  bodies  any  determination  and  consequent- 
ly no  increase  of  velocity  so  far  as  it  is  distinguished 
from  motion.  It  does,  however,  receive  motion ;  there- 
fore, some  adventitious  force  being  present,  it  must 
needs  be  moved  by  these  particles  as  we  have  shown 
in  this  Proposition,  and  this  is  clear  also  from  the 
method  by  which  we  demonstrate  Proposition  33. 

Proposition  XXXVI. 

//  some  body,  for  example  my  hand,  moves  with  a 
uniform-  motion  in  any  direction  so  that  it  in  no  way 
resists  any  bodies,  nor  do  any  bodies  in  any  way  resist 
it,  in  the  space  through  which  it  moves  the  bodies  must 
necessarily  be  moving  in  all  directions  and  with  a 
velocity  equal  to  that  of  my  hand. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

A  body  can  move  through  no  space  that  is  not  a 
plenum  (per  Prop.  3).  That  is,  the  space  through 
which  my  hand  is  moving  is  filled  with  bodies  which 
move  under  the  condition  given  above.     If  you  deny 

1  See  Proposition  24  of  this  book,  where  it  was  demonstrated 
that  bodies  resisting  one  another  are  opposed  only  in  their 
determination  and  not  in  their  motion. 


104  PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

it  let  it  be  supposed  that  they  are  at  rest  or  are  mov- 
ing in  some  other  way.  If  they  were  at  rest  they 
necessarily  resist  the  motion  of  the  hand  (per  Prop. 
14)  until  its  motion  is  communicated  to  them  so  that 
they  move  in  the  same  direction  and  with  a  velocity 
equal  to  that  of  my  hand  (per  Prop.  20).  But  it  is 
supposed  in  the  hypothesis  that  they  do  not  resist. 
Therefore,  they  are  moving,  which  is  the  first  point 
to  be  proved.  These  bodies  must  be  moving  in  all 
directions.  If  you  deny  it  let  it  be  supposed  that 
they  do  not  move  in  one  direction,  say  from  A  to  B. 
If,  therefore,  the  hand  is  moving  from  A  to  B  it 
will  necessarily  meet  with  moving  particles  (according 
to  what  has  just  been  said  and  according  to  hypo- 
thesis) with  a  different  determination  from  the  deter- 
mination of  the  hand.  Therefore,  they  would  resist 
it  (per  Prop.  14)  until  they  are  moved  in  the  same 
direction  as  the  hand  itself  (per  Prop.  24  and  Schol. 
Prop.  27).  And  since  (by  hypothesis)  they  do  not 
resist  the  hand,  they  will  be  moving  in  the  same  direc- 
tion, which  was  the  second  point. 

Again,  these  bodies  in  whatever  direction  they  move, 
will  all  have  an  equal  velocity.  For  if  it  be  supposed 
that  they  do  not  move  with  an  equal  velocity,  let  it 
be  supposed  that  those  which  move  from  A  toward  B, 
do  not  have  as  great  a  velocity  as  those  which  move 
from  A  toward  C. 
C  Therefore,  if  the  hand  moves  from 

A  to  B  with  the  same  velocity  as  the 
bodies  moving  from  A  to  C  (for  it 
-B  is  supposed  to  be  able  to  move  with  an 
equal  velocity  in  any  direction  without  resistance),  the 
bodies  moving  from  A  toward  B  will  resist  the  hand 
until  they  move  with  the  hand  with  an  equal  velocity 


A 


PART  II  105 

(per x  Props.  14  and  31).  But  this  is  contrary  to 
hypothesis.  Therefore  they  will  move  in  all  directions 
with  an  equal  velocity,  which  was  the  third  point. 

Finally,  if  these  bodies  do  not  move  with  an  equal 
velocity  to  the  hand,  the  hand  moves  either  slower  or 
faster  than  they.  If  the  former  the  hand  would  resist 
the  bodies  which  are  following  it  in  the  same  direc- 
tion (per  Prop.  31)  ;  if  these  particles  move  slower 
than  the  hand,  then  they  will  resist  the  hand,  both 
cases  being  contrary  to  our  hypothesis.  Therefore, 
since  the  hand  does  not  move  slower  or  faster  than 
the  particles  it  must  move  with  a  velocity  equal  to 
that  of  the  particles  amid  which  it  moves.     Q.  E.  D. 

If  you  inquire  why  with  an  equal  degree  of  velocity, 
I  would  reply  that  it  is  not  with  a  velocity  absolutely 
equal.  Sec  Schol.  Coroll.  Prop.  27.  If  then  you 
would  ask  whether  the  hand  while,  for  example,  it 
was  moving  front  A  to  B  would  not  resist  those  par- 
ticles at  that  time  moving  from  B  to  A,  read  Prop.  33, 
■in  which  you  will  see  that  the  force  of  these  bodies  is 
equalized  by  the  force  cf  bodies  moving  from  A  to  B 
(for  by  the  third  part  of  this  demonstration  this  force 
is  equal  to  that). 

Proposition  XXXVII. 

If  some  body,  A  for  example,  can  be  moved  in  a 
certain  direction  by  a  force  however  small,  it  is  neces- 
sarily surrounded  by  bodies  which  are  all  moving  with 
equal  velocity  in  all  directions. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

This  body  A  is  surrounded  on  all  sides  by  bodies 
(per  Prop.  6),  which  are  moving  in  all  directions  with 
an  equal  velocity.     For  if  they  were  at  rest  the  body  A 


io6  PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

(as  is  supposed),  could  not  be  moved  in  a  given  direc- 
tion by  a  force  however  small,  but  only  by  a  minimum 
force  which  was  able  to  move  A  together  with  the 
bodies  which  immediately  surround  it  (per  Ax.  20). 
Then  if  the  bodies  by  which  A  is  surrounded  are 
moved  in  one  direction  with  a  greater  force  than  in 
another,  for  example,  from  B  to  C  than  from  C  to  B, 

since  as  we  have  already  shown  it  is 
(j\^- —  surrounded    on    all    sides    by    moving 

bodies,  it  will  necessarily  be  moved 
along  the  line  from  B  to  C  (per  Prop.  30).  Hence 
a  force  however  small  would  not  suffice  to  move  A 
from  C  to  B,  but  one  sufficient  to  overcome  this  excess 
of  motion  toward  B  would  be  required  (Ax.  20). 
Therefore  these  bodies  must  be  moving  in  all  direc- 
tions with  an  equal  force. 

SCHOLIUM. 

Since  these  things  are  true  of  fluid  bodies,  it  follows 
that  fluid  bodies  are  those  which  are  divided  into 
minute  parts,  which  are  moving  in  all  directions  with 
equal  velocity.  And,  although  these  particles  cannot 
be  seen  even  T)y  the  eye  of  a  lynx,  still  the  truth  of 
what  we  have  thus  demonstrated  cannot  be  denied. 
For,  in  Propositions  10  and  11  it  was  shown  that  the 
subtlety  of  nature  is  so  great  that  it  cannot  be  known 
(I  shall  not  say  by  the  senses).  Beside,  as  was  also 
shown  above,  since  bodies  only  by  their  rest  resist 
other  bodies,  and  as  the  senses  tell  us  hardness  is 
nothing  else  than  the  resistance  the  parts  of  a  body 
offer  to  our  hands,  we  conclude  that  those  bodies  are 
hard  whose  particles  are,  with  regard  to  another  at 
rest,  and  near  together. 

Read  Articles  54,  55,  and  56,  Part  TT.  Prin. 


The  Principles  of  Philosophy  Demonstrated 
by  the  Method  of  Geometry. 

Part  III. 

The  universal  principles  of  nature  having  been  pre- 
sented, we  must  proceed  now  to  explain  those  things 
which  follow  from  them.  But  since  the  things  which 
follow  from  these  principles  are  more  than  can  ever  be 
known,  and  since  we  are  not  determined  by  them  to 
one  thing  rather  than  another,  first  of  all  a  brief  history 
should  be  given  of  the  principal  phenomena  whose 
causes  we  are  to  investigate.  This  you  have  in 
Articles  5  to  15,  Part  III.  of  the  Principles.  And  from 
Articles  20  to  40  the  hypothesis  is  expressed  which 
Descartes  deemed  best  fitted  not  only  to  explain  the 
phenomena  of  the  world,  but  also  for  investigating 
their  natural  causes. 

The  best  way  to  understand  the  nature  of  plants  or 
of  men  is  to  see  how  they  arise  and  develop  from 
their  germ  cells.  Principles  perfectly  simple  and  easily 
known  should  be  found  from  which  we  can  demon- 
strate that  the  heavens,  the  earth,  and  all  the  visible 
world  could  have  arisen  as  from  cells,  although  we 
know  full  well  that  they  have  not  actually  done  so. 
For  in  this  way  we  will  explain  their  nature  much 
better  than  if  we  only  describe  them. 

I  say  that  we  are  seeking  for  principles  which  are 
simple  and  easily  known.  Unless  such  are  found  we 
do  not   desire   any   at   all.     For   we   are   only   adding 

107 


io8  PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

the  first  principles  to  what  has  been  given  in  order 
that  the  nature  of  these  things  may  more  easily  be 
known,  and  that  we  may,  according  to  the  method 
of  mathematics,  advance  from  what  is  perfectly  clear 
to  that  which  is  more  obscure,  and  from  the  simple 
to  what  is  more  complex. 

Therefore,  we  said  that  we  are  seeking  the  prin- 
ciples from  which  we  might  demonstrate  that  the 
heavens,  the  earth,  etc.,  could  have  arisen.  We  are 
not  seeking  merely  the  causes  which  are  sufficient,  for 
explaining  the  phenomena  of  the  heavens  as  is  now 
and  then  done  by  astronomers.  But  we  are  seeking 
for  those  principles  which  will  lead  us  to  a  knowledge 
of  all  those  things  in  the  earth  (for  we  believe  that 
all  those  things  which  we  observe  in  the  earth  should 
be  included  in  the  phenomena  of  nature).  In  order 
that  these  may  be  found,  the  following  points  should 
be  observed  in  a  valid  hypothesis : 

I.  That  (considered  in  itself  alone),  it  implies  no 
contradiction. 

II.  That  it  should  be  as  simple  as  possible. 

III.  That  what  follows  from  it  may  be  easily 
known. 

IV.  That  all  things  observed  in  all  nature  can  be 
deduced  from  it. 

Finally,  we  said,  that  we  might  assume  an  hypo- 
thesis from  which,  as  from  a  cause  we  are  able  to 
deduce  the  phenomena  of  nature  although  we  know 
that  these  phenomena  have  not  thus  arisen.  In  order 
that  this  may  be  understood  I  will  give  an  example. 
If  a  person  should  find  on  a  paper  the  curved  line 
which  we  call  a  parabola  and  wished  to  investigate 
its  nature  it  would  make  no  difference  whether  he 
regarded  it  as  first  cut  from  some  cone  and  then  placed 


PART  III  109 

upon  the  paper,  or  whether  he  regarded  it  as  generated 
from  the  movement  of  two  straight  lines,  or  as  derived 
in  some  other  way.  In  whatever  way  he  conceives 
it  to  have  been  generated,  he  wishes  to  demonstrate 
all  the  properties  of  the  parabola  from  it.  Indeed, 
although  he  knows  that  it  was  made  from  the  cone, 
he  will  be  free  to  assign  some  other  cause  which  seems 
to  him  better  adapted  to  explain  all  its  properties. 
So  also  in  order  to  explain  the  forms  of  nature  we 
may  assume  any  hypothesis  at  will,  provided  we  de- 
duce from  it,  through  mathematical  inference,  all  the 
phenomena  of  nature.  And,  what  is  even  more 
worthy  of  note,  we  can  scarcely  assume  anything,  from 
which  we  may  not,  perhaps  with  more  labor,  through 
the  laws  of  nature  given  above,  deduce  the  same 
results.  For  since  in  accordance  with  these  laws, 
matter  assumes  successively  all  the  forms  of  which 
it  is  capable,  if  we  consider  these  forms  in  order  we 
will  come  finally  to  the  form  in  which  the  world 
exists.  We  need  not  fear,  therefore,  the  error  of  a 
false  hypothesis. 

A   POSTULATE. 

We  ask  that  it  be  conceded  that,  in  the  beginning, 
all  matter  of  which  the  visible  world  is  composed 
was  divided  by  God  into  particles  as  nearly  as  possible 
equal  to  one  another.  These  particles,  however,  from 
which  now  the  heavens  and  the  stars  are  composed 
were  not  spherical,  for  a  number  of  spheres  joined 
together  do  not  fill  up  the  space  they  occupy ;  but  they, 
small  in  size,  were  fashioned  in  some  other  way. 
These  particles  had  in  them  just  as  much  motion  as 
there  is  in  the  world  to-day  and  they  were  all  moving 
with  an  equal  velocity.     Not  only  did  single  particles 


no  PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

mutually  separate  from  one  another  move  about  their 
own  center  as  if  they  composed  a  fluid  body,  such  as 
we  think  the  heavens  to  be,  but  there  are  many  mov- 
ing  together  around  certain  other  points,  equally  re- 
mote and  like  disposed  and  now  the  centers  of  fixed 
bodies ;  then  also,  there  were  some  around  other  points 
which  equal  the  number  of  the  planets.  And  so  they 
compose  as  many  vortices  as  there  are  stars  in  the 
world.     Vid.  Fig.  Art.  47,  Part  III.  of  the  Principles. 

This  hypothesis  considered  in  itself  implies  no  con- 
tradiction; for  it  attributes  nothing  to  matter  except 
divisibility  and  motion,  which  we  have  already  dem- 
onstrated to  really  exist  in  matter.  And  since  we 
have  shown  that  matter  is  indefinite,  and  the  earth  and 
the  heavens  are  one  and  the  same,  we  can  suppose 
without  a  trace  of  contradiction,  that  these  modifica- 
tions are  in  all  matter. 

Then  this  hypothesis  is  a  very  simple  one,  because 
there  is  no  irregularity  or  dissimilarity  in  the  particles 
into  which  matter  was  divided  at  the  beginning,  nor 
in  their  motion.  For  these  reasons  this  hypothesis  is 
also  very  easy  to  understand.  This  is  evident  also 
from  the  fact  that  in  this  hypothesis  nothing  is  assigned 
to  matter  except  that  which  is  known  to  any  one  from 
the  concept  of  matter  alone,  namely,  divisibility  and 
motion  in  space. 

We  shall  attempt  to  show,  as  far  as  it  may  be  done 
and  in  the  following  order,  that  all  that  we  observe  in 
nature  can  be  deduced  from  this  alone.  In  the  first 
place  we  will  deduce  the  fluidity  of  the  heavens  from 
this  postulate  and  explain  how  this  is  the  cause  of 
light.  Then  we  shall  proceed  to  consider  the  nature 
of  the  sun   and  those  things   which   are  observed   in 


PART  III  in 

the  fixed  stars.     Afterward  we  shall  speak  of  comets 
and  of  the  planets  and  their  phenomena. 

DEFINITIONS. 

I.  By  the  Equator  (per  Eclipticam)  we  understand 
that  part  of  a  rotating  body,  which  as  it  turns  on  its 
axis,  describes  the  greatest  circle. 

II.  By  the  Poles  we  understand  those  parts  of  a 
rotating  body  most  remote  from  the  Equator,  or  which 
describe  minimum  circles. 

III.  By  the  Conatus  to  move  (conatum  ad  motum) 
we  do  not  understand  some  form  of  thought,  but  only 
that  a  part  of  matter  is  so  placed  and  impelled  to 
move  that,  if  it  is  not  impeded  by  some  external  cause, 
it  will  really  move  somewhere. 

IV.  By  an  Angle  we  understand  that  part  of  a  body 
which  extends  beyond  its  spherical  form. 

AXIOMS. 

I.  A  number  of  spheres  joined  together  cannot  fill 
the  space  they  occupy. 

II.  A  portion  of  matter  divided  into  angular  parts 
requires  more  space,  if  these  parts  each  move  about 
its  own  center,  than  if  they  are  all  at  rest  and  the  sides 
of  all  are  immediately  and  mutually  tangent  to  one 
another. 

III.  A  smaller  part  of  matter  is  easier  divided  by 
a  given  force  than  a  larger  one. 

IV.  Parts  of  matter  moving  in  the  same  direction 
which  do  not  in  this  motion  recede  from  one  another, 
are  not  really  divided. 


ii2  PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY 

Proposition  I. 

The  parts  into  which  matter  was  first  divided  are 
not  spherical  but  angular. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

In  the  beginning  all  matter  was  divided  into  equal 
and  similar  parts  (per  Postulate).  Therefore  (per 
Ax.  i  and  Prop.  2,  Part  II.)  they  are  not  spherical 
but  (per  Def.  4)  thus  far  angular.     Q.  E.  D. 

Proposition  II. 

The  force  which  causes  the  particles  of  matter  to 
move  about  their  own  centers,  also  causes  the  angles 
of  these  particles  to  be  worn  away. 

DEMONSTRATION. 

In  the  beginning  all  matter  was  divided  into  equal 
and  angular  parts,  (per  Postulate  and  Prop.  1).  If  the 
angles  were  not-  worn  away  when  they  began  to  move 
around  their  centers,  all  matter  would  occupy  (per 
Ax.  2)  more  space  than  if  they  were  at  rest.  But 
this  is  absurd  (per  Prop.  IV.,  Part  II).  Therefore 
their  angles  begin  to  wear  away  as  soon  as  they  began 
to  move.     Q.  E.  D. 


APPENDIX 


CONTAINING 


COGITATA   METAPHYSICA, 


In   which   are  briefly   discussed   some   questions 

and    difficulties    which    occur    in    regard    to 

Being   and   its   Affects,    God   and   His 

Attributes,    and    the    Human 

Mind. 


BY 


BENEDICTUS  DE  SPINOZA, 

Amsterdam. 

113 


APPENDIX 

CONTAINING 

COGITATA  METAPHYSICA. 

Part  I, 

In  which  some  points  relating  to  Being  and  its  Affects 
are  briefly  explained. 

Chapter  I. 

Concerning  Real  Being,  Fictitious  Being,  and  Being 

of  Reason. 

Concerning  the  definition  of  knowledge  (Scientia) 
I  shall  say  nothing,  not  even  of  the  knowledge  of  the 
things  here  discussed.  I  shall  only  attempt  to  explain 
some  obscure  points  in  those  authors  who  write  on 
Metaphysics. 

We     shall    begin,    therefore,    with 

Definition  of  Being,  by  which  I  mean,  all  of  that 

which,  when  it  is  clearly  and  distinctly 

conceived  is  found  to  exist  necessarily,  or  at  least  to  be 

able  to  exist. 

From  this  definition,  or,  if  you  pre- 

Chu^Z'anf%°eAng  fer>   from  this   description,   it   follows 

reaieason  are  not  ^at    chimeras,    fictitious    being    and 

being  of  the  reason  can  in  no  way  be 

called   real.     For   chimeras 1   by   their  nature   do   not 

1  By  chimera  is  understood  a  being  which  by  nature  involves 
a  contradiction  as  is  clearly  shown  in  Chapter  III. 

US 


no  THE  COG1TATA  METAPHYSICA 

exist.  Fictitious  being  precludes  any  clear  and  distinct 
concept,  because  man  by  his  mere  power  of  Freedom, 
not  unknowingly  as  in  false  concepts,  but  advisedly 
and  intelligently,  connects  what  he  wishes  to  connect, 
and  dissociates  what  he  will.  Finally,  being  of  reason 
is  nothing  except  a  mode  of  thought  which  pertains 
most  properly  to  the  intellect,  viz.,  to  retention,  to 
understanding,  and  to  the  imagination.  It  should 
here  be  noted  that  by  mode  of  thought  we  mean,  as 
was  explained  in  Schol.  Prop.  Pt.  L,  all  forms  of 
mental  states  as  understanding,  joy,  imagination,  etc. 

That    there    are    certain    modes    of 
in  what  zvay  objects  thought   which   serve   the  purpose   of 

are    retained    in  .     .  -  .  r        -        .         ,  , 

memory.  retaining  objects  firmly  in  the  mind, 

and  of  recalling  them  when  we  wish, 
is  evident  to  all  who  use  the  well-known  rule  of 
memory;  viz.,  that  by  which,  for  retaining  anything 
in  memory  and  impressing  it  upon  the  mind,  it  is  asso- 
ciated with  some  other  thing  familiar  to  us,  either 
by  name,  or  because  of  its  contiguity  with  that  object. 
In  this  way  philosophers  have  reduced  all  natural 
objects  to  certain  classes  called  genera,  species,  etc., 
and  to  these  they  refer  all  new  objects  as  they  are  met. 

Then,  for  explaining  things  we  have 
Z"«E£  Zlal  also  modes  of  thought  derived  by  com- 
paring  one  object  with  another.  Such 
modes  as  these  are  time,  number,  measure,  etc.  Of 
these  time  serves  for  explaining  duration,  number  for 
discrete  quantities,  and  measure  for  continuous  quan- 
tity. 

Finally  since  we  have  become  accus- 

Uiml&ne™linll     lomcd   to   picture   all   of   those   things 

which  we  understand,  even  the  images 
of  our  fancy  at  times,  it  happens  that  we  imagine  non- 


PART  I  117 

being  positively,  as  an  image  of  some  real  being.  For 
mind  considered  as  a  thinking  being  has  no  more 
power  to  affirm  than  to  deny.  And  since  to  imagine  is 
only  to  perceive  the  traces  in  the  brain  produced  by 
the  movement  of  the  spirits,  which  in  turn  are  caused 
by  the  stimulation  of  the  senses  by  an  external  object, 
such  a  sensation  can  only  be  a  confused  affirmation. 
Hence  we  imagine  all  the  forms  of  thought  which  the 
mind  uses  for  denying  as  blindness,  the  limits  or 
termini,  the  end,  shade,  etc.,  are  beings. 
„,     ,  .         ,  It  is  thus  evident  that  such  modes 

Why    beings   of 

reason  are  not     of  thought  are  not  ideas  of  things,  nor 

ideas     of     th/Ut£[S 

but  are  so  can  they,  in  any  possible  way  be  so 

considered.  .  .,  ,         rT^1  .  .   . 

considered.  I  hey  have  no  object, 
which  necessarily  exists,  as  the  source  of  the  idea,  nor 
could  such  an  object  possibly  exist.  The  reason  such 
forms  of  thought  are  so  often  held  for  ideas  of  things 
is  that  they  arise  so  directly  from  real  things,  that 
those  who  do  not  very  carefully  attend  to  their  thought 
readily  confuse  such  forms  of  thought  with  the  things 
themselves.  For  this  cause  also,  they  give  names  to 
these  ideas  as  if  they  signified  some  real  extra-mental 
object,  which  being,  or  rather  non-being,  they  call 
beings  of  the  reason. 

It  is  easy  to  see  how  inapt  is  the 

It  is  not  correct  to     ,.    .    .  .........        -r»    •  •  1 

divide  Being  into  division  which  divides  lieing  into  real 

real    being    and        1      • ,  j    *     •  r     ,1  tt> 

being  of  reason,  being  and  being  of  the  reason,  hor 
they  divide  Being  into  being  and  non- 
being  or  into  being  and  a  mode  of  thought.  How- 
ever, I  do  not  wonder  that  philosophers  sometimes  fall 
into  these  verbal  or  grammatical  errors.  For  they 
judge  objects  from  the  names  and  not  names  from  the 
objects. 


u8  THE  COGITATA  METAPHYSICA 

in  what  seme  Those   who   sav   that   being  of  the 

being    of    the  J  ° 

reason  may  be       reason   is   nothing,   however,    are   not 

called     nothing,  m  ° 

and  in  what         less   in  error.     If  you   seek  for  some 

sense    YCQ.I 

meaning  for  these  terms  apart  from 
the  mind  you  find  nothing;  but  if  we  understand  by 
the  term  a  mode  of  thought,  then  it  signifies  something 
real.  For  if  I  ask  what  a  species  is,  I  only  inquire 
for  the  nature  of  that  form  of  thought  as  something 
real  and  to  be  distinguished  from  other  modes.  These 
modes  of  thought,  moreover,  cannot  be  called  ideas, 
nor  can  they  be  said  to  be  true  or  false,  just  as  love, 
e.  g.,  cannot  be  called  true  or  false  but  only  good  or 
evil.  So  when  Plato  said  that  "  man  is  a  biped  with- 
out feathers,"  he  did  not  err  more  than  if  he  had  said 
that  man  is  a  rational  animal.  For  Plato  knew  that 
man  was  a  rational  animal  as  well  as  he  knew  the 
other.  He  merely  put  man  into  a  certain  class,  so 
that  when  he  wished  to  reflect  upon  man  by  recurring 
to  the  class  in  which  he  had  been  classified  he  would 
come  immediately  to  recognize  certain  characteristics 
as  belonging  to  his  nature.  Aristotle,  indeed,  made 
a  grave  mistake  if  he  thought  that  Plato  in  this  defi- 
nition attempted  to  express  the  essence  of  human 
nature.  Whether  Plato  did  well  we  may  question,  but 
this  is  not  the  place  to  discuss  that. 

From  all  that  has  been  said  above 

In   our  investigation   .  f  . 

of  things,  real       it  appears  that  there  is  no  conformity 

being   must   not  .  ...  ,     ,      .  f 

be  confused  with  between  real  being  and  being  of  rea- 
being  of  reason.    gon^     Therefore,  it  is  easily  seen  how 

seduously  we  must  be  on  our  guard  lest  we  confuse 
the  two.  For  it  is  one  thing  to  inquire  into  the  nature 
of  things  and  quite  another  to  inquire  into  the  nature 
of  the  modes  of  thought  under  which  they  are  per- 
ceived.    If  we  do  not  keep  this  distinction  clear  we 


PART  I  119 

will  be  unable  to  understand  modes  of  perception,  or 
the  nature  of  things  in  themselves.  But  what  is  more 
important,  since  this  affects  so  many  things,  is  that 
this  is  the  reason  we  often  fall  into  such  great  error. 

It  should  be  noted  also  that  many 

I11   what   way    being  .  --,'.. 

of  reason  and       confuse  being  of  reason  and  fictitious 

fictitious     being        .      .  „..  .   .     ,  .  . 

are  distinguish-  being.  1  hey  think  that  the  one  is 
equal  to  the  other  because  neither  has 
an  extra-mental  existence.  But  if  they  would  con- 
sider the  definitions  of  each,  great  and  important  dif- 
ferences would  be  found,  not  only  in  respect  to  their 
cause,  but  in  their  nature  apart  from  their  cause. 

For  we  affirm  that  fictitious  being  is  nothing  but 
two  terms  connected  by  the  mere  act  of  volition  with- 
out any  dependence  upon  reason.  Being  of  reason 
does  not  depend  upon  the  will  alone  nor  is  it  formed 
by  terms,  as  is  evident  without  a  rational  connection 
between  them,  from  the  definition  itself.  If  one  should 
ask,  therefore,  whether  fictitious  being,  or  being  of 
reason  is  real  it  should  be  answered  that  it  is  wrong 
to  divide  all  being  into  real  being  and  being  of  reason. 
The  question  is  fundamentally  wrong  for  it  presup- 
poses that  all  being  is  divided  into  real  being  and  being 
of  reason. 
~,      >•  •  •        *  But    to    return    to    the    proposition 

1  lie    division    of  if 

Being.  from  which  we  seem  to  have  digressed. 

From  the  definition  of  Being  or,  if  you  prefer,  from  its 
description,  it  is  now  easily  seen  that  Being  should  not 
be  divided  into  Being  which,  because  of  its  own  nature 
necessarily  exists,  or  Being  whose  essence  involves 
existence,  and  into  Being  whose  essence  involves  only 
a  possible  existence.  This  last  is  divided  into  Sub- 
stance and  Modes,  the  definitions  of  which  are  given  in 
the  Principles  of  Phil,  Pt.  I.,  Articles  51,  52  and  56. 


120  THE  COGITATA  METAPHYSICA 

We  need  not,  therefore,  repeat  them  here.  In  regard 
to  this,  however,  and  I  say  it  deliberately,  I  wish  it  to 
be  noted  that  Being  is  divided  into  Substance  and 
Modes,  not  into  Substance  and  Accidents.  For  Acci- 
dent is  nothing  but  a  mode  of  thought  and  exists  only 
in  regard  to  this.  For  example,  when  I  say  that  a  tri- 
angle is  moved  the  motion  is  not  a  mode  of  the  triangle 
but  of  the  body  moved.  Therefore,  in  respect  to  the 
triangle  motion  is  only  an  accident  but  in  respect  to 
the  body  it  is  real  being  or  mode ;  for  motion  cannot 
be  conceived  without  a  body  but  it  may  without  a 
triangle. 

Further,  in  order  that  we  may  the  better  understand 
what  has  been  said  and  what  is  to  follow,  we  will 
attempt  to  explain  briefly  what  is  meant  by  the  terms 
essence,  existence,  idea,  and  power.  We  are  the  more 
urged  to  do  this  by  the  ignorance  of  those  who  do  not 
recognize  the  distinction  between  essence  and  exist- 
ence, or  if  they  do  recognize  it  still  confuse  the  terms 
essence  with  the  terms  idea  or  power.  Therefore,  in 
order  to  help  them  and  to  make  the  matter  plain  we 
attempt  to  explain  this  as  clearly  as  possible. 

Chapter  II. 

What  should  be  understood  by  the  terms  Essence, 
Existence,  Idea  and  Power. 

In  order  that  it  may  be  known  what  content  to  give 
to  these  four  terms,  it  is  necessary  that  we  should 
understand  clearly  what  may  be  said  of  uncreated  sub- 
stance, or  God.     Namely: 


PART  I  121 

I.     That    God    eminently    contains 
All  created  things    all  that  is  formally  contained  in  created 

are    eminently 

contained  in  God.  things,  that  is,  Grod  has  certain  at- 
tributes in  which  these  created  things 
are  more  eminently  contained  than  in  the  things  them- 
selves. (Vid.  Pt.  I.  Ax.  8,  and  Coroll.  I.  Prop.  12  >. 
For  example,  we  can  clearly  conceive  of  extension 
without  existing  objects,  and  thus,  since  it  has  no 
power  of  existence  in  itself,  we  have  shown  that  it 
was  created  by  God  (Prop.  21,  Pt.  I.).  And,  since 
there  must  be  as  much  perfection  in  the  cause  as  there 
is  in  the  effect,  it  follows  that  God  contains  all  the 
perfection  of  existence.  But  since  we  find  later  that 
extended  matter  is  divisible,  that  is,  that  it  contains 
a  mark  of  imperfection,  we  cannot,  therefore,  attribute 
extension  to  God.  We  are  thus  compelled  to  admit 
that  God  has  some  attribute  more  excellent  than  all 
the  perfection  of  matter  and  thus  contains  (Schol. 
Prop.  9,  Pt.  I.)  what  the  defects  of  matter  cannot 
supply. 

2.  God  understands  Himself  and  all  other  objects; 
that  is,  He  holds  all  things  objectively,  in  Himself 
(Pt.  I.  Prop.  9) 

3.  God  is  the  first  cause  of  all  things,  and  works 
from  an  absolute  freedom  of  will. 

From  these  things  it  is  evident  what 

understood  by       we    must    understand    bv    these    four 

iZTInd "™?"  terms.     In  the  first  place  Essence  in 

nothing  else  than  that  mode  by  which 

created  objects  are  comprehended  in  the  attributes  of 

God;  an  idea  is  Idea  so  far  as  all  things  are  objectively 

contained  in  the  idea  of  God ;  Power  is  so  called  in 

respect  to  the  power  of  God,  by  which,  by  an  absolute 

freedom  of  will  He  was  able  to  create  everything  that 


122  THE  COGITATA  METAPHYSICA 

exists ;  finally,  existence  is  the  essence  of  things 
apart  from  God,  and,  considered  in  itself  alone,  is 
attributed  to  things  after  they  have  been  created  by 
God. 

These  four  terms  From  this   {t   is   evident   that  these 

are  not  distin-     four  terms  are  not  to  be  distinguished 

guished   the  one  & 

from  the  other     except  in  created  objects;  in  God,  in 

except    m    created 

objects.  no    way    can    they    be    differentiated. 

For  we  cannot  conceive  that  God  is  in  the  power  of 
another,  and  His  existence,  and  His  understanding 
are  not  to  be  separated  from  His  essence. 

From  what   has   been   said   we   can 

A  reply  to  certain  j-i  i  ,  .    •  ,■ 

questions    con-       readily     reply     to     certain     questions 

Essenc8e.G°dS  which     have     been     asked-       Sucll>     f°r 

example,  are  the  following:  Whether 
essence  is  different  from  existence;  and  if  different,  is 
it  something  diverse  from  idea;  and  if  different  from 
idea,  does  it  comprehend  something  extra-mental; 
which  last  follows  from  necessity.  To  the  first  in 
regard  to  distinction  we  would  reply,  that  essence  in 
God  is  not  different  from  existence,  indeed  the  one 
cannot  be  conceived  without  the  other.  In  other 
things  essence  differs  from  existence,  for  the  one  may 
be  conceived  without  the  other.  To  the  second  point 
we  respond,  that  things  which  can  be  clearly  and  dis- 
tinctly conceived  as  extra-mental  are  something  differ- 
ent from  idea.  But  then  it  is  asked,  whether  that 
which  is  extra-mental  exists  in  itself  alone,  or  whether 
it  has  been  created  by  God.  To  this  we  reply,  that 
formal  essence  does  not  exist  by  its  own  power,  nor 
even  when  created.  These  two  conditions  presup- 
pose that  the  object  exists  in  fact ;  but  they  depend 
upon  the  divine  essence  alone,  in  which  all  things  are 
contained.     So  far  we  would  assent  to  the  opinion  of 


PART  I  123 

those  who  affirm  that  the  essence  of  things  is  eternal. 
Again  it  may  be  asked,  How  can  we  understand  the 
essence  of  things,  when  God's  nature  is  not  yet  known; 
for  all  things,  as  we  have  just  said,  depend  upon  the 
nature  of  God.  To  this  I  reply  that  it  is  possible 
from  the  fact  that  things  are  now  actually  created. 
For  if  things  were  not  yet  created  I  would  concede 
that  it  would  be  impossible  until  we  had  an  adequate 
knowledge  of  God's  nature.  In  the  same  way  it  is 
impossible,  indeed  more  impossible  then  for  us  to 
know  the  orderly  nature  of  the  applications  of  a  para- 
bola whose  nature  is  not  yet  known. 

Although  the  essence  of  non-exist- 

Why    the   author   in    .  .  1  1     1      •         ,1 

his  definition  of    ing    modes    is    comprehended    in    the 

essence    Tcfevs    to  1  i*       1  1  1        1      * 

the  attributes  of   substance  oi   these   modes,   and   their 
God'  real  essence  is  these  substances,  never- 

theless we  desire  to  refer  them  to  God  in  order  to  ex- 
plain the  essence  of  modes  and  of  substances  in  general 
terms,  and  because  the  essence  of  modes  was  not  in 
substance  prior  to  creation  and  we  are  seeking  for  an 
eternal  essence. 

I  do  not  think  it  worth  while  to  re- 
Why  the  definitions  fute  those   authors   who  think  difTer- 

of    others    are  m 

not  examined.  ently  from  us,  or  even  to  examine  their 
definitions  or  descriptions  of  essence 
and  existence ;  this  would  only  make  what  is  clear 
more  obscure.  What,  indeed,  is  better  known  than 
the  meaning  of  essence  or  existence?  How  can  we 
give  a  definition  of  anything  which  does  not  at  the 
same  time  explain  its  essence? 

Finally,  if  any  philosopher  is  yet  in 
HTJtlfxfZc^rT  doubt   whether   essence  and   existence 

between     essence 

and  existence  can  are  distinguishable  in  created  objects, 

easily  be  seen.  °  J 

he  need  not  take  much  trouble  to  re- 


124  THE  COGITATA  METAPHYSICA 

move  that  doubt.  For  if  he  will  merely  approach 
some  statue  or  object  of  wood,  he  will  see  how  he 
conceives  of  the  object  not  yet  existing  in  a  certain 
manner,  and  how  he  knows  that  it  is  really  existing. 

Chapter  III. 

Concerning  those  things  which  are  Necessary,  Im- 
possible, Possible,  and  Contingent. 

The  nature  of  being  as  being  hav- 
What  is  here  ing  been  explained  we  would  next  con- 

understood    by  •  ■,  r    •.  rr  t.  i 

the  Affects  sider  some  of  its  affects.     It  may  be 

remarked  here,  that  by  affects  we 
understand  what  Descartes  termed  attributes  (Pt.  I. 
Prin.  Phil.  Art.  52).  For  being,  considered  merely 
as  being  does  not  affect  us  as  substance.  Wherefore 
it  must  be  explained  by  some  attribute  which  is  recog- 
nized only  by  reason.  Wherefore  I  cannot  wonder 
enough,  at  the  extreme  subtlety  of  those  who,  not 
without  deleterious  consequences  to  truth,  try  to  find 
some  middle  ground  between  being  and  nothing.  But 
I  will  not  delay  to  refute  this  error,  seeing  that  it 
fades  into  their  own  vain  subtlety  when  they  attempt 
to  give  a  definition  of  the  affects. 

We  then  take  up  the  matter  at  once 
DeAffec°tl  °f  the  and  say :  The  affects  of  being  are  cer- 
tain attributes  under  which  we  conic 
to  understand  the  essence  or  existence  of  every  single 
thing,  which  attributes,  however,  are  only  distinguish- 
able by  reason.  I  shall  attempt  here  to  explain  cer- 
tain things  about  these  (for  I  do  not  assume  that  all 
understand  this  thoroughly)  and  to  separate  by  proper 
terms  those  things  which  are  not  the  affects  of  being. 


PART  I  125 

First  I  shall  discuss  what  is  meant  by  necessary  and 
impossible. 

There  are  two  ways  in  which  a  tiling 

In    how   many    ways 

a  thing  may  be     may  be  said  to  be  necessary  or  impos- 

SOltl      to      \)€      1\€C€Sm 

sary  or  impos-  sible,  viz.,  in  respect  to  its  essence  or 
its  cause.  In  respect  to  His  essence 
we  know  that  God  necessarily  exists.  For  His  essence 
cannot  be  conceived  without  existence.  From  the 
implicated  essence  of  chimeras  they  cannot  exist.  In 
respect  to  their  cause,  things,  i.  e.,  materials,  are  either 
impossible  or  necessary.  For  if  we  merely  regard 
their  essence,  it  is  possible  to  clearly  conceive  of  that 
without  their  existence.  Therefore,  they  cannot  exist 
by  the  power  and  necessity  of  their  own  essence  but 
only  by  the  power  of  their  cause,  viz.,  God  the 
creator  of  all  things.  If,  thus,  it  is  the  divine  decree 
that  something  should  exist,  it  exists  from  necessity, 
or  if  less  than  this,  it  will  be  impossible  for  it  to  exist. 
For  it  is  a  self-evident  fact  that  that  which  has  no 
cause,  internal  or  external,  for  its  existence,  cannot 
possibly  exist.  And  an  object  under  this  hypothesis 
is  so  conceived  that  it  cannot  exist  by  the  power  of 
its  own  essence,  by  which  I  mean  an  internal  cause, 
nor  by  the  divine  decree,  the  one  external  cause  of  all 
things.  Whence  it  follows  that  objects  under  such 
condition  cannot  exist  at  all. 

It  should  be  noted:     I.  A  chimera 
a  chimera  is  right-  because  it  exists  neither  in  the  intel- 

ly   called  a  mere      ,  ,,  .  .         .    ,  ,, 

verbal  being.         lect  nor  in  the  imagination  is  rightly 

called  a  mere  verbal  being ;  for  we  can 

only  express  this  idea  in  words.     For  example,  we  use 

the  words  "  a  square  circle/'  expressing  it  in  words, 

but  we  are  by  no  means  able  to  imagine  it,  much  less 


126  THE  C0G1TATA  METAPHYSICA 

to  understand  it.     Therefore  chimera  is  only  a  word 
and  cannot  be  numbered  among  the  affects  of  being. 

2.  We  must  remember  that  not  only 
°hF*£%£.  does  the  existence  of  all  created  things 

7romeXGoTlce  depend  upon  God's  decree,  but  their 
essence  and  nature  as  well.  This  will 
be  clearly  shown  in  Part  II.  below.  Whence  it  follows 
that  created  objects  have  no  necessity  in  themselves, 
for  their  essence  is  not  self  derived.  No  more  do 
they  exist  by  their  own  power. 

3.  Finally,   it  should  be  noted  that 

TI[erJatedSSol%'cts  is  tne  necessity  of  created  objects,  such 
derived  from        as  we  £nc|  there   from  the  power  of 

their    cause,    and  " 

relates  to  their      the  cause,  is  either  in  respect  to  their 

essence   or  exist-  *■  _ 

ence.     in  God      essence  or  to  their  extension.     These 

these   two   things  .  t 

are  not  to  be       two  must  be  distinguished  in  created 

distinguished.  1  .  rT,1  .  .  . 

objects.  I  he  one  depends  upon  the 
eternal  laws  of  nature,  the  other  upon  the  series  and 
the  order  of  its  causes.  In  God  whose  essence  and 
existence  are  the  same,  necessity  of  essence  is  equiva- 
lent to  necessity  of  existence.  Whence  it  follows  that 
if  we  conceive  of  the  whole  order  of  Nature  we  will 
find  that  many  things  cannot  exist  whose  nature  we 
conceive  clearly  and  distinctly,  that  is,  whose  nature 
is  such  of  necessity.  For  we  find  that  it  is  equally 
impossible  for  such  things  to  be,  as  for  example  we 
know  that  it  is  impossible  for  a  great  elephant  to  pass 
through  the  eye  of  a  needle.  Nevertheless  the  nature 
of  each  is  clearly  conceived. 

Therefore  things  of  this  nature  do  not  exist  except 
chimeras,  which  we  are  able  neither  to  imagine  nor 
to  understand. 


PART  I  127 

So  much  concerning  necessity  and 
Possibility  and  con-  impossibility ;  to  which  it  seems  best 
alhctPo™ 'things,  t°  add  a  few  remarks  concerning  what 
is  possible  and  what  is  contingent. 
For  by  some,  these  two  terms  are  considered  affects 
of  things,  although,  in  truth,  they  are  nothing  more 
than  defects  of  our  intellect.  This  I  shall  clearly  show 
after  I  have  explained  what  should  be  understood  by 
these  terms. 

A  thing;  is  said  to  be  possible  when 

What   is   possible,  °  .  L 

what  is  contin-  ive  understand  its  efficient  cause,  out 
do  not  know  zvhether  it  is  determined. 
Therefore,  we  may  consider  that  to  be  possible  which 
is  neither  necessary  or  impossible.  If  now  we  attend 
merely  to  the  essence  of  a  thing  and  not  to  its  cause, 
we  say  it  is  contingent ;  that  is,  when  we  consider 
any  things  between  the  extremes  God  and  chimeras. 
This  is  true,  for  from  a  part  of  their  essence  we  find 
no  necessity  of  existence  in  these  things  as  in  God, 
nor  impossibility  of  existence  as  in  chimeras.  If  any 
one  wishes  to  call  that  contingent  which  I  call  possible 
and  possible  what  I  call  contingent  I  shall  not  contra- 
dict him.  For  I  am  not  accustomed  to  dispute  about 
mere  names.  It  will  be  sufficient  if  it  is  only  admitted 
that  these  arise  not  because  of  something  real,  but 
only  because  of  defects  of  our  perception. 

If  any  one  chooses  to  deny  this  his 

Possible   and   con-  .  1  .  .  ,      ■c-.i 

tingent  only  sig-  error  may  be  pointed  out  with  little 
our  understand-  trouble.  For  if  he  will  consider  Na- 
mg'  ture  and  how  it  all  depends  upon  God, 

he  will  find  nothing  contingent.  That  is,  he  will  find 
nothing,  which,  from  a  part  of  the  object  is  able  to 
exist  and  not  exist,  or,  as  it  is  generally  expressed,  the 
contingent   is   the   real.     This   is   evident,   also,   from 


128  THE  COGITATA  METAPHYSICA 

what  was  said  in  Ax.  10,  Pt.  I.  namely,  that  no  more 
power  was  needed  to  create  the  world  than  to  con- 
serve it.  Therefore  no  created  object  does  anything 
by  its  own  power  for  the  same  reason  that  it  did  not 
begin  to  exist  by  its  own  power.  From  which  it  fol- 
lows that  nothing  has  been  created  except  by  the  power 
of  the  Cause  which  has  created  all  things,  namely,  the 
power  of  God,  who  by  His  concurrence  procreates 
everything  every  single  moment.  And  since  nothing 
exists  except  by  divine  power  alone,  it  is  easily  seen 
that  the  world  as  produced  by  God's  decree  is  such  as 
he  wished  it  to  be.  So,  too,  since  there  is  no  change  or 
inconstancy  in  God  (per  Prop.  18  and  Coroll.  Prop. 
20,  Pt.  I.),  those  things  which  He  now  produces,  He 
has  decreed  from  eternity  that  they  should  be  pro- 
duced. Then  since  nothing  more  is  needed  for  their 
existence  than  God's  decree  that  they  should  exist,  it 
follows  that  the  necessity  of  the  existence  of  all  created 
things  has  existed  from  eternity.  Nor  can  we  say 
that  these  things  are  contingent  since  God  might  have 
decreed  otherwise.  For  since  in  eternity  there  are  no 
effects  of  time  neither  a  future  nor  a  past,  it  follows 
that  God  did  not  exist  before  that  decree,  so  that  he 
was  able  to  decree  something  else. 

Whatever   pertains   to   the   freedom 
The   reconciliation    0f  the  human  will,  which  we  have  said 

of  our  Freedom 

with  the  predes-   is  free   ( Schol.  Prop.  1 5,  Pt.  I.),  that 

tination    of    God's      1 

will  surpasses        also  is  conserved  by  the  concurrence 

human   under-  .    ^,      ,         ■>,  .       ,.  . 

standing.  of  God.     Nor  is  there  any  man  who 

wishes  or  does  anything  who  does  not 
do  as  God  has  decreed  from  eternity  that  he  should 
choose  or  act.  In  what  way  this  is  possible,  human 
freedom  being  preserved,  man  is  unable  to  understand. 
Since  we  clearly  conceive  this,  our  ignorance  of  how 


PART  I  129 

it  can  be  should  not  lead  us  to  reject  this  truth.  For 
we  clearly  and  distinctly  understand,  if  we  consider 
our  nature,  that  we  are  free  in  our  actions,  and  we 
deliberate  about  many  things  simply  because  we  choose 
to  do  so.  And  on  the  other  hand  if  we  consider  the 
nature  of  God  in  the  way  we  have  indicated,  we  see 
clearly  and  distinctly  that  all  things  depend  upon  Him 
and  that  nothing  exists  except  as  it  has  been  decreed 
from  all  eternity.  In  what  way  the  human  will  can 
be  thus  procreated  by  God  so  that  it  retains  its  free- 
dom, we  do  not  know.  Indeed,  there  are  many  things 
which  surpass  our  comprehension,  and  yet  we  know 
that  they  are  so  ordained  by  God ;  as  for  example,  that 
there  is  a  real  division  of  matter  into  indefinite  parts, 
which  was  sufficiently  proven  in  Proposition  11,  Part 
II.  although  we  do  not  understand  how  such  a  divi- 
sion can  be.  These  two  motions,  viz.,  possible  and 
contingent,  which  we  use  in  place  of  the  thing  known, 
only  signify  a  defect  of  our  knowledge  about  the 
existence  of  the  given  object. 

Chapter  IV. 

Concerning  Duration  and  Time. 

Because    above,    we    have    divided 

What  Eternity    is.     ,     .  •  «     .  •, 

being  into  being  whose  essence  in- 
volves existence,  and  being  whose  essence  involves 
only  a  possible  existence,  there  arises  the  distinction 
between  eternity  and  duration.  Concerning  eternity 
we  will  speak  at  length  below.  Here  we  would  only 
say  that  it  is  an  attribute  tinder  which  zve  conceive  the 

infinite  existence  of  God.     Duration  is 

What    Duration    is.  ..  ,  ,  .    . 

an  attribute  under  which  we  conceive 


130  THE  COGITATA  METAPHYSICA 

the  existence  of  created  objects  so  far  as  they  perse- 
vere in  their  own  actuality. 

From  which  it  clearly  follows  that 

What    Time  is.  ,  j.     .  .   .      .      r  . 

duration  is  distinguished  from  the 
whole  existence  of  an  object  only  by  the  reason.  For, 
however  much  of  duration  you  take  away  from  any 
thing,  so  much  of  its  existence  do  you  detract  from  it. 
In  order  to  determine  or  measure  this  we  compare  this 
with  the  duration  of  those  objects  which  have  a  fixed 
and  a  certain  motion,  and  this  comparison  is  called  time. 
Therefore,  time  is  not  an  affect  of  things  but  only  a 
mode  of  thought  or,  as  we  have  said,  a  being  of  rea- 
son ;  it  is  a  mode  of  thought  serving  to  explain  dura- 
tion. It  should  be  noted  under  duration,  as  it  will  be 
of  use  when  below  we  are  discussing  eternity,  that  it  is 
conceived  as  greater  or  less,  as  it  were,  composed  of 
parts  and  then  not  only  as  an  attribute  of  existence 
but  as  the  very  essence  of  existence. 

Chapter  V. 

Concerning    Opposition,    Order,    etc. 

Because  we  compare  objects  one  with  another,  there 
are  certain  notions  that  arise,  which,  however  apart 
from  the  things  themselves  are  only  modes  of  thought. 
This  is  very  evident,  since,  when  we  attempt  to  con- 
sider them  as  objects  apart  from  forms  of  thought 
we  hold  the  one  for  the  other  and  render  clear  con- 
cepts obscure.  Such  notions  are  the  following,  viz., 
Opposition,  Order,  Relation,  Diversity,  Connection, 
Conjunction,  and  other  similar  ideas.  These,  I  say. 
are  perceived  by  us  with  sufficient  clearness  provided 
we  do  not  conceive  of  them  as  something  in  the  essence 


PART  I  131 

of  things,  but  only  as  modes  of  thought  by  which  we 
can  more  easily  retain  these  objects  in  memory  and 
imagine  them.  Therefore,  I  do  not  think  it  necessary 
to  speak  further  of  this  but  pass  to  those  terms  com- 
monly called  transcendental. 

Chapter  VI. 

Concerning  Unity,  Truth  and  Goodness. 

By  almost  all  metaphysicians  these  terms  are  held 
to  be  affects  of  being.  For,  they  say,  all  being  is 
one,  true  and  good,  although  no  one  knows  about 
this.  By  examining  each  one  of  these  terms  sepa- 
rately we  shall  be  able  to  understand  their  proper  use. 

We  will  begin  with  the  first,   viz., 

What    Unity  is.  TT     •  r^-,  .  .,  .        .  r 

Unity,  this  term,  they  say,  signifies 
some  extra-mental  reality.  But  what  this  adds  to 
reality  they  are  unable  to  say.  Which  sufficiently 
shows  that  they  confuse  being  of  reason  with  real 
being,  so  that  what  is  perfectly  clear  becomes  obscure. 
We,  on  the  other  hand,  would  say  that  unity  is  in  no 
way  to  be  distinguished  from  the  thing  itself,  and 
that  it  adds  nothing  to  being.  But  it  is  only  a  mode 
of  thought  by  which  we  separate  one  thing  from  an- 
other, when  they  are  similar  or  for  some  reason  occur 
together 

To  the  term   Unity  we  oppose  the 

What  Plurality  is,    term    Plurality,    which    clearly    adds 

ZYlayhV?Jd  nothing  to  things  but  is  only  a  mode 

to  be  one,  andjn     £  bought  which  assists  us  in  under- 

what    sense    sui  o 

generis.  standing  the  objects  of  our  experience. 

Nor  do  I  see  that   anything  remains 

to  be  said  concerning  a  matter  as  self-evident  as  this. 


132  THE  COGITATA  METAPHYSICA 

We  may  add,  however,  that  God  so  far  as  we  separate 
Him  from  other  objects  may  be  said  to  be  one.  But 
so  far  as  we  think  of  His  nature  as  many-sided  He 
cannot  be  called  simple  Unity  (unum  et  unicum).  If 
we  examine  the  matter  more  accurately,  we  can  show 
that  God  is  improperly  called  simple  unity.  But  this 
is  not  of  sufficient  importance  to  make  it  worth  the 
discussion ;  it  is  a  matter  that  affects  not  the  reality 
but  the  names.  Therefore  we  pass  to  the  second 
point  and  explain  what  we  mean  by  '  false.' 

In  order  to  properly  understand  the 
u/un    •,  +„.,*  *1a     terms   true    and   false    we   will   begin 

Whac  is  True  and  '  o 

what  is  false   as   AVith  their  signification  from  which  it 

generally     under-  ° 

stood  and  as         will  appear  that  they  are  not   names 

understood    by 

philosophers.  of   qualities   in   the  things   themselves 

nor  attributes  at  all  except  rhetorically. 
Since  general  usage  first  fixed  their  meaning,  and 
they  were  only  used  afterward  by  philosophers,  it 
seems  best  to  inquire  for  their  primary  significance. 
Especially  is  this  necessary  since  other  sources  from 
the  very  nature  of  language,  are  wanting.  The  sig- 
nificance of  true  and  false  seemed  to  have  first  arisen 
from  narration.  That  narration  was  true  which  was 
in  accord  with  the  facts  which  it  concerned ;  that  was 
false  which  was  not  in  accord  with  the  facts  of  the 
case.  This  use  of  these  terms  was  then  borrowed  by 
philosophers  for  denoting  the  correspondence  of  the 
idea  with  the  thing  it  represents,  and  the  contrary. 
Therefore,  that  idea  is  said  to  be  true  which  repre- 
sents the  thing,  as  it  is  in  itself.  That  idea  is  false 
which  does  not  so  represent  its  object.  For  ideas  are 
nothing  else  than  mental  narratives  or  histories  of  na- 
ture. Afterward  these  are  metaphorically  applied  to 
other  things.     As   for  example,   that  gold   is   true  or 


PART  I  133 

false,  as  if  we  thought  that  gold  which  we  perceive 
might  tell  us  what  was  in  itself,  or  what  is  not. 

Wherefore   those   who   believe   that 

True   is   not  a  .  t  , 

transcendental       true  is   a  transcendental  term,   or  an 
affect  of  being,  are  plainly  deceived. 
For  we  only  apply  this  term  to  things  improperly,  or 
if  you  prefer,  rhetorically. 

If  you   inquire   further   what  truth 
H°trueTXah  dT/er.a  «  but  a  true  idea,  you  do  the  same 
thing  as  to  ask  what  whiteness  is  ex- 
cept a  white  object. 

Concerning  the  cause  of  the  true  and  the  false  we 
have  already  spoken ;  therefore  nothing  remains  to  be 
noted  which  would  be  worth  the  while,  if  writers, 
"  seeking  a  knot  in  the  bulrushes,"  did  not  so  far  en- 
tangle themselves  in  similar  folly  that  they  are  unable 
to  extricate  themselves. 

The  properties  of  truth  or  of  a  true 

What  are  the  Prop-  idea  are  i    I.  That  it  is  clear  and  dis- 

Certitude  iT not     tinct.     2.  That  it  is  beyond  all  doubt, 

%n  t  mgs.  or^  -n  a  worcjj  tnaf-  jt  js  certain.     Those 

who  seek  for  certainty  in  the  things  themselves  are 
deceived  in  the  same  way  as  when  they  seek  there  for 
truth.  Although  we  say  a  thing  is  uncertain,  we  rhe- 
torically take  the  object  for  the  idea,  and  in  the  same 
way  we  say  that  a  thing  is  doubtful.  Unless,  per- 
chance, we  understand  by  uncertainty,  contingency  or 
the  thing  which  makes  us  uncertain  or  doubtful.  But 
there  is  no  need  to  delay  about  this  point.  Therefore 
we  proceed  to  the  third  point  and  will  explain  what  is 
meant  by  this  term  and  its  opposite. 

An    object    considered    in    itself    is 
Good  and  Evil  only  neither  good  nor  evil,  but  only  in  re- 

relative   terms.  . 

spect  to  another  being,  which  it  helps 


134  THE  COGITATA  METAPHYSICA 

to  acquire  what  is  desired,  or  the  contrary.     Indeed, 

the  same  thing  at  the  same  time  may  be  both  good 

and  evil  in  respect  to  different  things.     For  example, 

the  council  of  Ahithophel  to  Absalom  is  called  good  in 

the  Sacred  Scriptures.     But  it  was  the  worst  possible 

to   David,   whose   destruction   it   would   have   caused. 

So  there  are  many  things  which  are  good,  but  not  good 

for  all.     Health  is  good  for  man,  but  neither  good  nor 

evil  to  senseless  matter  or  to  plants,  to  which  it  does 

not  apply.     God  is  called  perfectly  good  because  He 

preserves  all  things.     He  conserves  all  things  by  His 

concurrence,  and  no  greater  mark  of  goodness  could 

be  found  than  this.     Nor  is  there  any  absolute  evil, 

as  is  also  evident  in  itself. 

Those  who  seek  for  some  metaphysi- 
al v   some   conceive        .  .         .  .   .         i     11     *  r  r 

of  a  metaphysical  cal  good  which  shall  be  free  from 
relativity  are  laboring  under  a  misap- 
prehension of  the  case.  They  confuse  a  distinction  of 
Reason  with  a  distinction  of  Reality  or  Modality. 
They  distinguish  between  the  thing  itself,  and  its  con- 
atus,  by  which  each  object  is  conserved,  although 
they  do  not  know  what  they  mean  by  the  term  conatus. 
For  these  two  things,  although  they  are  distinguished 
by  reason,  or  by  words,  which  fact  deceives  them, 
are  not  to  be  distinguished  in  the  thing  itself. 

In  order  to  understand  this  we  will 
How  the  thing         notice   a   very   simple   example.     Mo- 

itself,   and    the  .  •  1  ,1  r  .,       ,r 

conatus  by  which  tion  has  the  power  of  preserving  itself 

every     object    en-    •  ,     .  ,  1  •  1         1         • 

deavors  to  con-  Vl  statu  quo;  this  power  clearly  is 
pZ7entSsifate',1  are  nothing  else  than  the  motion  itself, 
g°uished!stt"  l-  e->  it  is  m  tne  nature  of  motion  to 

do  so.  If  I  say  that  in  A  there  is 
nothing  else  than  a  certain  amount  of  motion,  it  fol- 
lows that  as  long  as   I  consider  only  this  body  A,  I 


PART  I  135 

must  consider  it  as  moving.  For  if  I  should  say  that 
it  has  lost  its  power  of  motion,  I  necessarily  attribute 
something  else  to  it  than  that  which,  from  the  hypothe- 
sis, it  possessed,  and  through  this,  it  has  lost  its  power 
of  motion.  If  this  reason  seems  obscure  — ■  well  then 
we  will  concede  that  this  conatus  of  self-movement  is 
something  more  than  the  laws  and  nature  of  motion. 
If,  therefore,  you  suppose  this  conatus  to  be  a  meta- 
physical good,  from  necessity  you  must  suppose  that 
this  conatus  will  have  in  it  a  conatus  of  self-preserva- 
tion, and  this  another,  and  so  on  to  infinity,  than  which 
I  do  not  know  anything  more  absurd.  The  reason 
some  distinguish  between  the  conatus  of  an  object 
and  the  thing  itself  is  this,  namely,  because  they  find 
in  themselves  the  desire  of  conserving  themselves, 
they  imagine  the  desire  is  present  in  everything. 
Whether  God  could       Moreover,  it  is  asked  whether  God 

gZd,bbeeforealled     COuM     haVe     beei1     Called     g°°d     bef°re 

creation.  creation.     From  our  definition  it  would 

seem  that  we  could  not  predicate  such  an  attribute  as 
belonging  to  God,  for  we  said  that  a  thing  considered 
in  itself  alone  can  neither  be  said  to  be  good  or  evil. 
This  will  seem  absurd  to  many ;  but  for  what  reason 
I  do  not  know.  We  attribute  many  things  of  this 
kind  to  God,  which,  before  creation,  could  not  exist 
except  potentially ;  as  for  example,  when  He  is  called 
Creator,  Judge  merciful,  etc.  Wherefore  similar  ar- 
guments should  be  allowed  us  here. 

And  further,  as  good  and  evil  are 
Infe™non  TreiaHve]  only  relative  terms,  so  also  is  perfec- 

%absoiute.scn5e        ^on»  un^ess  we  take  perfection  for  the 
essence  of  the  thing;  in  this  sense,  as 
we  have  said  before,  God  has  infinite  perfection,  that 
is   infinite  essence,  and  infinite  being. 


136  THE  COGITATA  METAPHYSICA 

It  is  not  my  intention  to  say  much  more.  For  the 
remaining  remarks,  which  pertain  to  general  meta- 
physics, I  believe,  are  sufficiently  well  known.  It  is 
not  worth  while,  therefore,  to  carry  the  discussion 
further. 


COGITATA    METAPHYSICA, 

Part  II. 

Wherein  are  briefly  explained  some  points  concern- 
ing God  and  His  Attributes,  and  concerning  the  Hu- 
man Mind. 


137 


Chapter  I. 

Concerning  the  Eternity  of  God. 

We  have  said  above  that  in  Nature  nothing  is  given 
except  substance  and  modes.  Therefore  it  will  not 
be  expected  that  we  shall  say  here  anything  about 
substantial  forms,  or  real  qualities ;  for  these  terms, 
as  well  as  other  similar  ones,  are  plainly  inapt.  We 
divide  substance  into  two  general  heads,  namely,  Ex- 
tension and  Thought.  Thought  is  either  created,  the 
human  mind,  or  uncreated,  i.  e.,  God.  God's  exist- 
ence we  have  above  demonstrated  a  posteriori,  that  is, 
from  the  idea  which  we  have  of  God,  and  a  priori,  or 
from  His  essence  as  the  cause  of  His  being.  But, 
although  we  have  already  briefly  considered  His  at- 
tributes, as  the  dignity  of  the  argument  requires,  we 
will  here  repeat  these  and  explain  them  more  fully, 
and  at  the  same  time  endeavor  to  answer  certain  ques- 
tions bearing  upon  the  subject. 

The  chief  attribute,  the  one  to  be 
DTjZeiStonGot  considered  before  all  others,  is  the 
Eternity  of  God.  This  term  we  em- 
ploy to  explain  His  duration.  Or,  rather,  as  we  can- 
not predicate  duration  of  God,  we  say  He  is  eternal. 
For,  as  we  noted  in  the  first  part  of  this  discussion, 
duration  is  an  affect  of  existence  not  of  the  essence 
of  things.  And  since  God's  existence  is  His  essence, 
we  cannot  say  that  duration  belongs  to  Him.  For 
whoever  predicates  duration  as  one  of  God's  attributes 

i39 


i4o  THE  COGITATA  METAPHYSICA 

differentiates  between  His  existence  and  His  essence. 
Nevertheless,  there  are  those  who  ask  if  God  has  not 
existed  longer  than  from  the  time  of  Adam,  and  this 
seems  to  them  to  be  perfectly  evident  since  they  be- 
lieve that  duration  in  no  way  is  derived  from  God. 
But  these  persons  beg  the  question ;  for  they  assume 
that  God's  essence  is  to  be  distinguished  from  His 
existence.  They  demand  to  know  whether  God,  who 
existed  before  the  creation  of  Adam,  has  not  existed 
for  a  longer  time  than  from  the  creation  to  the  pres- 
ent. They  attribute,  therefore,  a  longer  duration  to 
God  than  to  individual  objects,  as  if  they  suppose  that 
He  is  continually  created  by  Himself.  Did  they  not 
distinguish  between  God's  essence  and  His  existence, 
they  would  never  attribute  duration  to  God,  since  du- 
ration does  not  correspond  to  the  essence  of  things. 
No  one  would  say  that  the  essence  of  a  circle  or  a 
triangle,  so  far  as  it  is  eternal  truth,  has  endured  for 
a  longer  time  than  from  the  creation  of  Adam.  Fur- 
ther, since  duration  is  constantly  conceived  of  as  greater 
or  less,  or  as  consisting  of  parts,  it  clearly  follows 
duration  cannot  be  attributed  to  God.  For  qs  His 
being  is  eternal,  i.  e.,  there  is  no  past  or  future  to  His 
nature,  when  we  find  that  we  cannot  attribute  dura- 
tion to  Him  we  have  shown  that  our  concept  of  God  is 
true.  If  we  attribute  duration  to  God,  we  separate 
into  parts  what  is  infinite  by  nature  and  cannot  be  con- 
ceived except  as  infinite. 

The  reason  some  authors  attribute 

Why    some    authors      .  .  ~,     ,  -,-.  - 

attribute  Juration  duration  to  God,  is  :    i.  Because  they 
attempt    to    explain    eternity    without 
considering   the   nature  of  God ;   as  if  eternity  could 
be  understood  apart  from  the  divine  essence,  or,  in- 
deed, as  if  it  was  anything  except  this.     This  error 


PART  II  141 

arose  from  the  fact  that  because  of  a  defective  termin- 
ology, we  have  been  accustomed  to  attribute  eternity 
to  things  whose  essence  is  different  from  their  exist- 
ence. As,  for  example,  when  we  say  that  the  world 
has  existed  from  eternity,  although  this  is  not  implied ; 
and  also  that  the  essence  of  things  is  eternal,  although 
we    do    not    think    of    the   things    as    even    existing. 

2.  Because  they  do  not  attribute  duration  to  things 
except  so,  far  as  they  are  conceived  to  be  under  con- 
tinual change,  and  not  as  we  do,  only  so  far  as  their 
essence  is   to  be   distinguished   from  their   existence. 

3.  Finally,  because  they  distinguish  between  God's 
essence  and  His  existence  just  as  in  the  case  of  created 
objects.  These  mistakes  are  at  the  basis  of  their  error. 
The  first  error  was  a  misapprehension  of  the  nature 
of  eternity,  which  was  thought  to  be  some  form  of 
duration.  In  the  second,  they  could  not  easily  dis- 
tinguish between  the  duration  of  created  objects  and 
the  eternity  of  God.  Lastly,  they  distinguished  be- 
tween God's  essence  and  His  existence,  and  attributed 
duration  to  God,  as  we  have  said,  as  though  it  were 
an  affect  of  existence. 

In  order  to  better  understand  what 

What    eternity    is.  11       •  1        1        •  1 

eternity  really  is  and  why  it  cannot  be 
conceived  apart  from  the  essence  of  God,  we  should 
remember  what  has  already  been  said,  viz.,  that  all 
created  objects  or  all  things  except  God  Himself  ex- 
ist by  the  power  and  essence  of  God,  not  by  virtue  of 
their  own  essence.  Hence  the  present  existence  of 
objects  is  not  the  cause  of  their  future  existence,  but 
rather  the  immutability  of  God.  So  when  we  say  that 
God  has  created  an  object  we  are  compelled  to  believe 
that  He  will  conserve  it  or  continue  His  act  of  crea- 
tion.    From  this   we   conclude:     I.  That  created  ob- 


142  THE  COGITATA  METAPHYSICA 

jects  are  said  to  exist  because  existence  is  not  a  part 
of  their  essence.  We  cannot  affirm  existence  of  God, 
for  the  existence  of  God  is  God  Himself.  So,  also, 
concerning  His  essence.  Hence,  while  created  objects 
have  duration,  God  does  not.  2.  Created  objects, 
while  they  have  a  present  duration  and  existence,  do 
not  have  in  themselves  a  future  duration  or  existence, 
for  this  must  be  continually  given  to  them.  This, 
however,  is  not  true  of  the  essence  of  created  objects. 
Indeed,  since  His  existence  and  His  essence  are  one, 
we  cannot  attribute  a  future  existence  to  God.  For 
we  must  attribute  to  Him  now  what  He  has  always 
had.  Or,  to  speak  more  properly,  an  infinite  exist- 
ence pertains  to  God  in  the  same  way  as  an  infinite 
intelligence.  This  infinite  existence  I  call  eternity. 
This  can  be  attributed  to  God  alone,  not  to  created  ob- 
jects, even  though  they  have  no  end.  So  much  con- 
cerning eternity.  I  shall  say  nothing  of  the  necessity 
of  God's  being,  for  after  we  have  demonstrated  His 
existence  from  His  essence  this  would  be  useless. 
Hence  we  proceed  to  unity. 

Chapter  II. 

Concerning  the  Unity  of  God. 

We  have  often  wondered  at  the  futile  arguments 
by  which  some  have  sought  to  establish  the  unity  of 
God.  For  example,  such  as  the  following:  "If  one 
being  is  able  to  create  the  world,  more  than  one  would 
be  superfluous ;  and,  if  all  things  work  toward  some 
end,  they  must  have  a  common  source."  Other  sim- 
ilar arguments  might  be  mentioned  where  proof  is 
sought    from    relative    or    extrinsic    elements.     Since 


PART  II  143 

such  ideas  are  sometimes  held,  we  shall,  in  the  follow- 
ing order,   and  as  clearly  and  as  briefly  as  possible, 
give  our  demonstration. 
•       .         .    ,  Among   the    attributes   of  God    we 

God    is   a    single 

being.  enumerate  perfect  knowledge,  and  add 

that  His  perfection  all  arises  from  His  own  being. 
But  if  you  say  that  there  are  many  Gods  or  perfect 
beings,  all  of  them  must  be  omniscient.  It  would  not 
be  sufficient  for  each  one  merely  to  know  himself. 
For  as  each  is  omniscient  he  must  understand  all  other 
beings  as  well  as  himself.  From  which  it  would  fol- 
low that  the  omniscience  of  each  depends  partly  upon 
himself  and  partly  upon  another.  Therefore  such  a 
being  would  not  be  absolutely  perfect.  That  is,  God 
would  not  be  a  being  who  derives  all  of  his  perfection 
from  Himself.  But  we  have  already  shown  that  God 
is  in  every  way  perfect  and  that  He  exists  by  virtue 
of  His  own  power.  From  which  we  conclude  that 
God  is  one  being.  For  if  there  were  many  gods  it 
would  follow  that  the  absolutely  perfect  being  would 
have  an  imperfection,  which  is  absurd.  So  much  con- 
cerning the  unity  of  God. 

Chapter  III. 

Concerning  the  greatness  of  God. 

We  said  above  that  finite  or  im- 
'yTaheiZfinHe,  perfect  being  cannot  be  conceived,  ex- 
tnrea'tiat  Sense  cePt  we  ^rst  nave  some  concept  of  in- 
finite and  perfect  being,  i.  e.,  of  God. 
Therefore  God  alone  can  be  said  to  be  absolutely  in- 
finite, since  He  alone  possesses  an  infinite  perfection. 
He  may  be  called  great,  however,  or  interminable,  so 


144  THE  COGITATA  METAPHYSICA 

far  as  we  think  that  there  is  no  being  able  to  impose 
limitations  upon  Him.  From  which  it  follows  that 
the  infinity  of  God  —  an  inapt  expression  —  is  some- 
thing essentially  positive.  For,  so  far  as  we  conceive 
Him  to  be  infinite,  so  far  we  have  reference  to  His 
essence  or  His  absolute  perfection.  The  greatness  of 
God  is  but  a  relative  term ;  it  is  not  used  when  we 
consider  God  as  an  absolute  or  perfect  being,  but  only 
so  far  as  He  is  considered  as  a  "  first  cause."  Here, 
although  He  may  not  be  perfect  except  in  respect  to 
the  creation  of  the  world,  nevertheless  He  is  to  be 
considered  great.  For  no  being  can  be  conceived, 
and  consequently  there  is  no  being  more  perfect  than 
God  by  which  He  can  be  limited  or  measured.  (Con- 
cerning this  see  Ax.  9,  Pt.  I.). 

There  are  some  authors  who,  when 
What  is  generally     they   speak  of  the  greatness  of  God, 

understood  by  the  . 

greatness  of  God.  seem  to  attribute  quantity  to  Him. 
They  do  this  because  from  this  attri- 
bute they  wish  to  conclude  that  God  is  everywhere 
present.  As  if  they  thought  that,  were  God  not  in 
every  place  He  is  limited.  This  is  even  more  appar- 
ent in  the  reasons  they  adduce  to  show  that  God  is 
infinite  or  great  (for  they  confuse  these  terms).  If 
God,  they  say,  is  actus  puriis,  as  from  necessity  He  is, 
He  is  everywhere  present  and  infinite ;  for  if  He  is 
not  in  every  place  either  He  is  not  able  to  be  wherever 
He  wishes  or  from  necessity  (N.  B.)  He  must  be 
moved.  From  this  it  is  evident  that  they  attribute 
greatness  to  God  under  the  concept  of  quantity.  From 
the  properties  of  extension  they  look  for  their  argu- 
ments for  affirming  the  greatness  of  God,  which  is 
absurd. 


PART  II  145 

If  now  you  ask  us  how  we  prove 

God  is  proven  to  be     ,  ~     .     .  , 

everywhere  that    God    is   everywhere   present,    we 

respond    that    this    has    already    been 

clearly  proven  above,  when  we  showed  that  nothing 

could  exist  even  for  a  single  moment  unless  procreated 

continually  by  the  power  of  God. 

Before  we  can  fully  understand  the 

God's   omnipresence  .  .    ~      - 

cannot  be  omnipresence  ot  God,  we  must  under- 

stand the  nature  of  the  divine  Will. 
For  by  this  all  things  have  been  created,  and  are  con- 
tinually preserved.  Since  this  is  beyond  the  limits  of 
human  knowledge,  it  is  impossible  to  explain  His  om- 
nipresence. 

There    are    some    who    think    that 

God  S      £Y6(lt'Vl&SS 

sometimes  said  to  God's  greatness  is  three-fold,  namely, 

be  threefold.  tt       •  ±.     •        tt*  •        tt- 

He  is  great  in  His  essence,  in  His 
power,  and  in  His  efficacy.  But  this  is  nonsense,  for 
they  distinguish  between  God's  essence  and  His 
power. 

Others  affirm  the  same  thing  more 
Gou\t1£k*  ""'  openly  when  they  say  that  God  is 
essence  fr°m  h%s  everywhere  in  power,  but  not  in  es- 
sence. As  if  God's  power  could  be 
distinguished  from  His  other  attributes  or  from  His 
infinite  essence,  when  it  is  nothing  else  but  this.  For 
if  it  were  anything  but  this  it  would  either  be  some- 
thing created  or  some  accident  of  the  divine  essence, 
without  which  He  could  still  be  conceived.  But  these 
suppositions  are  both  absurd.  If  it  were  something 
created  it  would  need  God's  power  to  be  conserved, 
and  so  a  progression  to  infinity  would  be  given.  But 
if  it  were  some  accident  of  His  being,  God  would  not 
be  a  simple  being,  which  is  contrary  to  what  was 
demonstrated  above. 


146  the  cogitata  metaphysica 

Nor  can  his  Finally,  by  the  greatness  of  His  effi- 

ommpresence.  caCy  tjiey  w's|1  to  understand  some- 
thing beside  the  essence  of  God  by  which  all  things 
are  created  and  conserved.  Which  is  clearly  a  great 
absurdity,  and  one  into  which  they  fall,  because  they 
confuse  the  divine  intellect  and  the  human,  and  com- 
pare God's  power  with  the  power  of  kings. 

Chapter  IV. 

Concerning  God's  Immutability. 

By  the  term  change  we  here  understand  all  that 
variation  which  can  be  given,  the  essence  of  the  object 
remaining  the  same.  In  general,  this  signifies  the 
disintegration  of  the  object,  not  absolutely,  but  at 
least  incipiently;  as  when  we  say  that  turf  is  changed 
into  ashes,  or  that  men  are  changed  into  beasts.  Phi- 
losophers have  been  accustomed  to  use  another  term 
for  signifying  this,  viz.,  transformation.  But  we  are 
here  speaking  of  a  change  which  is  not  a  transforma- 
tion, as  when  we  say  the  rock  has  changed  its  color, 
character,  etc. 

We  must  ask  now  whether  there  is 
TToSfpia^f\°n  Gol  any  changeableness  in  God.  For  con- 
cerning transformation  it  is  not  neces- 
sary to  say  anything  more  than  that  God  exists  neces- 
sarily ;  that  is,  God  cannot  be  limited  in  any  way,  or 
be  transformed  into  another  God.  For  as  soon  as  He 
is  limited  there  must  be  other  gods,  which  proposition 
we  have  shown  to  be  absurd. 
The  causes  of  ^n    order    that    we    may    understand 

change.  more  fully  what  has  just  been  said,  we 

should   remember   that   all   change   arises   from   some 


PART  II  147 

external  cause,  the  subject  being  willing  or  unwilling, 
or  from  some  internal  cause,  viz.,  from  the  choice  of 
the  subject  itself.  For  example,  men  are  black,  or 
they  grow  older  and  stronger,  etc.  In  the  former 
case  the  subject  is  unwilling,  in  the  latter  the  sub- 
ject himself  desires  it.  To  desire  to  walk,  to  show 
oneself  angry,  etc.,  come  from  internal  causes. 

Changes  of  the  former  kind,  name- 

God  is   not   changed  1  ,  111  1 

by  any  other        ly,  those  produced  by   some   external 
ing'  cause,  are  not  found  in  God,  for  He 

alone  is  the  cause  of  all  things,  and  is  not  changed 
by  anything  He  has  made.  Beside,  created  objects 
have  in  themselves  no  power  of  existence,  and  so  much 
less  of  causality  over  other  objects.  And  although  in 
the  Scripture  it  is  said  that  God  is  angry  and  sad  on 
account  of  the  sins  of  men,  the  effect  is  here  taken  for 
the  cause.  In  the  same  way  wre  say  that  the  sun  is 
stronger  and  higher  in  summer  than  in  winter,  al- 
though it  has  not  changed  its  position  or  increased  its 
power.  That  such  things  are  often  taught  in  the  Sa- 
cred Scriptures  is  seen  in  Isaiah  when  he  says,  ch. 
52  \2,  accusing  the  people :  "  Your  iniquities  have 
separated  you  from  your  God." 
Nor  even  by  We  continue,  then,  and  ask  whether 

himself.  there  is  any  self-caused  change  in  God. 

This  also  we  at  once  deny,  for  all  change  that  arises 
from  volition  is  made  in  order  that  the  subject  may 
pass  to  a  better  state,  which  is  impossible  with  a  per- 
fect being.  Such  a  change  only  arises  as  a  means  of 
avoiding  something  unpleasant  or  to  acquire  some 
good  which  is  wanting.  But  neither  of  these  condi- 
tions is  possible  with  God.  Therefore  we  conclude 
that  God  is  immutable.1 

1  Note. —  It    will    be    evident,    also,   that    God   is   immutable, 


148  THE  COGITATA  METAPHYS1CA 

It  will  be  noted  that  I  have  deliberately  omitted 
the  ordinary  forms  of  change,  although  to  some 
degree  we  have  also  considered  them.  For  there  is 
no  need  to  show  the  impossibility  of  change  in  God 
in  respect  to  every  point,  since  we  have  demonstrated 
in  Prop.  1 6,  Part  I.,  that  God  is  incorporeal  and  that 
these  ordinary  forms  of  change  apply  only  to  matter. 

Chapter  V. 

Concerning  the  Simplicity  of  God. 

We  proceed  to  the  simplicity  of 
Thtinction°of  things  God.  In  order  to  correctly  under- 
aJ'rakZT'  stan^  this  attribute  of  God  we  should 
recall  what  Descartes  said  in  the 
"  Prin.  of  Phil.,'*'  Part  L,  Arts.  48  and  49,  viz.,  that  in 
nature  we  know  only  substances  and  their  modes. 
From  this  comes  the  distinction,  Arts.  60,  61,  and  62, 
of  things  as  real  and  modal,  and  rational.  That  is 
called  real  which  distinguishes  two  substances  from 
one  another,  whether  two  different  substances,  or  at- 
tributes of  the  same  substance ;  as  for  example, 
thought  and  extension  or  different  parts  of  matter. 
These  we  know  are  different  because  each  may  be  con- 
ceived apart  from  the  other,  and  consequently  may  so 
exist.  Modal  distinctions  are  of  two  kinds,  namely, 
that  between  a  mode  of  a  substance  and  the  substance 
itself,  and  that  between  two  modes  of  one  substance. 
The  first  we  recognize  because  while  one  mode  may  be 
conceived  without  another,  neither  can  exist  apart  from 
the  substance  whose  modes  they  are ;  the  second  be- 
when  we  have  shown  that  His  volition  and  His  understanding 
are  the  same.     This  might  be  proven  by  other  arguments  also. 


PART  II  149 

cause  while  substance  can  be  conceived  without  its 
modes,  modes  cannot  be  conceived  apart  from  sub- 
stance. Finally,  a  rational  distinction  is  that  arising 
between  substance  and  its  attributes,  as,  for  example, 
when  duration  is  distinguished  from  extension.  We 
recognize  this  distinction  because  substance  cannot*  be 
understood  without  that  attribute. 

From  these  three   forms  of  things 

WHons\CHslbhand     a11   forms   of  combination  arise.     The 
how  many  forms  £rst  form  js  ft&t  made  by  the  combina- 

there  are.  J 

tion  of  two  or  more  substances,  the 
attributes  being  the  same,  as  the  combination  of  bodies, 
or  the  attributes  being  different,  as  in  man.  The  sec- 
ond class  is  made  by  the  union  of  different  modes. 
The  third  is  not  made  in  reality,  but  only  conceived 
as  made  in  order  to  better  understand  objects.  What 
does  not  come  under  the  first  two  of  these  heads  is  not 
composite,  but  simple  in  its  nature. 

From  this  it  may  be  shown  that  God 
GoposlStc  lut  Znpie.  is    n°t    composite,    but    simple    being. 

For  it  is  a  self-evident  fact  that  the 
component  parts  of  a  composite  object  are  prior  in  na- 
ture to  the  object  itself.  Then  those  substances  from 
which  God  is  composed  are  necessarily  prior  in  their 
nature  to  God  Himself.  Each  could  then  be  con- 
ceived in  itself  apart  from  the  concept  of  God.  Each 
part,  therefore,  could  exist  per  se  and  we  would  have 
as  many  gods  as  there  are  substances  from  which  God 
is  supposed  to  be  composed.  For  when  each  part  can 
exist  per  se  it  must  exist  by  its  own  power.  Under 
these  conditions  (as  we  have  shown  in  Prop.  7,  Pt. 
I.,  where  we  demonstrated  the  existence  of  God)  it 
will  have  the  power  of  giving  to  itself  all  the  perfec- 
tion of  God.     As  nothing  could  be  more  absurd  than 


ico  THE  COGITATA  METAPHYSICA 

this,  we  conclude  that  God  is  not  composite,  that  is, 
made  by  the  coalition  and  union  of  substances.  The 
same  conclusion  is  also  evident  from  the  fact  that 
there  are  no  modes  in  God's  being;  for  modes  arise 
from  the  change  of  substances  (vid.  Principles,  Pt.  I., 
Arf.  56).  Finally,  if  any  one  wishes  to  conceive  of 
some  other  combination  of  the  essence  and  of  the  ex- 
istence of  things,  we  will  not  say  him  nay.  Only  he 
should  remember  that  there  are  not  two  separate 
things  in  God. 

We  may  conclude,  therefore,  that  all 

The    attributes    of       ,1  «•    ,•       ,•  ...  1 

God  are  only  dis-  the  distinctions  we  make  in  regard  to 

tingjdshed    by  tfl      attributes   of   God   are  not   real  but 

1  eason. 

rational  distinctions.  Let  it  be  under- 
stood that  such  distinctions  as  I  have  just  made  are 
distinctions  of  reason,  which  may  be  known  from  the 
fact  that  such  a  substance  could  not  exist  without*  this 
attribute.  Therefore,  we  conclude  that  God  is  sim- 
ple being.  We  do  not  care  for  the  other  minor  dis- 
tinctions of  the  Peripatetics,  and  proceed,  therefore, 
to  the  life  of  God. 


Chapter  VI. 
Concerning  the  Life  of  God. 

In  order  that  we  may  rightly  under- 

What    Philosophers  1     1  •  -i  r     1        it         r   /-      1 

in  general  under-  stand  this  attribute  of  the  life  of  God, 

stand  by   life.  •,  ,,  ... 

it  is  necessary  that  we  explain  in  gen- 
eral what  is  meant  by  this  term.  Here  we  may  ex- 
amine first  the  opinion  of  the  Peripatetics.  They  un- 
derstood by  life  the  continuance  of  support  to  the  soul 
by  means  of  heat  (Vid.  Aristotle,  Bk.  L,  de  Respirat. 
8).     And,  because  they  had   three  classes  of  minds, 


PART  II  151 

viz.,  vegetative,  sensative  and  intellectual,  which  they 
attribute  to  plants,  animals  and  men  respectively,  it 
follows  that  they  assume  that  other  objects  do  not 
have  life.  But  they  did  not  dare  to  say  that  minds 
and  God  do  not  possess  life.  They  feared  perhaps 
lest  if  they  denied  life  to  them  they  must  also  deny 
death  as  well.  Therefore,  Aristotle,  Metaphysics,  Bk. 
II.,  chap.  7,  gives  another  definition  of  life  peculiar 
to  minds,  namely :  "  Life  is  the  operation  of  the  in- 
tellect." In  this  sense  he  attributes  life  to  God  who 
is  a  cognitive  being  and  is  pure  activity.  We  will  not 
be  delayed  long  to  refute  these  conceptions,  for  what 
pertains  to  these  three  kinds  of  life  which  they  attrib- 
ute to  plants  and  animals  and  men,  we  have  already 
shown  to  be  mere  fiction.  For  we  showed  that  there 
is  nothing  in  matter  except  mechanical  form  and  ac- 
tion. Moreover,  what  pertains  to  the  life  of  God  re- 
lates no  more  to  an  act  of  the  understanding  than  to 
an  act  of  will  or  any  other  faculty.  But  since  I  ex- 
pect no  response  to  what  I  have  said,  I  pass  on  and 
endeavor  to  explain  what  life  really  is. 

Although  this  term  life,  by  a  trans- 
Tom7yt ^MJtll  f erence  of  meaning,  is  often  taken  to 
signify  the  customs  of  a  people  or  of 
an  individual,  we  shall  briefly  explain  its  correct  phi- 
losophical use.  It  should  be  noted  that  if  life  is  at- 
tributed to  corporeal  things,  then  nothing  is  void  of 
life;  but  if  only  to  those  objects  where  spirit  is  united 
to  body,  then  only  to  men  or  perhaps  also  to  the  lower 
animals,  but  not  to  minds  or  to  God.  In  truth,  since 
the  term  is  a  broad  one,  it  should  doubtlessly  be  at- 
tributed to  corporeal  objects,  to  minds  united  to,  and 
to  minds  separated  from  corporeal  body. 


152  THE  COGITATA  METAPHYSICA 

Therefore    we    will    understand    by 

general,  and  what  this    term    life,     the    'power    through 

it  'is   in   God.  i  •    i  r.  •       .  -±  l 

which  an  object  preserves  its  own  be- 
ing. And  although  that  power  in  different  objects  is 
very  different,  we  still  very  properly  say  that  those  ob- 
jects have  life.  Moreover,  the  power  by  which  God 
preserves  His  being  is  nothing  else  than  His  essence. 
Therefore  they  speak  most  truly,  who  say  that  God 
is  Life.  Nor  are  there  wanting  theologians  who  be- 
lieve that  it  was  for  this  very  reason  that  the  Jews 
when  they  made  a  vow  swore  by  living  Jehovah,  not 
by  the  life  of  Jehovah,  as  did  Joseph  when  he  swore  by 
the  life  of  Pharaoh  and  said  the  "  life  of  Pharaoh." 

Chapter  VII. 
Concerning  the   Understanding  of  God. 

Among   the    attributes   of   God    we 

God  is  omniscient.       ,  , 

nave  enumerated  omniscience  as  neces- 
sary to  His  being.  For  knowledge  is  an  element  of 
perfection,  and  God,  who  is  in  every  way  perfect,  must 
possess  this  attribute.  Therefore  knowledge  to  the 
highest  degree  must  be  attributed  to  God,  a  knowledge 
so  complete  that  it  allows  no  ignorance  or  defect  of 
intelligence.  Were  it  not  so  we  would  have  an  im- 
perfection in  the  attributes  of  God  and  so  in  God 
Himself.  From  this  it  follows  that  God's  knowledge 
is  immediate,  and  that  He  does  not  reason  by  logical 
processes. 

And  further,  from  God's  perfection, 

The  objects  of  f  „,      ,, 

God's  knowledge    it  follows  that  His  ideas  are  not  lim- 

are    not    objects        .,     .    ...  .   .  e 

apart  from  His      itcci    like   ours    to   objects    apart    from 
Himself.     On    the    contrary,    God    bv 


PART  II  153 

His  own  power  has  created  objects  existing  apart  from 
Himself,  but  they  were  determined  by  His  under- 
standing.1 Otherwise  they  would  have  their  nature 
and  essence  in  themselves  and  would  be  by  nature 
prior  to  God,  which  is  absurd.  Certain  ones,  because 
they  have  not  remembered  this,  have  fallen  into  egreg- 
ious blunders.  There  are  some  who  think  that  matter 
exists  in  its  own  power  apart  from  God,  and  yet  co- 
eternal  with  Him,  and  that  God,  knowing  this,  has 
merely  set  it  in  a  reproducing  order  and  impressed 
other  forms  on  it  from  without.  Then  others  believe 
that  things  are  by  nature  necessary,  or  impossible,  or 
contingent,  and  so  far  as  God  knows  them  as  con- 
tingent is  ignorant  whether  they  exist  or  not.  Finally, 
others  say  that  God  recognizes  contingent  being  from 
its  environment  because,  perchance,  He  has  had  a  long 
experience.  Beside  these,  there  are  other  errors  of 
like  nature,  to  which  I  might  refer  were  it  not  useless 
to  so  do.  For  from  what  has  been  said,  the  falsity  of 
these  is  evident. 

We  revert  now  to  our  proposition, 

But    God    himself.  .  , 

namely,  that  independent  of  God  there 
are  no  objects  of  His  knowledge,  but  that  He  Himself 
is  the  object  of  His  Knowledge,  indeed  He  is  that 
knowledge.  Those  who  think  that  the  world  is  the 
object  of  God's  knowledge  are  far  less  wise  than  those 
who  wish  some  building  planned  by  a  great  architect 
to  be  considered  the  object  of  their  knowledge.  For 
the  artificer  is  compelled  to  seek  for  suitable  material 
outside  of  himself;  but  God  sought  no  material  out- 


*It  clearly  follows,  therefore,  that  the  understanding  of 
God  by  which  he  knows  all  created  objects,  and  His  will  and 
power  which  determined  them  are  one  and  the  same  thing. 


i54  TUE  COG  IT  AT  A  METAPHYSICA 

side  of  Himself,  but  things,  in  essence  and  in  exist- 
ence, were  made  by  His  understanding  or  will. 
in  what  way  God         It  may  be  asked,  then,  whether  God 
tinrtfon^of'  J"     knows  evil  and  sin,  and  distinction  of 
reason,  etc.  reason,  etc.     We  reply  that  God  nec- 

essarily must  know  those  things  of  which  He  is  the 
cause.  Especially  since  nothing  can  exist  for  a  single 
moment  except  by  the  concurrence  of  the  divine  will. 
Therefore,  since  evil  and  sin  are  nothing  in  things, 
but  only  in  the  human  mind  as  it  compares  things 
with  one  another,  it  follows  that  God  does  not  know 
these  independent  of  the  human  mind.  Distinctions 
of  reason  we  have  said  are  only  modes  of  thought, 
hence  they,  too,  should  be  known  so  far  as  He  con- 
serves the  human  mind.  Not,  however,  that  God  has 
such  modes  of  thought  in  order  that  He  may  the  more 
easily  retain  what  He  knows.  Provided  one  carefully 
attends  to  these  few  remarks,  there  is  no  question 
that  can  be  asked  about  God's  understanding  which 
cannot  easily  be  answered. 

But  meanwhile,  we  must  not  over- 
God's  knowledge  of  look  the  error  of  those  who  think  that 

universal  s,   and  of    ^*      1      1  , 1   •  ±  1 

particular  truths.  God  knows  nothing  except  eternal 
truth,  e.  g.,  angels  and  the  heavens 
which  they  think  are  by  nature  without  beginning  and 
without  end.  Beside,  in  this  world  nothing  but  ideas 
are  without  a  beginning  and  unchanging.  They  seem 
to  err  from  choice  and  to  wish  to  keep  up  some  ob- 
scurity. What,  indeed,  is  more  absurd  than  to  deny 
God's  knowledge  of  individual  things,  which  cannot 
exist  for  a  single  moment  without  His  sustaining 
power !  Then  they  maintain  that  God  is  ignorant  of 
things  which  actually  exist,  but  knows  universal? 
which   do  not  exist  or  have  any   essence  apart   from 


PART  II  155 

these  individual  objects.  On  the  contrary,  we  would 
attribute  to  God  a  complete  cognition  of  individual 
things,  but  deny  the  knowledge  of  universals  except 
so  far  as  He  understands  the  human  mind. 

Finally,   before  ending  this   discus- 

There   is   but   one 

simple  idea  in  sion,  it  seems  necessary  to  give  some 
answer  to  those  who  inquire  whether 
God  has  many  ideas  or  only  one  simple  idea.  To  this 
I  respond  that  the  idea  of  God  because  of  which  He 
is  called  omniscient  is  one  and  simple.  For  God  is 
called  omniscient  only  because  He  has  an  idea  of  Him- 
self. This  idea,  or  knowledge,  since  it  exists  with 
God,  is  nothing  else  than  His  essence,  nor,  indeed, 
could  it  possibly  be  anything  but  this. 

God's   cognition   of  created   objects 

What  God's  knowl-  ,       ,  .  ,  1        ,  - 

edge  of  created     cannot  properly  be  said  to  be  knowl- 
°  Je(  edge.     For  if  God  so  chose,  these  ob- 

jects might  have  some  other  essence  which  has  no 
place  in  His  cognition  of  them.  Nevertheless,  it  is 
often  asked  whether  His  cognition  of  objects  is  mani- 
fold or  simple.  To  .this  we  would  reply,  that  this 
question  is  like  those  which  inquire  whether  God's 
decrees  and  acts  of  will  are  one  or  many ;  and  whether 
God  is  omnipresent,  or  whether  His  concurrence,  by 
which  separate  objects  are  preserved,  is  the  same  for 
all  things.  Concerning  such  questions,  as  I  have  al- 
ready said,  we  have  no  certain  knowledge.  Yet,  in 
the  same  way,  we  very  certainly  know  that  this  con- 
currence of  God,  if  it  is  correlated  with  his  omnipo- 
tence, must  be  unitary,  although  its  effect  is  manifested 
in  various  ways.  So  also  the  voluntary  acts  and  de- 
crees of  God  (for  we  may  so  call  His  cognition  of  the 
world),  considered  as  in  God,  are  not  many  although 
through  created  objects  (or  better  in  created  objects), 


156  THE  COGITATA  METAPHYSICA 

they  are  variously  expressed.  Finally,  if  we  consider 
the  analogy  of  nature  as  a  whole,  we  are  able  to  con- 
sider it  as  one  being,  and  consequently  the  idea  or 
decree  of  Natura  naturata  will  be  but  one. 

Chapter  VIII. 
Concerning  God's  Will. 

We  cannot  distin-  Jfe     w{\\     0f     Q0CJ       j^y     wnich      He 

gmsh    between  J 

God's  essence,       chooses  to  love  Himself,  follows  nec- 

His   understand- 
ing by  which  He  essarily    from   His   understanding,   bv 

knows    Himself,  , 

and  His  will  by    which    He    knows    Himself.     But    we 

which  He  'loves         «  .  n  TT.  ,   TT. 

Himself.  do  not  know  now  His  essence  and  His 

understanding,  by  which  he  knows  Himself,  differ 
from  His  will,  by  which  he  chooses  to  love  Himself. 
Nor  does  the  term  personality,  which  theologians  use 
to  explain  this,  escape  our  notice.  Although  we  are 
not  ignorant  of  the  term,  we  are  ignorant  of  its  sig- 
nificance, and  unable  to  form  any  clear  and  distinct 
concept  of  its  content.  Nevertheless,  we  consistently 
believe  in  the  beatific  vision  of  God,  which  is  promised 
to  faithful  ones  that  this  would  be  revealed  to  them. 
God's  will  and  As    is    sufficiently    clear    from    the 

a7objecZld7aen-  preceding,  God's  will  and  power  con- 
not  be  distin-        siciered   objectivelv   cannot   be   distin- 

guished   from   His  J 

understanding.  guished  from  His  understanding. 
For  we  have  made  it  clear  that  God  has  not  only 
decreed  that  things  should  exist,  but  also  what  char- 
acter they  should  have,  i.  e.,  their  essence  and  existence 
depend  upon  the  will  and  power  of  God.  From  this 
we  see  that  God's  understanding  and  power,  and  will, 
by  which  He  created  and  understands,  and  conserves 


PART  II  157 

or  loves  the  world,  cannot  be  distinguished  from  one 

another  except  in  respect  to  our  understanding. 

it  is  improperly  Moreover,   when   we   say   that   God 

said   that    God  111  •        ,  1  •  •         1  •    r  1 

hates  certain         holds  certain  things  in  disfavor,  and 

things  and  loves       ■,  .-,  .-,  •  i  r 

others.  loves    others,    this    is    spoken    figura- 

tively, as  when  the  Scriptures  say  that  the  earth  shall 
bring  forth  men.  That  God  is  not  angry  with  any 
one,  nor  loves  any  one  in  the  sense  that  people 
ordinarily  believe,  is  evident  from  the  Scriptures 
themselves.  So  Isaiah  says,  and  more  clearly  the 
Apostle  to  the  Romans,  chapter  9 :  "For  the  children 
being  not  yet  born,  neither  having  done  any  good  or 
evil,  that  the  purposes  of  God  according  to  election 
might  stand,  not  of  works,  but  of  him  that  calleth, 
that  the  older  shall  serve  the  younger,  etc."  And  a 
little  below :  "  Therefore,  hath  he  mercy  on  whom  he 
will  have  mercy,  and  whom  he  will  he  hardeneth. 
Thou  wilt  say  then  unto  me :  Why  doth  he  yet  find 
fault?  For  who  hath  resisted  his  will?  Nay,  but, 
O  man,  who  art  thou  that  repliest  against  God? 
Shall  the  thing  formed  say  to  him  that  formed  it, 
Why  hast  thou  made  me  thus?  Hath  not  the  potter 
power  over  the  clay,  of  the  same  lump  to  make  one 
vessel  to  ho'nor,  and  another  to  dishonor  ?  "  etc. 
„.y     _  ,     ,  If  then,  you  ask :  Why,  then,  does 

Why   God  admon-  '    J  J  ' 

ishes  men;  why     God  admonish  men?     To  this  it  may 

He   does   not  save 

them  without  ad-  be   responded,   that   God   has   decreed 

monishment ;    and     .  .  .   ,        , 

why  the  wicked      from  eternity  to  admonish  them  at  a 

are  punished.  .  .  .  ,         . ,      .     . ,  , 

given  time  in  order  that  those  whom 
He  wished  to  save  might  be  converted. 

If  you  inquire  further :  Whether  God  was  not  able 
to  save  them  without  this  admonishment,  we  respond 
that  He  was.  Why,  then,  does  He  not  thus  save  them, 
you  might   inquire.     To  this   I   will   reply  after   you 


158  THE  COGITATA  METAPHYSICA 

have  told  me  why  He  did  not  make  the  Red  Sea  pass- 
able without  a  strong  east  wind,  and  why  He  does  not 
make  things  to  move  without  the  agency  of  other 
things,  and  an  infinite  number  of  other  things  which 
He  does  by  means  of  mediating  causes.  Then  you 
will  ask :  Why  are  the  wicked  punished,  since,  because 
of  their  nature,  they  clearly  fulfill  the  divine  decree? 
I  respond  that  it  is  also  according  to  the  divine  decree 
that  they  should  be  punished.  And  if  only  those 
whom  we  believe  to  sin  from  choice  should  be  pun- 
ished, why  do  men  attempt  to  exterminate  venomous 
serpents?  for  they  only  act  according  to  their  nature, 
nor  are  they  able  to  do  otherwise. 

Finally,    if   there    are   other   things 

The  Scriptures  t  .    .  .        ^  ,     <-, 

teach  nothing       which  occur  in  the  sacred  Scriptures 

which   is   contrary        i  •    i  i  »•  j 

to  the  Laws  of     which    may    be    mentioned    as    points 
Nature.  worthy  of  examination  this  is  not  the 

place  to  explain  them.  Here  we  would  merely  inquire 
into  those  things  which  we  are  able  to  deduce  with 
certainty  from  Natural  Reason,  and  it  is  sufficient  if 
we  make  it  evident  that  the  Sacred  Pages  ought  to 
teach  the  same  things.  For  truth  is  not  at  variance 
with  truth,  nor  do  the  Scriptures  teach  the  nonsense 
that  the  multitude  believe.  For  if  we  find  anything 
in  them  contrary  to  the  laws  of  Reason  we  should 
refute  that  with  the  same  freedom  that  we  refute  such 
statements  in  the  Koran  or  the  Talmud.  However, 
there  is  no  reason  to  think  that  the  Sacred  Writings 
contain  anything  opposed  to  the  Natural  Reason. 


PART  11  159 

Chapter  IX. 
Concerning  the  Power  of  God. 

We   have   demonstrated   above   that 

How   we    should  ^      .  .  TT  M1 

understand  God's    God    is    omnipotent.     Here    we    Will 

omnipotence.  *      -i     •    n  i     •  i  ,  ,1   • 

only  briefly  explain  in  what  terms  this 
attribute  shall  be  understood.  There  are  many  who 
discuss  this  that  do  not  speak  with  sufficient  fullness. 
They  say  certain  things  are  possible  from  God's 
nature  not  from  His  decrees,  and  that  some  things  are 
impossible,  others  necessary.  God's  omnipotence  has 
a  place  only  in  regard  to  possible  things.  But  we, 
since  we  have  already  shown  that  all  things  depend 
absolutely  upon  the  decrees  of  God,  say  that  He  is 
really  omnipotent.  And,  since  we  know  that  He  has 
decreed  certain  things  from  His  freedom  of  will  and  is 
immutable,  we  conclude  that  nothing  can  happen  con- 
trary to  His  decrees,  and  that  nothing  is  impossible 
except  that  which  is  opposed  to  the  perfection  of 
God. 

Ail  things  are  neces-  But  perhaps  some  one  will  argue 
Sth7  deer/es^of  %°  ^at  we  ^n<^  some  things  necessary 
God;  not  some       from  the   decrees  of   God  and  others 

in    themselves, 

and  others  in       for  some  other  reason.     For  example, 

respect  to   these 

decrees.  that  Josiah  should  burn  incense  upon 

the  altars  of  the  idols  of  Jeroboam.  For  if  we  con- 
sider merely  the  will  of  Josiah,  we  will  adjudge  the 
thing  to  be  merely  possible ;  nor  can  it  be  said  to  have 
been  necessary  in  any  other  sense  than  that  the 
Prophet  had  commanded  it  as  being  the  decree  of  God. 
But  that  the  three  angles  of  a  triangle  are  equal  10 
two  right  angles  is  self-evident.     It  is  only  on  account 


160  THE  COGITATA  METAPHYSICA 

of  man's  ignorance  that  these  distinctions  are  made. 
For  if  men  clearly  understood  the  whole  order  of 
Nature  they  would  find  all  things  as  determined  and 
as  necessary  as  Mathematics.  But  as  this  is  beyond 
human  power  we  conceive  some  things  to  be  merely 
possible,  others  necessary.  Therefore,  we  must  either 
say  that  God  is  powerless,  since  all  things  are  deter- 
mined, or  that  He  is  all  powerful,  and  that  all  neces- 
sity rests  upon  the  decrees  of  God. 
if  God  had  made  If  now,  it  is  asked  if  God  had 
NHeUwoJfhaeve'  created  the  world  different  from  its 
given  us  other       present  order,  and  what  is  now  truth 

powers    of    under-  r 

standing.  were  error,  would  we  still  believe  the 

same  things  to  be  true?     We  would  if  God  left  our 

nature  as  it  is.     But  it  would  also  be  possible,  if  He 

wished  to  give  us  such  a  nature,  as  He  has  indeed 

done,   for  us  to  understand  the  nature  and   laws   of 

things  just  as  they  are  planned  by  God.     Indeed,  if 

we  consider  God's  veracity  He  ought  so  to  create  us. 

This  is  also  evident  from  what  we  have  said  above, 

namely,  that  Natura  naturata  must  be  considered  as 

unitary.     Whence   it    follows   that   man   is   a   part   of 

Nature,   and   ought  to  be  in   accord   with   the  world 

about  him.     Therefore,  from  this  simplicity  of  God's 

decrees  it  follows  that  if  God  had  created  things  in 

some  other  way  He  would  have  so  made  us  that  we 

would   understand    them -  as    they    were    created.     So 

while    we    desire    to    retain    this    distinction    which 

philosophers  in  general  lay  down,  viz.,  the  power  of 

God,  we  are  compelled  to  explain  it  differently. 

How  many  kinds  of      We>  therefore,   divide  God's  power 
power  in  God.       into      two      classes.     His      regulative 

power,  and  His  absolute  power. 


PART  II  161 

God's  power  is  called  absolute  when 

What    absolute,  •  1  tt-  •  •  1 

what     regulative,  we  consider  His  omnipotence  without 

what    ordinary  .  TT.  ,  ,  ,  r  1 1      • , 

end  wto  regard    to    His    decrees.     We    call    it 

ex  raor  mary.        regulative   when   we   have    regard    to 
His  decrees. 

We  also  say  God's  power  is  natural  or  supernatural. 
That  is  natural  by  which  the  world  is  preserved  in  its 
fixed  order.  That  is  called  supernatural  which  causes 
something  outside  of  the  order  of  Nature,  as  for  ex- 
ample, all  miracles,  such  as  various  appearance  of 
angels,  etc.  Concerning  the  latter  point  there  is 
evidently  some  room  for  doubt.  Still  it  would  seem 
to  be  a  greater  miracle  if  God  should  always  govern 
the  world  by  the  same  fixed  and  unchanging  laws, 
than  if  at  times,  on  account  of  the  foolishness  of  men, 
He  should  interrupt  the  laws  and  order  of  Nature 
which  He  from  free  choice  has  ordained.  (This  no 
one,  except  he  be  mentally  blind,  can  deny.)  But  we 
leave  this  for  theologians  to  discuss. 

Finally,  there  are  some  other  questions  often  asked 
concerning  the  power  of  God :  For  example,  whether 
God's  power  extends  to  events  already  past ;  or 
whether  He  might  not  have  created  more  objects  than 
he  did?  We  do  not  answer  these,  however,  for  their 
answer  is  easily  seen  from  what  has  been  said. 

Chapter  X. 

Concerning  Creation. 

It  has  already  been  said  that  God  has  created  the 
world.  We  shall  only  attempt  here,  therefore,  to  ex- 
plain what  is  meant  by  the  term  creation,  after  which 
some  opinions  on  the  subject  will  be  carefully  ex- 
amined.    We  will  begin  at  the  beginning. 


162  THE  COGITATA  METAPHYSICA 

We  say,  therefore,  that  creation  is 

What    creation    is.  .  , .  .  ,  .    , 

an  operation  in  which  no  causes  ex- 
cept an  efficient  one  concur.  Or,  a  created  object  is 
one  which  presupposes  for  its  existence  nothing 
except  God. 

It  should  be  noted  ( I )  that  we  have 
The  ordinary  defini-  here     omitted     those     words     which 

tion  is  rejected. 

philosophers  insert  in  their  definition, 
viz.,  ex  nihilo,  as  if  nothing  were  some  matter  from 
which  things  are  produced.  Because  they  are  accus- 
tomed to  speak  in  this  way,  and  to  think  always  of 
something  preceding  the  given  objects,  they  are  not 
able,  in  speaking  of  creation,  to  omit  this  particle  ex. 
The  same  thing  is  true  concerning  matter.  Because 
all  bodies  are  seen  in  some  position,  and  surrounded 
by  other  objects,  when  they  are  asked  where  matter 
is,  they  reply,  that  it  is  in  some  imaginary  space. 
Therefore,  it  is  clear  that  they  do  not  consider  nothing 
as  a  mere  negation  of  all  reality,  but  believe  or  im- 
agine it  to  be  a  something  real. 

2.  It  should  be  noted  also,  that  I 
T1e%efained°Perh  said  in  creation  no  causes  concur  ex- 
cept one  efficient  one.  I  might  have 
said  that  creation  negates  or  excludes  all  causes  except 
this  one.  I  did  not  choose  to  do  this,  however,  lest  I 
should  be  compelled  to  respond  to  those  who  ask 
whether  God  had  no  predetermined  end  in  Himself 
for  the  sake  of  which  He  created  the  world.  To  make 
the  definition  clearer  I  added  that  the  created  object 
presupposes  nothing  except  God.  For,  if  God  had 
predetermined  some  end  it  evidently  was  not  inde- 
pendent of  Him,  for  there  is  nothing  apart  from  God 
by  which  His  decrees  are  influenced  or  changed. 


PART  II  163 

3.  It    follows    from   this    definition 

Accidents   and  ,  .  ,  ,  . 

modes  were  not     that    accidents    and    modes    were    not 

created.  ,      •,         <■  .■> 

created,  for  they  presuppose  some 
created  substance  beside  God. 

4.  Finally,  it  should  be  noted  that 

Time   or   duration  .  . 

did  not  exist        before  creation  time  or   duration   did 

before  creation.  •    .  . ,  , 

not  exist,  nor  can  they  even  be  im- 
agined. For  time  is  a  measure  of  duration,  or  rather 
it  is  only  a  form  of  thought.  Therefore,  it  not  only 
presupposes  the  created  world,  but  it  depends  espe- 
cially upon  human  thought.  Moreover,  duration  is 
limited  by  the  existence  of  created  objects,  and  hence 
began  when  the  world  began.  I  say  limited  by  the 
existence  of  created  objects  for  eternity  alone  relates 
to  God  as  we  have  shown  sufficiently  above.  Hence, 
duration  presupposes  that  the  world  has  been  created 
or  at  least  that  it  exists. 

It  is  evident  that  they  who  think  duration  and  time 
existed  before  the  world  was  created,  are  laboring  un- 
der the  same  prejudice  as  they  who  conceive  of  space 
apart  from  matter.  So  much  for  the  definition  of 
creation. 
_,         .     ,        ,       There  is  no  need  to  repeat  what  is 

The   work    of   creat-  r 

ing    and    preserv-   g[yen    [n    Axiom    IO,    Part    I.    viz.,    that 

tug   the  world  ° 

are  the  same.  no  more  power  is  needed  to  create 
than  to  preserve  the  world.  God's  work  in  creating 
and  preserving  the  world  is  the  same. 

Having  recalled  this  point,  we  proceed  to  inquire 
first,  what  is  created  and  what  uncreated,  and  second, 
whether   what   is   created   has   existed   from   eternity. 

To    the    first    inquiry    we    respond 

whCrlatftgS  °re     briefly,  that  everything  has  been  created 

whose    essence    is    clearly    conceived 

even  without  existence,  and  yet  is  conceived  per  se ; 


164  THE  COGITATA  METAPHYS1CA 

as  e.  g.,  matter  of  which  we  have  a  clear  and  a  distinct 
concept  when  we  conceive  it  under  the  attribute  exten- 
sion, whether  we  think  that  it  exists  or  not. 

But  perhaps  some  one  may  say  that 

How  God's  knowl-  .  ,  .     ..  ,  ,     , 

edge  differs  from  we  nave  clear  and  distinct  knowledge 
even  when  the  object  does  not  exist, 
and  yet  attribute  this  knowledge  to  God.  To  this  we 
reply  that  we  do  not  say  that  God's  knowledge  is  like 
ours,  limited  by  nature,  but  is  pure  activity  involving 
existence,  as  we  have  shown  over  and  over.  For  we 
have  shown  that  God's  understanding  and  will  cannot 
be  distinguished  from  His  power  or  from  His  essence 
which  involves  existence. 

Nothing  independ-  Since  everything,  the  essence  of 
™-eternai°with  which  does  not  involve  existence,  has 
Hvn-  been  created  in  its  existing  form  and 

continually  conserved  by  the  power  of  God,  we  will  not 
pause  to  refute  the  opinion  of  those  who  think  that  the 
world  as  chaos,  or  as  matter  devoid  of  form,  is  co-eter- 
nal with  God,  and  so  far  independent  of  Him.  There- 
fore we  pass  on  to  the  second  point,  and  ask  whether 
what  has  been  created  could  have  existed  from  eternity. 
What  is  meant  by       In  order  to  understand  the  point  just 

the    expression  .        «  .  .  . 

from  eternity.  raised  we  must  consider  the  expression 
from  eternity.  For  we  wish  to  signify  by  these  words 
something  different  from  the  eternity  of  God.  By  this 
expression  we  now  mean  duration  from  the  beginning 
of  duration,  or  such  a  duration  that  although  numbers 
were  multiplied  through  thousands  of  years,  and  this 
product  again  by  millions  of  millions,  we  would  still 
be  unable  to  express  its  magnitude. 

Tt   is   evident   that  such   duration   is 

The   world  cannot        .  „  ,  .        .  . 

hare  existed   front    impossible  ;   TOT  11   tllC  World  COUld   liaVC 

begun  at  any  fixed  time  then  its  dura- 


PART  II  165 

tion  were  too  short  to  satisfy  these  conditions. 
Therefore,  the  world  cannot  have  endured  from  such  a 
beginning  to  the  present.  But  perhaps  you  say  since 
God  is  omnipotent  nothing  is  impossible,  and  He  could 
have  given  to  the  world  a  duration  than  which  no  longer 
can  be  conceived.  We  reply  that  God,  because  He  is 
omnipotent,  would  never  have  given  such  a  duration 
to  the  world.  For  the  very  character  of  duration  is 
that  it  can  always  be  conceived  as  greater  or  less,  as  in 
the  case  of  number.  You  may  insist,  however,  that 
God  has  existed  from  eternity,  and  since  He  has  per- 
dured  all  this  time  there  is  a  duration  given,  so  great 
that  no  greater  is  conceivable.  But  in  this  way  a  dura- 
tion composed  of  parts  is  attributed  to  God,  which  idea 
has  been  refuted  sufficiently  when  we  demonstrated 
that  eternity,  not  duration,  belongs  to  God.  Would 
that  men  might  remember  this !  For  then  they  could 
easily  extricate  themselves  from  many  arguments  and 
absurdities,  and  would  turn  with  the  greatest  delight 
to  the  blessed  contemplation  of  God.  Nevertheless  we 
proceed  to  respond  to  the  arguments  of  those  who 
attempt  to  show  the  possibility  of  such  an  infinite 
duration  from  some  fixed  time  in  the  past. 

_  .  .  In  the  first  place  it  is  said  that  the 

Because    God    ts 

eternal,  it  does     thing    produced    must    be    co-existent 

not    follow   that  ,  . 

the  things  he  has  with   its   cause.     And   since   God   has 

created    have   ex-  .  «    r  ■■  •,       ,1  re  r  tt- 

isted  from  existed  from  eternity  the  effects  of  His 

etermty.  being  ought  to  be  eternal.     This  argu- 

ment is  supported  by  reference  to  the  Son  of  God,  who 
has  existed  with  the  Father  from  eternity.  It  is 
evident  that  they  confuse  eternity  with  duration,  and 
only  attribute  to  God  a  duration  from  eternity.  This 
is  shown,  too,  in  the  example  cited.  The  same  eter- 
nity which  they  attribute  to  the  Son  of  God  they  think 


1 66  THE  C0G1TATA  METAPHYSICA 

can  be  attributed  to  created  objects.  They  imagine 
time  and  duration  to  have  been  instituted  before  the 
world  began,  and  think  of  duration  apart  from  created 
objects  as  some  think  of  eternity  as  independent  of 
God.  That  both  opinions  are  wrong  is  now  evident. 
So  we  respond  that  it  is  not  true  that  God  was  able  to 
communicate  His  eternity  to  the  world.  Neither  was 
the  Son  of  God  created,  but  was  eternal  like  the  Father. 
When  we  say  that  the  Father  had  begotten  the  Son 
from  eternity  we  only  mean  that  the  Father  has  always 
shared  His  eternity  with  the  Son.  . 

In  the  second  place  it  is  argued  that 
if  God  acts  from     when  God  acts  from  choice,  He  is  not 

116 CCS Si t'V    iXS    IS    11  Ot 

infinite  in  virtue,  less  powerful  than  when  He  acts  from 
necessity.  But  if  God  acts  from  neces- 
sity, since  He  is  infinite  in  virtue,  He  must  have  created 
the  world  from  eternity.  It  is  easy  to  reply  to  this 
argument  if  we  consider  its  basis.  For  these  same 
good  men  presume  that  they  may  hold  conflicting  ideas 
concerning  a  being  of  infinite  virtue.  They  conceive 
of  God,  a  being  of  infinite  virtue,  as  acting  both  from 
necessity  and  from  choice.  But  we  deny  that  God,  if 
He  acts  from  necessity,  is  a  being  of  infinite  virtue. 
Which  action  is  justified,  indeed,  and  must  of  necessity 
be  conceded  even  by  those  same  men  when  we  have 
shown  that  a  perfect  being  must  be  free,  and  can  only 
be  conceived  as  unitary.  Should  they  reply  that  it  is 
possible  to  suppose  that  God  acting  from  necessity  is 
still  infinite  in  His  virtue,  we  would  reply  that  we  are 
not  at  liberty  to  suppose  this,  any  more  than  we  are  at 
liberty  to  suppose  a  square  circle  in  order  to  conclude 
that  all  lines  drawn  from  the  center  to  the  circumfer- 
ence are  not  equal.  And  this,  we  repeat,  is  sufficiently 
proven    from    what    has   been    said    above.     We   have 


PART  II  167 

proven  that  there  is  no  duration  that  may  not  be  con- 
ceived as  greater  or  less  or  even  double  as  great.  If 
God  acts  from  free  choice  it  may  be  created  as  greater 
or  less.  But  if  God  acts  from  necessity  this  by  no 
means  follows.  Under  the  latter  supposition  only  those 
things  which  follow  from  His  nature  can  be  realized, 
not  an  infinite  number  of  hypothetical  results.  There- 
fore, it  may  be  argued  in  a  few  words :  If  God  should 
create  a  duration  so  great  that  no  greater  could  be 
given  He  necessarily  diminishes  His  own  power.  And 
this  is  impossible  for  His  essence  and  His  power  are 
one  and  the  same  thing.  Therefore,  etc.,  and  further, 
if  God  acts  from  necessity,  He  must  have  created  a 
duration,  than  which  no  greater  can  be  conceived. 
But  had  God  created  such  a  duration  He  would  not 
have  been  of  infinite  virtue.  For  we  are  always  able 
to  conceive  of  a  duration  greater  than  the  one  given. 
Therefore,  if  God  acts  from  the  necessity  of  His  nature 
He  is  not  of  infinite  virtue. 

A  point  which  may  be  a  difficulty 

Whence  we  have  a     ,  ,  ;      ..      «r        .         ,, 

concept  of  a  du-  to  some  here  presents  itself,  viz.,  that 
TafTany^cVuaiiy  although  the  world  has  only  been 
gtven'  created   some  five   thousand   years,   if 

our  chronology  is  correct,  we  are  nevertheless  able  to 
conceive  of  a  much  greater  duration,  and  this  notwith- 
standing we  have  said  above  that  duration  depends 
upon  created  objects.  The  difficulty  will  disappear 
if  we  remember  that  our  ideas  of  duration  arise  not 
only  as  we  contemplate  created  objects,  but  from  re- 
flection upon  God's  infinite  power,  in  creating  them. 
For  we  do  not  think  of  objects  existing  per  se,  but 
only  through  the  infinite  power  of  God.  Vid.  Prop. 
12,  Pt.  I.  and  Coroll. 

Finally  lest  we  consume  too  much  time  with  these 


* 


1 68  THE  COGITATA  METAPHYSICA 

futile  arguments,  but  two  things  need  to  be  kept  in 
mind :  ( I )  The  distinction  between  duration  and 
eternity,  and  (2)  that  the  former  without  created  ob- 
jects, and  the  latter  without  God  are  non-intelligible. 
These  things  being  kept  in  mind  it  is  easy  to  answer 
all  these  arguments.  So  we  need  delay  no  longer  upon 
this  point. 

Chapter  XL 
Concerning  the  Concurrence  of  God. 

About  this  attribute  of  God  little  or  nothing  remains 
to  be  said  after  we  have  shown  that  each  single  mo- 
ment God  creates  things  -as  if  anew.  From  this  we 
have  shown  that  objects  have  no  powTer  of  self  deter- 
mination or  of  operation  in  themselves.  And  this 
holds  true  in  the  human  will  as  well  as  in  all  other 
objects.  Then  we  replied  to  certain  arguments  per- 
taining to  this.  And,  although  many  other  objections 
are  often  raised,  since  these  relate  more  especially  to 
Theology  we  shall  not  discuss  them  here. 

Nevertheless,  since  there  are  many  who  admit  and 
believe  in  this  conserving  power  of  God,  but  in  a 
different  sense  from  us,  we  shall  recall  what  has 
already  been  proven  in  order  that  we  may  detect  this 
fallacy.  We  have  already  clearly  shown  that  present 
time  has  no  connection  with  future  time  (Yid.  Ax. 
10,  Pt.  I.).  Provided  we  consistently  remember  this. 
we  shall  be  able  without  difficulty  to  reply  to  all  the 
objections  of  these  philosophers. 

HZnhactsZse™'       But    lest   we   take    up   this    subject 

T'act"*  tMngs     without  result  we  will  reply  in  passing 

to  the  inquiry  whether  an  additional  element  of  God's 


PART  11  169 

power  is  needed  to  begin  some  action  in  things.  When 
speaking  of  motion  this  same  question  appeared  and 
we  then  gave  our  answer.  For  we  said  that  God  con- 
stantly preserves  the  same  amount  of  motion  in  nature. 
If,  therefore,  we  consider  the  total  amount  of  matter 
in  motion  nothing  is  added.  But  in  respect  to  particu- 
lar things  there  is  an  additional  element  given.  It 
does  not  seem,  however,  that  the  same  thing  can  be 
said  of  mental  phenomena.  For  it  does  not  appear 
that  they  are  related  the  one  to  the  other  in  this  way. 
Then,  finally,  since  the  parts  of  duration  do  not  have 
a  casual  connection,  we  speak  more  truly  to  say  then 
that  God  continually  procreates  than  to  say  that  he 
conserves  them.  Therefore,  if  man  at  a  particular 
moment  is  free  to  choose  some  course  of  action  it  must 
be  said  that  God  at  the  present  time  so  creates  him. 
To  this  it  is  no  objection  that  the  human  will  is  often 
determined  by  external  influences,  and  that  all  nature 
is  inter-related  and  mutually  determining.  For  this 
also  is  so  ordained  of  God.  Indeed,  nothing  deter- 
mines the  will  nor  does  the  will  determine  anything  ex- 
cept through  the  power  of  God.  We  confess  that  we 
are  ignorant  of  how  this  may  not  be  opposed  to  human 
freedom,  or  how  God  can  ordain  this  and  still  preserve 
the  freedom  of  man.     This  we  have  already  admitted. 

These  are  the  things  I  had  decided 

The    ordinary     di-  . 

vision  of  the  at-    to    say    concerning    the    attributes    of 

tributes    is   ^fiovc 

of  name  than  of  God.  No  satisfactory  division  of 
them  has  yet  been  made.  The  divi- 
sion given  by  some,  who  divide  God's  attributes  into 
incommunicable  and  communicable  attributes  seems 
more  nominal  than  real.  For  the  knowledge  of  God 
is  no  more  like  human  knowledge  than  the  Dogstar  is 
like  a  barking  dog,  and  perhaps  it  is  even  less  similar. 


i;o  THE  COGITATA  METAPHYSICS 

We  would  offer  this   classification : 

ThthilVuthor!ion  °f  There  are  some  attributes  which  ex- 
plain God's  essence,  and  others  that  tell 
nothing  of  His  reality  but  only  explain  the  modes  of 
His  existence.  Of  the  latter  kind  are  Unity,  Eternity, 
Necessity,  etc. ;  of  the  former  Understanding,  Volition, 
Life,  Omnipotence,  etc.  This  division  is  clear  and 
perspicuous  and  comprehends  all  the  attributes  of  God. 

Chapter  XII. 

Concerning  the  Human  Mind. 

We  pass  now  to  created  substance  which  we  classify 
as  extended  and  as  thinking  substance.  By  the 
former  we  understand  matter  or  corporeal  substance. 
By  thinking  substance  we  understand  only  human 
minds. 

Although   angels   are   also   created, 

Angels  are  objects         •  ,1  ,1  1 

for  consideration  since  they  are  not  known  by  our  nat- 
fnol  \o  the  °Mcta-  tural  powers,  they  should  not  be  re- 
physidan.  garded     in     Metaphysics.     For    their 

essence  and  existence  are  only  known  through  revela- 
tion and  so  far  they  pertain  only  to  Theology.  Since 
the  cognition  of  these  beings  is  so  entirely  different 
from  our  ordinary  form  of  knowledge  the  two  should 
not  be  confused  or  classed  together.  No  one  should 
expect  us,  therefore,  to  discuss  angels  in  this  connec- 
tion. 

The  human  mind  We   turn,   therefore,   to  the   human 

SSJ&fiZ  1"  mind  concerning  which  a  few  things 
created  by  God,-    remaiii  to  be  said.     It  will   be   noted 

but  how,  we  do 

not  know.  that   we   say   nothing   concerning   the 

time  of  its  creation,  for  it  is  not  clear  just  when  it  is 
created  since  it  can  exist  without  the  bodv.     But  it  is 


PART  II  171 

evident  that  it  does  not  arise  by  traduction  for  it  would 
then  have  a  place  only  in  things  already  created, 
namely  in  modes  of  some  substance.  But  substances, 
as  we  have  plainly  showed  above,  can  be  created  only 
by  the  power  of  omnipotence. 

We  shall  add  a  few  words  concern- 
in  what  sense  the      ing  immortality.     It  is  evident  that  we 

human   soul  is  r  1       1   •  1 

mortal.  cannot  say  ot  any  created  object  that 

its  nature  implies  that  it  cannot  be 
destroyed  by  the  power  of  God.  For  he  who  has  the 
power  of  creating  an  object  has  also  the  power  of 
destroying  it.  Beside,  as  we  have  sufficiently  shown 
above,  no  created  object  has  in  itself  the  power  to 
exist,  even  for  a  moment,  but  in  every  case  is  con- 
tinually procreated  by  God. 

Although  this  is  all  true  we  all 
>InimmortSinSe  know  that  we  have  no  concept  of  a 
destroyed  object,  as  we  have  of  an 
object  disintegrated  or  of  a  generation  of  modes.  For 
we  can  conceive  clearly  enough  of  the  human  organ- 
ism being  destroyed  but  not  of  the  annihilation  of  its 
substance.  Then  philosophy  does  not  inquire  what 
God  by  His  omnipotence  is  able  to  do,  but  seeks  to 
determine  from  nature  itself  what  laws  God  has  really 
given  to  the  world.  Therefore,  what  it  concludes  is 
rational  and  fixed  it  concludes  is  so  from  the  laws 
of  nature.  However  we  would  not  deny  that  God  is 
able  to  change  these  laws  and  all  other  things  as  well. 
Therefore,  when  speaking  of  the  soul  we  do  not  in- 
quire what  God  is  able  to  do  but  what  follows  from 
the  laws  of  nature. 

Since  it  is  true,  as  we  have  abun- 
its  immortality         dantly   proven,   that   substance   cannot 

demonstrated.  . 

be  destroyed  either  by  its  own  power, 


172  THE  COGITATA  METAPHYS1CA 

or  by  the  power  of  any  other  created  substance,  unless 
I  am  mistaken,  it  follows  that  we  are  compelled  to 
believe  from  the  laws  of  nature  that  the  soul  is  im- 
mortal. And  if  we  choose  to  investigate  further,  we 
can  very  clearly  demonstrate  that  it  is  so.  For  as  we 
have  just  shown,  it  follows  from  the  laws  of  nature 
that  the  mind  is  immortal.  And  these  laws  of  nature 
are  the  decrees  of  God,  appointed  by  his  will,  as  we 
have  already  made  evident.  Then  beside,  these  laws 
are  unchangeable.  From  all  of  this  we  conclude  with 
certainty  that  God  has  revealed  His  immutable  will 
concerning  man's  immortality,  not  only  by  revelation, 
but  also  by  natural  reason. 

It  is  no  objection  to  this  opinion,  if 
GtntreaSryntt  but     some  one  should  say  that  at  times  God 

above  Nature    and   sets    as^e   tJiese   natural    laws   jn   work- 

God  is  its  author. 

ing  miracles.  For  there  are  many 
thoughtful  theologians  who  concede  that  God  does  not 
act  contrary  to,,  but  above  the  laws  of  nature.  That  is, 
God  has  many  laws  of  action  which  He  has  not  made 
known  to  man ;  and  these  if  revealed  to  man  would 
seem  equally  natural  with  the  ones  he  already  knows. 
Therefore  it  is  evident  that  minds  are  immortal.  I 
do  not  see  that  anything  remains  to  be  said  concerning 
its  nature.  Nor,  indeed,  concerning  its  specific  func- 
tions is  there  anything  to  add  unless  I  respond  to  the 
argument  of  certain  authors  who  attempt  to  show  that 
our  sense  of  perception  is  not  to  be  accepted  as  true. 

There  are  some  who  think  thev  can 
W,ZTin  nhJtn)ree.  show    that    the    will    is    not    free   but 

always  determined  by  something  from 
without.  They  believe  this  because  they  think  of  the 
will  as  something  distinct  from  the  mind,  a  substance 
whose  sole  nature  it  is  to  be  indifferent.     In  order  to 


PART  II  173 

remove  all  confusion  on  this  subject  we  will  explain 
the  matter  in  such  a  way  as  to  easily  detect  the  fallacy 
of  their  arguments. 

We  have  said  that  the  human  mind 

What  the  will  is.       .  .  .       .  ,.  ,,, 

is  a  thinking  object.  Whence  it  fol- 
lows that  from  its  nature,  and  that  alone  considered, 
it  is  able  to  do  something,  viz.,  to  think ;  that  is,  to 
affirm  and  to  deny.  These  forms  of  thought  are  de- 
termined either  by  something  extra-mental  or  by  the 
mind  itself.  But  since  the  mind  is  a  substance  itself 
whose  essence  it  is  to  think,  it  follows  that  thought  can 
and  should  arise  from  the  mind  itself.  Those  mental 
acts  which  know  no  other  cause  than  the  mind  itself, 
are  called  volitions.  And  the  human  mind  so  far  as 
it  is  considered  as  a  sufficient  cause  for  producing  these 
thoughts  is  called  Will. 

That  the  mind,  though   excited  by 

There   is  a   Will.  ,       ,   •       ,1 

no  external  object  has  power  to  act, 
is  sufficiently  proven  by  the  example  of  the  ass  of  Buri- 
danus.  For  were  a  man  instead  of  the  ass  placed  in 
such  a  condition  of  equilibrium  he  would  be  regarded 
not  as  a  thinking  being  but  as  a  most  stupid  ass  if  he 
perished  with  thirst  or  hunger.  Then  this  is  evident 
also  from  the  fact  mentioned  above,  that  we  have 
willed  to  doubt  everything,  and  not  only  to  hold  as 
doubtful  those  things  which  can  be  called  in  question, 
but  also  to  expose  what  is  false.  (Vid.  Principles  of 
Descartes,  Part  I.  Art.  39). 

Further,   it   should   be   remembered 

that,  although  the  mind  is  influenced 
by  external  objects  to  affirm  or  deny,  it  is  not  com- 
pelled even  here  but  retains  its  freedom.  For  nothing 
has  the  power  of  destroying  its  essence.  What  it 
affirms  or  denies  it  is  always  free  to  affirm  or  to  deny 


174  THE  COGITATA  METAPHYSICA 

as  was  shown  by  Descartes  in  the  fourth  Meditation. 
Therefore,  if  any  one  asks  why  the  mind  wills  this  or 
that,  we  reply  that  it  is  because  the  mind  is  a  thinking 
being  whose  very  nature  it  is  to  wish,  or  to  affirm 
or  to  deny.  This  is  what  it  means  to  be  a  thinking 
being. 

Having  stated  our  position  we  will 
If fZl  wUhbdesirt  ^ice  some  arguments  opposed  to 
such  a  view.  ( i )  Such  is  the  argument : 
//  the  will  can  choose  contrary  to  the  last  judgment 
of  the  understanding,  if  it  is  able  to  choose  contrary  to 
that  which  is  best  as  determined  by  the  understanding, 
it  is  able  to  choose  evil  for  the  sake  of  its  evil. 
But  this  conclusion  is  absurd.  Therefore  in  the  first 
place  it  is  evident  that  they  do  not  understand  what 
the  will  is.  They  confuse  it  with  the  desire  the  mind 
has  after  it  affirms  or  denies  something.  They  were 
taught  this  by  their  teacher  who  defined  the  will  as 
desire  for  the  sake  of  some  good  (appetitum  sub  ra- 
tione  boni).  We  would  say  on  the  contrary  that  the 
will  is  the  affirming  that  this  is  good  or  bad,  as  we 
plainly  showed  when  discussing  the  cause  of  error, 
and  found  that  this  arises  because  the  will  extends 
further  than  the  understanding.  If  the  mind  did  not 
affirm  this  or  that  is  good,  thus  exercising  its  free- 
dom, it  would  not  desire  it.  Therefore  we  would 
reply  to  this  argument  by  conceding  that  the  mind 
cannot  choose  anything  contrary  to  the  last  judgment 
of  the  understanding,  that  is,  it  cannot  choose  any- 
thing so  far  as  it  is  unwilling;  as  is  here  supposed 
when  we  say  that  this  thing  is  evil  or  that  the  mind 
does  not  choose  it.  But  we  deny  that  it  is  impossible 
for  evil  to  be  chosen  or  be  considered  good,  for  this 
would  be  contrary  to  all  experience.     For  many  evil 


PART  II  175 

things  are  thought  to  be  good  and  many  good  things 
are  considered  evil. 

2.  The  second  argument  is   (or  the 
Nor  is  it  anything,    first    if    you    prefer,    since    the    other 

except    the    mind. 

amounted  to  nothing)  :  If  the  will  is 
not  determined  by  the  last  practical  judgment  of  the 
understanding  it  is  self  determined.  But  the  will  does 
not  determine  itself  because  in  itself  and  from  its  na- 
ture it  is  indeterminate."  From  this  they  proceed  to 
argue:  "If  the  will  by  nature  is  indifferent  to  acting 
it  cannot  be  determined  by  itself.  That  which  deter- 
mines anything  must  be  determined,  and  that  which  is 
determined  must  be  indeterminate.  But  the  will  con- 
sidered as  determining  itself  would  be  considered  both 
as  determinate  and  indeterminate.  For  these  oppo- 
nents presuppose  nothing  in  the  determining  will  that 
is  not  the  same  in  the  will  either  as  determined  or  as 
about  to  be  determined.  Nor  indeed  can  anything  be 
affirmed.  Therefore,  the  will  cannot  be  determined  by 
itself.  But  if  not  by  itself  then  otherwise."  These 
are  the  words  of  Professor  Heereboordius  of  Leyden,1 
in  which  he  clearly  shows  that  he  understood  by  voli- 
tion not  the  mind  itself,  but  something  else  outside  of 
the  mind,  a  tabula  rasa,  as  it  were,  free  from  all  forms 
of  thought  and  capable  of  receiving  images  upon  itself. 
Or  rather  as  a  weight  in  equilibrium,  which,  as  much 
as  it  is  determined  at  all,  from  without,  may  be  in- 
clined to  one  side  by  another  weight.  Or  finally  as 
something  which  cannot  be  understood  by  the  cogni- 
tion of  any  mortal.  We  have  just  said,  and  indeed 
shown,  that  the  will  is  nothing  but  the  mind  itself. 
That  is,  it  is  the  thinking  being,  a  being  who  affirms 
and  denies.     So  we  find  when  we  consider  the  nature 

1Vid.  ejus  Meletemata  Philosophies,  ed.  alt.  Ltigd.  Bat.  1659. 


176  THE  COGITATA  METAPHYSIC.l 

of  mind  that  it  has  an  equal  power  of  affirming  and 
denying.  For  this,  as  I  have  said,  is  the  meaning  of 
thought.  We  conclude,  therefore,  that  the  mind 
thinks,  that  it  has  this  power  of  affirming  and  of  deny- 
ing. Why  then  should  we  seek  extra-mental  reasons 
for  doing  what  is  sufficiently  explained  by  the  nature 
of  the  mind  itself?  But  you  say,  "the  mind  is  not 
determined  more  to  affirm  than  to  deny ;  hence  some 
extra-mental  cause  for  volition  is  necessary."  But  I 
argue  the  contrary ;  if  the  mind  were  by  nature  only 
capable  of  affirming  (although  such  a  conception  is 
impossible  as  long  as  we  conceive  of  the  mind  as  think- 
ing being)  so  that,  however  many  causes  concur,  it  is 
impossible  for  it  to  deny  anything.  Or  if  it  could 
neither  affirm  or  deny,  it  would  be  able  to  do  neither. 
Or,  finally,  if  it  had  the  power,  as  we  have  shown  it 
has,  it  would  be  able  to  do  both  from  its  nature  alone, 
no  other  cause  assisting.  This  is  evidently  the  case 
for  all  who  really  give  to  a  thinking  being  the  power 
of  thought.  Those  who  separate  the  attribute  of 
thought  from  the  thing  itself  from  which  it  is  only 
distinguished  by  the  reason,  denude  the  thinking  being 
of  all  thought  and  regard  what  remains  as  the  funda- 
mental substance  of  the  Peripatetics.  Therefore,  I 
respond  that  if  they  understand  by  will  something 
independent  of  thought,  we  will  concede  that  their 
will  is  indeterminate.  But  we  deny  that  the  will 
is  something  void  of  understanding ;  on  the  other 
hand,  we  believe  that  it  is  thought,  i.  e.,  it  is  the  power 
of  affirming  and  of  denying.  Certainly  nothing  else 
will  satisfy  the  conditions.  Then,  too,  we  deny  that 
even  if  the  will  is  indeterminate  it  is  therefore  de- 
spoiled of  thought,  and  can  be  determined  by  any 
external  object  except  God's   infinite  power.     For  to 


PART  II 


177 


Why  philosophers 
confuse    mind 
with   corporeal 
things. 


conceive  of  a  thinking  being  without  thought  is  the 
same  as  to  conceive  of  an  extended  body  without 
extension. 

Finally,  there  is  no  need  to  consider 
other  arguments,  but  I  shall  only  say 
that  opponents  of  this  view  confuse  the 
mind  with  corporeal  objects  because 
they  do  not  understand  the  will,  or  have  a  clear  and  a 
distinct  concept  of  the  mind.  As  has  been  said,  this 
error  arises  from  the  fact  that  words  properly  used 
only  to  describe  corporeal  objects  have  been  applied  to 
spiritual  things.  For  they  have  been  accustomed  to 
call  those  bodies  indeterminate  which  are  acted  upon 
by  two  equivalent  external  forces  acting  in  opposition 
to  one  another.  Therefore,  since  they  think  that  the 
will  is  indeterminate  they  seem  to  think  of  it  as  a 
body  in  equilibrium.  And,  because  those  bodies  have 
nothing  except  what  they  receive  from  external  causes 
(from  which  it  follows  that  they  are  always  deter- 
mined by  an  external  cause),  they  think  that  the  same 
thing  is  true  concerning  the  will.  But  as  we  have 
already  made  sufficiently  clear  why  these  things  are 
so,  we  shall  say  no  more. 

Concerning  extended  substance  we  have  already 
spoken  sufficiently  and  beside  these  two  forms  of 
created  substance  we  know  no  others.  What  pertains 
to  real  accidents  and  to  other  qualities  has  also  been 
sufficiently  criticised  nor  is  there  need  to  take  any  fur- 
ther time  in  refuting  them,  so  we  take  our  hand  from 
the  table. 


TITLE    LIST    OF     OPEN     COURT    PUBLICATIONS 
ARRANGED     ALPHABETICALLY      BY     AUTHORS 


ANESAKI,  M. 

345.  BUDDHIST  AND  CHRISTIAN  GOSPELS,  Being  Gospel  Paral- 
lels from  Pali  Texts.  Now  first  compared  from  the  originals 
by  Albert  J.  Edmunds.  Edited  with  parallels  and  notes'  from 
the  Chinese  Buddhist  Triptaka  by  M.  Anesaki     $1.50  net. 

BAYNE,  JULIA  TAFT. 

323.     HADLEY  BALLADS.     Julia  Taft  Baync.     75c  net. 

BERKELEY,  GEORGE. 

307.  A  TREATISE  CONCERNING  THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  HUMAN 

KNOWLEDGE.     George  Berkeley.     Cloth,   60c  net.      (3s.  net.) 

308.  THREE  DIALOGUES  BETWEEN  HYLAS  AND  PHILONOUS. 

George  Berkeley.     Cloth,  60c  net.      (3s.  net.) 

BINET,  ALFRED. 

201.  THE  PSYCHIC  LIFE  OF  MICRO-ORGANISMS.  Alfred  Binet. 
75c.     (3s.  6d.) 

270.  THE  PSYCHOLOGY  OF  REASONING.  Alfred  Binet.  Transl. 
by  Adam  Gowans  IVliyte.     75c  net.      (3s.  6d.) 

296.  ON  DOUBLE  CONSCIOUSNESS.  Alfred  Binet.  Cloth,  50c  net. 
(2s.  6d.  net.) 

BLOOMFIELD,  MAURICE, 

534.  CERBERUS,  THE  DOG  OF  HADES.  The  History  of  an  Idea. 
Prof.  M.  Bloomfield.     Boards,   50c  net.      (2s.   6d.   net.) 

BONNEY,  HONORABLE  CHARLES  CARROLL. 

304.  WORLD'S  CONGRESS  ADDRESSES,  Delivered  by  the  Presi- 
dent, the  Hon.  C.  C.  Bonney.     Cloth,   50c  net.      (2s.   6d.  net.) 

BONNEY,  FLORENCE  PEORIA. 

286.  MEDITATIONS  (Poems).  Florence  Peoria  Bonney.  Cloth,  $1.00 
net.) 

BUDGE,  E  .A.  WALLIS. 

325.  THE  GODS  OF  THE  EGYPTIANS  OR  STUDIES  IN  EGYP- 
TIAN MYTHOLOGY.  E.  A.  Wallis  Budge.  With  plates  and 
illustrations.    2  vols.     Cloth,  $20.00  net. 

226.  THE  BOOK  OF  THE  DEAD,  a  translation  of  the  Chapters, 
Hymns,  etc.,  of  the  Theban  Recension.  E.  A.  Wallis  Budge. 
Illustrated.'  3  vols.  $3.75  per  set  net.  Vols.  VI,  VII,  VIII 
in  the  series  of  Books  on  Egypt  and  Chaldea. 


tgWScnd  for  Complete  Illustrated  Catalogue. 


TITLE     LIST 


317.  A  HISTORY  OF  EGYPT,  From  the  End  of  the  Neolithic  Period 
to  the  Death  of  Cleopatra  VII,  B.  C.  30.  E.  A.  Wallis  Budge. 
Richly  illustrated.    8  vols.     Cloth,  $10.00  net. 

I.  Egypt  in  the  Neolithic  and  Archaic  Period. 

II.  Egypt   Under  the  Great   Pyramid  Builders. 

III.  Egypt  Under  the  Amenembats  and  Hyksos. 

IV.  Egypt  and  her  Asiatic  Empire. 

V.  Egypt  Under  Rameses  the  Great. 

VI.  Egypt  Under  the  Priest  Kings  and  Tanites  and  Nubians. 

VII.  Egypt  Under  the   Saites,   Persians  and  Ptolemies. 

VIII.  Egypt  Under  the  Ptolemies  and  Cleopatra  VII. 

CARUS,  DR.  PAUL. 

204.  FUNDAMENTAL  PROBLEMS,  the  Method  of  Philosophy  as  a 
Systematic  Arrangement  of  Knowledge.  Paul  Car  us.  Cloth, 
$1.50.      (7s.   6d.) 

207.  TFIE   SOUL  OF  MAN,   an  Investigation  of  the  Facts  of  Physio- 

logical and  Experimental  Psychology.     Paul  Cams.     Illustrated. 
Cloth,  $1.50  net.      (6s.  net.) 

208.  PRIMER  OF  PHILOSOPHY.     Paul  Cams.     Cloth,  $1.00.     (5s.) 

210.  MONISM  AND  MELIORISM,  A  Philosophical  Essay  on  Causal 
ity  and  Ethics.    Paul  Cams.     Paper,   50c.     (2s.  6d.) 

213.  (a)  THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  THE  TOOL.  10c.  (6d.)  (b)  OUR 
NEED  OF  PHILOSOPHY.  5c.  (3d.)  (c)  SCIENCE  A 
RELIGIOUS  REVELATION.     5c  .   (3d.)     Paul  Cants. 

2Q0.     THE  SURD  OF  METAPHYSICS,  An  Inquiry  into  the  Question 

Are  there   Things-in-themselves?    Paul   Cams.      Cloth,    $1.25 
net.     (5s.   6d.  net.) 

303.     KANT  AND  SPENCER,  A  Study  of  the  Fallacies  of  Agnosticism. 
Paul  Cams.     Cloth,  50c  net.      (2s.  6d.  net.) 

312.  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA  TO  ANY  FUTURE  METAPHYS- 
ICS.    Edited  by  Paul  Cams.     Cloth,  75c  net.      (3s.  6d.  net.) 

215.  THE  GOSPEL  OF  BUDDHA,  According  to  Old  Records,  told  by 

Paul  Cams.      Cloth,   $1.00.      (5s.) 

254.  BUDDHISM  AND  ITS  CHRISTIAN  CRITICS.  Paul  Cams. 
$1.25.     (6s.  6d.) 

261.  GODWARD,  A  Record  of  Religious  Progress.  Paul  Cams.  50c. 
(2s.  6d.) 

278.  THE.  HISTORY  OF  THE  DEVIL  AND  THE  IDEA  OF  EVIL, 
From  the  Earliest  Times  to  the  Present  day.  Paul  Cams.  Il- 
lustrated.    $6.00.      (30s.) 

280.     HISTORY  OF  THE  CROSS.     Paul  Cams.     (In  preparation.) 

321.  THE  AGE  OF  CHRIST.  A  Brief  Review  of  the  Conditions 
under  which   Christianity  originated.      Paul   Cants.      Paper,    15c 

net.      (iod.) 

341.  THE  DHARMA,  or  the  Religion  of  Enlightenment,  An  Exposi- 
tion of   Buddhism.     Paul   Car  us.      15c.      (.od.) 

216.  DAS  EVANGELIUM  BUDDHAS.    A  German  translation  of  The 

Gospel  of  Buddha.     Cloth,  $i.J5.      (5  marks.) 


;(    'Send  for  Complete  Illustrated   Catalogue, 


OPEN     COURT     PUBLICATIONS 


255- 
275- 

205. 
206. 

211. 

212. 
268. 

285. 

291. 

302. 

209. 

217. 

2I7G. 

246. 

247. 

267. 

28l. 
282. 

293- 
224. 

243- 


LAO-TZE'S  TAO  TEH  KING.  Chinese  English.  With  Introduc- 
tion,  Transliteration  and  Notes  by  Paul  Cams.    $3.00     (15s.) 

THE  WORLD'S  PARLIAMENT  OF  RELIGIONS  AND  THE 
RELIGIOUS  PARLIAMENT  EXTENSION,  a  Memorial  Pub- 
lished by  the  Religious  Parliament  Extension  Committee.  Popu- 
lar edition.     C.  C.  Bonney  and  Paul  Cants. 

HOMILIES  OF  SCIENCE.  Paul  Cams.  Cloth,  gilt  top,  $1.50. 
(7s.  6d.) 

THE  IDEA  OF  GOD.  Paul  Cams.    Paper,   15c.     (9d.) 

THE  RELIGION  OF  SCIENCE.  Paul  Cams.  Cloth,  50c  net. 
(2s.  6d.) 

KARMA,  A  STORY  OF  BUDDHIST  ETHICS.  Paul  Cams. 
Illustrated  by  Kwason  Susuki.     American  edition.      15c.     (iod.) 

THE  ETHICAL  PROBLEM.  Three  Lectures  on  Ethics  as  a 
Science.     Paul  Cams.     Cloth,  $1.25.      (6s.  6d.) 

WHENCE  AND  WHITHER.  An  Inquiry  into  the  Nature  of 
the  Soul,  Its  Origin  and  Its  Destiny.  Paul  Cams.  Cloth,  75c 
net.      (3s.  6d.  net.) 

NIRVANA,  A  STORY  OF  BUDDHIST  PSYCHOLOGY.  Paul 
Cams.    Illustrated  by  Kwason  Susuki.    Cloth,  60c  net.    (3s.net.) 

THE  DAWN  OF  A  NEW  RELIGIOUS  ERA,  AND  OTHER 
ESSAYS.    Paul  Cams.    Cloth,   50c  net.     (2s.  6d.  net.) 

TRUTH  IN  FICTION,  Twelve  Tales  with  a  Moral.  Paul  Cams. 
Cloth,   1. 00  net.      (5s.) 

KARMA,  A  STORY  OF  EARLY  BUDDHISM.  Paul  Cams. 
Illustrated.      Crepe  paper,  tied  in  silk.      75c.      (3s.   6d.) 

KARMA,  Eine  buddhistische  Erzahlung.  Paul  Cams.  Illustrated. 
35c. 

THE  CROWN  OF  THORNS,  a  Story  ui  the  Time  of  Christ. 
Paul  Cams.     Illustrated.     Cloth  75c  net.     (3s.  6d.  net.) 

THE  CHIEF'S  DAUGHTER,  a  Legend  of  Niagara.  Paul  Cams. 
Illustrated.     Cloth,  $1.00  net.      (4s.  6d.) 

SACRED  TUNES  FOR  THE  CONSECRATION  OF  LIFE. 
Hymns  of  the   Religion  of   Science.     Paul  Cams.      50c. 

GREEK  MYTHOLOGY.     Paul  Cams.     In  preparation. 

EROS  AND  PSYCHE,  A  Fairy-Tale  of  Ancient  Greece,  Retold 
after  Apuleius,  by  Paul  Cams.    Illustrated.    $1.50  net.   (6s.  net.) 

THE  NATURE  OF  THE  STATE.  Paul  Cams.  Cloth  50c  net. 
(2s.  6d.  net) 

GOETHE  AND  SCHILLER'S  XENIONS.  Selected  and  trans- 
lated by  Paul  Cams.     Paper,   50c.      (2s.   6d.) 

FRIEDRICH  SCHILLER,  A  Sketch  of  His  Life  and  an  Appre- 
ciation of  His  Poetry.     Paul  Cants.    Bds.  75c. 


&2pSend  for  Complete  Illustrated   Catalog::.. 


TITLE     LIST 


CLEMENT,  ERNEST  W. 

331.  THE  JAPANESE  FLORAL  CALENDAR.  E.  W.  Clement.  Il- 
lustrated.     Boards,    50c   net.      (2s.   6d.   net.) 

CONWAY,  MONCURE  DANIEL. 

277.     SOLOMON  AND  SOLOMONIC  LITERATURE.    M.  D.  Conway. 

Cloth,  $1.50  net.      (6s.) 

COPE,  E.  D. 

219.  THE  PRIMARY  FACTORS  OF  ORGANIC  EVOLUTION.  E. 

D.  Cope,  Ph.  D.     2d  ed.     Illustrated.     Cloth,  $2.00  net.      (10s.) 

CORNILL,  CARL  HEINRICH. 

220.  THE    PROPHETS    OF    ISRAEL,    Popular    Sketches    from    Old 

Testament  History.     C.  H.  Cornill.     Transl.  by  S.  F.   Corkran. 
$1.00  net.      (5s.) 

259.  THE  HISTORY  OF  THE  PEOPLE  OF  ISRAEL,  From  the 
Earliest  Times  to  the  Destruction  of  Jerusalem  by  the  Romans. 
C.  H.  Cornill.    Transl.  by  W.  H.  Carruth.    Cloth,  $1.50    (7s.  6d.) 

262.  GESCHICHTE  DES  VOLKES  ISRAEL.  C.  H.  Cornill.  Ge- 
bunden  $2.00.     (8  Mark.) 

251.  THE  RISE  OF  THE  PEOPLE  OF  ISRAEL.  C.  H.  Cornill,  in 
Epitomes  of  Three  Sciences:  Comparative  Philology,  Psy- 
chology and  Old  Testament  History.  H.  H.  Oldenberg,  J. 
Jastrow,  C.  H.  Cornill.     Colth,  50c  net.      (2s.  6d.) 

CUMONT,  FRANZ. 

319.  THE  MYSTERIES  OF  MITHRA.  Prof.  Franc  Cumont.  Transl. 
by  T.  J.  McCormack.    Illus.    Cloth,  $1.50  net.     (6s.  6d.  net.) 

DEDEKIND,  RICHARD. 

287.  ESSAYS  ON  THE  THEORY  OF  NUMBERS.  I.  Continuity 
and  Irrational  Numbers.  II.  The  Nature  and  Meaning  or 
Numbers.  R.  Dcdekind.  Transl.  by  IV.  W.  Beman.  Cloth, 
75c  net.      (3s.   6d.  net.) 

DELITZSCH,  DR.  FRIEDRICH. 

293.  BABEL  AND  BIBLE,  A  Lecture  on  the  Significance  of  Assyrio- 
logical  Research  for  Religion.  Prof.  F.  Delitzsch.  Translated 
by  T.  J.  McCormack.    Illustrated.    50c  net. 

293a.  BABEL  AND  BIBLE.  Two  Lectures  on  the  Significance  of. 
Assyriological  Research  for  Religion,  Embodying  the  most  im- 
portant Criticisms  and  the  Author's  Replies.  Prof.  F.  Delitzsch. 
Translated  by  T.  J.  McCormack  and  W.  H.  Carruth.     75c  net. 

DE  MORGAN,  AUGUSTUS. 

264.  ON  THE  STUDY  AND  DIFFICULTIES  OF  MATHEMATICS. 
Augustus  DeMorgan.     Cloth,  $1.25  net.     (4s.  6d.  net.) 

271.  ELEMENTARY  ILLUSTRATIONS  OF  THE  DIFFERENTIAL 
AND  INTEGRAL  CALCULUS.  Augustus  DeMorgan.  Cloth, 
$1.00  net.     (4s.  6d.  net.) 


83rScnd  for  Complete  Illustrated  Catalogue.'^t 


OPEN     COURT     PUBLICATIONS 


DESCARTES,  RENE. 

301.  DISCOURSE  ON  THE  METHOD  OF  RIGHTLY  CONDUCT 
ING  THE  REASON  AND  SEEKING  TRUTH  IN  THE  SCI 
ENCES.  Rene  Descartes.  Transl.  by  John  Veitch.  Cloth,  60c 
net.      (3s.   net.) 

310.  THE  MEDITATIONS  AND  SELECTIONS  FROM  THE  PRIN- 
CIPLES  of  Rene  Descartes.  Transl.  by/o/in  Veitch.  Cloth, 
75c  net.      (3s.   6d.  net.) 

346.     THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY  by  Bene- 

dictus  de  Spinoza.     Introduction  by  Halbert  Hains  Britan,  Ph. 
D.     Cloth,   75c  net,  mailed  85c. 

DE  VRIES,  HUGO. 

332.  SPECIES  AND  VARIETIES,  THEIR  ORIGIN  BY  MUTA- 
TION. Prof.  Hugo  de  Fries.  Edited  by  D.  T.  MacDougal. 
$5.00  net.      (2 is.  net.) 

EDMUNDS,  ALBERT  J. 

218.  HYMNS  OF  THE  FAITH  (DHAMMAPADA),  being  an  Ancient 
Anthology  Preserved  in  the  Sacred  Scriptures  of  the  Buddhists. 
Transl.  by  Albert  J.  Edmunds.     Cloth,  $1.00  net.     (4s.  6d.  net.) 

345-  BUDDHIST  AND  CHRISTIAN  GOSPELS,  Being  Gospel  Paral- 
lels from  Pali  Texts.  Now  first  compared  from  the  originals 
by  Albert  J.  Edmunds.  Edited  with  parallels  and  notes  from 
the  Chinese  Buddhist  Triptaka  by  M.  Ancsaki     $1.50  net. 

EVANS,  HENRY  RIDGELY. 

330.  THE  NAPOLEON  MYTH.  H.  R.  Evans.  With  "The  Grand 
Erratum,"  by  /.  B.  Peres,  and  Introduction  by  Paul  Cams. 
Illustrated.     Boards,   75c  net.      (3s.   6d.  net.) 

347-  TPIE  OLD  AND  THE  NEW  MAGIC.  Henry  R.  Evans.  Illustr. 
Cloth,  gilt  top.     $1.50  net,  mailed  $1.70. 

FECHNER,  GUSTAV  THEODOR. 

349.  ON  LIFE  AFTER  DEATH.  Gustav  Theodor  Fcchncr.  Tr.  from 
the  German  by  Hugo  Wernekke.    Bds.  75c. 

FINK,  DR.  CARL. 

272.  A  BRIEF  HISTORY  OF  MATHEMATICS.  Dr.  Karl  Fink. 
Transl.  from  the  German  by  W.  W.  Bcman  and  D.  E.  Smith. 
Cloth,  $1.50  net.     (5s.  6d.  net.) 

FREYTAG,  GUSTAV. 

24S.  MARTIN  LUTHER.  Gustav  Freytag.  Transl.  by  H.  E.  O.  Heine- 
mann.    Illustrated.     Cloth,   $1.00  net.     (5s.) 

221.  THE   LOST   MANUSCRIPT.     A  Novel.      Gustav  Freytag.     Two 

vols.     Cloth,  $4.00.      (21s.) 
221a.  THE  SAME.     One  vol.     $1.00.     (5s.) 

GARBE,  RICHARD. 

223.  THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  ANCIENT  INDIA.  Prof.  R.  Garbe. 
Cloth,   50c  net.      (2s.  6d.  net.) 

222.  THE  REDEMPTION  OF  THE  BRAHMAN.     A  novel.     Richard 

Garbe.     Cloth,  75c.      (3s.  6d.) 


SSWScnd  for  Complete  Illustrated   Catalogue."^. 


TITLE     LIST 


GOODWIN,  REV.  T.  A. 

225.  LOVERS  THREE  THOUSAND  YEARS  AGO,  as  indicated  by 
The  Song  of  Solomon.     Rev.  T.  A.  Goodwin.    50c  net.   (2s.  6d.) 

GUNKEL,  HERMANN. 

227.  THE   LEGENDS   OF   GENESIS.     Prof.   H.    Gunkel.     Transl.   by 

Prof.   W.  H.  Carruth.     Cloth,  $1.00  net.     (4s.  6d.  net.) 

HAUPT,    PAUL. 

292.  BIBLICAL  LOVE  -  DITTIES,  A  CRITICAL  INTERPRETA- 
TION AND  TRANSLATION  OF  THE  SONG  OF  SOLO- 
MON.    Prof.  Paul  Haupt.     Paper,   5c.      (3d.) 

HERING,  PROF.  EWALD. 

298.  ON  MEMORY  AND  THE  SPECIFIC  ENERGIES  OF  THE 
NERVOUS   SYSTEM.    E.  Hering.    CI.   50c  net.     (2s.  6d.  net.) 

HILBERT,  DAVID. 

289.  THE  FOUNDATIONS  OF  GEOMETRY.  Prof.  David  Hilbert. 
Transl.  by  E.  J.  Townsend.     Cloth,  $1.00  net.      (4s.  6d.  net.) 

HOLYOAKE,  GEORGE  JACOB. 

228.  ENGLISH   SECULARISM,  A  Confession  of  Belief.     G.  J.  Holy- 

oake.      Cloth,    50c  net. 

HUC,  M. 

244.  TRAVELS  IN  TARTARY,  THIBET  AND  CHINA,  During  the 
Years  1844-5-6.  M.  Hue.  Transl.  by  IV.  Hazlitt.  Illustrated. 
One  volume.     $1.25  net.      (5s.  net.) 

260.     THE  SAME.  Two  volumes.     $2.00.      (10s  net.) 

HUEPPE,  DR.  FERDINAND. 

257.  THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  BACTERIOLOGY.  Ferdinand  Hueppe. 
Transl.  by  Dr.  E.  O.  Jordan.     $1.75  net.     (9s.) 

HUME,  DAVID. 

305.  AN   ENQUIRY   CONCERNING   HUMAN    UNDERSTANDING. 

David  Plume.     Cloth,  60c  net.      (3s.  net.) 

306.  AN   ENQUIRY   CONCERNING  THE   PRINCIPLES   OF   MOR- 

ALS.    David  Hume.     Cloth,  60c  net.      (3s.  net.) 

HUTCHINSON,  WOODS. 

256.  THE  GOSPEL  ACCORDING  TO  DARWIN,  Woods  Hutchinson. 
Cloth,    $1.50.      (6s.) 

HYLAN,  JOHN  P. 

309.  PUBLIC  WORSHIP,  A  STUDY  IN  THE  PSYCHOLOGY  OF 
RELIGION.     /.  P.  Hylan.     Cloth,  60c  net.      (3s.   net.) 

INGRAHAM,  ANDREW. 
322.     SWAIN  SCHOOL  LECTURES.    Andre®  Ingraham.  $1.00  net. 
KHE1RALLA,  GEORGE  IBRAHIM. 

326.  BEI1A  'U'LLAH  (THE  GLORY  OF  COD).  Ibrahim  George 
Kheiralla,  assisted  by  Howard  MacNutt.     $j,.ov. 


A     'Send   for  Complete   Illustrated   Catalogue.      ;i 


OPEN     COURT     PUBLICATIONS 


LAGRANGE,  JOSEPH  LOUIS. 

258.  LECTURES  ON  ELEMENTARY  MATHEMATICS.  /.  L.  La- 
grange. Transl.  by  T.  J.  McCormack.  Cloth,  $1.00  net.  (4s. 
6d.  net.) 

LEIBNIZ,  G.  W 

311.  LEIBNIZ:  DISCOURSE  ON  METAPHYSICS,  CORRESPOND- 
ENCE WITH  ARNAULD  and  MONADOLOGY.  Dr.  George  R. 
Montgomery.     Cloth,  75c  net.     (3s.  6d.  net.) 

LEVY-BRUHL,  LUCIEN. 

273.  HISTORY  OF  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY  IN  FRANCE.  Lucien 
Levy-Bruhl.     With  portraits.     $3.00  net.      (12s.  net.) 

LOYSON,  EMILIE  HYACINTHE. 

338.  TO  JERUSALEM  THROUGH  THE  LANDS  OF  ISLAM.  Emilie 

Hyacinthe  Loyson.     Illustrated.      Cloth,   $2.50. 

MACH,  ERNST. 

229.  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS,  A  Critical  and  Historical  Ac- 

count of  its  Development.  Prof.  Ernst  Mach.  Transl.  by  T.  J. 
McCormack.   Illustrated.     $2.00  net.      (9s.   6d.  net.) 

230.  POPULAR    SCIENTIFIC    LECTURES.      Professor   Ernst   Mach. 

Transl.   by   T.  J.  McCormack.    Illust.     $1.50   net.     (7s.   6d.   net.) 

250.  CONTRIBUTIONS  TO  THE  ANALYSIS  OF  THE  SENSA- 
TIONS. Prof.  Ernst  Mach.  Transl.  bv  C.  M.  Williams.  $1.25 
net.      (6s.   6d.) 

MILLS,  LAWRENCE  H. 

318.  ZARATHUSHTRIAN  GATHAS,  in  Meter  and  Rhythm.  Prof. 
Laivrence  H.  Mills.    Cloth,  $2.00. 

339.  ZARATHUSHTRA   AND    THE    GREEKS,    a    Treatise    upon    the 

Antiquities  of  the  Avesta  with  Special  Reference  to  the  Logos- 
Conception.     Prof.  Laivrence  H.  Mills.     Cloth,   $2.00  net. 

MUELLER,  F.  MAX. 

231.  THREE    INTRODUCTORY    LECTURES    ON    THE    SCIENCE 

OF  THOUGHT.  F.  Max  Midler.  With  a  eorres] .ondeace  on 
Thought  without  words  between  F.  Max  Mtiller  and  Francis 
Galton,  the  Duke  of  Argyll,  G.  J.  Romanes  and  Others.  Cloth, 
75c.      (3s.  6d.) 

232.  THREE    LECTURES    ON    THE    SCIENCE    OF    LANGUAGE. 

With  a  supplement,  My  Predecessors.  F.  Max  Milller.  Cloth, 
75c.      (3s.   6d.) 

NAEGELI,  CARL  VON. 

300.  A  MECHANICO-PHYSIOLOGICAL  THEORY  OF  ORGANIC 
EVOLUTION.     Carl  von  Nagcli.    Cloth,   50c  net.     (2s.  6d.   net) 

NOIRE,  LUDWIG. 
297.     ON   THE   ORIGIN   OF   LANGUAGE,    and   THE   LOGOS   THE- 
ORY.    Ludwig  Noire.     Cloth,   50c  net.      (2s.  6d.  net.) 


i{':7$cnd   for  Complete  Illustrated   Catalogue      V. 


TITLE     LIST 


OLDENBERG.  PROF.  H. 

233.  •  ANCIENT  INDIA,  Its  Language  and  Religions.     Prof.  II.  Olden- 

berg.     Cloth,   50c  net.      (2s.   6d.) 

POWELL,  J.  W. 

263.     TRUTH    AND    ERROR,    or   the    Science   of   Intellection.      /.    IV. 
■  ■   ■  Pozvell.     $1.75.      (7s.   6d.) 

315.     JOHN    WESLEY    POWELL:    A    Memorial    to    an    American    Ex- 
plorer  and    Scholar.      Mrs.   M.   D.   Lincoln,    G.   K.    Gilbert. 
Baker  and  Paul  Cams.    Edited  by  G.  K.  Gilbert.  Paper,  50c  net. 

RADAU,  DR.  HUGO. 

294.  THE  CREATION  STORY  OF  GENESIS  I.  A  Sumerian  Theog- 
ony  and  Cosmogony.  H.   Radau.    Eds.,    75c  net.     (3s.   6d.   net.) 

RIBOT,  TH. 

234.  THE  PSYCHOLOGY  OF  ATTENTION.   Th.  Ribot.     Cloth,   75c. 

(3s.  6d.) 

235.  THE  DISEASES  OF  PERSONALITY.     Th.  Ribot.     Cloth,   75c 

(3s.  6d.) 

236.  THE  DISEASES  OF  THE  WILL.     Th.  Ribot.     Transl.  by  Mer- 

win-Marie  Snell.     Cloth,  75c.      (3s.  6d. ) 

279.  THE  EVOLUTION  OF  GENERAL  IDEAS.  Th.  Ribot.  Transl. 
by  Frances  A.   Welby.     Cloth,  $1.25.     (5s.) 

ROMANES,  GEORGE  JOHN. 

237.  DARWIN  AND   AFTER   DARWIN,    An   Exposition   of  the   Dar- 

winian Theory   and   a   Discussion   of   Post-Darwinian   Questions. 
George  John  Romanes.     Three  volumes.     $4.00  net. 

238.  Part  I.     The  Darwinian  Theory.     Cloth,  $2.00. 

239.  Part    II.       Post-Darwinian     Questions:     Heredity    and 
Utility.     Cloth,  $1.50. 

252.     Part    III.      Post-Darwinian    Question's:    Isolation    and 
Physiological   Selection.     Cloth,   $1.00. 

240.  AN  EXAMINATION  OF  WEISMANNISM.  George  John  Ro- 
manes.    Cloth,  $1.00  net. 

214.  A  CANDID  EXAMINATION  OF  THEISM.  Physicus  (the 
late  G.  J.  Romanes).      Cloth,   $2.00. 

242.  THOUGHTS  ON  RELIGION.  The  late  G.  J.  Romanes.  Edited 
by  Charles  Gore.     Cloth,  $1.25  net. 

ROW,  T.  SUNDARA. 

284.     GEOMETRIC  EXERCISES  IN  PAPER  FOLDING.     T.  Sundara 

Row.     Edited  by  IV.   IV.  Beman,  and  D.  E.  Smith.     Illustrated. 
Cloth,    $1.00  net.      (4s.  6d.  net.) 

RUTH,  J.  A. 

329.     WHAT  IS  THE  BIBLE?     /.  A.  Ruth.     75c  net.      (3s.   6d.   net.) 

SCHUBERT,  HERMANN. 

266.  MATHEMATICAL  ESSAYS  AND  RECREATIONS.  Prof.  Her 
matin  Schubert.  Transl.  by  T.  J.  McCormack.  Cloth,  75c  net. 
(3s.  6d.  net.) 


,(     'Send  for  Complete  Illustrated   Catalogue 


OPEN     COURT     PUBLICATIONS 


SHUTE.  D.  KERFOOT. 

276.  A  FIRST  BOOK  IX  ORGANIC  EVOLUTION.  D.  Kerfoot 
Shute.      Cloth,   $2.00  net.      (7s.   6d.   net.) 

STANLEY,  HIRAM  M. 

274.  PSYCHOLOGY  FOR  BEGINNERS.  An  Outline  Sketch.  Hiram 
M.  Stanley.     Boards,  40c  net.     (2s.) 

ST.  ANSELM. 

324.  ST.  ANSELM:  PROSLOGIUM;   MONOLOGIUM:  AN  APPEN- 

DIX   IN   BEHALF   OF   THE   FOOL,   by   Gaunilon;   and   CUR 
DEUS  HOMO.    Transl.  by  S.  N.  Deane.    Cloth,  $1.00  net. 

STARR.  FREDERICK. 

327.  READINGS  FROM  MODERN  MEXICAN  AUTHORS.  Fred- 
erick Starr.     $1.25   net.      (5s.   6d.   net.) 

325.  THE  AINU  GROUP  AT  THE   SAINT  LOUIS  EXPOSITION. 

Frederick  Starr.     Illustrated.     Boards,   75c  net.      (3s.   6d.   net.) 

STRODE.  MURIEL. 

333.  MY  LITTLE  BOOK  OF  PRAYER.  Muriel  Strode.  Boards,  50c 
net.      (2s.   6d.   net.) 

333a.  THE  SAME.     Cloth,  $1.00  net.     (4s.  6d.  net.) 

SUZUKI,  TEITARO. 

2S3.  ACVAGHOSHA'S  DISCOURSE  ON  THE  AWAKENING  OF 
FAITH  IN  THE  MAHAYANA.  Translated  by  Teitaro  Su- 
zuki.    Cloth,  $1.25  net.      (5s.  net.) 

TOLSTOY,  COUNT  LEO. 

348.  CHRISTIANITY  AND  PATRIOTISM  with  Pertinent  Extracts 
from  other  Essays.  Count  Leo  Tolstoy.  Trans,  by  Paul  Borger 
and  others.     Paper,  35c  net,  mailed  40c. 

TOPINARD,  PAUL. 

269.  SCIENCE  AND  FAITH,  OR  MAN  AS  AN  ANIMAL,  AND 
MAN  AS  A  MEMBER  OF  SOCIETY,  with  a  DISCUSSION 
OF  ANIMAL  SOCIETIES,  by  Paul  Topinard.  Transl.  by  T. 
J.  McCormack.    $1.50  net.      (6s.  6d.  net.) 

TRUMBULL,  M.  M. 

243.  WHEELBARROW,  Articles  and  Discussions  on  the  Laror 
Question,  including  the  Controversy  with  Mr.  Lyman  J.  Gage 
on  the  Ethics  of  the  Board  of  Trade;  and  also  the  Controversy 
with  Hugh  O.  Pentecost  and  Others,  on  the  Single  Tax  Ques- 
tion.    Cloth,   $1.00.      (5s.) 

245.  THE  FREE  TRADE  STRUGGLE  IN  ENGLAND.  M.  M.  Trum- 
bull.    Cloth,   75c.      (3s.   6d.) 

WAGNER,  RICHARD. 

249.  A  PILGRIMAGE  TO  BEETHOVEN.  A  Novel  by  Richard  Wag- 
ner.    Transl.  by  O.   W.   Weyer.     Boards,   50c  net.     (2s.  6d.) 

WEISMANN,  AUGUST. 

299.  ON  GERMINAL  SELECTION,  as  a  Source  of  definite  Variation. 
August  Weismann.  Transl.  by  T.  J.  McCormack.  Cloth,  60c 
net.     (3s.   net.) 


S^rSend  for  Complete  Illustrated  Catalogue. !£& 


10  TITLE    LIST 


WITHERS,  JOHN  WILLIAM. 

335.  EUCLID'S  PARALLEL  POSTULATE:  Its  Nature,  Validity 
and  Place  in  Geometrical  Systems.  /.  IV.  Withers,  Ph.  D., 
Cloth,   $1.25  net.      (4s.   6d.  net.) 

YAMADA,  KEICHYU. 

265.  SCENES  FROM  THE  LIFE  OF  BUDDHA.  Reproduced  from 
paintings  by  Prof.  Keichyu  Yamada.     $2.50  net.      (15s.) 

316.     THE  TEMPLES   OF  THE   ORIENT  AND  THEIR   MESSAGE 
IN  THE  LIGHT  OF  HOLY  SCRIPTURE,  Dante's  Vision,  and 
Bunyan's  Allegory.     By  the  author  of  "Clear  Round!"   "Things 
Touching  the  King,"  etc.     $4.00. 


PORTRAITS  AND  ILLUSTRATIONS 

332a.  FRAMING  PORTRAIT  OF  HUGO  DE  VRIES.  Platino  finish. 
10X12",   unmounted.      Postpaid,   $1.00.      (4s.   6d.  net.) 

336.  PORTFOLIO  OF  BUDDHIST  ART.  A  collection  of  illustra- 
tions of  Buddhism,  Historical  and  Modern  in  portfolio.  50c  net. 
(2s.    6d.   net.) 

202.  PHILOSOPHICAL  AND  PSYCHOLOGICAL  PORTRAIT  SE- 
RIES.   68  portraits  on  plate  paper,  $7.50   (35s.)   per  set. 

202a.  PHILOSOPHICAL  PORTRAIT  SERIES.  43  portraits  on  plate 
paper,  $6.25  (30s.)  Single  portraits,  on  plate  paper,  25c.  (is. 
6d.) 

202b.  PSYCHOLOGICAL  PORTRAIT  SERIES.  25  portraits  on  Japa- 
nese paper,  $5.00  (24s.)  per  set;  plate  paper,  $3.75  (18s.)  per 
set.  Single  portraits,  Japanese  paper,  50c  (2s.  6d.);  single 
portraits,   on  plate  paper,   25c    (is.   6d.) 

SMITH,  PROF.  DAVID  EUGENE. 

202c.  PORTRAITS  OF  MATHEMATICIANS.  Edited  by  Prof.  D.  E. 
Smith.  12  portraits  on  Imp.  Jap.  Vellum,  $5.00;  12  portraits 
on  Am.  plate  paper,   $3.00. 


THE  RELIGION  OF  SCIENCE  LIBRARY 

1.  THE  RELIGION  OF   SCIENCE.     Paul  Carus.     25c,   mailed  30c. 

(is.  6d.) 

2.  THREE    INTRODUCTORY    LECTURES    ON    THE    SCIENCK 

OF  THOUGHT.  F.  Max  Miiller.  With  a  coi  respondcnce  on 
"Thought  Without  Words"  between  F.  Max  Miiller  and  Francis 
Galton,  the  Duke  of  Argyll,  George  J.  Romanes  and  others. 
25c,  mailed  29c.      (is.   6d.) 

3.  THREE    LECTURES    ON    THE    SCIENCE    OF    LANGUAGE. 

With  My  Predecessors.  F.  Max  Miiller.  25c,  mailed  29c. 
(is.   6d.) 

4.  THE   DISEASES   OF    PERSONALITY.     Prof.   Ph.   Ribot.     25c 

mailed   29c.      (is.    6d.) 


ggrScnd  for  Complete  Illustrated   CatahgUt 


OPEN     COURT     PUBLICATIONS  11 


5.  THE  PSYCHOLOGY  OF  ATTENTION.     Prof.  Th.  Ribot.     25c, 

mailed  29c.     (is.  6d.) 

6.  THE  PSYCHIC  LIFE   OF  MICRO-ORGANISMS.     A   Study  in 

Experimental  Psychology.  Alfred  Binet.  25c,  mailed  29c.  (is. 
6d.) 

7.  THE  NATURE  OF  THE  STATE.     Paul  Cams.     15c,  mailed  18c. 

(9d.) 

8.  ON    DOUBLE    CONSCIOUSNESS.      Experimental    Psychological 

Studies.     Alfred  Binet.      15c,  mailed   18c.      (gd.) 

9.  FUNDAMENTAL   PROBLEMS.      The   Method  of  Philosophy    as 

a  Systematic  Arrangement  of  Knowledge.  Paul  Carus.  50c, 
mailed  60c.      (2s.  6d.) 

10.  DISEASES  OF  THE  WILL.     Prof.  Th.  Ribot.     Transl.  by  Mer- 

win-Marie  Snell.     25c,  mailed  29c.      (is.  6d.) 

11.  ON  THE  ORIGIN  OF  LANGUAGE  and  the  Logos  Theory.     L. 

Noire.      15c,  mailed  18c.      (is.  6d.) 

12.  THE  FREE  TRADE  STRUGGLE  IN  ENGLAND.     M.M.  Trum- 

bull.    25c,   mailed  31c.      (is.   6d.) 

13.  WHEELBARROW.  ARTICLES  AND  DISCUSSIONS  ON  THE 

LABOR  QUESTION,  including  the  Controversy  with  Mr.  Ly- 
man J.  Gage  on  the  Ethics  of  the  Board  of  Trade;  and  also 
the  Controversy  with  Mr.  Hugh  O.  Pentecost,  and  others,  on 
the  Single  Tax  Question.     35c,  mailed  43c.      (2s.) 

14.  THE  GOSPEL  OF  BUDDHA,  According  to  Old  Records  told  by 

Paul  Cants.     35c,  mailed  42c.      (2s.) 

15.  PRIMER    OF    PHILOSOPHY.      Paul    Carus.      25c,    mailed    32c. 

(is.   6d.) 

16.  ON    MEMORY    AND    THE    SPECIFIC    ENERGIES    OF    THE 

NERVOUS  SYSTEM.    Prof.  E.  Hering.    15c,  mailed  18c.   (9d.) 

17.  THE  REDEMPTION  OF  THE  BRAHMAN.     A  Novel.    Richard 

Garbe.      25c,   mailed  28c.      (is.   6d.) 

18.  AN    EXAMINATION    OF    WEISMANNISM.      G.    J.    Romanes. 

35c,   mailed  41c.      (2s.) 

19.  ON  GERMINAL  SELECTION  AS  A  SOURCE  OF  DEFINITE 

VARIATION.  August  IVeismann.  Transl.  by  T.  J.  McCor- 
mack.     25c,  mailed  28c.      (is.   6d.) 

20.  LOVERS    THREE   THOUSAND   YEARS   AGO    as   Indicated   by 

The  Song  of  Solomon.  Rev.  T.  A.  Goodwin.  15c,  mailed  18c. 
(9d.) 

21.  POPULAR    SCIENTIFIC   LECTURES.      Professor   Ernst   Mach. 

Transl.   by  T.  J.  McCormack.      50c,   mailed  60c.      (2s.   6d.) 

22.  ANCIENT  INDIA,  ITS  LANGUAGE  AND  RELIGIONS.    Prof. 

H.   Oldenberg.     25c,  mailed  28c.      (is.   6d.) 

23.  THE    PROPHETS    OF    ISRAEL.      Popular    Sketches    from    Old 

Testament  History.  Prof.  C.  H.  Cornill.  Transl.  by  S.  F. 
Corkran.     25c,  mailed  30c.      (is.  6d.) 


j&rSend  for  Complete  Illustrated   Catalogue.**^ 


12  TITLE     LIST 


24.  HOMILIES  OF  SCIENCE.     Paul  Cams.     35c,  mailed  43c.     (25.) 

25.  THOUGHTS  OX  RELIGION.     The  late  G.  J.  Romanes.     Edited 

by  Charles  Gore.     50c,  mailed  55c.     (2s.  6d.) 

26.  THE   PHILOSOPHY   OF   ANCIENT   INDIA.     Prof.   R.   Garbe. 

25c,  mailed  28c.      (is.  6d.) 

27.  MARTIN    LUTHER.      Gustav    Freytag.      Transl.    by    H.    E.    O. 

Heincmann.     25c,   mailed  30c.      (is.   6d.) 

28.  ENGLISH   SECULARISM.     A  Confession  of  Belief.     George  J. 

Holyoake.     25c,  mailed  30c.      (is.   6d.) 

29.  ON  ORTHOGENESIS  AND  THE  IMPORTANCE  OF  NATU- 

RAL SELECTION  IN  SPECIES-FORMATION.  Prof.  Th. 
Eimer.     Transl.  by  T,  J.  McCormack.     25c,  mailed  30.    (is.  6d.) 

30.  CHINESE    PHILOSOPHY.      An    Exposition    of   the    Main    Char- 

acteristic Features  of  Chinese  Thought.  Dr.  Paul  Cams.  25c, 
mailed  30c.      (is.   6d.) 

31.  THE   LOST   MANUSCRIPT.      A   Novel.      Gustav  Freytag.      One 

volume.     60c,  mailed  80c.      (3s.) 

32.  A    MECHANICO-PHYSIOLOGICAL    THEORY    OF    ORGANIC 

EVOLUTION.     Carl  ion  Ntigcli.     15c,  mailed  18c.      (od.) 

33.  CHINESE    FICTION.      Rev.    G.    T.    Candlin.      Illustrated.      15c 

mailed   18c.      (od.) 

34.  MATHEMATICAL   ESSAYS    AND    RECREATIONS.     Prof.   H. 

Schubert.    Tr.   by   T.  J.  McCormack.     25c,  mailed   30c.     (is.  6d.) 

35.  THE    ETHICAL    PROBLEM.      Three    Lectures    on    Ethics    as    a 

Science.     Paul  Cams.      50c,   mailed  60c.      (2s.   6d.) 

36.  BUDDHISM   AND    ITS    CHRISTIAN    CRITICS.     Paul    Cams. 

50c,  mailed  58c.      (2s.   6d.) 

37.  PSYCHOLOGY  FOR  BEGINNERS.    An  Outline  Sketch.    Hiram 

M.  Stanley.     20c,  mailed  23c.      (is.) 

38.  DISCOURSE   ON   THE   METHOD   OF   RIGHTLY   CONDUCT- 

ING THE  REASON,  AND  SEEKING  TRUTH  IN  THE 
SCIENCES.  Rene  Descartes.  Transl.  by  Prof.  John  Veitch. 
25c,  mailed  29c.      (is.  6d.) 

39.  THE  DAWN  OF  A  NEW  RELIGIOUS  ERA  and  other  Essays. 

Paul   Cams.      15c,   mailed   18c.      (9d.) 

40.  KANT   AND    SPENCER,    a    Study    of   the    Fallacies    of    Agnosti- 

cism.    Paul  Cams.     20c,   mailed  25c.      (is.) 

41.  THE   SOUL  OF  MAN,   an  Investigation  of  the   Facts  of  Physio 

logical  and  Experimental  Psychology.  Paul  Cams.  75c,  mailea 
85c.      (3s.  6d.) 

42.  WORLD'S    CONGRESS    ADDRESSES,    Delivered   by    the    Presi- 

dent, the  Hon.  C.  C.  Bonney.      15c,  mailed  20c.      (9J) 

43.  THE  GOSPEL  ACCORDING  TO  DARWIN.    Woods  Hutchinson. 

50c,  mailed  57c.     (2s.  6d.) 

44.  WHENCE    AND    WHITHER.      The    Nature    of    the    Soul,    Its 

Origin   and   Destiny.     Paul   Cams.     25c,   mailed   32c.      (is.  6d.) 


SStSend  for  Complete  Illustrated   Catalogu 


OPEN     COURT     PUBLICATIONS 


13 


45.  AN   ENQUIRY   CONCERNING   HUMAN   UNDERSTANDING. 

David  Hume.     25c,   mailed  31c.      (is.   6d.) 

46.  AN   ENQUIRY   CONCERNING  THE   PRINCIPLES   OF   MOR 

ALS.     David  Hume.     25c,  mailed  31c.      (is.  6d.) 

47.  THE  PSYCHOLOGY  OF  REASONING,   Based  on  Experimental 

Researches  in  Hypnotism.  Alfred  Binet.  Transl.  by  Adam 
Gowans  Whyte.     25c,  mailed  31c.      (is.  6d.) 

48.  A  TREATISE  CONCERNING  THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  HUMAN 

KNOWLEDGE.     George  Berkeley.     25c,  mailed  31c.     (is.   6d.) 

49.  THREE  DIALOGUES  BETWEEN  HYLAS  AND  PHILONOUS. 

George  Berkeley.     25c,  mailed  30c.      (is.   6d.) 

50.  PUBLIC  WORSHIP,   A   STUDY  IN  THE  PSYCHOLOGY  OF 

RELIGION.     John  P.  Hylan.     25c,  mailed  29c.     (is.  6d.) 

51.  THE  MEDITATIONS  AND  SELECTIONS  FROM  THE  PRIN- 

CIPLES of  Rene  Descartes.  Transl.  by  Prof.  John  Veitch. 
35c,  mailed  42c.      (2s.) 

52.  LEIBNIZ:  DISCOURSE  ON  METAPHYSICS,   CORRESPOND- 

ENCE WITH  ARNAULD  and  MONADOLOGY,  with  an  In- 
troduction by  Paul  Janet.  Transl.  by  Dr.  G.  R.  Montgomery. 
50c,  mailed  58c.      (2s.   6d.) 

53.  KANT'S    PROLEGOMENA  to   any   Future   Metaphysics.      Edited 

by  Dr.  Paul  Cams.     50c,  mailed  59c.      (2s.  6d.) 

54  ST.  ANSELM:  PROSLOGIUM;  MONOLOGIUM;  AN  APPEN- 
DIX ON  BEHALF  OF  THE  FOOL,  by  Gaunilon;  and  CUR 
DEUS   HOMO.     Tr.   by  S.N.Deane.     50c,  mailed  60c.    (2s.  6d.) 

55.  THE  CANON  OF  REASON  AND  VIRTUE  (Lao-Tze's  Tao  Teh 

King).  Translated  from  the  Chinese  by  Paul  Carus.  25c 
mailed  28c.      (is.  6d.) 

56.  ANTS    AND    SOME    OTHER    INSECTS,    an    Inquiry    into    the 

Psychic  Powers  of  these  Animals,  with  an  Appendix  on  the 
Peculiarities  of  Their  Olfactory  Sense.  Dr.  August  Forel. 
Transl.  by  Prof.   W.  M.   Wheeler.     50c,  mailed  53c.      (2s.   6d.) 

57.  THE   METAPHYSICAL    SYSTEM    OF   HOBBES,    as   contained 

in  twelve  chapters  from  his  "Elements  of  Philosophy  Concern- 
ing Body,"  and  in  briefer  Extracts  from  his  "Human  Nature'' 
and  "Leviathan,"  selected  by  Mary  IVhiton  Calkins.  40c, 
mailed  47c.      (2s.) 

58.  LOCKE'S   ESSAYS   CONCERNING  HUMAN   UNDERSTAND- 

ING. Books  II  and  IV  (with  omissions).  Selected  by  Mary 
IVhiton  Calkins.     50c,  mailed  60c.     (2s.  6d.) 

59-  THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DESCARTES'  PHILOSOPHY.  Bene- 
dictus  de  Spinoza.  Introduction  by  Halbert  Hains  Britan,  Ph. 
D.  Paper,  35c  net,  mailed  42c. 


THE  OPEN  COURT  PUBLISHING  CO. 

1322  Wabash  Avenue,  Chicago 

London  :  Kegan  Paul,  Trench,  Trubner  &  Co.,  Ltd. 


IgWSend  for  Complete  Illustrated  Catalogue.*^, 


THE  OPEN  COURT 


sx     ra      L«» 


An  Illustrated  Monthly  Magazine 

Devoted  to  the  Science  of  Religion,  The 
Religion  of  Science  and  the  Extension 
of  The  Religious  Parliament  Idea 


THE  OPEN    COURT  is  a  popular 
magazine  discussing  the  deepest 
questions   of   life.      It   offers   the 
maturest   thought    in    the    domains   of 
Religion,  Philosophy,  Psychology,  Evo- 
lution and  kindred  subjects. 

THE  OPEN  COURT  contains  articles 
on  the  recent  discoveries  of  Babylonian 
and  Egyptian  excavations,  an  Old 
Testament  Research,  the  Religion  of 
the  American  Indians,  Chinese  culture, 
Brahmanism,  Buddhism,  Mithraism — 
in  short  anything  that  will  throw  light 
on  the  development  of  religion  and 
especially  on  Christianity. 

THE  OPEN  COURT  investigates  the 
problems  of  God  and  Soul,  of  life  and 
death  and  immortality,  of  conscience, 
duty,  and  the  nature  of  morals,  the 
ethics  of  political  and  social  life  — 
briefly  all  that  will  explain  the  bottom 
facts  of  Religion  and  their  practical 
significance.  The  illustrations  though 
artistic  are  instructive  and  frequently 
reproduce  rare  historical  pictures. 


50  Cents 
Per   Copy 


THE  MQNIST 


$2.00 
Per    Year 


A      Quarterly      Magazine 

Devoted  to  the  Philosophy  of  Science. 
Each  copy  contains  160  pages;  original 
articles,  correspondence  from  foreign 
countries,  discussions,  and  book  reviews 


The  Monist  Advocates  the 
Philosophy  of   Science 

Which  is  an  application  of  the  scientific  method  to 
philosophy.  The  old  philosophical  systems  were 
mere  air-castles  (constructions  of  abstract  theories), 
built  in  the  realm  of  pure  tbought.  The  Philosophy 
of  Science  is  a  eystematization  of  positive  facts;  it 
takes  experience  as  its  foundation,  and  uses  the 
systematized  formal  relations  of  experience  (mathe- 
matics, logic,  etc.)  as  its  method.  It  is  opposed  on 
the  one  hand  to  the  dogmatism  of  groundless  a  priori 
assumptions,  and  on  the  other  hand,  to  the  scepticism 
of  negation  wbich  finds  expression  in  the  agnostic 
tendencies  of  to-dav. 


Monism  Means  a  Unitary 
World  -  Conception 

There  may  be  different  aspects  and  even  contrasts, 
diverse  views  and  opposite  standpoints,  but  there  can 
never  be  contradiction  in  truth.  Monism  is  not  a 
one-substance  theory,  be  it  materialistic  or  spiritual- 
istic or  agnostic;  it  means  simply  and  solely  con- 
sistency. All  truths  form  one  consistent  system,  and 
any  dualism  of  irreconcilable  statements  indicates 
that  there  is  a  problem  to  be  solved;  there  must  be 
fault  somewhere  either  in  our  reasoning  or  in  our 
knowledge  of  facts.  Science  always  implies  Monism, 
i.  e.,  a  unitary  world-conception. 

Illustrated  Catalogue  and  Sample  Copies  Free. 

The  Open  Court  Publishing  Co. 

1322-1328      Wabash      Avenue,       Chicago,      Illinois 


v 


3  ~s     ^ 


<t> 


ft  v. 


>s 


6  >  ^ 


*<\ 


k"     \ 


♦/•% 


.^. 


0 


A 


a  i  \ 


'A  *  -       a  <P  .V, 


^     % 


<>. 


V* 


•O  '  '  I  s  s  \'X  °/  0   *    .V. 


^ 


rp  a      flV  .*r  N  ">>  »       or 


<3 


s 


x 

V 


vw 


l"0 


•\ 


Nr-X 

b  o 


■ 


j* 


%  A 


0  0 


v*- 


!*     A.       *' 


A*'       .  *»*  v  *.  A 


1    B 


V- 


>'-  -%  v* 


^  V  A  V 

*<        <P  '  A  -  A>       -  t- 


^  ,A 


\ 


Oo 


■V 


-•*.       '   -  *  s        .A        _  v  i 


A 


A 


>      0 


»,    / 


3>   ?, 


\^'\',1'*,A 


A 


•^        y  o  ,    v^         •  O 


$"%>  \ 


& 


I    8 


Kf 


^  -<3 


^    .<°       , 


«     'lo 


r0V    sc 


o  o 


4  #v 


^-   ^ 


A- 

8    1 


\ 


0°* 


"ooX  1.        ^    V 

A'      -  A     C-r->  X  ,AX"       x^> 

<A-       AX'  ^     -el* 


'<■•  A^       n  o 

o5  ^ 


LIBRARY