Skip to main content

Full text of "Transactions"

See other formats


Oo 
E 
= 
fe) 
Ss 
° 
= 
ve 
(2) 


UNIVERSITY 


I 


3 1761 014189 


Unie ge 
Tozaan 
Lip sn 


Hil} 


DAA Ty eee Ope 


\=\ 


Digitized by the Internet Archive 
in 2009 with funding from 
University of Toronto 


: http://www.archive.org/details/transactions23conn 


Transactions 


of the 


Connecticut Academy of 
Arts and Sciences 


Volume XXIII 


New Haven, Connecticut 


1912, 1920 


; 
a i 
“ 
os 
: ¢ 
a) 
‘ = 
i 
» 
i 
ee Ay 
ia 
fy 


ie * ‘4 ¥ 
Be 


© \ Sleek Bae 
eh Xt eae 
>. @ Lae 
| s 
.~ 
¥ 
4 


ce ioe Wi 
5 THIS 


SA ATNS 


—- 


; o> 


? 


OFFICERS FOR 1919-20 


President 
Hon. SIMEON E. BALDWIN 


Vice-Presidents 
Pror. ALEXANDER W. EVANS 


Pror. CHARLES C. TORREY 


Pror. CLIVE DAY 


Secretary 
Mr. GEORGE F. EATON 


Treasurer 


Mr. GEORGE PARMLY DAY 


Librarian 


Mr. ANDREW KEOGH 


Committee on Publication 
Hon. S. E. BALDWIN, Chairman Pror. A. W. EVANS 


Pror. A. S. COOK Pror. CLIVE DAY 
Pror. E. S. DANA Prov. CHARLES C. TORREY 
Pror. A. M. HARMON Mr. ANDREW KEOGH 


Mr. GEORGE F. EATON 


ART. 


ART. 


ART. 


Art. 


ART. 


Art. 


Arr. 


III. 


EY’: 


VII. 


CONTENTS 


CHAUCERIAN Paprers—I By Albert S. Cook 


SpPENSER’S ENcLisH RIvERS By Charles G. Osgood 


New Species oF DevoNIAN Fossits FRoM WESTERN 
TENNESSEE : : : i By Carl O. Dunbar 


Earty History oF AMERICAN AuUCTIONS—A CHAPTER 
IN CoMMERCIAL HisToRY By R. B. Westerfield 


Russta’s CONTRIBUTION TO SCIENCE 
By Alexander Petrunkevitch 


THe RHETORICA OF PHILODEMUS By H. B. Hubbell 


THE PRINCIPLE OF GENERAL RELATIVITY AND EINsTEIN’s 


THEORY OF GRAVITATION . By Leigh Page 


\N 


1-63 


65-108 


109-158 


159-210 


211-241 


243-382 


383-416 


TRANSACTIONS OF 
muir CONNECTICUT ACADEMY 
OF ARTS AND SCIENCES 


VOLUME 23] NOVEMBER 1919 [PAGES 1-63 


Chaucerian Papers-I 


BY 


ALBERT STANBURROUGH COOK 


PROFESSOR OF THE ENGLISH LANGUAGE AND LITERATURE 
IN YALE UNIVERSITY 


NEW HAVEN, CONNECTICUT 
PUBLISHED BY THE 
CONNECTICUT ACADEMY OF ARTS AND SCIENCES 
AND TO BE OBTAINED ALSO FROM THE 
YALE UNIVERSITY PRESS 


a: | 
ary. vie 
1.9) 
ee OH ae | 
2°) FVPAY 2, . ‘ eee ya: st 
ry S | 
| ry be 
oo 


é 


TABLE OF CONTENTS 


OF CDN AT | 1 ie c= a oe 5 
The ‘Sweet Breath’ of Zephyr rari. | aa: 22 
PNET OMS 5 pon RE aE AS a ee a 25 
RPE ACE GO Meee re tia ese ccoats tc is eet es yes 29 
2 ST Ad WG] 52270 (0 as) le 30 
150 B12 Ny Rag Za BG] CAS SE’ 5° a ore a 31 
Meaweers = Owerd Of WINGED Jost es oe ec te se 32 


The Complaint of Chaucer to his Empty Purse .... 33 


SUR Ps (es al Oli here a) en ek 38 
Chaucer’s Mission to Florence in 1372 ........... 39 
ESB CINC. SMV BECEM De hs sieve eons de be ward ews we 44 


aon de Rue, and Chaucer). 35.05.52. .0i. ees 55 


at GSA: 


Py PROLOGUE 1-11 


In the Danaides’ of Aeschylus (525-456 B. c.), Aphrodite is 
represented as saying: 


The pure heaven longs to penetrate the soil, while at the same time 
desire lays hold upon the earth to enjoy these nuptials. Accordingly 
the rain, descending from the bridegroom heaven, impregnates the 
earth, which then brings forth grain for the use of mortals, and food 
for their flocks. The fruits of the trees, too, arrive at their perfec- 
tion by means of this moist wedlock.2 And all these things are 
brought to pass with my aid. 


Not unlike this is the fragment* (890 Nauck) of Euripides 
(480-406 B. c.), associated with it by Atheneus (600 B): 


The earth longs for rain when the dry soil, barren by reason of 
drought, must needs have moisture. The holy heaven, in turn, when 
laden with showers, longs, at the impulse of Aphrodite, to descend 
into the earth, And when these two have been made one by love, 
they bring forth and nourish for us everything by which men 
everywhere live and thrive. 


As Munro, the editor of Lucretius, has said*: 


From the Vedas to the Pervigilium Veneris, poets and philosophers 
love to celebrate this union of Ether and Earth, Ether as the father 
descending in showers into the lap of Mother Earth. The notion 


*Frag. 44 Sidgwick (otherwise 41 or 43): 
épa bev ayvos ovpavos TpOcat x Obra, 
pws 5é yatay NauBdver yduou Tuxety: 
duBpos 5° am’ evdvatHpos ovpavod meray 
éxvge yatav:  6é TlkTeTau Bporots 
unrtov te Bookas kal Blov Anurjrpiov ° 
dévdpwv drudpa 6’ éx vorivovTos ydvous 
Tédelds EoTL* TOHVS’ eyw mwapalrwos. 

* Reading the traditional yduou for the emendation, ydvous. 

5 épa pév duBpov yai’, drav Enpdv wébov 

dkaptov a’yuw vorldos évdeds @x7 * 
€pa 5’ 6 ceuvods odpavds mnpovuevos 
duBpou mecety eis yatav ’Adpodirns iro: 
bray d€ cuupmxOATov és TavTOv dvo, 
pvovow jnuty ravra Kal Tpépovo’ dua, 
dv’ Gv Bpdreov (7H Te kal OddrNE yévos. 

*Note on I. 250. 


6 Prologue I-II 


naturally had birth in warm climates, such as India, where the exces- 
sive heat, at stated periods, seemed to bring the ether down in 
abundant rains, which at once quickened all thirigs; hence the Agni 
of the Rig-Veda codperating with the mighty parents, Heaven and 
Earth, to shed abundant showers. 


The thought of Aeschylus and Euripides has been thus 
expressed (1. 250-3) by Lucretius (96?-55 B. c.): 


Postremo pereunt imbres, ubi eos pater ether 
In gremium matris terrai precipitavit; 

At nitide surgunt fruges ramique virescunt 

Arboribus, crescunt ipse fetuque gravantur.® 


And again in a passage (2. 992-4) imitated from Euripides®: 


Omnibus ille idem pater est, unde alma liquentis 
Umoris guttas mater cum terra recepit, 
Feta parit nitidas fruges arbustaque leta.’ 


Lucretius (with perhaps his originals) is followed and ampli- 
fied by Virgil (Georgics 2. 323-333): 


Ver adeo frondi nemorum, ver utile silvis, 
Vere tument terre, et genitalia semina poscunt. 
_Tum pater omnipotens fecundis imbribus Aether 
Conjugis in gremium late descendit, et omnis 
Magnus alit, magno commixtus corpore, fetus. 
Avia tum resonant avibus virgulta canoris, 
Et Venerem certis repetunt armenta diebus; 
Parturit almus ager, Zephyrique tepentibus auris 
Laxant arva sinus; superat tener omnibus umor; 
Inque novos soles audent se gramina [var. germina] tuto 
Credere.® 


* Munro renders: ‘Lastly rains die, when Father Ether has tumbled them 
into the lap of Mother Earth; but then goodly crops spring up, and boughs 
are green with leaves upon the trees, trees themselves grow, and are 
laden with fruit.’ 

*Frag. 836. This is also translated in prose by Vitruvius, at the 
beginning of his Eighth Book. 

7*All have that same Father, by whom Mother Earth, the giver of 
increase, when she has taken in from him liquid drops of moisture, con- 
ceives and bears goodly crops and joyous trees.’ 

®* Thus rendered by Lonsdale and Lee: ‘The spring it is that ministers to 
the leafage of the groves, and to the forests themselves as well; in spring 
the land heaves with fruitfulness, and requires the procreative seed. The 
Heaven, the Almighty Father, comes down in fertilizing showers into the 


Prologue I-11 7 


Columella (fl. ca. 50 A. D.) has the following lines? (10 
204-210) : 
Maximus ipse deum posito jam fulmine fallax 
Acrisioneos veteres imitatur amores, 
Inque sinus matris violento defluit imbre ; 
Nec genitrix nati nunc aspernatur amorem, 
Sed patitur nexus flammata cupidine tellus. 
Hinc maria, hinc montes, hinc totus denique mundus 
Ver agit. 


Of about Columella’s period was probably Petronius, who 
embodiés the same conception (Sat. 127) in a somewhat vaguer 
form than his predecessors. According to him, roses, violets, 
and lilies spring up as the result of the union. 

The same note is heard as late as the Pervigilium Veneris 
(ca. 350 A. D?): 

Cras erit cum primus ether copulavit nuptias ; 
Tunc cruore de superno spumeo et ponti globo, 


lap of his joyous bride, and in his might, mingling with her mighty frame, 
nourishes every product. Then ring the thickets wild with tuneful birds, 
and on their days the herds devote themselves to love; the bounteous 
field gives birth to life, and, beneath the west-wind’s breezes warm, the 
meadows unloose their folds, and all with delicate moisture overflow, and 
the herbage safely dares to trust itself to meet the new-born suns.’ 

And thus by Dryden: 


The spring adorns the woods, renews the leaves; 
The womb of earth the genial seed receives; 
For then almighty Jove descends, and pours 
Into his buxom bride his fruitful showers; 

And, mixing his large limbs with hers, he feeds 
Her births with kindly juice, and fosters teeming seeds. 
The joyous birds frequent the lonely grove, 
And beasts, by nature stung, renew their love. 
Then fields the blades of buried corn disclose, 
And, while the balmy western spirit blows, 
Earth to the breath her bosom dares expose. 
With kindly moisture then the plants abound; 
The grass securely springs above the ground. 
The tender twig shoots upward to the skies, 
And on the faith of the new sun relies. 


®Columella was at least known to Boccaccio (Hortis, Studj, p. 436), 
though probably not to Petrarch (Nolhac, Pétrarque et !Humanisme, 2d 
ed., 2. 100, note 3). 


8 Prologue I-11 


Cerulas inter catervas, inter et bipedes equos, 
Fecit undantem Dionem de maritis imbribus: 

Ut pater totum crearet veris annum nubibus, 

In sinum maritus imber fluxit almze conjugis,” 
Unde fetus perque pontum perque celum pergeret, 
Perque terras mixtus omnes alere magno corpore.” 


We have seen above that Aphrodite (Venus) proclaims her 
active complicity in the process and the result outlined by 
Aeschylus, and a similar thought is expressed by the fourth line 
quoted from the Pervigiliwm Veneris. Nor are these the only 
passages of a similar purport. Hesiod, describing the birth of 
Aphrodite, refers to her influence on vegetation (Theog. 194 ff.) : 
‘Then forth stepped an awful, beauteous goddess, and beneath 
her delicate feet the verdure throve around; her gods and men 
name Aphrodite, the foam-sprung goddess.’ Aud thus Lucretius 
(1. 7-8): om 

Tibi suavis dedala tellus 
_ Summittit flores.” 


Elsewhere Lucretius says (5. 737-9): 


It ver et Venus, et Veneris preenuntius ante 
Pennatus graditur, Zephyri vestigia propter 
Flora.* 


Ovid is no less explicit in his association of the goddess and the 
season (Fasti 4. 125, 129): 


*Arnobius (ca. 303) accuses (Bk. 5, chaps. 31, 34, 35, 37, 40, 43) the 
heathen writers whom he is attacking of relating the story about Jupiter 
and Ceres (cf. Hesiod, Theog. 912), Ceres (Demeter) being of course the 
Earth under another personification. 

“Thus rendered by Mackail: ‘To-morrow will be the day when the 
primal Ether joined wedlock; then from the moisture overhead and the 
orbed sea-foam, amid green multitudes and finned horses, sprang Dione 
[Aphrodite], wave-born under nuptial showers. é 

‘To quicken the whole year from the clouds of spring, the bridegroom- 
shower has flowed into the lap of his fair bride, that so, mingling with 
the vast frame, he might pass through sea and through sky and through 
all the lands, to nourish their offspring.’ 

“For thee earth, manifold in works, puts forth sweet-smelling flowers.’ 

*‘Spring and Venus go their way, and the winged harbinger of Venus 
steps on before; and close on Zephyr’s footprints Mother Flora.’ Cf. 
Botticelli’s Primavera. 


wT a ee eres Soe 


a, ee Le Pe = 


——— a 


+ 
. 
7 

i 


Prologue I-II 9 


Nec Veneri tempus quam ver erat aptius nullum. 
Et formosa Venus formoso tempore digna est.” 


Of the spring months, it was April that was especially asso- 


ciated with Aphrodite; in fact, one of the two ancient etymologies 


for ‘April’ related it to the name of the goddess (Macrobius, 
Sat.® 1. 12. 8): ‘Secundum mensem nominavit Aprilem, ut 
quidam putant cum adspiratione quasi Aphrilem, a spuma quam 
Greci a¢pov vocant, unde orta Venus creditur.’*® 

Moreover, Horace explicitly calls (Od. 4. 11. 15) April ‘the 
month of sea-born Venus.’*” 

In the light of the preceding, it may be worth while to regard 
attentively the opening lines of Chaucer’s Prologue: 


Whan that Aprille with his shoures sote 
The droghte of Marche hath perced to the rote, 
And bathed every veyne in swich licour 
Of which vertu engendred is the flour; 
Whan Zephirus eek with his swete breeth 
Inspired hath in every holt and heeth 
The tendre croppes, and the yonge sonne 
Hath in the Ram his halfe cours yronne, 
And smale fowles maken melodye, 

That slepen al the night with open ye, 
(So priketh hem nature in hir corages).® 


“*And no season was there more becoming for Venus than the 
spring. . . . And the lovely Venus is deserving of the lovely season.’ 

Cf. Horace, Od. 1. 4. 1ff.; Preller, Griech. Myth., 2d ed., pp. 270-1; 
Spenser, Amor. 70. 1. 

* Chaucer is not usually credited with knowing the Saturnalia, but it 
is certain that Petrarch was familiar with it (Nolhac, Pétrarque et 
PHumanisme, 2d ed., 1. 157), and there seems no reason why Chaucer 
may not have been. Cf. p. 12, note 24. 

* “He [Romulus] called the second month April, or, as some suppose, 
Aphril (with the aspirate), from foam, which the Greeks called aphros, 
and from which Venus is believed to have sprung.’ 

“Cf. Preller, as above; Pauly-Wissowa, Real-Encyclopadie 1. 2768-9; 
Shakespeare, Ant. and Cleop. 3. 2. 43. 

*As throwing light upon the detailed interpretation, I append the 
translation by Hertzberg (Chaucer’s Canterbury-Geschichten, p. 67): 

Wenn, von Aprillenregen mild durchdrungen, 

Der Staub des Marz recht griindlich ist bezwungen, 
Und so von Saften jede Ader schwillt, 

Dass aus dem Boden Blum’ an Blume quillt; 


10 Prologue I-11 


If this be compared with the extract from the Georgics, it will 
be seen that not only are individual Chaucerian words and 
phrases accounted for—shoures, Zephirus, tendre croppes 
(reading germina, in the sense of ‘sprigs, sprouts, buds’), yonge 
sonne, smale fowles—but that the general thought of the whole 
eleven lines, with the exception of 8, 10, and 11, is to be found 
in the Virgilian passage. 


Certain individual points remain to be considered. These 
will now be taken up in order. 

Aprille (1). The month, regarded as masculine, takes the 
place of Aether (Jupiter),?° which would have been less intel- 
ligible or appealing to Chaucer’s English readers. April, we 
have seen, suggests Venus; cf. the Venerem of Georg. 1. 329. 

shoures sote. This corresponds to Virgil’s fecundis imbribus 
(325). Showers and rain are assigned to April in T. and C. 
4. 751; A. and A. 309. One suspects sote of having been 
employed partly for the sake of the rhyme (rhymed in Squire’s 
Tale 389; L. G. W. 2612, with rote; cf. swote, Rom. Rose 1661; 
L. G. W. 1077; Miller's Tale 19; Parl. Fowls 274); on the 
other hand, see swote dewes, R. R. 60 (where the original has 
only rousée), and note the fact that sote (swote) is often 
employed in the middle of the line. It is several times used in 


Wenn Zephyr dann mit seinem siissen Hauch 

In Wald und Haide jeden zarten Strauch 
Durchwehet; wenn der Strahl der jungen Sonnen 
Zur Halfte schon dem Widder ist entronnen; 
Wenn lust’ge Melodie das Voglein macht, 

Das offnen Auges schlaft die ganze Nacht 

—So stachelt die Natur es in der Brust. 


* May is regarded as feminine in T. and C. 2. 50: 
In May, that moder is of monthes glade. 


On the other hand, it is masculine, like April, in Franklin’s Tale 179-180: 


Which May had peynted with his softe shoures 
This gardin ful of leves and of floures. 


* Perhaps Juppiter (Joves) most nearly illustrates the conception out- 
lined above, in such passages as T. and C. 3. 15 ff. (based upon the 
Filostrato of Boccaccio; see Oxford Chaucer 2. 474-5) and Monk’s 
Tale 762. 


Prologue I-11 11 


connection with grene, and to characterize grass. For softe 
shoures, see p. 10, note 19.** 

droghte (2). That this can hardly refer to a typical English 
March is indicated by the proverb, occurring in slightly different 
forms from 1530, that a bushel (peck) of March dust*® is worth 
a king’s ransom (see N. £. D., s. v. March, 1.b and 2.a), 
explained by Robert Boyle, in 1685 (Works, ed. 1772, 5. 51): 
‘So unfrequent is dry weather during that month in our climate.’ 
As early as the middle of the 11th century, the Old English 
Menologium characterizes March by frost and hail-storms. 
Droghte can hardly mean ‘dryness, lack of rain’ (N. E. D.), but 
rather ‘dry land’ (cf. Lat. arida, Gr. émpé, of Gen. 1.9; Matt. 
23. 15, etc.; Milton, P. R. 3. 274). Rain, under these circum- 
stances, naturally suggests a dry soil on which to descend; an 
example is Virgil, Ecl. 7. 57, 60: 


Aret ager. ; 
Juppiter et leto descendet plurimus imbri.” 


Moreover, the Euripidean fragment expressly mentions the 
‘dry soil, barren by reason of drought’; Chaucer, however, would 
of course have known nothing directly of this, though he may 
easily have been acquainted with the Eclogue, if he knew the 
Georgics. Drought, then, seems like a literary reminiscence of 
more tropic conditions, and not an attempt to render his English 
experience. There is, however, one other possibility. It is that 
droghte is here employed to denote a caked condition of the soil, 
due, not to heat, but to cold— 


*t Since writing this paper, I see that Lowes (Mod. Pil. 15. 707, April, 
1918) compares with Prol. 2-4 the following from Boccaccio, Filocolo 2. 238: 
‘Se quella terra che noi incalchiamo lungamente alle tue radici presti 
grazioso umore, per lo quale esse diligentemente nutrite le tue fronde 
nutrichino. 

*TIt is interesting, however, that Hertzberg renders droghte by Staub. 

* Translated by Lonsdale and Lee: ‘The field is scorched. 

Jove in a gladdening shower shall plenteously descend.’ 


And by Dryden: 


Parched are the plains, and frying is the field. 
And Jove descends in showers of kindly rain. 


12 Prologue I-11 


The parching air 
Burns frore, and cold performs the effect of fire.” 


perced to the rote (2). This may possibly have a physiological 
connotation, if one has regard to the fissures produced in the 
earth by drought. Cf. Virgil, Georg. 2. 353: ‘The sultry dog- 
star cleaves the fields that gape with drought’; 3. 432: ‘When 
the marsh is burnt up, and the ground gapes with the burning 
heat’; add Catullus 68. 62; Tibullus 1. 7. 21. See especially 
rima, Juvenal 3. 97, and cf. Macrobius 7. 16. 27. For a possible 
remote analogy, see Milton, Par. Lost 7. 453 ff., and cf. Georg. 
2. 330: ‘Parturit almus ager.’ Similar clefts are sometimes 
produced by frost, as well as by drought. Mote, in one of its 
senses, appears to signify the lowest or deepest point of a thing. 
Thus, herte rote (‘bottom, depths, ground of the heart’): Rom. 
Rose 1661-2: 


The savour of the roses swote 
Me smoot right to the herte rote; 


and again (Wife’s Prol. 471): 


It tikleth me aboute myn herte rote. 


The association of droghte and rote may perhaps have been 
facilitated by Isa. 53.2; Hos. 9. 16. 

veyne (3). This is difficult to visualize. Vein of what? Of 
the dry earth? Then it must mean minute cracks, well under the 
surface (cf. Petrarch’s “dentro, dove gia mai non s’aggiorna,’ 
quoted in Romanic Review 8. 225; my note there must be 
judged in the light of the present paper). Of the embryonic 
plant? Or of the matrix or mould for the plant, continuing the 


* Par. Lost 2. 594-5. Cf. Ecclesiasticus 43. 20-21: ‘When the cold north 
wind bloweth, and the water is congealed into ice, . . . it ies 
burneth the wilderness, and consumeth the grass as fire.’ Urere, adurere 
are thus used in Latin: for the latter, cf. Virgil, Georg. 1. 92; Ovid, 
Met. 14. 763-4; for the former, Lucan 4. 54-5: ‘The whole earth [in 
Spain] . . . was parched, hardened beneath the winter’s clear sky.’ 
All of these were accessible to Chaucer, as was possibly Macrobius, Sat. 
I. 12. 14, with its truer etymology of ‘April’ (see p. 9, note 15): 
‘Cum fere ante equinoctium vernum . . . terre . . . aut aqua 
aut pruina aut nivibus contegantur, eaque omnia verno, id est hoc mense, 
aperiantur, . . . ab his omnibus mensem Aprilem dici merito credendum 
est, quasi Aperilem.’ 


a ae 


I 


Prologue I-II 13 


physiological figure? Cf. Perv. Veneris (immediately following 
the last passage on p. 7, above) : 


Ipse venas atque mentem permeanti spiritu 
Intus occultis gubernat procreatrix viribus.” 


licour . . . . engendred (3-4). Again fecundis imbribus. 
Zephirus (5). The Latin poets are apt to think of Zephyr as 
thawing the frozen ground. Thus Virgil, Georg. 1. 43-4: 


Vere novo, gelidus canis cum montibus umor 
Liquitur, et Zephyro putris se gleba resolvit.” 


ferace, Od. 1: 4. 155: 


Solvitur acris hiems grata vice veris et Favoni. 
Jam Cytherea choros duxit.” 


And Statius, Theb. 4. 1-2: 


Tertius horrentem Zephyris laxaverat annum 
Pheebus. 


At the beginning of the Second Book of the Teseide, Boccaccio 
is evidently amplifying the sentence just quoted from Statius: 


Il Sole avie due volte dissolute 

Le nevi agli alti poggi, ed altrettante 
Zefiro aveva le foglie rendute 

E gli be’ fiori alle spogliate piante.* 


Boccaccio, in turn, is imitated by Chaucer (TJ. and C. 5. 8-11): 


The golden-tressed Phebus heighe onlofte 
Thryes hadde alle with his bemes shene 
The snowes molte, and Zephirus as ofte 
Ybrought ayein the tendre leves grene. 


Elsewhere (L. G. W. 171-4) Zephyr and Flora are associated 
as god and goddess: 


* Translated by Mackail: ‘Herself the creatress in hidden might sways 
flesh and spirit from within with her enkindling life.’ 

* Translated by Lonsdale and Lee: ‘In early spring, as soon as the dis- 
solving snow melts on the white mountains, and the earth trembles, 
unbound by zephyrs.’ 

7 ‘Keen winter is melting away beneath the welcome change to spring 
and the western breeze [Zephyr]. . . . Now Venus, Lady of Cythera, 
leads her choirs’ (Lonsdale and Lee). 

* Ed. Camposampiero, Milan, 1819. 


14 Prologue I-11 


And Zephirus and Flora gentilly 

Yaf to the floures, softe and tenderly, 

Hir swote breth, and made hem for to sprede, 
As god and goddesse of the floury mede.” 


Cf. Lydgate, Balade for May Day at Bishop’s Wood 1-16": 


Mighty Flourra, goddes of freshe floures, 
Whiche clothed hast the soyle in lousty grene; 
Made buddes springe with his swete showres, 
By influence of the sonnes so sheene, 

To do pleasaunce of entent ful clene, 

Unto the states whiche that now sitte here; 
Hath Veere doune sent hir owen doughter dere, 
Making the vertue that dured in the roote, 
Called of clerkes, the vertue vegytable, 

For to trascend moste holsome and moste sweete, 
Into the crope this saysoun so greable. 

The bawmy lykour is so comendable, 

That it rejoythe with the fresshe moysture, 

Man, beeste, and foole, and every creature, 
Whiche hathe repressed, swaged, and bore doune, 
The grevous constreinte of the frostes heere. 


Zephyr is called ‘the debonair wind’ in Boeth. I m. 5. 15. 
Deschamps has ‘Zephirus, li doulz vens’ (Oeuvres, ed. Saint- 
Hilaire, 6. 98) and ‘Doulz Zephirus, qui faiz naistre les fleurs’ 
(5. 229), the last clause of which looks like an original for Bk. 
Duch. 403. Cf. Alain de Lille (ca. 1128-1202), De Planctu 
Nature, Metre III (tr. Moffat): ‘Flower-bearing Zephyrus had 
softened the rugged year, and quelled the wars of Boreas with 
its peace, and, bathed in a hail of flowers, rained privet-bloom, 
and ordered the blossoming snows to be in the: meadows.’*4 

swete breeth (5). One is at first tempted to think of such a 
passage as Par. Lost 4. 156-8: 


° Cf. Bk. Duch. 402-3: 


For bothe Flora and Zephirus, 
They two that make floures growe. 


“Chronicle of London, ed. Tyrrell and Nicolas, p. 257; cf. Gross, 
Sources and Lit. of Eng. Hist., No. 1739; MacCracken, Lydgate Canon, 
Pp. XViii. 

“Yale Studies in English 36. 21; cf. Wright, Anglo-Latin Satirical 
Poets 2. 447. 


EE ee al 


~~! = 


Prologue I-11 15 


Now gentle gales 
Fanning their odoriferous wings, dispense 
Native perfumes, and whisper whence they stole 
Those balmy spoils”; 


or of the Shakespearean lines from which it was perhaps imitated 


oN. LS 
( : Like the sweet South,” 


That breathes upon a bank of violets, 
Stealing and giving odor. 


And so it was evidently taken by Hawes (Pastime of Pleasure 
72): 

Encensying out the aromatike odoure 

Of Zepherus breath, whiche that every floure 

Through his fume doth alwaye engender. 


But swete does not, I believe, here mean ‘odorous.’ Chaucer 
first uses the phrase in Rom. Rose 547, as a translation of douce 
alene, and there it clearly does mean ‘odorous’: 


With swete breeth and wel savoured. 


We have noted above the swote dewes of Rom. Rose 60, and 
this may account for Bk. Duch. 415: 


Swetnesse of dewe had mad it waxe. 


In neither case should we be tempted to define the word by 
‘fragrant, ‘fragrance’; see the remark under shoures sote, above. 

To understand what is meant by the sweet breath of Zephyrus, 
we must first see what is meant by his breath in general. The 
‘tepentibus auris’ of Georg. 2. 330 is a plural, so that one is 
tempted to look for a singular in another author whom Chaucer 
is known to have translated. Such a singular we find in the 
Third Metre of the Second Book of Boethius: 


Cum nemus flatu Zephyri tepentis 
Vernis inrubuit rosis. 


* Cf. Herodotus 3. 113; Lucian, True History 2. 5; Evelyn, Dedication 
of Fumifugium to Charles II (Misc. Writings, ed. Upcott, p. 208) ; 
Memoirs, ed. Bray, 1. 127 (Diary, ed. Bray-Wheatley, 1. 95); Voyage 
de Francois Leguat (Hakluyt Soc.) 1. 39, cf. 1. lx; Tennent, Ceylon 1. 4, 
note; Longfellow, Tales of a Wayside Inn, Part I, Prelude 195-200; 
Maupassant, A Repulse (English Works 4. 51); Countess Martinengo 
Cesaresco, Lombard Studies, p. 104; T. Moore, Epist. 3 (from Bermuda, 
Jan., 1804). Add Diodorus Siculus 2. 49; Stisted, Life of Burton, p. 176. 

*Emendation for sound. 


16 Prologue I-I1 


Here is a word which might be translated ‘breath’—in one of its 
meanings; here we have the warm Zephyr that recalls Virgil’s 
line; and here is nemus, which might be translated ‘holt.’ Let 
us see what Chaucer makes of it in a prose translation: 


Whan the wode wexeth rody of rogsene floures, in the first somer 
sesoun, thorugh the brethe of the winde Zephirus that wexeth warm.” 


As the words for the breath of men or animals are such as 
anima, halitus, spiritus, and as flatus is virtually never employed 
with that meaning,*®° it is evident that here, at least, breeth must 
mean ‘blowing.’ Then neither the ‘Zephyri tepentibus auris’ of 
Virgil, nor the ‘flatu Zephyri tepentis’ of Boethius, if rendered by 
Chaucer ‘Zephirus . . . sewath “his “swetersereeth, can sae 
said to warrant the interpretation of breeth as ‘respired air,’ 
uor of swete as ‘fragrant’; the first might be rendered by 
‘breeze,’ and the second by ‘warm, mild, soft, genial, gentle, 
balmy’—or even, with Pope (Dunciad 4. 422, “Waves to the 
tepid Zephyrs of the spring’), by ‘tepid.’ It would appear, then, 
that Chaucer, though he coined swete breeth in Rom. Rose 547 
on the basis of the French douce alene,*®° employs it in the 
Prologue in a quite different sense.** 

Inspired (6). Blown upon. Lowes (see above, p. 11) quotes 
from Boccaccio, Filocolo 2. 239: ‘Come quando Zeffiro soave- 
mente spira si sogliono le tenere sommita degli alberi movere per 
li campi.’ 

holt and heeth (6). Cf. T. and C. 3. 351-3: 


“* The Old English prose translation runs: ‘Ponne smylte blawed sipan- 
westan wind, bonne weaxad swide hrade feldes blosman.’ In verse we 


have: 
Ponne smolte bl&w6S saan and westan 


Wind under wolcnum, bonne weaxad hrade 
Feldes blostman, feegen bet hi mdton. 
* A typical use of flatus is exemplified by Georg. 2. 330: 
Hibernis parcebant flatibus Euri. 
. “For another form of the phrase, see p. 27. 
** Spenser has our line in mind in Prothalamion 2: 
Sweete-breathing Zephyrus did softly play. 
Thomson (Spring 32-3) thus renders Georg. 2. 330-1: 


Forth fly the tepid airs; and unconfined, 
Unbinding earth, the moving softness strays. 


OE |. 


Prologue I-II 17 


But right so as these holtes and these hayes, 
That han in winter dede been and dreye, 
Revesten hem in grene whan that May is. 


Other authors of Chaucer’s time employ holt and heeth in 
alliterative combination. So in Dest. Troy 1350 (about 1350- 
1400 A. D.): ‘Over hilles and hethes into holte woddes’; Gawain 
and the Green Knight 1320 (ca. 1370): “To hunt in holtez and 
hepe.’ The combination is also found in Middle High German: 
thus in Hartmann von Aue’s Erec*® 3105-7 (ca. 1192): 


Nid riten si beide 
Na holt nt heide, 
Unz daz si der tac verlie. 


The conjunction of the two words suggests the ‘silvas saltusque’ 
of Virgil, Aen. 4. 72; Georg. 3. 40 (‘saltus silvasque,’ Georg. 
4. 53), saltus being defined as ‘woodland-pastures,’ ‘glades or 
open spaces in forests, where cattle pastured and wild beasts 
wandered.’ 

heeth. Current definitions are: ‘An uncultivated tract of 
heathy or shrubby land, usually of a desolate character’ (Cent. 
Dict.); ‘A bare, more or less flat, tract of land, clothed with 
low herbage and dwarf shrubs, esp. with the shrubby plants 
known as heath, heather, or ling’ (New Eng. Dict.). Neither 
of these suggests the presence of trees, as does the Latin saltus, 
and explicitly Prol. 606-7 (of the Reeve) : 


His woning was ful fair upon an heeth, 
With grene trees shadwed was his place. 


In Hardy’s Return of the Native, too, there was at one side of 
a house (1v. 5) ‘a knoll, and on the top of the knoll a clump of 
fir trees’ (but see his descriptions in I. 1). 

tendre croppes (7). See above, p. Io. 

yonge sonne. See Virgil’s novos soles, and cf. Ovid, Fasti 
I. 163-4: 

Bruma novi prima est, veterisque novissima solis ; 
Principium capiunt Phcebus et annus idem.” 


8 Based upon Chrétien de Troyes’ Erec et Enide (ca. 1192). Tennyson 
thus conceives the landscape (Geraint and Enid 31-2): 
Gray swamps and pools, waste places of the hern, 
And wildernesses, perilous paths. 
‘The winter solstice is the first day of the new, and the last of the old 
sun; Phoebus and the year take the same period for commencement.’ 


18 Prologue I-11 


slepen al the night with open ye (10). Cf. Sowdone of Baby- 
lone 41-6 (ed. Hausknecht) : 


Hit bifelle bytwyxte March and Maye, 
Whan kynde corage begynneth to pryke, 
Whan ffrith and felde waxen gaye, 

And every wight desirith his like, 
Whan lovers slepen with opyn y3e, 

As nightyngalis on grene tre. 


See also 963-978 (Wells, Manual, p. 84). The poem is ‘of about 
1400 or shortly thereafter.’ 

So priketh hem nature [better, Nature] in her corages (11). 
Apparently from Lucretius I. 12-3: 


Aerie primum volucres te, diva, tuumque 
Significant initum perculse corda tua vi.” 


If we assume this to have been Chaucer’s original, he. can 


hardly have read perculse (see Munro’s definitions below), since hi 


this would, not correspond to any recognized meaning of prike: 


bd 


which, along with such senses as ‘spur,’ has one that is- iis? tn 


trated by the following Chaucerian quotations, and which may 
be represented by ‘stab, pierce’ (cf. Spenser, F. Q. 4. 10. 45. 7): 
Rom. Rose 1058-9: 


They prike [MS. prile] and poynten 
The folk right to the bare boon.* 


A. B.C. 163-4: 
Longius his herte p[r]ighte, 
And made his herte blood to renne adoun. 


Now as the meaning of prick with which we are familiar might 
stand for Lat. pungere, so this other might well represent Lat. 
percutere. In Cicero, Pro Milone 26. 65, we are told of a certain 


“ ‘First the fowls of the air, O Lady, shew signs of thee and thy entering 
in, thoroughly smitten in heart by thy power.’ 
Munro comments: ‘Perculs@ is literally “knocked down, struck to the 


ground”; . . . hence often “stunned, smitten through all the frame” 
by a strong passion, as here by love; . . . comp. Plaut. trin. 
242, . . . where perculsus is restored from the Ambrosian, the other 


mss. having percussus, with which it is so often confused.’ 
“Les gens poignent 
Par derriere dusques a l’os. 


Prologue I-11 19 


Licinius, ‘se gladio percussum ab uno de illis’ (he was stabbed 
by one of them). If, then, we may suppose Chaucer to have read 
percuss@, his translation is accounted for, since that word is used 
in the metaphorical sense of ‘agitate, excite’ (so, for example, 
Pro Milone 29.70). Cf. K. T. 185-6: 


The sesoun priketh every gentil herte, 
And maketh him out of his sleep to sterte. 


It may be objected that Chaucer could have known nothing of 
Lucretius,*” since scholars were ignorant of that poet until 
Poggio sent a manuscript of his poem from Germany to Italy 
in 1417.*° However, there is testimony that Lucretius was read 
throughout the Middle Ages,** and Philippe (33. 133; see note 
44) speaks of manuscripts of the De Rerum Natura as existing 
in abbeys* ruled over by disciples of Alcuin. 

Nolhac denies** that either Petrarch or Boccaccio knew Lucre- 
tius at first hand; but, however that may be, it seems reasonably 
certain that Dante was acquainted with him. The evidence for 


“Cf. Lounsbury, Studies in Chaucer 3. 405. 

“Lucretius, ed. Munro, 4th ed., Text, p. 2. 

“Jourdain, Recherches Critiques sur Age et l’Origine des Traductions 
Latines d’Aristote (Paris, 1843), p. 21: ‘A toutes les époques du moyen 
age on a lu .. . le poéme de Lucréce.’ Cf. Monnier, Alcuin et 
Charlemagne (Paris, 1864), p. 279; Philippe, Lucréce dans la Théologie 
Chrétienne du IIle au XIIIe Siécle (Rev. de l'Histoire des Religions 
32. 284-302; 33. 19-36, 125-162). 

“Corbie (p. 153), St. Bertin, near St. Omer (p. 151; cf. Munro, Text, 
p. 22), Bobbio (pp. 151-2; cf. Munro, p. 2), Mainz (p. 132). The 
manuscript of the last-named abbey was copied by a scribe of the calli- 
graphic school of Tours, and carefully corrected by a Saxon scribe (p. 
132). A twelfth-century catalogue of the library of Corbie has an entry: 
‘Titus Lucretius Poeta.’ It is hardly to be supposed that Chaucer read 
Lucretius at either St. Bertin or Bobbio; yet St. Bertin (in the vicinity 
of Chaucer’s ‘Popering,’ Sir Thopas 9) was only a day’s easy ride from 
Calais (in or near which Chaucer was in 1360 and 1377), and Bobbio was 
on the main road from Genoa to Piacenza, about 60 miles from the former 
(where Chaucer was in 1373, being again in Lombardy in 1378). Seven 
manuscript copies, made directly or indirectly, between 1417 and 1473, 
from that which Poggio sent to Italy, are still extant in England (Munro, 
Pp. 3), but of course none of these could have been in Chaucer’s hands. 

“ Pétrarque et Il’Humanisme, 2d ed., 1. 159-160. 


20 Prologue I-11 


this is furnished by a comparison of Par. 14. 112-7** with Lucre- 
tius 2. 115-121. The former reads**: 


Cosi si veggion qui diritte e torte, 
Veloci e tarde, rinnovando vista, 
Le minuzie dei corpi lunghe e corte, 
Moversi per lo raggio, onde si lista 
Tal volta l’ombra, che per sua difesa 
La gente con ingegno ed-arte acquista.® 


The passage of Lucretius runs: 


Contemplator enim, cum solis lumina cumque 
Inserti fundunt radii per opaca domorum: 
Multa minuta, modis multis, per inane videbis 
Corpora misceri radiorum lumine in ipso, 

Et, velut eterno ccrtamine, preelia pugnas 
Edere, turmatim certantia nec dare pausam, 
Concilia et dissidiis exercita crebris.” 


“First suggested by I. C. Wright, in his translation (1840). Moore 
seems to suppose (Studies in Dante 1. 295) that the discovery was made 
by Builer. 

* Correspondences are indicated by italics. Their number and closeness 
may be estimated by a comparison with the following sentence from 
Isidore of Seville (13. 2. 1), which employs the same general figure: 
‘Hi per inane totius mundi irrequietis motibus volitare, et huc atque illuc 
ferri dicuntur, sicut tenuissimi pulveres qui infusis per fenestras radiis 
solis videntur.’ 

*® Thus translated by Butler: “Thus are seen here, straight and twisted, 
swift and slow, changing appearance, the particles of bodies, long and 
short, to move through the ray wherewith at times the shade is bordered 
which folk acquire with art and wit for their protection.’ Aud thus by 
Wicksteed: ‘So we see here, straight, twisted, swift, or slow, changing 
appearance, long or short, the motes of bodies moving through the ray 
which doth sometimes streak the shade which folk with skill and art 
contrive for their defense.’ 

Longfellow comments: ‘Mr. Cary here quotes Chaucer, Wife of Bath’s 
Tale [12]: 

As thikke as motes in the sonnebeme. 

And Milton, Penseroso 8: 

As thick and numberless 
As the gay motes that people the sunbeam.’ 


* Munro translates: ‘Observe, whenever the rays are let in, and pour 
the sunlight through the dark chambers of houses: you will see many 
minute bodies, in many ways, through the apparent void, mingle in the 
midst of the light of the rays, and, as in never-ending conflict, skirmish 


a 


ee ee ee ey 


Prologue I-I1 21 


Moore*! is not disposed to allow that Dante was acquainted 
with the De Rerum Natura. He says: ‘Even if the passage of 
Lucretius be copied here (which seems to me very doubtful), 
it was probably found by Dante as quoted by some other author, 
or else it may be in some of the Florilegia, though the former 
would here seem the more probable supposition, if any is needed.’ 
It is not easy to see why Dante, as well as the author whom he is 
supposed to have quoted, should not have had access to Lucre- 
tius; but, if we accept either of Moore’s alternative hypotheses 
as true for Dante, there appears no reason why it should not be 
equally true for Chaucer. It may be noted that Scartazzini also 
quotes Lucretius on Dante’s lines. 


With the foregoing parallels may be confronted a few passages 
from modern authors. Lowell, Chaucer (Prose Works, River- . 
side ed., 3. 292): ‘If here be not the largior ether [@ther, Aen. 
6. 640], the serene and motionless atmosphere of classical 
antiquity, we find at least the seclusum nemus [Aen. 6. 704], the 
domos placidas [Aen. 6. 705], . . . that persuade us we are 
in an Elysium none the less sweet that it appeals to our more 
purely human, one might almost say domestic, sympathies.’ 

Ibid., p. 302: ‘Virgil had wellnigh become mythical’ [in the 
thirteenth and fourteenth centuries]. 

Ibid., p. 306: ‘The invocation of Venus, as the genetic force 
of nature, by Lucretius [1. 1-43], seems to me the one sunburst 
of purely poetic inspiration which the Latin language can show.’ 

Mather, edition of Prologue, etc., p. lv: ‘The opening lines of 
the Prologue set us in the very heart of an English springtime; 
we know that buds are bursting, and hear the song of birds.’ 


and give battle, combating in troops and never halting, driven about in 
frequent meetings and partings.’ 

Modis multis seems to have suggested Dante’s diritte e torte, veloci 
e tarde, lunghe e corte. 

* Studies in Dante 1. 205. 


22 The ‘Sweet Breath’ of Zephyr 


Il) THE “SWEET BREATH’ OF ZEPHYR 


A passage which Chaucer may have had in mind in writing 
Prol. 51 is one from the Old French poem entitled La Dame de 
Fayel,? written (ca. 1190) by we know not certainly whom, but 
attributed by one out of six manuscripts to Guiot de Dijon. This 
poem puts into the mouth of a lady her fears and sadness on 
account of the lover absent on pilgrimage in Holy Land. The 
text of the poem, in the critical edition of Bédier, is as follows®: 


Chanterai por mon corage 
Que je vueill reconforter, 
Car avec mon grant damage 
Ne quier morir n’afoler, 
Quant de la terre sauvage 
Ne voi nului retorner 
Ou cil est qui m’assoage 
Le cuer, quant j’en oi parler. 
Dex, quant crieront Outree! 
Sire, aidiés au pelerin 
Por cui sui espoentee, 
Car felon sunt Sarrazin. 


Soferrai en tel estage 

Tant quel voie repasser. 

Il est en pelerinage, 

Dont Dex le lait retorner! 

Et maugré tot mon lignage 

Ne quier ochoison trover 

D’autre face mariage; 

Folz est qui j’en oi parler! 
Dex, etc. 


De ce sui au cuer dolente 
Que cil n’est en Biauvoisis 
Qui si sovent me tormente: 
Je n’en ai ne gieu ne ris. 


*See above, pp. 14-16. 

* Otherwise spelled Fael, Faioel. 

*Bédier, Les Chansons de Croisade, pp. 112-4 (cf. 308-9); Meyer, 
Recueil d’Anciens Textes, p. 368; Gaston Paris, Litt. Fr. au Moyen Age, 
3d ed., p. 198; Hist. Litt. de la France 23. 556-7; 28. 373; Chansons du 
Chatelain de Coucy, ed. Michel, pp. 95-8 (Chansons de Divers Auteurs) ; 
L’Histoire du Chatelain de Coucy et de la Dame de Fayel, ed. Crapelet, 
Pp. XVii-xx, etc. (see Bédier, p. 109). 


The ‘Sweet Breath’ of Zephyr — 23 


Il est biaus, et je sui gente. 
Sire Dex, por quel feis? 
Quant l’uns a Il’autre atalente, 
Por coi nos as departis? 

Dex, etc. 


De ce sui en bone atente 
Que je son homage pris, 
Et quant la douce ore vente 
Qui vient de cel douz pais 
Ou cil est qui m’atalente, 
Volentiers i tor mon vis: 
Adont m’est vis qui jel sente 
Par desoz mon mantel gris. 
Dex, etc. 


De ce sui mout deceiie 
Que ne fui au convoier; 
Sa chemise qu’ot vestue 
M’envoia por embracier: 
La nuit, quant s’amor m’argue, 
La met delez moi couchier 
Mont estroit a ma char nue 
Por mes malz assoagier. 

Dex, etc. 


Which may be thus translated?: 


I will sing for my heart, which I wish to console, for, in spite of 
my great misery, I desire not to perish nor go mad; and yet I see no 
one return from the savage country where he abides who solaces my 
heart when I hear him spoken of. 

O Lord God, when they cry Outrée* succor the pilgrim for whom 
I am in terror, for cruel are the Saracens. 


I will endure in this estate until I see him return. He is now on 
pilgrimage; God grant that he may come back from it! Noble 
though my lineage be, I seek no occasion to wed another—mad is he 
whom I hear suggest it! 

O Lord God, ete. 


What makes me sorrowful is that he is not in the Beauvaisis* who 
so often causes me torment; of him I have neither joy nor laughter. 


‘There is a translation into modern French in Crapelet, pp. xix-xx, 
from a text published on pp. xvii-xix. 

5° The marching-shout of the pilgrims. Cf. Romania 9. 44; Bédier, pp. 
XIV-XV. 

* The territory of Beauvais. 


24 The ‘Sweet Breath’ of Zephyr 


If he is handsome, I am lovely. O Lord God, why hast thou done 
so? When each longs for the other, why hast thou parted us? 
O Lord God, etc. 


What gives me assured hope is that I have received his homage; 
and when the sweet breeze blows from that sweet land where he is 
for whom I yearn, I turn my face thither with gladness, and at that 
moment seem to feel him underneath my gray mantle. 


O Lord God, ete. 


Where I have been cozened is that I was not of his escort when he 
departed.’ He sent me, that I might kiss it, the tunic that he had 
donned; and at night, when love for him gives me no rest, I take it 
to my bed and lay it next my naked flesh, to soothe my woe. 

O Lord God, etc. 


The last two lines of the first stanza are referred to® in 
Guillaume de Lorris’ part of the Roman de la Rose (ed. Michel, 
2688-94) : 


Si me semble [Kaluza, sovient] que por ce dist 
Une dame qui d’amer sot, 

En sa chancon un cortois mot: 

‘Moult sui, fet-ele, 4 bonne escole, 

Quant de mon ami oi parole; 

Se m’aist Diex, il m’a garie 

Qui m’en parle, quoi qu’il m’en die.’ 


The Middle English rendering of the above lines is (2837-50), 
in Skeat’s text (cf. Kaluza, p. 165) : 


And therefore now it cometh to minde, 
In olde dawes, as I finde, 

That clerkis writen that hir knewe, 
Ther was a lady fresh of hewe, 
Which of hir love made a song 

On him for to remembre among, 

In which she seide, ‘Whan that I here 
Speken of him that is so dere, 

To me it voidith al [my] smerte; 
Ywis, he sit so nere myn herte, | 
To speke of him, at eve or morwe, 


* The pilgrim, with the staff and scrip he had assumed, was accompanied 
through the first stage of his journey by his relatives and friends. This 
being passed, he resumed his ordinary garments, of which the tunic in 
question was not one. See Bédier, p. 117. 

®So Hist. Litt. de la France 28. 373, note 3; Romania 8. 360, note 5. 


The ‘Sweet Breath’ of Zephyr 25 


It cureth me of al my sorwe. 
To me is noon so high plesaunce 
As of his persone daliaunce.’ 


Chaucer, as translator of the Roman de la Rose (L. G. W. 
255: 329) would of course have known of this passage of Old 
French. It is generally denied,® however, that he was the trans- 
lator of B (1706-5810).° As bearing on this point, I subjoin 
_ indications of Chaucer’s probable translatorship of the above 
lines: 

(a) Rhymes: 

minde: finde (common in Chaucer). 

knewe: hewe (K. T. 789-790; L. G. W. 55-6 (57-8), 1760-1). 

song: among (Bk. Duch. 297-8; T. and C. 2. 883-5; 3. 1814-6). 

Here: dere (K. f.1005-6; Man of L. T..139-140; Clerk’s T. 
275-8). 

herte: smerte (Prol. 149-150; K. T. 1367-8, 1533-4, 1907-8; 
Franklin’s T. 127-8, 245-6, 531-2, etc.). 

morwe: sorwe (common). 

plesaunce: daliaunce (To Rosemounde 22-4). 

Observe particularly the rhyme-sequence in K. T. 1905-8: 
dere: here: herte: smerte; cf. R. R. 2843-6, above. 

(sp) Correspondences of phrase: 

in olde dawes (so Franklin’s T. 452). 

aemienuide (so. 7..and C. 4. 1138;. ci. Sec. N..T..94, 124; T. 
me et TASS Man of L. T..807; Prior. T..200; K., T. 1267; 
T. and C. 5. 375, 1463; Monk’s Prol. 99). 

aesn ot hewe (so L. Gi W.57: 55; ci. L. G: W..1761;_R. RR. 
3629). 

sit so nere myn herte (cf. sit so in myn herte (rhyming with 
smerte), Bk. Duch. 1108). 

eve and morwe (K. T. 1063; Wife's Prol: 152; T. and C. 
1. 487; 5. 725; cf. on even and amorwe, Prol. Merch. T. 2; ne 
night ne morwe, Bk. Duch. 22; either on morwes or on evenes, 
oP, 4). 

Cf. my remarks on R. R. 3809-14 in The Historical Background 
of Chaucer's Knight (Trans. Conn. Acad. of Arts and Sciences 
20. 181, note 4). 


° Wells, Manual, p. 650. 


26 The ‘Sweet Breath’ of Zephyr 


The Roman de la Rose does not name ‘la dame de Fayel,’ but 
this is done in a ballade attributed with much reason to Eustache 
Deschamps,’® of which I quote the first two stanzas": 


Hester, Judith, Penelopé, Helaine, 
Sarre, Tisbe, Rebeque et Sarry, 
Lucresce, Yseult, Genevre, chastellaine 
La trés loyal nommée de Vergy, 
Rachel aussi, la dame de Fayel 

Onc ne furent sy precieux jouel 
D’onneur, bonté, senz, beauté et valour 
Con est ma trés doulce dame d’onnour. 


Se d’Absalon la grant beauté humaine, 

De Salomon tout le senz sanz demy, 
D’Alixandre l’avoir et le demaine 

Des .1x. preux eusse et leur prouesce aussy 
Et la force, syque se aucun appel 

Avoye, ne seroie bon ne bel 

Ne digne assez pour sy trés noble flour 
Con est ma trés doulce dame d’onnour. 


If these be compared with the corresponding two stanzas of 
Chaucer’s ballade in the Legend of Good Women (B 249-262), 
and the underscored words be noted (see also the -aine rhyme of 
the one, and the -eyne rhyme of the other—thus, Helaine, 
Eleyne), it will seem probable that Chaucer had Deschamps in 
mind as he wrote: 


Hyd, Absolon, thy gilte tresses clere; 

Ester, ley thou thy meknesse al adoun; 

Hyd, Jonathas,” al thy frendly manere; 

Penalopee, and Marcia Catoun,” 

Mak of your wyfhod no comparisoun; \ 
Hyde ye your beautes, Jsoude and Eleyne, 

My lady cometh, that al this may disteyne. 


Thy faire body, lat hit nat appere, 

Lavyne; and thou, Lucresse of Rome toun, 
And Polixene, that boghten love so dere, 
And Cleopatre, with al thy passioun, 


* Cited by Skeat, who, however, did not know of the attribution to 
Deschamps. 

* Oeuvres 9. 49. 

“Deschamps has ‘Jonathas’ (Oeuvres 2. 195). 

‘Marcia, la fille Cathoun’ (Oeuvres 9. 178). 


Prologue 386 27 


Hyde ye your trouthe of love and your renoun; 
And thou, Tisbe, that hast of love swich peyne; 
My lady cometh, that al this may disteyne. 


Froissart also mentions the lady of Fayel (Prison Amoureuse 
#10-222; Poesies, ed. Scheler,; 1. 217): 
La castellainne de Vregi, 
Et le castellan de Couchi, 


Qui oultre mer morut de doel 
Tout pour la dame de Faioel. 


Chaucer’s acquaintance with the name of the lady of Fayel, 
through these or any other intermediaries, would, however, prove 
nothing as to his familiarity with the poem bearing that title; 
but if we might assume such familiarity, we should have another 
source for the phrase ‘swete breeth,’ in the alaine douce which 
is a variant reading for the douce ore'* of the fourth stanza. 
Thus we read (Michel, Chansons, p. 97): 


Et quant l’alaine’’ douce vente 
Qui vient de cel douz pais 
Ou cil est qui m’atalente, 
Volontiers i tour mon vis. 


Ill. PROLOGUE 386 


As supplementary to the quotation concerning a mormal, or 
ulcerated leg, in Mod. Lang. Notes 33. 379, I print below an 
extract from John Arderne’s (1307- after 1377) Treatises, ed. 
Power (EL. E. T. S., No. 139), pp. 52-4, omitting the details of 
cure, including the composition of the Dublin ointment. 

‘[A] chanon was on a tyme seke, and when he bigan to wex 
hole, bar was made a grete gedryng togidre of humours descend- 


* This expression is probably taken from the beginning of a poem by 
Bernart of Ventadour (fl. 1275), the troubadour (ed. Appel, p. 212, 


No. 37): 
Cun la rej’ aura venta 


Deves vostre pais, 
Vejaire m’es qu’eu senta 
Un ven de Paradis, 


where some manuscripts read douss(a) aura. 
* MS. B (Meyer), I’aleisne. 


28 Prologue 386 


yng doune in his legge. After a tyme, forsob, ber wex puscelez 
brounysch and clayisch* . . . At be last, forsop, ber grow 
in bat party of be legge a large wounde, and about pe ankles bre 
or four smale woundez to be brede of ane halfpeny. And be 
legge semed of zelow? colour, medled with rednes, fro be calf to 
pe ankelez. And pe skynne kast evermore out many skalez. .. . 
It come to a mormale; be which, when I had sene it, I affermed 
it to be a mormale. 

‘And I did sich a cure to it: pis is be cure to be mormale— 
first sewe be pacient[s] legge strongly with a lynne clobe. 
After wasche wele pat legge so sewed with hote watre, after pat 
pe pacient may suffre. And so after be waschyng lat it lye by a 
naturel day, bat is ane hole day & a nizt,? kepyng be legge fro 
aier and fro cold. Pe second day, forsop, remove be clope, and 
mundifie be wounde, or be woundes if pai be many, and putte in 
every wounde a litel pece of lynne clope moisted in cold watre. 
Afterward putte of be oyntement of Dyvylyne in pe circuite of 
be wounde above be hole skynne, so pat it touche no waiez be 
woundez within, & cover it with a lynne clobe ywette. Do 
pus euery day tuyez, renewyng be oyntment, and mundifying be 
woundez, and fyllyng bam of a lynne clope ywette, as it is seid 
above. : 

‘Per was dede flesch of blo colour, to be brede of a peny; pat 
dede flesch, forsob, was mich pikke, and, pat yse, I kutte with 
a rasour a litel be over party of pat flesch. Afterward I putte 
to larde, and so at be last, with larde & with cuttyng, I dissolved, 
i.[e.] lesyd, it utterly. Pat flesch perfor remove[d], eftsonez with 
pe oyntment of Dyvylyn aforeseid, and a clobe wette in water, I 
held be wounde opne to be brede of a peny. And pan eftsonez 
per brest out a wounde aboute pe sidez, and it bygan to large it 
unto pat it was almost of be same gretnez as it was afore. 

‘And if pou se pe bone mortified, witte pou bat it is incurable, 
or unnep for to merowe [mowe?] be cured. If pou trow it be 
curable, it is to be helped with some cure of be mormale in be 
boke of Lamfrank. Also, as it is seid above, som tyme a man is 
smytyn som party of be legge violently without wondyng of pe 
skynne, as of ane hors fote, or of a stone or staffe, or sich oper, 


*The margin reads: pustule fusce et late. 
* The z represents open (palatal) g. 


Prologue 493-8, 527-8 29 


and pan is it gode sone for to scarifie pe place ysmyten, and 
drawe pe blode bennez, and after put on enplastrez repressyng 
akyng and bolnyng, ffor ofttymez be mormale comeb of sich 


pings.’ 


IV. PROLOGUE 4938, 527-8 
Weare told of Chaucer’s Parson that he would 
visite 
The ferreste in his parisshe, muche and lyte, 
Upon his feet, and in his hand a staf. 
This noble ensample to his sheep he yaf, 
That first he wroghte, and afterward he taughte— 
Out of the gospel he tho wordes caughte. 


But Cristes lore, and his apostles twelve, 
He taughte, and first he folwed it himselve. 


In the Oxford Chaucer, published in 1894, Skeat has two notes 
on the sources of these lines: “498. The allusion is to Matt. v. 
19, as shewn by a parallel passage in P. Plowman, C. xvi. 
igs. 520) Ct. Acts, 1. 1; Gower, Cont. Amantis, ii, 1887 

More than a dozen years earlier, Mayor and Lumby, in their 
edition of Books 3 and 4 of Bede’s Ecclesiastical History, had 
brought the above lines into relation with Bede’s account of 
Aidan, in their notes on Eccl. Hist. 3. 5. Thus they quote: “Non 
aliter quam vivebat cum suis ipse docebat. . . . Discurrere 
per cuncta et urbana et rustica loca non equorum dorso sed 
pedum incessu vectus . . . . solebat’; and to this they add 
a number of parallels. Still other. parallels may be found in 
Plummer’s edition (1896) of Bede, Opera Historica 1. xxxvi. 
To these we may add a line from the epitaph on Gregory the 
Greaty(2ccl. Hist.2..1-):: 


Implebatque actu quicquid sermone docebat. 


‘In his hand a staf’ scarcely demands a literary source; if it 
did, the Bible would readily suggest the form: Gen. 33. 18; 
Exod: 12. 11; 1 Sam. 17/4052 Kings 4: 29 3 Zech: 3: 4. 


30 Knight's Yale 1290 


MVM. MKNIGHTIS TALE 1290 


On the wall of the Camera degli Sposi of the Castello di Corte 
at Mantua, Andrea Mantegna, between 1468 and 1474, repre- 
sented a meeting between Lodovico II Gonzaga, lord of Mantua, 
and his son Francesco, then Cardinal. In one of the smaller 
compartments of the fresco is depicted the horse from which the 
Marquis has just alighted, and near the horse two large dogs, 
perhaps three feet in height to the top of the head, white or grey 
in color, one at least being held by a leash. This dog, the one 
facing the spectator, is of powerful build, the head large, the eyes 
small, and the ears cropped. The picture is reproduced by Thode 
(Mantegna, p. 61), Knapp (Andrea Mantegna, p. 41), and 
Kristeller (Andrea Mantegna, p 251). Thode describes the 
does merely as Lodovico’s favorites; Cruttwell (Andrea 
Mantegna, p. 69), as ‘fierce looking boarhounds’; and Kristeller 
(p. 249), as ‘huge dogs (not hounds for the chase, as has been 
supposed).’ It is evident that the biographers are in considerable 
uncertainty as to the species of the dogs in question, even though 
Kristeller elsewhere maintains (p. 262) that these ‘animals [are] 
studied from nature with amazing care and fidelity.’ It occurs to 
me to suggest that these dogs may perhaps be alaunts, of which 
Baillie-Grohman remarks (Cook, The Last Months of Chaucer's 
Earliest Patron: Trans. Conn. Acad. of Arts and Sciences 21. 
135): ‘Both Gaston [de Foix] and the Spanish king [Alfonso — 
XI] say that the body of the Alaunt was like that of a heavy 
greyhound, their eyes were small, they were square in the jaw, 
and that their ears were trimmed and pointed to make them look 
alert. The tail was rather large than small. They were of three 
colors, white, grey, and blackish.’ De Noirmont (op. cit., p. 136) 
‘compares it to the Great Dane or German boarhound, to which 
he assigns a height of 30 to 32, or, exceptionally, 34 inches’-— 
that is, to the shoulder. It will be seen that these accounts apply 
sufficiently well to the dogs delineated by Mantegna. Chaucer’s 
alaunts, as we know, were white. 

Other representations of dogs which might be consulted in 
this connection are in Titian’s picture of Charles V (Prado), 
Venus and Adonis (Prado), and Van Dyck’s Duke of Juliers 
and Berg (Munich). 

For the alaunt in a fifteenth-century shield, see Encyc. Brit., 
11th ed. 13.326. 


Book of the Duchess 368 31 


Wis SBOOK.OF ‘THE DUCHESS 368 


The present Master of Peterhouse, writing in 1880,* thus com- 
ments on this line: “The Emperor Octovian (a favorite character 
of Carolingian legend? . . . in Chaucer’s poem probably a 
flattering allegory for the King) is holding his hunt.’ Skeat, 
though he says® ‘the name originally referred to the emperor 
Augustus,’ and notwithstanding its occurrence in that sense in 
L. G. W. 624, apparently accepts Ward’s view, and supposes the 
allusion to be to the personage of the medieval romance. 

As bearing on this matter, it may be noted that Deschamps, 
who employs the name five times, never alludes to the legendary 
personage. Once, in discoursing on the Nativity, and the con- 
ditions then prevailing in the Roman world, he says*: 

Octovien sanz doubtance 
Regnoit vertueusement. 
‘Le temps Octovien’ is conceived as a golden age. Thus (2. 5): 


Quant verray je le temps Octovien, 
Que toute paix fut au monde affermée? 


And at the beginning of another ballade (7. 251): 


Je voy le temps Octovien 

Que toute paix fut reformée, 

Je voy amer le commun bien, 

Je voy justice estre gardeée, 

Je voy Saincte Eglise essaucée, 
Chasteté en religion, 

Bonnes euvres, devocion, 

Charité, foy, droit jugement 

Faire et tenir sanz fiction. 

—Dit il voir?—Par may foy, il ment. 


Elsewhere he compares the Emperor Charles IV (1316-1378), 
son of John of Bohemia, to Augustus (1. 296) : 


Et l’empereur ot gracieux renom, 
L’empire tint com fist Octoviens, 
Sanz nul debat. 


*Chaucer (English Men of Letters), pp. 68-9. 

*Cf. Gaston Paris, Litt. Fr. au Moyen Age, 3d ed., p. 50; Wells, 
Manual, p. 118. 

® Oxford Chaucer 1. 472-3. 

“Oeuvres, ed. Saint-Hilaire, 7. 153. 


32 Chaucer’s ‘Swerd of Winter’ 


Finally, after the death of Charles V of France (1380), he com- 
plains to Charles VI, possibly with allusion to his father ($..159)*; 
Li tempts n’est pas qu’Octoviens 
Regnoit. 
In the light of these instances, then, it would seem probable that 
Chaucer is comparing Edward III to Augustus Cesar. 

In representing Edward as enjoying the pleasures of the chase, 
Chaucer is upheld by the monk of St. Albans to whom we 
owe the Chronicon Anglie. On his deathbed, it appears, being 
encouraged by Alice Perrers to believe that he would recover, 
he would talk of nothing but hunting and hawking, ‘and trifles 
of that sort.’ 


VII. CHAUCER’S ‘SWERD OF WINTER’ 
In the Legend of Good Women (125-7) we read: 


Forgeten had the erthe his pore estat 
Of winter, that him naked made and mat, 
And with his swerd of cold so sore greved. 


And in the Squire’s Tale (52-7): 
Ful lusty was the weder and benigne, 
For which the foules, agayn the sonne shene, 
What for the seson and the yonge grene, 
Ful loude songen hir affecciouns ; 
Hem semed han geten hem protecciouns 
Agayn the swerd of winter kene and cold. 


With these may be compared Roman de la Rose 6678-82 (ed. 
Michel) : . 

Et quant bise resouffle, il fauche 

Les floretes et la verdure 

A lespée de sa froidure, 

Si que la flor i pert son estre 

Sitost cum el commence a nestre. 


The general notion is that of the ‘penetrale frigus’ of Lucretius 
I. 494, and the ‘penetrabile frigus’ of Virgil, Georg. I. 93; 
Martial 4. 19.9; so in English we speak of piercing, biting (and 
bitter), cutting, sharp, keen cold. 


° Cf. Oeuvres 11. 253-5. 

°Ed. Thompson (Rolls series), p. 142: ‘Itaque factum est ut, per totum 
illud tempus, de aucupatione, venatione, talibus quoque nugis ser- 
mocinaretur.’ 


The Complaint of Chaucer to his Empty Purse 33 


Mik Leeo@wenaliNT OF CHAUCER TO Hig 
EMPEY. PURSE 


Root? justly calls this a ‘delightful poem, which with delicate 
humor applies the conventional language of amorous poetry to 
an empty purse.’ Assigning the envoy to 1399, he adds: ‘It is, 
of course, possible that the preceding stanzas had been written 
at an earlier time.’ The latter statement is in accord with Skeat’s 
view?: ‘I think it highly probable that the poem itself is older 
than the Envoy.’ This is suggested by the fact that MS. Harl. 
7333 heads the poem: ‘A Supplicacion to Kyng Richard by 
Chaucier.’ Wells says*: “There is a general impression that the 
envoy is Chaucer’s latest composition, and was added to the 
stanzas, which are of earlier date.’ 

Skeat’s remarks on the model for the poem are as follows*: 
‘A somewhat similar complaint was addressed to the French 
king John II by G. de Machault in 1351-6; but it is in short 
rimed lines; see his works, ed. Tarbé, p. 78. But the real model 
which Chaucer had in view was, in my opinion, the Ballade by 
Eustache Deschamps, written in 1381, and printed in Tarbé’s 
edition, at p. 55 [Oeuvres, ed. Saint Hilaire, 2. 81]. This Ballade 
is of a similar character, having three stanzas of eight lines each, 
with a somewhat similar refrain, viz. “Mais de paier n’y scay 
voie ne tour,” i. e. but how to pay I know therein no way nor 
method. It was written on a similar occasion, viz. after the 
death of Charles V of France, and the accession of Charles VI, 
who had promised Deschamps a pension, but had not paid it. 
Hence the opening lines :— 


*The Poetry of Chaucer, p. 78. 

* Oxford Chaucer 1. 88; cf. p. 562; and see Ten Brink, in Litteraturblatt 
for 1883, pp. 426-7. 

* Manual, p. 637; ci. p. 616. On p. 637 he also says: ‘It is a pleasing 
bit of humorous application of conventional love-phrasing, not to a lady, 
but to an empty purse. It occurs in three forms: three rime-royal stanzas 
with like rime-sounds and final refrain line, followed by an envoy aabba; 
the three stanzas without the envoy; and the three stanzas without the 
envoy and with a set of rime-royal stanzas on imprisonment.’ 

* Oxford Chaucer 1. 562-3. 


34 The Complaint of Chaucer to his Empty Purse 


Dieux absoille le bon Roy trespassé! 
Et Dieux consault cellui qui est en vie! 
Il me donna rente le temps passé 

A mon vivant; laquelle je n’ay mie. 


The Envoy has but six lines, though the stanzas have eight; 
similarly, Chaucer’s Envoy has but five lines (rimed aa b Db a), 
though the stanzas have seven. Chaucer’s Envoy is in a very 
unusual metre, which was copied by the author of the Cuckoo 
and the Nightingale’ [cf. Oxford Chaucer 7. 347-358]. 

This opinion of Skeat is not very convincing. In the first 
place, Chaucer’s envoy, which, if we adopt Skeat’s view, would 
be the link between Chaucer’s ballade and that of Deschamps, 
has the air of being an afterthought, and, in tone, as well as in 
construction, is quite different.from the body of the poem. Like 
Steadfastness and Truth, this poem has an envoy; but while in 
the former it is a rhyme-royal stanza, on the same rhymes as the 
three preceding stanzas, in this it has five lines, on entirely new 
rhymes.® 

But not only is the envoy different from the body of the poem; 
the latter is quite different, in tone and diction, from the ballade 
of Deschamps. Deschamps’ ballade is not light and humorous, 
nor is its language that of an amatory poem.® Chaucer’s ballade 
has the air of being a genial parody of a love-lyric, perhaps a 
well known one—or, at least, of employing some of its phraseol- 
ogy. Such a love-lyric exists—famous, too, in its period. It 
was written by Guy de Coucy, who was castellan of the castle 
of that name from 1186 to 1203,’ and of whom Villehardouin® 
relates that he was lost at sea in 1203° on the way from the island 
of Andros, south-east of Euboea, to Constantinople: ‘Et rentrer- 
ent en lor vaissiaus et corrurent par mer. Lors lor avint uns 
granz domaiges; que uns halz hom de l’ost, qui avoit nom Guis 
li chastelains de Coci, morut et fu gitez en la mer.’ 

The Chatelain de Coucy, as he is generally designated, was an 
imitator of the troubadours, belonging to the same general 


*Cf. Ten Brink, Chaucers Sprache und Verskunst, p. 213; Schipper, 
Altenglische Metrik 1. 335. 

*Cf. Oeuvres 2. 81-2. 

7 Encyc. Brit., 11th ed., 7. 307. 

*Ed. Natalis de Wailly, § 124; cf. § 114. 

* Not 1201, as Lanson would have it (Hist. de la Litt. Fr., p. 85). 


The Complaint of Chaucer to his Empty Purse 35 


period as Conon de Béthune, Blondel de Nesles, Gace Brilé, 
and Thibaut de Navarre.*° Of his poems, some fifteen or six- 
teen are accredited by modern criticism, of which none attained 
the celebrity of that which we print below. 

Our text is taken from Brakelmann, Les Plus Anciens 
Chansonniers Frangais, pp. 103-5. Another is to be found in 
Michel, Chansons du Chatelain de Coucy, 1830, pp. 79-84 (its 
ancient music on pp. 190-1), and a critical text in Fath, 1883, 
Die Lieder des Castellans von Coucy, pp. 36-9 (from twelve 
MSS.). Still a fourth is incorporated in L’Histoire du Chitelain 
de Coucy, 1829, pp. 244-5 (translation on pp. 409-IT). 


A vos, amant, plus" qu’a nule altre gent 
Est bien raisons que ma dolor complaigne, 
Quant il m’estuet partir oltreement 

Et dessevrer de ma dolce compaigne; 

Et quant li pert, n’ai rien qui me remaigne 
Et sache bien amors seiirement 

Se wi morisse por avoir cuer dolent, 
Jamais par moi n’iert meiis vers ne lais. 


Dolce dame, qu’iert ce donc et coment 
Covendra moi qu’a la fin congié praigne? 
Oil, par Deu, ne puet estre altrement; 

Por vos m’en vois morir en terre estraigne. 
Ne cuidiez mais qu’altres mals me soffraigne, 
Que je n’en ai comfort n’aligement, 

Car de nule altre avoir joie n’atent 

Fors que de vos, ne sai se c’iert jamais. 


Dolce dame, qu’iert il del consirrer, 

Des dolz solas et de la compaignie, 

Del bel semblant que me soliez mostrer 
Quant vos m’estiez, dame, compaigne, amie? 
Et quant recort sa simple cortoisie 

Et les dolz moz que solt a moi parler, 
Coment me puet li cuers el cors durer 

Que ne s’en part? Certes, trop est malvais!* 


* Lanson, as above. 

“The Histoire and MS. A have ains. 

“This stanza is quoted in La Chastelaine de Vergi, ed. Brandin, p. 69 
(= Romania 21. 173, Raynaud’s text, from which Brandin’s is taken), 
with a translation on p. 18; line 2 of stanza 3 here reads: 


Du dous solaz et de la compaingnie. 


36 The Complaint of Chaucer to his Empty Purse 


Or voi je bien qu’il m’estuet comparer 
Toz les deduis qu’ai eiis en ma vie, 
Deus ne m’i volt en pardon rien doner ; 
Ancois criem molt, cist loiers*ne m’ocie. 
Merci, amors," que Deus hait vilenie, 
Que vilain font bone amor dessevrer, 
Et je ne puis mon cuer de li oster, 

Si me covient que je ma dame lais. 


Or seront lié li fals losengeor 

Qu’avoient duel des biens qu’avoir soloie, 
Ja pelerins ne serai a nul jor 

Por ce qu’a els en bone pais resoie. 

Por tant puis bien perdre tote ma voie, 

Et sachent bien li felon menteor, 

Se Deus voloit qu’il reiissent m’amor 

Ne me porroit chargier plus pesant fais.™ 


Je m’en vois, dame, a Deu le creator, 

Qui soit o vos en quel liu que je soie. 

Et sachiez bien, niant iert del retor, 
Aventure est que jamais vos revoie, 

Por Deu vos pri qu’en quel liu que je soie, 
Que mes covens tiegniez, viegne ou demor; 
Et je pri Deu qu’ensi me doinst honor, 
Com je vos ai esté amis verais. 


The romance in question was written about 1280 (Gaston Paris) or 
between 1282 and 1288 (G. Raynaud, in Romania 21. 153). It is referred 
to by Froissart, Paradys d’Amour 992, and Prison Amoureuse 219, as 
well as by Deschamps 2. 182; cf. also pp. 26, 27, above. Chaucer would 
therefore have known of the romance, and, if he read it, as he doubtless 
did, would have had his attention attracted by this stanza, and by the 
fact that it was assigned by the author to the ‘chastelains de Couci’ 
(1. 292). Four ivory caskets, besides the fragment of another (Bargello, 
Florence), representing scenes from La Chastelaine de Vergi, and all 
belonging to the first quarter of the fourteenth century, are still pre- 
served; these are in the British Museum (reproduced as the frontispiece 
of Brandin’s edition), the Louvre, and the Pierpont Morgan collection 
(two). Others are to be found at Milan, Vienna, and Lyons (R. S. 
Loomis, in Romanic Review 8. 197, supplemented by information in a 
letter of Dec. 18, 1917). 

*% Four MSS., including Brit. Mus. Egerton 274. 13(13th century), have 
Merci li cri. 

4 ‘Pesant fais’ occurs in an anonymous poem of the thirteenth century 
(Chansons du Chatelain de Coucy, ed. Michel, p. 101; cf. Gaston Paris, 
in Romama 8. 354). 


The Complaint of Chaucer to hs Empty Purse 37 


De moie part di, changons, si t’en croie, 
Que sols m’en vois, que n’ai altre seignor: 
Et bien sachiez, dame de grant valor, 
Se je revieng, que por vos servir vais. 


If, now, the italicized passages in the French poem are com- 
pared with those written by Chaucer, as given below, I think 
it can hardly be doubted that he expected the literate to enjoy 
his playful allusions to the former. From line 6 it is evident that 
the manuscript Chaucer knew was of type z (Fath, pp. 21, 36) ; 
see the variant reading at the foot of page 36. It will be 
observed that two of Chaucer’s rhyming words, companye and 
curtesye, both coupled with the refrain, are also rhyming words 
of the French poet. 


To you, my purse, and to non other wight 
Compleyne I, for ye be my lady dere! 

I am so sory, now that ye be light; 

For certes, but ye make me hevy chere, 
Me were as leef be leyd upon my bere; 
For whiche unto your mercy thus I crye: 
Beth hevy ageyn, or elles mot I dye! 


Now voucheth sauf this day, or hit be night, 
That I of you the blisful soun may here, 

Or see your colour lyk the sonne bright, 
That of yelownesse hadde never pere. 

Ye be my lyf, ye be myn hertes stere, 
Quene of comfort and of good companye: 
Beth hevy ageyn, or elles mot I dye! 


Now purs, that be to me my lyves light 

And saveour, as doun in this worlde here, 
Out of this toune help me through your might, 
Sin that ye wole nat been my tresorere; 

For I am shave as nye as any frere.* 

But yit I pray unto your curtesye: 

Beth hevy ageyn, or elles mot I dye! 


LENvOoY DE CHAUCER 


O conquerour of Brutes Albioun! 
Which that by lyne and free eleccioun 


* Cf. Prol. 590 (of the Reeve): 
For he was shave as ny as ever he can. 


38 ; Sir Geoffrey Chaucer 


Ben verray king, this song to you I sende; 
And ye, that mowen al our harm amende, 
Have minde upon my supplicacioun! 


Chaucer’s envoy is more in the vein of such demands as 
Deschamps. sometimes made upon his patrons (cf. Skeat’s 
remarks above, p. 33, and Deschamps, Oeuvres 11. 32 ff., 256, 
300).1° The phrase, ‘Brutes Albioun,’ too, seems to repose on 
reminiscences of Deschamps, who introduces both words, and 
variants of them (‘Albie,’ etc.), not only in his poem addressed 
to Chaucer (2. 138-140; cf. Oxford Chaucer 1. lvi-lvii"), but 
elsewhere (1. 106-7, 318; 2. 33; 3. 110; 6. 87; 7. 244-5). In 
the rhymes with Albio(w)n, Latin derivatives are usually, and 
almost necessarily employed, as by Chaucer here (1. 317-8; 3. 
109-10; 6. 133-4; 7. 244-5; but Bullion, 3. 110; Lion, 7. 244). 


IX. SIR GEOFFREY CHAUGER 


Would not the poet, from August, 1386, have been entitled 
to the above designation? On the 6th of that month, a writ was 
addressed to the Sheriff of Kent, requiring him to have “duos 
Milites, gladiis cinctos, magis idoneos et discretos,’ chosen as 
knights of the shire, whereupon he returned William Betenham 
as the one knight, and Chaucer as the other.t Other testimony, 
some of it more dubious on account of its lateness, is as follows: 


1. Bale, in 1548, calls Chaucer ‘eques auratus.” and Leland 
(ca. 1545) had written ‘De Gallofrido Chaucero, Equite.” 


% The first two lines are illustrated by Gower’s Cronica Tripartata 
3. 322-5: ' 
Unde coronatur trino de jure probatur, 
Regnum conquestat, que per hoc sibi jus manifestat; 
Regno succedit heres, nec ab inde recedit; 
Insuper eligitur a plebe que sic stabilitur. 
Cf. Stubbs, Const. Hist. Eng. 3. 11-12. 

™ Critical edition by Jenkins, Mod. Lang. Notes 33. 268, 437. 

1 Kirk, Life-Records IV, pp. 261-2. 

?Hammond, Chaucer, p. 8. Pits (1619) has: ‘Ipse tandem auratus 
factus est Eques’ (ibid., p. 13). Phillips (1674) calls him ‘Sir Geoffry 
Chaucer’ and ‘Knight’ (ibid., p. 36). 

*Spurgeon, Five Hundred Years of Chaucer Criticism and Allusion, 
p. 87. 


Chaucer's Mission to Florence in 1372 39 


2. Chaucer bore arms, which were formerly to be seen upon 
his tomb.* 

3. The designation of ‘Sir’ is given to him ca. 1560 in 
Sloane MS. 314 (Spurgeon, p. 95); by Legh, 1562 (97); by 
Whetstone, 1576 (113); by Greene, 1590 (131); in 1590 (132); 
in 1592 (137-8); by Peacham, 1622 (197); by Foulis, 1635 
(211); by Baker, 1643 (222); by Gayton, 1654 (229); by 
Jones, 1659 (237); by Gayton, 1663 (240); by Aubrey, 1669-96 
(245); by Ramesey, 1669 (246), and in Dryden’s patent as poet 
laureate, 1670 (247), etc. 


X. CHAUCER’S MISSION TO FLORENCE IN 1372 


No one seems ever to have conjectured what was the errand 
on which Chaucer was dispatched to Florence. What service 
could the Florentines render Edward III, in the existing state 
of his affairs? He would hardly have sent Chaucer to negotiate 
concerning the establishment of a Florentine quarter in some 
English port, since they only incidentally and individually traded 
to foreign ports; and for a similar reason he would not have 
been in quest of galleys. Besides, why should such a mission be 
secret, since for these objects Edward sent public embassies to 
Genoa, and openly declared the reasons why they were sent? 
In relation to distant countries, what interest did Florence 
peculiarly represent? No one needs to be told that it was banking 
and the coinage of money. The florin was a standard measure 
of value, and the Bardi were known throughout Western Europe. 
Now that Edward was at this time in dire need of money is 
beyond question. In 1371 Parliament demanded £50,000 from 
the parishes of England, and the clergy were induced to vote 
£50,000 more. But these sums were as nothing in comparison 
with the amounts lost or wasted by the government. Off La 
Rochelle, on June 24, 1372, 20,000 marks, with which Guichard 
d’Angle, fellow-commissioner with Chaucer in 1377 and 1378, 
was to pay Edward’s soldiers in Guienne, went down in a founder- 


*Hammond, pp. 20, 47. 
* Dict. Nat. Biog. 17. 66 


40 Chaucer's Mission to Florence in 1372 


ing ship, or were carried away by the victorious Spaniards*?; and 
by Oct. 9 of that year, Edward, who had been cruising in the 
Channel for several weeks, in a vain endeavor to bring succor to 
his troops in Guienne, returned to England, having wasted 
£900,000 in a hopeless enterprise.* At the October Parliament, 
‘a heavy subsidy on wool was granted for two years, and a 
fifteenth for one year, to meet the king’s urgent need of money 
for the expenses of the war.’ A little later, Edward received 
‘a grant of customs, which was clearly an unconstitutional pro- 
ceeding.’ These measures indicate the straits to which the 
King was reduced, especially since in January, 1370, he had 
received the grant of a tenth for three years from the clergy, 
and yet borrowed largely from his subjects for the expenses of 
the war.’ Guienne was being lost to England, because of the 
financial embarrassment prevailing there.© John of Gaunt’s 
disastrous raid through France in 1373 cost immense sums, for 
which he was not only obliged to draw on his own princely 
‘income, but.also to pledge his credit in every direction, borrowing 
here £2000, there £200 or 200 marks.? Even before leaving 
Guienne, toward the end of 1371, he was reduced to borrowing 
so small a sum as £208—and this when he had permanently in 
his pay a hundred knights and a hundred squires, of whom a 
single individual might receive a yearly retainer amounting to 
more than $25,000 of our money.’ Well might it be said of the 
King that he was profuse in his expenditure’; well might it be 
said of John of Gaunt; and well might it be said of the Black 
Prince.t At the time of Chaucer’s appointment, Edward was 


? Froissart, ed. Luce, 8. 43, cf. p. xxvii; Walsingham, Hist. Angl. 1. 
314; Nicolas, Hist. of the Royal Navy 2. 145. 

* Walsingham 1. 315; cf. Armitage-Smith, John of Gaunt, pp. 98-9. 
4 Dict. Nat. Biog. 17. 67. 

* Dict. Nat. Biog. 17. 66. 

° Armitage-Smith, pp. 85, 88; Dict. Nat. Biog. 17. 100. 

7 Armitage-Smith, pp. 102-3. 

8 Tbid., p. 117, note 2. 

* [bid., p. 228. With the number of knights, cf. K. T. 993, 2096, 2099. 

Dict. Nat. Biog. 17. 51. 

™ When he was preparing in 1365 for the expedition which was to be a 
principal means of losing England her French empire, he lent Peter the 
Cruel 56,000 florins (£8,400 = $630,000 or more), and broke up his plate 
to pay the soldiers whom he engaged on Peter’s behalf. 


Chaucer’s Mission to Florence in 1372 41 


falling into premature and dishonored senility, having less than 
five years more to live; after Crécy and Poitiers, after the naval 
exploits of Sluys and Espagnols-sur-Mer, England was fallen 
upon evil days, and encountering reverses on every hand: the 
Black Prince had come home to die; Guienne was practically 
lost; and John of Gaunt, who was now working his will with 
the kingdom and the King.?? Whether he was successful or not, 
cessful. Edward knew not where to betake himself for the 
indispensable funds, become more indispensable than ever, now 
that the shadows of the fifth act of his dramatic life were thicken- 
ing round him, and the skill and indomitable perseverance of 
Charles V were at length proving more than a match for the 
brilliant impetuosity which signalized the Edwardian house. The 
Commons were beginning to grumble, to contrast the present 
plight of the kingdom with its glory twenty years earlier’; and, 
worst of all, they were more and more loath to appropriate the 
heavy sums repeatedly called for. Edward engaged a Genoese 
fleet, and appointed a Genoese captain, but where was he to 


2 Cf. Nicolas 2. 148-9: ‘Parliament met on the 3rd of November [1372], 
and the state of the Navy received immediate attention. After the Com- 
mons had granted another subsidy for its support, they represented that 
“twenty years since, and always before that time, the navy of the realm 
was so noble and so plentiful in all ports, maritime towns, and those on 
rivers, that the whole country deemed and called our Lord King of the 
Sea, and he and all his country were the more dreaded both by sea and 
land on account of the said navy. And now it was so decreased and 
weakened from diverse causes that there was hardly sufficient to defend 
the country in case of need against royal power, whence there was great 
danger to the realm, the causes of which were too long to write.”’ 

* Nothing came of this, apparently. The skill of Pietro Fregoso was 
required in another quarter, with rewards far beyond any that Edward 
was prepared to offer, and no doubt the proposed mariners and galleys 
were requisitioned for the Genoese adventure in Cyprus. Historians 
continue to say that the Genoese fleet was on the spot, or actually employed 
in the English service (Nicolas, 2. 149; Ronciére, Hist. de la Marine Fr. 
2. 23), but I see no proof of this, and the contract for a year with 
Gregorio Usodimare and Oberto Gay on Jan. 8-9, 1373 (Rymer) seems 
a clear indication to the contrary. The 50 crossbow-men and 50 sailors 
called for by this contract were not nearly enough to man a single galley 
(each galley of the Genoese fleet engaged by the French in 1337 was to 
carry 210 men, according to Ronciére 1. 411, note 3; according to Nicolas 
2. 225, these consisted of 180 rowers and 30 crossbow-men, the latter to 


42 Chaucer’s Mission to Florence in 1372 


obtain the money it would cost?#* Where, but in the financial 
centre of Europe, in Florence? 

With Florentine banks England had had relations for at least 
three-quarters of a century. ‘In 1299 Edward | was endeavoring 
to obtain a large sum from the Spini (Rymer, June 12), and two 
years later Boniface VIII complained that they had been molested 
in London (Rymer, Sept. 24). In 1317 Edward II sent to 
Philip V, requesting protection for the Bardi (Rymer, Nov. 23). 
Before 1345 Edward III must have borrowed large sums from 
both the Bardi and the Peruzzi, for in that year both these banks 
failed, dragging down many smaller houses in their fall, and 
causing widespread misery in Florence. Edward owed the Bardi 
900,000, and the Peruzzi 600,000 gold florins*® (£135,000 and 
£90,000, respectively—say, normelly, $10,125,000 and $6,750,000, 
but really, in the present year, 1919, much more).*® 


include the master of the vessel and four other officers; in 1356, I5 
Aragonese galleys were each to have 30 crossbow-men, besides the rowers, 
according to: Ronciére 1. 507, note 2, and cf. 1. 267; again, Nicolas, 
2, 225, tells us of five galleys in 1335, each with 154 rowers and 12 
crossbow-men). 

“The cost per galley to Charles V was 1000 florins a month in 1371 
(Ronciére 2. 12), and the same to John II in 1356, with the addition of 
bread (ibid. 2. 507); and 900 gold florins to Philip VI in 1337 (Nicolas 
2. 225). Edward’s contract with Usodimare and Gay called for 25 francs 
a month for each of these, 15 each for two companions, 10 for each cross- 
bow-man, and 7 for each sailor, besides half of all prisoners and goods 
captured, and everything that could properly be accounted pillage (Nicolas 
2. 224-5) ; the monthly expense for even this comparatively slight aid was 
therefore 930 francs. If we suppose the Genoese fleet originally con- 
templated by Edward to have consisted of 20 galleys, the cost per month 
would have been £3000 (at least $225,000), not to speak of the probably 
high salaries of Fregoso and Provan (cf. the scale of wages in the 
English navy, Nicolas 2. 177, 193-4). 

* Giovanni Villani 12. 54 (Rer. Ital. Script. 13. 934); Dict. Nat. Biog. 
17. 57; Coulton, Chaucer and his England, p. 126. The rate of interest 
at this period, owing to debasement of coin, defalcations, repudiation, etc., 
varied from 20 to 33 per cent. 

** Notwithstanding, the Bardi did not utterly decline to deal with 
Edward, for they were bound to him in a large sum of money on the 
following dates (Cal. Pat. Rolls): Oct. 12, 1364; Sept. 29, 1365; Sept. 
29, 1366; July 28, 1368; one member of that company on Dec. 10, 1373; 
while considerable amounts are recorded as having been paid to them for 
the King on Aug. 16, 1372, and July 7, 1373. These sums, however, 
probably represented but a fraction of Edward’s requirements. 


Chaucer’s Mission to Florence in 1372 43 


Now, however, the King and the realm were in sore straits, 
and no stone must be left unturned. The Genoese fleet must be 
paid for; the services of the Doge’s brother were sure to come 
high; and greater sums might possibly be obtained by an appli- 
cation in Florence itself than by an approach through the agencies. 
At all events, it was worth the effort.7 So Edward may have 
reasoned, and, so reasoning, may have resorted to a skilful 
negotiator*—to whom but the silver-tongued, mild-mannered, 
capable, dexterous young squire, already perhaps possessing some 
knowledge of Italian, already perhaps a visitor to Italy in the 
train of Prince Lionel in 136871 If so, it is explicable why he 
was sent on the King’s secret business—the matter must make 
no stir, else the chances of success were imperiled; explicable, 
too, why a person of no greater note was sent; explicable why 
his ostensible mission, publicly proclaimed, was to Genoa, and 
that he occupied only the third place in that commission; 
explicable, finally, why he dispatched those three messengers to 
the King in succession during his stay in Italy—the matter was 
too important to brook delay until he should return, while yet 
it was imperative that he should stay until every expedient was 
exhausted. 

All this, so far as it relates to Chaucer, is conjectural, to be 
sure; but I can not help thinking that it fits in sufficiently with 


™ Some light is thrown upon the relations between Florence and Eng- 
land about this time by the following (Dict. Nat. Biog. 12. 343): ‘About 
this time [1376] a bull of Gregory XI against the Florentines, with 
whom the Pope was then at war, was brought into England. Wherever 
they were, the Florentines were to be pronounced excommunicate, and 
their effects were to be forfeited. Courtenay published the bull at Paul’s 
Cross. . . . As a constitutional politician, he probably was glad to 
forward the downfall of the Italian merchants, from whom the King 
had long derived the money which he wasted in extravagance, and as 
Bishop of London he was no doubt willing to gratify the citizens, who 
were jealous of foreign traders. The Londoners pillaged the houses of 
the Florentines, and made a riot. This caused the interference of the 
city magistrates, and they sided with the King, who took the foreigners 
under his protection.’ 

On Mar. 9, 1373, John Gouche, spicer, a Florentine resident in London 
from his youth, had the liberties of the city of London conferred upon 
him (Cal. Pat. Rolls). 

% Cf. Legouis, Chaucer, p. 19. 

® See Trans. Conn. Acad. of Arts and Sciences 21. 6 ff. 


44 Chaucer's Mission to Florence in 1372 


the known conditions, and especially the known exigencies of 
the kingdom and the King.*°. Whether he was successful or not, 
his efforts were certainly appreciated. Pollard has remarked’?: 
‘From the mission to Genoa dates a great advance in Chaucer’s 
prosperity.” 


XI. KATHARINE SWYNFORD 


It has often been assumed of late that John of Gaunt’s irregular 
relations with Katharine Swynford began about the year 1372. 
Armitage-Smith,’ relying on the Monk of Evesham’s statement, 
‘Quam ut concubinam multo tempore vivente uxore Constancia 
carnaliter cognovit,’ and Froissart’s assertion? that he had kept 
her in the lifetime of his queen, Constance, that is, within the 
period 1371-94, and also as well before as after the death of 
her husband (Nov. 13, 1371),* concludes: ‘Only the years 1371 
and 1372 fit in with this statement.’ In fact, any connection 
which took place between John of Gaunt’s marriage to Constance 


"Cf. Young, Kittredge Anniversary Papers, pp. 415-6, unfortunately 
overlooked till this paper was in type. 

** Chaucer, p. 13. 

* Cf. Legouis, p. 12; Skeat, Oxford Chaucer, p. xxv. Kirk (Life-Rec- 
ords IV, p. xxv) thus summarizes his income for the year after his return, 
1374: ‘Geoffrey was receiving 13/. 6s. 8d. yearly from the King, a pitcher 
of wine daily (of about the same value), 1ol. from the Controller- 
ship, . . . and tol. from the Duke, while his wife’s two pensions 
amounted to 16]. 13s. 4d; in all, 63/. 6s. 8d., or more than r1oool. a year 
of our money.’ Of all this, Chaucer had previously had only the item 
first mentioned, besides Philippa’s two pensions, so that now their joint 
income was more than doubled. By 1376, as Kirk notes (p. xxvi), two 
years later, he had received three extra grants, which ‘may have brought 
him a sum equal in our present currency to about four thousand pounds’ 
(more than $300,000). 

No less significant than the increase of Chaucer’s income is the fact 
that towards the close of 1376 he was again employed on the King’s 
secret business, that between Feb. 17 and March 25 of 1377 he was engaged 
on another secret mission, and between April 20 and June 26 on still 
another—75 days in all, at his regular wages of 13s. 4d. per day (say 
$3750, before the recent decline in the value of money). Cf. Froissart, 
ed. Luce, 8. cxxxix, note 3. 

*John of Gaunt, p. 462. 

*Ed. Kervyn de Lettenhove 15. 2309. 

* Derby Accounts, ed. L. T. Smith, p. 301. 


Katharine Swynford 45 


and the death of Sir Hugh Swynford must have been between 
September, 1371, and November 13 of that year. Armitage- 
Smith adds: ‘The petition to the Pope® . . . mentions the 
adultery in the life of Duchess Constance, not in that of the 
Duchess Blanche.’ Accordingly, he assigns these conjectural 
dates® for the birth of the illegitimate children of the pair: John, 
1373(?); Henry, 1375(?); Thomas, 1377(?); Joan, 1379(?). 
These dates, it will be observed, are purely inferential from the 
assumed date of the first illicit connection of Catherine and the 
Duke. Other good authorities do not differ widely from this. 
Sir Harris Nicolas,” arguing from the fact that John, the eldest 
son, was a knight in 1391, deduces that he ‘must have been 
born at least as early as 1375,’ while Lucy Toulmin Smith*® says 
that he ‘would be about 15° in 1390, when he joined the Barbary 
crusade.’ 

It is my purpose, in the next few pages, to adduce some reasons 
for believing that Armitage-Smith’s dates are too late to account 
for certain indisputable facts. 

First, as to John Beaufort. 

(1) In 1390 he was closely associated with seasoned knights, 
and pitted against some of the boldest and most adventurous 
spirits in Western Europe, for in the spring of that year he 
belonged to a group of four knights who jousted on the same 
day at St. Inglevert,?? near Calais, one of these being his half- 
brother, then 24 years old, who nine years later was to become 
King Henry IV, and who on this occasion gained much distinc- 
tion for his prowess.1t Another of the same group, also 
prominent in the tilting, was Robert Ferrers, who had borne 


* Armitage-Smith, p. 93. 

5 Papal Letters 4. 545: ‘While Constance was still alive, he had com- 
mitted adultery with the said Catherine, an unmarried woman, and had 
offspring by her.’ This does not agree with Froissart’s statement that 
their relations had preceded, as well as followed, the death of Sir Hugh 
Swynford. 

“Ps 380, 

7In Samuel Bentley’s Excerpta Historica, p. 155; cf. Derby Accounts, 
p. 302. 

® Derby Accounts, p. 301. 

°So Beltz, Memorials, p. 354. 

*® Froissart 14. 416; Armitage-Smith, p. 462. 

“Wylie, Henry the Fourth 1. 5; 4. 127, note 4. 


46 Katharine Swynford 


arms as early as 1378 or 1379’? (Chaucer, we may remember, 
is supposed to have first borne arms at the age of 19). Still 
another Englishman who distinguished himself in the jousting 
was Lewis Clifford, then about 54 years old.** If we suppose 
John Beaufort to have been only 17 years old at this time, how 
can he have held his own with men so much older and more 
experienced? 

(2) From St. Inglevert a number of Englishmen repaired 
to the siege of Mehediah (called by the chroniclers Africa), 
southeast of Tunis. In one band there were 25 men of rank 
(gentils hommes) and 100 archers, prominent among whom were 
Lewis Clifford, Thomas Clanvowe,"* and Peter Courtenay.’® At 
this siege we find John Beaufort as a knight banneret,*® encamped 
as second in a group of 29 knights at the left of the commander 
in chief of the expedition, Louis de Bourbon.** 

(3) While it is uncertain whether he joined Henry of Derby 
in Germany,’® after the siege of Mehediah was raised, he was 
certainly in Lithuania in 1394, where he took part in an extensive 
raid,*® and was probably at the disastrous battle of Nicopolis 
on Sept. 25, 1396.7° Is it likely that he was a knight banneret at 
17, encamped in so honorable a station; that he served with the 
Prussian knights at the age of 21 (Henry, who was certainly 
adventurous enough, did not go thither till after St. Inglevert, 
when he was 24 years old; Henry of Lancaster, his grandfather, 
till he was 52; William Ufford, till he was 26; Thomas Beau- 


* Froissart 21. 193. 

* Beltz, Memorials, p. 261; cf. Froissart 14. 110-2; Hist. Background, 
p. 192. Clifford was made a Knight of the Garter in 1377 (Beltz, p. cliii). 

“Wylie 3. 261; cf. Hist. Background, pp. 214-5. . 

* Cabaret, Chronique du Bon Duc Loys de Bourbon, p. 222 (cf. pp. 
238, 248-9; Cabaret misspells Courtenay’s name); cf. Le Roulx, La 
France en Orient 1. 166ff.; Derby Accounts, p. xxxviii. Courtenay 
became Knight of the Garter in 1388 (Beltz, p. cliv). 

* Froissart 14. 225: ‘Messire Jehan de Beaufort, fils bastard au duc 
de Lancastre, a banieére.’ 

“Cf. Hist. Background, p. 209; Wylie 3. 261; Derby Accounts, pp. 
XXXvili, 301; Le Roulx, La France en Orient 1. 176, 242; 2. 14. 

* Derby Accounts, p. 301; Hist. Background, p. 200. 

” Hist. Background, p. 209. 

” Wylie 3. 261; Le Roulx 1. 242. 


EE 


Katharine Swynford 47 


champ, till he was 52; nor Hotspur, till he was 28**); and that 
he was at Nicopolis at the age of 21° 

(4) In 1396 John was made a Knight of the Garter??; on 
Feb. 9, 1397, he, with his brothers and sister, was legitimated 
by act of Parliament**; and the next day he was created Earl of 
Somerset, reason for this being found in the exploits he had 
performed in foreign countries, by which he had shed lustre on 
the English name.2* Had he probably brought great honor to 
the King and kingdom by his various campaigns and enterprises 
in many realms and lands before he was fully 24? 

(5) On May 9g, 1388, John Beaufort was made Admiral of 
both the Northern and the Western Fleet,?? whereas, for the 
most part, each fleet had its own admiral. Of thirteen admirals 
belonging to that century whose ages can be exactly or approxi- 
mately ascertained,”® the average was over 40, the range being 
from 31 to 52. If we assume the lowest of these ages for 
Beaufort, he would have been born in 1367; but such an assump- 
tion must be viewed in the light of other facts, which will be 
adduced below. 


“For these see Hist. Background, pp. 203, 205, 207. 

* Beltz, Memorials t. cliv. 

* Rymer, Rot. Parl. 3. 343. 

“Rot. Parl. 3. 343: ‘Le grant honour q’il ad fait par sa persone en 
diverses journees et travaulx en pluseurs roialmes et terres d’outre meer, 


-a grant honour du roy et de [du?] roialme.’ On this occasion the new 


Earl was led to King Richard by the Earl of Huntingdon, half-brother of 
the King, and son-in-law to John of Gaunt; and by the Earl Marshal, 
Mowbray, ‘banished Norfolk’ that was to be. After being girt with the 
sword by the King, he was seated between the Earl Marshal and the 
Earl of Warwick. Among the witnesses were his father and his half- 
brother, who in a little more than two years was to be Henry IV. 

*On Feb. 2, of the Irish Fleet (Nicolas, Hist. Royal Navy 2. 338, 518, 
532). Beaufort was appointed under the title Marquis of Dorset, which 
he bore irom Sept. 29, 1397, to Oct. 6, 1309 (Cokayne, Complete Peerage 
3. 146). He was also Warden of the Cinque Ports (Cokayne 7. 170; 
Beltz, p. 355). 

* These are: Thomas Ughtred, 45; Robert Ufford, 39; William 
Montacute, 36; Robert Morley, 43; Richard Fitzalan II, 33; William 
Bohun, 41; Henry of Lancaster, 52; Thomas Percy, 34 (37?); Henry 
Percy, 41; John Holland, 37; Michael de la Pole, 46; William Montacute, 
48; Richard Fitzalan III, 31. The general result is only confirmed by 
Bartholomew Burghersh, who, when he was made Admiral of the Western 


48 Katharine Swynford 


Secondly, as to Henry Beaufort. 
(1) Of his early life the following account was given by Foss**: 


In January, 1307, . . . Henry Beaufort, the second son, was 
probably just of age; as he is called Clericus* on the Roll, and his 
next brother, Thomas, is styled Domicellus. Of his youth we have little 
information beyond the fact that he was educated in part at Aix-la- 
Chapelle,” and in part at Queen’s College,” Oxford, and that when he 
was little more than a boy he formed an amatory connection with 
Alicia, daughter of Richard," Earl of Arundel, sister to the Arch- 
bishop of Canterbury, and nearly related by marriage to John of 
Gaunt himself. . . . If this is a true relation, the lady must have 
been much older, and therefore probably the corrupter of his youth; 
be this as it may, the amour did not impede his future fortunes, nor 


Fleet in 1337, had borne arms for 20 years. John’s younger brother, 
Thomas, made Admiral in 1408 (Nicolas 2. 532), may have been born 
about 1377 (Cokayne 3. 297). For the list of admirals, see Nicolas 
2. 524-532. John Hastings, Earl of Pembroke, came to grief off La 
Rochelle in 1372, at the age of 25; but he, though in command of that 
expedition, was not an admiral. 

* Tudges of England 4. 286-7. 

**Clericus’ would of course mean nothing as to his age. 

“This is an error. Godwin, it is true, says (Bishops of England, ed. 
1615, p. 241): ‘He was brought up for the most part at Aken in Ger- 
many, where he studied the civill and canon law many yeares’; but Wylie 
(3. 263, note 5) asserts that this statement, based upon Holinshed, and 
often repeated, is a mistake, Oxford being meant. 

* He was in residence there during the terms 1390-1, 1392-3, 1395-6 
(Obituary Book of Qucen’s College, p. 70, cf. p. 14; Hist. MSS., 2d - 
Report, p. 141; Beltz, Memorials, p. 354, note 2); but he was also in 
residence at Peterhouse, Cambridge, in 1388 (Hist. MSS., 1st Report, p. 
78). Queen’s College was founded in 1340-1, in honor of his grand- 
mother Philippa, and its books bear the name of Edward, the Black 
Prince. In 1397 Henry Beaufort was still contemplating further study 
at Oxford, for on April 13 of that year he was allowed, by papal indult, 
to let to farm the fruits of his deanery of Wells, with the annexed 
prebend of Wademore, and of his other benefices, while studying letters 
at Oxford or other university (Papal Letters 5. 26). In this he is called 
student of theology and Master of Arts (cf. p. 49). 

*Foss thinks of this Richard as the second of the name (1307 ?-1376), 
instead of the third (1346-1397). The Archbishop of Canterbury was 
Alicia’s uncle, not her brother (Dict. Nat. Biog. 19. 99, 101). Alice may 
easily, then, have been as young as Henry, or younger, since her father 
was six years younger than his. The Johanna, wife of Edward Stradlyng, 
to whom Henry makes a bequest (Test. Vet., p. 251) is assumed to be his 
daughter. 


Katharine Swynford 49 


prevent his brother, King Henry IV, from placing his own son, after- 
wards Henry V, under his tuition in the same college.” This was 
about the year 1399, when Beaufort had been appointed Chancellor 
of the University, an office which he held only one year. . . . Bred 
up as an ecclesiastic, he received in the year of his legitimation the 
‘deanery of Wells, together with a prebend in the church of Lincoln,” 
and was elected* Bishop of the latter see on July 14, 1308. 


(2) Beaufort was a Master of Arts by Feb. 4, 1393, as appears 
from an account—‘magistro Henrico .Beaufort’—quoted by 
Beltz.*° As the average age of the Bachelors was 17 or 18, and 
as it required three years more to become a Master,*® it may be 
supposed from this that Henry could not have been born later 
than 1373. But it must be remembered that he might have 
remained for years in the status of Master. 

(3) As we have seen, Henry Beaufort was made Bishop of 
Lincoln in 1398, and that implies, in the absence of any informa- 
tion to the contrary, that he had completed his thirtieth year 
before Feb. 27.°* Rarely, in the English history of the period, 
de we find this requirement dispensed with.** Only four®® cases 
have come to my notice—those of William Courtenay (1370), 
Thomas Arundel (1373), Robert Neville (1427), and George 


* This is a tradition (Wylie 3. 263; Tyler, Henry the Fifth 1. 21). 

*“He was made prebendary of Thame 1389, and of Sutton 1391, both 
in the diocese of Lincoln’ (Dict. Nat. Biog. 4. 41). -We also find him 
named as ‘Warden of the Free Chapel in Tickhill Castle,’ in Yorkshire 
(Wylie 3. 263; cf. Dict. Nat. Biog. 51. 144), and Canon of York (Papal 
Letters 5. 641). 

“Rather, consecrated (see Tyler, Henry the Fifth 1. 21). His 
approaching consecration is referred to on Feb. 27, 1398, where he is 
called ‘elect of Lincoln’ (Papal Letters 5. 112; cf. 5. 115, 175). Boniface 
IX informs him that on that day he had provided Henry to the see of 
Lincoln, Tickhill to be retained (Papal Letters 5. 507; cf. 5. 284). 

*® Memorials, p. 354, note 2. 

* Lyte, Hist. of the Univ..of Oxford, pp. 206, 211. 

* Corpus Juris Canonici, Decret. Greg. IX, De Electione 1.6.7: ‘Nullus 
in episcopum eligatur nisi qui jam trigesimum annum etatis exegerit.’ 
Ci. Realencyk. fiir Prot. Theol., 3d ed., 3. 245. The Pope, however, might 
dispense (Wetzer and Welter, Kirchenlexikon, 2d ed., 1. 635). 

* Cf. Hook, Lives of the Archbishops of Canterbury 4. 405. 

Thomas Bourchier, made Bishop of Worcester in 1434, may well 
have attained the canonical age (Dict. Nat. Biog. 6. 15; Foss, Judges of 
England 4. 2097). 


50 Katharine Swynford 


Neville (1458). Courtenay was born about 1342, and his defect 
in age was made up by a papal bull of Aug. 17, 1369, so that he 
was consecrated Bishop of Hereford in the following July.* 
Arundel, who eventually became Archbishop of Canterbury 
(1396), was born in 1353, being own cousin to Blanche, John of 
Gaunt’s first wife. Gregory XI conferred upon him the bishopric 
of Ely.on Aug. 13, 1373, when he was 20 years old, though he 
was not consecrated till 1374. The Pope wrote him* on Aug. 
29, 137347: ‘No one so young has been appointed to a see. The 
Pope has done this at the request of your father, Richard, Earl 
of Arundel, whose example in defending ecclesiastical liberties 
the Pope exhorts you to follow.’ Robert Neville (1404-1457), 
a nephew of Arundel, was made Bishop of Salisbury by papal 
provision in 1427,** and received a special dispensation ‘super 
defectum zetatis.’** George Neville, nephew of Robert, was born 
before Dec. 21 (probably before Dec. 3), 1432, since Nicholas V 
had required him to complete his twenty-second year before he 
should be ordained priest,*® and this occurred on Dec. 21, 1454. 
He was consecrated Bishop of Exeter on Dec. 3, 1458, Calixtus 
III having insisted, three years before, that he should first reach 
his twenty-seventh year.*® 

We have, then, these four instances in which the Pope makes 
an exception, once confessedly at the intercession of a relative; 
in the second he notes the exception in a letter to the bishop 
designate, and in the others there is a formal dispensation. In 
still another case, the Pope declines to accede to the request, 
though the candidate is apparently related to the Earl of War- 
wick, and Edward III, his sponsor, is at the summit of his power. 
With respect to Henry Beaufort, there is no hint of a dispensa- 
tion, though, as Walsingham and the author of the Annales 


Dict. Nat. Biog. 12. 342-3. 

“ Papal Letters 4. 129. 

“Ten years before (Nov. 28, 1363), Urban V had written to Edward 
III, declining to appoint Philip Beauchamp to the see of Bath and Wells, 
as being under age—presumably the canonical age—and therefore unfit: 
for the episcopate (Papal Letters 4. 5). 

“Cf. Papal Letters 8. 200. 

“Dict. Nat. Biog. 40. 300. 

“ Papal Letters 10. 717-8. 

“Dict. Nat. Biog. 40. 253. 


—EEeE—E—E— 


— 


ee ee ee 


Katharine Swynford 51 


Ricardi Secundi say, the appointment was made out of regard 
for John of Gaunt.** Accordingly, we must suppose him to 
have been born not later than Feb. 27, 1368. 

(4) In 1398 Henry Beaufort also became Chancellor of 
Oxford.*® While this office was exceptionally conferred upon 
younger men,*® it was one of much responsibility,°° and until in 
the next century it suffered degradation,** and the custom grew 
up of allowing it to bé held by practical absentees,** it was usually 
bestowed upon a Doctor of Theology or Canon Law,** who had 
often spent 20 years on the studies leading to this degree.** 

(5) On Feb. 28, 1403, Beaufort was appointed Chancellor of 
England. This was an office almost never held at an early age, 
Thomas Arundel (b. 1353), Chancellor in 1386, being the 
youngest I have noted in that epoch. Other Chancellors were: 
Richard de Bury (55), Courtenay (ca. 39), Stafford (52), 
Wykeham (65), Michael de la Pole (ca. 53), Richard le Scrope 
(ca. 51), Waynflete (ca. 61). Add Sudbury (18 years after 
becoming Bishop of Lincoln); Braybrooke (22 years after 
becoming priest); Thoresby (29 years after becoming acolyte) ; 
Offord (15 years after becoming Archdeacon of Chester, and 


““Ob Ducis reverentiam et amorem’ (Walsingham, Hist. Angl. 2. 228; 
Annales, p. 227). When the author of the Annales subjoins ‘admodum 
puero, he may be contrasting Beaufort with the: previous incumbent, 
John Bokyngham, translated to Lichfield in order to make way for his 
successor, for the Pope had alleged his ‘imbecillitatem et senectutem, 
quibus reddebatur impotens ad regendum tantum dicecesim et plebem.’ 
When Beaufort was translated to Winchester in 1404, again by papal 
provision, he succeeded William Wykeham, who had died at the age 
of 80; Beaufort himself died in 1447, ‘annis non minus quam divitiis 
gravis’ (Froissart 20. 282); and Waynflete, who succeeded Beaufort, 
was about 91 when he died, still Bishop of Winchester, in 1386. 

“Wylie 3. 263. » 

“ Courtenay obtained it in 1367, when only 25 (Dict. Nat. Biog. 12. 342). 

Lyte, Hist. Univ. Oxford, pp. 170, 231-2. Robert Stratford, Chancellor 
in 1335, was already Chancellor of England in 1331; Richard Fitzralph, 
born before 1300, was Chancellor in 1333; Thomas Gascoigne (b. 1403), 
in 1434; Thomas Bourchier (b. 1404?), in 1434, the same year he was 
made Bishop of Worcester. 

* Lyte, pp. 326-7. 

Peyie,- ps 325. 

PayieS pi eat: 

F myte: ps 223° cf. p. 190. 


52 Katharine Swynford 


three years before becoming paralytic); John Stratford (19 
years after becoming Doctor of Laws); Robert Stratford (12 
years after becoming priest) ; Edington (10 years after becom- 
ing Bishop of Winchester); Knyvet (25 years after he was 
already practising law in the courts), etc.*° 

We have seen that a birth-date at least as early as 1367 will 
best account for the various recorded facts in the early life of 
John Beaufort, and that his next younger brother, Henry, could 
not well have been born after Feb. 27, 1368.°° But as Thomas 
Swynford, the only child of Katharine born in wedlock, was 
four years old at his father’s death on Nov. 13, 1371,°7 he must 
have been born in 1367, and therefore neither John nor Henry 
Beaufort can have been born in that year. Moreover, Richard 
III asserted to his chancellor, John Russell, in 1485, that John 
Beaufort was ‘in double avoutry gotyn.’* This being assumed, 
he must have been begotten between May 19, 1359, when John 
of Gaunt married Blanche, and Sept. 12, 1369, when she died. 
But we have seen that a date later than Feb. 27, 1368, would not 
fit the birth of Henry Beaufort, and that John’s birth was of 
course earlier. Hence both brothers were probably born before 
Thomas Swynford, in other words, before 1367. It follows 
that at any period between May 19, 1359, and (say) 1365, the 
two brothers might have been begotten through the adultery of 
their father; for John we must assume a year not later than 
1364. If, then, John Beaufort was begotten in double adultery, 
Katharine must have been married to Hugh Swynford by 1364, 
or earlier. This would seem fairly unlikely if we accept the 
current theory that she was born about the year 1350.°° That 
date, however, is purely conjectural, and I know of no attempt 
to justify it. John of Gaunt was born in 1340; Hugh Swynford 
was born in 1340°°; and there seems no good reason why 


5 See Dict. Nat. Biog. under these names. 

“Seep. 40) (3). 

Derby Accounts, p. 301; Exc. Hist., p. 157. Katharine also had a 
daughter, Blanche, born in wedlock (Armitage-Smith, p. 461). 

5 Paston Letters, ed. Gairdner, 3. 317, and note 14; Ellis, Orig. Letters 
2. 1. 164; cf. Exc. Hist., pp. 152, 155-6; Wylie 3. 260; Dict. Nat. Biog. 
55. 243; Cokayne 7. 160. 

° Exc. Hist., p. 155; Dict. Nat. Biog. 55. 243. 

EL CAMEL SE ape bas 


ee 


Sa — = - = 


| 


Katharine Swynford 53 


Katharine might not have been born within half a dozen years 
thereafter. She became the mistress, or governess, of Blanche’s 
two daughters,*? Philippa and Elizabeth, of whom Philippa was 
born in 1360. Froissart tells us (15. 238) that Katharine ‘fut 
mise de sa jeunesse en l’ostel du duc et de la duchesse Blanche 
de Lancastre.’ 

The assumption of adultery with Katharine in Blanche’s life- 
time is confirmed by Froissart’s account (15. 240) of the indig- 
nation expressed by the foremost ladies of England when John of 
Gaunt married her, for they referred to her as ‘une telle duchesse 
qui vient de basse lignie, et qui a esté concubine du duc ung trop 
long temps en ses mariages.’** Now mariages must refer to both 
his previous marriages, that to Blanche as well as that to Con- 
stance. An even more explicit statement is made in the Percy 
manuscript 78, quoted by Armitage-Smith (pp. 464-5) : 

Iste etiam Johannes Gaunt post mortem Constancie secunde uxoris 
sue adhuc superduxit dominam Katerinam de Swynfurth, de qua 
genuit in diebus domine Blanchie prime uxoris sue Johannem Bow- 
furth, comitem Somersissie; Johannam Bowifurth, comitissam West- 
morelandie; Henricum Bowfurth, presbiterum, cardinalem, et 
episcopum Wyntonyensem; . . . Thomam Bowfurth, ducem 
Exoniensem. 


The comment of Armitage-Smith is (p. 462): ‘No contem- 
porary evidence supports the statement of Percy MS. 78, 
which places the birth of the Beauforts in the life of the Duchess 
Blanche. There is no doubt, however, that most historians have 
postdated the birth of the Beauforts, or at least of the eldest of 
them.’ He quite ignores the testimony borne by Froissart, as 
quoted above, and asserts (p. 461): “There is no evidence that 
any amour disturbed the married life of John of Gaunt and 
Blanche of Lancaster.’** 


* Exc. Hist., p. 152; Wood, Letters of Royal and Illustrious Ladies 1. 78; 
Armitage-Smith, p. 227. 

* Armitage-Smith, p. 94. 

® Translated in the plural by Johnes (4. 473). Cf. Jahrb. fiir Rom. 
und Engl. Lit. 8. 142 (Hertzberg). 

“He ascribes, however, to 1358 or 1359 (p. 461) an amour with Marie 
de Saint Hilaire (like Katharine, a Hainauter), of which the issue was 
a daughter Blanche. May not this Blanche, like Katharine’s own daugh- 
ter (see p. 52, note 57), have been born after his marriage, and have 


54 Katharine Swynford 


Another circumstance pointing to the birth of John Beaufort, 
at least, not only during the lifetime of Blanche, but even before 


been named after his wife? She herself was no doubt named after her 
great-grandmother, Blanche of Artois, niece of St. Louis, through whom 
the lordship of Beaufort, near Troyes, came to the Lancasters (Armitage- 
Smith, p. 197). She, in turn, may have derived her name from her great- 
aunt, Blanche of Castile, the mother of St. Louis. Chaucer’s Blanche 
seems to have been very lenient toward Katharine, since in 1372 (May 
15) John of Gaunt, in commuting a former grant of 20 marks a year, 
in recognition of the ‘bone et greable service quelle avoit fait et ferroit 
a nostre tres chere compaigne, que Dieux assoille,’ to a present 50 marks 
for life, alleges ‘la tres grande affeccion que nostre dite compaigne avoit 
envers la dite Katerine’ (John of Gaunt’s Register 1. 169). No wonder 
John wished to be laid by Blanche; and no wonder Chaucer puts into his 
mouth these praises (Bk. Duch. 929-932, 937, 994-8) : 


I durste swere, thogh the Pope hit songe, 
That ther was never through hir tonge 
Man ne woman gretly harmed; 

As for hir, [ther] was al harm hid. 

Ne chyde she coude never a del. 

Therto I saw never yet a lesse 
Harmful than she was in doing— 

I sey nat that she ne had knowing 
What was harm, or elles she 

Had coud no good, so thinketh me. 


With certain obvious changes one might apply to Blanche and her 
mother-in-law, Philippa (cf. Dict. Nat. Biog. 45, 167), who died scarcely 
a month earlier, what I have elsewhere (Last Months, p. 110) quoted con- 
cerning the wife of John of Gaunt’s brother, Lionel, and two women 
nearly related to her: ‘She was a lady of sweet and honorable soul. It 
rarely happens that in one house are found three spirits so exquisite, so 
compassionate, and so swift to all goodness, as were Bianca of Savoy, 
Isabella of France, and Violante. . . . They were noble souls in lovely 
bodies, and Heaven only knows what good they wrought in natures like 
those of Galeazzo and his son.’ 

Considering Blanche’s goodness, it is not so surprising that she should 
have condoned Katharine’s most grievous fault; but, notwithstanding the 
public acceptance of certain bastards, such as the Count de la Roche 
toward the end of the 15th century (see Exc. Hist., p. 172), and of the 
Beauforts themselves, we are not prepared to hear the following with 
regard to Katharine (Wylie 3. 258-9): ‘During the lifetime of . 
Constance, she and her daughter Joan were attached to the household 
of the Countess Mary (Henry’s first wife), and received every Christ- 
mas their livery in scarlet and white silk furred with minever, with 
pieces of white damask bawdekin, and their presents of diamonds, gold 
rings, coral rosaries, and so forth each New Year’s Day and Egg-Friday.’ 


~~ 4s 


Katharine Swynford 55 


that of Henry IV (May 30, 1366),°° is the fact that when this 
monarch confirmed in 1407 the patent of legitimation granted 
ten years earlier by Richard II, he caused to be inserted the 
words, excepta dignitate regali, a phrase which might indeed 
have been intended to bar his illegitimate half-brother, or his 
descendants, in any case, but which would certainly have more 
point if John Beaufort had been born earlier than Henry himself ; 
the case thus guarded against actually arose®* when the throne 
was claimed by Henry VII.%7 

Finally, such a reputation had Katharine acquired by the acts 
of her earlier life that doubts were cast, in her native country of 
Hainaut, upon the legitimacy of her lawful son Thomas Swyn- 
ford (born, as we have seen, probably in 1367), for in October, 
1411, Henry IV found it necessary, in order that he might inherit 
in that country, to certify that he was begotten in lawful wed- 
lock.*® As Sir Harris Nicolas observes, ‘the suspicion of his 
legitimacy may have arisen from his mother losing her reputa- 
tion when she became the mistress of John of Gaunt, and from 
the idea that he was the Duke’s child’; but this suspicion would 
have been all the more justified, had it been known that she had 
already borne a child or children to the Duke. 


XI. SIR PAON DE RUET AND CHAUCER 


Paon de Ruet was a Hainauter, who was the lineal ancestor, 
at the fifth remove, of Henry VII of England, and so, at the 
seventh remove, of Queen Elizabeth; he was also the ancestor, 
at the fifth remove, of that young Earl of Lincoln? who was a 


*® See Hist. Background, p. 166, note 4. 

% See the charge made by Richard III (above, p. 52). 

* Nicolas, in Exc. Hist., pp. 152-3; Wylie 3. 260, note 2; Derby 
Accounts, p. 202. : 

SExc. Hist., pp. 157-9; Wylie 3. 260; Cokayne 7. 1609. 

*Paon had (1) daughter, Katharine, who had (2) son, John Beaufort, 
Earl of Somerset, who had (3) son, John Beaufort, Duke of Somerset, 
who had (4) Margaret, Countess of Richmond and Derby, who had (5) 
Henry VII. 

*Paon had (1) daughter, Philippa, who had (2) son, Thomas Chaucer, 
who had (3) daughter, Alice, who had (4) son, John de la Pole, Duke of 
Suffolk, who had (5) son, John de la Pole, Earl of Lincoln (1464?-1487), 
chosen by Richard III as heir (Hist. Background, p. 178). 


56 Sir Paon De Ruet and Chaucer 


rival of Henry VII for the English throne, and who died in 
battle against the King at Stoke upon Trent in 1487, two years 
after Bosworth Field. The most comprehensive statement that 
we have about Paon de Ruet is this by Froissart (15. 238) : 


En ce temps [1396] se remaria le duc de Lancastre tiercement a 
une damoiselle, fils d’un chevalier de Haynnau, qui jadis s’appella 
messire Paon de Roet [var. Ruet], et fut en son temps des chevalliers 
a la noble et bonne reyne Philippe d’Angleterre, qui tant ayma les 
Haynnuras, car elle en fut de nation. 


His relation to Philippa becomes clearer on comparison with 
Froissart’s passage descriptive of the young queen’s departure 
from Valenciennes to join her youthful husband in England at 


the close of 1327 (1. 195): 


La jone roine Phelippe d’Engleterre, en l’eage entre trése et 
quatorse ans, se départi de Valenchiennes en la compagnie de messire 
Jehan de Hainnau, son oncle, dou signeur de Fagnoelles, dou signeur 
de Ligne, dou signeur de Brifuel, dou signeur de Haverech, dou 
signeur de Wargni, et plus de quarante chevaliers et esquiers de 
Hainnau, et servoit devant lui adont uns jones esquiers qui se 
nommoit Watelés de Mauni, qui puis fu messires Watiers; . . . et 
se départirent de Hainnau pluissier jone esquier en entente que pour 
demorer en Engleterre avoecques la roine. 


As the king was in the North, a number of the Flemings 
returned home without proceeding further than London, but 
Kervyn de Lettenhove assumes that Paon de Ruet was one of 
those who remained in England, and that he was already a 
knight (2. 513): 

Nous voyons Edouard III, dés le commencement de son régne, 
combler de ses faveurs les barons de Hainaut, en méme temps que la 
reine Philippe s’entoure de gentes damoiselles venues avec elle de 
ce bon et doux pays. Les chevaliers entrés au service du roi d’Angle- 
terre sont Michel de Ligne, Robert de Fiennes, Nicolas d’Aubrecicourt, 
Guillaume de Saint-Omer, Wulfard de Ghistelles, Thierri de la Croix, 
Simon de Hale, plus connu sous le nom de Simon de Mirabel, et 
Paonnet de Roet,® dont la fille fut plus tard duchesse de Lancastre 


* There seems no sufficient reason for assuming Ruet to have been a 
knight when he came to England. Froissart, writing three-quarters of 
a century later, calls him a knight of Philippa’s (see above), but the con- 
text shows that the love for the Hainauters here spoken of belongs to a 
time when she was well established in her new home. His name does 


Sir Paon De Ruet and Chaucer 57 


et l’aieule des Tudor. Parmi les écuyers on cite Watelet de Mauny,* 
Robert de Gagés, Robert de Maule. 


If Paon de Ruet was, as Kervyn supposes, a knight in 1327, 
he may well have been born in the early years of the century. 
Kervyn conjectures (15. 399) him to have been the son of Jean 
de Ruet (7 1305), himself a son of Huon de Ruet. 

As to the name, Paon de Ruet, we find it as early as 1227 ina 
legal document, in the form Paganus de Rodio.®? Now Rodium 
is the medieval Latin form corresponding to the modern Reeulx, 
or Le Reeulx, the name of a town of 3000 inhabitants, 8 miles 
north-east of Mons,® on the highway leading from Mons to 
Nivelle. It stands upon a hill, 400 feet above sea-level, in the 


not appear in the list of knights who accompanied the queen from 
Hainaut, and there is no ground for supposing that he occupied a higher 
status'than Walter Mauny, who was not knighted till 1331 (Dict. Nat. 
Biog. 36. 76), though in high favor with Philippa from the first. He is 
more likely to have been one of the ‘pluissier jone esquier’ mentioned 
above. 

*Another manuscript says, with reference to the departure of the 
Flemings (1. 194): ‘Messires Jehans de Haynau prist congiet, et s’en 
parti o toute sa compagnie de Haynau, . . . et demora li jone royne 
Phelippe a petite compagnie de son pays, formis ung jeune damoisiel que 
on clamoit Watelet de Mauni, qui y demora pour servir et taillier devant 
li’ The Walter Mauny whose name will always be remembered in con- 
nection with Philippa’s intercession for the burghers of Calais appears 
here as carving before his mistress at the table (cf. Prol. 100). He was 
not knighted till four years later (Dict. Nat. Biog. 36. 76). 

°* Monuments (see below, p. 58, note 8) 2. 834-5. 

The representation of the Latin Paganus by Paon is not easy to under- 
stand; yet, though it is customary to cite the name of Katharine’s father 
in modern books as Payne Roet, no form corresponding to Payne is 
found in the fourteenth-century texts which mention him, so far as I am 
aware. Such a form would of course be Paien(s), and this indeed occurs 
in Paiens de Maisiéres, designating a poet who flourished about 1200 
(Hist. Litt. de la France 19. 722; 20. 68); the names of four crusading 
knights who appear in the earlier French epics (Langlois, Table des 
Noms Propres dans les Chansons de Geste, p. 512); and that of Payen 
d'Orléans (Geoffroi de Villehardouin, ed. Natalis de Wailly, pp. 6, 305, 
etc.). 

® Not, as Kervyn de Lettenhove supposes, the French Reeulx, just north 
of Bouchain. 


58 Sir Paon De Ruet and Chaucer 


midst of a broken and wooded country.?. The town grew up 
around a Premonstratensian abbey founded about 1126, bearing 
the name of St. Fullan, or Foillan, an Irish missionary to this 
region, who was murdered in 655. The lords of Rceulx, who 
sprang from the counts of Hainaut, and several of whom had 
borne the name of Eustace, came to an end about 1336; but the 
lordship finally devolved in the fifteenth century upon the family 
of Croy, to which is due the existing chateau, one of the finest 
edifices in Belgium. Charles V erected the domain into a count- 
ship in 1530. Its arms are: Vert, a lion argent, armed [teeth 
and claws] and langued gules, holding in its dexter paw a wheel 
or, surmounted by a count’s coronet.* A great variety of spell- 
ings for Roeulx is found in the ancient documents, of which the 
commonest is Rues; others are: Ruet, Rueth, Ruez, Roes, Roelx, 
Roeld, Ruelt.2 It may be noted that Katharine of Lancaster’s 

name is spelled Roelt in the Patent Roll for Oct. 5, 1411.1° 
The circumstances in Hainaut which determined the knight- 
errantry of its nobles are suggested by the following passage": 
In Holland, the population was mainly burgher and peasant, while 


Hainaut was the very last stronghold*of the feudal nobility, with 
all the virtues and with all the faults of chivalry.* Spurs of the 


*Froissart mentions it in a pastourelle (Poésies, ed. Scheler, 2. 319; 
Bartsch, Altfr. Romanzen und Pastourellen, p. 328): 

Entre le Roes at la Louviere 

Vi awen desous un ourmiel, 

Ensi qu’a basse remontiere, 

Mainte touse et maint pastouriel, etc. 


La Louviére is 6 miles east of Reeulx. With the opening line compare 
Froissart’s (Bartsch, pp. 321, 323) ‘Entre Aubrecicourt et Mauni’ and 
‘Entre Eltem [Eltham] et Wesmoustier’ [Westminster]. 

*Grande Encyclopédie 28. 810; Jourdain and Van Stalle, Dict. Encye. 
de Géog. Hist. du Royaume Belgique 2. 271-2; Monuments pour servir 
a Histoire de Namur, de Hainaut, et de Luxembourg (Coll. des Chron. 
Belges) 1. 757; Larousse, Grand Dict. Univ. 13. 1291; Chevalier, 
Répertoire: Topo-Bibliographie 2. 2573; Bede, Hist. Eccl., ed. Plummer, 
2, 172: 

*See Monuments, Vols. 1 and 2; Froissart 2. 64, 113, 117; 17. 16. 

* Exc. Hist., p. 159; Rymer; Cal. Pat. Rolls. 

“Blok, Hist. of the People of the Netherlands 1. 302-6. 

“It will be remembered that this region was the home of Czsar’s 
Nervii. Holmes says (Cesar’s Conquest of Gaul, p. 53): ‘This people, 
whom of all his enemies Cesar most respected, and of whom he wrote 


—_— — 


Sir Paon De Ruet and Chaucer 59 


Ardennes made Hainaut hilly and unfit for agriculture, while the 
picturesque points of jagged rock offered many a tempting site for 
castles which could command the surrounding country from a craggy 
and easily defended height. The forests offered extensive hunting- 
grounds.” Commerce had almost no foothold; the mines were not 
exploited till a late date, and manufacture was not established until 
the fourteenth century, and then was a protected industry fostered 
by the counts. . . . The people in Hainaut remained unknown, 
while her nobles were renowned throughout Europe, and proudly 
maintained their feudal state, feudal sentiment, and feudal man- 
ners. . . . Count William I of Hainaut (1304-1337) was prominent 
in European politics, acting frequently as mediator, being brother-in- 
law to the king of France, father-in-law to the king of England and 
to the emperor. . . . Meanwhile the cities of Hainaut began to 
grow powerful in proportion as the nobles lost ground. The very 
battles in which they gained honor were their destruction; and the 
flower of Hainaut chivalry was left on the battle-fields to which their 
prowess and love of adventure had led them. 


Paon de Ruet may have been impelled to seek his fortune in 
England by the recital of the exploits of Fastré de Ruet, who 
accompanied Sir John Beaumont in 1326, when, with three hun- 
dred followers, he went to assist the English against the Scots. 
Fastré** was the younger brother of the last lord of Reeulx 
descended from the Counts of Hainaut. Both brothers fell into 
pecuniary straits, and were obliged to alienate their landed pos- 
sessions. Fastré died in 1331, and was buried in the abbey- 
church of Reeulx, while his brother Eustace survived till 1336.*° 
Perhaps Paon was, like Fastré, a younger brother, possibly of a 
collateral line. 

Of the rewards for Paon’s services in England we know almost 
nothing; only Kervyn de Lettenhove tells us (23. 38): ‘En 1332, 
un compte de la maison de la reine d’Angleterre mentionne un 


with one of those rare touches of enthusiasm that here and there relieve 
the severity of his narrative, were the Nervii.’ The battle in which 
they were overcome was fought near the present Neuf-Mesnil and Haut- 
mont (Holmes, pp. 53 ff., 654 ff.), west of Maubeuge, and 25 miles south- 
west of Reeulx. 

* The modern Hainaut is larger than Rhode Island, and smaller than 
Long Island. 

] Euoisart 2. 64,60, 454, E14, 117, 110, 122; 17. 16; Jean le Bel,-ed: 
Viard and Déprez, I. 40. 

* Froissart 23. 39-41. 


60 Sir Paon De Ruet and Chaucer 


don fait Panneto de Roed, de Hannonia. This I have not been 
able to verify. Perhaps it is on the form Panneto that Kervyn 
bases his Paonnet?® (above, p. 56). 

Ruet is reported, on the faith of a document which I have not 
seen, to have been Guienne King:of Arms as early as 1334 
(Edmondson, Complete Body of Heraldry 1. 104): ‘A grant said 
to be made by Sir Paen Roet, in 1334, to Andrew, stiles him 
expressly king of arms of the duchy of Guyenne,’* which, if it 
be not genuine, shews however the opinion of the age wherein 
that instrument was made.’ This statement, which Edmondson 
seems to doubt, is confirmed, though not with respect to the date, 
by Speght (1598), in the life of Chaucer prefixed to his edition, 
where a genealogical tree’® begins: ‘Paganus de Rouet Han- 
noniensis, aliter dictus Guien Rex Armorum.’ Just before he 

as: ‘He [Chaucer] matched in marriage with a Knight’s daugh- 
ter of Henault, called Paon de Ruet, king of Armes,”° as by this 
draught appeareth,”* taken out of the office of the Heraldes.’ 

In 1347, Ruet was at the siege of Calais, and was one of two 


“The paonnet of Rom. Rose (ed. Michel) 7390 (cf. 7400) is from 
Lat. pedonem (cf. Book of the Duchess 661), and can have no connection 
with our name. 

“Tt is certain that there was a Guienne King of Arms at the coronation 
of Henry the Fifth (1413), that Sir William Bruges held that title in 
the fifth year of his reign (Edmondson 1. 104),and that the same monarch 
was accompanied to France before Agincourt by a herald bearing that 
name (Wylie, Reign of Henry the Fifth 1. 493). 

* Hammond, Chaucer, p. 22. According to Speght (ibid., p. 24), the 
authority for this stemma was the trustworthy Somerset Herald, Robert 
Glover (1544-1588). 

1 bids, (ps23: 

” Speght’s authority was Stow, as in Annales of England, 1592 (there is 
nothing to the point in the edition of 1580), p. 517: ‘He had to wife the 
daughter of Paine Roete alias Gwine [ed. 1631, Guian] king at armes, by 
whom he had issue Tho. Chaucer.’ To the same effect Annales, 1614, pp. 
527-8. In the edition of 1631, p. 326, Stow states that he supplied the infor- 
mation to Speght from records in the Tower and elsewhere. Add Joseph 
Holland (1601), quoted by Spurgeon, Five Hundred Years of Chaucer 
Criticism, p. 167: ‘John of Ghaunt, Duke of Lancaster, married Katharine 
daughter of Guyon King of Armes in the time of K. Edward the 3, 
and Geffrey Chaucer her sister.’ Francis James, in 1638, calls Chaucer 
‘Payne Roéts Nephew’ (Spurgeon, p. 219). 

* Kervyn de Lettenhove (Froissart 23. 38) says that Ruet was thus 
designated in the English Rolls, but this I have not been able to confirm. 


——— ee ee 


Sir Paon De Ruet and Chaucer 61 


knights deputed by Queen Philippa to conduct out of town the 
citizens whom she had saved (Froissart 5. 215): 

Et au matin elle fist donner a casqun sys nobles [say, $150], et les 
fist conduire hors de l’oost par messire Sanse d’Aubrecicourt et 
messire Paon de Ruet, si avent que il vorrent, et que il fu avis as 
deus chevaliers que il estoient hors dou peril, et au departir il les 
commandérent a Dieu, et retournérent li chevalier en l’oost. 


He was still living in 1351, according to the following item 
of account quoted by Kervyn de Lettenhove (Froissart 15. 399- 
400): ‘A monseigneur Paon de Ruet, pour offrandes pour 
monseigneur le duch Willame, le duch Aubiert, et le duch Othon, 
quant il alérent en pellegrinage a Saint-Ornon a Sebourch.’ 

In 1658, Dugdale thus reports”? concerning Ruet’s tomb: 

In australi ala, navi Ecclesie opposita (prope tumulum D. Johannis 


de Bellocampo), sub lapide marmoreo, jacet Paganus Roet, Rex 
Armorum tempore Regis Edwardi tertii. 


With this may be compared the remarks of Nicolas (Aldine 
Chaucer, p. 107): 


It is remarkable that the name of Sir Payne Roet has not been found 
in any of the numerous Records that have been examined. All that 
has been discovered of him is the following statement® in Weever’s 
‘Ancient Funeral Monuments, p. 413%: ‘In St. Paul’s, near unto 
Sir John Beauchamp’s tomb, commonly called Duke Humphrey’s, 
upon a fair marble stone inlaid all over with brass (of all which 
nothing but the heads of a few brazen nails are at this day visible), 
and engraven with the representation and coat of arms of the party 
defunct, thus much of a mangled funeral inscription was of late 
times perspicuous to be read, as followeth: 


Hic Jacer Pacanus Roret Mires GuyENNE REX 
ARMORUM PATER CATHERINE DucissE LANCASTRIE.’ 


The Reeulx coat of arms seems always to have played upon the 
word for wheel.2?> Thus the modern family of Reeult, dit 
Resteau, has, for the Rceult quarterings, Gules, three wheels 
argent.2* Kervyn (Froissart, p. 462) describes the arms of 


* Hist. of St. Paul’s Cathedral, p. 55. 

8 Kirk also says (p. xvi): ‘This seems to be all that is known of him’; 
to the same effect Skeat, Oxford Chaucer t. 1. 

** This refers to the edition of 1767, edited by William Tooke. There 
is nothing on the subject in the edition of 1631. 

* Godefroy gives roelz, roeux, roeulx, as the plural of roel, Path roal. 

* Rietstap, Armorial Général. 


62 Sir Paon De Ruet and Chaucer 


Paon de Ruet as Gules, three Catherine wheels or; but this 
seems a mere inference from the arms borne by Katharine of 
Lancaster (who perhaps substituted the Catherine-wheel, with 
spikes or teeth projecting from the rim, for the ordinary form, 
in allusion,to her own name?’) and by Thomas Chaucer.** The 
same arms are assigned to Roet and Chaucer by Glover’s 
Ordinary, and to Roet and Swinford by Edmondson. 

The backward reference to Paon de Ruet from Thomas Chaucer 
depends upon the assumptions that the latter was the son of 
Philippa Chaucer, and that she was the sister of Katharine Swyn- 
ford. The arguments in favor of these assumptions have been 
summarized by Wylie (4. 313-4), with citation of the authorities, 
and may be briefly recapitulated here: 


1. The pedigree referred to above (p. 60) gives as Chaucer’s 
wife Altera®® fiiarum et coheredum Guienni Armorum Rex, and, 
as their son, Thomas Chaucer.*° 

2. The Ruet arms on Thomas Chaucer’s tomb. But this is 
no testimony to the descent from Paon de Ruet, unless we have 
independent evidence that they were borne by the latter. Such 
evidence, as we have seen, is only constructive in this case, but 
nevertheless valuable. 

3. A letter,*+ probably of 1420, from Henry Beaufort (see 
pp. 48-52) to Henry V, his half-nephew, in which he refers to 
‘my Cousin Chaucer,’ which every one interprets as meaning 
Thomas. : 

4. The seal used by Thomas Chaucer at one period of his life 
is the same as that of the poet, Per pale argent and gules, a bend 
counterchanged. This would imply that he was Chaucer’s son, 
but would have no bearing on his descent from Ruet.*? 


7 So on her tomb in the choir of Lincoln Cathedral (Exc. Hist., p. 155, 
note 2). She gave to the cathedral a variety of vestments figured with 
silver wheels (Wylie 3. 259). 

78 On his tomb at Ewelme. So Nicolas, p. 45; Dict. Nat. Biog. 10. 158. 

2° Not elder, as assumed by Nicolas (Aldine Chaucer, p. 49). 

*® Born, according to Speght (Hammond, p. 25), about 1364 or 1365. 

51 Printed by Kirk, p. 334. 

® Cf. Nicholas, p. 45; Hammond, pp. 19-20; Archeologia 34. 42; Kirk, 
PP. 333-4 (Wylie says the legend is Thomai, not Ghofrai: Atheneum, Oct. 
5, 1901). Chaucer’s tomb, on which his arms were to be found, is gen- 


~s 


— ee eee 


, 


Sir Paon De Ruet and Chaucer 63 


5. Thomas succeeded Chaucer as Forester of North Pether- 
ton, in Somersetshire. 

6. Thomas Gascoigne, Chancellor of Oxford University, posi- 
tively asserts (at some time between 1434 and 1457) that Geoffrey 
Chaucer was the father of Thomas: ‘Fuit idem Chawserus pater 
Thome Chawserus, armigeri, qui Thomas sepelitur in Nuhelm 
[Ewelme], juxta Oxoniam.’**® This, of course, proves nothing 
as to his descent from Ruet. 


To the foregoing may be added the fact discovered by Edward 
Scott,?* and published by Skeat in 1900 (Atheneum, June 27), 
that about 1422 Thomas Chaucer paid the warden of St. Mary’s 
Chapel at Westminster £1 6 8 for the rent of his house, which, 
was just half what Chaucer was to pay,°® is assumed by Skeat 
to represent a half-year’s rent. The payments continued till 
1434, in which year Thomas Chaucer died. 

This, again, proves nothing as to the descent from Ruet, which 
must therefore repose upon I, 2, and 3—the explicit assertion 
of Robert Glover, the cousinship acknowledged by Henry Beau- 
fort, and the fact that Thomas Chaucer’s arms, as found upon 
his tomb, were those of Katharine Swynford. That he was the 
son of Chaucer there seems no valid reason to doubt.*® 


erally supposed to have been erected by Nicholas Brigham in 1555 (Ham- 
mond, pp. 17, 30, 44 ff.; Dict. Nat. Biog. 6. 331); but cf. Hammond, pp. 
42-3. 

Printed by Kirk, p. 322. Hales, who prints the passage (Folia 
Literaria, p. 111, from the Atheneum for March 31, 1888), remarks: 
‘Thomas Chaucer . . . must have been well known, not only by report, 
but personally, at Oxford; for he had residences both at Woodstock, 
some seven miles north, and at Ewelme, some fifteen miles south-west, 
the direct road between Woodstock and Ewelme passing through Oxford.’ 

*4 See Coulton, Chaucer and his England, p. 73. 

“The lease to Chaucer bears date Dec. 24, 1399, and is printed, with 
comments, by Kirk, pp. 329-330. 

*For discussion of the whole subject, see Nicolas, Aldine Chaucer, pp. 
44-50, 86; Hammond, pp. 24, 47-8; Kirk, pp. li-lvii; Dict. Nat. Biog. 
10. 158-9; Lounsbury, Studies in Chaucer 1. 104 ff.; Skeat, Oxford 
Chaucer 1. 1-li; Pollard, Chaucer, pp. 9-10. 


wy ii 


Sats 


.. a ee Ma 
‘* ‘4 ail Call 
ave) ‘Hiyt oaks Lz 

io akt in aya 


“) P Ap ae baad Lips ie -f ; 


= Po _ 
x 


Epes ea tet 


oe 


vo 
2 
. 
7 
=e 
~~? 
7 
aw 
« 


Api 


a 
< 
4 
wnt 
“ 
eel 
. 
. 
he 
¢ 


‘“ mats a 7 
bd “2 
cI hack 
ttn Mie) 
« é ’ 
=s » 
be of 
e z 
= & 
4 
1 
2 is 
* 


“sf 
14 


a 
~ 


D's 


ee ee 


TRANSACTIONS OF 
mie CONNECTICUT ACADEMY 
OF ART ooo D- SCIENCES 


VOLUME 23] JANUARY 1920 [PAGES 65- 108 


Spenser’s English Rivers 


BY 


CHARLES GROSVENOR OSGOOD 


PROFESSOR OF ENGLISH IN PRINCETON UNIVERSITY 


NEW HAVEN, CONNECTICUT 
PUBLISHED BY THE 
CONNECTICUT ACADEMY OF ARTS AND SCIENCES 
AND TO BE OBTAINED ALSO FROM THE 
YALE UNIVERSITY PRESS 


41 


SPENSER’S ENGLISH RIVERS 


Critics of Spenser have often remarked that he is eminently a 
pictorial poet. His poetry is like a gallery crowded with pictures 
of all kinds—portrait, genre, landscape, free invention—ever 
varied in their composition, spirit, and significance. To the 
restricted uses of mural decoration his designs are admirably 
suited, and one wonders that mural painters, as they confront 
great wall-spaces teeming with possibilities unrealized, have not 
discovered the vast riches lying at arm’s length in the poetry of 
Spenser. No other poet is more fertile in designs which, both in 
subject and manner, would lend themselves to this kind of paint- 
ing. They are highly objectified, symmetrical, spectacular, and 
vivid with color and motion. Spenser’s art is in a peculiar meas- 
ure decorative. Surely it was in large part this excellence of 
the poet in pictorial pageantry that delighted Milton with his 


Pomp, and feast, and revelry, 
With mask and antique pageantry, 
Such sights as youthful poets dream 
On summer eves, by haunted stream. 


Some of Spenser’s greatest and most conspicuous passages are 
in their primary effect spectacular. They present a crowded 
stage filled with gorgeous, rapidly shifting color. Among his 
favorite themes are elaborate tableaux, visionary and emblematic, 
or thronging processions, or glimpses of a crumbling antique 
world, fading in rich and solemn splendor. Examples will multi- 
ply in the mind of every reader, from the fanciful idylls in the 
April and the June eclogue of the Shepherd’s Calendar, to the 
highly wrought wedding-procession in the Epithalamion. 

In each book of the Faery Queen the poet has introduced one 
or more conspicuous examples of elaborated spectacle. In the 
First Book are the procession of the Seven Deadly Sins and the 
series of episodes in the House of Holiness; in the Second, the 
Cave of Mammon, the House of Temperance, the Voyage of 
Life, and the Bower of Bliss; in the Third, the Gardens of 
Adonis, the House of Busirane, and the Mask of Cupid; in the 
Fifth, the Wedding of Florimel, the Temple of Isis, and the 
Hall of Mercilla; in the Sixth, the Dance of the Graces; in 
the fragment of the so-called Seventh, the Trial of Mutability. 


68 Charles G. Osgood, 


The Fourth Book presents the Temple of Venus, and what may 
be described as the purest example of pageant which Spenser has 
given us; that is, a procession devoid of symbolism or implied 
significance. So purely spectacular is it that, in at least one 
critic’s opinion, it may have been modeled after some contem- 
porary mask.’ It is the pageant of sea-gods, rivers, and nymphs 
coming to attend the marriage of the river Medway with the 
Thames in the hall of Proteus. First appear the sea-gods—Nep- 
tune and Amphitrite, Phorcys, Brontes, Orion, the many ruling 
sons of Neptune, and the rest. Then follow the great rivers, the 
Nile, the Rhone, the Ister, and some dozen more, including Orin- 
oco, ‘though but knowen late.’ In another group are enumerated 
the many English rivers, led by the bridegroom, Thames. “Ne 
thence the Irishe rivers absent were,’ but are told to the number 
of hearly twenty. Following these is the bride, attended by her 
tributaries, after whom troops a host of sea-nymphs, over fifty 
of whom Spenser calls by name, and the air is astir with the roar 
of Triton’s horn or the softer murmurings of Amphion’s harp. 

In a learned and charming article in Fraser’s Magazine for 
1878,2 P. W. Joyce has considered that part of the eleventh canto 
of the Fourth Book® which deals with the Irish rivers, identifying 
those which are not apparent, and explaining epithets and allu- 
sions. He writes with the authority of one who has traversed the 
ground, and viewed with his own eye the regions of which he 
speaks. This was necessary to a full explanation of the passage, 
since it is evident that Spenser himself depended in writing it 
much less upon printed accounts and hearsay than upon his own 
observation, and his familiarity with the scenes themselves. 

The case of the English rivers is different. Though the pas- 
sage devoted to them—stanzas 23-39—is more than three times 
as long as that which describes the Irish rivers, it wants the 
peculiar freshness and spontaneity of the other, which doubtless 
came from the poet’s familiarity with the rivers themselves, and 
indeed from his undisguised love of his Irish home. The passage 
about the English rivers, for all its lovely movement and cadence, 


*O. Elton, Introduction to Michael Drayton, Spenser Soc. Pub., extra 
number, p. 38. Cf. H. R. Patch, Modern Language Notes 35. 178. 

*\N. S. vol. 17, pp. 315-333. 

*Stanzas 40-44. 


Poa bel 


Spenser's English Rivers. 69 


breathes in comparison a faint odor of lucubration and bookish- 
ness. 

And bookish it proves, both by the poet’s own statement and 
by detailed analysis. In an oft-quoted passage from a letter to 
Harvey dated ‘Quarto Nonas Aprilis,* 1580, Spenser writes: 
‘I minde shortely at convenient leysure, to sette forth a Booke in 
this kinde, whiche I entitle Epithalamion Thamesis; whyche 
Booke, I dare undertake wil be very profitable for the knowledge, 
and rare for the Invention and manner of handling. For in 
setting forth the marriage of the Thames: I shewe his first begin- 
ning, and offspring, and all the Countrey, that he passeth 
thorough, and also describe all the Rivers throughout Englande, 
whyche came to this Wedding, and their righte names, and right 
passage, &c. A worke, beleeve me, of much labour, wherein not- 
withstanding Master Holinshed hath muche furthered and advan- 
taged me, who therein hath bestowed singular paines, in searching 
oute their firste heades and sources: and also in tracing and 
dogging oute all their Course, til they fall into the Sea.” 

The English rivers named by Spenser in his pageant of the 
marriage of the Medway and the Thames are in most cases easily 
recognized and traceable on any good modern map. Several there 
are, however, whose identity is not clear, and various details of 
the passage require explanation. It has long been observed that 
the Epithalamion Thamesis probably bears some precedent rela- 
tion to the bridal passage before us. Setting aside for the 
moment the question of this relationship, the poet’s hint in the 
passage quoted points any inquirer concerning the meaning of his 
lines in the Faery Queen on English rivers to Holinshed’s Chron- 
icles, where he finds a part—perhaps half—of the light he seeks. 
It is found in chapters 11 to 16 of the First Book, entitled “The 
Description of Britain.’ This part, as is well known, was written 


* April 2. 

° Works of Spenser, Globe ed., p. 709. In the second chapter of her 
study on The Sources of the British Chronicle History in the Faerte 
Queene (pp. 10-22), Dr. Carrie A. Harper quotes this passage, and makes 
several scattered notes on the sources of Spenser’s knowledge of English 
rivers. She finds that while, of course, he referred to the first edition, 
1577, of Holinshed’s Chronicles in the passage of 1580 just quoted, yet 
in arranging the pageant of English rivers of the Fourth Book he used 
the edition of 1587. 


70 Charles G. Osgood, 


by William Harrison, but is here sometimes cited as ‘Holinshed’ 
for convenience. 

For the rest a hint is given in the Ruins of Time. The poem 
is essentially the monody of a grief-stricken woman, who is the 
genius of the ancient city of Verulam, lamenting dead members 
of the Dudley family, especially Sir Philip Sidney. Some one 
hundred and twenty verses she devotes to a recital of her own 
history, her past glories and particularly her woes. This recital 
concludes (166-75) with an apostrophe to William Camden as 


the only 
one, that maugre Fortunes injurie 
And Times decay, and Envies cruell tort, 
Hath writ my record in true-seeming sort. 


Cambden, the nourice cf antiquitie, 

And lanterne unto late succeeding age, 

To see the light of simple veritie 

Buried in ruines, through the great outrage 
Of her owne people, led with warlike rage, 
-Cambden, though Time all moniments obscure, 
Yet thy just labours ever shall endure. 


This amounts almost to a statement that Spenser learned what 
he has to say of Verulam from Camden. That this is true but 
in part will appear later in the present discussion. For the 
moment it is enough to follow the poet’s hint, and to discover that 
something like half his material about the English rivers he owes 
to Camden’s Britannia.® 

But beyond his use of books, Spenser knew at first hand some 
of the English rivers which he mentions, though not so many as in 
the case of the Irish rivers. One who dwells on this subject, 
therefore, must be aware that in studying the geography of 
Spenser he could profitably visit some of the regions mentioned 
by the poet, and see for himself what Spenser saw. In default of 


® William Camden’s Britannia first appeared in 1586, and other editions 
in Spenser’s lifetime followed in 1587, 1590, and 1594. I have usually 
quoted from the first translation, by Philemon Holland, 1610, said to have 
been overseen by Camden himself. But all quoted passages have been 
compared with the Latin original in the edition of 1590, and where the 
original differs significantly from the translation, I have given the Latin 
version as that which the poet used. Miss Harper observes some traces 
of help from the Britannia in Spenser’s stanzas on the Irish rivers, and 
merely intimates, without demonstration (p. 17), that he read in it also 
for his knowledge of English rivers. 


a 


a 


Spenser's English Rivers. 71 


such an advantage, I have followed Bartholomew’s half-inch-to- 
the-mile maps, based on the ordnance-maps, and occasionally the 
ordnance-maps themselves, and have consulted various choro- 
graphic works. The results may perhaps be most conveniently 
presented in the form of quotation and running comment. 

First came the bridegroom, 


The noble Thamis, with all his goodly traine; 

But him before there went, as best became, 

His auncient parents, namely th’ auncient Thame: 

But much more aged was his wife then he, 

The Ouze, whom men doe Isis rightly name; 

Full weake and crooked creature seemed shee, 

And almost blind through eld, that scarce her way could see.” 


Harrison writes of the Thames: ‘I affirme that this famous 
streame hath his head or beginning out of the side of an hill, 
standing in the plaines of Cotswold, about one mile from 
Tetburie, . . . where it was sometime named Isis, or the Ouse, 
although diverse doo ignorantlie call it the Thames even there, 
rather of a foolish custome than anie skill, bicause they either 
neglect or utterlie are ignorant how it was named at the first.’* 
And later: ‘From hence [Abingdon] it goeth to Dorchester, and 
so to Thame, where joining with a river of the same denomina- 
tion, it looseth the name of Isis or Ouse (whereof Ouseneie at 
Oxford is producted) and from thenceforth is called Thamesis.’ 
And again (p. 84), the Isis ‘beneath Dorchester taketh in the 
Thame water, from whence the Isis loseth the preheminence of 
the whole denomination of this river, and is contented to impart 
the same with the Thame, so that by the conjunction of these 
two waters Thamesis is producted.’ Camden says: ‘A little 
beneath this towne Tame and Isis meeting in one streame 
become hand-fast (as it were) and joyned in Wedlocke: and 
as'in waters, so in name, they are coupled. . . . For ever after 
this, the river by a compound word is called, Tamisis, that is, 
Tamis’ (p. 384, Oxfordshire). He then quotes at considerable 
length from a Latin poem, on the wedding of the Isis and the 
Thame, from which he cites other passages elsewhere.® In that 


SE. 24. 

*Vol. 1, p. 79. I cite from the edition of 1807. 

° See below, p. 103, for the contents of the fragments in Camden, and 
n. 67 on the question of authorship. 


ty 


~I 


Charles G. Osgood, 


poem, however, Isis is the groom and Thame the bride. Spenser 
may have got from it a suggestion both of subject and method 
of treatment, as Upton thinks,!° but he borrowed no details 
except possibly one in the picture of the Medway.” 

As for the ‘weake and crooked’ Isis, that “scarce her way 
could see,’ Harrison carefully describes her deviousness just 
above and about Oxford; but Spenser is almost certainly writ- 
ing with a map before him, as is indicated by various details in 
his account. Here his characterization would be readily sug- 
gested by the crooked course of the Isis on the map. That the 
map was one of Christopher Saxton’s, who published his port- 
folio of maps of sections of England in 1579, to which Camden 
often refers, is almost certain.’ 

Therefore on either side she was sustained 
Of two smal grooms, which by their names were hight 


* The Churne and Charwell, two small streames, which pained 
Them selves her footing to direct aright.” 


‘From hence [Tetbury] it runneth directlie toward the east 
(as all good rivers should) and meeteth with the Cirne or 
Churne’ (Hol. 1. 79). ‘It passeth at length by Oxford, of some 
supposed rather to be called Ouseford of this river, where it 
meeteth with the Charwell’ (Hol. 1. 79). On page 82 Harrison 
traces in detail the course of the Churne, and on pages 83-4 that 
of the Cherwell. On the map it readily appears that Isis was 
sustained on either side by these smaller streams. 


But Thame was stronger, and of better stay. 


Thame is, of course, the smaller stream, and, as we have seen, 
“in the old poem is the bride of Isis. Spenser may have reversed 
the relation because Isis is feminine in implication, and because 
the name of Thame dominates the new name Thames. And 
to emphasize this reversal he has insisted upon the feebleness of 
Isis, and, contrary to fact, upon the greater strength of Thame. 

Whether purposely or by mistake, he contradicts himself in 
stanza 26, making it the Thame, not the Isis, which flows by 


2% Note on F. Q. IV. xi. 8. 3, in Todd’s Spenser 5. 431. 

See below, p. 90. 

” Many of Saxton’s maps reappear in Holland’s translation of Camden, 
from which I quote. 

<St. 25. 


Spenser's English Rivers. 73 


Oxford, though in stanza 25, by mention of the Cherwell, whose 
mouth is in the lower end of Oxford, the river is there the Isis. 


And eke he somewhat seem’d to stoupe afore 
With bowed backe, by reason of the lode 

And auncient heavy burden which he bore 

Of that faire city, wherein make abode 

So many learned impes, that shoote abrode, 
And with their braunches spred all Britany, 
No lesse then do her elder sisters broode.™ 


In Saxton’s map the courses of the Isis near Oxford are 
shown more in a southeasterly than a southerly direction, as 
on the modern maps. Oxford is represented by a group of 
towers, and the effect of the whole is exactly that of a laboring 
back bent under the ‘auncient heavy burden’ of the ‘faire city.’ 

In stanza 28 Thames is crowned with towers, that is, with 
Troynovant or London. The idea is obviously classical, but is 
clearly illustrated in Saxton’s way of indicating more important 
cities, by crowded clusters of towers arranged coronet-wise.’® 
His crown seems to mark him as the chief and king of the 
attendant English rivers (cf. st. 30), illustrating Camden’s 
phrase, ‘fluminum Britannicorum regnator’ (ed. 1590, Glouces- 
Beramite, p.-207 ; cf. p: 173): 

Thames is attended by many little rivers, which ‘owe vassal- 
age to him’: 

The chaulky Kenet, and the Thetis gray, 
The morish Cole, and the soft sliding Breane, 
The wanton Lee, that oft doth loose his way, 


And the still Darent, in whose waters cleane 
Ten thousand fishes play, and decke his pleasant streame.“ 


These tributaries are named by Spenser in order of their 
occurrence on the course of the Thames toward the sea. 
‘Chaulky Kenet’ is obviously the Kennet, which joins the Thames 
at Reading. Holinshed does not call it chalky, except to speak 
of its ‘taking the Chalkburne rill withall’ (1. 85). Camden, 
mentioning Marlborough on its upper waters, is not sure whether 


Sti Ao 

* For Cambridge as the ‘elder sister’, see below, p. 82. 
matast: 34, 17; 

Pest. 26: 


74 Charles G. Osgood, 


it takes its name from marl: ‘Marleborow, olim Marleberge. 

An hoc recentius factum fuerit nomen a Marga, quam 
Marle nostra lingua dicimus, . . . non facile dixerim’ (1590, 
Wiltshire, pp. 184, 5). In MHolland’s translation is added: 
‘Certes, it lieth neere a chaulkey hill, which our Ancestours before 
they borrowed this name Chaulke of the Latine word Calsx; 
named Marle’ (Wiltshire, p. 255). 

‘Thetis gray’ is the least of all this group. It is the modern 
Wye, which meets the Thames from the north at Bourne End, 
near Hedsor. Harrison twice refers to it—once at 1. 80: ‘the 
Thetis commonlie called the Tide that commeth from Thetis- 
ford’; and again at 1. 86: ‘It [Thames] meeteth with a brooke 
soone after that consisteth of the water of two rilles, whereof 
the one called the Use, riseth about west Wickham [mod. West 
Wycombe], out of one of the Chilterne hilles, and goeth from 
thence to east Wickham or high Wickham, a pretie market towne. 
The other named Higden, descendeth also from those mounteines 
but a mile beneath west Wickham, and joining both in one at the 
last, in the west end of east Wickham towne [High Wycombe], 
they go togither to Wooburne, Hedsor, & so into the Thames. 
Some call it the Tide; and that word doo I use in my former 
treatise.’ Higden survives in the name of the village Hugh- 
endon, on the north branch of the little stream, but I find no 
name Thetisford on the modern map. Why Thetis is called 
‘gray’ I do not know. 

‘Morish Cole’ is the Colne, which meets Thames from the 
north at Staines. ‘Morish’ in Spenser means ‘marshy,’!$ and 
the epithet may well describe the Colne valley as it was in 
Spenser’s time. In Leland’s Itinerary (Ed. T. Smith 1. 105) 
Colne is called ‘the moore water.’ 

‘Soft sliding Breane’ is probably the old Brane or modern 
Brent. Harrison says (1. 87): ‘The next fall of water is at 
Sion [cf. modern Sion House], neere unto new Brainford, so 
that it issueth into the Thames between them both. This water 
is called Brane, that is in the Brittish toong (as Leland saith) a 
frog. It riseth about Edgeworth [Edgeware], and commeth 
from thence by Kingesburie, Twiford, Perivall, Hanwell, and 
Austerleie [Osterley].’ Spenser may himself have observed that 
it is ‘soft sliding.’ 


* Cf. Vergii’s Gnat 251; Ruins of Time 140; F. QO. V. x. 18, 4. 


Spenser's English Rivers. 75 


‘Wanton Lee’ is obvious. Though Holinshed does not speak 
of its wantonness, his long description (1. 87-9) supports 
Spenser’s line. Saxton’s, or any other map, makes his charac- 
terization even more evident. The river first flows generally 
southeast for some fifteen miles, then east and northeast about 
ten, to Ware, then, by a wide bend, to the southeast and south 
towards its mouth at Blackwall. Camden speaks of its hastening 
‘with a merry glee’ to the Thames—‘Lea jam letior ad Tamesim 
properat’ (1590, Hertfordshire, p. 313). 

Of ‘still Darent’ Camden says it ‘runneth with a soft streame’ 
(Kent, p. 328). Its course through Kent to the Thames near 
Dartford is fully described by Holinshed (p. 89), but neither 
he nor Camden speaks of its fish. This and the beauty of the 
country the poet had opportunity to observe for himself. 

The ‘stately Severne’ (st. 30) needs no comment. MHolinshed 
says that in many respects ‘it commeth farre behind the Thames,’ 
though in others ‘it is nothing at all inferiour,’ and calls it a 
‘noble streame’ (I. 117). For the Humber see the comment on 
stanza 38. 

There was the speedy Tamar, which devides 
The Cornish and the Devonish confines; 
Through both whose borders swiftly downe it glides, 


And meeting Plim, to Plimmouth thence declines: 
And Dart, nigh chockt with sand of tinny mines.” 


‘The river Tamara, now Tamar,’ says Camden, ‘shewing his 
head heere not farre from the northern shore, taketh his course 
with a swift running streame southward’ (Cornwall, p. 196). 
Both he and Harrison (1. 104) speak of it as the boundary 
between Devonshire and Cornwall.2° Neither describes it as 
joining the Plim; indeed, Harrison makes clear the contrary. 
Spenser, in a hurried glance at the map, may have confused the 
Plim and the Tavy, which meets with the Tamar in the upper 
reaches of Plymouth Bay, or he may have thought of the narrow 
bay as the Plim River above Plymouth. Saxton’s map favors 
such an error. More likely, however, Spenser is here careless, 
as in stanzas 25 and 34. 


pet3i- 
” This fact and the following inaccuracy are noted by Dr. Harper, 


Dp. 12,17. 


76 Charles G. Osgood, 


Of the Dart Holinshed says: ‘Of it selfe moreover this water 
is verie swift, and thorough occasion of tin-workes whereby it 
passeth, it carrieth much sand to Totnesse bridge [near its 
mouth], and so choketh the depth of the river downeward, that 
the haven it selfe is almost spoiled by the same’ (1. 103).*4 

But Avon marched in more stately path, 
Proud of his adamants, with which he shines 


And glisters wide, as als’ of wondrous Bath, 
And Bristow faire, which on his waves he builded hath.” 


Holinshed calls the Avon ‘a goodlie water, and growne to be 
verie famous by sundrie occasions’ (1. 115), and Camden writes 
of ‘the noble river Avon: which holding a crooked course, 
runneth anon to that ancient City which of the hote Bathes. 
we_at this day [call] Bath’ (Somerset, p. 233). Then follow 
long descriptions of the glories of Bath and Bristol (pp. 233-9). 
As the Avon leaves Bristol, ‘there are on ech side very high 
cliffes . . . the one of them which on the East-side overlooketh 
the river beareth the name S. Vincent's rock, so full of Diamants 
[adamantum adeo foecunda, p. 173], that a man may fill whole 
strikes or bushels of them. These are not so much set by, 
because they be so plenteous. For in bright and transparent 
colour they match the Indian diamants, 1f they passe them not: 
in hardnesse onely they are inferior to them; but in that nature 
her selfe hath framed them pointed with six cornered or foure 
cornered smooth sides; I thinke them therefore worthy to be 
had in greater admiration. The other rocke also on the West- 
side is likewise full of Diamants [adamantum est ferax, p. 172], 
which by the wonderfull skill and worke of nature, are enclosed 
as young ones within the bowels of hollow and reddish flints.’ 
Camden is speaking of the valley-walls underneath Clifton 
Downs, a suburb of Bristol. In Saxton’s map of Somerset both 
Bath and Bristol are shown by clusters of towers rising from the 
line of the river. 

And there came Stoure with terrible aspect, 
Bearing his sixe deformed heads on hye, 


That doth his course through Blandford plains direct, 
And washeth Winborne meades in season drye.” 


* Quoted by Dr. Harper, pp. 12-14. 
“aS eal 
* Ste 32 


Spenser’s English Rivers. 77 


This is the Stour in Dorset. Harrison describes it (1. 98) as 
‘a verie faire streame,’ and says: ‘It riseth of six heads,” 
whereof three lie on the north side of the parke at Sturton within 
the pale, the other rise without the parke; & of this river the 
towne and baronie of Sturton dooth take his name as I| gesse, for 
except my memorie do too much faile me, the lord Sturton 
giveth the six heads of the said water in his armes.’ He was 
right: the arms of Baron Mowbray, Segrave, and Stourton, 
are to-day ‘quarterly of six; Ist sable, a bend or, between six 
fountains.*° When Spenser describes Stour ‘with terrible 
aspect, Bearing his sixe deformed heads on hye,’ he may be 
framing a heraldic compliment to the then Lord Stourton.** Or 
more likely Stour’s ‘terrible aspect,’ as Joyce suggests, is another 
instance of Spenser’s fondness for etymology in proper names.‘ 
The word ‘stour,’ meaning variously ‘struggle,’ ‘agony,’ “‘parox- 
ysm, ‘terrifying menace,’ is a favorite of Spenser’s; he uses it 
more than fifty times. 

By Blandford plains, which are not especially mentioned in 
either Holinshed or Camden, Spenser may mean the broad open 
country, four or five miles above Blandford, traversed by the 
Stour, the Cale, and the Lydden; or more likely the region just 
below Blandford, where the valley spreads into a wide plain 
towards Wimborne Minster, Spenser’s Winborne. Leland 
remarks that ‘the soile about Winburn Minstre self is very good 
for corne, grass and woodde.’** 


rT 


Next him went Wylibourne with passage slye, 
That of his wylinesse his name doth take, 
And of him selfe doth name the shire thereby.” 


** Quoted by Dr. Harper, p. 12. 

~ Debrett’s Peerage, s. v. Mowbray. The six springs which form the 
northern sources of the Stour are all now within Stourton Park (Bae- 
deker, Great Britain, 1906, p. 111). The modern map shows a string of 
little ponds lying in the park, along what is called Six Wells Bottom. 

* This was Edward, ninth baron, who married Frances, daughter of 
Sir Thomas Tresham. He was of no eminence, but his father was one 
of the peers who sat at the trial of Mary Queen of Scots. His grand- 
father had been hanged for murder. 

* Joyce cites ‘Tygris fierce’ (IV. xi. 20. 9), Wylibourne and Mole 
(IV. xi. 32), Trent (IV. xi. 35. 8), Stour, and among the Irish rivers 
‘sad Trowis’ (41. 7), ‘balefull Oure’ (44. 5), and ‘false Bregog’ (VII. vi. 
40. 4). Perhaps one may add Wharf, Dee, and Humber; see below. 

* Itinerary, ed. Smith, vol. 1, p. 256. 

Se 32. 


78 Charles G. Osgood, 


This is the modern Wylye, which flows from the northwest to 
meet the Avon at Salisbury. Camden, speaking of Wiltshire 
plains, says: ‘On the South side thereof, there runne quietly two 
most still Rivers, Willey-borne. . . and Nadder.’ The Nadder 
is so called from its serpentine windings. Spenser seems to 
invent, as he is always ready to do, the explanation of the name 
Wylibourne. Camden adds: ‘At the meeting of these two rivers 
Willey giveth his name to Wilton, a place well watered, and 
sometime the head towne of the whole Shire, which thereof tooke 
the name’ (Wiltshire, pp. 245-6). So unimportant a stream as 
the Wylye may well have found its place in the procession by 
way of honor to Mary Sidney, Countess of Pembroke, who lived 
at Wilton House, on its banks. 


And Mole, that like a nousling mole doth make 
His way still under ground, till Thamis he overtake. 


This is the modern Mole, which flows from north of Dorking, 
Surrey, and joins the Thames at Hampton Court. Spenser 
doubtless found the reason for its name in Camden: ‘Within 
some few miles from thence the river Mole, having from the 
South side passed through the whole country, hasteneth to joine 
with the Tamis; but at length beeing letted by overthwart hils, 
maketh him selfe a way under the ground in manner of a mould- 
warp; ... whereof it may seeme it tooke name, seeing that 
creature living within the ground, is called also in English a 
Mole’ (Surrey, p. 296). On Norden’s map of Surrey*® this 
interruption of the Mole’s course is indicated at Mickleham, but 
I find no modern mention of it. At this point the river swings a 
half mile out of its general direction around a rise of ground, 
From Camden’s indefinite statement Spenser proceeds to repre- 
sent that much of the river’s course runs underground. 

Then came the Rother, decked all with woods 

Like a wood god, and flowing fast to Rhy: 

And Sture, that parteth with his pleasant floods 

The easterne Saxons from the southerne ny, 

And Clare and Harwitch both doth beautify: 

Him follow’d Yar, soit washing Norwitch wall 

And with him brought a present joyfully 

Of his owne fish unto their festivall, 

Whose like none else could shew, the which they ruffins call.” 


1610, in Speed’s Theatre. 
Sian 


30 


Spenser's English Rivers. 79 


The Rother is perhaps thirty miles long, and flows southeast 
into the Channel. Thus Holinshed, who calls it ‘a noble river’: 
“This Rother separateth Sussex from Kent, and hath his head in 
Sussex, not farre from Argas hill neere to Waterden forrest.’ 
He then traces its old course, to a point in its lower waters; 
‘hence also growing into some greatnesse, it runneth to Rie’ (1. 
92). The interior of Sussex, the region of Ashdown Forest, 
where the Rother takes its rise, was famous for its woods. 
Camden says: ‘Citerior et Borealis tractus sylvarum opacitate 
amecenissimus uti olim universa hec regio, SE invia fuerat’ 
(1590, Sussex, p. 227). 

‘The Sture or Stoure parteth Essex from Suffolke, as Hove- 
den saith, and experience confirmeth’ (Hol. 1.177). And Cam- 
den: ‘This is the Stour, that running betweene Essex and 
Suffolke serveth as a bound to them both, and on'this side [Essex] 
watereth nothing else but rich and fruitfull fields’ (Essex, p. 
451). Camden mentions its mouth, ‘where now lieth Harewich 


a most safe road.’ Harrison, in describing the river’s course, 


mentions both Clare and Harwich. 

The Yar is modern Yare, Norfolk. Strictly speaking the 
Yare does not come within a mile or two of ‘soft washing Nor- 
witch wall,’ but it generally encircles the southern half of the 
town at about that distance, from west to east, where it receives 
the Wensum, just below the city to the east. On Saxton’s map 
it appears to touch the city. The Yare is described by Camden 
as ‘Ruffo pisce admodum fcecundus’ (1590, Norfolk, p. 374). 
In Holland’s version of 1610 this phrase is expanded into a 
description of the ruff, as a kind of perch, ‘much commended 
for holsomnesse; and for eating tender & short’ (Norfolk, p. 
476). That Spenser was an angler and curious about varieties of 
fish none of his readers can doubt. The New English Diction- 
ary records the form ‘ruffin’ as ‘obs. rare,’ and the line in 
Spenser is the first of only two quotations. 

Next these the plenteous Ouse came far from land, 
- By many a city, and by many a towne, 

And many rivers taking under hand 

Into his waters, as he passeth downe, 

The Cle, the Were, the Grant, the Sture, the Rowne 

Thence doth by Huntingdon and Cambridge fiit, 

My mother Cambridge, whom as with a crowne 

He doth adorne, and is adorn’d of it 

With many a gentle n muse, =, and many a learned w it. o 


bd 


Bats 34: 


80 Charles G. Osgood, 


This general description of the Ouse is illustrated by any map. 
The tributaries, however, offer some difficulty. The Cle, or Clee 
in Holinshed, is the modern Ouzel or Lovat, as appears by his 
description (1. 173): ‘This river riseth in the verie confines be- 
tweene Buckingham and Bedfordshires, not farre from Whip- 
pesnade [modern Whipsnade on the heights three miles south of 
Dunstable], and going on toward the northwest, by Eaton [Eaton 
Bray ?] and Laiton [Leighton Buzzard], it commeth to Linchlade 
[Linslade], where it entreth whollie into Buckinghamshire, and 
so goeth on by Hammond [Stoke Hammond], Brickle [ Brickhill, 
Great and Little], Fennie Stratford, Simpson, Walton, and 
Middleton [Milton Keynes], . . . and so goeth on till it meet 
with the Ouze neere unto Newport |Newport Pagnell].’ 

The Were is the modern Tove, which joins the Ouze from the 
northwest, near Stony Stratford and Wolverton, some five or 
six miles above the Ouzel. ‘Here,’ says Holinshed (1. 173), ‘the 
Ouze meeteth with a water (called, as Leland conjectureth, the 
Vere or Were) on the left hand, as you go downewards, that 
commeth betweene Wedon [Weedon Lois] and Wexenham [Wap- 
penham?]| in Northamptonshire, and goeth by Towcester, and 
Alderton, and not farre from Wolverton and Haversham into 
the foresaid Ouze, which goeth also from hence to Newport- 
paganell.’ Then follows the account of the Clee. 

The Grant is, of course, the modern Granta or Cam, flowing 
through Cambridge. As you go upstream, about three miles 
south of Cambridge, and nearly a mile above Grantchester, the 
river is divided: one branch (a) comes from Ashwell and the 
southwest, and on modern maps is named the Cam or Rhee; 
another comes from the southeast, which two or three miles 
above, near Stapleford, is again divided, one branch (b) flowing 
from Great Chesterford and the south, and now named on some 
maps Cam, on others Granta; the other branch (c) flowing from 
Linton and the southeast, and now named Granta. Below the 
junction where all these streams are united in one, the river is 
the Cam or Granta until after passing Cambridge, when it is 
simply the Cam. In Holinshed (i. 173-5) the name Cam does 
not occur; (a) is called the Rhee or Barrington Water, (b) the 
Granta, and (c) the Babren. As Harrison, author of the 
description in Holinshed, had studied at Cambridge, and by his 
own statement (1. 174) had viewed this region at least in part, 


Spenser's English Rivers. 81 


and as Spenser from his days at Cambridge was likely to know 
it as well as any part of England, it is fairly safe to infer that by 
the Grant he meant (b) the southerly branch. Yet his state- 
ments grow careless in the last lines of the stanza. 

In Holinshed the Granta is traced in its course among the 
colleges through Cambridge, ‘receiving by and by the Stoure, 
or Sture (at whose bridge the most famous mart in England is 
yearlie holden and kept)’ (1. 174). This is the famous Stour- 
bridge Fair, on the lower side of Cambridge. But the little 
Stour, tiniest of all Spenser’s rivers, seems now to be lost in the 
ditches. 

The Rowne is a mystery; it is mentioned in neither Holinshed 
nor Camden, nor in any of the books or maps of the time that I 
have seen. I suspect that ‘Rowne’ is a misprint for ‘Downe,’ 
which might easily have been made by the printer to avoid what 
looked to him like an identical rhyme. Such rhymes, however, 
are not infrequent in Spenser.*® The Downe, or Dune, is, by 
the description in Holinshed (1. 175), clearly the Little Ouse, 
which rises in Suffolk in the same source as the Waveney, but 
flows west, while the Waveney flows east. It meets the Ouse 
more than twenty miles below Cambridge. “The Dune,’ writes 
Harrison, ‘goeth first of all by Feltham [Thelnetham?], then to 
Hopton, & to Kinets hall [Knettishall],’? thence on to Euston, 
receiving various tributaries. ‘From hence also they hasten to 
Downeham,’ that is, Santon Downham, clearly marked ‘Dowen- 
ham’ on Saxton’s map, between Thetford and Brandon, and so 
through the fens to its mouth. 

Spenser’s ‘thence’ in line 6 is careless, as one, and probably 
two, of the rivers mentioned are below Cambridge. Further- 
more, he speaks of the Ouse as if it passed Cambridge, as well 
as Huntington. For the moment he implies that the name Ouse 
covered not only the main river, but the whole system. 


* Thus in this Fourth Book we have went, n.: went, v., in lines 4 and 5 
as here, of stanza 47 of canto 11; morne:morne, st. 41 (really concat- 
enation) ; sound, n.: sound, v., IV. vii. 4. 8, 9; between alternate lines, 
erines. 5) 7 th. 30, 5507 ells 9.0, Ge due EGe ee Vv. 33.5, 75 vil. 30.2, 4; 
identical rhymes more widely separated abound: i. 24. 2, 7; 35. 2, 7; 
Maan: i 0.10, 0; 37-.0, 03 Agu495.-52. 2,9, etc. In the Fourth Book 
identical lines average about two and one half to a canto. The number 
is more than doubled if one includes such rhymes as bound: abound, 
1, 13; along: long, x. 7. 


82 Charles G. Osgood, 


The reference to Cambridge, like that in stanza 26, is alto- 
gether in the spirit of Camden, who pauses in his description to 
glorify the town and the university. His words are in one or 
two details close to Spenser’s: ‘Cis pontem, ubi urbis pars longe 
maxima jacet, platearum descriptione, templorum frequentia et 
quatuordecim pulcherrimis Musarum sacrariis, sive Collegiis 
omnia nitent, in quibus eruditissimi viri magno numero aluntur’ ; 
cf. Spenser’s ‘With many a gentle muse, and many a learned 
wit’; ‘maximarumque artium scientia, et linguarum cognitio ita 
florent, ut literarum, religionis, et totius doctrine fontes jure op- 
timo censeantur, qui ecclesiz et Reipub. hortos salutaribus aquis 
suavissime irrorant’ (1590, p. 384).°* In stanza 26 Spenser calls 
Cambridge the ‘elder sister’ of Oxford. The phrase had more 
significance than a casual reader might suspect, prompted as 
it doubtless was by the contest for seniority then raging between 
the two universities.*° Camden says (1590, pp. 344-5): ‘Verum 
ne in optimos illos literarum patronos, imo (ut cum Eumenio 
loquar) liberorum nostrorum parentes pessime ingrati videamur, 
ipsos et Collegia, que bonis literis consecrarunt, honoris caussa 
ex historia Cantabrigiensi summatim memoremus. Cantabrum 
Hispanum anno ante Christum natum 375. Academiam hanc 
primum instituisse, et Sebertum Orientalium Anglorum regem 
post Christum 630 restituisse perhibetur.’ In Holland’s transla- 
tion, which Camden is thought to have overseen, the author 
discredits this tradition, and fears to become involved in the 
controversy. The question is also raised by Holinshed in his 
chapter on the Universities (Bk. 2, chap. 3, p. 249), who seems 
to favor the seniority of Cambridge. 


And after him the fatall Welland went, 

That if old sawes prove true (which God forbid) 
Shall drowne all Holland with his excrement, 

And shall see Stamford, though now homely hid, 
Then shine in learning, more then ever did 
Cambridge or Oxford, Englands goodly beames.* 


** For Cambridge as a crown to the river, see above, comment on st. 28. 

% An account of this controversy is given in J. Parker’s The Early 
History of Oxford, pp. 20 ff. It began as early as 1566, or even earlier 
(cf. Polydore Vergil, Historia, Basel, 1555, p. 107), and was very lively 
when Spenser died. 

Othe 


Spenser's English Rivers. 83 


The material for this stanza is found in neither Camden or 
Holinshed. The prophecy that the Welland would drown that 
part of Norfolk called Holland I have not found in any earlier 
writer. Camden records the founding of a university at Stam- 
ford in the reign of Edward III (1333). Thither the northern 
students at Oxford migrated, but returned at the command of 
a royal proclamation, and so ended the University of Stamford 
(1590, Lincolnshire, pp. 423, 4; 1610, p. 533).°7 Upton cites 
Anthony a Wood’s Historia et Antiquitates Oxontae, p. 165: *° 
‘Merlini nempe vaticinium, qui sic ante secula complura pre- 
dixerat : 


Doctrine studium, quod nunc viget ad vada boum [i. e. Oxford], 
Tempore venturo celebrabitur ad vada Saxi [i. e. Stamford].’ 


Though Upton calls the subject ‘trite,’ he mentions no possible 
source of Spenser’s information. It may have seemed trite 
because it figured in the long controversy for seniority. 
Spenser, who was not without interest in the dispute, may have 
read in John Caius’ De Antiquitate Cantabrigiensis Academiae, 
London, 1568: ‘Non excidit vestris animis (scio) diu fuisse in 
discrimine vestram Academiam, & longa persuasione atque metu 
partim vaticinii, quod fatidico quodam carmine Robertus Tal- 
botus, antiquarius Oxoniensis, libro suo peramplo de versibus 
antiquis, cui inscriptionem fecit satis familiarem, aurum ex ster- 
core, titulo de enigmaticis & propheticis, sic expressit: 


Hoc magnum studium, quod nunc est ad vada boum, 
Tempore venturo celebrabitur ad vada Saxi: 


partim rei gestze quoque exemplo, quod quidam ex Oxoniensibus, 
Oxonium deserentes, . . . multos secum Oxoniensis schole Stam- 
fordiam abduxere, quibus eo loci prelegerunt. Hinc expectatum 
continuo est, ut, ex dissoluta vestra Academia, Stamfordiensis 
resurgeret.’*° 


* Cf. Stow, Annales, ed. 1615, p. 232; Drayton, Polyolbion 24. 1-9. 
Hardyng (Chron., chap. xxv) and Grafton (Chron., pt. 5, yr. 863) tell 
how King Bladud of Britain in his time founded a university at Stam- 
ford. 

* Spenser, ed. Todd, 5. 448. 

* Quoted here from Hearne’s edition in his Thome Cat Vindicie, 2 
vols., 1730, I. 254. Talbot’s work is still in manuscript, according to 
D. N. B. The prophecy seems to have been adapted from lines in 


84 Charles G. Osgood, 


And next to him the Nene downe softly slid; 
And bounteous Trent, that in him selfe enseames 
Both thirty sorts of fish and thirty sundry streames.” 


The well-known course of the Nene is described in detail in 
Holinshed ‘from its source above Northampton to Peterborough, 
Wisbech, and its mouth in the Wash. Harrison speaks of its 
dissipation into many branches ‘among the fennes and medowes, 
not possible almost to be numbred’ (1. 172), thus sliding softly 
down, as Spenser has it. 

In Holinshed the ‘bounteous Trent’ is ‘one of the most excel- 
lent rivers in the land, not onlie for store of samon, sturgeon, 
and sundrie other kinds of delicate fish wherewith it dooth 
abound, but also for that it is increased with so manie waters, 
as.for that onelie cause it may be compared either with the Ouze 
or*Saverne’ (I. 162).*t Spenser’s intimation of the meaning of 


Alexander Neckam’s De Naturis Rerum, cap. 174 (ed. T. Wright, Rolls 
Series, no. 34)° ‘Juxta vaticinium etiam Merlini, viguit ad Vada Boum 
Sapientia tempore suo ad Hibernie partes transitura.’ Cf. the Animad- 
versiones of Thomas Caius, who defends the seniority of Oxford 
(Hearne, T. Caii Vindicig, 2. 337). Brian Twyne, in his Antiquitatis 
Academie Oxoniensis Apologia, Oxford, 1608, reviews the ‘trite’ subject 
(Bk. 2, pp. 148-50). He cites Neckam’s words, and then a sermon on 
the text Prov. 9. 1, doubtiully ascribed to Bonaventura (‘in sermone 
scholastico Theologicae facultatis in studio Parisiensi’), which in turn 
cites Rabanus and a ‘vita Dionysii Areopagite’ to the effect that 
‘secundum vaticinium Merlini vigebant studia in Anglia tempore suo ad 
partes Hyberniz transitura ad vada saxa’ (italics mine). I do not find 
this in Rabanus or any vita of Dionysius, or among the Sermones of 
Bonavezxtura, authentic or doubtful.. Whatever ‘ad vada saxa’ means, it 
is evident that under the influence of the migration to Stamford in 
Edward III’s reign, the statement of Neckam is undergoing revision, 
since Twyne says (p. 150): ‘Preter illud vero, est et aliud, Merlinii 
nomen pre se ferens existimatur, de translatione literarum Oxoniensium 
ab Oxonia Stanfordiam, usque vaticinium; quod sic habet: 


Doctrine studium, quod nunc viget ad vada Boum 
Tempore venturo (vel ut alii recitant) 
Ante finem Secli, celebrabitur ad vada Saxi.’ 


But Twyne suspects that it is not a genuine prophecy of Merlin, as it 
is found in no ancient or trustworthy author. It is clear, however, that 
it could not have escaped Spenser in his antiquarian reading or con- 
versation. 

arse 

“ Quoted by Dr. Harper, p. 13. 


si i i a 


Pas? - 


Spenser’s English Rivers. 85 


the name is obvious, but may have been suggested to him by 
Camden: ‘The river Trent, in the old English-Saxon tongue 
Treonta (which some Antiquaries of small note and account 
have called Triginta in Latine, for the affinity of the French 
word Trent that signifieth that number Triginta, that is, Thirty)’ 
(Nottinghamshire, p. 547). He adds that ‘pisces Trenta large 
suppeditat’ (1590, p. 436), with an old verse—‘Limpida sylva 
[Sherwood] focum, Triginta dat mihi piscem.’ 


Next these came Tyne, along whose stony bancke 
That Romaine monarch built a brasen wall, 
Which mote the feebled Britons strongly flancke 
Against the Picts, that swarmed over all, 
Which yet thereof Gualsever they doe call.* 


The Tyne in the old authors is called the South Tyne through- 
out its course. Camden says that, as it turns eastward from 
Bellister Castle, near Fetherston Haugh, it ‘runneth directly 
forward with the /Vall, which is in no place three miles distant’ 
(Northumberland, p. 799, cf. 646). Camden, in discussing the 
origin of the wall, says that Severus is shown to have been the 
builder by its ‘Britannicum nomen Gual Sever’ (1590, Picts 
Wall, p. 643). Saxton’s map shows the wall following the 
Tyne, and marks it ‘Pictes wal’ and ‘Vallum Severi.’ But 
Spenser’s information may be drawn also from Holinshed: 
‘After his time [Hadrian’s] Severus the emperour comming 
againe into this Ile (where he had served before in repression of 
the tumults here begun, after the death of Lucius) amongst 
other things he made another wall (but of stone) betweene 
eightie and a hundred miles from the first, & of thirtie two miles 
in length, reaching on both sides also to the sea, of whome ‘the 
Britons called it S. Murseveri, or Gwall Severi, that is, The 
wall of Severus, or Severus dale, which later indureth untill these 
daies in fresh memorie, by reason of the ruines & square stones 
there oft found, whose inscriptions declare the authors of that 
worke’ (1. 214). ‘Brazen’ in Spenser would not contradict 
Harrison’s statement that the wall was of stone. It is a favorite 
word of the poet, often meaning little more than ‘strong, impreg- 
nable.’ A long list of illustrations may be found in the con- 
cordance. 


pa E030; 


86 Charles G. Osgood, 


And Twede, the limit betwixt Logris land 

And Albany: and Eden, though but small, 

Yet often stainde with bloud of many a band 

Of Scots and English both, that tyned on his strand.* 


What Spenser says of the Tweed seems to reflect the words 
in Holinshed concerning the Humber (1. 157): ‘This river in old 
time parted Lhoegres or England from Albania, which was the 
portion of Albanactus, the yongest sonne of Brute. But since 
that time the limits of Lhoegres have beene so inlarged, first by 
the prowesse of the Romans, then by the conquests of the English, 
that at this present daie the Twede on the one side, & the Solve 
on the other, be taken for the principall bounds betweene us and 
those of Scotland.’ 

The course of the Eden is followed in detail by Harrison. 
Camden says: ‘For, Eden, that notable river, which wandereth 
through Westmoreland and the inner partes of this shire, 
powreth forth into it [the Solway] a mighty masse of water, 
having not yet forgotten, what a doe it had to passe away strug- 
ling and wrestling as it did, among the carcasses of freebutters, 
lying dead in it on heapes, in the yeere of salvation 1216, when 
it swallowed them up loden with booties out of England, and 
so buried that rable of robbers under his waves’ (Cumberland, 
p. 776). He has more to say of the border troubles in connec- 
tion with the Eden’s neighbors, Esk, Leven, and Kirsop. 

Then came those sixe sad brethren, like forlorne, 
That whilome were (as antique fathers tell) 

Sixe valiant knights, of one faire nymphe yborne, 
Which did in noble deedes of armes excell, 

And wonned there where now Yorke people dwell: 
Still Ure, swift Werfe, and Oze the most of might, 
High Swale, unquiet Nide, and troublous Skell; 

All whom a Scythian king, that Humber hight, 

Slew cruelly, and in the river drowned quight.* 


Spenser here groups various tributaries of the Ouse in York- 
shire, which is thus properly ‘the most of might.’ They con- 
verge, flowing from the North and the West Riding and from 
the southwest. Beginning from the north they are the Swale, 
the Ure, which unite to form the Ouse, the Skell, which is a 


SSEs0 
oS tea7: 


Spenser's English Rivers. 87 


tributary of the Ure, the Nidd, and the Wharf. The poet 
observes no order in naming them. As for ‘still’ Ure, Camden 
speaks of ‘Ure, which now [in its lower parts] is called Ouse, 
flowing with a gentle streame from the North part Southward’ 
(p. 701). ‘Swift Werfe’ so appears in Camden, who calls it 
‘This Wherf or Wharf, in the English Saxons language Guerf. 

If a man should thinke the name to be wrested from the 
word Guer, which in British signifieth Swift and Violent, verily, 
the nature of that river concurreth with his opinion; For he 
runneth with a swift and speedy streame, making a great noise 
as hee goeth, as if he were froward, stubborne, and angry’ 
(Yorkshire, pp. 696-7). Camden complains of its dangers, 
especially in summer, which he learned at his peril when his 
horse once nearly lost his footing in the swift current. ‘High’ 
Swale he describes as ‘magno aquarum assultu influentem’ 
(1590, Richmondshire, p. 595), and says: ‘Swale rusheth rather 
than runneth as I have said with fooming waters, meeting here 
and there with rockes, whereby his streame is interrupted and 
broken’ (1610, Richmondshire, p. 730). The other epithets—of 
the Nidd and the Skell—may easily have been inferred by 
Spenser from the nature of the country through which the 
streams are described as flowing. Their courses are in each 
instance traced by Harrison. 

In stanza 38 the poet continues the story about king Humber, 
to the effect that Locrinus, son of Brutus, avenged the death of 
the six knights, and drove him into the river, where he was 
drowned; whence its name, as well as its stormy character. A 
part of this story of the Humber is in Hclinshed (1. 156-7): 
‘Certes it is a noble arme of the sea, and although it be properlie 
to be called Ouze or Ocellus, . . . yet are we contented to call 
it Humber of Humbrus or Umar, a king of the Scithians, who 
invaded this Ile in the time of Locrinus, thinking to make him- 
selfe monarch of the same. But as God hath from time to time 
singularlie provided for the benefit of Britaine, so in this busi- 
nesse it came to passe, that Humber was put to flight, his men 
slaine: and furthermore, whilest he attempted to save himselfe 
by hasting to his ships (such was the prease of his nobilitie that 
followed him into his owne vessell, and the rage of weather which 
hastened on his fatall daie) that both he and they were drowned 
togither in that arme. And this is the onelie cause wherefore it 


88 Charles G. Osgood, 


hath beene called Humber, as our writers saie; and whereof I 
find these verses: 


Dum fugit obstat ei flumen submergitur illic, 
Deque suo tribuit nomine nomen aque.’ 


But the ‘antique father’ who tells the story of the six slain 
knights, children of a nymph, who gave their names to the six 
rivers, I have not found. The texture of that part of the story 
is true Spenserian, and the poet very likely invented it. His 
insistence upon the stormy character of the Humber, both here 
and in stanza 30, line 7, may not improbably arise from his recol- 
lection of Greek 6uBpos, ‘storm.’ 

These after, came the stony shallow Lone, 

That to old Loncaster his name doth lend; 

And following Dee, which Britons long ygone 

Did call divine, that doth by Chester tend; 

And Conway, which out of his streame doth send 

Plenty of pearles to decke his dames withall; 

And Lindus, that his pikes doth most commend, 

Of which the auncient Lincolne men doe call.* 


Of the first of these Harrison says (1. 145): ‘I came to a 
notable river called the Lune or Loine, . . . and giveth name to 
Lancaster, Lonecaster, or Lunecaster.’ Camden also writes: 
‘Lone having passed on some few miles from hence, commeth 
within sight of Lancaster, standing on his South banke, the cheife 
towne of this region [county]: which the inhabitants more truly 
call Loncaster, as the Scots also, who name it Loncastell of the 
River Lone’ (Lancashire, p. 754). The stream descends from the 
hills of Westmoreland to its mouth just below Lancaster. Cam- 
den describes it as flowing southward in ‘a channell now broad, 
now narrow with many a reach in and out hindring his streame’ 
(Lancashire, p. 753). It abounds in salmon, ‘which because 
they delight in cleere water and especially in shallow places that 
are sandy, come up thick togither,’ etc. 

Spenser’s lines on the Dee may well have been based upon his 
reading of Camden: “The river Dee, called in Latin Deva, in 
British Dyffyr-dwy, that is, the water of the Dwy, . . . for 
Dwy in their tongue signifieth Two. Yet others, . . . interpret 
it Black-water, others againe, Gods-water, or Divine water’ 


= Sit BO: 


Spenser's English Rivers. 89 


(Cheshire, p. 602). Camden combats the last explanation, 
though he admits the ancient British custom of regarding rivers 
as sacred. Spenser, however, accepts it, as being to him more 
easily explicable (as from Lat. divus) and interesting. Cam- 
den’s account of the river brings it to Chester, of which city he 
gives a detailed description (pp. 604 ff.). 

For the Conway in North Wales, Spenser depends upon 
Camden, who describes it as ‘breeding certaine shelfishes, which 
being conceived of an heavenly deaw, bring forth pearles’ (Car- 
narvonshire, p. 669). 

The Lindus is the modern Witham of Lincolnshire, which 
flows generally north past Grantham, eastward past Lincoln, and 
southeast to Boston and the Wash. Spenser’s description seems 
to echo Harrison’s: ‘Now come I to the course of the Witham, 
a famous river, whereof goeth the biword, frequented of old, 
and also of Ancolme, which I before described: 


Ancolme ele, and Witham pike, 
Search all England and find not the like. 


Leland calleth it Lindis, diverse the Rhe, and I have read all 
these names my selfe: and thereto that the Lincolneshire men 
were called in old time Coritani and their head citie Lindus, 
Lindon and Lindocollinum’ (1. 169).** Again Holinshed makes 
Lindum and Lindodunum the old names of Lincoln (1. 320). 
Camden mentions but discredits the derivation of Lincoln from 


Lindus (p. 328). 


Then came the bride, the lovely Medua came, 

Clad in a vesture of unknowen geare, 

And uncouth fashion, yet her well became; 

That seem’d like silver, sprinckled here and theare 
With glittering spangs, that did like starres appeare, 
And wav’d upon, like water chamelot, 

To hide the metall, which yet every where 

Bewrayd it selfe, to let men plainely wot, 

It was no mortall worke, that seem’d and yet was not.” 


Her hair fell loose over her shoulders to her waist, ‘as a new 
spring,’ and down upon it from her flowery chaplet ran drops of 


“Quoted by Dr. Harper, p. 14. 
OS ae Ep 


go Charles G. Osgood, 


dew. Similarly appears the bride Thame in the old poem in 


Camden: : 

Utque fluit, crines madidos in terga repellit, 

Reddit et undanti legem formamque capillo. 
(Oxfordshire, p. 385) 


Harrison writes: ‘Next unto the Thames we have the Midwaie 
water, whereof I find two descriptions, the first beginneth thus. 
The Midwaie water is called in Latine Medevia (as some write) 
bicause the course thereof is midwaie in a manner between 
London and... 7-Canturburie’ (1.90). 

On her two pretty handmaides did attend, 

One cald the Theise, the other cald the Crane; 

Which on her waited, things amisse to mend, 

And both behind upheld her spredding traine; 

Under the which her feet appeared plaine, 

Her silver feet, faire washt against this day: 

And her before there paced pages twaine, 

Both clad in colours like, and like array, 

The Doune and eke the Frith, both which prepard her way.” 


The Medway, as appears on any map, rises in Surrey, but 
soon enters Kent, and flows in a direction a little north of east 
to Yalding. There it takes a more northerly course towards its 
- estuary and the Thames. The ‘Theise,’ so spelled in Holinshed, 
is, of course, the Teise, which approaches the Medway from 
Goudhurst and the south, and meets it at Yalding. Almost at 
the same point it is joined by the river Beult, which comes from 
a southeasterly direction. Thus Holinshed: ‘From thence also, 
and not farre from Yalling [Yalding] it receiveth the Theise 
(a pretie streame that ariseth about Theise Hirst [Ticehurst]) & 
afterward the Gran or Crane, which having his head not farre 
from Cranbrooke, and meeting with sundrie other rivelets by 
the waie,’ etc. (I. 90). This identifies the Crane with the Beult 
up as far as Headcorn, about ten miles, and then with the branch 
now called Hammer Stream, coming northeast from Cranbrook. 
The name Beult now continues up the main stream towards the 
southeast to its source not far southwest of Ashford.*® 

The particular office of upholding the bride’s train which fell 


Sie 20g 
“Further proof appears in Harrison’s more detailed account of the 
Theise and the Crane, pp. 90-1. ~ 


——EE 


Spenser's English Rivers. gI 


to the Theise and the Crane may have been suggested to the 
poet while looking at a map. There the Medway seems to the 
fanciful eye to be curiously trailing that part of her course from 
her source to Yalding, where she stands more erect towards the 
north. These two handmaids attend her just at this point, and 
seem to help uphold her train. 

The ‘pages twaine,’ the Doune and the Frith, give some diffi- 
culty. Harrison says of the Medway: ‘It hasteth to Pensherst, 
and there carrieth withall the Eden, that commeth from Lingfield 
parke. After this it goeth to the southeast part of Kent, and 
taketh with it the Frith or Firth, on the northwest side, and an 
other little streame that commeth from the hilles betweene 
Pevenburie and Horsemon on the southeast’ (1. 90). Spenser’s 
words seem to imply that the streams are small, well paired, and 
that they reach the Medway above the Theise and the Crane. 
The Frith, by Harrison’s brief account, might be one of several 
little streams coming in from the northwest in the neighborhood 
of Tonbridge. One of these rises in Frith Wood, at Dene Park, 
a mile or more west of the hamlet of North Frith. Spenser’s 
Frith may, however, be the river Shode, a brook flowing south 
from Wrotham, with its mouth near East Peckham, just above 
Yalding. The stream from the hills between Pembury and 
Horsmonden to the southwest (there is no stream in this region 
from the southeast before we reach the Teise and the Beult) 
has no name on the modern maps, and I have been unable to dis- 
cover whether it now has one; but in Harrison’s description it 
corresponds most closely with what Spenser calls the Doune. 

Penshurst, the home of the Sidneys, is on the Medway above 
Tonbridge, not more than five or six miles from its upper waters. 
Is it not likely that Spenser knew these tiny streamlets and ‘dales 
of Kent’ at first hand, either from his association with Pens- 
hurst, whatever that association was, or other occasion of 
acquaintance with the Kentish country ?°° 


On Philip Symonson’s map of Kent, probably first published in 1576, 
this stream is marked as coming from the southeast, as Harrison says. 
Symonson’s map is highly praised by Lambarde and later writers, and 
well deserves praise for its comparative accuracy and fineness of detail. 
See An Account of a Map of Kent, dated 1596, by the Hon. Henry 
Hannen, in Archeologia Cantiana 30. 85-92, with a reproduction of 
Symonson’s map on a reduced scale. On neither Symonson’s map nor 


92 Charles G. Osgood, 


Camden, in his account of the Medway, pauses in mentioning 
Penshurst to glorify at some length the memory of Sir Philip 
Sidney. Spenser is conspicuously silent. A line or two of 
allusion would not have disturbed the course of his pageant. 
Perhaps inthe earlier Epithalamion Thamesis the Medway had 
been chosen as the bride, because of its association with Pens- 
hurst. Any allusions to Sidney in that poem may have seemed 
for some reason less appropriate at this later date. 

So much at present for the English rivers that came to the 
wedding of the Thames and the Medway. Two other passages, 
however, that deal with English rivers may claim our attention. 

The first is the lament of the ancient city Verulam, already 
cited from the Ruins of Time. Though Spenser, in the lines 
quoted above on page 70, plainly implies that the only memori- 
alist of Verulam ‘in true-seeming sort’ is Camden, yet it appears 
by examination that he owes most of the passage to Holinshed: 


I was that citie which the garland wore 

‘Of Britaines pride, delivered unto me 

By Romane victors, which it wonne of yore; 
Though nought at all but ruines now I bee, 
And lve in mine owne ashes, as ye see: 
Verlame I was; what bootes it that I was, 
Sith now I am but weedes and wastfull gras?” 


And again: 


O Rome, thy ruine I lament and rue, 

And in thy fall my fatall overthrowe, 

That whilom was, whilst heavens with equall vewe 
Deignd to behold me, and their gifts bestowe, 

The picture of thy pride in pompous shew: 

And of the whole world as thou wast the empresse, 
So I of this small Northerne world was princesse.™ 


These passages unmistakably derive from the thirteenth chapter 
of the Description in Holinshed, entitled ‘Of Cities and Townes 
in England.’ He writes: ‘The British Verolamians, therefore, 


Saxton’s, the only maps of Kent in Spenser’s time, are the streams 
named. Symonson locates and names North Frith. It would therefore 
“seem that Spenser knew the region at first hand, and had personal 
associations with its streams. 

* Li. 36-42. 

? LI. 78-84. 


Galan See 


Spenser's English Rivers. 93 


having for their noble service in the warres deserved great com- 
mendations at the hands of the Romans, they gave unto them the 
whole freedome of Romans, whereby they were made Muni- 
cipes, and became more free in truth than their Colonies could 
be’ (p. 322). A little earlier he says: ‘It would seeme when 
these ancient cities flourished that the same towne, which we 
now call saint Albons, did most of all excell: but cheefelie in 
the Romans time, and was not onelie nothing inferior to London 
it selfe, but rather preferred before it,** bicause it was newer, 
and made a Municipium of the Romans, whereas the other was 
old and ruinous’ (p. 321). Holinshed speaks more than once of 
the ruins, which he says he had viewed with his own eyes 
(p. 323). 
The genius of Verolam continues: 

To tell the beawtie of my buildings fayre, 

Adornd with purest golde and precious stone, 

To tell my riches, and endowments rare, 

That by my foes are now all spent and gone, 


To tell my forces, matchable to none, 
Were but lost labour. 


High towers, faire temples, goodly theaters, 
Strong walls, rich porches, princelie pallaces, 
Large streetes, brave houses, sacred sepulchers, 
Sure gates, sweete gardens, stately galleries 
Wrought with faire pillours, and fine imageries, 
All those (O pitie!) now are turnd to dust.” 


Says Harrison (p. 322): ‘Of the beautie of the citie it selfe 
you shall partly understand by that which followeth at hand.’ 
He then tells how, in King Edgar’s time, the abbot Eldred dug 
in the ruins for material with which to embellish his abbey of 
St. Alban’s. ‘He had no sooner begun to dig among the rubbis, 
but he found an exceeding number of pillers, peeces of antike 
worke, thresholds, doore frames, and sundrie other peeces of 
fine masonrie for windowes and such like, verie convenient for 
his purpose. Of these also some were of porphyrite stone, some 
of diverse kinds of marble, touch, and alabaster, beside manie 
curious devises of hard mettall. . . . Besides these also he 
found sundrie pillers of brasse, and sockets of latton, alabaster 


= Cf. Ruins of Time 99-103. 
“11. 85-97. 


94 Charles G. Osgood, 


and touch, all which he laid aside by great heaps.’ Eldred’s 
successor, Edmer, continued the work, and ‘not onelie found 
infinite other peeces of excellent workemanship, but came at the 
last to certeine vaults under the ground, in which stood divers 
idols, and not a few altars, verie superstitiouslie and religiouslie 
adorned. . . . These images were of sundrie mettals, and some 
of pure gold, their altars likewise were richlie covered.’ ‘In 
proceeding further, he tooke up diverse pots of gold, silver, 
brasse, glasse, and earth, whereof some were filled with the 
ashes and bones of the gentils.’. He found also two old books 
containing descriptions of pagan rites and the martyrdom of 
St. Alban. ‘Thus much have I thought good to note of the 
former beautie of Verolamium, whereof infinite other tokens 
have beene found since that time, and diverse within the memorie 
of anan, of passing workemanship, the like whereof hath no where 
else beene seene in anie ruines within the compasse of this Ile, 
either for cost or quantitie of stuffe.’ 

In the same connection Camden says: ‘If I were disposed 
upon the report of the common people to reckon up what great 
store of Romane peeces of coine, how many cast images of gold 
and silver, how many vessels, what a sort of modules or Chapters 
of pillars, and how many wonderfull things of antique worke, 
have been digged up, my words would not carry credit. The 
thing is so incredible’ (Hertfordshire, p. 411). He adds a 
briefer account than Harrison’s of the discoveries of Eldred and 
Edmer. 


Theretoo, for warlike power and peoples store, 
In Britannie was none to match with mee, 

That manie often did abie full sore: 

Ne Troynovant, though elder sister shee, 

With my great forces might compared bee; 
That stout Pendragon to his perill felt, 

Who in a siege seaven yeres about me dwelt.” 


That London was both older and weaker than Verulam was 
asserted in the passage quoted from Holinshed above on page 
93. Of the seven years’ siege by Pendragon, Spenser doubt- 
less learned in Camden, who quotes from Alexander Neckam, 
‘who 400. yeeres since was there borne’: 


°° LI. 99-105. 


——— 


Spenser's English Rivers. 95 


Urbs insignis erat Verolamia, plus operosze 
Arti, nature debuit illa minus. 

Pendragon Arturi patris hzec obsessa laborem 
Septennem sprevit cive superba suo.” 


But long ere this, Bunduca Britonnesse 

Her mightie hoast against my bulwarkes brought, 
Bunduca, that victorious conqueresse, 

That, lifting up her brave heroick thought 

Bove womens weaknes, with the Romanes fought, 
Fought, and in field against them thrice prevailed: 
Yet was she foyld, when as she me assailed.” 


Both Holinshed and Camden may have lent matter to this 
passage. Holinshed describes two victories of Bonduca over 
the Romans (Bk. 4, chap. 12), one at Camelodunum, and men- 
tions the fall of Verulam at the hands of the Britons. Camden 
says of her expressly: ‘Camalodunum Coloniam, et Verolamium 
municipium excidit’ (1590, p. 355). Perhaps Spenser has these 
three victories in mind when he says that Bonduca ‘thrice pre- 
vailed.” Yet in the last line he speaks of her being foiled at 
Verulam. For this I find no authority. In F. Q. II. x. 44 she is 
said to have been finally defeated at the Severn. But for this 
statement, also, Dr. Harper finds no corroboration.** The phrase, 
‘lifting up her brave heroick thought Bove womens weaknes,’ 
may owe something to the exalted plea to defend their freedom 
that Bonduca makes to her army in a ‘gallant oration’ which 
constitutes Holinshed’s eleventh chapter. 

In lines 113-9 Spenser speaks of the conquest of Verulam by 
the Saxons, bought with much bloodshed and the death of their 
general, whose monument, long a wonder, is now lost. Neither 
Camden nor Holinshed, nor any other I have seen, speaks of this. 
Holinshed, in his account of Eldred’s excavations, says inciden- 
tally that Verulam had now been ‘overthrowne by the furie 
of the Saxons and Danes.’ Camden writes: ‘Not long after 
[the year 429], the English-Saxons wonne it: but Uther the 
Britan, surnamed for his serpentine wisedom Pendragon, by a 
sore siege and a long [cf. above, p. 94], recovered it. After 


From Neckam’s De Laudibus Divinae Sapientie, 5. 850-64, ed. T. 
Wright, Rolls Series, No. 34. 
711. 106-12. 


* Sources of the British Chronicle History, etc., p. 119. 


96 Charles G. Osgood, 


whose death, it fell againe into their hands’ (Hertfordshire, p. 
410). 

In lines 125-6 Spenser describes the ruins of Verulam as now 
the haunt of 


greislie shades, such as doo haunt in hell 
With fearfull fiends, that in deep darknes dwell. 


The suggestion may well have come from the account of the — 
Abbot Eldred’s excavations, quoted by Camden from ‘an old his- 
toriographer.’ The abbot, having ‘serched for the ancient vaults 
under ground at Verulam, overthrew all, . . . and stopped up 
all the waies with passages under ground, which were strongly 
and artificially arched over head: For they were the lurking 
hooles of whores and theeves. He levelled with the ground the 
ditches of the Citie and certaine dennes, into which malefactors 
fled as unto places of refuge’ (1610, p. 411; 1590, p. 317). 


And where the christall Thamis wont to slide 
. In silver channell, 

There now no rivers course is to be seene, 

But moorish fennes, and marshes ever greene.” 


The Thames, says Verulam, has fled far away to escape the 
sight of her miseries. She continues: 


There also where the winged ships were seene 
In liquid waves to cut their fomie waie, 

And thousand fishers numbred to have been, 
In that wide lake looking for plenteous praie 
Of fish, which they with baits usde to betraie, 
Is now no lake, nor anie fishers store, 

Nor ever ship shall saile there anie more.” 


Camden discredits the tradition that the Thames once flowed by 
Verulam. In speaking of the ‘wide lake,’ he says that the monks 
filled it up. ‘Ubi nostra memoria cum anchore fuerint effosse, 
crediderunt nonnulli, corrupto Gilde loco inducti, Tamisim ali- 
quando hac alveum egisse’ (1590, p. 326). But Holinshed 
appears to be Spenser’s chief informant: ‘Furthermore, whereas 
manie are not afraid to saie that the Thames came sometimes by 
this citie, indeed it is nothing so; but that the Verlume . . . did 


Selelene4—A0: 
© LI. 148-54. 


aa 


Spenser's English Rivers. 97 


and dooth so still (whatsoever Gildas talketh hereof, whose books 
may be corrupted in that behalfe) there is yet evident proofe 
to be confirmed by experience. For albeit that the river be now 
growne to be verie small by reason of the ground about it, which 
is higher than it was in old time; yet it keepeth in maner the 
old course, and runneth betweene the old citie that was, and the 
new towne that is standing on Holmehirst crag, as I beheld of 
late. Those places also which now are medow beneath the 
abbaie, were sometimes a great lake, mere, or poole [“now I am 
but weedes and wastfull gras,’ 42], through which the said 
river ran, and (as I read) with a verie swift and violent course, 
wheras at this present it is verie slow, and of no such deapth as 
of ancient times it hath beene. But heare what mine author 
saith further of the same. As those aforsaid workemen digged 
in these ruines, they happened oftentimes upon Lempet shels, 
peeces of rustie anchors, and keeles of great vessels, whereupon 
some by and by gathered that either the Thames or some arme 
of the sea did beat upon that towne, not understanding that 
these things might aswell happen in great lakes and meres, 
wherof there was one adjoining to the north side of the citie’ (p. 
323). Spenser seems not only lightly to accept the belief that 
Thames once passed by Verulam, but contradicts himself by say- 
ing, in lines 146-7, that it does so no longer, while in the opening 
of the poem he appears walking along the Thames, 


Nigh where the goodly Verlame stood of yore. 


Holinshed continues: ‘This mere (which the Latin copie of the 
description of Britaine, written of late by Humprey Lhoid our 
countrie man calleth corruptlie “stagnum exanimum” for “stag- 
num maximum”) at the first belonged to the king, and thereby 
Offa in his time did reape no small commoditie. It continued 
also untill the time of Alfrijc the seventh abbat of that house, 
who bought it outright of the king then living, and by excessive 
charges drained it so narrowlie, that within a while he left it 
drie, . . . bicause there was alwaies contention betweene the 
moonks and the kings servants, which fished on that water unto 
the kings behoofe.’ 

It thus appears that while Spenser is praising Camden as the 
only worthy commemorator of Verulam, he is really much more 
indebted to Harrison and Holinshed for what he says of her. 


98 Charles G. Osgood, 


What is more, the very words by which he introduces his eulogy 
>f Camden bear a noticeable resemblance to those of Harrison: 


But me no man bewaileth, but in game, 
Ne sheddeth teares from lamentable eie: 
Nor anie lives that mentioneth my name 
To be remembred of posteritie, 

Save one, 


namely Camden. Says Harrison: ‘Good notice hereof also is 
to be taken by Matthew Paris, and others before him, out of 
whose writings I have thought to note a few things, whereby the 
majestie of this ancient citie may appeare unto posteritie, and the 
former estate of Verlamcester not lie altogither (as it hath doone | 
hitherto) raked up in forgetfu'nes, through the negligence of 
such as might have deserved better of their successours, by leav- 
ing the description thereof in a booke by it selfe, sith manie 
particulars thereof were written to their hands, that now are lost 
and perished’ (pp. 321-2). 

A passage in the third canto of the Third Book, stanzas 7-14, 
unrelated to the one just considered, but concerned with two 
rivers in Wales, may not inconveniently be dealt with at this 
point. It tells of the visit of old Glauce and the love-lorn Brito- 
mart to Merlin in quest of his counsel: 


To Maridunum, that is now by chaunge 

Of name Cayr-Merdin cald, they tooke their way: 
There the wise Merlin whylome wont (they say) 

To make his wonne, low underneath the ground, 

In a deepe delve, farre from the vew of day, 

That of no living wight he mote be found, 

When so he counseld with his sprights encompast round. 


And if thou ever happen that same way 

To traveill, go to see that dreadfull place: 

It is an hideous hollow cave (they say) 

Under a rock, that lyes a litle space 

From the swift Barry, tombling downe apace 

Emongst the woody hilles of Dynevowre: 

But dare thou not, I charge, in any cace, 

To enter into that same balefull bowre, 

For feare the cruell feendes should thee unwares devowre. 


But standing high aloft, low lay thine eare, 
And there such ghastly noyse of yron chaines 
And brasen caudrons thou shalt rombling heare, 


—— Se eee 


NN 


Spenser's English Rivers. 99 


Which thousand sprights with long enduring paines 
Doe tosse, that it will stonn thy feeble braines; 

And oftentimes great grones, and grievous stownds, 
When too huge toile and labour them constraines, 
And oftentimes loud strokes, and ringing sowndes, 
From under that deepe rock most horribly rebowndes.” 


The poet then tells how Merlin, ere he died, planned to encircle 
Cairmardin with a brazen wall, and enjoined his sprites to 
accomplish this work. But, lured from this task by the Lady 
of the Lake, he first bound his sprites to labor at the wall until 
it should be done, and then followed the lady away in hopeless 
love, never to return. For she, by false and magic practice, 
subdued him, and buried him for ever ‘under beare.’ The noise 
in the cavern of Cairmardin is the sound of the sprites still 
fashioning the brazen wall. 

As for the geography of this passage, which now concerns us, 
Spenser locates the cave of Merlin at Maridunum, that is, Cayr- 


Merdin, now Carmarthen, 
a litle space 
From the swift Barry, tombling downe apace 
Emongst the woody hilles of Dynevowre. 


In point of fact, Spenser is here confusing two localities. Car- 
marthen and the hills of Dynevor are not ‘a litle space’ from the 
cave and the Barry, but more than fifty miles in a straight line 
further west and a little north. Both places lie along the southern 
coast of Wales. Carmarthen is near the mouth of the Towy, and 
some fourteen miles up the river, near Llandilo, is the ancient 
Dynevor Castle amid the hills. On the other hand, the Barry is a 
little stream, perhaps ten miles long, now known as the Cadoxton 
river, which reaches the sea about six miles southwest of Cardiff, 
opposite a tiny island or promontory called Barry. 

Warton, in his note on this passage,®* refers to the Itinerary of 
Giraldus Cambrensis 1. 6. Here we find a part of the material 
for Spenser’s description. Giraldus is speaking of the island of 
Barry, whence his family came: ‘Est autem hic notabile, quod 
in ipso insulz introitu, in rupe marina apparet rima permodica, 
ad quam, si aurem apponas, audies opere strepitum quasi fab- 


™ Stanzas 7-9. 
“Todd’s Spenser 4. 336. 


100 Charles G. Osgood, 


rilis; nune follium flatus, nunc martellorum ictus, nunc cotis et 


ferri sonora fricamina, 
Stridentesque cavernis 
Stricturas Chalybum, et anhelum fornacibus ignem.’™ 


This phenomenon Giraldus explains by the entrance and exit of 
the sea. 

How Spenser came to confuse the little Barry with the big 
Towy, which really does tumble down among the hills of Dyne- 
vor, is not clear. Possibly the explanation is found in Holinshed. 
Harrison, in describing the rivers of Great Britain, follows the 
coast-line westward, discussing each stream and its tributaries 
as he passes its mouth. In following the south coast of Wales 
he has passed the Barry and proceeded westward, taking each 
stream in order. He has just described the Gwendraeth Tawr 
and the Gwendraeth Fach, the last before you come to the Towy, 
and is on the point of proceeding with this stream, when, without 
clear warning, he suddenly returns to resume his account of the 
Barry. Perhaps Spenser, expecting next to read of the Towy, 
with characteristic inadvertence may have taken Barry for an 
alternative name of that river.** 

The passage about the Barry, quoted above from Giraldus, 
Spenser could as well have read in Camden, who quotes it in his 
account of Glamorganshire (1590, p. 516). He also mentions 
‘Caer-Mardin, which the Britans themselves call Caer Firdhin, 
Ptolomee, Maridunum’ (Carmardenshire, p. 649). On the same 
page he describes the Towy flowing ‘by Dinevor, a princely 
castle, standing aloft upon the top of a hill, . . . and last of all, 
by Caer-Marden.’ And further: ‘In this Citie was borne the 
Tages of the Britans, I meane Merlin: For like as Tages 
being the sonne of an evill Angell taught his Countrimen the 
Tuscans the art of Sooth saying, so this Merlin the sonne of an 
Incubus Spirit, devised for our Britans prophesies.’ Hence it 
is unnecessary to suppose that Spenser drew any of the material 
for the passage before us directly from Giraldus. 

To return to one or two considerations concerning the Protha- 


*Verg. Aen. 8. 420. 

* Giraldus, Jtin. 1. 10; Description of Wales, 1. 5; and Camden, 
Carmardenshire, p. 649, as well as the old maps, are all perfectly clear on 
this point. 


barn 


Spenser's English Rivers. 101 


lamion, the lost Epithalamion Thamesis, and canto xi of the 
Fourth Book. These works should be regarded not as isolated 
works, but as specimens of a type not uncommon in their time. 
Of these I may mention three. 

(1) In 1897 there appeared in the Atheneum a number of 
communications, notably from the hands of Wickham Flower, 
John W. Hales, and Robert Case, on the relation of Vallans’ 
poem, The Two Swans, first published in 1590, to Spenser’s Pro- 
thalamion. The discussion, unnecessarily prolonged, leaves it 
probable that Spenser knew Vallans’ poem, and that he echoes 
it in at least one line of the Prothalamion (121). Viewed some- 
what more inclusively, it becomes clear that such passages as the 
eleventh canto of the Fourth Book and the Prothalamion are but 


examples—preéminent of course—of certain types of poems not 


uncommon in their time. I here give brief resumés of several 
which could not have been unknown to Spenser. 

Vallans’ Tale of Two Swans, not now found in its first edition, 
may be read in Thomas Hearne’s edition of Leland’s Itimerary, 
Oxford, 1769, vol. 5, pp. v-xx. A full antiquarian commentary 
is included. The poem is written in English blank verse, and 
contains 266 lines. 

It opens with a description of the spring. Venus in Hertford- 
shire sends Cupid to bring two choice cygnets from Cayster. 
These she releases, and wins from Jove a promise that they shall 
increase and prosper. At length as king and queen of a large 
progeny, they begin their progress through their realm, with a 
train of forty swans. They visit the course of the River Lea, 
and traverse its tributaries—the Beane, the Rib, the Ash, the 
Stort, and others. Then they turn their course down stream, 
and pass various famous places, such as Theobalds, Ware, Strat- 
ford-at-Bowe. At length they reach the mouth of the Lea, 
where they are received by flocks of swans: 

After a noyse in ‘signe of passing joy, 

A Swanne of Thames invites the King and Queene 
Upon a day prefixt, to see and celebrate 

The marriage of two Rivers of great name. 


Which granted, everie one departes his way, 
The King and Queene againe into their Lee. 


Vol. of Jan. to June, pp. 378-80; 415-16; 446-7; 480-1; 510; 544; 
577-8. 


102 Charles G. Osgood, 


(2) Another poem of this class, published in 1545, forty-five 
years earlier than the Two Swans, is the so-called Cygnea Cantio, 
in Latin hendecasyllabics, by Leland. It is confessedly an anti- 
quarian work, of 699 lines, with a full commentary by the author, 
all reprinted in Hearne’s Leland, vol. 9, pp. 1-108. 

In his dedicatory address to Henry VIII, Leland explains that 
this is his swan-song to the Muses before turning to more serious 
antiquarian studies. He then cites a multitude of Latin authors 
in verse and prose to support the tradition of the swan-song. 
The swan whose song constitutes the poem lives in the island of 
the divided Isis at Oxford. It tells how it was seized with a 
desire of roving, and, summoning other swans, chose twelve 
companions, made a farewell speech, and proceeded on its way, 
reviewing the beauties and antiquities of various sites down 
along the Thames—Reading, Windsor, Eton, Richmond, Kew, 
London, Greenwich, and Deptford. Then, from speaking of 
England’s ships and prowess by sea, it begins a eulogy of Henry 
VIII, and a'review of his works and exploits, which occupy the 
rest of the poem. At the end, the swan bids its mates farewell, 
in preparation for its journey to heaven. 

(3) The third poem of the group, already mentioned on p. 
71, is incomplete, but available in sufficient length for the pres- 
ent purpose. It is written in Latin hexameters, of which some 
93 verses survive in Camden’s Britannia, quoted in fragments at 
various points.°® Camden calls it De Connubio Tamis et Isis, 
and is himself probably the author of it.** It describes the wed- 
ding of the bride, Thame, to the groom, Isis. 


“1610, Oxfordshire, p. 373, 6% lines; pp. 384-5, 61 lines; Middlesex, 
p. 419, 7 lines; Surrey, p. 298, two passages of 9% and 9 lines. I give 
these in what appears to have been their order in the complete poem. 

“Upton, in his note on F. Q. IV. iii. 3 (quoted in Todd’s Spenser 5. 
431), says confidently: ‘When Camden was a young man he wrote The 
Bridale of the Isis and Tame’. This is but a guess of Upton’s, though 
probably a correct one. Camden frequently quotes verses, and is usually 
explicit concerning the author. In this case he mentions no author, but 
says: ‘Poeticam vero fontis descriptionem, ex Tamei et Isis Conubio 
subjunxi, quam sive admittas, sive omittas, minimi refert’ (1590, Oxford- 
shire, p. 282). ,On page 285 he again mentions the marriage, ‘de quo 
quidam non ita pridem cecinit’. This probably amounts to a pleasant 
acknowledgment of authorship. The Life prefixed to Gough’s edition 
of the Britannia, 1806, and based on Smith’s account, enumerates Camden’s 


Spenser's English Rivers. 103 


The fragments tell first how Isis, on his way to his wedding, 
passes Radcot Bridge, where Sir K. Vere, Earl of Oxford, was 
defeated in Richard II’s time. As he proceeds, he is arrayed 
for his wedding by Zephyr and Flora. Meanwhile Thame, 
hurrying from her hills to meet him, passes Tame and Dor- 
chester. Their union is attended by rejoicing nymphs, satyrs, 
birds, Echo, and cupids, while Britona sings of how she became 
an island, and was visited by Hercules, Ulysses, Brutus, and 
Cesar. Then, united as Thamesis, they hasten to the sea, pass- 
ing historic Runnimede, and later old Sheen, new named Rich- 
mond by Henry VII, where died Edward III of noble memory. 
Here Thames meets the tide, and boasts that all rivers ‘vail to 
him.’ No other river so regularly renews its waters except 
Scheldt and Elbe. 

From these fragments and the context it is clear that the poem 
as a whole was primarily antiquarian, and, like Leland’s Cygnea 
Cantio, was a product of the new antiquarian enthusiasms of the 
sixteenth century. 

In the three poems just described, three motives or themes 
are distinguishable: A, the journey of the swans; B, the mar- 
riage, either in prothalamion or epithalamion, of the rivers; and 
C, the topographic and antiquarian review of their shores. In 
most cases A or B is a mere vehicle for C. In the oldest— 
Leland’s poem—A supports C; in Camden, B supports C; and 
in Vallans, A supports C, with a clear intimation of B at the 
close. In the case of Spenser’s Prothalamion A is exquisitely 
blended with B by transferring the wedding theme from rivers to 
swans, with a passing intimation of C in stanza viii, especially 
lines 132-6: 


There when they came, whereas those bricky towres, 
The which on Themmes brode aged backe doe ryde, 
Where now the studious lawyers have their bowers, 
There whylome wont the Templer Knights to byde, 
Till they decayd through pride. 


attempts in verse, and mentions “The marriage of the Tame and Isis, of 
which he more than half confesses himself the author’ (vol. I, p. xxviii). 
In a note it quotes Nathanael Salmon’s Hertfordshire, 1728 (p. 3): ‘This 
poem seems to be of his own composition. He was so delighted with 
the thought of the name of Tamesis being revived [derived?] from the 
names and union of the two rivers Tame and Isis: his modest intro- 
duction of the verses giving ground for such a conjecture’. 


104 Charles G. Osgood, 


In canto xi B is combined with C, though C is subordinate and 
incidental to B.*s 

B indeed here becomes elaborate pageantry, and the two ele- 
ments represent two favorite and dominating interests of the 
poet. 

His love of all that is old is readily apparent to every obser- 
vant reader. The words ‘ancient,’ ‘antique,’ ‘old,’ ‘eld,’ and their 
kind, are always on his lips, often without designation of a par- 
ticular period, or distinction between myth and history. For his 
masterpiece he dared revive setting, legend, and apparatus which 
were long out of fashion and covered with dust. His dialect 
is everywhere, in varying degree, archaic. He is keenly suscep- 
tible to the charm which age and long association with the life 
of men add to everything—so keenly that this charm sometimes 
becomes an illusion that deceives him. At the beginning of this 
pageant of the rivers, he invokes for new inspiration the Muse 


To whom those rolles, layd up in heaven above, 
And records of antiquitie appeare. 


As in his love of pageantry, so in his love of topographical 
antiquities, Spenser was of his time. It was the century of 
Leland, Hall, Stow, Speed, Harrison, Holinshed, and Camden. 
His friend Sir Walter Raleigh was a member of Archbishop 
Parker’s Society of Antiquaries, and in such works as these men 
produced, Spenser, from early manhood, found both a stimulus 
for his poetic powers and material to work on. 

That Spenser knew the poems by Vallans and Camden is well- 
nigh certain. He was never so given as his great Puritan suc- 
cessor to verbal echo and refinement upon the details of his 
original; therefore one is not surprised to find little evidence 
that his verses about rivers owed few if any details to similar 
poems.°° 

Much as two of the nymphs crowned the two swans, when 
they set out, with garlands of freshest flowers, and sang a song 


(Cf. stanzas 15,16, 10, 26, 28, 31-0, 41-3: 

” The resemblance between Proth. 119-21 and a passage in The Two 
Swans, remarked in Atheneum 1897. I. 379, can hardly have been a 
coincidence. 


——— 


Spenser's English Rwers. 105 


of gratulation, so in Leland’s Cygnea Cantio (52-6), when the 
swan begins his journey, his attendants crowd about: 


Aptantes capiti meo coronam, 
Baccatam nitidis et hinc et illinc 
Gemmis, ac niveum aurez catenz 
Collum multiplici orbe circinantes 
Postremoque vale vale canentes. 


In the same poem, as the swan approaches London—from the 
west, however—he views the splendid palaces along the Thames, 


Quid magnas referam edium nitelas 
Multarum, radiant suo emicanti 

Quz nunc lumine, clivus adjacet qua 
Ripz excelsior, aspicitque lymphas 
Nymphae ceruleas sibi faventis? 


He enumerates two or three palaces, but omits Leicester, later 


Essex, House: 
Hine templi veteris ruina sensim 
Frontem attcllere ccepit excitata. 


In the Prothalamion the swans, ascending the stream, see first 
the ‘bricky towres’ of the Temple, and after it the stately Essex 
House, their journey’s end. 

Any detailed use of Camden’s poem which Spenser may have 
made has already been noted. But whether these slight resem- 
blances signify or not, it is clear that the Prothalamion and canto 
xi are glorifications of motives not unfamiliar in academic verse. 

That Spenser had long meditated such themes appears from 
his lost earlier work, the Epithalamion Thamesis. Critics and 
editors of Spenser have long been accustomed to say that this 
lost work is essentially preserved in canto xi, in which it is 
embodied. So said Upton,’® and so Miss Helen FE. Sandison in 
the most recent study of the ‘lost works.’* But evidence has 


™Todd’s Spenser 5. 431. 

™P.L. M. A. 25. 148-9. ‘If the poem Ep. Tham. was actually written, 
and not merely projected, at that date [1580], as seems very probable, 
we can reasonably believe that we have in the Faerie Queene the actual 
poem which Spenser described revised only to meet the exigencies of 
the epic stanza’ (p. 149). Some, however, are in doubt whether the 
Ep. Tham. was ever written. See C. A. Harper, Sources of the British 


106 Charles G. Osgood, 


for some time been at hand which shows that the Epithalamion 
Thamesis was first written in Latin, and that Spenser projected 
an English version in quantitative verse, which, even if he com- 
pleted it, he was never willing to circulate. In his ‘Preface to 
the Reader’ Vallans sets forth his reasons for publishing The 
Two Swans. His first object was to illustrate his native Hert- 
fordshire. ‘Another reason was, that albeit neither my writing, 
nor Other indevour whatsoever, be able to perfourm any thing 
that might either beautifie or adorne the places I speake of: 
Yet hereby I would animate, or encourage those worthy Poets, 
who have written Epithalamion Thamesis, to publish the same. 
I have seen it in Latine verse (in my judgment) wel done, but 
the Author, I know not for what reason, doth suppresse it. That 
which is written in English, though long since it was promised, 
ye.is it not perfourmed. So as it seemeth some unhappy Star 
envieth the sight of so good a work: which once set abroad, such 
trifles as these would vanish, and be overshadowed, much like the 
Moon and other Starres, which after the appearing of the Sunne 
are not to be seen at all.’ The mention of ‘Poets’ might prompt 
the conjecture that at least the Latin version was by another 
hand than Spenser’s, perhaps was the very poem quoted in Cam- 
den; but in the letter to Harvey, cited at the beginning of this 
article, Spenser clearly describes his own labor in composing the 
poem. In the same letter he says that the English version was 
to be a specimen of the new quantitative verse. His unwilling- 
ness to complete and publish it may well have been the result 
of his diminishing confidence in this medium. In any case, 
Vallans’ words surely support the conjecture that Spenser never 
finished, perhaps never began, the English version, but that he 
went as far as to collect and arrange his material in a Latin 
poem. 

The opinion that canto xi is made of the material of the lost 
Epithalamion, in revised metre, must also be modified. The 
whole pageant properly occupies stanzas 11 to 53, that is, forty- 
three stanzas in all. Of these, nine (11-19) enumerate the sea- 


Chronicle History, etc., p. 11; R. E. N. Dodge, Cambridge ed. of Spenser, 
p. Xiv. 
™Leland’s Itinerary, ed. Hearne, vol. 5, pp. vi, vii. 


Spenser's English Rivers. 107 


gods, three (20-2) the famous rivers of the world, twenty 
(23-39; 45-47) the English rivers, and six (48-53) the sea- 
nymphs. In his letter to Harvey, Spenser has nothing to say 
about sea-gods, nymphs, or famous rivers other than English; 
presumably the Epithalamion Thamesis did not employ them. 
Neither could it have contained the review of the Irish rivers, 
since the matter for that passage, being partly from Camden,” 
but in far the greatest part from Spenser’s personal acquaintance 
with Ireland, was not available till later years. Hence the Epi- 
thalamion Thamests could be represented in canto xi only in the 
part dealing with the English rivers. 

But at least half of this matter, as already shown, p. 70, was 
drawn from Camden’s Britannia, which did not appear till 1586, 
not less than six years after the composition of the lost poem. 
And in his use of Holinshed, Spenser consulted the fuller second 
edition of 1587 rather than the first of 1577.7. Then, too, in the 
letter to Harvey, Spenser had said that he would show in his 
Epithalamion Thamesis not only the Thames’ ‘first beginning, 
and offspring,’ which he has actually done in canto xi, but ‘all 
the Countrey, that he passeth thorough,’ which he has not done, 
though he may have done this in the lost poem.*® Lastly, the 
bride at the earlier wedding may not have been the Medway, 
which is Thames’ younger brother at S. C. Jul. 83. 

Obviously, then, canto xi owes but a small portion of its mate- 
rial to the Epithalamion Thamesis, and whatever has been 
retained from the earlier poem has been so unraveled and 
rewoven in the new fabric that it could be recognized only in 
shreds here and there, and, so far as any surviving semblance of 
the old poem may be sought in the Faery Queen, it is lost indeed. 

Spenser admits that even by 1580 he had already found that 
his treatment of this subject involved much labor. It was an 


% Harper, p. 17. 

™ Harper, pp. 12-15. I cannot find in Spenser’s language of 1580 any- 
thing to support Dr. Harper’s inference, on page 22 of her book, that 
Spenser was planning to supplement what he got from the first edition 
of Holinshed with material from other sources. 

* Such promises, however, Spenser did not keep literally, as in the case 
of the prefatory letter to Raleigh about the Faery Queen, in comparison 
with the poem itself. 


108 Charles G. Osgood. 


‘endlesse worke,’ harder than ‘to tell the sands, or count the 
starres,’ incapable of perfection, though the poet had ‘an 
hundred tongues, . . . And hundred mouthes and voice of 
brasse, . . . and endlesse memorie’;*° and as the reader, with 
an eye to the poet’s originals, watches him in the process of 
selection, arrangement, and adaptation, he cannot doubt the 
pains which Spenser bestowed upon this episode. 

Yet the final effect is anything but laborious. The entire 
canto is full of life and measured freedom, crowded but well 
ordered, moving to the finest cadence of Spenser’s music. Nor 
is it composed of mere spectacle and pageantry. Beneath it all 
one catches the vastly varied sounds of water, its murmur, it 
tinkle, its rush, its roar. The whole picture is permeated with 
the spirit of water, and expresses its variableness, power, and 
beauty as subtly and surely as these are to be felt in Undine. 


GRA, Oe ee ete als es 


~~ 


TRANSACTIONS OF ee 


RHE CONNECTICUT ACADEMY 
OF Ak brseAND SCIENCES 


VOLUME 23)] FEBRUARY 1920 [PAGES 109-158 


New Species of Devonian 
Fossils from Western 
‘Tennessee | 


BY 


CARL O. DUNBAR 


NEW HAVEN, CONNECTICUT 
PUBLISHED BY THE 
CONNECTICUT ACADEMY OF ARTS AND SCIENCES 
AND TO BE OBTAINED ALSO FROM THE 
YALE UNIVERSITY PRESS 


‘ 


Contributions from the Paleontological Laboratory, Peabody 


Yale University, New Haven, Connecticut, U. S. A. ~ 


> ree. 
* 
: 5 


THE TUTTLE, MOREHOUSE & TAYLOR COMPANY 


Mere 
")¢ 


ttf 


TABLE OF CONTENTS 


oD 


i elle i ee bi Me 


re ee ie rey ys" 


! 


ey w= 


PAGE 
EY EPRODUCTION «. : : : + 153 
DESCRIPTIONZOF SPECIES ; : : SoS ele 
Crass ANTHOZOA . . ‘ : fo > WE 
Zaphrentis parsonsensis, n. sp. ey 
Favosites foerstei, n. sp. 117 
Pleurodictyum trifoliatum, n. sp. 118 
Criass BLASTOIDEA 119 
Codaster lore, n. sp. 119 
CLass CRINOIDEA 120 
Edriocrinus adnascens, n. sp. 120 
CLass BRACHIOPODA 121 
Dalmanella pygmea, n. sp. 121 
Dalmanella rockhousensis, n. sp. . 122 
Dalmanella macra, n. sp. 123 
Dictyonella subgibbosa, n. sp. 124 
Leptena ingens, n. sp. 125 
Pholidostrophia lindenensis, n. sp. 126 
Brachyprion purduei, n. sp. 126 
Strophonella punctulifera holladayi, n. var. 127 
Strophonella lineolata, n. sp. 128 
Leptostrophia beckiu tennesseensis, n. var. 129 
Chonetes wadet, n. sp. 129 
Chonetes fornacula, n. sp. 130 
Chonetes hudsonicus camdenensis, n. mut. . 13 
Gypidula multicostata, n. sp. 131 
Rhynchotreta insinuata, n. sp. 432 
Wilsonia wadei, n. sp. 133 


I1l2 


Table of Contents. 


Uncinulus lindenensis, n. sp. 
Eatonia tennesseensis, n. sp. 
Eatonia fissicosta, n. sp. ; 
Oriskania condom (McChesney) 
Megalanteris (?) saffordi, n. sp. 
Delthyris cyrtinoides, n. sp. 


Delthyris octocostata tennesseensis, n. mut. 


Trematospira bella, n. sp. 
Trematospira costata angusta, n. var. 


CLass GASTROPODA . 


Saffordella, n. gen. 

Saffordella tennesseensis, n. sp. 
Distemnostoma, n. gen. | 
Distemnostoma princeps, n. sp. 
Distemneastoma curtum, n. sp. 
Aulopea, n. gen. 

Aulopea nelsoni, n. sp. 

Holopea planidorsata, n. sp. 
Diaphorostoma quadrangulare, n. sp. 


CLass CRUSTACEA 


Dalmanites purduet, n. sp. 


Dalmanites retusus, n. sp. 


nim > 


((3 
INTRODUCTION 


The Devonian is represented along the Western Valley of 
Tennessee by highly fossiliferous formations of Helderbergian, 
Oriskanian, and Onondagan age. Unconformably overlying 
these strata is the widespread but nearly unfossiliferous Chatta- 
nooga shale, which is referred with some question to the late 
Devonian, but which may be of early Mississippian age. The 
stratigraphy and correlation of these Devonian formations have 
recently been discussed by the writer elsewhere.t. During the 
study of the faunas it was found that a number of characteristic 
indigenous forms are new to science, and these it is the purpose 
of the present paper to describe. There are thirty-seven new 
species, and three new genera. 

The accompanying synoptic table (page 114) will indicate the 
sequence and something of the character of the several Devo- 
nian formations. The Linden or Helderbergian group is here 
well developed, consisting mostly of limestone and calcareous 
shale, with a thickness of about 250 feet. Three breaks in this 
sequence separate the Helderbergian of Tennessee into four 
formations, but one finds it difficult to correlate these divisions 
in detail with the four divisions of the same group in the Appa- 
lachian trough. The reason for this is to be found in the fact 
that the Devonian of western Tennessee belongs to a southern or 
Gulf embayment. This epeiric sea was for the most part iso- 
lated and measurably independent of the Appalachian trough. 
In general, the Helderbergian seas were rather restricted in their 
spread except during the New Scotland epoch, when in many 
countries there was an expansion of the seas. At this time only, 
during the Helderbergian, is there clear evidence of direct com- 
munication between the Appalachian trough and the southern 
embayment which was covering western Tennessee; and the 
Birdsong shale fauna is then so nearly identical with that of the 
New Scotland of New York as to show not only exact equiva- 
lence in age, but also direct faunal inter-dispersions. Even at 


> Stratigraphy and correlation of the Devonian of western Tennessee. 
Amer. Jour. Sci. (4), vol. 46, 1918, pp. 732-756. Published in more 
extended form as Bulletin 21 of the Tennessee Geological Survey, 1910. 


114 Carl O. Dunbar, 
GENERALIZED DEVONIAN SECTION OF WESTERN TENNESSEE 
— 2 = 
SERIES| GROUP FORMATION | ee | CHARACTER 
& Chautau- Chattanooga shale 20’+ Black fissile carbona- 
= quan Hardin sandstone ceous shale 
= member Thin basal sandstone 
oS TUS ERE a igen ——— — =e — 
> | Senecan 
——|—— Break 
Erian 
is 
2s 
= ? ; 
2 Pegram limestone 10+ Heavy-bedded white 
2 : | limestone 
9 Ulsterian Break — a eae 
er -o—z200’/+ Thin-bedded buff col- 
aS Camden chert ored novaculite 
— ~ — Break -— - ——- 
| Harriman chert 30—55' Heavier bedded white 
‘ and buff novaculite 
Oriskanian Break a Z oe 
Quall limestone TO Heavy-bedded cherty 
gray limestone 
| ——— Break 
s Decaturville chert 6’ Porous gray chert 
3) 
‘e Break Jie 
= 
© . | ,  Bluish shaly limestone 
g Birdsong shale 35 65 Laity. barr: : 
—_ | 
SS Helder- : Bret ea 5 ; 3 
bergian ¢ Flat Gap o—53' Massive pure lime- 
Lind ey | stone _ 
inden |. | Massive limestone and 
| Bear Branch— o—45' oolitic hematite in 
|; Pyburn | | north — impure 
| o | cherty limestone in 
> 
aS south 
© Ross o—60’+ Impure thin-bedded 
teal cherty limestone 
Break ~ ee 


‘Rockhouse shale 


| o—26’ Bluish green calcare- 
| ous shale 


New Species of Devonian Fossils. 115 


this time, however, the Tennessee faunas retained something of 
their provincial aspect, for certain highly characteristic forms, 
such as the Scyphocrini and Camarocrini among the crinoids and 
Rensselerina medioplicata, Eatonia tennesseensis, Gypidula mul- 
ticostata and Meristella atoka among the brachiopods, did not 
spread into the Appalachian trough. Devonian formations hav- 
ing the same faunal facies as that of the Birdsong shale also 
occur along the Mississippi River in southwestern Illinois and 
adjacent parts of Missouri and again further to the west in the 
Arbuckle uplift of Oklahoma. These occurrences of Helder- 
bergian strata serve to indicate something of the extent of this 
southern embayment, whose eastern shore flanked on the western 
side of the Nashville Dome and lay not far east of the present 
Western Valley, and whose northern limit extended some dis- 
tance beyond Cairo, Illinois. 

The equivalence of the Birdsong shale and the New Scotland 
being evident, it would seem from the stratigraphic relations that 
the Rockhouse shale has its time equivalent in some part of the 
Keyser, and that the thick Olive Hill formation is of the age of 
the Coeymans, if not also of a part of the Keyser. As for the 
faunal evidence, the fauna of the Rockhouse shale is certainly 
of very early Devonian age, a fact that is indicated both by 
Silurian holdovers, as Dictyonella subgibbosa, and by the primi- 
tive aspect of such Devonian forms as Pleurodictyum trifoliatum. 
No faunal relations with the Keyser can be seen, however, for 
there was at this time no connection with the Appalachian basin. 
This small fauna has yielded eleven of the new species here 
described. 

The fauna of the Olive Hill formation is remarkable for the 
dominance of the Scyphocrini and their associated root-bulbs, 
the Camarocrini. These crinoids had previously appeared in 
Tennessee in the Decatur limestone of late Middle Silurian age. 
They recur in abundance in the Rockhouse shale, are at their 
climax in the Ross limestone member of the Olive Hill forma- 
tion, and persist with a few stragglers through the Birdsong 
shale. They are also extremely abundant in the Helderbergian 
of Oklahoma. They are particularly characteristic of this 
southern embayment, where they must have been sequestered 
from Middle Silurian well into early Devonian time. During 


116 Carl O. Dunbar. 


this period they appeared only sporadically in the Appalachian 
trough, several specimens of Camarocrinus having been found in 
the Manlius of New York, while these anchoring bulbs are com- 
mon at one thin horizon in the Keyser of Maryland. In other 
respects, the fauna of the Olive Hill formation is largely made 
up of species which continue into the succeeding Birdsong forma- 
tion, and the chief difference in these faunas is the sudden 
appearance in the Birdsong shale of many new species, the typi- 
cal New Scotland facies, which now come to mingle with those 
already present in the Ross limestone. 

The Oriskany faunas of the Quall and Harriman formations 
again show an advent of the Appalachian faunas almost 
unchanged. 

The Camden chert, on the other hand, has a fauna distinctive 
ot the southern embayment, which occupied practically the same 
position as that of Helderbergian time. It was only during the 
deposition of the almost immediately succeeding Pegram lime- 
stone that communication with the Appalachian seas was again 
established, and the Onondagan coral faunas attained western 
Tennessee. The evidence for the Onondagan age of the Camden 
chert is fully presented in the larger paper mentioned above. 

The study of these Devonian faunas was made in the paleon- 
tological laboratories at Yale University, and the types of the 
new species here described are the property of the Peabody 
Museum, The writer wishes to acknowledge his indebtedness 
to Professor Charles Schuchert for helpful criticism in the 
preparation of the paper. 


DESCRIPTION OF SPECIES 


CLASS ANTHOZOA 
SuBcLass TETRACORALLA 
FAMILY ZAPHRENTIDE 
Zaphrentis parsonsensis, n. sp. 
Plate fies! 1; :2 
Description: Corallite very large, simple, conical, straight, 
expanding uniformly and rapidly. Apical angle about 60°, so 
that the diameter of the calyx equals its height. Septa about 
120 in number where the diameter of the calyx is 70 mm., alter- 
nating long and short. The type specimen is a natural cast which 
does not show the tabulz, and they were probably not strongly 
developed. The length of the septa in the upper part of the cup 
is not shown, but in its basal portion the longer septa reach the 
center, where they are twisted into a pseudocolumella. 
Dimensions: Length, 90 mm.; diameter of calyx, 90 mm. 
Occurrence: A single specimen, the type, was found in the 
Harriman chert on Harriman Creek, near Parsons. 


SuscLass TABULATA 
FAMILY FAVOSITIDE 
Favosites foerstei, n. sp. 
Plate I, figs. 3, 4 

Description: Corallum subhemispherical, the convex base cov- 
ered with a thick and concentrically wrinkled epitheca which 
covers all but the youngest corallites. Upper surface, in the 
fossil condition, flat or concave. At the center of the base is a 
small point of attachment about which the corallum is symmetri- 
cally developed. The prismatic corallites arise from an unde- 
fined central axis and quickly bend outward into a horizontal 
position, which they maintain to the periphery. The corallites 
vary in diameter from I.5 mm. to 3.2 mm. at the surface, but the 
majority measure about 2.3 mm. Each side of a corallite bears 
two vertical rows of round mural pores, of which a row of ten 


118 Carl O. Dunbar, 


pores occupies a distance of 7 mm. to 7.4 mm. Tabule some- 
what irregularly arranged, eight to twelve in a distance of 10 
mm. 

Dimensions: An average specimen measures 50 mm. in diam- 
eter and 25 mm. in height, but there is much variation in size, the 
largest specimen being 85 mm. in diameter. 

Discussion: The convex base and horizontal corallites of this 
species contrast strongly with the flat base and ascending coral- 
lites of F. conicus, with which it is associated. It most closely 
resembles the mid-Devonian F. hemisphericus, but that species 
is much larger, has a more pointed and decidedly excentric apex 
to its base. 

Occurrence: Common in the Birdsong shale and Ross lime- 
stone at localities on Birdsong and Lick creeks, at Perryville, 
Grandview, Pyburns, etc. 

Name: The form is named after Doctor August F. Foerste, 
who recognized it as a distinct species but did not describe or 
name it.? 


Pleurodictyum trifoliatum, n. sp. 
Plate I, figs. 5-7 

Description: Small trifoliate corallum, composed of three 
shallow cup-shaped corallites. The corallites are subcircular on 
their free sides but are flattened slightly where they are con- 
tiguous. Externally they are covered by a wrinkled epitheca. 
Internally the wall of each corallite is marked by about thirty 
strongly granulose longitudinal ridges, and the bottom of each 
cup is irregularly granulose. The common wall between con- 
tiguous corallites is irregularly perforated by communicating 
mural pores. The colony almost invariably consists of three 
corallites, though a few have been found with only two, and one 
specimen has but one; there is also a single instance of a colony 
with five corallites. 

Dimensions: Diameter of a corallite, 5-6 mm.; height, 3-5 mm. 

Discussion: The development of this simple colony is readily 
made out, and it agrees exactly with that determined by Beecher? 


+The Silurian and Devonian limestones of western Tennessee. Jour. 
Geology, vol. II, 1903, p. 714. 


*Beecher, C. E., The development of a Paleozoic poriferous coral. 
Trans. Conn. Acad. Arts Sci., vol. 8, 1891, pp. 207-212. 


New Species of Devonian Fossils. 119 


for P. lenticulare, excepting that the earlier and ancestral spe- 
cies, P. trifoliatum, attains maturity at the three-celled stage and 
usually does not proceed further. The specimen with the initial 
zooid only is especially instructive, since it was not attached to 
any solid support and the basal side is therefore free to observa- 
tion. The corallite appears to be mature, though the lateral buds 
failed to develop. It is at least suggestive that the lack of the 
usual solid support for the colony was the reason for this. The 
places where the buds should have developed are indicated by 
nodes-on the outside of the corallite, and by corresponding pits 
within. As is to be expected, one of them appeared earlier than 
the other. Figure 5 of Plate I is also interesting, since the 
lateral corallites have not covered the prostrate initial portion 
of the primary corallite. The development of the typical tri- 
foliate corallum took place in the following manner: The initial 
cell was at first procumbent, spreading rapidly and secreting an 
attached base. When this base had been completed, the upward 
growth of the walls began. At this point a lateral cell budded 
off from one side of the initial corallite, and soon thereafter a 
second one budded off from the opposite side. These secondary 
cells spread their procumbent bases, often covering the prostrate 
apex of the parent cell, and then as they grew upright, developed, 
with the initial cell, into the regular three-zooid stage as shown 
in Figure 7, Plate I. 

This is the earliest and simplest known species of Pleurodic- 
tyum. In the succeeding formations of the Linden group, the 
typical Helderbergian species, P. lenticulare, is quite common. 

Occurrence: Common in the Rockhouse shale at the sulphur 
spring, 5 miles southeast of Savannah, and at Rockhouse, both 
on Horse Creek, Hardin County. 


CLASS BLASTOIDEA 

FAMILY CODASTERIDZ 

Codaster lore, n. sp. 
Plate: Tiiies: 15/2 


Description: This rare little blastoid resembles C. attenuatus 
and C. canadensis of the Middle Devonian. The calyx is an 
inverted pentagonal pyramid with an obtusely pyramidal summit. 


120 Carl O. Dunbar, 


Basal angle about 52°. Angle between sides and summit slopes 
about 120°. Ambulacra lanceolate-petaloid. The lancet plate 
bears two rows of side plates separated by a central food groove 
and bordered on the outer side by narrow grooves separating 
them from adjacent radials. The margins of the latter are 
nearly vertical and the hydrospire slits are practically hidden until 
the side plates are removed. These slits are only three in num- 
ber on each side of each ambulacrum. ‘The surface of the calyx 
plates appears smooth in the specimens studied. 

Dimensions: Height of calyx, 10 mm.; maximum width, 7 
mm. 

Discussion: The new species may be distinguished from the 
nearest forms, C. attenuatus and C. canadensis, by the fact that it 
is shorter and more robust, its ambulacra narrower and more 
elongate, and its hydrospire slits fewer in number and less well 
exposed. 

Occurrence: Found near the middle of the Birdsong shale, 1% 
miles south of the old Allen’s mill on Birdsong Creek, and 21%4 
miles northeast of Parsons on the J. P. Rains place. 


CLASS CRINOIDEA 
FAMILY AGASSIZOCRINIDZ 
Edriocrinus adnascens, n. sp. 
Piate diene. 3 


This little crinoid is known only from its base, which was 
invariably cemented to some foreign object. Although it was 
rather common, especially in the Birdsong shale, none of the 
specimens yet found retain the radials and brachials. The 
depressions for the insertion of the former on the basal cup are, 
however, clearly shown. ‘The upper side of the basal cup com- 
pares closely with that of a much larger but unattached species 
occurring only in the highest layers of the Birdsong shale. The 
latter Doctor Frank Springer proposes to describe as E. pyrami- 
datus, and of this species, fortunately, he has a complete speci- 
men. 

Description: Base flat and cemented to some foreign object, 
usually a brachiopod shell. The central portion is occupied by 
a broad and very shallow depression, bounded by a low rim, out- 


New Species of Devonian Fossils. 121 


side of which the surface is concave as it slopes away to the 
margin. The rim of the shallow basal cup is scalloped by six 
slight, concave depressions for the insertion of the five radials 
and the anal plate. Since these are all of the same size, the anal 
was doubtless of about the same width as the radials. These 
scallops continue to the center of the visceral cup as shallow, 
concave, radial depressions. Radials and brachials unknown. 

There is considerable variation in the size and thickness of 
these crinoid bases, the height of the rim, and the proportionate 
size of the cup. Frequently the base is very thin, appearing as a 
mere circular ring, while in other cases, as in the specimen shown 
in Figure 3, it is thickened and spreads beyond the margin of 
the visceral depression. 

Dimensions: Width of the base of the type specimen, 13 mm.; 
width of cup, 8 mm.; height of rim of base, 3 mm. Of another 
specimen: base, 14 mm.; cup, 12 mm.; height, 2.8 mm. 

Discussion: It is known that E. sacculus of the Oriskany was 
sessile in youth and later became free-living, and it is thought 
that E. pocilliformis may have undergone a similar development. 
The new species, however, evidently remained attached through- 
out life. That these are not the bases of young specimens of E. 
pocilliformis is quite evident from their size, their extreme flat- 
_ hess, and especially the fact that E. pocilliformis is exceedingly 
rare in the formations where this species is abundant. 

Occurrence: Rockhouse shale, at Rockhouse and the sulphur 
spring. Birdsong shale, at Perryville and numerous localities 


along Big Lick and Birdsong creeks in Benton and Decatur 
counties. 


CLASS BRACHIOPODA 
FAMILY ORTHIDE 
Dalmanella pygmea, n. sp. 

Plate li figse' 4.95 
Description: Shell very small, subcircular to subquadrate in 
outline, and nearly equally biconvex. Hinge-line one-fourth 
shorter than the greatest width of the shell, cardinal extremities 
rather sharply rounded. Area narrow and not extending to the 
extremities of the hinge-line. Surface covered with very fine 


122 Carl 'O. Dunbar, 


strize of which ten to twelve occupy a space of 2 mm. at the ante- 
rior margin of the shell. The striz increase by both intercala- 
tion and bifurcation, and there is considerable variation from 
subequal stria in some specimens to distinctly fasciculate striz in 
others. Pedicle valve strongly convex, with a slight undefined 
median fold. Beak small and incurved over the cardinal area. 
Dorsal valve also strongly convex and but little shallower than 
the pedicle. A distinct but narrow median sinus extends entirely 
to the beak. Interior characters closely resembling those of D. 
subcarinata. 

Dimensions of a mature individual: Length, 7 mm.; width, 7.5 
mm.; depth, 4 mm. 

Discussion: This beautiful little species closely resembles the 
young of D. subcarinata, with which it is associated. Teas 
slightly more finely striated and distinctly more gibbous, how- 
ever, than the young of that species. It has a matured and 
dwarfish appearance. The subequal convexity of its valves will 
distinguish it from other described species of this small size. 

Occurrence: Birdsong shale member of the Linden. At the 
Swayne’s mill locality, at exposures on Big Lick and Birdsong 
creeks, and at other localities in Benton and Decatur counties. 


Dalmanella rockhousensis, n. sp. 
Plate II, figs. 6-8 


Description: Shell small, subcircular in outline, width equal to 
or very slightly greater than the length. Hinge-line shorter than 
the greatest width of the shell, cardinal extremities rounded, 
cardinal area shorter than half the width of the shell and strongly 
curved. Ventral valve rather strongly convex, prominent in the 
umbonal portion, but curving evenly to the front and sides with- 
out any fold. Beak small and incurved over the cardinal area. 
Dorsal valve gently convex, marked by a sinus which is very 
narrow but distinct at the beak and widens toward the anterior 
margin, where it is shallow and not sharply defined. Surface 
covered with very fine radiating striz, which increase rapidly 
by intercalation and frequently show a distinctly fasciculate 
arrangement, coarser striz being separated by three or four finer 
ones. About ten strie in a space of 2 mm. along the margin. 


@ 


New Species of Devoman Fossils. 123 


In the ventral valve the hinge-teeth are strong, supported by 
dental plates which continue forward on the floor of the valve 
as very slightly diverging ridges reaching to the center of the 
valve and bounding the small, slender, deeply impressed muscle- 
scars. The muscle-scar is deeply bilobed in front, each half 
tapering out to a sharp point alongside the ridges just described. 
In the dorsal valve the cardinal process is exceedingly minute, 
the dental sockets well developed, the brachial lamelle strong 
and produced forward as a distinct ridge bounding the narrow 
elongate muscle-scars which reach the middle of the valve. 

Dimensions: The average specimen has a length of 9 mm.; 
width, Io mm.; depth, 4 mm. A large specimen: length, 12 
mm.; width, 11 mm.; depth, 6 mm. 

Discussion: This species resembles D. postelegantula of the 
Decker Ferry of New Jersey, but in comparison with that species 
it is smaller, more nearly circular in outline, less carinate on the: 
ventral valve, its dorsal sinus extends to the beak, and it is more 
finely lined. Compared with D. concinna of the Keyser forma- 
tion, this shell is much smaller, more finely lined, lacks the cari- 
nation of the ventral valve, and has a relatively small cardinal 
area. It is perhaps closest to D. elegantula of the Niagaran, but 
that species is proportionately longer and its dorsal valve is flat 
or concave. 

Occurrence: Common in the Rockhouse shale at the sulphur 
spring and at Rockhouse, both on Horse Creek, Hardin County. 


Dalmanella macra, n. sp. 
Plate II, figs. 9, Io 


Description: Shell transversely subelliptical in outline, hinge- 
line a little shorter than the greatest width of the shell, cardinal 
extremities sharply rounded. The ventral valve is subcarinate 
along the median line, but the lateral slopes are gently concave, 
giving the shell an emacerate appearance. The dorsal valve is 
slightly convex in the umbonal region, but concave in the ante- 
rior portion. The valve bears a median sinus which is narrow at 
the beak but widens rapidly anteriorly and loses its distinctness 
in the general concavity of the valve. Ventral muscle-scars 
extremely small, almost embraced between the hinge-teeth. 


124 Carl O. Dunbar, 


Dorsal muscle-scars similar to those of D. subcarinata, but more 
slender. Surface covered by coarse fasciculated striz, of which 
about thirteen occupy a space of 5 mm. at the margin. 

Dimensions: Length, 15 mm.; width, 17 mm.; depth, 6 mm. | 

Discussion: In outline and carination this shell closely resem- 
bles D. subcarinata, but in comparison with that species it is 
more coarsely striated, has a more emacerated appearance, the 
dorsal valve being concave in the anterior portion, and, internally, 
the ventral muscle-scars are proportionately less than half as 
large as in D. subcarinata. 

Occurrence: Rockhouse shale at Rockhouse and the sulphur 
spring, both on Horse Creek, Hardin County. 


FAMILY EICHWALDIIDE 
Dictyonella subgibbosa, n. sp. 
Plate II, figs. 11-13 


Description: Shell of medium to large size, subtriangular in 
outline. Ventral valve strongly convex in the posterior half, its 
beak prominent and large and strongly curved over that of the 
dorsal valve. The sides of the beak form less than a right angle, 
usually about 80°. The anterior part of this valve is occupied 
by a broad shallow sinus slightly exceeding one third the width 
of the shell. The sinus is generally distinctly marked at the 
front of the valve, but it becomes shallower and indistinct posteri- 
orly, continuing as a mesiai flattening entirely to the denuded spot 
on the beak. The dorsal valve is more gibbous and more nearly | 
oval in outline, its beak strongly incurved beneath that of the 
opposite valve. At the anterior margin it bears a distinct but 
broad low fold which becomes lower posteriorly and is lost in 
the general convexity of the valve near its middle. The surface 
reticulations are very fine and of nearly uniform size over vari- 
ous parts of the shell. The pits are about as long as wide, and 
where well preserved appear nearly round or sometimes hex- 
agonal. They are about one-half larger than those of D. gibbosa 
and about one-half as large as the average of those in D. reticu- 
lata. Counting along a row, twenty-eight to a of the pits 
occupy a space of 5 mm. 

Discussion: Only fragmentary specimens of this species were 


New Species of Devoman Fossils. 125 


found in the Rockhouse shale in Tennessee, and the description 
is based upon specimens from the equivalent faunal horizon in 
the Arbuckle Mountains of Oklahoma. Collections at Yale made 
by Doctor C. A. Reeds show that the Rockhouse faunal zone is 
present in Oklahoma between the Henryhouse and Haragan 
formations. 

The shell rather closely resembles D. gibbosa, but upon com- 
parison with the type of Hall’s species, it was seen to be a dis- 
tinct form. The distinguishing features may be summed up as 
follows: The ventral beak in D. gibbosa is smaller and more 
neatly pointed than in the new species. Its ventral sinus is more 
obscure and is confined entirely to the anterior portion of the 
valve, the central part of the umbonal region being evenly ven- 
tricose, while in the new species the sinus is more sharply 
defined and extends as a distinct flattening entirely to the beak, 
as in D. reticulata. The coarseness of the surface reticulations 
is also distinctive, six pits in the new species occupying the space 
of nine in D. gibbosa. 

Occurrence: Rare in the Rockhouse shale at Rockhouse, Har- 
din County, but common in an equivalent zone in the Arbuckle 
Mountains of Oklahoma. 


FAMILY STROPHOMENIDZ 
Leptzna ingens, n. sp. 
Plate IT, fre. 24 

Description: Shell very large, semi-elliptical, and gently con- 
cavo-convex but not geniculate. Huinge-line straight, making the 
greatest width of the shell; lateral margins usually very slightly 
contracted below the hinge, curving evenly into the regularly 
rounded anterior margin. Ventral valve varying from slightly 
to moderately convex; . curvature stronger near the beak and 
near the anterior margin than over the middle portion of the 
valve. Muscle-scars strongly impressed, similar to those in L. 
rhomboidalis. Surface marked by fine radial striations as in that 
species, and the posterior portion, only, bearing rather fine and 
subdued concentric undulations. 

Dimensions: Length, 49 mm.; width,60 mm. Convexity varv- 
ing from 6 to 12 mm. 


126 Carl O. Dunbar, 


Discussion: This ponderous Leptena is nearest to L. ventri- 
cosa, a contemporaneous form in the Appalachian trough, but is 
larger and readily distinguished by its contour and the subdued 
character of its corrugations. Externally it resembles some of 
the large Leptostrophias rather than a Leptena, but the deep 
ventral muscle-scar is distinctly that of the latter genus. 

Occurrence: Harriman novaculite, near Camden, Parsons, 
Perryville, etc. 


Pholidostrophia lindenensis, n. sp. 
Plate II, figs. 15, 16 

Description: Shell small, semi-elliptical in outline, hinge-line 
a little longer than the shell in front of it. Ventral valve 
stiongly and evenly arched, almost hemispherical, with the curva- 
ture slightly flattened only near the cardinal extremities. Con- 
tour of the dorsal valve closely conforming to that of the ventral. 
Hinge-line denticulate. Surface entirely smooth. Inner layers 
of the shell coarsely punctate. 

Dimensions: Length, 9 mm.; width, 12 mm.; depth of con- 
vexity, 4.5 mm. 

Discussion: In its size and contour this little shell resembles 
P. (?) niagarensis of the mid-Silurian, but that species shows 
distinct striations and has a more gibbous umbonal region. 
From P. iowaensis of the Middle Devonian it differs in being 
more strongly arched, proportionately longer and narrower, and 
in the absence of lamellose growth varices. 

Occurrence: A rare shell in the Birdsong shale, found at 
Perryville and at the old Swayne’s mill site near the mouth of 
Big Sandy River. 


Brachyprion purduei, n. sp. 
Plate II, figs. 22, 23 


Description: Shell semi-elliptical, length generally about three- 
fourths the width but in some cases equalling the latter. Ven- 
tral valve evenly and rather strongly convex, the greatest ele- 
vation being near the center, from which point there is an equal 
curvature to the anterior, posterior, and lateral margins. Hinge- 
line straight and equalling or slightly exceeding the width of the 


New Species of Devonian Fossils. 127 


shell below. Dorsal valve conforming in contour to the ventral. 
Surface marked by fine striz, about twelve of which occupy a 
width of 5 mm. The striz are low and rounded and separated 
by rounded interspaces. They increase rapidly by bifurcation 
on the dorsal valve, while both bifurcation and intercalation were 
observed on the ventral valves, the latter predominating. The 
strie are crossed by very fine concentric lines. When slightly 
exfoliated, the shell appears almost smooth, only darker translu- 
cent lines marking the former position of the striz. Shell sub- 
stance finely punctate. Cardinal area narrow and mostly confined 
to the ventral valve. Denticulations extending only about half 
way from the beak to the cardinal extremities, about twenty 
denticulations in a distance of 5 mm. On the ventral valve the 
muscle-scars are very lightly impressed, consisting of narrow 
flabelliform diductors, embracing the narrow adductors, which 
are close up under the beak. 

Dimensions: Length, 32 mm.; width, 40 mm.; depth of con- 
vexity, 10 mm. 

Occurrence: Abundant in the Birdsong shale at the “steel 
bridge” on Big Sandy River, at numerous localities on Birdsong 
and Big Lick creeks, and at Perryville. Also occurs in the Olive 
Hill formation at Olive Hill, Grandview, and elsewhere. 

Name: Species name given in honor of Doctor A. H. Purdue, 
late state geologist of Tennessee. 


Strophonella punctulifera holladayi, n. var. 
Plate Il, figs. 18; 19 


Description: Shell having the general shape and contour of 
S. punctulifera. Surface marked by a few fine and widely 
spaced striations, between which are nearly flat interspaces cov- 
ered with much finer, subdued striz. The larger striations are 
sharp and threadlike, less than 0.5 mm. across, and equally as 
high. They increase by intercalation, in the umbonal region 
only, so that the interspaces increase in width to an average of 
3 mm. at the anterior margin. About thirty of these strong 
striz may be counted around the edge of the shell. The obscure 
secondary striz, of which ten to twelve occupy a space of 2 mm., 
are barely visible to the eye. The whole surface is covered by 


128 Carl O. Dunbar, 


exceedingly fine concentric lines, of which twenty-five to thirty 
occupy a space of 2 mm. Occasionally one of the major striz 
disappears before reaching the edge of the shell, in which case 
one of the nearby secondary striz at once becomes stronger to 
take its place. 

Dimensions of an imperfect specimen: Length, about 40 mm.; 
width, about 50 mm. 

Discussion: In the Linden formation of Tennessee, S. punc- 
tulifera has a tendency to fail to normally increase its strie with 
growth. For this reason the specimen described is retained as a 
variety of that highly variable species. In the rather extensive 
collection made by the writer, however, no closely connecting 
forms were found to link this new variety to that species. The 
shell most closely resembles S. williamsi of the Niagaran, which 
is a much smaller species with more distinct secondary striz. 

Occurrence: Birdsong shale, on Sycamore Creek, near Hol- 
laday. 

Name: The variety is named for Mr. John Holladay, to whom 
the writer is indebted for information and fossils from the Syca- 
more Creek localities. 


Strophonella lineolata, n. sp. 
Plate I], figs:20, 21 


Description: Outline semi-elliptical, the length varying 
between three-fourths and four-fifths the width, the hinge-line 
usually a little less than the greatest width below. Ventral valve 
slightly convex in the umbonal region, and evenly concave over 
the lateral and anterior portions; the dorsal valve conforming 
in contour, slightly concave near the umbo, and gently convex 
to the margin but not geniculate. The depth of curvature of the 
shell equals about one-fourth of its lateral width. 

The surface is covered with narrow, sharp striations, sepa- 
rated by concave interspaces that are about twice as wide as 
the striez. The striz increase by intercalation and average about 
seven in a space of 5 mm. on the middle portion, but usually 
become finer and more numerous near the anterior margin, where 
about ten occupy a space of 5 mm. 

Dimensions: Width, 44 mm.; length, 35 mm. 


New Species of Devoman Fossils. 129 


Discussion: This species belongs to the group of S. punctuli- 
fera, but is distinguished from that form by the fineness of its 
striations and by being less strongly arcuate. 

The fine striations make it closely resemble S. keyserensis of 
the Keyser formation, but that older species is smaller, more 
elongate, and has the hinge-line more extended. 

Occurrence: Common in the Birdsong and Olive Hill forma- 
tions at many localities in Benton and Decatur counties. 


Leptostrophia beckii tennesseensis, n. var. 
Plate III, fig. 18 
Desct iption: This fine large Leptostrophia is distinguished 
from L. beckii only by the character of the corrugations which 
ornament its surface. Instead of the fairly regular and even- 
crested concentric corrugations of L. beckii, this variety is 
marked by concentric ridges that are not only crooked but also 
undulate in height. The result is the characteristic wavy or 
“dimpled” surface shown in the figure. 
Occurrence: This variety is confined to the Birdsong shale, 
and was found at Perryville and at other localities along Big 
Lick and Birdsong creeks. 


FAMILY PRODUCTIDZ 
Chonetes wadei, n. sp. 
Plate II, fig. 14 


Description: Shell very minute, semi-circular, moderately con- 
vex, more strongly arched toward the anterior margin than in 
the umbonal region. Hinge-line straight and slightly longer 
than the shell below. A cardinal spine about I mm. long and 
directed slightly outward is located 1 mm. from the beak. 
Another probably existed near the cardinal extremity. Surface 
covered by exceedingly fine rounded striations, of which about 
eleven occupy a space of 2 mm. About sixty may be counted 
along the margin of the valve. Dorsal valve and interior 
unknown. 

Dimensions: Length, 3.5 mm.; width, 6 mm.; convexity, 
about 1.2 mm. 


130 Carl O. Dunbar, 


Discussion: This little shell seems to be closest to C. subacuti- 
radiatus from the New Scotland of Maryland, from which it 
differs in being less arcuate, proportionately wider, and in hay- 
ing about twice as many striations and these correspondingly 
finer. ‘ 

Occurrence: A single well preserved specimen was found near 
the center of the Bear Branch member of the Olive Hill forma- 
tion at Olive Hill. 

Name: Named after the writer’s friend, Doctor Bruce Wade, 
who directed him to many localities in the southern part of the 
Tennessee valley. 


Chonetes fornacula, n. sp. 
Plate II, fig. 25 

Description: Shell minute, very strongly convex, longitudinally 
semi-elliptical in outline. Greatest width at the hinge-line, 
below which the sides are very slightly constricted, converging 
gently to the more sharply rounded anterior margin. Umbo of 
the ventral valve very gibbous, overarching the hinge-line. 
Curvature about uniform from beak to anterior margin along 
the median line, but sharper from the middle of the valve toward 
the lateral margins and then flattening out near the slightly 
extended cardinal extremities. Surface covered by relatively 
coarse angular strize which increase by intercalation. About 
fourteen striz may be counted around the margin of a specimen 
4 mm. wide. Cardinal spines not known. 

Dimensions: Length, 4 mm.; width, 4 mm.; height, 2 mm. 

Discussion: This minute Chonetes belongs to a group of small, 
arcuate, coarsely striated forms which includes C. billingsi, C. 
mucronatus, C. laticosta and C. highlandensis. The Camden 
chert species is smaller, proportionately longer, and more strongly 
arched than any of these forms. It most closely resembles C. 
laticosta of the Corniferous, but in addition to the differences 
noted above, that species is less constricted in front of the hinge- 
line. 

Occurrence: Rare in the Camden chert, in the vicinity of 
Camden. 


New Species of Devonian Fossils. 131 


Chonetes hudsonicus camdenensis, n. mut. 
Plate Tl) ig. 17 


Description: Shell of medium size, almost semi-circular in 
outline. Greatest width at the hinge-line, beneath which the 
lateral margins are very slightly contracted and then round 
evenly into the nearly transverse anterior margin. Pedicle valve 
varying from nearly flat to gently and evenly convex, except 
where slightly flattened toward the cardinal extremities. Its 
cardinal margin commonly shows one short spine near the car- 
dinal extremity, directed outward at an angle of 50° or 60° from 
the beak. There are indications of two pairs of smaller spines 
nearer the beak. Surface covered by very fine radiating striz 
of which about twenty occupy a space of 5 mm. Striz increas- 
ing by both intercalation and bifurcation. 

Dimensions of an average specimen: Length, 12 mm.; width, 
19 mm.; convexity, 2.5 mm. 

Discussion: This shell closely resembles C. hudsonicus of the 
Oriskany. It averages fully one-half larger, however, and does 
not show any sign of a ventral sinus such as the New York form 
possesses. 

Occurrence: Rare in the Harriman novaculite and common in 
the Camden chert at many localities in Benton County. 


FAMILY PENTAMERID 
Gypidula multicostata, n. sp. 

Plate II]; figs. 12; 13 
Description: Shell subtrigonal in outline. Ventral valve 
strongly convex and much larger than the dorsal. Its beak 
narrow and strongly arched, but not incurved over that of the 
opposite valve. The sides diverge regularly to their greatest 
width at about three-fourths to four-fifths the distance to the 
front of the shell, then round abruptly into the broad and very 
slightly emarginate anterior margin, so that the outline is almost 
an isosceles triangle. Dorsal valve transversely elliptical and 
gently convex. <A broad but low flat fold occupies the median 
half of the ventral valve, becoming obsolete before reaching the 
beak, and a corresponding sinus is present on the dorsal valve. 
The fold and sinus bear each ten to twelve slender, sharp, angu- 


132 Carl O. Dunbar, 


lar plications separated by angular grooves of equal width, while 
the inner part of each lateral slope is marked by four or five 
obscure plications, of which the outer is the most indistinct. 
Beyond these, the lateral slopes are smooth. The spondylium in 
the ventral valve is similar to that of G. coeymanensis, but con- 
siderable variation may be noted in the development of the 
median septum which supports it. In some specimens the 
septum is strong and in a few entirely absent. 

Dimensions: Length, 40 mm.; width, 4o mm.;_ thickness, 
about 25 mm. 

Discussion: The species is readily distinguished from all other 
described ones by the large number and slenderness of its plica- 
tions. It is most closely related to G. coeymanensis, but that 
species has fewer and much coarser plications and reaches its 
greatest width nearer its mid-length. 

Occurrence: Birdsong shale, at numerous localities in Benton 
and Decatur counties, especially along Birdsong Creek, at Perry- 
ville, etc. 


FAMILY RHYNCHONELLIDE 
Rhynchotreta insinuata, n. sp. 
Plate ILI, figs: .1,..2 


Description: Shell small, subtriangular, width and length 
equal. Posterolateral sides angulated and vertical, slightly con- 
cave, meeting at the beak with an angle of less than 90°. Beak 
pointed and erect. Valves subequally convex, without either 
fold or sinus, flattened in the central portion, angulated at the 
posterolateral edge and abruptly truncated around the anterior 
margin. Thickness of the shell about equal from umbo to lateral 
or front margin. The dorsal valve bears nine and the ventral 
ten small rounded plications, separated by wider, concave inter- 
spaces. Plications mostly simple, reaching to the beak, but two 
are added by bifurcation on the dorsal valve and one by inter- 
calation on the ventral. 

Dimensions: Length, 10 mm.; width, 10 mm.; depth, 5 mm. 

Discussion: The interior of this little shell is unknown, but 
its vertical posterior sides and erect pointed beak suggest its 
reference to Rhynchotreta. It most closely resembles FR. trans- 
versa of the Coeymans formation of New Jersey, but is larger 


x oT Ate hall 


New Species of Devonian Fossils. 133 


and differs distinctly in its truncated anterior margin and in the 
absence of a fold and sinus. 

Occurrence: Birdsong shale, the single known specimen being 
found at the Swayne’s mill locality near the mouth of Big Sandy 
River. 


Wilsonia wadei, n. sp. 
Plate III, figs. 3, 4 


Description: Shell small, subglobular or subpentahedral in 
form; deepest and strongly truncate at the front margin; length, 
breadth, and height about equal. Ventral valve depressed con- 
vex, but sharply deflected, almost angulated along the margins; 
beak short and small, neatly incurved. A mesial sinus begins 
about the middle of the valve and is produced anteriorly into a 
narrow linguiform extension that is sharply deflected at right 
angles to the plane of the valve. Dorsal valve about as deep as 
the ventral, also gently convex and steeply angulated at the 
margins. A fold on the anterior portion corresponds to the sinus 
of the opposite valve. The surface bears low rounded plications, 
of which one occupies the sinus, two the fold, and three each 
lateral slope. Rarely in large specimens there are two plications 
on the sinus and three on the fold. The plications become obso- 
lescent near the beak. 

Internally the hinge-plate in the dorsal valve bears a crural 
cavity as in Camarotachia, and the cardinal process is wanting. 

Dimensions: Length, 9 mm.; width, 9 mm.; height, 8.5 mm. 
Of a large specimen: II mm., 10.5 mm., and 9.2 mm. respec- 
tively. 

Occurrence: Common in the Birdsong shale and less abundant 
in the Ross limestone at Grandview, Perryville, Big Lick Creek, 
Birdsong Creek, etc. 


Uncinulus lindenensis, n. Sp. 
Plate III, figs. 5, 6 


Description: Shell of medium size, subpentahedral in form, 
subtriangular to subpentagonal in outline, as wide as or wider 
than long. Ventral valve almost flat, shallow and steeply angu- 
lated at the margins. A flat shallow sinus is visible only near 
the anterior margin, where it is produced into a very long 


134 Carl O. Dunbar, 


linguiform extension, sharply deflected at right angles to the 
valve. Dorsal valve very deep, sharply deflected at the margins 
into the deep, nearly vertical sides, highest in front, and sloping 
with depressed convexity to the beak. Beaks small, and postero- 
lateral sides often concave. Surface marked by rounded plica- 
tions, of which three or four occupy the sinus, four or five the 
fold, and five or six each lateral slope. Anteriorly the plications 
are marked with a fine median line. 

Dimensions: Length, 15 mm.; width, 14 mm.; height, 15.5 
mm. <A broad specimen measures: Length, 15 mm.; width, 16.8 
mm.; height, 16.5 mm. 

Discussion: This species resembles U. abruptus and U. nucleo- 
latus, but differs from either in the flatness of its ventral valve 
(especially the umbonal region), in the slightness of its fold and 
sinus, and the smaller number of plications on the fold and sinus. 

Occurrence: Common at most exposures of the Birdsong shale 
and the Ross limestone. 


Eatonia tennesseensis, n. sp. 
Plate III, figs. 9-11 

Description: Shell ovate to subtriangular. Ventral valve 
depressed convex in the middle near the beak, but gently concave 
between this point and the deflected margins; below the middle 
extended into a broad deep sinus which bends upward in front, 
in the more gibbous forms coming to lie almost at right angles 
to the plane of the valve. A sharp angular inflection of the 
posterior and lateral margins makes a distinct false cardinal area 
which extends to the anterolateral corners. Beak small and 
perforate, tightly incurved over that of the opposite valve so as 
to hide the deltidial plates which cover the delthyrium. The 
pedicle foramen is resorbed through the apex of the valve. 
Dorsal valve gibbous, elevated anteriorly into a fold which cor- 
responds to the sinus of the opposite valve. The posterolateral 
margins are gently inflected so as to form with the inflected 
margin of the opposite valve a concave space extending from the 
beak along each side of the shell. 

In the interior the ventral muscular impression is large, 
elongate oval, sharply defined by an elevated border, and divided 
by a very low rounded septum. Just posterior to its middle are 


New Species of Devonian Fossils. 135 


the very small, elongate, and more deeply impressed adductor 
scars. The diductor scars are marked by less distinct radiating 
lines. Teeth small, supported by dental lamelle which are adnas- 
cent to the thickened sides of the shell. In the dorsal valve 
the cardinal process is very large, consisting of a thickened trunk 
which ends anteriorly in a short low median septum, and pos- 
teriorly it is cleft into two apophyses which are directed poste- 
riorly and downward into the opposite valve. These apophyses 
converge and unite into one at the beak on the posterior side. 
The surfaces of attachment are medially grooved. From the 
sides of the trunk of the cardinal process arise the stout short 
crura. 

Surface marked by rather coarse striations crossed by exceed- 
ingly fine concentric growth-lines. There is also an incipient 
development of plications which appear only near the front 
margins, being quite distinct in some specimens and scarcely 
defined in others. They are low and rounded and separated by 
rounded interspaces. There is a tendency to be four on the fold 
and three on the sinus, with three fainter ones on each lateral 
slope, but on some specimens the latter are very indistinct or 
absent, while one large specimen shows only three plications on 
the fold. There is a very slight median depression on the pos- 
terior half of the dorsal valve. 

Dimensions of an average specimen: Length, 23 mm.; width, 
21 mm.; depth, 15 mm. 

Discussion: This species is nearest E. singularis, but compared 
with that shell it is much larger, proportionately narrower, its 
fold and sinus are not so sharply defined, its striations are much 
coarser, and it is distinctly characterized by its rounded plications. 
Compared with E. peculiaris, it is much larger and broader in 
the anterior portion, it shows a distinct median depression over 
the dorsal umbo which that species does not have, its striations 
are coarser, and there are internal differences in the muscle- 
scars, the diductors being relatively larger and more quadrate 
and the adductors in the ventral valve being relatively nearer the 
beak. The new species is readily distinguished from this and 
all other described species by its rounded hemiplications. 

Occurrence: Common in the Birdsong shale at Perryville, 
various localities on Big Lick and Birdsong creeks, and especially 


136 Carl O. Dunbar, 


in the upper layers of the shale on the lower course of Big Sandy 
River. 
Eatonia fissicosta, n. sp. 


Plate If], fies,.7,.6 


Description: Shell planoconvex, transversely ovate in outline. 
Ventral valve varying from slightly concave to gently convex 
as a whole, with a sharper convexity for a short distance below 
the beak. A narrow sinus begins near the middle of the valve, 
widening gradually and becoming deep at the front, where it 
forms a linguiform extension. The sinus is bounded by sharp 
ridges on either side, which correspond to depressions on each 
side of the fold of the opposite valve. Hinge-line slightly 
declining from the beak, which is small and neatly incurved, hid- 
ing the deltidium. The beak is perforate as in E. tennesseensis. 
A well developed false cardinal area is present on each side of the 
beak. Dorsal valve gibbous. The high and narrow fold does 
not reach to:the beak. Ventral muscular impression essentially 
similar to that of E. tennesseensis. Surface with many rather 
fine angular plications which rapidly increase by bifurcation. A 
stronger one usually occupies the center of the sinus. The rate 
of bifurcation is irregular, and the number of plications increases 
with size, but an average specimen has eight on the fold and 
twelve on each lateral slope. This character of bifurcating pli- 
cations, to which the name alludes, is sufficient to distinguish the 
species from any other known Latonia. 

Dimensions of a medium specimen: Length, 16 mm.; width, 
18 mm.; depth, 12mm. One very large specimen almost doubles 
these measurements. 

Occurrence: Common in the Rockhouse shale at the Rockhouse 
locality on Horse Creek. 


FAMILY CENTRONELLIDE 
Oriskania condoni (McChesney) 
Plate III, figs. 16, 17 
Rensseleria condoni McChesney, New Pal. Fossils, 1861, p. 85; 
Trans. Chicago Acad. Sci., 1868, p. 36, pl. 7, fig. 2—Meek 
and Worthen, Geol. Surv. Illinois, vol. III, 1868, p. 401, pl. 
8, fig. 4. 


New Species of Devomian Fossils. 137 


Newberria ? condoni Hall, Tenth Ann. Rept. New York State 
Geologist, 1891, p. 95 (p. 7 of extract). 

Megalanteris condoni Hall and Clarke, Pal. New York, vol. 8, 
pt. II, 1893, p. 280.—Savage, Am. Jour. Sci. (4), vol. XXV, 
1908, p. 437. 

Remarks: Although the exterior of this shell is well known, 
its interior characters have not heretofore been described. The 
sharp molds and casts of the species in the Camden chert clearly 
show the characters of muscle-scars and cardinal process, and 
one specimen preserves the loop entire. The cardinal process is 
large and elevated, its posterior face forming an angle of about 
45° with the plane of the valve. 

This surface bears a high, thin, vertical median ridge bounded 
by deep, narrow muscular grooves. The cardinal process thus 
closely resembles that of O. lucerna (Maryland Geol. Surv., 
Lower Devonian volume, pl. 67, fig. 24). Because of this char- 
acter, the species is here referred to the genus Oriskania. 

The loop closely resembles that of Beachia suessana. ‘The 
descending lamellz join to form a flat triangular plate which 
makes the anterior part of the loop. ‘This plate is broader and 
shorter than in a similar specimen of B. swessana before the 
writer, and the descending lamellz are more evenly arched so 
that the outline of the loop is subcordate. The slender projec- 
tion from the posterior edge of the triangular plate extends 
almost to the ends of the crura. 

Occurrence: A very common shell in the Camden chert of 
Tennessee and in the Clear Creek chert of southern Illinois. 


Megalanteris (?) saffordi, n. sp. 
Plate LiL fies 14, 05 

Description: Externally resembling closely M. (?) ovalis both 
as to size and contour, this species could scarcely be distinguished 
from the latter except by interior characters. The sharp exter- 
nal molds of the new species show distinct though low striations 
over its surface which would help to distinguish it, the surface of 
M. (?) ovalis being practically smooth. 

Internally the cardinal process is a little more highly special- 
ized than that of M. (?) ovalis, the median ridge upon its 
summit arising as a high vertical plate, more elevated than that 


138 Carl O. Dunbar, 


of the latter species, though not so narrow as the same plate in 
Oriskania. 

The shape of the loop, which is preserved in two of the 
writer’s specimens, is the character which definitely convinced 
him that this is really a distinct species. The descending lamellz 
diverge rapidly at first, and then by an almost even curvature 
arch forward and then inward to where they meet anteriorly. 
The loop thus formed is’about as broad as long and subcircular 
in shape. A slender process.projects backward and upward 
from the front center of the loop and a similar narrow process 
extends straight forward from the center of the loop. The 
triangular plate-like expansion of the loop seen in M. (?) ovalis 
and Beachia suessana is here lacking. The loop in both speci- 
mens has a drusy-coating of tiny quartz crystals, and it can not 
be demonstrated that the front margin of it was not broken off 
before fossilization. Still, it is scarcely likely that both were 
broken and both in the same shape, and it seems highly probable 
that the loop is practically perfect, and as drawn in Figure 15. 
Regardless of the front portion, the back part of the loop is 
broader and more evenly curved and rounded than in M. (?) 
ovals. 

The genus Megalanteris is in doubtful standing. If Suess’ 
determination of the nature of the loop in the genotype be cor- 
rect, then neither this shell nor M. (?) ovalis has any relation 
to that genus. There seems to be doubt on this point, and the 
writer therefore has followed the New York Geological Survey 
in referring these species doubtfully to Megalanteris. 

Occurrence: A common shell in the Harriman novaculite, near 
Camden, Parsons, and Grandview. 


FAMILY SPIRIFERIDZ 
Delthyris cyrtinoides, n. sp. 
Plate IV, figs. 1-3 


Description: External aspect identical with the less alate 
forms of D. perlamellosa. Hinge-line varying from slightly less 
to a little greater than the width of the shell below. Cardinal 
angles varying from sharp to slightly rounded. Area one- 
fourth to one-third as high as long. Deltidium very narrow. 


New Species of Devoman Fossils. 139 


Surface marked by three or four strong narrow plications on 
each side of the prominent fold and sinus, which are crossed by 
strong concentric imbricating lamelle as in D. perlamellosa. 
The distinctive features are internal: the strong dental lamellz 
of the ventral valve converging below, uniting with the sides of 
the strong median septum just before reaching the bottom of the 
shell; the septum continuing upward into the V-shaped structure 
thus formed by the dental lamelle. 

Dimensions of an average specimen: Length, 18 mm.; width, 
23 mm.; depth, 13 mm. 

Discussion: The Cyrtina-like structure formed by the dental 
lamellz is a case of parallelism and does not indicate a relation 
to Cyrtina. The new species is closely related to D. perlamel- 
losa, but on the average it is much smaller and less alate, while 
the convergence of the dental lamellze and their fusion with the 
strong median septum are distinctive features. 

Occurrence: Rockhouse shale, at the sulphur spring and at 
Rockhouse, both on Horse Creek, Hardin County. 


Delthyris octocostata tennesseensis, n. mut. 
Plate IV, figs. 8, 9 


Description: This common Spirifer of the Linden group in 
western Tennessee very closely resembles the earlier D. octo- 
costata of the Keyser formation of Maryland. It differs from 
the latter in being proportionately shorter and more transverse, 
the ratio of length to breadth being 3 to 5 as compared with 4 
to 5 in the Maryland form. There is also a tendency to have 
more plications which diverge less rapidly, the mutation fre- 
quently developing eight and occasionally ten, whereas the spe- 
cies usually has six and rarely eight. The ventral beak is more 
erect, the cardinal area is proportionately larger, more clearly 
defined, less curved, and more nearly in the plane of the valve. 
The deltidium is wider. The dorsal valve is proportionately 
smaller and its beak less prominent. 

Dimensions: Length, 16 mm.; width, 25 mm.; depth, 16 mm. 

Occurrence: Common in the Birdsong shale and rare in the 
Ross limestone at Grandview, Perryville, Big Lick Creek, Bird- 
song Creek, etc. 


140 Carl O. Dunbar, 


Trematospira bella, n. sp. 
Plate IV, figs. 4, 5 

Description: Shel small, gibbous. Hinge-line shorter than 
the width of the shell, cardinal extremities rounded. Surface 
very strongly plicate. Valves subequally convex. The ventral 
valve has a deep sinus bordered by a very high, narrowly rounded 
plication on either side. Two smaller slender plications occupy 
the sinus, and there is an additional sharp plication on each lat- 
eral slope. The sinus is continued into a linguiform extension 
that is strongly arched up almost at right angles to the plane 
of the valve. The ventral beak is perforated by a small rounded 
foramen but is tightly incurved over that of the opposite valve. 
The dorsal valve has a high median fold occupied by three nar- 
row plications, and each lateral slope is occupied by two high, 
sharply rounded plications. A few lamellose lines of growth are 
prominent near the anterior margin of the shell. 

Dimensions: Length, 10 mm.; width, 13.5 mrm.; thickness, 
TO mm. 

Discussion: This little shell very closely resembles T. gibbosa 
of the Hamilton, from which it differs in being smaller and in 
having only two plications on each lateral slope, while that spe- 
cies has three or four. The ventral beak is also more tightly 
incurved. These shells are so much alike that we can not avoid 
the conclusion that the new species is the ancestor of the Middle 
Devonian one. 

The little form figured in Volume 8, Part II, of the Paleon- 
tology of New York (PI. 83, figs. 21-23) and named T. tennes- 
seensis, is of the same size as our species, but it has a different’ 
aspect. It has but one plication in the sinus and two on the fold, 
while the lateral plications are broader and blunter. Hall and 
Clarke’s species has, in fact, no conspicuous fold and sinus, and in 
the profile view does not present the truncated appearance of 
the anterior margin which characterizes the new species. Its 
hinge-line is also not so straight and the ventral beak is more 
erect, exposing the deltidium. 

Occurrence: The holotype was found in the Birdsong shale 
at the old Swayne’s mill locality near the mouth of Big Sandy 
River, Henry County. 


New Species..of-Devomian Fossils. 141 


Trematospira costata angusta, n. var. 
Plate IV, figs.-6, 7 

’ This variety of T. costata which occurs in the Birdsong shale 
of Tennessee differs from the New York form chiefly in pro- 
portion of length to breadth. In New York, the shells are less 
than half as long as wide, and each lateral slope bears five or 
commonly six plications; in Tennessee, the length is about 
three-fourths the width, and the lateral slopes have only five pli- 
cations. This narrower and elongate form is therefore a clearlv 
distinguished variety, though in all its other characters it agrees 
fully with Hall’s species. 

Dimensions: Length, 17 mm.; width, 22 mm.; thickness, 11 
mm. 
Occurrence: Rather rare in the Birdsong shale at the old 
Swayne’s mill locality on Big Sandy River, Henry County. 


CLASS GASTROPODA 
FAMILY PLEUROTOMARIIDZ 
Saffordella, n. gen. 


Diagnosis: Shell depressed subconical, consisting of a few 
rapidly expanding whorls that are rounded subangular at the 
periphery. Base convex, umbilicus small or lacking. Aper- 
ture oblique, subquadrate, and deeply notched. Depth of slit 
unknown. Slit-band distinctly defined by a sharply depressed 
line along its upper and lower margins. Band broad, gently 
convex, and situated entirely upon the upper slope of the whorl, 
its lower margin not reaching quite to the periphery. The 
growth-lines on the upper slope swing strongly backward to the 
slit-band with a sigmoidal curvature, being convex forward near 
the suture and concave forward near the band. On the lower 
side they first run strongly forward and then recurve near the 
base, but finally bend forward again upon entering the umbilical 
depression. The lines of growth crossing the slit-band are 
notable because their curvature is convex forward. 

In general appearance this genus most closely resembles Eoto- 
maria, from which it may have been derived. It is readily dis- 
tinguished from the latter, however, by the characters of the 
slit-band. In Eotomaria the band is concave, it is proportion- 


142 Carl O. Dunbar, 


ately narrow, its lines of growth are concave forward, and its 
lower margin is at the periphery. In the new genus, the band is 
convex, broad, its lines of growth arch forward, and it is located 
above the periphery of the whorl. 

The genus is erected to receive the new species S. tennesseen- 
sis, which is the genotype. 

Etymology: The genus is named in honor of Tennessee’s 
great geologist, Professor James Safford. 


Saffordella tennesseensis, n. sp. 
Plate IV, fig. 17 

Description: Shell depressed subconical, consisting of about 
three and a half rapidly enlarging whorls. Apical angle about 
90°. Base ventricose and practically imperforate. The last 
whorl much larger than all the preceding ones. In the two 
earliest volutions the whorls are well rounded and the sutures 
rather deep, but with growth the later whorls become more quad- 
rangular in section, the lower and upper slopes becoming flat- 
tened and the periphery bluntly rounded angular. The suture 
at the same time becomes shallower. The aperture is subquad- 
rate, as deep as wide, broadly and deeply notched at the periphery, 
and also marked by a rounded sinus next to the columella. The 
slit-band is 4.5 mm. wide and located on the upper slope of the 
whorl, its lower-margin being about f mm. above the ambitus. 
The band is clearly delimited by shallow depressed margins. It 
is gently convex and its growth-lines arch forward to an extent 
about half as great as the width of the band, indicating that its 
apertural margin must have been a short rounded crest either at 
the base of the notch or within the slit, if indeed the shell pos- 
sessed a slit. Surface of the shell marked only by fine lines of 
growth. On the upper slope, these lines, taking a sigmoidal 
course, bend strongly backward to the band, while on the under 
slope they first run strongly forward, then curve backward in 
crossing the ventricose center of the base, and finally forward 
again as they reach the inner lip. 

Dimensions: Height, 40 mm.; width, 39 mm.; height of aper- 
ture, 24 mm.; width of same, 24 mm. 

Occurrence: A single specimen was found in the Rockhouse 
shale at Rockhouse on Horse Creek, Hardin County. 


New Species of Devonian Fossils. 143 


Distemnostoma, n. gen. 

Diagnosis: Shell low to moderately high spired, consisting of 
three to five or six volutions. Whorls deeper than wide, and 
either rounded above or flattened to form a nearly horizontal 
shoulder. Aperture higher than wide, with a broad notch and a 
short slit at its top and a deep channel at its base. Slit-band 
broad and situated entirely upon the upper side of the whorl. 
The inner margin of the band lies along the median line of the 
top of the whorl, and its outer margin is at least the width of 
the band above the ambitus. Inner lip entire, thin. Umbilicus 
narrow or lacking. 

Genotype: D. princeps, n. sp. 

The type of this genus resembles that of Omospira in its 
flattened shoulder and in the high position of the band. It 
appears to represent an entirely independent development, how- 
ever, since its aperture was deeply channeled at the base, while 
that of Omospira was rounded, and it had a slit and a true slit- 
band, whereas Ulrich states that his genus had no slit. These 
characters show important differences in the soft parts of the 
animals’ bodies. The above mentioned characters suffice to dis- 
tinguish the genera, but in addition the band in the new genus is 
even higher up on the upper surface of the whorl than in 
Omospira. Indeed, in this respect it is distinguished from all 
_ other genera of its family. In most of the Pleurotomariide the 
band is on the side of the whorls and intimately related to some 
peripheral angulation. In Omospira, it is seen to have moved to 
the upper side of the shoulder, but here it reaches an extreme: 
of migration to the top of the whorl, when in D. princeps the 
inner margin of the band is actually hid in the suture. 

Etymology: dis, double, + réuvo, to cut, + ordpa, mouth. 


Distemnostoma princeps, n. sp. 
Plate 1V; figs. 16,49 
Description: Shell high-spired, consisting of four or five 
gradually expanding volutions; apical angle about 65°. Whorls 
subtriangular in cross-section, the upper surface flattened and 
nearly horizontal, meeting the outer and inner sides in narrowly 
rounded shoulders; sides depressed convex and converging 


144 Carl O. Dunbar, 


equally to the narrowly rounded base. Each whorl rises nearly 
its entire height above the succeeding one, covering only the 
inner half of the flattened upper side of the latter. Umbilicus 
very narrow or lacking. The early whorls more rounded than 
the later ones. 

Aperture subtriangular, a little higher than wide, notched 
above by a broad, short slit, and deeply channelled at the base. 
Outer lip thin and extending forward as a lateral crest. Inner 
lip entire and thin. 

A broad slit-band occupies the horizontally flattened shoulder 
of the whorl, its inner margin lying in the suture and the outer 
margin being just above (within) the line where the shoulder 
begins to curve into the outer side of the whorl. The band is 
delimited by a sharply depressed line along each edge. It 
varies from depressed convex to more strongly convex along its 
median line and concave near the outer margin. ‘The lunule 
show an unusual irregularity in their curvature in the most per- 
fectly preserved specimen, though this may be a pathological 
condition. The normal direction seems to be obliquely backward 
and outward for over halfway across the band, and then forward 
again with a sharper curvature, as in O. laticincta. On the last 
half whorl of the best preserved specimen, the lunulz are doubly 
bent, arching strongly backward near either margin and forward 
near the center of the band. This irregularity is suggestive of 
an injury to the exhalent siphon. 

Surface marked by fine uneven lines of growth. On that 
portion of the upper surface covered by the preceding whorl, 
these lines curve strongly backward to the slit-band, becoming 
tangential with its inner margin. From the outer margin of 
the band they first run sharply forward, but having crossed the 
periphery, they descend nearly vertically and with a gentle cur- 
vature across the outer side. They arch strongly backward in 
crossing the narrowly rounded base, conforming to the margin 
of the deep channel. Certain of the stronger varices of growth 
can be followed across the band, and they seem to indicate that 
the slit was only 5 to 7 mm. deep. 

Dimensions: Height, 34 mm.; width, 24 mm.; height of aper- 
ture, 17 mm.; width of same, 12 mm.; width of band, about 


4.5 mm. 


New Species of Devoman Fossils. 145 


Occurrence: Rockhouse shale, at Rockhouse, on Horse Creek, 
Hardin County. 


Distemnostoma curtum, n. sp. 
Plate IV, figs. 10-12 


Description: Shell small, consisting of two and a half or three 
rapidly expanding whorls; spire depressed, the inner volutions 
rising only a little above the outer one. Suture deep. Whorls 
subovate in cross-section, almost twice as high as wide, the great- 
est width being about one-fourth the distance below the top. 
Aperture ovate, with a broad notch and short slit at the top, and 
deeply channeled at the bottom. Inner lip entire, straight, and 
thin. Base with a moderately narrow umbilicus. 

Slit-band of medium width, situated upon the outer half of 
the rounded upper side of the whorl. Its inner margin follows 
the central and highest line of the whorl, and its outer one is 
about the center of the rounded shoulder but well above the 
ambitus. 

Surface marked by fine, uneven lines of growth that curve 
strongly backward from the suture to the band, and on the out- 
side of the band first run strongly forward and then descend over 
the outer side with a gentle curve to near the base, where they 
arch strongly backward and then forward again on entering the 
umbilicus, thus conforming to the deeply channeled margin of 
the aperture. 

Dimensions: Height, 14 mm.; width, 16 mm.; height of aper- 
ture, I2 mm. 

Occurrence: Rockhouse shale, at Rockhouse, on Horse Creek, 
Hardin County. 


(?) FAMILY STROPHOSTYLIDE 
Aulopea, n. gen. 

Diagnosis: Shell low-spired, of few gradually but rapidly 
expanding whorls that are laterally compressed and much higher 
than wide. Aperture elliptical, nearly vertical, deeply channeled 
at the base. Inner lip thin and somewhat wrinkled, bounding 
a deep, narrow umbilicus. Surface marked by lines of growth 
only. 


146 Carl O. Dunbar, 


Genotype: A. nelsoni, n. sp. 
The general form of this type of shell resembles on the one 
hand Holopea, and on the other Diaphorostoma and Platyceras, 


but from these associated genera it is readily distinguished by its H 
laterally compressed whorls, and especially the deeply channeled | 
aperture. } 


Etymology: avdAds, channel, + 67, aperture. 


Aulopea nelsoni, n. sp. 
Plate IV, figs. 14-16 

Description: Shell low-spired, of about three gradually 
expanding volutions. Whorls laterally compressed, almost twice 
as high as wide, rather narrowly rounded below and above, 
widest a little above the middle. The outer side of the whorl is 
marked by a broad, slightly concave zone that is more clearly 
defined above than below. The inner whorls rise only a short 
distance above the outer. Suture rather deep. Base with a 
deep but moderately narrow umbilicus. Aperture narrowly 
ovate, rounded above, and having a deep, rounded channel at the 
base. Inner lip thin and somewhat wrinkled where it bounds the 
umbilicus, and very thin but entire where in contact with the 
preceding whorl. Surface marked by fine lines of growth, and 
more distant, uneven, and coarser growth varices. The growth- 
lines are curved so as to be gently concave forward on the upper 
side of the whorl and broadly convex forward on the outer side. 
A distinct grooved line running along the outer edge of the base 
marks the outer side of the anterior channel. At this line the 
growth-lines are sharply deflected backward and then cross the 
base with an even curvature, swinging forward again as they 
enter the umbilicus. These lines indicate that the channel in the 
aperture was about 5 mm. deep. 

Dimensions: Height, 30 mm.; width, 27 mm.; height of aper- 
ture, 22 mm.; width of same, 13 mm. 

Occurrence: Rockhouse shale at Rockhouse on Horse Creek, 
Hardin County. 

Name: This gastropod is named after the state geologist of 
Tennessee, Mr. Wilbur A. Nelson. 


ey 


New Species of Devomian Fossils. 147 


Holopea planidorsata, n. sp. 
Plate IV; fig33 


Description: Shell small, of three or four whorls wound in a 
moderate spire; apical angle about go°. Base hemispherical, 
with a very tiny umbilicus or none. Whorls flat and horizontal 
on top, with the shoulder rather sharply rounded. The ambitus 
is just below the shoulder, and from here to the axis of the base 
the whorl is strongly and evenly convex. Each whorl rises about 
three-fourths its height above the succeeding, and the sutures 
are deep. The younger whorls are more evenly rounded than 
the last one. Aperture entire and vertical. Inner lip thin and 
recurving so as to enclose a very narrow hollow axis, or to form 
a columella. Surface marked by very fine and even lines of 
growth that have a strong retral arch on the upper side of the 
whorl, but are nearly straight and vertical from the ambitus to 
the umbilicus. 

Dimensions: Height, 15 mm.; width, 15 mm.; height of aper- 
ture, 8 mm.; width of same, 9 mm. 

The flattened shoulder and deep suture of this species are 
distinctive. 

Occurrence: Rockhouse shale, at Rockhouse, on Horse Creek, 
Hardin County. 


Diaphorostoma quadrangulare, n. sp. 
Plate IV, figs. 20, 21 

Description: Shell low-spired, consisting of between three and 
four gradually but rapidly expanding volutions. In cross-sec- 
tion the whorls are rounded subquadrangular. The upper side 
is very gently convex and horizontal, the outer side is almost 
vertical and is marked by an undefined median slightly concave 
zone. ‘The base is as broad as the top and almost horizontal, 
but a little more strongly convex than the top side of the whorl. 
The four angles of the whorl are rather broadly rounded. The 
aperture entire, subquadrangular, and _ slanting somewhat 
obliquely backward below. Inner lip smooth. Base perforated 
by a narrow umbilicus. Surface marked by fine lines of growth 
and uneven coarser varices of growth which cross the whorl with 
a gently sinuous course, being gently convex forward at the 
center of the upper and outer sides, concave forward over the 


148 Carl O. Dunbar, 


rounded shoulder, and broadly concave forward across the base 
of the whorl. 
Dimensions: Height, 37 mm.; width, 33 mm.; height of- aper- 
ture, 27 mm.; width of same, 20 mm. . 
Occurrence: Rockhouse shale, at Rockhouse, on Horse Creek, 
Hardin County. 


CLASS CRUSTACEA 
SUBCLASS TRILOBITA 
FAMILY PHACOPIDE 
Dalmanites purduei, n. sp. 
Plate V,igs.. 1,2 

Description: Species of very large size. Cephalon semi- 
elliptical, with moderately long sharp genal spines and with a 
slight prolongation of the anterior margin in front of the gla- 
bella. Glabella large, depressed convex, most elevated between 
the palpebral lobes, and descending with even curvature to the 
front. Front lobe transversely elliptical, a trifle over three-fifths 
as long as wide, and marked by three shallow subcircular pits. 
The deeper of these is in the median line and just back of the 
center of the lobe, while the others are so shallow as to be 
scarcely visible, and one is near the center of each lateral half of 
the lobe. The first glabellar furrow deep and extending nearly 
three quarters of the distance to the axis. The second, third, 
and fourth glabellar lobes are well fused at their extremities, the 
second and third lateral furrows being reduced to mere oblong 
pits upon the glabella. Cheeks with rather strongly arched 
slopes and with a gentle concave zone bordering the margin. 
Occipital furrows deep and wide. Eyes large and elevated. 
Lateral facial sutures lying in a distinct groove. Surface in all 
the specimens exfoliated, but the cast of the free cheeks rough- 
ened by shallow dimples. 

Pygidium subtriangular in outline, and ending in a blunt 
spine. Number of segments in the axial lobe varying from 
seventeen in a small specimen to twenty-two in the largest one. 

Dimensions: A mature cephalon measures 81 mm. from occi- 
pital ring to front margin; 130 mm. across the head at the eye 
lobes, 60 mm. between the eyes. The largest pygidium has a 


New Species of Devonian Fossils. 149 


length of about 100 mm. and a width of 105 mm. A smaller 
entire individual has a length over all of about 120 mm. 

Discussion: This giant trilobite may be readily distinguished 
from the associated specimens of D. pleuroptyx by the facts that 
the second, third, and fourth glabellar lobes are confluent at 
their extremities, and that the facial sutures lie in distinct 
grooves. 

The fusion of the glabellar lobes indicates that this species 
belongs to the group of D. anchiops, D. stemmatus, and D. 
dolbeli, whose characters have been discussed by Clarke. The 
new species is remarkable not only for its great size, but also 
for the degree of fusion of the glabellar lobes at this early 
horizon. 

Occurrence: Ross limestone, at Olive Hill, Pyburns Bluff, and 
other localities in Hardin County. 


Dalmanites retusus, n. sp. 
Plate V, fic. 3 

Description: Species known only from the pygidium, which is 
semi-elliptical in outline, broader than long, and evenly rounded 
behind without any spinous extension. Axis low, only slightly 
arched, rapidly tapering, marked by fourteen or fifteen annula- 
tions, the last of which are very indistinct as the axis becomes 
obsolete posteriorly. Pleura gently arched, marked by ten or 
eleven broad ribs separated by narrower grooves, all of which 
become obsolete before reaching the edge, leaving a smooth 
margin about 4 mm. wide. 

Dimensions: Length, 27 mm.; width, 41 mm.; convexity, 5 
mm. 

Discussion: The absence of a spinous extension of this 
rounded pygidium is sufficient to distinguish it from all other 
species of Dalmunites except D. aspinosus of the Decker Ferry of 
New Jersey. Compared with this much earlier form, the pygi- 
dium of the new species is proportionately wider and more 
broadly rounded behind, its axis tapers more rapidly, and it pos- 
sesses a smooth marginal border. 

Occurrence: Occurs sparingly in the Birdsong shale at Perry- 
ville, Big Lick Creek, Birdsong Creek, the old Swayne’s mill 
locality, etc. 


Plate I 


g. 1.—Zaphrentis parsonsensis, n. sp. Lateral view of a natural cast 


of the interior of the corallum. 


ig.-2.—Apical view of the same. 
ig. 3.—Favosites foerstei, n. sp. Lateral view, showing the subhemis- 


pheric base of the corallum. 


ig. 4.—Basal view of the same, showing the subcentral point of attach- 


ment ‘and the wrinkled epitheca which covers the base. 


ig. 5——Pleurodictyum trifoliatum, n. sp. A mature colony attached to 


one valve of Rhipidomella oblata. The apex of the initial coral- 
lite is visible between the lateral corallites. 


ig. 6—Pleurodictyum trifoliatum, n. sp. An abnormal one-celled indi- 


vidual which was not cemented to any solid object, x2. The 
lateral nodes, one on either side, are the aborted lateral coral- 
lites. 


ig. 7—Another colony of the same species, with the three corallites 


mutually contiguous. 


1G 


PLAT 


Vol. XXIII. 


Trans. Conn. Acad. 


= ans 


L- 7 


e ; - 7 ct | 


a 
# 


i! 


aS We ret 
t AAS Sipe 


is ny ie 


a 


‘ed 


(> 


Plate II 


1.—Codaster lore, n. sp. Summit view. 

2.—Lateral view of another specimen of the same species. 

3.—Edriocrinus adnascens, n. sp. 

4.—Dalmanella pygme@a, n. sp. Posterior view, showing the sinus 
and fold. 

5.—Dalmanella pygmea, n. sp. Dorsal view of a typical specimen. 

6.—Dalmanella rockhousensis, n. sp. Interior view of a ventral 
valve, showing the characteristic diductor muscle-scars. 

7—Dalmanella rockhousensis, n. sp. Ventral view. 

8.—Dalmanella rockhousensis, n. sp. Lateral view, to show the 
distinct convexity of the dorsal valve. 

9.—Dalmanella macra, n. sp. Interior of a ventral valve, showing 
the very minute diductor muscle-scars. 


. 10.—Dalmanella macra, n. sp. Ventral view of a typical specimen. 
. 11.—Dictyonella subgibbosa, n. sp. Ventral view. 
. 12—Dictyonella subgibbosa, n. sp. Enlargement of the surface pits, 


x 10. 


. 13.—Dictyonella subgibbosa, n. sp. Lateral view, to show the thick 


umbonal region and the strongly incurved ventral beak. 


. 14.—Chonetes wadei, n. sp. Ventral view of the holotype, x2. 
. 15.—Pholidostrophia lindenensis, n. sp. Dorsal view of a nearly 


complete specimen. 


. 16.—Profile of the same. 
. 17.—Chonetes hudsonicus camdenensis, n. mut. Ventral view of a 


natural cast. 


. 18.—Strophonella punctulifera holladayi, n. var. Profile view. 
. 19.—Strophonella punctulifera holladayi, n. var. Ventral view of the 


imperfect holotype, showing the characteristic surface orna- 
mentation. 


. 20.—Strophonella lineolata, n. sp. Dorsal view. 

. 21.—Profile of the same species. 

ig. 22—Brachyprion purduei, n. sp. Ventral view. 

g. 23.—Brachyprion purduei, n. sp. Interior view of the ventral valve. 
. 24.—Leptena ingens, n. sp. Ventral view of a natural mold of the 


interior, showing the characteristic muscle-scars. 


. 25.—Chonetes fornacula, n. sp. Ventral view, x 2. 


|= EA BA, DI be 


XXIII. 


Aead. Vol. 


Trans. Conn. 


vs 


By ete 


Plate III 


1.—Rhynchotreta insinuata, n. sp. Ventral view of the holotype. 
2.—Anterior view of the same. 

3.—Wilsonia wadei,n. sp. Ventral view. 

4—Anterior view of the same. _ 

5.—Uncinulus lindenensis, n. sp. Dorsal view. 

6.—Uncinulus lindenensis, n. sp. Anterior view. 

7—Eatonia fissicosta, n. sp. Lateral view. 

8.—Eatonia fissicosta, n. sp. Ventral view. 

9.—Eatonia tennesseensis, n. sp. Interior of the ventral valve. 


 10.—Eatonia tennesscensis, n. sp. Ventral view of a typical speci- 


men, faintly showing the low plications at the anterior margin. 
Eatouia tennesscensis, n. sp. Dorsal view of a very large speci- 
men, with unusually coarse striations. 


ge, 12—Gypidula multicostata, n. sp. Interior view of the umbonal por- 


tion of a ventral valve, showing the small spondylium. 


g. 13.—Gypidula multicostata, n. sp. Ventral view, to show the numer- 


ous narrow plications. 


. 14.—Megalanteris (?) saffordi, n. sp. Ventral view of a wax cast 


from a natural mold. The margin is incomplete. 


. 15.—The loop of the same species. The anterior margin is possibly 


incomplete because of breakage before fossilization. This 
seems improbable, however, since two specimens preserving 
the loop agree in shape. 


. 16.—Oriskania condoni (McChesney). The loop of this species. 
. 17——The cardinal process of the same species, to show the median 


vertical ridge. 

18.—Leptostrophia beckii tennesseensis, n. var. View of an incom- 
plete ventral valve, showing the characteristic wavy or 
dimpled surface. 


Vere, 


Trans. Conn. Acad, Vol. XXIII. PLATE Ill, ’ 


IS4 


1 


-— 


Plate IV 


1.—Delthyris cyrtinoides, n. sp. Ventral view of a typical specimen. 

2.—Lateral view of the same. 

3.—Inside view of the ventral beak of the same species, showing 
the convergence of the dental lamellae and their union with 
the median septum. 

4.—Trematospira bella, n. sp. Lateral view of the holotype. 

5.—Cardinal view of the same. 

6.—Trematospira costata angusta, n. var. Lateral view. 

7.—Trematospira costata angusta, n. var. Dorsal view. 

8.—Delthyris octocostata tennesseensis, n. mut. Lateral view. 

9.—Delthyris octocostata tennesseensis, n. mut. Ventral view. 


& 10.—Distemnostoma curtum, n. gen., n. sp. Lateral view of the holo- 


type. The line bounding the basal channel may be seen near 
the base. 


. I1.—Apical view of the same specimen. 
g. 12—Sketch of the preceding view, to show the course of the 


egrowth-line and the slit-band. 


. 13.—Holopea planidorsata, n. sp. 
. 14—Aulopea nelsoni, n. gen., n. sp. Lateral view, from the aper- 


tural side, x 8/7. 


, 15.—Aulopea nelsoni, n. gen., n. sp. View from the opposite side, 


showing the deep compressed form of the whorls. 


. 16.—Sketch of the basal view of the same specimen, showing the 


channel at the base of the aperture. 


. 17.—Saffordella tennesseensis, n. gen., n. sp. Side view, to show the 


erowth-lines and the broad slit-band. 


. 18.—Distemnostoma princeps, n. gen., n. sp. View of the upper sur- 


face of a broken whorl, showing the character of the slit- 
band. 


. 19.—Distemnostoma princeps, n. gen., n. sp. Lateral view of one of 


the types. 


. 20.—Diaphorostoma quadrangulare, n. sp. View from the apertural 


side, x 10/0. 


. 21.—Diaphorostoma quadrangulare, n. sp. View from the opposite 


side. 


\ 
4] 
{ ihrans. Conn. Acad. Vol. XXIII. PLATE IV. 


Plate V 


Fig. 1—Dalmanites purduci, n. sp. Drawing of the cephal Of; 
Fig. 2—Dalmanites purduei, n. sp. Pygidium of a somewhat 
+; individual. 

Fig. 3—Dalmanites retusus, n. sp. Pygidium. 


at 


Trans. 


Conn. Acad. Vol. XXIII. 


ft. 


TRANSACTIONS OF | 
Poe CONNECTICUT ACADEMY 
OF ARTS AnD SCTENCGES 


VOLUME 237] MAY 1920 [PAGES 159-210 


Early History of American 
Auctions--A Chapter in 
Commercial History 


BY 


RAY BERT WESTERFIELD, Ph.D. 


Assistant Professor of Political Economy in Yale University. 


NEW HAVEN, CONNECTICUT 
PUBLISHED BY THE 
CONNECTICUT ACADEMY OF ARTS AND SCIENCES 
AND TO BE OBTAINED ALSO FROM THE 
YALE UNIVERSITY PRESS 


TASLE OF CONTENTS 


IBONEMERCIAL EFFECTS OF THE AUCTIONS: {23.5.6 0c sic eens 3 
BPRS, RESINS #5). yoyo tdl oo ny Sc aE OMe OSs oct ME ei 
MinBER- VALUATION OF IMPORTS. . 222 tia sles es eee e wes 
WEPReLIONG TO THE-AUCTIONS «ocd ncacis ols sed cme sees 


Maneericw AGAINST THE AUCTIONS % s/s 2 <c.2.. «cs lccest «levee 


~~ 


wise apes, 
: tf i ee 
uGts's s* ao >. 


INTRODUCTORY. 


The genius of the American business man is respected the 
world over. It is the natural product of American conditions: 
great natural resources, a wide expanse of country, an aggressive 
people, a democratic government, a great personal freedom, and 
a high social approval of competitive success, are conditions 
which foster big business achievement. It is probably natural 
that a people thus successful should be so impressed with its 
wonderful industrial and commercial organization that it forgets 
or does not inquire about the origin and development of that 
organization. 

But America has been a great business laboratory; its industrial 
and commercial history shows a rapid turn-over of inventions and 
improved processes and devices. These have had a tremendous 
effect on our social and political life. Adequate studies have never 
been made of our mercantile system. This monograph is an 
inquiry into the early history of one business device that was not 
only basic in an economic way but also vitally affected national 
policy and politics. Auctions are a very common device for sell- 
ing goods. They, like other middleman devices, are so common- 
place that one may wonder with what warrant can an historical 
study be made of them. But these commonplace methods and 
devices of business have exercised an influence too little known 
and too little realized, upon our economic, social and political 
history. 


RISE OF THE AUCTION PROBEEM, 


The method of selling at auction is ancient and quite universal.* 
It was used in America by the Colonists from very early date? 
as a means of disposing of property under judicial process, and 
of closing out stocks of merchandise (on account of commercial 
failures, on account of underwriters, or of unsalable goods 
remaining in importers’ hands at end of the season), second-hand 
household furnishings, farm utensils and animals. But this 
“business was inconsiderable. It was then considered a dis- 
creditable mode of selling goods, and various methods were 
practiced for concealing the owner’s name.”* 

During the Embargo and the War of 1812 the English manu- 
facturers resorted to auctions to sell their products both in 
London and America. This innovation hurt the London and 
provincial tradesmen, and it was bewailed that “a commercial 
nation should have fallen into the mistake of suffering the sale of 
manufactured goods” through the “numerous and increasing 
progeny of auction marts . . . academies of trick and chi- 
canery,’ causing bankruptcies by underselling and by rapid 
selling of goods bought on credit.* 

The American ports being closed to direct importations from 
Europe, the volume of imports declined, and only through neutral 
ports or Canada did goods enter to stem the rising prices and in 
this trade “several houses were often jointly interested in the 
same importation. For this reason quick sales were desirable; 
and consequently package-sales at auction were introduced as the 
most expeditious, as well as the most profitable, mode of dis- 


*For a general survey see Hunt’s Merchants Magazine, II, 72. 

“In New York City, for instance, mention of auction sales in 1676 is 
found; in that year ‘Matthias Nicoll was appointed vendee master, and 
gave 2000£ security, which is an indication of the importance and 
responsibility of the office at that time.” Goodrich, Picture, 453. A long 
train of fiscal and regulatory legislation re auctions exists in the archives 
of nearly every colony. 

* Bolles, Financial History, I, 387. 

*“The ruinous tendency of auctioneering and the necessity of restrain- 
ing it for the benefit of trade, etc.,’”’ New York, 1813; second ed. London, 
1848, with copious explanatory notes added, p. 3. 


Rise of the Auction. Problem 165 


posal.’’® Boston, during the War, had been practically free from 
blockade by the British and so this city and its hinterland had 
continued to receive relatively plenty of British products in the 
old way. But New York, Philadelphia, Baltimore and other 
ports depended upon blockade runners and indirect importa- 
tions. “During the war the British merchants established exten- 
sive depots of goods in Halifax, Bermuda and other British 
possessions, that they might be ready to supply the American 
market on the declaration of peace. Immediately after the close 
of the war these goods were sent’”’ into the more destitute ports, 
but chiefly New York.® For a time the competition among 
buyers was very keen and the British found auctions the most 
profitable and quickest method. Fresh goods from Europe began 
to pour into the country. Since the practice at this time was for 
the auctioneer to advance the cash for the sales immediately, the 
importer enjoyed a very high rate of turn-over. ‘Merchants, 
finding that they could sell their goods at auction with such facil- 
ity, and be ready for another venture so soon, ordered twice as 
many as they would have done had they continued to sell all their 
goods in the old way.’* Auctions, therefore, soon glutted the 
market; its extraordinary demand was satiated by the autumn 
of 1816, and prices started to decline that winter. Prices fell till 
they scarcely covered the duties. A severe crisis broke upon the 
importers and jobbers, almost all failed or were seriously crippled. 

During this period of distress American importers ceased 
ordering from Europe. British manufacturers determined to rid 
themselves of their accumulating stocks. They dispatched agents 
to America, who found auctions the readiest means of sale.® 
The prices prevailing in England were very low, lower than in 
America. It was alleged at the time that the prices in both places 
were below the cost of production. However that may be, the 
low prices in England appeared on the invoices which were 
genuine; and the fact that the tendency was for prices to decline 
further gave excuse for fictitiously invoicing shipments at less than 
the prevailing English prices; and the low invoice prices greatly 


* Bolles, I, 387. 
PEant s; to: 156: 
7 Bolles, I, 388. 
® Bolles, I, 388-9. 


106 Early History of American Auctions 


reduced the ad valorem tariff duties in the United States, to the 
advantage of the British manufacturer and the American 
auctioneer. As a consequence auctioneers increased in number, 
wealth and influence in all the commercial cities. A course of 
trade which‘had thus been begun partly from temporary causes 
was found by experience to insure the British a very decided 
advantage in the competition with the American importer. 


THE MENACE OF PEACE. 


The Embargo of 1807, the Non-Intercourse Act of 1809, the 
higher tariff duties, and the restrictions on trade during the War 
of 1812 had caused a mushroom growth of manufactures of 
cottens, woolens, iron, glass, pottery, and other articles. The 
continuance of these war-born industries after 1815 depended 
largely upon the maintenance and extension of protection.12 A 
very distinct feeling had arisen in favor of manufactures and 
Congress made clear concessions in the tariff act of 1816 to pro- 
tect textiles and other needy lines; this was in addition to the 
high level of duties for strictly fiscal purposes. Despite this 
measure the importations of British manufactures during 1816 
and 1817 were excessively large. Exporting speculators and 
manufacturers found good markets in the United States until the 
fall of 1817 and thereafter found this the least costly mart in which 
to sacrifice their glut of wares. Not only did the sales net them 
more but sacrifices in America tended also to work an ultimate 
benefit; for, as Lord Brougham said, “it is well worth while 
to incur a loss upon the first exportation in order, by the glut, 
to stifle in the cradle those rising manufactures in the United 
States which had forced into existence, contrary to the natural 
course of things.”4. It was the common talk of the day that 
the British manufacturers were making a concerted, open and 
studied effort to defeat our rising manufactures by buying out 
and suppressing inventions and makers of machinery, by buying 
up our sheep, by dumping their manufactures on our market 


* Annals of Congress, 15th Congress, Ist session, p. 50. 
” Taussig, Tariff History of the U. S., 16-8. 
“ Hansard, Parliamentary Debates, Ist Series, XX XIII, 1090. 


——— 


The Menace of Peace 167 


regardless of cost and pooling their losses which amounted to 
“several hundred thousand pounds sterling.’””” 

The machinery used to dump their wares was an arrangement 
by which agents of foreign manufacturers and merchant export- 
ers (1) received consignments on more or less fictitious invoices 
and therefore largely evaded import duties, (2) paid the duties 
by signing customs bonds indorsed by fellow agents or auction- 
eers and (3) sold the goods by private treaty or more usually at 
auctions, for cash advanced by the purchaser or the auctioneer 
or on long credits of six, nine, or twelve months.” 

The result of this natural and forced glut of our market was 
a serious industrial distress which reached its worst in the panic 
of 1819. The inflated state of the currency contributed mightily 
to this crisis. ‘Many of our manufacturers fell easy prey to 
their mighty rivals. First of all the newly erected manufactories 
of earthenware. . . . Inthe same way went most of the glass- 
factories, and the manufactures of white and red lead. The 
manufacture of iron continued longer, but in a feeble way, 
dwindling every year. . . . During the four years between 
1817 and 1821, the holders of property in the United States 
were supposed to have suffered a depreciation of nearly 
$800,000,000.”!4 Sheep-raising declined rapidly as domestic 
factories closed and the wool produced was more largely 
exported.1® The one sustaining force was pronounced to be the 
protective tariff and the high sterling exchange rates, which 
together amounted to from 4o to 50% of the foreign cost of 
production.t® The iron interests were temporarily revived by a 
duty of $15 per ton imposed in 1818. The balance of trade went 
decidedly against the States; the premium on London exchange 
ranged in 1821-2 from 8 to 15%, and the country lost much of 


” Niles, 10: 322; 21: 4. The names of some of the alleged conspirators 
were Earl Grosvenor, Lord Folkstone, Mr. Brougham and Sir Robert 
Peele. Niles, 18: 151. 

* Niles, 18: 419; Bolles, I, 366, 488; Dewey, Financial History of 
ES rGo: 

“ Bolles, I, 370-371. 

* Bolles, I, 367. 

* Memorial of New York Chamber of Commerce, 1824, quoted in Bolles, 
i372: 


168 Early History of American Auctions 


its gold and silver by export.1* The commercial disadvantage 
of high exchange premium was, however, partly compensated for 
by the rapid turn-over made possible by more regular and speedy 
packet service.'§ 

By 1823:dumping had done its worst and those manufactures 
which remained were thought to be on a sound economic footing 
or at least sufficiently protected by existing tariffs.1° The cotton 
manufactures were in prosperous condition’; even protectionists 
ascribed the prosperity to the extensive use of labor-saving 
machinery rather than the tariff.24_ It is probable that the 
exhausted purchasing power and low state of credit and high 
exchange rates were strong factors in reducing foreign importa- 
tions and in giving our manufactures a second wind. The 
winter of 1823-4 witnessed a reaction and Niles published a 
“view of the calamitous situation of the United States.’? This 
time the British woolen manufacturers in particular flooded our 
markets through the auction method at prices alleged to be below 
cost, and our woolen manufacturers called for government help 
lest they be swamped as quickly as the first set had been in 1817.”* 
The third period of dumping was 1827-8 and was occasioned by 
over-production of woolens, and of cottons to a less degree, in 
England and an unprecedented stagnation in trade and fall in 
prices. Large quantities of surplus woolens, some not suited to 
the home-market or made of inferior materials, were sacrificed 
on the American market at prices dictated by the desperate state 
of trade.2* The next period when auction dumping hurt again 
was when the tariff was reduced between 1833 and 1842.?° 
Thereafter auctions declined. 


1 Niles; 22: °175. 23, 0323) 232 a7 

8 Niles, 19: 424. 

1 Niles, 24: 67, gives extensive list of manufactures exported, made 
from both domestic and foreign materials, in 1822. 

*° Niles, 24: 103, 117; 21: 4, 39, 148, 163; 18: 266; Gallatin, Memorial 
of The Free Trade Convention, 1831; Tudor, Letters on the Eastern States 
(1819). 253-266; Holmes, An Account of the United States of America 
(1823), 201-8. 

™ Niles, 21: 4, 190. 

* Niles, 25: 179. 

* Bolles, I, 367. 

** Bolles, I, 384-5; N. Hale, American System, 41-2. 

** Bolles, I, 427. 


The Menace of Peace 169 


The auction system tended to defeat the protective tariff. 
Before 1816 auctions had played such an unimportant role that 
their evils were not mentioned in the memorials of manufacturers 
and chambers of commerce praying for protection to domestic 
producers.2* The first petitions listed in the Annals of Congress 
complaining of auctions and pleading for protection were two 
presented in February, 1817, one from “sundry inhabitants of 
the city of New York on behalf of domestic manufacturers” and 
a similar petition from the merchants of that city, and recom- 
mending a 10% tax on auction sales.27_ This movement started 
naturally in New York where the abuses were most extensive 
and severe and spread rapidly to all commercial cities, even towns 
far inland.22 The manufacturers asked Congress for further 
protection in three ways: (1) to abolish customs credits on 
imports, (2) to alter and increase the duties on imported goods, 
and (3) to impose a restrictive, if not prohibitory, tax on sales 
at auction. The auction system was opposed with great fury 
for many years.” The distress wrought by dumping after 1816 
was a chief factor in inspiring the demand for a secure and stable 
“home market.”°° The anti-auction movement was affiliated 
with the “American System” movement.*? 


**For instance, the memorial of the mechanics and manufacturers in 
New York City for protection to manufacturers in 1800 (Annals of 
Congress, 6th Congress, 2d session, 1291); petition of the Philadelphia 
artisans and manufacturers in 1803 (Annals of Congress, 8th Congress, 
2d session, 1467); petitions for protection in 1811-2 (Annals of Congress, 
12th Congress, Ist and 2d session) ; Tench Coxe’s report on manufactures 
in 1813 (Annals of Congress, 13th Congress, Vol. II, 2570-2642); peti- 
tions of the cotton manufacturers, in December, 1815, and February, 1816 
(Annals of Congress, 14th Congress, Ist session, 1645-1656) gives a 
long list of difficulties under which cotton manufacturers were working 
but does not mention auctions. 

* Annals of Congress, 14th Congress, 2d session, 848-51, contains the 
text of these petitions. 

**For example read the petition of the Berkshire County (Mass.) 
merchants assembled at Pittsfield and see how it appeals on the basis of 
protection. Given in Niles, 38: 94. 

” Bolles, I, 390; Niles, 37: 208. 

* Niles, 21: 147. 

= At a “Great meeting at New York” in 1828 of citizens supporting 
the “American System” and “friendly to national industry” adopted 
the resolution: “That we deprecate, as injurious to domestic industry, 


170 Early History of American Auctions 


Through the rise of auctions the native American importing 
merchants were placed in a most peculiar position relative to the 
tariff. Normally they would oppose the tariff since it was to 
their interest to have large importations, and the higher the 
duties the stronger would be their opposition.2? The rise of 
domestic industry would shift trade from the importing mer- 
chants to the jobbers. Some persuasion was needed to ally the 
merchants with the protectionists.* But this alliance was 
effected because the system of foreign agents selling through 
auctioneers diverted a considerable trade to new groups of 
middlemen and gave them competitive advantages which tended 
to rob the merchants of their business. The merchants were 
therefore in the dilemma of losing business either to domestic 
jobbers by the stoppage of foreign trade as effected by the 
taritf and the abolition of auctions, or to British agents and 
auctioneers by the consignment and auction sales system. The 
diversion of trade to the British agents and auctioneers was 
more obvious, direct, sudden and offensive, and the merchants 
therefore supported the tariff program and its counterpart, the 
abolition of auctions. 


VOLUME OF -AUGTION SALES) 


Except for the City and State of New York the statistics of 
sales at auction are wanting. The petitioners from other cities 
often made rough estimates of the total auction sales or of the 
proportion of the total sales of merchandise that were done by 
auction.** Such estimates are questionable and probably exag- 
gerate the importance of auctions. In New York, where auction 


the existing system of auctions; and that we will use all honorable 
exertions to suppress it.” Niles, 35: 131. The same year a report of a 
citizens’ committee in New York said: “The abolition of auctions is their 
best remedy. It would be worth ten tariffs. . . . The existing duties 
would be more than a sufficient protection, in the absence of auctions, 
which, alone, are fatal to native industry.” Niles, 34: 258. 

* Niles, 20: 245, 298, 342; 18: 422. 

3 Niles, 20: 66. 

“*For the year 1818, when auctions were at about their best, it was 
estimated from auctioneers’ reports that auction sales in New York City 
amounted to $14,000,000, and the total auction sales in the United States 
were at least $30,000,000. See petition from New York City, Dec. 20, 
1819, in Annals of Congress, 16th Congress, Ist session, 2201. 


Volume of Auction Sales 171 


duties were imposed, certain relatively authentic statistics exist. 
It was common to assert in petitions (1) that the proportion of 
auction sales to private sales was increasing; (2) that the pro- 
portion of sales done on foreign account, i. e., by British agents 
on consignment, to sales done on domestic account, i. e., by 
domestic importing merchants, was increasing; and (3) that the 
auction business tended to become concentrated in relatively few 
houses, thus creating an idle mercantile class and making possible 
monopolistic abuses.*° The following table*® will indicate the 
growth of auction sales in New York State: 


* “Tt has already (1820) become alarming to all the commercial cities.” 
Niles, 18: 419; 35: 30. 

* Based on Williams Annual Register, 1836: 196. Revenue figures, 
slightly varying from these and probably more authentic, from 1784 to 
1844 are found in New York Assembly Document 208 (1845), Vol. 6, 
and from 1845 to 1862 similar data are found in New York Senate 
Document 80 (1863), Vol. 5. 

An auction duty is a tax assessed upon auctioneers in proportion to the 
volume of sales made by them. The auction duties’ system of New York 
State is described in pages 197-9. This table of duties and dutiable goods 
should be interpreted in the light of the changes of rates imposed by the 
following laws respectively : 

Act of April 6, 1804: 


On East India goods, in original package ........ 14% 
On West India “ + s ees seco, sae 27% 
On wines and ardent spirits, “ ST eR 270 
Act of April 6, 1813: 
On East India goods, in original packages ....... 14% 
Gh dOmMeEStHeCOOUS. A-ceeines «a \s-e te oie oss e enrete 1A% 
On West India goods, in original packages ...... 270 
Onsiwinesrand ardent sspiritss -ansace esate 290 
On all other goods, 
feasoldmn New VoOtks Cltye saeco cee sce 390 
fiesolde in other-places austere cece ace 2% 
Act of April 13, 1814: 
@neall-coods! ...n eae oe ee eto ee hie 1% 
Act of April 15, 1817: 
On East India goods, in original package ........ 1% 
Gnawines and andentsspicitsesseen pee vases eee 2% 
@neal! “other cOodS #2 soca See oe eee 14% 


Two or three other States derived revenue from duties on sales at 
auction or by licensing auctioneers, but these were small compared with 
New York. Niles, 27: 290. Pennsylvania in 1845 received $71,248.03, 
and Maryland got from Baltimore auctions $27,263.27 (Niles 69: 336), 
whereas New York got that year $176,108.62. 


172 Early History of American Auctions 


Amount Amount of 
Amount of dutiable non-dutiable Total 
of duties sales sales sales 
Year (000) (000,000) (000,000) (000,000) 
1810 $126 $ 5.6 $ 0.5 $ 6.1 
1811 110 4.3 0.3 4.7 
1812 124 5.2 0.4 ve es 
1813 ‘156 6.0 1.0 7.0 
1814 86 3.5 0.4 3.9 
1815 182 12.1 1.0 13.2 
1816 171 11.3 o.8 WR 
1817 199 12.5 0.7 13.2 
1818 176 11.9 1.6 13.5 
1819 141 0.5 7 Wie 
1820 154 10.2 1.8 12.0 
1821 154 10.5 1.8 12.3 
1822 181 12.3 1.8 14.1 
1823 208 13.8 an 16.9 
1824 226 15.7 Batata op 075 10.3 | 
1825 285 10.7 4.5 24.2 ‘ 
1826 243 16.3 4.7 21.0 
1827 248 16.4 3.1 10.5 ‘ 
1828 257 17.4 8.6 26.0 | 
1829 243 16.5 8.7 25.2 
1830 219 15.5 10.3 25.8 
1831 256 17.4 10.2 277, 
1832 216 14.1 11.7 25.9 
1833 239 22.0 12.4 34.4 
1834 193 14.4 13.3 27.7 
1835 273 19.6 14.7 34.3 | 
Total 5070 334.1 123.0 457.1 
These figures understate the auction sales in as much as various 
devices existed for evading duties and not reporting sales cor- 
rectly.*7 Practically all auction sales in the State occurred in New 
York City.28 Taking the year 1817 for illustration, the auction 
* See treatment below, page 108. 
88 Albany ranked next to New York City. The duties paid were as 
follows (New York Assembly Journal, 1823: 737): 
Paid by Paid by 
New York City Albany and 
and County Albany County 
Year (000) (000) 
1813 $156.1 $2.2 
1814 100.0 Tez 
1815 180.1 1.8 | 
1816 174.7 2.1 | 


1817 122.0 2.2 


The Auction System 3 


duties amounted to 1.6% of dutiable sales; and in 1828 to 1.5%. 
The largest auction revenue producers were English and French 
dry goods, and the next largest were teas and silks from China, 
and then sugars, groceries, and ardent spirits.*® Added to this 
were the customs duties paid to the federal government.*° 


THE AUCTION SYSi EM. 


An auctioneer is a person who is authorized to sell at public 
auction, for a commission. He differs from a broker who may 
buy as well as sell, whereas an auctioneer, generally speaking, 
may only sell; and a broker may sell at private sale, but an 
auctioneer only at public vendue.*t The auctioneers in New 
York City had very early settled along what is now Water Street 
and their buildings, opposite the old Coffee House, were known 
(about 1780) as the “Merchants’ Promenade or Auctioneers’ 
Row.”’? 

The system was for the British manufacturer or exporter to 
consign his goods to an agent or an auctioneer, who would bond 


Paid by Paid by 


New York City Albany and 
and County Albany County 
Year (000) (000) 
1818 176.3 2.8 
1819 142.0 D7, 
1820 154.6 1.6 
1821 151.8 0.6 
1822 79.6 1.8 


For comparative figures for 1831 see Annual Report of the State Comp- 
troller, 1831-2: 56; for 1848 see his Report, 1848: 166; and for 1860-1878 
see N. Y. Assembly Document 64 (1875). The concentration in New 
York City grew apace. 

* Goodrich, Picture, 455. 

“” The import duties paid by New York City were as follows :— 
(Hardie, Description, 300.) 


(000,000) (000,000) 
Year Duties Year Duties 
1815 $14.6 1821 $72 
1816 10.8 1822 9.9 
1817 6.3 1823 9.0 
1818 8.3 1824 Tile 
1819 6.5 1825 Pigs) 
1820 5.5 1826 11.5 


eS Eiint’s, Ll 72. 
“J. G. Wilson, Memorial History of the City of New York, 536. 


174 Early History of American Auctions 


the goods, have them Janded and sold at auction for promissory 
notes which were discounted at the banks, and, having deducted 
the commission, remitted the proceeds to the British principal ; 
the proceeds thus included the duties for which the govern- 
ment allowed a credit of 8, 10, and 12 months without interest, 
and until maturity of the customs credits the collected duties 
formed additional capital in the Britisher’s hands.** The follow- 
ing very detailed description of the system is contained in a 
defensive memorial of the auctioneers to Congress in 1821**: 
“Sales of dry goods are made at auction by package or by 
piece; and this is the only important distinction to be observed 
in all the varieties of the trade. Package sales, being more 
important in amount, more attractive, by the assortments of 
merchandise they combine, excite most interest, and are attended 
with greatest competition. When the sale is of magnitude, it is 
generally advertised in the principal commercial cities, with an 
enumeration of the articles to be sold.*? Printed catalogues are 
prepared, specifying the term of credit, with other conditions of 


*® Niles, 18: 410. 

* Annals of Congress, 16th Congress, 2d session, 1526-9. 

* Some characteristics of auctioneers’ advertisements as they appeared 
in the New York “Commercial Advertiser” 1816-20 may be noted. There 
were special columns for “public sales’; the auctioneer’s name headed 
the advertisements; the advertisement covered several distinct sales, one 
different days, at different places, and of different things; the same auc- 
tioneer sold such widely different things as imported goods, real estate, 
stocks in trade, bankrupt stocks, court sales, ship-damaged goods, shops, 
paintings, household furniture, sheep, etc.; the advertisements were wholly 
informative, with little, if any, boasting of goods, except patent medicines ; 
in the same advertisement would be goods offered at “private sale” much 
detailed; sometimes the sales were designated “package sale (of hard- 
ware, etc.)”; side by side with auctioneers’ advertisements were adver- 
tisements for sales by private brokers and merchants; the sales were to 
take place at certain auction rooms, in front of certain auction rooms, at 
the wharf, at the Coffee House, etc.; it was stated that “the goods will 
be ready for examination on” a certain day and “the catalogues ready” 
on an earlier day; there were regular weekly sales in books and stationery; 
it was cited that the goods “will be sold on a liberal credit” or “sold 
without reserve on liberal terms.” During the period 1816 to 1820 as many 
as twenty different auction firms advertised in the “Commercial Adver- 
tiser.” 


The Auction System 175 


sale, and detailing the contents of each package, the number of 
pieces, the varieties of quality, by number or otherwise, and the 
lengths; all of which is guaranteed to the purchaser. ‘The 
widths are also in some instances specified, but always with a 
reservation expressed in the conditions of the sale, on the printed 
catalogues, or published by verbal explanation, that there is on 
that point no warranty, except that the goods not exhibited shall 
correspond in this as well as in every other respect with the 
samples shown; 

“The packages are arranged in lots corresponding with their 
numbers on the catalogue, and are exhibited sometimes two entire 
days before the sale, sometimes but one; the length of the exhibi- 
tion being regulated by the magnitude of the sale. When the 
goods are prepared for inspection, the purchasers are invited by 
public notice in the papers to examine them. Where it is neces- 
sary for an advantageous examination, whole packages are dis- 
played; where it can be made with more convenience from 
samples, one or more pieces of each quality are exhibited; and 
where there are many packages exactly corresponding one only 
is shown. 

“Pattern cards are exhibited displaying the assortment of 
colors, etc. The purchaser receives every information and facility 
that can contribute to his convenience and protect him from 
mistake. The goods are arranged with so much attention to the 
accommodation of the purchasers, that three or four hundred 
packages may be examined with care and accuracy in one day. 

“On the day of sale the purchasers assemble, each prepared 
with a catalogue marked with his estimate of the value of the 
articles wanted; a practice that not only guards the buyer against 
any disadvantageous excitement which competition naturally pro- 
duces, and refers him to the deliberate opinion formed upon care- 
ful examination before the sale, but also promotes a general 
knowledge of merchandise in every variety, and creates a useful 
register of the fluctuations of the market, as these catalogues are 
generally preserved, with notes in the margin of the prices at 
which every article has been sold. 

“At the commencement of the sale the conditions are recapitu- 
lated by the auctioneer, among which is a provision that no 
allowance will be made for damage or deficiency after the goods 


176 Early History of American Auctions 


have left the city (a regulation at once equitable and necessary), 
as otherwise there would be no protection for the auctioneer in 
the settlement of his accounts, or for the seller against the 
fraudulent claims of strangers. This being however, a declared 
condition at all times, the publicity of the rule insures the prompt 
examination of the goods. 

“Package sales are resorted to when entire cargoes are to be 
sold, or where the quantity of goods is too great to be disposed 
of in detail. Large assortments of merchandise are daily offered 
at the piece sales, where packayes are opened, and the goods 
sold in small or large lots, as may most tend to the interest of the 
seller and the convenience of the purchaser. These sales are 
regular and systematic, being held by each auctioneer of extensive 
business on two or more specified days in each week, and are 
principally depended upon by the retailers as well as the larger 
dealers for their uniform supplies; they are held under the same 
implied regulations which govern sales by package. Every article 
is opened and exhibited on shelves on the morning of the sale; 
a sample piece of every package, as it is offered by the auctioneer, 
is displayed upon the counter for examination, and several others 
distributed among the company in original folds; the rest of the 
packages, if of similar quality, is sold in order; but the same 
process takes place whenever any difference in value exists, or 
where the accommodation of the purchasers makes it necessary. 
Ample time is given during the sale to examine accurately every 
article as it is offered. 

“A credit of three, four, or six months, is usually given on 
sales by the piece, where the amount purchased exceeds $100, 
and approved security is always required by the auctioneer. 
Legal interest is allowed for cash payment; and men of limited 
means, by a combination of their purchases, secure the credit 
which is at all times convenient, and frequently necessary—their 
united responsibility being admitted for amounts for which either 
individual would not be accepted. When it is considered that 
these transactions take place daily, and that the supplies so 
obtained are essential to the support of numerous inferior estab- 
lishments, the importance and value of the accommodation will 
be evident.” 

As the auctioneers grew in number and wealth they became 


CO Ah 


The Auction System 177 


a powerful influence in the money market. They were directors 
in nearly every bank in New York and obtained almost indefinite 
lines of credit.*® A report by a Citizens Committee in 1828 put 
it this way: “As auctioneers, in many cases give their own notes in 
payment for goods sold by them while at the same time they have 
the use of the very large amounts which they receive from those 
who buy from them, an increditable capital is thus accumulated 
in the hands of a few persons, who form a moneyed aristocracy, 
influencing the banks, controlling by the fear of their displeasure, 
the free expression of public opinion, and hostile to the genius of 
republican government.’** Since they took such precautions to 
have good names on the notes which they accepted for mer- 
chandise, their paper was accepted by the banks as prime; when 
a buyer became insolvent he commonly assigned his whole effects 
to protect his indorser and the auctioneers thus virtually absorbed 
the whole estate, to the detriment of his other debts by private 
sale. “Relying on this preference, they are proverbial, as a body, 
for trusting many dealers who, among merchants, are not con- 
sidered trustworthy,” . . . and “give ruinous facilities to rash 
young men to begin business without experience, character, or 
capital, and multiply failures to an extent that could not otherwise 
happen.’’#§ 

The rate of commission was determined by private bargain but 
tended to uniformity as among the auctioneers; the rates differed 
with the kind of goods and services performed. In a calculation 
for eleven New York auctioneers in 1829 a writer used 314% 
as the normal rate on foreign goods sold.*® In a schedule of 
rates recommended for adoption and allowed by the New York 
Chamber of Commerce when no agreement subsisted to the con- 
trary about 1820-5 the rate for sale of merchandise for foreign 
business was 5% and for inland business 214%.°° The profits 
of some auction firms were considered very large, the net to one 
firm exceeding $100,000 a year.*4 


“ Bolles, I, 380. 

“ Niles, 34: 260. 

* Tbid. 

” Niles, 35: 403. 

* Hardie, Description, 316. Many other rates are also given. 
* Niles, 18: 421. 


178 Early History of American Auctions 


An examination of the auction duties paid by the auctioneers 
of New York, Philadelphia, and Baltimore confirms the justice 
of persistent criticism that the auction markets were dominated 
by relatively few and powerful auctioneers; but the further 
charge that they were monopolistic seems questionable for the 
number of auctioneers was large and a comparison of the lists 
of auctioneers paying the largest amounts of auction duties shows 
not only radical changes in rank but also the appearance of new 
names in very short interims.°? These facts would indicate that 
competition was at work. 


” The duties paid by the big auctioneers in the fiscal year 1815-6 in New 
York City were: 


(000) 
Chas. Town $143. 
P. Hone 15. (One quarter) 
M. Hoffman 54. 
D. Dunham 335 
A. G. Thompson ite 
Saalicks 20. 
T. Franklin 10. 
T. Tripler 8. 
Wee Graitollly, ep 
C. S. Barstow 5. (Three quarters) 
P. McCarty 5. (Three quarters) 
Jas. Bleecker 4. 
I. Purdy Px 
W. T. Cook 2s 
R. M’Mennomy 2, 
Total 348. 


There were this year 45 auctioneers and the total duties paid were 
$355,000, of which the above 15 paid $348,000. Data from New York 
Assembly Journal, 1816: 410. 

In 1823 in New York City the ranking auctioneers were 


Van Schaick - $45,000. 
J. D. Wallace 34,000. 
J. Shotwell 32,000. 


There were three others who paid between $10,000 and $20,000 each, five 
between $5,000 and $10,000, six between $1,000 and $5,000, and eighteen 
less than $1,000, and several less than $100. The total duties this year were 
$207,000. Niles 25: 387. 

In 1828 the ranking list was: 


~ aa 


The Auction System 179 


Increasingly after 1816 auction sales of imported goods were 


' done for foreign account. British manufacturers and exporters 


consigned their goods directly to auctioneers or more commonly 
to agents sent to our ports. These “foreign agents of manu- 
facturing and mercantile establishments of Europe” were “most 
of them—single men, and aliens,—in the habit of living at board- 
ing houses, neither hiring houses, stores, or employing clerks.” 


(000) 

Haggerty & Austen $72. 
J. Hone & Sons 61. 
Ty. -Pearsall 45. 
R. Lawrence Sie 
A. G. Thompson 16. 
W. Timpson 12" 
Mills & Minton 10. 
M. Hoffman 8. 
AS 3S: Glass Oe 
Total 262. 


Thirty seven others paid a total amount of $37,000. Goodrich, Picture, 


53- 
In 1835 the ranking sales were as follows: 


Amount of sales Amount of 
_ Auctioneer non-dutiable sales dutiable Total sales 
(000) (000) (000) 
Jas. Bleecker $6,786. 6. $6,792. 
D. Austen . 202. 4,001. 4,353. 
S. Phillips 573. 3,263. 3,830. 
A. W. Bleecker 261. 3,276. 3,538. 
W. Timpson 693. Tegoce 2,010. 
R. Lawrence 972. 650. 1,632. 
J. W. Corlies 852. 612. 1,465. 
J. M. Muller 1,178. aie 1,210. 
H. L. Paterson 82. 1,090. 1,181. 
T. M. Hooper 8I. 836. O17. 


It is noteworthy that certain auctioneers specialized in non-dutiable goods, 
notably James Bleecker and J. M. Muller; such specialization would affect 
their relative importance when ranked on the basis of duties paid. Data 
from Williams Annual Register, 1836; 197. 

Further similar statistical data for New York for the years 1840-8 are 
given in New York Assembly Document 218 (1849) Vol. 5, p. 4; for 
Philadelphia data see Niles, 25: 80; 67: 342; 69: 336, and for Baltimore 
see Niles, 67: 324. 

N.Y. Assembly Journal, 1829: 391. 


180 Early History of American Auctions 


“On the arrival of their goods, their general practice” was “to 
hand over their invoices and endorsed bills of lading to their 
auctioneer, leaving it to him to enter their goods at the custom 
house and give bonds for the duties.” The auctioneers were “in 
the habit of making advances on goods so placed under their 
control, to an amount equal to two-thirds of their value, and to 
pay the balance on sales as soon as they” were made out and thus 
enabled “the agent to make an immediate remittance to 
shippers.’** It was frequently charged that these agents inter- 
fered in American elections, contributing substantial “sums of 
money for electioneering purposes . . . as well as for printing 
of pamphlets, &c., about the tariff, and for the support of agents 
at Washington when it was under discussion.’*® 

Besides the general advantages to the British principal of tend- 
ing to stifle our manufactures and of finding a market for his 
goods, the agent auction system gave him the certainty of an 
immediate sale and immediate remittance. It gave him the benefit 
of the customs credits and thus increased his working capital; 
the auctioneer became his bondsman for the duties at the custom 
house, as the law required that the sureties should be American 
citizens.°° The expenses of selling were greatly reduced com- 
pared with those which were unavoidable to a regular mercantile 
establishment—house and store rent, stationery, fuel, insurance, 
clerk hire, family expenses, taxes, bad debts, expenses of col- 
lections, fall in value of the goods left on hand—expenses which 
were estimated to amount to 7% to 10%.*" His agents tended 
to become experts, “and by constantly attending public sales, 
and becoming perfectly acquainted with the market, kept their 
friends advised of every change; so soon as any article sold at 
a profit, it was instantly ordered, and transmitted with great 
rapidity.’”°* They were said “to be always on the alert to obtain 
copies of orders sent to England by the old and experienced 
American importers, and the articles directed by them to be fur- 
nished as suitable for our market” were “hastily prepared and 


* Tbid. 

= Niles, 35: 83. 

* Bolles, I, 389; Annals of Congress, 16th Congress, Ist session, 2205. 
* Niles, 18: 419; Annals of Congress, 16th Congress, 2d session, 1650. 
** Bolles, I, 380. 


~~ ee 


ety Sete... 


eo 


Commercial Effects of Auctions 181 


sent off, to anticipate such orders, and supply the market before 
the goods on account of such orders” reached this country.* 

Custom house practices, as well as the ease of concealment, 
made it impossible to determine what proportion of imported 
goods were handled on foreign account. It was, in 1817, “sup- 
posed that more than one-half of the goods subject to ad valorem 
duties, . . . imported into the United States” were “entered 
by . . . the mere representatives of the owners of the goods.’ 
In 1819 an estimate, based upon “a careful examination of the 
weekly abstracts of merchandise entered at the custom house in 
New York” was that three-fourths of the importations were on 
foreign account.*t The New York Mercantile Society in a peti- 
tion to Congress in 1820 stated that the proportion ranged 
between two-thirds and three-fourths, and of dry goods from 
England, Scotland and Ireland four-fifths.°* In 1824 it was 
claimed it could be “substantiated by a reference to official papers, 
that about three-fourths of all British and French goods imported 
into New York” were on foreign account. 


COMMERCIAL EFFECTS OF THE AUCTIONS. 


It has been shown above that the auction system tended to 
reduce the efficiency of the protective tariff; this fact gave 
auctions a political importance as well as economic and fiscal; 
the resulting legislative campaign against auctions is treated in 
later paragraphs. The auction system produced some important 
commercial effects. Auctions facilitated the introduction of new 
foreign and domestic products; goods were forced on the market 
by rank price-cutting and in time the prejudices that opposed their 
introduction and advancement were overcome; this was true 
both of foreign and domestic goods.** The auctions were a 
solvent and revolutionary factor that broke down the too staid 


® Niles, 27: 280. 

* Annals of Congress, 15th Congress, Ist session, 51. 

* Niles, 18: 300. 

® Annals of Congress, 16th Congress, 2d session, 1653. 

* Niles, 27: 273. See similar and more detailed estimates in Niles, 27: 
289 (1825), and Niles, 34: 106 (1828), and Bolles, I, 445 (1840), citing 
Ingersoll’s Minority Report, April 4, 1844, No. 306, 28th Congress, Ist 
session. 

* Annals of Congress, 16th Congress, 2d session, 1531. 


182 Early History of American Auctions 


traditional methods of commerce and consumption; the changes 
in dress, for instance, were toward “cheap but showy fabric” 
and were noticed by contemporaries.® The auctions served par- 
ticularly the humbler domestic manufacturers with a means of 
reaching the market, and some who were too small to maintain a 
sales organization did all their selling through auctions.*® 

The strongest argument and apology for the auctioneers were 
that they tended to lower prices to the retailers and con- 
sumers through their economies in selling.®’ Certainly the sale 
at auction of a lot of merchandise at a sacrifice tended to give a 
very public expression of the apparent values of that sort of 
merchandise and set a presumptive low value on all the existing 
stock,®® but such an assessment of value is a common objection 
to price-cutting in any sale however conducted. It was often 
alleged that auctioneers sold more goods daily than they adver- 
tised; that often the advertised lot was sold at a good price but 
other lots of the same goods were auctioned at successively 
lower prices; and that, this practice of the auctioneers being 
known, the price of the advertised lot was not bid up and there 
was therefore a general depression of prices.® 

Undoubtedly there was much confusion as to values. Oppo- 
nents of auctions claimed that the original diminution of prices 
to consumers soon ceased to exist and was compensated for by a 
reduction in quality.*° Others dwelt upon the fact that auction- 
eers provided much less service for their customers, as catering 
to individuality, delivery, better inspection, store open every day 
at all hours, book credit, etc.” 

Other opponents denied outright that prices were any lower. 
It was argued that it was impossible that three-fourths of the 
imports into the United States could be sold for a series of 
years at a loss, and that since those sold at auction were subject 
to additional expense of about 5% above those sold at private 
sale, this added expense would be added to the cost of the 


Se Wibids. 1530: 
Sa libidesus32: 
* “Remarks upon the Auction System,” 9. 
Niles 17> 337. 

° Niles, 34: 260. 

Niles, 18: 421. 

™“Ruinous Tendency,” 8, 34-5. 


3 


Commercial Effects of Auctions 183 


goods and be ultimately borne by the consumer.** A most 
prominent auctioneer declared before an investigation committee 
of the New York Legislature in 1829 that goods sold higher at 
auction than at private sale.™* Auctions made it possible to test 
the market without real selling; the principal might instruct 
his agent to bid in the goods at a certain minimum price; to test 
the market the auctioneer would offer a small lot for trial and if 
these were sold above the limited price the sale would continue.** 
The psychology of auction sales, with the excitement of a crowd 
of buyers bidding against each other, tends to raise prices. 

The auction system affected the business of the importing 
merchants and the jobbers very materially. The passage of the 
auction law in New York in 1817, with its moderate duties on 
auction sales, gave New York City a comparative advantage 
over Boston and Philadelphia where “the free and absolute sale 
of goods at auction was not encouraged.” East India goods 
which formerly all went to Boston were thereafter sent to New 
York.”* Of course, other factors were tending to give supremacy 
to New York, such as the establishment of the first regular packet 
line between New York and Liverpool in 1817 and the con- 
struction of the Erie Canal in 1825 and the natural advantages 
of New York.7® 

The interior merchants and retailers resorted increasingly to 
auction sales at New York’; they came from Ohio, Indiana, 
Tennessee, Missouri, and other states, and the compelling motive 
was said to be the cheaper prices*®; the periodicity and dependa- 
bility of the auction sales were a great convenience to the visiting 


Feiilesuas: 220; 342258; 27: 200. 

Niles, 36: 186; 34: 258. See Niles, 34: 298, and “Remarks upon the 
Auction System,’ 48-52, for instances where auction prices exceeded 
retailers’ prices. 

™ Niles, 34: 250. 

® Hunt’s, 10: 167. 

*For a contemporary expert estimate of the relative merchandising 
advantages of New York, Boston and Philadelphia, see Girard, Merchants’ 
Sketch Book, 1, 6: “In New York alone is located a class of foreign 
agents, whose whole business is to vend, through auctioneers and com- 
mission houses, the immense surplus production of their manufacturing 
districts.” 

(aNiles) 2-103: 

*“An Examination of the ‘Remarks on Auctions,” 4, 9. 


184 Early History of American Auctions 


buyers; and they found the jobbers became more accommodating 
in the face of the competing auctions.*® The overstocking of the 
seaports tended to force the goods into the interior “generally 
on extended credits’®®; in the mercantile world the East tended 
to become creditor to the-West. It was complained at the time 
that the New York auction tax had the effect of making the 
consumers of taxed goods in all states subject to New York tax 
laws.*! The American manufacturers did not object so much to 
wholesale sales of foreign goods provided they were made through 
the regular jobber channels, but sales at auction obstructed their 
distributing system by eliminating the jobber.*? 

Besides the country merchants, the small city retailers were 
advantaged by auction sales. They were able to procure their 
supplies without the necessity of paying the intermediate jobbers’ 
profits, which were commonly estimated at 15 or 20%.°** A con- 
temporary estimated that in New York City in 1831 there were 
about 7,000 persons engaged in the retail dry goods business 
most of whom made their purchases at auction piece sales.** 
The retailer with small capital, either on his sole account or 
jointly with others of his class, was able to buy direct and free 
himself from jobber monopoly.’*> A common complaint, however, 
of the retailer was that he had to spend so much time in auction 
rooms.*® 

The two middlemen who were hurt most were the importing 
merchants and the jobbers. A majority of the American dry- 
goods importing merchants, formerly the most numerous and 
important of the mercantile class, gave place to, or became them- 
selves, agents of British manufacturing houses.** If an Ameri- 
can merchant sent an order with description or samples the 
British manufacturer frequently sent by the same ship a large 


* Annals of Congress, 16th Congress, 2d session, p. 1530. 

* Annals of Congress, 16th Congress, Ist session, p. 2302. 

*" Niles, 34: 259. 

® Annals of Congress, 16th Congress, Ist session, p. 2108. 

© Annals of Congress, 16th Congress, 2d session, p. 1531. 

“An Examination of ‘Remarks on Auctions,” 4. 

® Tbid., 6; Annals of Congress, 16th Congress, 2d session, p. 1531. 

* Niles, 34: 350. 

** “Observations on the Report of the Committee of Ways and Means,” 
1028. pues: ANilesh anette ss: 24 23nd: 


oe 


SS A a NR . 


Commercial Effects of Auctions 185 


quantity of the same goods to be sold at auction by his agent, 
thus defeating the merchants’ market.** On account of this and 
other devices, the old importing houses failed*® and new houses 
were restrained from beginning.®*® The general decline of the 
American merchant marine after 1815 was a leading factor in 
this tendency to mortality of mercantile houses. 

The jobbers, as distinguished from retailers on the one hand 
and importing merchants on the other, were opposed to seeing 
their old customers go to auctions and were loud in their con- 
demnation of the auction system.°t The auctioneers, replying 
to the jobbers’ demand for legislation prohibiting auctions, urged 
the danger of class legislation,®? that other classes of tradesmen 
might be abolished or regulated when once such legislation had 
been initiated. Their efforts to abolish their new competitor 
having failed, there arose an “intermediate grade of merchants” 
who purchased largely at auctions, at the package sales, from 
wholesale importers, and in such other ways as they could obtain 
merchandise on reasonable terms, and who sold to local and 
country retailers.°* One of these New York houses, Reuben 
Vose, shoe and hat store, was the first to introduce the one-price 
plan, which has come to characterize American business; he 
published a catalogue describing some hundred different articles 
with all prices marked against them; he gained and kept the 
ascendency over all other New York jobbers in sales to western 
and southern merchants; his business was conducted on a strictly 
cash basis and he won from the credit houses their cash busi- 
ness.° There arose at this time in New York a company of 
young men, called “Prime Ministers,’ who were the junior 


“Remarks on Present System of Auctions,’ 12; Bolles, I, 389-90. 

®° Read the lamentation of a Philadelphian in 1823, Niles, 23: 130. Of 
the 37 names, all merchants of high standing, appearing on an insurance 
policy in 1799, 27 had become bankrupt by 1823; of 54 persons or houses 
having merchant flags in the Baltimore observatory as engaged as ship 
owners in foreign trade and importers, 24 became bankrupts in the four 
years ending 1823. 

Niles;-95 + 241. 

“ Niles, 20: 66. 

* “An Examination of ‘Remarks on the Present System of Auctions,’” 8. 

*% New York Assembly Journal, 1829, p. 393. A common form of such 
transaction is detailed in Niles, 34: 208. 

“ Girard, Merchants’ Sketchbook, 8. 


186 Early History of American Auctions 


partners and confidential clerks of the jobbing houses; they had 
entire control of all country buyers who visited the city for the 
first time; they were men of education and polished manners, 
superior to the merchants who employed them; and they soon 
acquired a powerful influence in the mercantile world.” 

By these (purchase by package at auction one-price-cash-sale, 
employment of expert salesmen, and entertainment of visiting 
buyers) and other devices the jobbers withstood to a good degree 
the competition of the auction houses. 


CUSTOMS CREDILS: 


A confusion of interests was injected into the commercial and 
fiscal situation by customs credits and duty bonds. Legislation,** 
in 1789, 1790, and 1795, had provided credit for customs on 
certain imported commodities for from four to twelve months, 
varying with the source and commodity. In 1799 a more general 
system was adopted: on goods from the West Indies, half of 
the duties were due in three and half in six months; on salt, in 
nine months; on wines, in twelve months; while on goods from 
Europe, one-third of the duties was due in eight, ten and twelve 
months; on goods other than from Europe, one-half in six, and 
one-fourth each in nine and twelve months; teas might, at the 
option of the importer, be deposited in storehouses agreeable to 
the importer and revenue inspector, and bonds be given running 
two years for double the amount of the duties. Collectors were 
also allowed to receive imported goods on deposit, to secure the 
payment of duties, as a substitute for sureties on bonds. If the 
importer, therefore, did not care to give such sureties, he could 
give his own bond, and remove of his merchandise all but enough 
to insure the payment of the duties on the whole. Duties for less 
than $50 were payable in cash (after 1832 this minimum was 
raised to $200). The law of 1799 was amended in 1805 and 1818 
by minor extensions of credit periods.” 


elbid., 17: 


* For a precise chronological summary of the legislation see Niles, 18: 
200. 


* Bolles, I, 478; Niles, 18: 209-300. These extensions were primarily 
due to petitions by the East India merchants of Boston and Salem. Niles, 
18: 306. 


Customs Credits 187 


In 1820 a reaction appeared and great effort was made to 
limit customs credits to drugs, dye stuffs, and groceries, except 
wines and ardent spirits, at three months and six months; to 
teas, at three, six and nine months; and to require that duties 
on manufactured goods be paid on arrival, or be deposited for 
six months and then sold at auction if the duties were not paid. 
The importer who might contemplate re-exportation was to have 
three alternatives: to avail himself of the system of drawbacks, 
by giving his bond for the duties and taking the debenture on 
re-exportation, or to declare his intention at the time of entry, 
giving his bond for security, to export and not re-land the goods; 
or, in lieu of such surety, to deposit them in a warehouse and 
take his time to decide whether to sell in the domestic or the 
foreign market. No discrimination was made in this bill between 
importation on foreign and domestic account, although consider- 
able pressure was brought to that end; the reasons against 
discrimination were (a) the desire to retain the dwindling carry- 
ing trade®* and (b) the shipping agreements with England.°® 
The bill did not satisfy those merchants who petitioned the indis- 
criminate abolition of credits; the Congressional leaders believed 
so radical a measure would confound our commerce, and saw no 
reason for tampering with the West India trade which was in 
the hands of American merchants and did not operate to injure 
our manufactures. Credits to the Far East were to be reduced, 
so the arguments ran, because the balance of trade with these 
countries was adverse and led to exportation of specie, and it 
was not best to encourage such trade, and because the merchants 
who conducted it were rich capitalists who did not need credits 
of longer term than was required to make a single voyage. 

This bill of 1820 failed to pass, but marks the reversion of 
Opinion in the matter of credit extensions. In 1832 the law 
was decisively changed, so that “duties on wool, woolens and 
all merchandise of which wool formed a part, were required 
to be paid in cash without discount, or, at the option of the 
importer, be stored under bond at his risk, subject to the pay- 
ment of interest from the date of importation. On all other 
merchandise, the duty, if not exceeding $200, must be paid in 


eoNtless. ToOses0 le 
® Niles, 18: 302. 


188 Early History of American Auctions 


cash; if exceeding $200, be paid or secured in the manner 
formerly required—one-half payable in three months and the 
balance in six months. When any installment of duties became 
due, enough merchandise was to be sold at public auction to pay 
them, if this was not done by the importer.’’!°° 

The object in allowing a credit in the payment of duties on 
foreign imports was to enable the importer, out of the proceeds 
of the sales of the goods imported, to reimburse himself the 
amount of such duties before they became payable. The length 
of the credit was, therefore, presumably determined by the 
interval required to dispose of the goods after entry; a shorter 
credit would force the importer to tie up his capital in customs 
paid and limit the volume of his business and our foreign trade,*™ 
whereas a longer credit would provide the importer with addi- 
tional capital from the time the goods were sold till the revenue 
bonds came due. Our early national policy was to promote 
foreign trade and navigation; there was little capital in the 
country, and the provision of capital by this indirect means was 
thought necessary to divert trade from foreign ships and mer- 
chants.1° In the East Indies trade the voyages were under par- 
ticularly heavy expense; the goods were of high price, large 
quantity, slow consumption, and slow returns, and therefore 
Congress gave exceptionally long credits to goods from the Far 
East.1°* The British government provided warehouses for the 
deposit of imported goods and the payment of duties only when 
removed and sold; the United States government had provided 
no warehouses as yet, nor had private warehouses arisen due to 
the dearth of capital, and so customs credits were allowed instead, 
being cheaper for the government. 

The amount of the duties was in fact a loan from the govern- 
ment to the importer, without interest, and became a real part 
of his capital and as productive as his direct contributions. When 
the term of the customs credits exceeded that allowed by him in 


™ Bolles, I, 495; Act of 1832, Sections 5 and 6. Further limitations 
were passed in 1842. Bolles, I, 480. The difficulties attending these 
restrictions were great, but were somewhat allayed by the establishment 
of the British warehouse system in the United States in 1854. 

*” Annals of Congress, 8th Congress, 2d session, p. 1404. 

1” Niles, 18: 290. 

* Annals of Congress, 16th Congress, Ist session, p. 2342. 


_~——— 


Customs Credits 189 


sales to retailers it provided him free of cost with the active use 
of government funds.1°%* The importers were accordingly 
strongly opposed to cash customs duties or shortened credits as 
provided in the bill of 1820.1°° Undoubtedly the advantage from 
this free continuing loan on government account did not accrue 
wholly to the importers; for, to the degree that they were in 
competition, they would be forced to pass the advantage on to 
the consumers, by way of lower prices of the products handled. 
It is impossible to determine the exact extent of this percolation. 

It was argued that this generous provision of commercial 
funds by the government was particularly advantageous to the 
younger and smaller importers, and that the abolition of such 
credits and the insistence upon cash payment of duties would 
not only curtail importations but would create and retain a 
monopoly of foreign trade in the hands of the large foreign 
and home capitalists.°°° This became the most popular defense 
of customs credits ; but the small importers were willing to forego 
customs credits if that would defeat the auction system.1°%* By 
1820 the country possessed considerable free capital which might 
be borrowed by importers on practically the same security as 
had to be given the government.*°§ 

The customs credit system did not discriminate between goods 
imported by American importers and on American account and 
those imported on foreign account. It seems that customs credits | 
and auctions gave the British an advantage over the American 
importer and increased his commercial capital by the amount of 
duties.*°° It was possible for the British agent to turn his goods 
three times within the average period of the credits and his 


™ Niles, 18: 299; Annals of Congress, 16th Congress, Ist session, p. 
2305. Customs credits helped to make the fortunes of N. L. and G. 
Griswold, John Jacob Astor, and Th. H. Smith. Barrett, Old Merchants, 
pesos 

*° See resolutions of merchant associations as reported, Niles, 18: 306; 


-I9: 168, 222; 33: 380, and Annals of Congress, 15th Congress, Ist session, 


p. 368. 

* Bolles, I, 495; No. Am. Review, XII: 66; Annals of Congress, 16th 
Congress, Ist session, 2306. 

7 See arguments against the bill of 1820, Niles, 18: 305. 

*8 Annals of Congress, 16th Congress, 2d session, p. 1652; Niles, 27: 305. 

° Niles, 18: 300, describes the manner of this. The Liverpool packets, 
by increasing the turnover, added to this advantage. 


190 Early History of American Auctions 


capital was therefore doubled.° A contemporary estimated that 
the United States government thus made a continuing loan of six 
million dollars without interest to foreigners, our competitors.** 

Protectionists logically claimed that custom house credits were 
a positive bounty on importations and minimized or nullified the 
protection given by import duties.* Cash duties meant more 
stringent protection and therefore manufacturers supported the 
bill of 1820. 

Customs credits, by easing the importation of goods, undoubt- 
edly stimulated excessive and speculative importations.** These 
were injurious to our manufacturers, merchants, and government, 
for they made business less stable and dependable, caused bank- 
ruptcies, and resulted in heavy losses of revenues. It is probable, 
however, that consumers got goods at lower prices.*** The losses 
of revenue from failure to pay customs credits were particularly 
heavy in the case of foreign agents, for they had little property 
other than their imported cargoes and it was too common that 
one agent went surety for another. Auctions offered a speedy 
sale and ready means of getting away without paying their 
credits.%° In 1821 it was remarked that the “increase of custom 
house delinquencies has kept pace with the increase on foreign 
account.”42% A calculation of the revenue duties from 1789 to 
1820 showed that of the $351.3 million duties only $1.5 million 
or 0.45% had been lost by the insolvency or was doubtful.* 

The system of customs credits as a source of commercial 
capital became more efficient as the turnover of goods and the 
number of voyages within the interval of the credit were 


2° Niles, 34: 106. 

1 Niles, 27: 274. See a contrary opinion in Annals of Congress, 16th 
Congress, Ist session, p. 2305. 

eo Niles sic SOlnes04s) LOss2g4- 

18 Bolles, I, 495; Niles, 17: 337. 

14 Annals of Congress, 16th Congress, Ist session, p. 2304. 

45 Niles, 18: 301; Annals of Congress, 14th Congress, 2d session, p. 850. 

48 Niles, 18: 301. A statement of the amounts in litigation is given 
according to cities and shows that litigations in ,those cities whose trade 
was on foreign account far exceeded those whose trade was on American 
account, whether their trade was relatively large or small. 

47 Niles, 18: 9. See also Report of Secretary of Treasury, Crawford, 
February 23, 1820. A quarterly statement of customs bonds outstanding 
1821-2 is given in Niles, 23: 403; they ranged from $16 to 24 million. 


te i 


Undervaluation of Imports 1gt 


increased. Auctions facilitated these operations; by selling at 
auction for cash, or on short term notes which could be discounted 
at the banks, the amount of the duties thus loaned could be 
invested in a new voyage, and possibly several such rounds be 
completed before the first came due.*"* 


UNDERVALUATION OF IMPORTS. 


Another means by which the protection to American manu- 
factures was minimized, and which was facilitated by auction 
sales, was the system of evaluating imports.14® The plan in use 
was to take the invoice valuations, as of the exporting country, 
and certain flat addenda of to or 20%.1*° Such additions were, 
of course, artificial; the foreign cost so augmented was not the 
domestic cost, for the increment did not equal the difference in 
value here and abroad. The importer, consignee, or agent, had 
to make an entry and state under oath that the entry and invoice 
stated the actual cost of the goods abroad; if the goods were not 
invoiced at their actual cost at the place of exportation, with 
the design of evading any part of the duties, the goods, or the 
value of them, was forfeited; and if the collector suspected that 
the goods were invoiced at less than this true cost, he might retain 
them until an appraisement was made and the duties set accord- 
ing to the appraised value. But in practice this privilege of 
home appraisal was, for numerous reasons,!?! not effective, and 
the systematic evasion of duties by undervaluation was rank. 

“Even when the foreign manufacturer entered his goods at 
their cost to him, the price was about 16% lower than the prices 
of similar goods entered by American importers.”!”? The foreign 
merchants could always lay in their goods on better terms than 


“* Niles, 18: 300. The Mercantile Society of New York therefore stood 
for prohibitive taxes on sales at auction without any reduction in the 
term of customs credits. Annals of Congress, 16th Congress, 2d session, 
p. 1650. 

™ For complete statement of details of methods of collecting revenues, 
see Annals of Congress, 15th Congress, Ist session, p. 35 ff. 

™ Niles, 19: 157. 

The reasons are given in Annals of Congress, 15th Congress, Ist ses- 
sion, pp. 44-6. 

™ Bolles, I, 391; Proceedings, General, Harrisburg Convention, 1827, 
Pp. 47-51. 


192 Early History of American Auctions 


American houses having no connection abroad; if sent by the 
foreign manufacturer himself, the cost price could be quite 
arbitrarily set for he could consider only the cost of his mate- 
rials and omit his own labor and industry and his profits and, 
as the prices realized in the American market bore no necessary 
relation to the invoice price, he was tempted to invoice the goods 
at the lowest price which he thought he could get by the custom 
house.'*" 

But more unscrupulous evasions were practiced, too. As the 
valuation upon which duties were to be paid were determined 
in most cases by the person who was to pay the duty, the tempta- 
tion was strong to undervalue, and evasions were more common 
after the passage of each law raising the tariff rates. Various 
devices were used to make fictitious entries.°* The foreign 
merchant who bought his goods from manufacturers would do 
so as opportunities were favorable, and often in different parcels, 
at different places, from several persons, at different prices; 
obviously when he prepared his own invoice he could set arbi- 
trary prices, for it was quite impossible to trace the true costs.” 
If necessary, fictitious sales between principal and agents or 
partners or friendly traders might be used to create semblance 
of a true price.2° The goods might be consigned to an Ameri- 
can or foreign agent who had no knowledge of the foreign cost 
of the goods, except the invoice as sent to him, and who could 
without perjury enter the goods and take the custom house oath. 
The danger of conviction for perjury in swearing that a fictitious 
invoice was true was small any way, for the testimony requisite 
to maintain a criminal prosecution could very seldom be obtained 
in this country and the agent or consignee only swore that the 
invoice produced was the true and only invoice sent to him. 


23 Annals of Congress, 15th Congress, Ist session, p. 38; Niles, 27: 290; 
Bolles, I, 391. It was alleged that two invoices were sometimes used, one 
with undervaluations to enter by, and another with true valuations to 
sell by; the true invoice was often sent to a third person, who was agent 
of the consignor of the goods and who was instructed and authorized to 
demand the goods from the consignee who made the entry. 

24 See a series of instances in “Remarks upon the Auction System,” pp. 
12-18. 

5 Annals of Congress, 15th Congress, Ist session, p. 36-8. 


6 Thid., 47. 


a 


——————— ee Orr 


Objections to the Auctions 193 


These evasions ‘were much more common in importations on 
foreign account than on American account. The great reason 
for this was the greater facilities offered by the agency system. 
It is likely that the foreign agent also did not feel the direct 
responsibility for moral rectitude which he would feel in his 
own country. The agent was also concealed behind the auction- 
eer, and the rapidity with which the latter transacted business 
rendered it difficult to detect frauds that would be exploited 
against the regular trader.’*" The auctioneer might or might not 
be privy to such frauds.’*§ 

The goods which were subject to ad valorem duties were 
mostly manufactures; the principal articles paying specific duties 
were iron, hemp, sugar, tea, coffee, wine, spirits, spices, molasses 
and salt. The evasions of duties by undervaluations applied, of 
course, only to the former group. Before 1815 the revenues 
yielded by the specific duty group exceeded those from the 
ad valorem group; but after 1815 this proportion “was not 
only suddenly but greatly reversed” and the common explanation 


-was that the possibility of evading duties and thus lowering the 


bar to importation stimulated relatively the importation of the 
ad valorem group.’”® 

In the tariff act of 1832 Congress provided for the home 
valuation of imports, but this provision wa's not to go into effect 
for ten years, and meanwhile it was repealed, and has never since 
been passed. 


OEBTECLIONS TO THe AUCTIONS. 


Many of the objections to auctions have been stated above. 
These and others will be summarized here.**° 

(a) Auctions tended to defeat the American protective policy. 
They facilitated dumping by foreign manufacturers, made cus- 
toms credits more advantageous to importers, and abetted the — 
evasion of duties by undervaluation. 

(b) Auctions hurt certain vested interests, particularly the 


SNES 275 200; 35: 137. 

#8 Niles, 34: 250. 

”° See argument, Annals of Congress, 15th Congress, Ist session, p. 51. 
There were many other factors working to this end. 

189 See general statements in Niles, 34: 174; 27: 258; New York 
Assembly Document 53, Vol. 4: 287. 


194 Early History of American Auctions 


American importing merchants and jobbers, and disturbed the 
accustomed channels of trade, and diverted a large part of foreign 
commerce to foreign agents and consignees resident in America. 

(c) The auctioneer was less responsible than the merchant and 
retailer for dishonest practices and frauds, such as short lengths, 
deficient numbers, defective materials, etc.'*? 

(d) Auctions tended to concentrate a considerable proportion 
of the trade in a few hands and draw away the customers of 
merchants and retailers, and were therefore attacked as “monop- 
olistic.” But it was a perverted use of the term, for the ear-marks 
of monopoly are limitation of supply, higher prices, discrimina- 
tions, and excessive profits, none of which characterized the 
auctions. Indeed they tended to make trade more competitive, 
to break the hold of jobbers and retailers on their customers, 
and to give open publicity to prices and profits. The concen- 
tration of auction sales at fewer places was to the convenience 
of buyers and very likely intensified competition among buyers. 
Auction sales made it possible for small local and interior retailers 
to get a start whom the jobbers refused or hesitated to encourage. 
The complaint against auctions was that against big business 
and plutocracy; they were held to be “unjust, by giving to a 
few, that which ought to be distributed among the mercantile 
community generally. A single auction house does as much 
business as would support fifty respectable firms in private trade, 
each consisting of two partners, maintaining two families, and 
two or three clerks. The evident tendency of this monopoly is 
to crush the middle ranks, and to divide the society into the 
very rich and the poor.’**? Evidently the case is exaggerated 
and the economic doctrine questionable. The only basis for 
charge of monopoly was that the auctioneers were under license 
by the State and their number limited and no other persons were 
allowed to sell in this way***; but as there were every year some 
auctioneer licenses not taken it is evident that New York was 


“! For instances showing the impossibility of holding the auctioneer 
responsible, see “Remarks upon the Auction System,” pp. 27-31, 36-42. 
For a direct denial of such responsibility and for a strong statement of 
the auctioneers’ honesty and honor, see the “Auctioneers’ Memorial” in 
Annals of Congress, 16th Congress, 2d session, p. 1521. 

= Niles o4e5os) LO laO-L 30 moe sons 

*%3 Niles, 18: 418. 


=~” 


‘ rs. ~* 


Objections to the Auctions 195 


not suffering from the restriction on the number of auctioneers.*** 
Nor were good evidences of monopoly the common charges that 
certain goods could be found only at auctions, that some stores 
refused to sell certain goods by private treaty but only through 
auctions where higher prices might be gotten, and that buyers at 
auction had frequently to buy more than they wanted.™° 

(e) In proportion to the amounts of goods imported and sold, 
the agents, consignees and auctioneers did not hire as many 
houses, stores and clerks and did not, therefore, contribute as 
much to the public coffers as the generality of resident merchants, 
jobbers and retailers. So they were alleged to hurt the city 
and escape their due burden of public expenditure.’** But, on 
the other hand, the revenue derived by the State of New York 
from auction taxes constituted one of the principal items in the 
canal fund—“a revenue which grew out of a business which drew 
merchants or purchasers from all parts of our widely extended 
country, which tended directly to enhance the value of houses, 
stores and lots, multiply the business of the shipper, importer 
and jobber, and which has filled our city with palaces, and made 
our merchant princes.”!** 

(f) Auctions tended to concentrate the whole trade of the 
country in a few large cities, to the extinction of all other whole- 
sale markets. The importers of such places as Richmond, Peters- 
burg, Charleston, Savannah, Augusta, disappeared within a few 
years.‘** Goods bought at auction in seaboard cities were carried 
by itinerant dealers to interior towns and offered for sale at 
auction day after day and night after night in some rooms 
adjoining the local retail stores; such operations tended to disrupt 
and destroy the local retail trade.‘*? Some of these interior 
auctioneers were resident and maintained purchasing agents at 
the seaboard city.'*° 


134.N. Y. Senate Document 44, (1832), Vol. I, p. 8. 

* “Remarks upon the Auction System,” 34. 

8 N.Y. Assembly Journal, 1829, p. 301. 

*" Hunt’s, 10: 157; New York, Senate Journal, 1823, p. 1035. 

#8 Niles, (1828) 34: 258. 

9 N. Y. Assembly Document 12 (1832) Vol. I, contains memorial from 
Ogdensburgh. Rochester petitioned the State Legislature in 1831, but 
the fact that the total auction taxes paid by that city in 1831 were only 
$80 is evidence that the evils alleged were exaggerated. N. Y. Assembly 
Document I51. 

N. Y. Assembly Document (1831) 151. 


196 Early History of American Auctions 


(¢) It was argued that the foreign agent auction system hurt 
the country: because it tended to cause the export of money 
which would otherwise be expended inside our boundaries. An 
estimate of the profits of foreign agents in 1825 was $2,000,000, 
which, it was pointed out, would employ 500 principal merchants, 
with their 1,000 clerks and assistants, together with their families, 
and require stores, warehouses and dwellings, fully 1,000 houses 
with rentals of $250,000, and would percolate to advantage 
through mechanics, dependent branches of business, farmers, 
etwas 

(h) Auction sales disturbed the regularity and dependability 
of commerce and industry. Dumping by foreign manufacturers 
had that very purpose. That steadiness of market which is 
required to yield a reasonable profit and regular employment 
was adversely affected.‘** Prices fluctuated widely and speculative 
purchases were fostered.*** 

(i) A charge against auctions, reiterated without end, was 
that they injected into use a poorer quality of goods than the 
people were wont to buy by private treaty and than they thought 
they were buying. It was a period when, the world over, people 
began to wear cheaper clothes introduced and made possible by 
the Industrial Revolution, particularly cotton goods. Auctions 
probably did facilitate this change of custom in costume by break- 
ing the rigid trade channels and giving the manufacturer a 
competing outlet for his new products. But the enemies of the 
auction system charged the manufacturers and auctioneers with 
fraudulent activities. It was alleged that manufacturers pre- 
pared “on purpose for auctions, goods defective in every 
respect—in length, width, quality, color, and pattern, which no 
reputable house would venture to import and to offer at private 
sale—and which would be dear at any price”’**; that they used 
auctions to force the sale of refuse and damaged goods***; and 


18 Niles, 27: 274, 2890. This Mercantilistic doctrine is immemorial; for 
a similar complaint in 1704 see Goodrich, Picture, 45. 

im Niles, 27: 273); 134: 250. 

148 Niles, 34: 258, 250, 350. 

M44 Niles, 34: 258; 31: 24, 86; 18: 419-420. ‘Remarks upon the Auction 
System,” 18-21. Some of these charges smack strongly of protectionism 
and connote a newspaper propaganda. 

8 Niles, 27: 280. 


Se Ee 


2 ee ee ae. 


Objections to the Auctions 197 


that they artfully made and packed the poor quality goods so 
that none but good judges could discriminate.**® Auctions were 
supposed to facilitate these deceptions because the time and con- 
veniences allowed to examine the goods were entirely inade- 
quate.*7 Auctions caused a decline in the “distinctive character 
of goods,’ that is, they could no longer be bought simply by 
name and brand and number™® but only after personal inspection. 
These allegations were probably somewhat exaggerated, for most 
of the goods sold at auction were sent there from the stocks of 
importers and retailers'*® and the difficulty of examining the 
goods in the short interval at time of sale was “in some measure 
removed by the previous exposure of the goods for examination 
(1 to 3 days) and also by the three days allowed after each 
sale, as allowed by common custom for the examination, within 
which time, goods sold as perfect, and of specific lengths, 
breadths and qualities, if found to differ from the terms of sale, 
in either of these respects,” might be returned, or retained by 
the purchaser “receiving such deductions as may be agreed upon 
at his option.’”’°° That so few claims were made for deficiencies 
is evidence that the frauds were not rank.*** 

(j) Various undesirable social results were ascribed to 
auctions. They were thought to lower private morals. Decep- 
tions, frauds, irresponsible sellers, etc., which were alleged to 
prevail at auctions, were said to be subversive of “the mutual 


6 Niles, 18: 419. The difference amounted to at least 20%. 

“7 “Remarks upon the Auction System,’ 42-4. “At what are called 
piece or shelf sales, which form nine-tenths of auction sales,—one minute, 
or even less, and scarcely ever so much as two minutes, is all the time 
usually allowed to a large company of perhaps two hundred buyers, to 
examine, in the twilight of an auction store, amidst noise and confusion, 
goods which they never saw before. The worse the goods—the shorter 
will probably be the time given.” Niles, 34: 250. 

“8“Names and lengths now (1828) really mean nothing—for years past 
all has been confusion.” “Remarks upon the Auction System,’ 22-26. 
Instances are given. 

An Examination of Remarks upon the Auction System,” 10. 

'N. Y. Assembly Journal, 1820, p. 393. 

*“The average amount of deductions made from package sales of 
British dry goods, for claims of every nature, will not equal the one- 
sixteenth of one per cent.” Auctioneers’ Memorial, Annals of Congress, 
16th Congress, 2d session, p. 1528. 


198 Early History of American Auctions 


confidence and courtesy that subsisted, in our better days, between 
the responsible importer and his customers,” “subversive of all 
the milder and kindlier charities of our nature, and unavoidably 
conducive to progressive and infinite depravity.”!°? The spirit 
of gambling was supposed to be excited by bidding at public 
sales, and resulted in over-buying, bankruptcies and misery.1™ 
The auctioneers claimed that their business was conducted on a 
high moral plane, and that credit extensions by private treaty 
sellers encouraged over-buying to a greater extent than auction 
sales.1°* 

(x) In this connection certain business practices were criti- 
cized. Fictitious bidding at auctions was alleged; false news 
was published; the market was rigged; etc.1°° To evade auction 
duties small quantities of a certain commodity were offered at 
auction to determine the price, and then large sales at this price 
were made in private; false reports of sales were used***; the 
auctioneers sold their commissions,’°* conducted sales at other 
places than their regular place of business,’°* and did other 
irregular things. 


CAMPAIGN AGAINST THE AUCTIONS. 


The opponents of auctions tried openly three methods for 
ousting or restricting them. One was a vehement publicity 
campaign exposing their evils and shortcomings in violent and 
exaggerated language. This was done through newspapers, 
pamphlets and mercantile associations. The campaign was 
nation-wide but largely concentrated in the seaboard cities. 
Alliances between cities and with the protectionists were effected. 
The auctioneers fought this by a counter publicity campaign 


*** Citizens’ Committee, N. Y.; Niles, 34: 258. 

™ Niles, 19 s713ie 

** Annals of Congress, 16th Congress, Ist session, p. 2175; 2d session, 
p. 15290; N. Y. Assembly Journal, 1820, p. 393. 

*° Niles, 34: 261; “Remarks upon the Auction System,” 44-6. 

*® Niles, 18: 420; “Ruinous Tendency,” 13; Annals of Congress, 13th 
Congress, Vol. III, p. 1853; Bolles, 113; N. Y. Senate Document 44 
(1832), Vol. I, p. 6. 

*7N. Y. Senate Document 44 (1832), Vol. I, p. 7. 

*’ New York Assembly Journal, 1820, p. 530. 


State Legislation 199 


and by threats to withdraw their advertisements from hostile 
newspapers.*°? 

The second device was to boycott the auctions. The members 
of merchant associations agreed to purchase no goods at auction 
and to deal with no one who did. The United Dry Goods Asso- 
ciation of New York in 1821 adopted unanimously a strong reso- 
lution against auctions but found after a short trial that its 
boycott was not respected by its members and repealed by 
close vote so much of the resolution as bound them to boycott.*® 
In 1830 165 dealers in New York pledged themselves for one year 
not to purchase at any sale by auction where endorsed notes were 
required because they believed auction sales should be on an 
equality in this respect with private sales. Another large list 
of dealers pledged themselves not to deal with auctioneers who 


at a package sale exhibited dry goods in lots or parcels of less 


value than $150, except in original packages, or who offered for 
sale duplicate packages not declared in the catalogue, or refused 
to sell a sample lot that had been exhibited. And a third long 
list of signers agreed not to attend, or be concerned in any pur- 
chase made at, auction after two o’clock p. m.*%* Boycotts of 
this limited nature which sought to correct specific abuses were 
more successful than omnibus boycotts against the whole auction 
system. 

The third method of opposition was legislation, by the State 
and federal governments. 


SPATE LEGISEAVEMON: 


The colonies had from very early dates regulated auction sales ; 
the regulations pertained to the places and times of auctions, the 
appointment of the auctioneer, his commission, his bond, the 
goods salable, reports, etc. In 1713 New York laid a duty on 
auction sales'®? and auctions were taxed almost continuously 


*%° Niles, 36: 186. 

Niles, 20 > 103. 

*! Niles, 37, 410. 

= Act ot @etober 23, 1713, chapter 267;- cf. Act of July 5, 171s, 
chapter 294; cf. Act of May 14, 1717, chapter 326, and Act of June 24, 


200 Early History of American Auctions 


thereafter throughout the 18th century. In 1804 New York 
experimented in classifying goods according to their sources and 
kinds and original packages and in fixing different taxes accord- 
ingly,1** but abandoned the plan temporarily in 1814 and. adopted 
a flat rate.°* In 1801 the number of auctioneers in the City of 
New York was limited by law to 24, in 1803 to 30, in 1813 to 
36, in 1824 to 42, and in 1825 to 54. In 1817 the auction law 
was overhauled but with no animosity toward the auction system; 
the taxes laid were $2 per $100 sales of wines and ardent spirits, 
$1 per $100 sales of East India goods, in original package, and 
$1.50 per $100 sales of all other goods whatsoever; auctioneers 
were to be appointed by the governor and council, as many as he 
pleased, but not more than 36 for New York City; the mayor 
was to name the place of sale at auction of horses, carriages and 
household furniture, auctions held at other than his place of 
business had to have two days’ notice in the newspapers; auction- 
eers forfeited their licenses by accepting a license in another 
state; the auctioneer was to pay to the State a tax of 2%% of 
the auction duties collected by him.1° This act was sponsored 
and approved by the auctioneers and was wholly regulatory and 
fiscal in purpose; auctions had not yet incurred the displeasure 
of protectionists, merchants and retailers. The auction revenues 


1719; cf. Act of November 10, 1720, chapter 399. These acts show that 
it became the permanent policy to use auction sales as a source of revenue 
early in the 18th century. For later similar acts see Act of May 20, 
1769, chapter 1392, and amendment of January 1, 1770, and Act of Feb- 
ruary 26, 1772, chapter 1516, and the Act of February 20, 1784, 7th session, 
chapter 4, and Act of April 2, 1801, chapter 116. 

*%8 Act of April 6, 1804, chapter 65; these rates were modified by the 
Act of April 6, 1813, chapter 70. 

4 Act of April 13, 1814, chapter 116. See note, page 171. 

165 Act of April 15, 1817, chapter 275. This 214% tax was a sort of 
license tax and was continued till 1843, even after the limitation on the 
number of auctioneers was removed in 1838, when it was no longer 
warranted. See Annual Report, Comptroller, N. Y., 843, p. 63; Act of 
February 28, 1838, chapter 52; and Act of April 8, 1843, chapter 86; 
Governor Van Buren criticised the monopolistic nature of auctioneers 
and recommended that the law be modified to allow every citizen who 
could give security for the duties to sell at auction by wholesale only, 
under license. Governors’ Messages, Vol. III, p. 246-7. 


a Cr 


| 
| 


State Legislation 201 


were devoted to the canal fund and to certain charities in New 
York City and were therefore tenaciously held to.*®° 

Despite the spirited campaign against auctions which arose 
after 1817, the New York Legislature was not moved to alter the 
Act of 1817 and make it more severe on auction sales. The 
pressure was for federal rather than State legislation, for the 
protection of manufactures was a national problem. Demands 
were, however, made that certain abuses of auctions be cor- 
rected.*°* The memorials of 1830-2 were closely considered by 
special select committees and investigations were made by the 
Comptroller.1°* The penal parts of the law were defective’® 
and were strengthened by specific provisions.**° It was not, 
however, until 1846 that auction duties were lowered.*™4 

The Pennsylvania auction laws were not much unlike those of 
New York.” The culminating law of the pre-national period 
limited the auctioneers to three for Philadelphia, fixed the bonds 
at £20,000, auction duties at 1%, and varying commission rates.1*° 
Later laws provided for auctioneers at Lancaster,’** Pittsburgh, 
and other cities.17* In 1821 the limitation on the number of 
auctioneers in Philadelphia was removed*** and special auction- 
eers for horses, cattle and carriages were provided. The classi- 
fication of auctioneers was further extended in 1822 with license 
fees and bonds varying with the kinds of goods handled.**s 


#6 N. Y. Senate Journal, 1829, p. 252; see amendment to State Consti- 
tution, 1835. For statistical statement of disposition, see Senate Document 
80 (1863), Vol. 5. 

#° See list in N. Y. Senate Document 44, Vol. I, p. 9. 

-*°N. Y. Assembly Document 381 (1830); Document 53 (1831), Vol. 
4; Senate Document 44 (1832), Vol. I, pp. 5, 28, 35. 

#°'N. Y. Governors’ Messages, III, p. 18. 

“OE. g., Act of 1835, chapter 62; Act of 1847, chapter 242; Act of 
1840, chapter 390. 

** Act of 1846, chapter 62. 

*“ For comprehensive detailed statement of the New York auction law 
as of 1840, see Hunt’s, II, 73-5. 

*8 Act of 1780, chapter 908. 

** Act of 1808, chapter 96. 

™ Act of 1814, chapter 178. 

™° Act of 1832, chapter 140. 

™ Act of 1821, chapter 161. 

8 Act of 1822, chapter 158. 


202 Early History of American Auctions 


Certain abuses were provided against in 1824'7? and the whole 
auction law was overhauled with respect to Philadelphia and 
Pittsburgh in 1842."*° No evidence appears in any of this legis- 
lation of an animus to the auction system; it too was wholly 
regulatory and fiscal in purpose. 

This summary of the legislation of two leading commercial 
States is illustrative of the legislative situation with respect to 
auctions. 


FEDERAL LEGISLATION. 


Until 1817 auctions received consideration by Congress as a 
source of revenue only. The question of the advisability of 
taxing auction sales was a part of the more general question 
between the Republicans and Democrats whether the government 
should depend upon internal revenue duties. Jefferson and 
Gallatin opposed the plan on the grounds that it contravened the 
principles of liberty and was inquisitorial, that it was injurious 
to the morals of the people, that industry was injured by it, that 
it invaded the rights of States, that it operated unequally in dif- 
ferent sections of the country, that it was unpopular and unwise 
politically, ete. Hamilton and the Federalists saw social, political 
and fiscal advantages in direct and internal revenue taxes. In 
1794 the House Committee proposed a tax of 1% on sales at 
auction and estimated a yield of $100,000.15! The act passed 
that year imposed duties of one-quarter of 1% on auction sales 
of real estate, farming implements and stock, ships and vessels, 
and of one-half of 1% on sales of all other “goods, chattels, 
rights, and credits.”” The auctioneers were to pay the duties, 
were licensed, put under bond, subjected to district supervision, 
and required to make reports to the Treasury; no licenses were 
granted in a state or town where that state or town provided for 
licensed auctioneers. The auctioneers were allowed 1% com- 
‘mission. The act was to be in operation two years, but it was 


™ Act of 1824, chapter 100. 

8° Act of 1842, chapter 90. New York prohibited the sale of stocks and 
bonds at auction, but Pennsylvania permitted such sales and subjected 
them to a duty of 114%, whereas the duty was 1%4% on all other sales 
except on real estate or shipping. 

81 Annals of Congress, 3d Congress, Ist session, p. 1307. 


Federal Legislation 203 


renewed in 1795 for six years, and in 1801 without limitation of 
time. The act was repealed in 1802 through the efforts of 
Randolph, Chairman of the Ways and Means Committee, as a 
party necessity primarily. The duty fell almost wholly on 
imported commodities; its productiveness depended largely upon 
the honesty of the auctioneers and false reporting was common.**? 
In 1795 it yielded $36,000 and in 1796, $43,000.1%° The duty 
was relatively easy to collect for it was confined practically to 
the chief towns and to few persons, but, on the other hand, it 
required the examination of the voluminous entries of the 
auctioneers.*** . 

Gallatin was forced by the adverse situation of the Treasury 
in 1812 to recommend a return to internal revenue duties, and 
among these a duty on auction sales of articles of foreign produce 
or manufacture and at the same rate as heretofore.***> The Ways 
and Means Committee in that year also recommended auction 
duties at rates of 2% on foreign merchandise and one-quarter of 
1% on vessels, with an estimated yield of $150,000.1°° In July, 
1813, was passed an act to go into effect January 1, 1814, for the 
duration of the war, at rates of 1% on merchandise and one- 
quarter of 1% on vessels.*** On December 23, 1814, the auction 
duty rates were doubled and the auction tax was put under gen- 
eral pledge to be kept in force till the public debt was paid or 
equal duties of other kinds substituted for the purpose’; and 
in December of the following year the Secretary of the Treasury 
recommended that the auction duty be continued without 
change.'®® In 1814 auction duties produced $155,000.1°° 

Efforts in the second session of the 14th Congress (1816) to 
repeal the internal revenue duties were unavailing. In December, 


182 


Bolles, I, 113; Dewey, 108. 

** Annals of Congress, 5th Congress, Ist session, Vol. III, p. 3582. 

**Thid., 3591. See Report of Committee on Ways and Means, Dec. 
12, 1817, for expenses of collecting internal revenues. 

**° Annals of Congress, 12th Congress, Ist session, Pt. I, p. 854. 

7° Tbid., 1050. 

*7 Thid., 13th Congress, Volume II, p. 2728. 

18 Tbid., Volume III, p. 1852. 

*° Tbid., 14th Congress, Ist session, p. 1637. 

® Niles, 20: 355. See Niles, 7: 331, for portions paid by the different 
states. 


204 Early History of American Auctions 


1817, ona bill to repeal all internal revenue duties, Mr. Tallmadge 
of New York moved to except the auction duties, arguing that 
they had a beneficial operation as imposing an additional burden 
on foreign products, protecting the fair dealer, and encouraging 
our manufactures.'*t Obviously, protectionism made its début 
into the auction system. This proposal was debated and lost; 
Mr. Smith of Maryland, while favoring prohibitory auction duties 
on certain articles, particularly dry goods, held that that matter 
ought to be taken up on its own footing’®?; Chairman Lowndes 
of the Ways and Means Committee saw no decisive injury and 
considerable benefits from auctions’®*; he was supported in this 
view by Mr. Clay of Kentucky.4%* Mr. Whitman of Massachu- 
setts would support the Tallmadge resolution if it were possible 
to discriminate among cities, in commercial depots the tax was 
desirable but in smaller seaports and towns it bore “almost with- 
out exception, on the necessitous and poor.’’*®® Others argued 
that the cost of collection of the tax, if retained alone, would 
absorb the whole tax.1°° The act to repeal all internal duties 
passed by overwhelming vote and became effective January I, 
1818. The Secretary of the Treasury in his report on the revision 
of the revenue laws issued that day made no mention of the pro- 
posal about auction taxes and the matter seemed definitely closed. 

The protectionists brought three bills before Congress in 1820, 
one for a prohibitory tax on auctions, one for abolition or restric- 
tion of customs credits, and one for higher import duties.1°* The 
reasons for the precipitation of the tariff problem in 1817 and 
following years have been explained above. The auction bill was 
presented by Mr. Baldwin of Connecticut, Chairman of the House 
Committee on Manufactures. It proposed a tax of 10% on 
auction sales of a long list of enumerated foreign manufactures 
that competed with American manufactures, 2% on foreign 
grown or manufactured products not enumerated, 1% on Ameri- 
can manufactures, and 5% extra if sold in other than their 


1 Annals of Congress, 15th Congress, Ist session, p. 420. 
1% Tbid., 427. 

#8 Ibid., 428. 

== Noiily Cp 

1% Tbid., 426. 

* Tbhid., 427. 

17 Niles, 17: 361; 18: 160; 24: 104 


ait 


| 
? 
q 
| 
} 
} 


Federal Legislation 205 


original packages.1°* The bill had two purposes—to produce 
revenue and to protect American industry. Mr. Baldwin did not 


. think the 10% rate prohibitory, but the generality proposed that 


it should be nearly so.1*® Some objected to the rates, not because 
they were prohibitory, but because they would work too partially 
or would be evaded.?°° 

The introduction of this bill had been in response to a flood 
of petitions and memorials that had been pouring into Congress 
from the commercial cities during the early months of 1820.7°1 
This bill was said to be “imperiously called for—by at least nine- 
tenths of the merchants of New York, Philadelphia, and Balti- 
more.”?°? It was debated for several days, but, along with the 
other two bills, failed to pass, and action on the amended bill was 
postponed until next session.*°* One of the most objectionable 
features was that the federal taxes, in themselves prohibitory, 
together with the existing State taxes, would destroy the auctions 
which were a productive source of revenue to certain States, 
notably New York.*°* There was also considerable division of 
opinion on the whole subject.?°? At the next session of Congress 
petitions were presented by both auctioneers and opponents? ; 
the bill was debated a whole day in committee of the whole and 
amended, but a motion then to consider it in the House was lost.?°7 

Another auction bill was presented in 1824 by the Committee 
on Manufactures.?°* This was in conjunction with the pressure 
for tariff legislation that year. Congress was again much memo- 
rialized on the subject of auctions.2°° This bill proposed 714% 
duties on sales whether of foreign or domestic growth, and 214% 


** Annals of Congress, 16th Congress, Ist session, p. 2173. 

*® Tbid., 2176; Niles, 18: 420. 

me alinitien 2475-0; 

*™ Note the presentations of petitions mentioned in Annals of Congress, 
16th Congress, Ist session, pp. 78, 367, 374, 430, 454, 509; and in Niles, 18: 
127, 148, 166, 160. 

* Niles, 18: 422. 

** For legislative history of the bill see Niles, 18: 169, 183, 185. 

* Niles, 18: 185, 420; 27: 258, 300. 

*° Niles, 21: 103, gives reasons for failure of the legislation. 

*° Annals of Congress, 16th Congress, 2d session, 142. 

*% Thid., 864, 1227. 

*8 Ibid., 18th Congress, Ist session, p. 1308. 

™ Tbid., 123, 775, 931, 1398; 3128; Niles, 25: 275, 280, 337. 


206 Early History of American Auctions 


extra when the original packages were broken.*!? No action was 
taken by Congress. 

The campaign reached a high pitch of intensity in 1828 along 
with the tariff legislation then engaging Congress. Memorialists 
said that “the effects of the auction system as detailed in memo- 
rials—in 1817, 1818, and again in 1824,” had “increased in an 
alarming degree” and might “now be denominated a national 
evil.’’*"_ “Above fifty memorials, from almost every state,” were 
received at Washington’? and it was confidently expected that 
Congress would act.*™ 

A monster petition with 10,000 names was sent by New York?" 
and a great anti-auction meeting was held and resolutions adopted 
and sent.?!°" From this date political pressure was openly brought 
on Congressmen ; a meeting of mechanics in New York nominated 
an anti-auction ticket for Congress; this ticket was indorsed by 
a meeting of the merchants’ clerks.2"* Mr. McDuffie wrote a 
letter to the New York Evening Post explaining that the New 
York resolution and petition came too late for legislative action 
and thus he hoped to defend Mr. Verplanck, Congressman from 
New York, from inaction or ineffectiveness.*4* In the wards 
of the city where the commercial and trading classes principally 
resided the anti-auction candidates carried the election.** 

Meanwhile an inter-city movement was organized, committees 
were appointed to cooperate with similar committees of other 
cities and to push the propaganda.**® Mass meetings were held 
at Philadelphia, Baltimore, and other cities.**° Petitions poured 
in from widely separate cities, as Buffalo, N. Y., Norwich, Conn., 
Northampton, Mass., Lynchburg, Va., Nashville, Tenn., Hart- 


TONES. 25ies ye 

* Niles, 34: 140. 

* Niles, 38: 185. 

*8 Niles, 35: 241. 

*“ Niles, 35: 255. 

18 Niles, 34: 174, gives the resolutions. 

*% Niles, 34: 188. 

“Niles 935s) DIO} 120, 00472 

Niles, 36: 185. 

"1° Niles, 34: 349-50. See report of activities of the anti-auction com- 
mittee in Niles, 36: 184. 

*” Niles, 35: 2009, 228-9. 


Federal Legislation 207 


ford, Conn., Pittsford, N. Y., Edenton, N. C., New Haven 
and New London, Conn., Pittsburgh, Pa., Providence, R. I., 
Montpelier, Vt., Wheeling, W. Va., etc.??* 

In January, 1829, the Ways and Means Committee made a 
report”*? on auctions and accompanied it with a bill. It prohibited 
sales by auction unless the auctioneer at the time of sale exhibited 
the original invoice on which the duties had been levied at the 
custom house. It required the auctioneer to publish in one or 
more newspapers of the city wherein the auction was held forty- 
eight hours immediately before the sale, schedules of the goods, 
name of the importer or consignee, detailed description of the 
goods and their marks, name of vessel by which they were 
imported and the time of their importation, and such schedules 
were also to be exhibited at the time and place of sale. It fixed 
as penalties for violation one-third of the value of the mer- 
chandise sold; but if the auctioneer knew the goods were 
smuggled, the penalty was full value; one-half of the penalty 
was to go to the informer or prosecutor. It did not apply to 
auctions of deceased persons’ property, to sheriffs’ sales, to 
re-sales by auction of goods once bona fide so sold, to tariff-free 
goods, and to sales of the stock of goods of any retailer or trader. 
It was designed merely to protect the revenue from frauds, and 
the Committee explained that Congress had no powers to act 
upon the subject except in that capacity; and that a tax upon 
auction sales would neither prevent the alleged frauds upon the 
revenue, nor the alleged advantages enjoyed by foreigners, unless 
it be a prohibitory tax; and that for whatever frauds were com- 
mitted upon the community through auctions the application of 
the remedy belonged exclusively to the state legislatures.??? This 
bill was very unsatisfactory to the anti-auctionists. Meanwhile 
Mr. Johnson of New York presented a substitute bill as drafted 
by the anti-auction committee of that city, containing added pro- 
visions against fictitious bidding, for continuing the auctioneer’s 
responsibility for frauds, errors or deficiencies during seven days 
allowed for examination after sale, and for a schedule of duties 


eI MES 3421377-84" 353 271: 

* Niles, 35: 341-2, gives the text of the report and bill. Mr. McDuffie 
was chairman. 

3 Tbid., 329, 342. 


208 Early History of American Auctions 


on auction sales. The rates of duty ranged from $2.50 to $5.00, 
depending upon whether the goods were foreign or domestic and 
upon the value of the parcel.*** 

Neither bill was acted upon. The short session of Congress 
and the disinclination to act upon any important subject till the 
new President was installed, were the reasons alleged for the 
default.**° But the campaign continued. A larger mass meeting 
than ever was held in New York and a memorial to Congress 
was drawn up praying for a resumption of the consideration of 
the auction bill of the last session.**° The response, however, 
was that the Ways and Means Committee brought forward the 
Ingersoll bill, which was the 1829 bill in all essentials.*** Thus 
all efforts to procure help from Congress against auctions failed. 

Within the next decade auctions ceased to play as important 
role relatively, and became less offensive. There were several 
reasons for this. Steam navigation brought together the agents 
of foreign commission houses and the jobbers of this country 
and the inducements for a speculative and uncertain market 
were lessened. The introduction of the bond and warehouse 
system enabled importers to hold their surplus stocks from auction 
until the market could absorb them in the regular mode of 
private sales. Many articles which were formerly sold largely 
at auction either ceased to be imported on account of our rising 
manufactures or for other reasons, or came to be largely sold 
through brokers.* It seems that the auction duties proved 
prohibitive in case of certain commodities, and these were 
increasingly sold through brokers.*° By 1844, at least, the anti- 
auction war had passed and the era of peace prevailed.?*° 


=4 Thid., 380. 

25 Niles; 36: 185. 

2S Niles a7) 303: 

#1 Niles, 37: -422. 

“8 N, Y. Assembly Document (1849) 218, Vol. V, p. 8. 
2° N. Y. Assembly Document 25 (1846), p. 44-5. 
Edit SLO: TSA. 


INDEX 


Advances made by auctioneer to foreign principal, 179. 

Advantages of auctions to English manufacturer, cost of marketing re- 
duced, 180; customs credits provided capital, 179; defeated American 
manufactures (see Dumping) ; ready cash market provided, 179-80. 

Auctioneers, advances made against consignments, 179; business profits, 
176-8; classification in Pennsylvania, 201-2; commission rates, 176-7 
202; concentration of business, 177-8; importance in local affairs, 
176-7; personnel, 177-8. 

Boycott of auctioneers, 198-9. 

Campaign against auctions, by boycott, 198-9; decline after 1830, 208; 
federal legislation, 202-8 (see Legislation); protection becomes a 
factor, 203-4; publicity campaign, 198-9; state legislation, 199-202; 
taxes in New York, 199-201; taxes in Pennsylvania, 201-2. 

Catalogues issued, 174-5. 

Concentration of auction sales in few cities, 195. 

Conduct of auction sales, 173-7 

Credit allowed, 176. 

Customs credits, acts of 1789, 1794, 1795, 186; acts of 1799, 1805, 1818, 186; 
failure of bill of 1820, 187; act of 1832, 187-8; caused excessive im- 
portations, 190; credits allowed, 186; defeated the tariff, 189-90; 
effects, 188-9; favored the British, 189-90; legislation, 186-8; losses of 
revenue, 190; objections and criticisms, 189-91; relation to auction 
problem, 190-1; term of credits, 188; theory of customs credits, 188; 
were really a loan to importer, 188-9. 

Decline, reasons for, 208. 

Display and inspection, 175. 

Dumping of English wares, effects, 167-8; in 1816, 165-8; in 1823, 168; 
kinds of merchandise, 166-8; occasioned call for protection, 169-70. 
Duties on auction sales, cause increase of goods subject to ad valorem 
duties, 193; federal act of 1794, 202; of 1814-6, 203-4; of 1820, 204-5; 

of 1824, 205-6; of 1829, 207-8; paid in New York, 171-3, 178-9. 

Effects of auctions, changes commercial methods, 181-2; introduced new 
lines of goods, 181-2; lowered prices, 182-3; on interior merchant 
operations, 184-5; on retailers, 185; on status of jobbers and mer- 
chant importers, 183-4, 184-5 

Embargo occasioned use of auctions, 164-5. 

Foreign account, imports on, 179; relative proportion on, 180-1. 

Foreign agents, activities of, 179; advantages to foreign manufacturers 
and exporters from using, 179-80. 

Jobbers adversely affected, 183-4, 184-6, 193-4. 

Legislation, act of 1794, 202; acts of 1812-16, 203-4; repeal of these acts, 
1818, 203-4; efforts at legislation in 1820, 205-6; in 1824, 205-6; in 
1828, 206-7; in 1829, 207; federal legislation, 202-8; legislation in 
New York, 199-201; in Pennsylvania, 201-2. 


210 Early History of American Auctions 


Methods, advances allowed to principals by auctioneers on consignments, 
179; catalogues issued, 174-5; conditions and terms of sale, 175-6; 
conduct of sales at auction, 173-6; credit allowed to buyers, 176; dis- 
play and inspection, 175-6; piece sales, 174-6; sale of package goods, 
175-6; system of dumping, 167-8, 173-4. 

Monopolistic, 178-9, 194-5. 

Morals lowered by auction methods, 194, 197-8. 

Objections to auctions, caused export of money, 196; caused poorer quality 
of goods, 196-7; concentrated trade in a few large cities, 195; dis- 
turbed the stability of commerce and industry, 196; encouraged dis- 
honest practices and frauds, 144; gave less support to the home city, 
195; hurt importers and jobbers, 143-4; introduced bad business prac- 
tices, 198; lowered the morality of business, 197-8; made trade monop- 
olistic, 194-5. 

Origin of auctions, before 1816, 164; in the colonies, 164; in early New 
York, 173; origin of protectionists’ hostility, 203-4. 

Package goods, methods of sale of, 175-6. 

Petitions (memorials) to Congress, in 1820, 205; in 1824, 206; in 1828, 
206-7; in 1829, 207. 

Piece sales, method of, 174-6. 

Publicity, hostile campaign against auctions, 198-9. 

Quality of goods lowered, 196-7; new goods introduced, 181. 

Tariff, attitude of American import merchants, 170; auctions become a 
factor in tariff legislation, 203-4; efforts of protectionists in Congress 
(see Legislation) ; protectionists become anti-auctionists, 169; pro- 
tective tariff defeated by auctions, 169, 193. 

Terms of sale, 175-6. 

Undervaluation of imports, cause larger proportion of imports to be of 
those subject to ad valorem duties, 193; act of 1832, 193; evasions of 
duties more common in case of goods on foreign account, 192-3; sys- 
tem of valuation used, I91; various evasions of customs duties, IgI-2. 

Volume of sales, based on auction duties of New York, 170-3; concentra- 
tion in New York City, 172; estimates of contemporaries, 170-1; 
sources of data, 170-I. 

War of 1812 occasioned use of auctions, 164-6. 


TRANSACTIONS OF 
rae CONNECTICUT ACADEMY 
OF ARTS AND SCIENCES 


VOLUME 23] JUNE 1920 [PAGES 211-241 


Russia’s Contribution 
to Science 


BY 


ALEXANDER PETRUNKEVITCH, Ph.D. 


Professor of Zoology in Yale University. 


NEW HAVEN, CONNECTICUT 
PUBLISHED BY THE 
CONNECTICUT ACADEMY OF ARTS AND SCIENCES 
AND TO BE OBTAINED ALSO FROM THE 
YALE UNIVERSITY PRESS 


ee ok 


ae Phe yi af 
2 enya ie im 


ree trea > ee 


‘ 
‘ he 
3 4nd 
( 
2 ho 
7 
> 
7b 
an 
§ i 
> 
ec 
tr 
ss - ) 5 
4 
‘ 
be 2 
. 
f 
! 
= eS 
i > 
. a. 
i 
+ ate _ = 
= ~ 
ri 
J é 
‘ 
eo 
’ * J : + ce 
> J tine Te oa 7i3 {MHtTAGS 
¥ ’ s A 
° i ; ' Z 
: ae Si iATaS eh mer 
‘ s Bi 
ie 
a 
¢ 
_ 
‘ * 
; 
‘ 
4 * 


OE — —— 


int 


RUSSIA’S: CONTRIBUTION TO SCIENCE 


While Russian literature, Russian music, Russian art and 
Russian dance are fairly well known to the American people, 
few realize the extent of Russia’s contribution to science. This 
is quite pardonable considering the lack of knowledge on the 
part of the broad public of the ever growing achievements of 
exact science in all its branches, regardless of nationality, and 
taking into account also the difficulty of even casual acquaint- 
ance with subjects which require special training. To this must 
be added that a great deal of the work published by Russian 
scientists has been written in foreign languages, mostly in Ger- 
man and French periodical publications, while Russian publi- 
cations are few and of these only one or two are known to 
foreigners. 

In Russia itself education in general and science in particular 
has been for a long time unpopular, has been limited to a com- 
paratively small circle of people and has even at the present time 
not yet penetrated into the broader masses. Purely clerical 
knowledge of the Tsarist Russia gave way to military training 
and to such education as was necessary for service in the bureau- 
cratic institutions created by Peter the Great. Later humanistic 
studies and law became the standard of good education and 
dominated Russian society and Russian thought until compara- 
tively recently. Medicine of course was early recognized as 
necessary knowledge, yet the people regarded it in the light of 
special knowledge rather detrimental to broad education. Ap- 
plied science, such as engineering, was for a long time looked 
upon in the same way with the additional stigma of mistrust. 
Pure science has been looked upon rather as a hobby for men 
with sufficient means, dangerous in as far as it inclined to pro- 
duce a critical attitude toward religion and the established order 
of things, undesirable inasmuch as it did not open any other 
field for activity than an academic career, and insufficient as a 
general basis for broad education. Yet in the second half of 
the past century pure science came into its own, conquered the 
opposition of society and furnished many a name looked upon 
with esteem and even admiration in Russia and far beyond its. 
political frontiers. 


214 Alexander Petrunkevitch, Ph.D., 


To say that Russia might have produced a great deal more in 
the field of science than it actually has produced, had the de- 
velopment of the country been allowed to proceed normally, is 
not a mere figure of speech or an excuse, an attempt as it were 
to find extenuating circumstances for natural shortcomings. In 
a country where the word “constitution” was struck by the 
censor even from the pages of learned investigations, where the 
chief duty of the Secretary of Education was to devise means 
to prevent the spreading of knowledge, creative work in science 
was more than simply hampered, it was often physically impos- 
sible. Yet a glance at a list of works published by Russian 
scientists will show the productivity and many-sidedness of the 
Russian genius. There is scarcely a field of science in which 
Russians have not done some creditable work, increased the 
store of our knowledge, cleared up some intricate problem or 
opened new chapters and set forth new questions. 

And all this had to be done in the face of great difficulties of 
which western institutions have no idea. There was always a 
lack of funds and a lack of men, a lack of institutions and a 
lack of young men to be trained for such institutions. The 
educational system was borrowed from Germany, its negative 
qualities were intensified while the most important positive quali- 
ties were partially or completely suppressed. The Russian 
national character was not taken into account by that system 
foreign to its spirit which was put as it were into a straight- 
jacket and had its wings clipped by two most efficient tools in 
the hands of autocracy—censorship and espionage. Used per- 
sistently with only occasional short intermissions, during more 
than one century, and embracing all phases of national and private 
life, being constantly present in all university recitation halls, 
laboratories and even private offices, censorship and espionage 
ruined the relationship between teacher and pupil, affected the 
character of the institutions and prevented the normal develop- 
ment of many a promising youth. 

To understand the ruinous influence of espionage and censor- ° 
ship on national character and the productive genius of the 
people one must have grown up and gone through the schools 
in Russia. The offices of inspector and his aids in every second- 
ary school were especially created to control not only the be- 
havior of pupils in the school, but their life outside of school 


Russia's Contribution to Science. 215 


walls. The teachers themselves were subject to this supervision 
and dreaded the never-closing Argus eye of the inspector. The 
duties imposed on them, the general atmosphere of life amidst 
poverty, suspicion, bribery, and Simonism, prevented the teachers 
of secondary schools from doing original work of any character. 
Such work, not uncommon in Germany, is of the rarest occur- 
rence in Russia and only teachers of quite remarkable ability 
managed to step out of the high-school routine and drudgery 
into the broader field of an academic career. The Russian 
“Gymnasia,” the Russian ‘Realnoje Utchilishtche” were pat- 
terned after the German “Gymnasium” and “Realschule” but 
the spirit of reactionary orthodox Russian autocracy was added 
to the German worship of authority and discipline of mind and 
will, and coupled with corruption, pervaded everything and cor- 
rupted and perverted the growing mind. It is a wonder under 
the circumstances that the mind, the spirit of Russian youth 
was not completely crushed in its instinctive upward struggling 
for light and knowledge and free expression of self. 

The entrance into the sacred precincts of the highest educa- 
tion was purposely made difficult to prevent an undesirable 
growth of knowledge in wider circles. Only pupils who had 
studied in a gymnasium and had therefore had seven years of 
Latin and six years of Greek and who passed the examinations 
at the end of their studies extending altogether over eight years, 
had the. right to study at a university. Yet it may not be quite 
out of place to mention here that a boy entering the university 
in Russia knows no more of mathematics than a high-school 
boy in America and knows even less of physics and chemistry, 
while biology was not on the program of studies at all. 

One was allowed to postpone military training until after the 
studies at the university had been finished, and in the cases of 
men preparing for an academic career military training was alto- 
gether waived. This exemption applied both to those who became 
teachers at schools and professors at universities. But the re- 
quirements for professorial positions were so high, as we shall 
see later, that the exemption from military training was in no 
sense an inducement. 

On entering the university the student had to follow a pre- 
scribed course of studies through all four years, but could and 
was expected to take also other courses, provided they did not 


216 Alexander Petrunkevitch, Ph.D., 


coincide with the obligatory ones. A course in theology, i. e., 
in the dogma of the Russian orthodox church, was compulsory 
for every student in the first year of his studies. Compared 
with the American colleges the work at the Russian universities 
is much heavier, the number of hours is considerably greater 
and the number of subjects required cover a much wider range. 
It was customary to work Saturday afternoon and some classes 
were given even on Sunday mornings, as for example entomology 
at the University of Moscow at the time that I was studying 
there. To give an idea of the scope of studies required at a 
Russian university from a student in natural sciences preparing 
for an academic degree, I shall simply enumerate the subjects 
which I myself had to study in Moscow: Physics (four hours 
per week during two years); inorganic chemistry (first year) ; 
qualitative analysis and quantitative analysis (second year) ; or- 
ganic chemistry (third year); physical geography (one year) ; 
geology and paleontology (one year); mineralogy and crystal- 
lography (one year); meteorology (one year); human anatomy 
(one year); physiology (one year); histology and embryology 
(one year); introduction to zoology (one year); invertebrate 
zoology (one year); vertebrate zoology (one year) ; entomology 
(one year); botany (three years) (including general morphol- 
ogy, anatomy, physiology and systematics) and theology (one 
year). In the first and second year the spare hours were given to 
economics and principles of law. During the last term of the 
fourth year a thesis has to be written on a subject assigned by the 
professor, consisting of a review of work done by other workers 
and some original investigation. After a six-hour written 
examination on some subject in the department of study chosen 
by the student and after oral examinations in all subjects studied 
during the third and fourth year, those studied during the first 
and second year having been disposed of previously, the student 
receives a university diploma conferring on him the degree of 
Candidat rerum naturalium, which as may readily be seen is a 
much higher degree than either the corresponding degree of the 
German universities, or the B.A. of American colleges. It will 
be also seen from the foregoing that the training of a Russian 
student at the end of his studies is in every respect broader and 
covers a much wider range of subjects than either that of an 
American or a German student. 


Russia's Contribution to Science. 217 


Students with exceptionally high standing, who desire to 
follow an academic career, are allowed to continue their studies 
at the university after they have received their degree. They 
have no more lectures to attend, but receive a general outline 
of reading and work to be done as a preparation for an examina- 
tion which will give them the right to present a thesis for the 
degree of Magister in the subject which they have chosen, i. e., 
Magister of Chemistry, Magister of Botany, etc. This examina- 
tion may under no circumstances take place sooner than two 
years after the examination for the degree of Candidat. It is 
one of the stiffest examinations imaginable and the amount of 
reading required is simply appalling. To give even an approxi- 
mate idea of the ground which has to be covered by the candi- 
date during these two years, I shall only mention that in my 
own case the books recommended to me by my professor occupied 
more than a five foot shelf and contained such works as Bronn’s 
Classen und Ordnungen and similar works, all of which were 
supposed to be used not as reference books but as text books 
and the detailed information contained in them to be kept in 
one’s memory ready to be drawn upon at a moment’s notice. 
It has happened time and again that candidates were flunked 
because they were unable to produce from memory facts which 
the examining professor himself knew only because he was 
recently engaged in research on the subject. 

After the successful passing of this examination the candidate 

receives the title of Magistrant and is admitted to lecturing and 
laboratory work in the capacity of a privat-dozent, a title also 
borrowed from the Germans. At the same time he must present 
his thesis for public discussion before he receives the degree of 
Magister. This dissertation has to be the result of an original 
investigation and to cover the ground thoroughly. It has to 
review the literature of the subject as far back as possible, in 
some cases going actually back to Aristotle. The public defense 
is no sinecure, for the officially appointed opponents take especial 
pleasure in tearing the arguments and evidence to pieces and 
in pointing out the slightest flaw in the treatment of the problem. 

If the degree has been awarded the holder of it may now be 
appointed “extraordinary professor.” Within not less than two 
years nor more than ten he has to present a second dissertation 
for the highest degree attainable, that of Doctor, not Doctor of 


218 Alexander Petrunkevitch, Ph.D., 


Philosophy as in Germany or America, but Doctor of the special 
science which he has chosen. The degree of Doctor of Philos- 
ophy in the American sense of the term does not exist in Russia, 
and whenever a professor is in possession of a Russian degree 
of Doctor of Philosophy, that means that he is a specialist in 
philosophy. 

It will be seen that it is utterly impossible for a Russian to 
possess more than one degree of Doctor, unless it be an honorary 
degree which is scarcely ever given. The only exception is the 
degree of Doctor of Medicine, which strange to relate, does not 
need to be preceded by a Magister degree, is often given for 
some quite unimportant and small piece of work and comes near- 
est to the German M.D., especially since it has to follow upon 
an examination without which practice is not allowed. But the 
training of the medical student in Russia is also vastly broader 
than in the United States and the scope of knowledge possessed 
by the average Russian practicing physician has often been a 
subject of admiration to foreigners. 

But the amount of work required of those who prepare for 
an academic career has also its negative side. Memory is easily 
overburdened with unnecessary details, much valuable time is 
lost in gathering the knowledge required for the examinations, 
and perhaps still more in reading and reviewing the work done 
by others, which in the majority of cases has long ago lost all 
scientific value and in many cases might have been better for- 
gotten altogether. What with the academic duties of lecturing, 
laboratory work, committees, etc., the creative ability is easily 
stunted and unfortunately it is not an uncommon occurrence that 
the dissertation for the Doctor’s degree is the last original work 
of the overburdened professor. Only the more talented and 
more pertinacious hold out under the strain and continue as inves- 
tigators. 

And all the time the outside life invades the peaceful premises 
of the university and asserts itself in the most uncompromising 
manner. Neither the Russian student, nor the Russian professor 
can avoid its influence. Censorship and espionage are more 
developed and stricter in the university than elsewhere and it 
seems that in this respect the renowned Bolshevik reformers and 
heralds of educational freedom for the poorest citizen, have far 
outdone the old Tsarist advocates of the muzzle and whip. But 


Russia’s Contribution to Science. 219 


censorship and espionage notwithstanding, the professor and 
student alike have to possess a distinct reputation as belonging 
either to the progressive or to the reactionary political group, 
and no liberal minded assistant may continue indefinitely to assist 
a reactionary professor. He has ultimately either to ally himself 
definitely with the reactionary elements or to resign. Asa general 
rule we may say that the best work was done by progressive 
professors, although some very reactionary men have contributed 
creditable work in their particular field of learning. But real 
expression of political views was not possible except for a short 
period in the sixties and again after the revolution of 1905, and 
even then it had to be sufficiently guarded. 

The first scientific institution created in Russia was the Im- 
perial Academy of Sciences and its foundation was due to the 
genius of Peter the Great who conceived the idea and had con- 
ferences regarding its execution with Heinrich Fick as early 
as 1718. Dr. Blumenrost prepared a project which was approved 
by Peter in 1724 and according to which the Academy should 
be not only a research, but also an educational institution. Peter 
died in 1725 and it was his widow Catherine the First who 
ordered the opening of the Academy on November 12, 1725, and 
fixed its yearly budget at 24012.00 Roubles. Foreigners, mostly 
Germans, were invited as professors. About the year 1727 there 
were seventeen of these including such men as Hermann, and 
Goldbach in mathematics, Nicholas Bernulli in mechanics, Buer- 
ger in chemistry, Biefinger in physics, Duvernoie in anatomy and 
zoology, Leonhard Euler in mathematics, etc. The eight stu- 
dents who had to study with these professors were all Germans, 
all imported for the purpose from Germany. By the year 1742 
there were as many as twelve students. In 1747 the Academy 
was divided into two sections—the Academy proper, and the 
University. The internal organization of the Academy was 
changed in 1803 and again in 1836 and in 1841, when it was sub- 
divided into three sections. The Memoirs of the Academy are 
so well-known and contain so many important articles in all 
branches of science that we do not need to consider them here 
further. 

The Academic University died a natural death through lack 
of students and the first Russian university must be considered 
to be the University of Moscow which was opened in 1754, and 


220 Alexander Petrunkevitch, Ph.D., 


had as many as one hundred students in 1758. In 1804 a con- 
stitution was adopted, framed on German model by W. N. 
Karasin. This constitution recognized the autonomy of the 
university and was extended to the newly founded universities 
in St. Petersburg, Kazan, Kharkov, Vilno and Dorpat. In 1830 
the University of Vilno was abolished and that of Kiev opened. 
In 1835, however, the constitution was modified. The number 
of students was limited, and the Government appointed special 
curators to control university affairs. The last traces of aca- 
demic freedom were obliterated in 1849 when the new constitu- 
tion framed by Prince Shirinsky-Shikhmatoff was introduced into 
all universities. All executive officers and all professors were 
from now on appointed and not elected and “harmful” sciences, 
such as constitutional law, were forbidden. The liberating and 
progressive movement at the beginning of the sixties brought 
with it a change in the universities also. A new constitution 
prepared by Golovin restored academic freedom, but only for a 
short period. In 1866 Count Dmitri Tolstoy was appointed 
Secretary of Public Instruction and began immediately to in- 
terfere with the work of the universities by means of special 
decrees. A constitution prepared in accordance with his sug- 
gestions was introduced in 1884, when Delyanoff was Secretary, 
and from now on until the revolution of Ig05 the universities 
were entirely under the strictest control of the government. A 
short breathing space after the revolution, then oppression worse 
than before; then again a sudden wonderful efflorescence of free- 
dom in 1917 and now almost complete ruin under the Bolsheviki! 

Such is the sad history of the Russian universities which 
played such a glorious role in developing Russian youth, in com- 
bating reaction based on ignorance and avarice and in contribut- 
ing through the patient work of their professors to the store of 
human knowledge. Only a century of existence, a century of 
martyrdom! During that time many thousands of students were 
never allowed to finish their education, some banished to Siberia, 
others imprisoned, many killed. And during that time many 
professors were removed from office, banished, censured, im- 
prisoned, broken in spirit. And in the aftermath of the revolu- 
tion some of the best among them have died of starvation, others 
have been executed and all execrated as enemies of the proletariat. 

Yet even in the darkest hours and years of reaction the uni- 


P2024 


Russia's Contribution to Science. 221 


versities continued their work in science. Every university has 
its own publications in the shape of transactions or proceedings, 
or of similar publications of societies organized by the univer- 
sities. Especially well known are the publications of the St. 
Petersburg Mineralogical Society, of the St. Petersburg Society 
of Naturalists, of the Moscow Society of Naturalists and of the 
Moscow Friends of Natural Sciences, Anthropology and Ethnog- 
raphy. But, other publications, such as the Proceedings of the 
Society of Naturalists of Kazan, founded in 1869, and those of 
the corresponding society of Kiev, also founded in 1869, and of 
Kharkov contain many valuable and important articles. Men 
who studied at universities but who were forced by circumstances 
to live in cities which had no university or other higher educa- 
tional institution, founded small scientific societies, little local 
museums, as the Society of Naturalists in Ecaterinburg, which 
publishes its own proceedings, another similar society in Saratov, 
again one in Tiflis, an anthropological and _ ethnographical 
museum in Twer and so on. The foreigners can have scarcely 
any idea as to how much all these publications contain of material 
referring to local fauna, local flora, local ethnography, etc. The 
various Governmental Departments have been also publishing 
many important contributions to our knowledge both in pure and 
applied sciences, geological, mineralogical, entomological investi- 
gations. Reviews of Russian contributions to the various 
branches of science have been printed from time to time, such as 
Anatoli Bogdanoff’s “Materials for the History of Pure and 
Applied Zoology and of Allied Branches of Knowledge in Russia,” 
1850; Sabaneeff’s “List of books and papers on hunting and 
nature study,’ 1883; G. A. Kojewnikoff’s “Reports about Rus- 
sian Zoological Literature,” 1893, etc., but the special work 
which was in preparation when the revolution disrupted all uni- 
versity work in Russia and which was to embrace all branches 
of science in a way similar to the volume dealing with human- 
istic sciences, has been interrupted by the upheaval and may have 
been lost. 

The physical conditions of the country, the climate, the his- 
torical development, the political oppression, the economic back- 
wardness, the general stagnation and hopelessness of life have 
moulded the Russian national character to a form differing from 
that of other nationalities. And as the Frenchman is different 


222 Alexander Petrunkevitch, Ph.D., 


from the Englishman not in language and nationality alone, but 
in all qualities of mind as well, so the national character may be 
traced, broadly speaking, not only in the sphere of politics, trade 
or business, but also in other branches of mental activity. If 
the average quality of the German scientist is heavy thorough- 
ness, that of the Frenchman clearness and lucidity of thought 
combined with an impulse to treat science as art, that of the 
British extraordinary positivity and that of the American an 
ability to combine specialization with mass production, then the 
distinctive character of the Russian may be seen in the restless- 
ness of his spirit and the striving to embrace a wide field .of 
knowledge, to find answers to questions which are ever present 
in his thoughts and which once raised may not be lightly put 
aside, but must be settled the one way or the other, if only for the 
satisfaction of his own soul. 

These qualities have been manifested already by the father of 
Russian science, Michail Vassilievitch Lomonossoff, who came of 
peasant stock and gradually rose to the distinction of being the 
foremost man of science and letters in Russia. He was born 
in I71I ina small village of the Government of Archangel in the 
dreary north, far from any civilization. He learned reading 
with the aid of books given him by some villagers who took 
interest in him and when 19 years old, in 1730, went to Moscow 
to study at the so-called Slavo-Latin Academy. Here he spent 
five years, living in poverty and studying with grim determina- 
tion amidst boys many years his juniors, who laughed at the big, 
ignorant fellow. A glimpse of this period may be gained from 
Lomonossoff’s letter to Shuvaloff written in 1753. “With an 
allowance of three pennies (altyn) a day, I was not able to spend 
more than a penny for bread, a penny for kvas (a Russian bever- 
age) and a penny for paper, footwear and other necessaries. 
Thus I lived during five years, yet I did not give up my studies.” 
From Moscow Lomonossofft went to Germany where he studied 
mathematics, physics and philosophy with Wolff, chemistry and 
metallurgy with Henkel. He spent five years in Germany and 
returned to Russia in 1741. The following year Empress Eliza- 
beth appointed him Adjunct in Physics to the Imperial Academy. 
In 1745 he was appointed Professor of Chemistry in the Aca- 
demic University the foundation of which was due mostly to his 
influence. There he created the first Russian Chemical Labora- 


Russia’s Contribution to Science. 223 


tory in 1748 and in 1756 was the first to explain what we now 
understand as oxydation by converting tin into stannic oxyde, 
antedating the work of Lavoisier on a similar subject by 18 years. 
Lomonossoff was one of the pioneers in work on atmospheric 
electricity and shares with Franklin the honor of the discovery of 
the lightning rod. He made the suggestion that electricity is 
responsible for the aurora borealis. In astronomy he was the 
first to discover the presence of an atmosphere around the planet 
Venus. He elucidated the nature of amber as balsam of extinct 
vegetation. He taught that anthracite originated from peat. 
All this was done at a time when science was looked upon as 
almost of the Devil by the Russian Church and in his paper about 
the planet Venus, Lomonossoff took therefore particular pains to 
explain that there is no contradiction between science and the 
Bible. 

But the activity of Lomonossoff was not limited to natural 
sciences alone. He was a historian with two important works in 
this field to his credit. He was a philologist and wrote a book on 
“Rhetoric,” a “Grammar” and “Rules of Russian Versifica- 
tion.” He was an orator and a poet. He was a statesman and 
prepared a project concerning trade, industry, agriculture and 
education and another project for the foundation of a university 
in Moscow which he planned to open to students in 1755 and was 
unable to do so only because of the unexpected death of Empress 
Elizabeth. He died in 1765 at the age of 54 years in the fullness 
of his powers and at the height of his mental activity. 

I take another example, that of the great composer Alexander 
Porphirievitch Borodin. To Americans he is known only as the 
composer of “Prince Igor,” but although he achieved greatness 
in music he was by education and profession a chemist, a pro- 
fessor of this science at the University of St. Petersburg. He 
worked chiefly with haloides and to his credit are no less than 
21 papers in chemistry. He was the first to produce benzoyl 
fluoride. He lectured for ten years to women students of medi- 
cine. He was a forefighter for education for women and when 
he died, his former students placed a wreath on his monument 
with the inscription: “To the founder, defender and guardian 
of the medical classes for women, to the friend of pupils—from 
women physicians of ten classes.” 

And how about Nicolai Petrovitch Wagner, the discoverer of 


224 Alexander Petrunkevitch, Ph.D., 


pedogenesis in insects, who received two prizes for his zoological 
investigations, one of them from the Paris Academy, and who 
achieved no lesser fame and endeared himself to all Russian 
children by his incomparable “Tales of the Purring Puss”? not 
to mention his less known novel in two volumes printed in 1890 
and entitled “The Dark Path.” How about the writer and critic 
Danilewsky who published in 1885 two volumes on “Darwinism” 
in which he collected all evidence that could be brought against 
Darwin’s theories? How about Ilya Llyitch Metchnikoff who 
first achieved fame as zoologist, changing later to bacteriology 
and the study of immunity and occupying an assistant director- 
ship in the Institut Pasteur in Paris where he died quite recently ? 

Yet the beginning of scientific study and research as we have 
seen was made by foreigners whom Peter the Great marked out 
for the work and Catherine the First called to occupy the first 
chairs in the Impérial Academy while Catherine the Second fol- 
lowed their example. Some of them became in time loyal 
Russians, others at least enjoyed Russian hospitality and condi- 
tions which were evidently more favorable to work than profes- 
sorial positions in their own countries. To that extent at least 
the great Swiss mathematician Euler; the great embryologist 
Karl Ernst Baer, known in Russia where he was born of German 
parents and where he spent almost all his life as Karl Maximo- 
vitch; the German anatomist and physiologist, the creator of the 
Theory of Epigenesis, Kaspar Friedrich Wolff, born in Berlin 
in 1733 and called to Russia by Catherine the Second in 1766 and 
resident in Russia until his death in St. Petersburg in 1794, have 
contributed to Russia’s share in science and to avoid mentioning 
them would be as unfair to their memory as to avoid the name 
of Louis Agassiz in speaking of America’s contribution to science. 
They were favored, they were happy in their work in Russia. 
They became identified with the Imperial Academy, they printed 
their papers in the Memoirs of that institution which they and 
others after them made great. 

It is not my purpose to present in this short sketch of Russia’s 
contribution to science an outline of work in all branches of 
natural sciences. Nor do I intend to give a list of all men and 
women who contributed to the world’s treasury of knowledge, 
still less to give a list of books and papers written by Russian 
scientists. Such a list would fill several stately volumes. All I 


1 


Russia’s Contribution to Science. 225 


desire is to recall to the memory of those who have always 
admired Russia and of those who have lately lightly condoned 
the destruction of Russian universities by fanatics and adven- 
turers under the pretext that Russian men of science serve not 
the proletariat but wealthy bourgeois alone, to recall to their mem- 
ory the great service rendered by Russia. And for this purpose 
I shall dwell only on a few of the natural sciences and mention 
only the most important work done. 

Uppermost in my mind is chemistry, that particular science 
for which lately the Germans more than other nationalities were 
admired. But Voskresensky, Zinin, Beketov, Butlerov, Beilstein, 
Mendelejeff, Menshutkin—what a cluster of names of which any 
country may justly be proud! Although Lomonossoff had been 
the first to teach chemistry and created the first chemical labora- 
tory, the “Grandfather of Chemistry in Russia” is usually con- 
sidered to be and is known under that endearing nickname Alex- 
ander Abramovitch Voskresensky, born in 1809 in the city of 
Torjok, in the Government of Twer. He was the teacher of 
Mendelejeff who always spoke of him with reverence and 
admiration. His works were numerous and covered a wide field 
of research. He studied various reactions of sulphuric anhy- 
dride. But his chief work was in organic chemistry. He was 
the first to discover and describe the quinones, to elucidate the 
chemical structure of naphthalene, to find theobromine in choco- 
late. Nicolai Nicolaevitch Zinin, born in 1812 in the Caucasus 
and professor of chemistry in St. Petersburg from 1847 to his 
death in 1880, was so distinguished in organic chemistry, espe- 
cially through his exhaustive investigations of benzene and its 
derivatives, that he was elected corresponding member of the acad- 
emies of Paris and Berlin and of the London Chemical Society. 
He discovered naphthylamine (he called it naphthylidam), and 
described the preparation of amines from nitro compounds with 
the aid of hydrogen sulphide, a reaction of great importance in 
the production of modern aniline dyes, and still referred to as 
Zinin’s reduction. 

Nicolai Nicolaievitch Beketov, born in 1827, was one of the 
first theoretical chemists of his time, at a time when theoretical 
chemistry was not yet in vogue, and was particularly interested in 


the problem of chemical affinity which he made the subject of 
a number of articles. 


226 Alexander Petrunkevitch, Ph.D., 


Alexander Michailovitch Butlerov, born in 1828 and for many 
years professor in St. Petersburg, created a whole school of 
chemistry. He wrote a celebrated book entitled “Introduction 
to a Complete Mastery of Organic Chemistry” and dozens of 
special articles dealing with the derivation and structure espe- 
cially of isomeric alcohols and hydrocarbons. It may be added 
that he was also an expert in bee-keeping and wrote a popular 
book on “The Bee: Its Life and the Rules for Rational Bee- 
Keeping,” published in a cheap edition in 1871 and reprinted 
repeatedly. He was also interested in the occult questions of 
spiritism and achieved quite a fame in this field much to the 
dismay of his more materialistic colleagues. 

Feodor Feodorovitch Beilstein, born in St. Petersburg in 1838, 
is sufficiently well known to foreigners as one of the most dis- 
tinguished students of organic chemistry, who usually consider 
him to be a German because he wrote in German. Yet he lived 
all his life in Russia where he was professor, spoke Russian and 
considered himself and was considered by his students a Russian. 
At least I remember him as such presiding over the examination 
in chemistry which I myself had to take in Moscow. The best 
known of his works is his “Handbuch der Organischen Chemie,” 
the standard reference book on the subject, but he has published 
many special articles on aromatic compounds, on Russian petro- 
leum, on molecular rearrangement, etc. 

Nicholai Alexandrovitch Menshutkin, born in 1842, in St. 
Petersburg, a pupil of the Russian chemist N. N. Sokoloff and of 
the Germans Strecker, Wuertz and Kolbe, is best known by his 
textbook of analytical chemistry, printed in 1871, reprinted since 
that time in many editions and translated into three foreign lan- 
guages, but not less valuable is his “Lectures in Organic Chem- 
istry” also published in many editions. His earlier work was 
on the synthesis and properties of carbamides, but later he was 
more interested in the question of the relation between isomeric 
alcohols and acids and esters, and received a prize for this work 
in 1878. Since the foundation of the Russian Chemical Society 
in 1868 Menshutkin was closely associated with it and was the 
editor of its journal. The British Association for the Advance- 
ment of Science elected him corresponding member. A complete 
list of his papers may be found in the second volume of the Bio- 
graphical Dictionary of the University of St. Petersburg. He 


Russia's Contribution to Science. | 


took interest in local affairs and was a member of the Luga 
County Zemstwo and of the St. Petersburg Zemstwo. Although 
very exacting to his students in the laboratory, he was a friend 
of all who were striving to acquire education and was for many 
years president of a committee of aid to needy students. 

It seems to be scarcely necessary to review the work of the 
greatest of all Russian chemists and the pride of all to whom 
Russia means more than a land of mystery, surprises, Kazaks, 
knuts, vodka and revolution. But the account would be incom- 
plete without some reference to Dmitri Ivanovitch Mendelejeff, 
the creator of the periodic system. He was born in 1834 in 
Tobolsk in Siberia the youngest of a family of seventeen. His 
father died while he was a child and his mother when he was 
a youth of fifteen. At first he attended a gymnasium in Tobolsk, 
then in Moscow. Later he studied at the Pedagogical Institute 
of St. Petersburg and the St. Petersburg University. As a 
student he published his first research in chemistry concerning 
isomerism. After graduation he became high school teacher, 
first in Sympheropol then in Odessa. Only in 1856 had he been 
appointed Privatdozent in chemistry at the University of St. 
Petersburg, after the successful public defense of his dissertation 
on the subject of “Specific Volumes.” In 1859 he went to Heidel- 
berg where he made a research in capillarity of fluids. While 
there he also began the publication in Russian of his course in 
organic chemistry. In 1863 he returned to Russia and was 
appointed professor at the Imperial Technological Institute. At 
this time questions of applied chemistry and technology occupied 
most of his attention. He investigated the oilfields of Baku in 
the Caucasus and performed various experiments in connection 
with agricultural problems. In 1866 he was appointed professor 
of chemistry at the University of Petrograd. In 1868 he began 
the publication of his Principles of Chemistry wherein he pro- 
pounded for the first time his periodic law. This work marked 
an epoch in the study of chemistry and was repeatedly reprinted 
with additions and corrections made by the author. It was also 
translated into many languages and brought him later in 1882 as 
reward for his discovery the Davy medal of the Royal Society. 
The arrangement of the elements into short anid long periods 
according to their atomic weight and properties showed the pres- 
ence of various gaps in the series and permitted Mendelejeff to 


228 Alexander Petrunkevitch, Ph.D., 


predict the existence of the yet unknown, missing elements as 
well as their atomic weight and properties. This prediction 1s 
justly likened to the prediction of the planet Neptune by Leverrier 
from his mathematical calculations. And indeed two years after 
the prediction in 1871, the first element was discovered, and 
called gallium (Mendelejeff proposed the name ekaboron). In 
1879 was discovered scandium (Mendelejeff’s ekaaluminium) and 
in 1886 germanium (Mendelejeff’s ekasilicon). In several cases 
Mendelejeff ventured to question the correctness of the commonly 
accepted atomic weights, because they did not fit rightly into his 
periodic system and later investigations proved the correctness 
of his assertion. In 1888 he made an exhaustive study of the 
Donetz anthracite industry and was subsequently appointed 
member of the council of trade and manufacture. To this period 
belongs also his work on smokeless powder done at the request 
of the ministry of war. In 1893 he resigned his professorship to 
become Director of the Bureau of Weights and Measures. In 
1902 in a paper on the chemical conception of ether he gave 
expression to a hypothesis that ether is a gaseous element with 
an atomic weight smaller than that of hydrogen. Mendelejeff 
died in 1907 and the list of his works comprises over 140 titles 
including many investigations in various branches of physical 
chemistry, such as indefinite solutions, expansion of liquids with 
heat, etc. 

But for lack of space it would be unjust to pass in silence over 
the splendid work done by Russian chemists in recent years. « I 
cannot refrain however from mentioning V. N. Ipatiev’s exten- 
sive researches in organic chemistry, especially in hydrogenation 
of oils; and I. I. Ostromuislenskii’s investigations of rubber. 

In the closely interrelated sciences of crystallography, miner- 
alogy, petrography, and physical geology, several names stand 
out amidst a number of less known investigators. Ewegraf Step- 
anovitch Fedoroff was the first to prove that all crystals belong 
to the one or the other of the 32 possible types of symmetry and 
created the nomenclature afterwards accepted by Grote and 
others. He was a productive worker and made many researches 
in geometry, crystallography, geology, physical and descriptive, 
ores, etc. 

His pupil and my teacher in crystallography and mineralogy, 
Wladimir Ivanovitch Vernadsky, one of the broadest and best 


Russia’s Contribution to Science. 229 


educated men in the world, is the real creator of the mineralogical 
museum in Moscow and author of many researches. He investi- 
gated the mines of Austria and Germany in 1894 during which 
trip I had the privilege of accompanying him and shall never 
forget his enthusiasm, energy and perseverance. He worked at 
that time from morning till late in the evening, collecting minerals, 
visiting mines, museums, art galleries and points of interest and 
in the evening when I was totally exhausted and ready to fall 
asleep, he would open some new treatise on history of art, or 
civilization or sociology and read until late into the night. Later 
he took part in the liberating movement of Russia, was member 
of the Imperial Council, and quite recently member of the Provi- 
sional Government, remaining in Petrograd at his post when 
the Kerensky Government was fighting its last battle. A man of 
the tenderest heart, a friend of youth, he lived through most 
trying experiences during the student revolt, enduring discom- 
fitures and incurring insult for extending with fatherly love his 
protection to persecuted students. 

Alexander Alexandrovitch Inostrantzev is perhaps the most 
distinguished Russian geologist, born in 1843. He travelled a 
great deal throughout European Russia, the Caucasus and the 
Ural mountains and published many works among which I cannot 
omit mentioning his two volumes of Materials for the Geology of 
Russia, published in 1869, his Geological Investigations of the 
North of Russia, published in 1872, his subdivision of the stone 
age into periods, published in 1880, and his Treatise of Geology, 
published in 1885 and reprinted several times with additions and 
revisions. Inostranzev was for years president of the geolog- 
ical section of the St. Petersburg Society of Naturalists and 
president of the Russian Anthropological Society. He worked 
up the geological collection brought by Przewalsky, Potanin, 
Pievtzov and others, and made the St. Petersburg Geological 
Museum one of the best in Russia. It may be interesting to 
recall to memory the fact that the Philadelphia Academy of 
Sciences elected Inostranzev corresponding member. 

One more name should be mentioned in connection with geolog- 
ical and mineralogical sciences. It is the distinguished name of 
the unfortunate Dokutchaeff, who did so much for the elucida- 
tion of the nature of the black earth in Russia, created a school 
of learning, founded a museum of natural science in Poltawa and 


230 Alexander Petrunkevitch, Ph.D., 


another in Nishnij Novgorod and succumbed finally to a slow 
affection of the brain. He described the formation of the river 
valleys in European Russia in 1878, and in the next year gave 
expression to the then novel idea of the influence of the geo- 
graphical factor in the formation of soils. In 1883 in his stand- 
ard work on Russian black earth he explained its origin through 
the decomposition of the herbaceous plants of the steppe under 
the influence of climatic factors which exist even at present. He 
published many investigations on soils which he regarded as 
things different from minerals and rocks and the study of which 
he raised to the level of a separate science. His private life, full 
of privations, sufferings, disappointments and struggle, is one of 
the saddest chapters in the history of Russian men of science and 
will be forever an example of achievement through nothing but 
talent and indomitable will. 

Turning our attention to biological sciences in the broader sense 
_ of the word, I should like to touch only briefly on physiology and 
adjoining fields of knowledge, for this science is so intricately 
connected with other aspects of human life that it should find 
special consideration in connection with medicine. Four names 
command our admiration, Setchenoff, Tarkhanoff, Pavloff, and 
Bekhtereff, each with a group of followers many of whom are 
known throughout the world. 

Ivan Mikhailovitch Setchenoff, born in 1829, received his first 
education as officer in a military academy, but left service to study 
medicine at the University of Moscow from which he graduated 
in 1856. He occupied the chair of physiology at first at the 
Medico-Surgical Academy, then at the Novorossiisk University, 
then at the University of St. Petersburg and finally at the Uni- 
versity of Moscow, where he served until he was retired, con- 
tinuing in the capacity of private-dozent and emeritus at the same 
time. He was a man of broad knowledge and deep thought, 
commanding the respect and admiration of the widest circles. 
He published investigations about the gases in the blood, about 
alcoholic intoxication, cerebrospinal reflexes, about centers inhib- 
iting reflexes, about the innervation of the heart, and so on. 
Especially well known in Russia are his “Physiology of Vegeta- 
tive Processes,” “Reflexes of the Brain,” “Psychological Stud- 
ies,” and “Elements of Thought.” I remember his speech at 
the meeting of: physicians and naturalists in Moscow more than 


SE ag Oe 


Russia's Contribution to Science. 231 


25 years ago on the subject of “What is Thought?’ Unassum- 
ing and quiet, he spoke in the immense assembly hall of the 
Moscow nobility without raising his voice which nevertheless 
was heard by everybody in the audience. 

Prince Ivan Romanovitch Tarkhan Mouravov, better known 
as Tarkhanoff, a Georgian by nationality, born in 1846, was for 
many years professor of physiology at the Medical Academy of 
St. Petersburg. His works embrace the physiology of thermic 
reflexes, the innervation of the spleen, the application of the tele- 
phone to the study of animal electricity, the physiology of the 
normal sleep in animals, the automatic movements of decapitated 
animals, the influence of music on animals and man, etc. 

The physiologist best known in foreign countries and one of 
the most remarkable experimenters of the world is Ivan Petro- 
vitch Pavlov, born in 1849 and professor of physiology at the 
Medical Academy of St. Petersburg since 1890. His investiga- 
tions extending over many years and contained in numerous 
articles may be divided into three groups: work relating to the 
innervation of the heart, work in connection with the so-called 
Eck fistula, and work on the secreting activity of the stomach. In 
the first series of papers, Pavlov has shown that besides centers 
accelerating and retarding the heartbeat, the heart possesses also 
centers augmenting and depressing the strength of the heart- 
beat. In the second series of experiments Pavlov used the opera- 
tion suggested by his teacher Eck and consisting in an artificial 
connection of the portal vein with the inferior caval vein. 
Through this connection the blood flowing from the digestive 
organs was diverted from the liver and the function of the latter 
organ can be studied independently. It was thus that Pavlov was 
enabled to show how the liver acts as an organ absorbing from 
the blood harmful substances and purifying it. 

But the most celebrated of his investigations are those based on 
cesophagotomy, 1. e., on an operation consisting in the severing of 
the cesophagus and the production of an artificial fistula, allow- 
ing a direct observation of the contents of the stomach under 
various conditions. This operation is too well known to require 
an explanation or detailed description here. The results of these 
investigations, which have been translated into many languages, 
may be briefly summarized as follows: the secretion of saliva is 
caused by reflexes through smell, sight, etc., before food is taken 


232 Alexander Petrunkevitch, Ph.D., 


into the mouth. Similarly the secretion of the gastric juice is 
induced by'a psychic condition before food is taken into the 
mouth. If, unknown to the animal, solid food is introduced 
directly into the stomach through the fistula, no secretion of 
gastric juice takes place for at least an hour. Mechanical stimu- 
lation is ineffective. 

Studying the chemical phenomena of digestion Pavlov used 
another remarkable operation consisting in the artificial produc- 
tion of an accessory miniature stomach connected with, yet 
separate from the main one. The action of the vagus nerve 
which conveys the excitation to the glands of the stomach was 
excluded by a division of this nerve. Thus Pavlov was able to 
show that meat juice and beef extract cause secretion while no 
secretion of gastric juice follows the introduction of eggwhite, 
fat, or starch into the stomach. 

Wladimir Mikhailovitch Bekhterev, born in 1857, is an alienist 
by profession. As such, he has had a great deal to do with 
normal and pathological functions of the nervous system. His 
works embrace a wide range of subjects from the anatomy of the 
nervous system to the psychopathy and its relation to responsi- 
bility before the law. He wrote on the physiology of the central 
nervous system, especially on the localization of tactile and pain 
centers in the brain. In 1884 he published an interesting paper 
on the formation of our conception of space. Induced by special 
circumstances he has also made a psychological and ethnograph- 
ical investigation of the semibarbaric Votyaks and published a 
paper on their history and present status. 

Many were the Russian workers in botany and there is scarcely 
a branch of this science that has not been made subject of thor- 
ough investigation. Nicolai Ivanovitch Annenkoff, born in 1819, 
was the first student of the local flora. To his patient work in 
this field is due our knowledge of it. He prepared the celebrated 
herbarium kept in the botanical Museum of Moscow University. 
He wrote the “Flora Mosquensis Exsiccata,” and later in 1859, 
the “Botanical Dictionary,” which is a most valuable reference 
book. His successor in the field of systematics was Nicolai 
Nicolaevitch Kaufman, born in 1834, whose “Moscow Flora” 
reprinted many times plays in Russia the role of Gray’s Manual 
and is in the hands of every student of flowering plants. Lev 


Russia's Contribution to Science. 233 


Semenovitch Cienkowsky, born in 1822 in Warsau, was the most 
distinguished student of the lowest plant organisms of his day. 
In his paper on “The Lowest Alge and Infusoriz,”’ published 
in 1856, he was the first to express the idea that these organisms 
are not complicated creatures as taught by Ehrenberg, but uni- 
cellular forms. His earlier works are mostly on myxomycete, 
fungi, and alge. Later he was particularly interested in Bac- 
teriology and shares with Pasteur the distinction of founder of 
this science. He applied his knowledge also to practical ends and 
has described an improved method of inoculation against anthrax. 
Christopher Yakovlevitch Gobi, another student in alge, born in 
1847, made numerous contributions to our knowledge of the 
marine flora of the Gulf of Finland, of the White Sea and other 
Russian seas. In more recent years a great deal of work has 
been done by various Russian botanists on local floras taxonomy 
and geographical distribution of plants, much of this work hav- 
ing been published in Russian journals. 

Anatomy and physiology of plants have also found many dis- 
tinguished investigators among Russian botanists. Andrei Ser- 
geevitch Faminzyn, born in 1835, a student of Cienkowsky’s, is 
the first to be mentioned in this line. In his student years he 
published a “Natural History of the Conifers of the St. Peters- 
burg Flora.’’ But soon he turned his attention to physiological 
problems. In 1861 he printed an investigation entitled “An 
Attempt of a Chemico Physiological Investigation of the Process 
of Ripening in Grapes.” He worked a great deal with alge 
as material. In 1867 he published his paper “On the Action of 
Light on Alge and other closely related Organisms.” He 
extended these investigations to cover many forms, studying the 
formation of starch and other processes dependent upon the 
action of light. In 1883 appeared his “Metabolism and Trans- 
formation of Energy in Plants.” His paper on crystals and crys- 
tallites, published in German in 1884, was a natural sequence of 
these studies. In 1889 he published “A Contribution to the 
Question of Symbiosis between Algze and Animals,” followed in 
1890 by an essay on “The Psychic Life of the Lowest Represen- 
tatives of Living Beings.’ In 1898 he wrote an article “On 
Contemporary Natural Science and Psychology,” and in rgor1 on 
the “Reform of the System of Education in Russia.” 


234 Alexander Petrunkevitch, Ph.D., 


Of his numerous students the best known are Batalin, Borodin, 
Baranetzky, Ivanovsky and Timiryaseff. Alexander Fedoritch 
Batalin (born in 1847) published many investigations in cereals 
and other useful plants. But the work which attracted most 
attention was “On the Influence of Light on the Form in Plants” 
(1872) and “The Mechanics of Movement in Insectivorous 
Plants,” mentioned by Charles Darwin in his books on the sub- 
ject. Ivan Petrovitch Borodin (born in 1847) made investiga- 
tions in the anatomy of plants, especially of their leaves, published 
in 1888 a well known “Course in Anatomy of Plants,” studied 
the process of breathing, the formation and distribution of crys- 
tals in plants, etc. 

Clementi Arcadievitch Timiriazeff, born in 1843, is known by 
his studies of the chlorophyll. He discovered protophylline, a 
compound distinct from etioline and derived from the chloro- 
phylline through reduction. Under the influence of light and 
air the oxydized protophylline becomes again chlorophylline. 
The absorption band of the protophylline being in the orange rays, 
Timiriaseff concluded that the orange rays are mostly responsible 
for the green color in plants, a conclusion which later found con- 
firmation in the experiments of the German scientist Reincke. 
But Timiriaseff’s fame rests chiefly on his ability as teacher, lec- 
turer and populariser. His book ‘The Life of the Plant” was 
published in several editions and has been translated into German. 
For many years he was professor of plant anatomy and physi- 
ology at the University of Moscow, beloved and admired by his 
students. A staunch supporter of Darwin he published a book 
in 1863 on “Darwin and His Theory” which has since seen many 
editions. He was violently opposed to Weismann’s theories of 
heredity and I remember him attacking Weismann in his lectures 
with all the vigour of his eloquence. His works found him 
recognition on the part of the Royal Society which elected him 
Fellow. 

Wladimir Palladin, born in 1859, is another of the well known 
contemporary Russian botanists of the older generation. He 
worked in anatomy and physiological chemistry of plants. His 
books “Plant Anatomy” and ‘Plant Physiology’ are used as 
textbooks in all Russian universities and have seen several edi- 
tions. Many of his investigations have for their subject metab- 
olism in plants. 


Russia’s Contribution to Science. 235 


Of other Russian botanists whose work is known outside of 
Russia I may mention Belajeff, Nawaschin, Gorojankin and 
Golenkin as well as the distiguished bacteriologist Vinogradsky. 

Zoology, embryology, and allied sciences have been always 
popular with the Russians. We have seen already that as early as 
1725 Duvernoie was called to the first chair of anatomy and 
zoology established at the St. Petersburg Academy. Three 
names of men who, because of their Teutonic origin and great 
achievements in science are claimed by the Germans, may be even 
with greater justice claimed by Russia because they spent most 
of their life in Russia and became identified with the Imperial 
Academy of Petrograd. These are Wolff, Pallace and Baer. 

Kaspar Friedrich Wolff, who by right should be called the 
founder of the science of embryology, was born in Berlin in 1733, 
the son of a tailor. In Halle where he studied medicine he wrote 
his “Theoria generationis”’ published in 1759, a remarkable 
work in which he attacked the so-called evolution or preformation 
theory and advanced his own theory of epigenesis or gradual 
development. Unable to continue his studies in Germany, Wolff 
gladly accepted a call to the St. Petersburg Academy in 1766. 
In 1768 and 1769 he published his second great work “De Forma- 
tione Intestinarum” in the Memoirs of the Academy. Von Baer 
spoke of this work as “the greatest masterpiece of scientific obser- 
vation which we possess.” Wolff died in St. Petersburg in 1794 
and those Germans who claim him because of his origin and 
still more because of the excellence of his work, should remember 
the statement made by Ernst Haeckel himself in his Natuer- 
liche Schopfungsgeschichte that “De Formatione Intestinarum”’ 
remained unknown to the Germans until it was translated from 
the Latin in which it is written into German in 1812—which 
means that Wolff during his life did not exist for the Germans 
since he left Germany at the age of 33. 

Peter Simon Pallas, born in Berlin in 1741, is = aig claimed by 
the Germans. Yet he left Germany when 20 years of age, lived 
in England where he was elected member of the Royal Society, 
then in Holland, served for a short time as professor of surgery 
in Berlin and was ‘called to the Imperial Academy of St. Peters- 
burg in 1767, i.e. at the age of 26 years. In Russia he spent 43 
years, i. e., until 1810, and when his wife died, returned to Ger- 
many only to die the following year. He was a great traveller 


236 Alexander Petrunkevitch, Ph.D., 


and a prolific writer. Before going to Russia he published 
“Elenchus Zoophytorum” and ‘Miscellanea Zoologica.” He 
began publishing his celebrated “Specilegia Zoologica” in 1767. 
The natural history results of his six years of travel through 
Russia and Siberia were published in the French translation of 
his ‘Travels, etc.” (eight volumes with nine volumes of plates, 
1788-1793). He published “Icones Insectorum presertim Ros- 
siz Siberieque peculiarum” in 1781-1806, and ‘“Zoographia 
russo-asiatica” in three volumes, in 1811. His was a remarkable 
mind interested in many problems, he was an accomplished geol- 
ogist and paleontologist, he studied the geographical distribution 
of animals, wrote a memoire on variation in animals, as botanist 
published the first “Flora Rossica” in two volumes in 1784-1788. 
He was besides a philologist, topographer, mineralogist, ethno- 
grapher, archeologist, agronomer and technologist. He was well 
known in other countries, but although he did not particularly 
enjoy life in Russia, he spent most of it there, partly in travels, 
partly in research in his estate in the Crimea, which Catherine the 
Second presented to him. 

Carl Ernst, or Carl Maximovitch von Baer, the father of 
embryology, was born a Russian subject in 1792 in Estland, 
Russia, and studied first at Reval at a gymnasium and then from 
1810 to 1814 at the University of Dorpat. His work is too well 
known to need any particular mention here. What I want how- 
ever to point out is that Baer, like Wolff and Pallas, spent most of 
his life in Russia. In Germany he spent only seventeen years as 
professor at Konigsberg, from 1817-34, when he was called for 
the second time to the St. Petersburg Academy. (He was called 
the first time in 1829, but returned from St. Petersburg to Kon- 
igsberg in 1830.) From now on to the end of his life, 1. e., 
forty-two years, he lived in Russia and worked there, dying in 
Dorpat in 1876. Thus even the second volume of his celebrated 
“Embryology of Animals,’ published in 1837, appeared three 
years after his departure from Germany. And his discovery of 
the mammalian egg in 1827 was also for the first time reported 
in a communication to the St. Petersburg Academy. Baer was a 
many-sided investigator, traveller, anthropologist, ethnographer, 
historian and geographer. Some of his investigations were writ- 
ten in the Russian language including the especially important 
paper “Why have our rivers which flow north or south, a high 


Russia’s Contribution to Science. 237 


right and a low left shore,” in which he established the law of 
meridional deviation of rivers usually known as Baer’s Law. 

Johann Friedrich, or better Fedor Fedorovitch Brandt, born 
in Germany in 1802, was called to Russia in 1831 and became 
director of the Zoological Museum of the St. Petersburg Acad- 
emy. During the forty-eight years of his life in Russia he wrote 
a number of papers in Latin and German on the subject of syste- 
matics, anatomy, paleontology and geographical distribution. 
His son Alexander Fedorovitch Brandt, born in St. Petersburg in 
1844 and for years professor of zoology at the University of 
Kharkov, is known for his work on the Anatomy of Inverte- 
brates and especially on the structure of the reproductive system 
in insects as well as the development of round worms. 

The problems of anatomy have occupied and are still occupying 
the attention of many investigators. Such men as Kowalewsky, 
Metchnikoy, Salensky, Bobretzky, Korotneff, Tikhomirov, Zograf, 
Kulagin, Schimkevitch, Cholodkowsky, Schewiakow, W. Wagner, 
Kojevnikoy and others have published papers on the one or the 
other invertebrate group, and Menzbir, Koltzoff, Ivantzoff, Nas- 
sonow, Sushkin on the anatomy of vertebrates. The subject, 
however, does not lend itself easily to a general account and I 
shall merely remind the reader of the interesting descriptions of 
the two creatures forming a transitional stage between the comb- 
jellyfish and the flat worms. One of these papers was written 
in Russian by A. Kowalewsky and is entitled “Cceloplana Mets- 
chnikowi,” and has been published in the Proceedings of the 
Society of Friends of Natural Science in Moscow, in 1882 (a 
preliminary account was published by Kowalewsky in German in 
1880). The other belongs to A. Korotneff, is entitled ‘‘Cteno- 
plana Kowalewskii,” and was published in German, in the 
Z. f. W. Z. in 1886. Of great interest is also the work of Knipo- 
witsch on the strange group of Ascothoracida among the Cirri- 
pedia. 

Microscopic anatomy and histology have also been made sub- 
jects of extensive studies. The microscopic structure of inverte- 
brates is generally treated by zoologists, but what is known as the 
department of histology in Russia has to deal almost exclusively 
with vertebrates. Here the names of Owsjannikov and Law- 
dovsky are first to claim our attention, especially because of their 
remarkable textbook ‘Microscopic Anatomy of Man and Ani- 


238 Alexander Petrunkevitch, Ph.D., 


bd 


published in two large volumes in 1887-8 in codperation 
with Dogiel, Erlitzky, Peremeschko, and Stieda, all of whom 
were at that time professors in various Russian universities 
(Stieda was professor at Dorpat). I also wish to mention the 
excellent textbook in cytology written by Ogneff, and published 
in 1903. 

The study of systematics, zoogeography, and local faunas was 
continued uninterruptedly since the first works of Pallas. The 
museums in Petrograd, Moscow and other universities were 
enriched by numerous collections (of special interest is the Equus 
Przewalskii). Articles treating special groups of animals are 
found in all Russian periodicals. The study of fishes was always 
popular in Russia. We find the excellent monograph on the 
“Bieluga” written by Sabaneeff in 1871 and his ‘Fishes of 
Russia” published in 1875. In more recent years my classmate 
Berg has distinguished himself as student of Russian and Asiatic 
fishes. Of the books on Russian birds I should like to mention 
only the classical two volumes by Menzbir which embody all our 
knowledge of the life and system of that group, and the books of 
Modest Bogdanoff. 

The impetus given by Baer through his discovery of the 
germlayers, directed the attention of zoologists toward the prob- 
lems of embryology. Here the names of Metchnikoff and 
Kowalewsky occupy quite an enviable position. Alexander Onu- 
frievitch Kowalewsky was born in 1840 and at first studied engi- 
neering. His first work in embryology, published in 1865, on the 
“History of Development of Amphioxus lanceolatus” at once 
placed him in the ranks of distinguished investigators. Equally 
fine was his thesis for the degree of Doctor of Zoology, “On the 
Development of Phoronis,’ published in 1867. In the next year 
Kowalewsky was called to the chair of zoology at Kazan, a year 
later to Kiev. The year after he undertook a scientific journey to 
the Red Sea and Algiers. Returning, he was appointed professor 
at the University of Novorossijsk and in 1890 member of the 
St. Petersburg Academy and in 1891 professor of histology at 
the University of St. Petersburg. His investigations cover 
almost the entire field of invertebrate embryology and in view of 
their importance it would be almost impossible to point out any 
title in preference to others. We may, however, mention his 
“Embryology of Simple Ascidians,” published in 1866, an epoch- 


mals,’ 


Russia’s Contribution to Science. 239 


forming work because in it the Ascidians were for the first time 
shown to be of chordate nature; his “Embryological Studies on 
Worms and Arthropods” published in 1871, a work which 
received the prize of the St. Petersburg Academy and which con- 
tained besides other interesting observations, the celebrated 
description of the development of Sagitta; and some of his later 
publications on the physiology of excretory and circulatory organs 
in invertebrates. 

Ilya Ilyitch Metchnikoff was born in 1845 and studied at Khar- 
kov. From 1864 to 1867 he worked in Germany at various uni- 
versities. His first important publications published in 1866 deal 
with the development of insects. His work in zoology extends 
over about twenty years before he changed from zoology to bac- 
teriology and immunity. His influence on the development of 
our knowledge of invertebrate embryology was no less than that 
of Kowalewsky and his researches also cover almost all groups of 
invertebrates. He was the first to give a careful description of 
the development of Hydrozoa and proposed the term of Paren- 
chymula for their early larvee. He described parthenogenesis or 
as he terms it “Sporogony” in Cunoctanta. He gave the first, 
remarkable description of the embryology of the scorpion. He 
described the six-legged larva of the Diplopoda. In his ‘“Embry- 
ological Studies of Insects,” published in 1866, he described the 
early separation of the progenital cells which he termed the 
“polecells” in parthenogenetic Diptera. It was while working on 
the development of invertebrates that Metchnikoff discovered 
phagocytosis in 1882, the discovery which proved of such vital 
importance in the study of disease and immunity and which 
gradually diverted his attention from purely zoological subjects. 
But Metchnikoff worked also in anthropology and published in 
1874 and in 1876 investigations of the Kalmyks. He was also a 
populariser of biology and wrote numerous articles published 
in the Russian magazines: “Naturalist,” ‘“Vestnik Evropy,” 
“Nature,” “Home and School.” 

The brilliant young zoologist Alexander Pavlovitch Fedchenko, 
who perished at the age of 29 in a snowstorm on Mont Blanc in 
1873, has left a few remarkable investigations, as for example, 
the description of the life history, hitherto unknown, of the 
Guinea worm, Dracunculus medinensis. He brought from 
Turkestan a rich collection of animals and plants, the description 


240 Alexander Petrunkevitch, Ph.D., 


of which was published later in Russian journals. The wife of 
Fedchenko continued his studies in plants and published numer- 
ous papers of a taxonomic and phytogeographic character. 

I have already mentioned the discovery of pedogenesis by 
Nikolai Petrovitch Wagner in 1861, such a startling discovery at 
the time that von Siebold refused to print the paper until the 
German zoologist Pagenstecher two years later made a similar 
observation. But Wagner’s paper was meanwhile printed in 
Russian and received a prize. 

The discovery of artificial parthenogenesis was also made for 
the first time by a Russian, my teacher Alexander Andreevitch 
Tikhomirof, in 1881, on the eggs of Bombyx mori, the silkworm. 
To him belongs also the best monograph on this insect, unfor- 
tunately unknown to foreigners because written in Russian, in 
1882, and he was the first to introduce Scorcionera as food-plant 
for silkworms instead of the mulberry which cannot grow in the 
far north. By this substitution of food Tikhomirov made sericul- 
ture possible in North Russia and Finland. In 1887 he published, 
also in Russian, an interesting investigation in the development of 
Hydrozoa. A man of extraordinary education and wide knowl- 
edge, Tikhomiroy was unfortunately misled by ambition, diverted 
his activities into administrative channels and cast a shadow on 
his name as investigator through his cooperation with the secret 
service while Acting President of the University of Moscow. 
But the little that he published will endure and is to the credit of 
Russian science. 

Salensky, Korotneff, Cholodkovsky and Schimkevitch as well 
as others have contributed to our knowledge of the development 
of various animals. The anatomy and development of spiders, 
for example, was for a long time almost entirely based on the 
studies of Schimkevitch and his “Text-book of Comparative 
Anatomy” has been translated into German. Cholodkovsky was 
the first to elucidate the complicated life history of Scale-Insects 
in a series of articles. 

A host of younger scientists were engaged in research in their 
respective sciences when the world war claimed the attention of 
all patriotic men. As I have explained before, in Russia, men 
espousing an academic career were exempt from service and 
therefore did not, in the majority of cases, receive any military 


Russia's Contribution to Science. 241 


training whatsoever. But many men of science volunteered their 
services in other capacities than soldiers. The revolution of 1917 
brought new hopes, but these were soon shattered and now the 
universities are deserted and empty but for a few who have 
adapted themselves to the Bolshevik régime or chose to remain at 
their posts and to carry on the torch of light amidst the darkness 
of ruin and desolation. Some perished. Others fled to foreign 
countries. Russia’s contribution to science may become a closed 
chapter, unless new forces will arise capable not only of adjusting 
themselves to the new conditions, but of creating and producing 
where the present generation has failed. 


March, 1920 


tan) 


i 


winsh we r ee via inay 


- ye shd Lieinateled penta eS 
: * 5 2 Tad a ee at ee weitt is seein ste 
meth Seley MeL 1 The 2 tel aes 
ern (Rak ive t ae Sey be Sek ers A 
Sa 2 yx: Ss I eS yufttig t's ete te Tass ye OF eat HY 
arta? uftl ffs atoebrnie iaetyigt ee Bay CE: a 
a erst path, cc oultaptebsotfe seme eit pis Ale a i 
lsaticher ly fia Ca Ie Aes aise Rgehae. oy 
Suiweat rls (a. ebdaels, oie as <pelt Soles 3 sal ene 


BIG) Oe eae ee ee 
. 
| 
a 
‘4 


y = oe a 
" J a ’ ) ths 

E : 

2. a 

Pe 


, 


Se ns ee 
pf 


*~ 


Sr ey 
we ati 
i 


* 


wei 0 


oe J 
S73 


) 


TRANSACTIONS OF 
THE CONNECTICUT ACADEMY 
OF ARTS AND SCIENCES 


VOLUME 23 | SEPTEMBER 1920 [ PAGES 243-382 


THE 
Rhetorica of Philodemus 


TRANSLATION AND COMMENTARY 
BY 


HARRY MoU BSELL, Ph.D: 


Assistant Professor of Greek and Latin in Yale University. 


NEW HAVEN, CONNECTICUT 
PUBLISHED BY THE 
CONNECTICUT ACADEMY OF ARTS AND SCIENCES 
AND TO BE OBTAINED ALSO FROM THE 
YALE UNIVERSITY PRESS 


PREFACE. 


This work is intended to be a systematic presentation of the 
rhetorical fragments of Philodemus, with an interpretation of 
the more important passages, in the hope that they may be made 
more accessible to the general reader than they have heretofore 
been. On many points of interpretation the author’s judgment 
has changed repeatedly in the course of the work, and he is far 
from positive that the correct rendering has in all cases been 
attained. But in the present condition of the text perfection is 
an unattainable ideal, and some slight gain in accuracy would 
hardly justify a greater expenditure of time. It would perhaps 
be more exact to call it a paraphrase than a translation. While 
it has been possible in general to translate almost literally, there 
are many passages where the papyrus is so fragmentary that 
nothing more than an approximation is possible, and the gaps 
must in some cases be filled entirely by conjecture. Moreover 
at times it has seemed best to condense some of the more prolix 
paragraphs. It is hoped that this will in no way hinder the 
student who is seeking an introduction to Philodemus. 

The author is profoundly grateful to his colleagues and friends, 
Professor G. L. Hendrickson and Dr. E. W. Nichols, who very 
generously read the translation in manuscript, and offered 
valuable criticism. 


" © 


at LS 


} : i *) 
i .* 
, ‘ 
, ; G 
7 Me P 
ee 2 \ 
” a ‘ 
» he 3 
a) : 
, 
2 sf, Bs 
“ey eve ioek Rie 
oP 
a >. 
, = 


‘ d 
i 7 
a . 
i > Oe 
4, 1 
— 
‘ fs 
\ 
- , 
= : ¢ 
‘ / i : 
= 4 ; 
4 2 
“ nie, 
, 
at he 
y ’ 
ee 
: i 
ey ; 
i vol 
») . 
\ 
: . i! a f i 
‘ Ay ’ 
y iar ‘ ye yh a! 


THE, RH ETORICA, OF PHIL@DEMUS. 


INTRODUCTION. 


The excavations at Herculaneum in the eighteenth century, 
so rich in results for the student of classical archaeology, pro- 
duced another treasure which aroused the greatest interest in the 
learned world, and seemed for a time likely to overshadow in 
its importance the additions which these excavations made to 
our knowledge of ancient sculpture. In one of the villas were 
found many charred papyrus rolls. At first they were not recog- 
nized as such, and many were destroyed before the discovery 
was made that they were the remains of a very extensive private 
library. Even then the task was hardly begun, for it was found 
impossible at that time to unroll the papyri; many were cut apart 
and sadly mutilated before a successful method was devised. 
Thereafter the work of unrolling and deciphering them was 
undertaken, and has continued, though with very serious inter- 
ruptions, to the present time. Two series of Herculanensia Volu- 
mina totaling twenty-one volumes were published in Naples, and 
a third series is now planned, of which the first volume has 
already appeared.‘ In addition to these editions copies of many 
of the rolls were made under the direction of English scholars 
early in the last century. These copies are preserved at Oxford; 
some have been published. These do not exhaust the Hercula- 
nean discoveries, but are fairly representative of the whole mass 
of papyri. 

The expectations aroused in the scholarly world by the dis- 
covery of these papyri have been realized only to a small degree. 
For instead of finding the lost works of some master of Greek 
literature, it was seen that the library was composed of philo- 
sophical works, almost entirely of the Epicurean school; nor 
were the volumes written by the greatest of the Epicureans, but 


* Herculanensium Voluminum quae supersunt XI Tom. Naples, 1793-1855. 
Vol. VII did not appear. Herculanensium Voluminum quae supersunt 
collectio altera, XI Tom. Naples, 1862-1876. Herculanensium Voluminum 
quae supersunt collectio tertia, Tom. I, Milan, ro14. 

*Herculanensium Voluminum Ps. I, II, Oxford, 1824, 1825; W. Scott, 
Fragmenta Herculanensia, Oxford, 1885. 


248 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


mainly by Philodemus, at best an authority of the second rank. 
In fact it has been acutely conjectured by Comparetti® because 
several copies were found of the same works of Philodemus that 
this was Philodemus’ own library, and by another ingenious bit 
of reasoning Comparetti concludes that the villa in which the 
library was found belonged to the Piso family. We know that 
Philodemus was for many years a member of the household of 
L. Calpurnius Piso cos. 58 B. C., and it may well be that at his 
decease his library passed into the possession of the Pisos.*‘ 

It is to his connection with Piso that we owe most of our 
knowledge of Philodemus. He was a native of Gadara, had 
studied with the Epicurean Zeno at Athens, had been expelled 
from Himera, for what cause we do not know,’ and settled at 
Rome where he became the client of Piso. From this point our 
knowledge of him is derived from Cicero. In the attack on 
Piso Cicero mentions an Epicurean who lived on terms of inti- 
macy with Piso, and describes in no complimentary terms his 
activities in commemorating the grosser side of the revels in the 
Pisonian circle. Cicero mentions no name, but Asconius iden- 


* La villa de’ Pisoni e la sua biblioteca in Pompei e la regione sotterrata 
di Vesuvio nell’ anno LX XIX (Naples, 1879) p. 159 ff. also in Comparetti 
e de Petra, La villa Ercolanese dei Pisoni, Turin, 1883. 

* Certainty cannot be obtained, and Mommsen (Archae. Zeit., XX XVIII 
(1880), p. 32) has argued strongly that the villa cannot have belonged to 
Piso. Comparetti replied in La Bibliotheque de Philodéme, in Mélanges 
Chatelain, 1910, p. 118 ff. 

° Evidence of his expulsion is given in a fragment of Aelian quoted by 
Suidas s. v. Tyw@vra. Another notice (s. v. cuxodavrety and ‘Imepala) may 
also be from Aelian and is commonly printed with the other notice in 
editions of Aelian, e. g. fr. 40 Hercher. If it refers to Philodemus, it 
appears that epidemics and famines at Himera were supposed to have 
been caused by his contemptuous remarks about the gods; his expulsion 
followed. 

“In Pisonem 28, 68; Dicet aliquis: unde haec tibi nota sunt? Non 
mehercules contumeliae causa describam quemquam, praesertim ingenio- 
sum hominem atque eruditum, cui generi esse ego iratus, ne si cupiam 
quidem, possum. Est quidam Graecus qui cum isto vivit, homo, ut vere 
dicam-sic enim cognovi-humanus, sed tamdiu, quam diu cum aliis est aut 
ipse secum. Is cum istum adolescentem iam tum hac dis irata fronte 
vidisset, non fastidivit eius amicitiam, cum esset praesertim appetitus: 
dedit se in consuetudinem, sic ut prorsus una viveret nec fere unquam ab 
eo discederet. Non apud indoctos, sed, ut arbitror in hominum eruditis- 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 249 


tifies the object of the attack as Philodemus, and there is no 
reason to doubt his statement.?’ Much of Cicero’s abuse of 
Philodemus is undoubtedly due to the heat of the invective 
against Piso, and should be correspondingly discounted, but the 
basis of fact is probably only too true, for Philodemus has borne 
testimony against himself in the scabrous epigrams preserved 
in the Anthology. It is noticeable, too, that Cicero qualifies his 


simorum et humanissimorum coetu loquor. Audistis profecto dici philo- 
sophos Epicureos omnis res, quae sint homini expetendae, voluptate metiri. 
Recte an secus, nihil ad nos, aut, si ad nos, nihil ad hoc tempus: sed 
tamen lubricum genus orationis adolescenti non acriter intelligenti est 
saepe praeceps. 609. Itaque admissarius iste, simul atque audivit volupta- 
tem a philosopho tanto opere laudari, nihil expiscatus est: sic suos sensus 
voluptarios omnis incitavit, sic ad illius hanc orationem adhinnivit, ut non 
magistrum virtutis, sed auctorem libidinis a se illum inventum arbitraretur. 
Graecus primo distinguere et dividere illa, quem ad modum dicerentur: 
iste claudus, quem ad modum aiunt, pilam: retinere quod acceperat, testi- 
ficari, tabellas obsignare velle, Epicurum desertum dicere; etenim dicit, 
ut opinor, se nullum bonum intelligere posse demptis corporis voluptatibus. 
70. Quid multa? Graecus facilis et valde venustus nimis pugnax contra 
imperatorem populi Romani esse noluit. Est autem hic, de quo loquor,) 
non philosophia solum, sed etiam ceteris studiis, quae fere ceteros Epi- 
cureos negligere dicunt perpolitus. Poema porro facit ita festivum, ita) 
concinnum, ita elegans, nihil ut fieri possit argutius. In quo reprehendat 
eum licet si qui volet, modo leviter, non ut improbum, non ut audacem, 
non ut impurum, sed ut Graeculum, ut assentatorem, ut poetam. Devenit 
autem seu potius incidit in istum eodem deceptus supercilio Graecus atque 
advena, quo tot sapientes et tanta civitas. Revocare se non poterat famili- 
aritate implicatus, et simul inconstantiae famam verebatur. Rogatus, 
invitatus, coactus ita multa ad istum de isto quoque scripsit, ut omnes 
libidines, omnia stupra, omnia cenarum conviviorumque genera, adulteria 
denique eius delicatissimis versibus expresserit. 71. In quibus si qui velit 
possit istius tamquam in speculo vitam intueri: ex quibus multa a multis 
lecta et audita recitarem, ni vererer ne hoc ipsum genus orationis, quo 
nunc utor, ab huius loci more abhorreret: et simul de ipso, qui scripsit 
detrahi nihil volo. Qui si fuisset in discipulo comparando meliore for- 
tuna, fortasse austerior et gravior esse potuisset: sed eum casus in hanc 
consuetudinem scribendi induxit, philosopho valde indignam: si quidem 
philosophia, ut fertur, virtutis continet et offici et bene vivendi disciplinam: 
quam qui profitetur, gravissimam sustinere mihi personam videtur. 72. 
Sed idem casus illum ignarum quid profitetur, cum se philosophum esse 
diceret, istius impurissimae atque intemperatissimae pecudis caeno et 
sordibus inquinavit. 

‘Vol. V pt. 2, p. 16, Orelli; Philodemum significat, qui fuit Epicureus 
illa aetate nobilissimus, cuius et poemata sunt lascivia. 


250 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


condemnation of Philodemus; he grants that he is humanus as 
long as he remains in proper society. He has a breadth of cul- 
ture far surpassing that of the average Epicurean, and his poetry 
has the charm and polish of the best society verse. However 
his too easy good nature has brought him into the meshes of 
Piso’s net, from which he is unable to extricate himself. These 
qualifying phrases agree with the other notice in Cicero* which 
may be taken as showing more nearly than the harsh words of 
the In Pisonem his real attitude toward Philodemus.° 

I have mentioned that Philodemus was a disciple of Zeno. 
This connection is of prime importance in estimating Philode- 
mus’ position in the Epicurean sect, and in the contemporary 
world of letters, and necessitates a brief consideration of Zeno. 
Here again, we rely for our information largely upon Cicero. 
When the latter was a student at Athens in 79/8 he was advised 
by Philo to study Epicureanism under Zeno. He was probably 
at this time head of the school, though the fact cannot be estab- 
lished beyond a doubt.'® At any. rate he was the ablest exponent 


of the Epicurean doctrine, and Cicero records that his style - 


distinguished him from the other representatives of his sect. 
Non igitur ille, ut plerique, sed isto modo ut tu, distincte, gra- 
viter,. ornate. .De. Nat. Deora, 21, 59> “We detivesiunines 
information about his style from the notice in Diog. Laert. VII, 
I, 35. Diogenes is enumerating the different philosophers by 
the name of Zeno, with a line of description for each; of our 
Zeno he says, 6yd00s LuwWwvios Td yévos, Pirocodos *Emixovpeos Kat 
vonoar Kal Epunvetoa cadys- Evidently his style was_ striking, 
otherwise we should not have two independent notices de- 
voted so markedly to it; this characteristic is all the more 
remarkable because the Epicureans affected indifference to man- 
ner of presentation. Now we have seen that Philodemus 


®*De Fin. II, 35, 119; Quae cum dixissem, Habeo, inquit Torquatus, ad 
‘quos ista referam, et, quamquam aliquid ipse poteram, tamen invenire 
‘malo paratiores. Familiares nostros, credo, Sironem dicis et Philodemum, 
‘cum optimos viros, tum homines doctissimos. ¢ 

*W. Cronert in an article published in the Jahreshefte d. 6st. archae. 
Inst., vol. X (1907), pp. 145-153, entitled Die Epicureer in Syrien, thinks 
that he has discovered in Pap. ined. 986, fr. 19 mention of the enmity 
between Philodemus and Cicero. 

* See the discussion in Zeller III, 1 (3rd ed.), p. 373, n. 2. 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 251 


was poet to the Piso family, and his reputation in Rome 
rested fully as much on his poetry as on his philosophy. 
And we shall find in the second book of his epi pyropuxjs that a 
strife had arisen among the Epicureans which perhaps was not 
serious enough to be called a schism, but at least gave rise to 
several controversial pamphlets, and much truly Epicurean bil- 
lingsgate. In this quarrel Zeno and Philodemus supported the 
thesis that a certain kind of rhetoric, to which they applied the 
adjective “sophistic,’ was an art, and this was disputed as heresy 
by the opposing party. The Epicureans as a who’e rejected all 
rhetoric as useless; Zeno and Philodemus held that the epideictic 
branch of rhetoric was a proper subject for study because that 
alone could be reduced to rule, whereas the parts involving per- 
suasion depended on the speaker’s ability to catch the popular 
favor. The rhetorical works of Philodemus are an exposition of 
this doctrine. Thus the fragments which we have are the remains 
of a distinct literary movement in the Epicurean sect, and should 
be regarded as a literary pronunciamento. The interesting point 
of connection here is that Zeno whom Cicero lauds a stylist was 
the champion of this new view which accepted that part of 
rhetoric which above all others was primarily concerned with 
style rather than with thought. 
Philodemus’ importance as a man of letters in Rome is shown 
again by his relation to the Augustan group, Horace, Vergil, 
Varius, Quintilius. That these poets were at one time strongly 
influenced by the Epicurean philosophy is too well known to 
need mention. But it is only recently that any close connection 
between this group and Philodemus has been shown. To be 
sure there was the allusion to Philodemus at the end of the 
second satire of the first book, but this did not prove anything 
more than that Horace was acquainted with Philodemus’ epi- 
grams. But Korte has discovered amid the almost undecipherable 
fragments of Ilepi xodaxetas the names Ovdpre, Koivrire, Ov| epyiAue, 
‘Opa|ree, showing with great probability that Philodemus was 
acquainted with the Augustan group.'t Still more recently Hen- 
drickson has traced the influence of the technique of an epigram 
of Philodemus on Horace Car. I, 38.17 It may therefore be set 


™ Augusteer bei Philodem, Rhein. Mus. XLV (1890), pp. 172-177. 
“An Epigram of Philodemus and two Latin Congeners. Amer. Journ. 
Phil. XX XTX (1918) pp. 27-43. 


252 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


down with a reasonable degree of certainty that Philodemus 
was a prominent figure in the literary circles of Rome of the 
late republic and early empire; that his interest in polite letters 
distinguished him as it had his master Zeno from the rest of the 
Epicureans, and that his interest in literature is reflected in the 
doctrines of the Rhetorica. 

The latter works have attracted less attention than they de- 
serve. The philosophical works were naturally the first to be 
attacked in the hope of supplementing our scanty knowledge of 
Epicurean doctrines. But little that was satisfactory was done 
on the Rhetorica until Sudhaus’ edition.’® In this he collected 
all the fragments of the Rhetorica, using the Oxford and Nea- 
politan copies, and supplementing these with his own examina- 
tion of the papyri. His results were little short of astounding, 
when the nature of his material is taken into consideration, 
though unfortunately for the general reader or even for the 
specialist in this field they are almost nullified by glaring faults 
in arrangement and presentation. He has clearly established the 
existence of two works, a ‘Yrouvypatixdy in one book, and Ilepi 
pytopixns in seven. ‘The relationship between these works is as 
follows: The Hypomnematicon is the precursor of the Tepi 
pytopixns. It was intended for private circulation, to propound 
to his own immediate associates at Rome his peculiar views on 
rhetoric, at that time a subject of lively interest and active debate 
in the Graeco-Roman world. These views were not original 
with Philodemus; he had derived them from his master, Zeno, 
and their source may be still higher in the Epicurean school. 
But Zeno was known to Roman audiences mainly through the 
intermediary of Romans who like Cicero had attended his lec- 
tures at Athens, and Philodemus may have found that his doc- 
trines had the appearance of novelty at Rome. The pamphlet 
circulated anonymously, though we must suppose that the author- 
ship was an open secret, at least in Rome. By accident the book 
fell into the hands of an Epicurean of Rhodes, who scented 


* Spengel published the fourth book in 1837, an admirable piece of work 
considering the scanty nature of his materials. Gros published the 
Rhetorica from the Oxford copies with Latin translation and commentary 
in 1840. 


~. 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 253 


heresy, and recognizing the views as peculiar to Zeno, assumed 
that he was the author, and published a reply. This attack led 
Philodemus to return to the subject of rhetoric with a reply to 
his critic, and a restatement of his views now expanded to the 
seven books On Rhetoric. Naturally, then, the two works cover 
much of the same ground, and seem to have followed the same 
general plan. The Hypomnematicon contained criticisms of the 
arguments for and against rhetoric, such as we find at length 
in the second book Uepi fntopsxqs, and again in the seventh book. 
From this section we have a considerable group of quotations 
from Diogenes cf Babylon who appears also in the seventh book. 
We have also small fragments of the criticism of Nausiphanes 
and the Peripatetics, which forms the bulk of our fragments 
of the sixth book. There was also a discussion of the nature 
of “art,” parallel to that of book I. But most important of all 
we have in col. XX XIX ff. a full statement of the contents of 
the constructive part of the work with Philodemus’ definition of 
rhetoric."* 
The Ilept fytopuxjs may be briefly outlined as follows: 


” 


Book I General introduction. Nature of “art. 
Book II Is rhetoric an art? Criticism of arguments for and against. 
Philodemus’ view that sophistic i. e. epideixis is an art, 
but all other varieties of rhetoric, as well as politics, are not. 

Book III The sophistical school does not produce statesmen; in fact the 
sophistical training is often harmful. 

Book IV Criticism in detail of the claims of rhetoric, apparently as 
given in some manual. Philodemus denies the ability of 
the sophistical schools to teach a beautiful style; complains 
of their faulty treatment of metaphors; denies the claim of 
the sophists to universal knowledge, and their assumption of 
moral superiority. 

Book V_ Detailed discussion of the disadvantages of rhetoric, with a 
comparison of the wretched life of the rhetor with the 
happy life of the philosopher. 

Book VI Attacks on philosophical schools which advocated the study 
of rhetoric. The surviving fragments deal with Aristotle 
and Nausiphanes. 

Book VII Criticism of the Stoic attitude toward rhetoric. Further criti- 
cism of Aristotle. Comparison of rhetoric and philosophy. 


“Tn this paragraph we have followed in the main the conclusion stated 
by Sudhaus in the note on p. 44 of his Supplementum. 


Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


ty 
on 
= 


It will be seen that the work assumes a twofold character. 
On the one hand it is a discussion of the moral and educational 
value of rhetoric, and is a counterpart of the encomia of rhetoric 
prefixed to manuals such as we find in the Rhetores Graeci. On 
the other hand it is a discussion of a minor point in Epicurean 
philosophy, an attempt to interpret the Epicurean creed to meet 
the changed conditions of the time. The latter side was the im- 
mediate occasion for the work, and the one into which Philo- 
demus throws his whole soul. But by the perversity of history 
it is his criticism of other works on rhetoric which is of most 
interest to us. For in the hazy condition of our knowledge of 
the development of rhetoric subsequent to Aristotle, and of the 
educational conflict between the rhetoricians and the philoso- 
phers, any additional facts assume an importance quite out of 
proportion to their original value. Nausiphanes, Alexinus, Diog- 
enes of Babylon, these are names which Philodemus has made 
more than mere names. One who wishes to see how far Philo- 
demus is of service to the history of literature should carefully 
study Philodemus in connection with the first chapter of von 
Arnim’s Dio von Prusa, and note how much of our still meager 
history of the period depends on Philodemus. 

If the most valuable portions of the Rhetorica are the quota- 
tions from earlier authors, the unique part is his definition of 
‘“sophistic rhetoric.” His discussion of the value of rhetoric and 
its place in the educational system is concerned first with the 
definition of “Art.” After a lengthy refutation of the views 
of others he presents his own definition, which he claims is sanc- 
tioned by usage, and not formed, as those of his opponent have 
been, for the purpose of proving the doctrines of some school. 
An art, he tells us, is a habit of action resulting from the obser- 
vation of certain fundamental principles which apply to the 
majority of cases. The art produces a result that is beyond the 
power of those who have not studied it. Moreover, it produces 
this result regularly and surely, and not at random."® 

On the basis of this definition he examines the claims of 
rhetoric, and makes a threefold division. These three divisions, 
he says, are not the ordinary divisions, tavyyvpuxdv, roAutiKdv, Suxav- 
uxov, but coduorixy pytopixn, generally called by him simply codu- 


S 1eGo) 2 — Suppl...35, I. 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 2 


U1 
U1 


oTiky, pytopixy in the strict sense including forensic and delibera- 
tive oratory, and zodutixy or political science.'® Of. these three 
only cogiorixy is used in a technical sense, which apparently 
originated with the Epicureans, and is restricted to the study 
of the principles of composition, with special reference to epi- 
deictic oratory. It is placed on a level with poetics and might 
be called the art of prose writing. I, 122, 29 = Suppl. 61, 12. 


Kat dAnGeav 7 codurtiKy pyropiKyn Téxvn Tis eoTW TeEpi TE Tas emibE(EELs 
olas avTot TowdvTal, Kai Tas TOV Aoywv dwbecEs, olwy aiTol ypaphovoly 
Te Kal oxedialovow. PDapev toivey TO peOodikov ew aityv, ob Todd de 
Kabdmrep ovde TV ToUNTUKHY. 

To the other two branches, pyropixy in the narrow sense and 
mourn, he denies the position of an art. They lack the essential 
characteristic, namely a definite set of principles which can be 
imparted from teacher to pupil. Quite the contrary, ability in 
oratory and politics is the result of practice and experience. 
The successful public speaker may be compared to a good mer- 
chant, a hunter, or even a successful thief.17 All succeed, how- 
ever, as a result of their own skill based on experience, and their 
occupations cannot be called arts in the sense in which we speak 
of music as an art. 

Similarly cofuorys means an epideictic orator, and by a natural 
enlargement of its semantic area, a teacher of epideictic oratory ; 
and codgucrevey means to teach or practice epideictic. This mean- 
ing of “sophist” is quite different from that current down to 
the fourth century. The development of meaning has been 
worked out by Brandstatter,S and need not be repeated here 
except so far as it affects our immediate discussion. Brand- 
statter infers from the fragments of Philodemus that Epicurus 
was the first to use ‘“‘sophist” and related words in this sense, 
and that it became a part of the technical vocabulary of the 
school in the writings of Hermarchus and Metrodorus. But 
an examination of the passages on which he based his conclusion 
(i 78; 2-10; “78, 19-85, 19; 85, 27-89; /10;) P20, IO; 120, 22) 
will show that Philodemus nowhere quotes from Epicurus an 
example of the use of the word. The passages are in some 


=i UCI eager, 


‘ E 74, TS: 
* Leipziger Studien, 1894. 


256 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


parts hopelessly corrupt, but the general sense is clear enough. 
It seems that Epicurus recognized epideictic oratory as an 
art, and made the distinction between this and practical oratory 
which Philodemus makes. That he applied the term “sophistic” 
to epideictic oratory cannot be proved from Philodemus. The 
latter is arguing against an unnamed opponent who claimed to be 
unable to find in Epicurus a statement that sophistic was an art. 
But the mere fact that Philodemus is compelled to argue that 
Epicurus meant this, instead of quoting a short sentence that 
would settle the question definitely, seems to point to the con- 
clusion that the statement was not to be found in Epicurus 
except by implication. As to Metrodorus the case is simpler, 
for we know the title Ilpés tots cogioras,’® in which sophist prob- 
ably had the meaning which it bears in Philodemus. We might 
conjecture that this work was the first in which the word was 
regularly used in the technical sense. The question is doubtful, 
however, for there is the possibility that cogisorns was used in a 
different sense. Diogenes Laertius (x, 26) concludes his list of 
Epicureans with the words, Zjvev & 6 SWwvios axpoarns *AzrohA0dwpov, 
rodvypados avip* Kal Anuytpios 6 éruxAnbets Adxwv, Avoyevyns 6’ 6 Tapaevs 
6 Tas émAexTovs TxXOAas ovyypaas, Kal ’"Qpiwy Kat dAAor ods of yvyovoL 
’Ezixovperon copiotas aroKaXovow. 

The difficulty arises first in regard to the antecedent of ovs. 
Is it a@\Ao or Demetrius, Diogenes, Orion and others? It is 
tempting to reason thus: Zeno invented this meaning of cogvoriKy 
and goduiorys; he with the others mentioned with him, and Philo- 
demus formed a distinct group of Epicureans noted for their 
contention that sophistic was an art, and called sophists in deri- 
sion by orthodox Epicureans. But two objections arise to this 
interpretation; Zeno was probably head of the school; if so he 
was presumably orthodox. In the second place it is probable 
that this list in Diogenes comes from Philodemus’ ovvragis rév 
diroodduv. If that is so the last clause ovs—dazoxadovow cannot 
refer to Zeno, for Philodemus would not reproach his master 
with heterodoxy. Consequently the identity of those called soph- 
ists remains doubtful, and there is always the possibility that 
the word may have had two different applications in the Epi- 
curean school, and that Metrodorus used one and Zeno the other. 


© Diog. J.aert. X, 24. 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 257 


But in the absence of definite proof it is perhaps safe to say 
that Zeno used the word in the same general sense as Metro- 
dorus, but with greater precision.” 

This peculiar use of cogiorys and the theory of the artistic 
nature of codiorixy colors the whole of Philodemus’ argument, 
and should be kept in mind in reading the following pages. It 
may not be amiss to discuss at this point some other words which 
are used in peculiar senses by Philodemus, and which require 
some comment if the translation is not to be misunderstood. 
téxvyn is (1) an art, craft or profession, or (2) the formal state- 
ment of the principles of the same, i. e., a manual or handbook. 
The English would undoubtedly be better if I had varied my 
translation between craft and profession, but where so much of 
the argument depends on the meaning of this one word I have 
thought it best to have a uniform translation at the cost of a 
certain artificiality of expression. [t was almost imperative, 
also, to use a word which would permit of a derivative denoting 
agent, for rexvirys is used constantly of one who has mastered a 
rex. “Art” and “Artist” give the necessary pair in English, 
and if it is borne in mind that in this work “art” means any 
activity or occupation which is reducible to rule, and “artist” 
anyone who pursues such an occupation, no confusion will 
result.21.| The opposite of texvirns is drexvos which I have rendered 


”° See the discussion in Korte, Metrodori Epicurei Fragmenta, Jahrb. f. 
cl. Phil. Suppl. XVII (1890), p. 552 ff. 

The history of téyvn and ‘art’ and their derivatives affords interesting 
parallels. ‘Art’ in its largest meaning in English has nearly as extensive 
a semantic area as Téxvy in Greek; “profession” which is included under 
réxvn is not wholly included under art in English; e. g. medicine is either 
an art or a profession, but the ministry is not an art. Artist and Texvirns, 
theoretically equivalent, have both undergone a narrowing process; 
texvirns came to mean an actor, while artist suggests primarily a painter. 
Both became terms of compliment, and both were extended to cover fields 
of activity which caused the more respectable artists to blush at the 
misuse of the word. A passage from R. G. White, Words and their Uses, 
forms an interesting parallel to some words of Philodemus, “Artist has 
been beaten out so thin that it covers almost the whole field of human 
endeavor . . . A cook is an artist; so is a barber; and Goldsmith 
soberly calls a cobbler an artist.” Philodemus I, 59, 19 =Suppl. 30, 7 
Ta 5° ék waparnpjcews Kal Tivos ictopias curyoknuéva Téxvas ) cvvHGera T Ov ‘ENAHvwv 
ob mdvu Te mpooayopever KaTa Tov KUpiov Tpbmov GAN ~oTw bre KaTaxpwuévn, KabaTeEp 
évlore kal Tovs év Tots Gavuaci cuvtévous Texvitas Kael kal 76 deit@s EVNa cxloa Kal 


258 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


by “layman,” As the opposition is almost always between the 
trained speaker or lawyer, and one not so trained, this use of the 
word will be natural enough to English readers. “Emory is 
used at times in the same sense as téxvn. At other times there is 
the usual distinction between art and science, a distinction which 
is emphasized by the use of adjectives; Téxvy oroxaotuKy is Op- 
posed to éemoryun mays or éoryxvia. I do not recall seeing téxvy 
Talos. 

‘Pyrwp and its derivatives form another group that is puzzling 
to the translator. The start can be made with pytopexy for which 
the time-honored translation “rhetoric”? must almost necessarily 
be used. But fyrwp causes trouble. As used by Philodemus it 
shifts from orator to teacher of rhetoric, though for the latter 
he sometimes uses pyropixos, and one’s first impulse is to vary 
the translation to suit the shift in meaning. But a twofold 
objection arises: the word “orator’’ does not cover the same 
semantic area as pytwp, even if we exclude from the latter word 
the meaning “professional teacher of speaking.” With us 
“orator” means either a person chosen to speak on a definite 
occasion as in the phrase “orator of the day”? in which case it is 
equivalent to speaker, or a person gifted in speech, as “he was 
a natural orator.” There is nothing in either case to indicate 
that speaking is the man’s habitual occupation. The Greek 
pytopes, however, formed a distinct profession; it covered the 
field which to-day forms part of the fields of the lawyer, the 
preacher, the statesman and the public lecturer. Manifestly 
“orator” fails to cover the semantic area of fytwp. A second 
reason is that in Philodemus there is a constant play between 
pytwop and pytopiky?? which depends for its point entirely on 
etymology, and this is lost if we translate by “orator” and “rhe- 
toric.” I have therefore translated pyrop throughout as “rhetor,” 
preferring the awkwardness of using a word hardly acclimated in 
English to the loss of the point of many of Philodemus’ sentences. 
pytopixds [ render by “‘rhetorician” in the sense of teacher of 
rhetoric. 


cuvbetvar kal évedpedoal Tiva Tovnpas Texvixov éyer kal Téxvas Tas év Tals Kwumdlats 
kal wav TO ToUTOLsS TapamAnowv, Kal uyv T@ kal waparypynow Kal doxnow Téxvnv 
mpocayopevery TA TetaTa TOv ev TO Blw Téxvas mpocayopevorres ovK Av POdvouuer. 

* See II, 215, col. XI for a case of the double meaning of pjrwp which 
is easily lost in translation. 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 259 


mohitixy and zodutixos should strictly speaking be rendered so 
as to keep the etymological connection, e. g. “politics” or 
“political science” and “politician.” However as zodutixos has 
none of the opprobrium which sometimes attaches to politician 
in English, I have rendered it by “statesman.” There is not in 
the case of this pair the reason for keeping the etymological con- 
nection plain which we have noticed in the case of pytwp-pyropikés.- 

The date of the Rhetorica cannot be determined with exact- 
ness. It was written in the lifetime of Zeno, if we may be allowed 
to interpret strictly the present tenses of the paragraph referring 
to him; Suppl. p. 44 ff.; p. 45, 1. 1: 6 wap’ qpdv éotw Zyvov, 
p. 48, 1. 13: ris éxeiv’ dvaypaias éotiv; Od Zyvwv ye. Zeno’s dates 
cannot be determined exactly; he was born as early as 150, was 
teaching and apparently head of the school in Athens in 79/8, and 
was succeeded by Phaedrus shortly thereafter, if Phaedrus was 
succeeded by Patro in 70/69.?* If we place Zeno’s death at 75 
we should have the inferior limit for the Rhetorica. One other 
point may be taken into consideration; the Ilepi pytopixjs was 
addressed to a certain young Gaius (@ Taie wat, I, 223, 5). This 
would suggest that Philodemus was at Rome, acting as tutor in 
some Roman family. The beginning of Philodemus’ Roman 
sojourn may be approximated as follows: he met Piso when the 
latter was adolescens.** If we place the limit of adolescentia at 
30, the acquaintance must have begun before 71, as Piso was 
born at least as early as 101. That would make it possible for 
Philodemus to have been in Rome in the seventies, and so to 
have addressed the Rhetorica to his pupil Gaius before the death 
On Zenon! (circ. )75.7° 

It is almost paradoxical to pass judgment on the style of an 
author from whom we have scarcely a single sentence that has_ 
remained entire. Much of the obscurity is undoubtedly due to 


* We really are not certain about the date of the succession of Patro. 
Phaedrus was contemporary with Zeno and probably did not long survive 
him. The only certainty is that Patro became head of the school before 
51 B. C.,, v. Cic. Ad Fam. XIII, 1. For a fuller discussion of the dates v. 
Zeller III, 1 (3rd ed.), pp. 373-5, Susemihl II, p. 261 ff. 

—Gic, in Pis. 28, 68. 

* Comparetti on slightly different grounds arrives at a conclusion 
regarding the limits of Philodemus’ literary activity which admits of the 
date given above for the publication of the Rhetorica. v. La Biblio- 
theque de Philodéme, Mélanges Chatelain, p. 128. 


260 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


unskillful emendation, and many of the half sentences would 
be plain enough if we only knew how the sentence began. Any- 
one who will take the pains to study the articles in which Sudhaus 
first published his reconstructions, and notice the steps by which 
the difficulties were cleared away year after year will appreciate 
the fact that it is dangerous to dogmatize about Philodemus’ 
obscurity, for a single brilliant discovery may affect the inter- 
pretation of a whole book. For example, after Sudhaus had 
published his first volume, he discovered that Papyri 1015 and 
832 were the upper and lower parts respectively of the .same 
papyrus. The result was the complete reconstruction of the 
sixth book in his second volume, and a brilliant contribution to 
the history of rhetoric by von Arnim. But allowing for the 
difficulties arising from the fragmentary condition of the papyrus, 
many others still remain. Chief among these is the philosophic 
jargon of the Epicurean school, and the habit, also due to 
philosophy, of preferring abstract to concrete, and the impersonal 
to the personal. There is a dreary wordiness and prolixity which 
is so often characteristic of both philosopher and rhetorician in the 
period of decline. Characteristic, too, of the period is the hair- 
splitting, the page after page devoted to quibbles over the meaning 
of “art,” “rhetoric,” “sophistic,” and the dozen other trifles with 
which the scholastic age of Greek literature amused itself. 
Philodemus’ interest in expression did not carry him into the 
refinements of Atticism; his Greek is the typical literary Koine 
of the day, and he distinctly deprecates any attempt at imitation 
of the ancients and the cultivation of a special or artificial dic- 
tion.*® His theory of style is that there is no style except the 
ordinary language of every day intercourse.2* A clear use of 
this provides a better means of expression than is offered by 
all the schools of rhetoric. Thus while renouncing all theories 
of style he commits himself to a very far-reaching theory. Free- 
dom from the frills of rhetoric he certainly attained; one could 
wish that we might say as much of the clarity of his style. From 
the smooth, flowing style of the epigrams we might expect a 
similar ease and sharpness of definition in the Rhetorica. It 
is however wholly lacking even in the portions which are nearest 


CAMELS 99 66 


*T, 151, 6: “Emera el uev unde els Fv puotkds Kadds byos, tows dv Hv dvayKatoy 
dyanrdy Tov kara Oéua : viv 6€ brdpyovros, AO\wv 7d mapiévras ad’rov éx’ éxetvoy 
KaTavray, 


711 ;/153, coluex. 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 261 


to a state of complete preservation. It is an interesting com- 
mentary on the artificiality of the epigram that a second-rate 
writer like Philodemus can attain comparative success in it while 
failing to write a readable prose style. Philodemus’ mastery of 
the epigrammatic style is purely formal; nowhere does he show 
any great originality of thought; but his style is uniformly lucid 
and pleasing. In his prose, partly as a result of his theory of 
style, partly as a consequence of his rambling method of thought, 
he never attained such a degree of excellence. Even after 
making due allowance for the obscurity caused by imperfect 
restoration, it is hardly possible that he will ever be found to 
deserve the characterization of his master, Kat vopoa Kat €ppyvetoa 
says. 

The translation follows closely the edition of Sudhaus in three 
volumes ; Philodemi Volumina rhetorica edidit Dr. Siegfried Sud- 
haus, Leipzig, B. G. Teubner 1892, vol. II, 1896, Supplementum, 
1895. As the fragments are presented in some confusion by 
Sudhaus, I have appended a schematic arrangement of the 
contents according to the divisions of Philodemus’ work. 


Philodemus Sudhaus: Hubbell 
Book I I, 1-12= Suppl. 3-8 265-267 
Book II I, 13-18 267-293 

19-123 = Suppl. 11-61 

123-136 

136-137 = Suppl. 61-62 

137-146 

II, 65-130 

Book III v. Sudhaus’ Intro. P. XXXVI 203 
Book IV I, 147-225 i 293-305 
Book V II, 131-167 305-318 

I, 225-270 

Book VI I, 270-289 318-332 
I, 289-325; revised in II, 1-64 

Book VII TI, 325-385 332-341 

Frag. Incerta II, 168-105 341-346 

Hypomnematicon II, 196-303 346-364 


Corresponding pages in the Sudhaus edition and in this trans- 
lation. 


Sudhaus Hubbell 
i. 1-140 265-286 
147-225 203-305 
225-385 311-341 


(289-325 revised in II, 1-64) 


to 
fo) 
tN 


Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


Sudhaus Hubbell 
if, tod 321-332 
65-130 286-293 
131-167 305-311 
168-195 341-346 
196-303 346-364 


The following bibliography aims to include editions of the 
Rhetorica, and journal articles which deal with Philodemus’ 
literary relations and with critical and exegetical questions 
raised by the Rhetorica. No attempt has been made to include 
reference to Philodemus in the ordinary encyclopaedias, or 
histories of literatvre and philosophy. 


LIFE AND LITERARY RELATIONS. 

Cronert W., Die Epicureer in Syrien. Jahrb. d. Ost. arch. Instituts, 
X (1907) pp. 145-153. 

Hillscher A., Hominum litteratorum Graecorum ante Tiberii mortem in 
urbe Roma commoratorum historia critica. Commentatio ex supple- 
mentis annalium philologicorum (pp. 355-444) seorsum expressa. 
Leipzig, 1891. 

- Korte A., Augusteer bei Philodem. Rhein. Mus. XLV (1890) pp. 172-177. 

Stemplinger E., Strabons literar-historische Notizien. Munich, 1894. 


EDITIONS OF THE RHETORICA. 


Herculanensium Voluminum quae supersunt XI tom. Naples, 1793-1855. 
Vol. VII did not appear. The rhetorical fragments are in vols. IV, 
V and XI. 

Herculanensium Voluminum quae supersunt collectio altera. Tom. I-XI 
Naples, 1862-76. The rhetorical fragments are in vols. III-XI. 
Herculanensium Voluminum partes I, IJ, Oxford 1824, 1825. The rhetor- 

ical fragments are in vol. IT. 

Bassi D., Frammenti inediti di opere di Filodemo (sept wovorxhs, repli fear, 
mepl pytopixjs) in papiri Ercolanesi. Rivista di Filologia XXXVIII, 
3, Pp. 321-356. Unimportant new fragments. May be of Philo- 
demus; at any rate seem to discuss the same questions. 

Diibner F., Philodemi Fragmenta (Philologis Gothae conventum agentibus 
s. p. d. Fr. Dittbner), Paris, 1840. 

Spengel L. Philodemi de Rhetorica. Librum Quartum ex voluminibus 
Herculanensibus Oxonii MDCCCXXV_ excussis ed. Leonardus 
Spengel. In Abhand. d. Minch. Akad. Phil. Classe, II Thi. 1 Abth. 
1837, DP. 207-303. 

Gros E., Philodemi epi pyropexjs. Ex Herculanensi papyro lithographice 
Oxonii excusa restituit, latine vertit, dissertatione de Graeca elo- 
quentia et rhetorica notitiaque de Herculanensibus voluminibus 
auxit, annotationibus indicibusque instruxit E. Gros. Adiecti sunt 
duo Philodemi libri de rhetorica Neapoli editi. Paris, 1840. The 
fourth book. 


= ee ._ Je 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 263 


Sudhaus S., Philodemi volumina rhetorica edidit Siegfried Sudhaus. 2 
vols. Leipzig, 1892, 1896. 
Supplementum. Leipzig, 1895, with the title 
Pidodyjuou rep! pynropixjs A’ B’. The introduction is largely by L. Rader- 
macher, entitled, ‘“Critolaus und die Rhetorik.” 


USEFUL ACCOUNTS OF THE DISCOVERY AND DECIPHERING OF THE ROLLS. 


Comparetti D. and de Petra G. La Villa Ercolanese dei Pisoni. Turin, 
1883. Contains p. 91 ff. a “Catalogo generale dei Papiri Ercolanesi 
redatto dal Dr. Emidio Martini.” 

Mommsen T. Inschriftsbiisten. Archae. Zeit. XXXVIII (1880) 32. . 

Scott W. Fragmenta Herculanensia; a descriptive catalogue of the 
Oxford copies of the Herculanean rolls together with the texts of 
several papyri accompanied by facsimiles, edited with notes and 
introduction. Oxford, 1885. 


PALAEOGRAPHY AND LANGUAGE, 


Comparetti D. La Bibliotheque de Philodéme. In Mélanges offerts a 
M. Emile Chatelain, 19Io. 

Cronert W. Falschungen in den Abschriften der Herculanensischen 
Rollen. Rhein. Mus. LIII (1898) pp. 585-595. 

Cronert Guil. Quaestiones Herculanenses. Leipzig, 1898. 

Cronert W. Kolotes und Menedemos. Texte und Untersuchungen zur 
Philosophen-und Literaturgeschichte. Leipzig, 1906. 

Cronert W. Memoria Graeca Herculanensis. Leipzig, 1903. 

Cronert W. Die Ueberlieferung des Index Academicorum. Hermes, 
XXXVIII (1903) pp. 357-405. 

Glatzel A. De optativi apud Philodemum, Strabonem, Pseudo-Longinum 
usu. Diss. Breslau, 1913. 

Grein E. L. My for ot before Lucian. Studies in honor of Gildersleeve. 
1902, p. 472. 

Schmid W. Der Attizismus in seinen Hauptvertretern von Dionys von 
Halicarnassus bis auf den zweiten Philostratus. Stuttgart, 1887- 
1897. The references to Philodemus are in parts III and IV. 

Schréfel E. De optativi apud Dionysium Halicarnaseum usu. Diss. 
Breslau, 1900. 

Strathmann G. De hiatus fuga, quam invenimus apud Philodemum Epi- 
cureum. Progr. des Realgymn. Viersen, 1802. 

Wendland P. Berliner Philologischer Wochenschrift XVI (1806) p. 1451. 


CRITICAL AND EXEGETICAL STUDIES. 


von Arnim H. Ein Bruchstiick des Alexinos. Hermes, XXVIII (1893) 
pp. 65-72. 

von Arnim H. Coniectanea in Philodemi Rhetorica. Hermes, XXVIII 
(1893) pp. 150-154. 

von Arnim H. Leben und Werke des Dio von Prusa. Berlin, 1898. — 
Chapter I. 


264 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


von Arnim H. De restituendo Philodemi de rhetorica lib. II]. Progr. 
Rostock 1893. 

Biicheler F. Ante-Diluvianisches aus Philodem. Rhein. Mus. XX (1865) 
pp. 311-314. 

Diibner F. Passages détachés des Papyrus d’Herculanum. Revue de 
Philologie I (1845) pp. 311-323. ‘ 

Fuhr K. Zu griechischen Prosaikern. II] Zu Philodems rhetorischen 
Schriften. Rhein. Mus. LVII (1902) pp. 428-436. 

Gomperz Th. Beitrage zur Kritik und Erklarung griechischen Schrift- 
steller. IV, no. 27 In Sitzungsber. d. phil. hist. Classe d. k. Akad. 
d. Wiss. in Wien CX XII (1890), Wien. 

Gomperz Th. Herculanensia. Zeit. f. d. 6st. Gymn. XXIII (1872) pp. 
24-32. 

Gomperz Th. Die herculanischen Rollen. Zeit. f. d. ost. Gymn. XVI 
(1865) pp. 815-828; XVII (1866) pp. 691-708. 

Gomperz Th. Kritische Bemerkungen. Wiener Studien II (1880) pp. 
T=20,:. nO. 4. 

Gomperz Th. Marginalien. Rhein. Mus. XXXII (1877) pp. 475-478. 

Liers H. Rhetoren und Philosophen im Kampfe um die Staatsweisheit. 
Progr. des. Gymn. Waldenburg, 1888. ° 

Olivier F. De Critolao peripatetico. Diss. Berlin 1895. 

Radermacher L. Studien zur Geschichte der antiken Rhetorik. III Eine 
Schrift tiber den Redner als Queile Ciceros und Quintilians. IV 
Ueber die Anfange des Atticismus. Rhein. Mus. LIV (1899) pp. 
285, 351. 

Sandys J. E. Review of Philodemus ed. Sudhaus vol. I. Class. Rev. IX 
(1895) pp. 358-359. 

Schneidewin W. Studia Philodemea. Diss. Gottingen, 1905. Studies in 
the fifth book. 

Sudhaus S. Alexinos. Rhein. Mus. XLVIII (1893) pp. 152-154. 

Sudhaus S. Aristoteles in der Beurtheilung des Epikur und Philodem. 
Rhein. Mus. XLVIII (1893) pp. 552-564. 

Sudhaus, S. Exkurse zu Philodem. 1. Ein literarischer Streit in der 
epikureischen Schule. 2. Eine Scene aus Epikurs Gastmahl. 3. 
Noch einmal Nausiphanes und Aristoteles bei Philodem. Philo- 
logus LIV (1895) pp. 80-92. 

Sudhaus, S. Neue Lesungen zu Philodem. Philologus LIII (1894) pp. 
I-12. 

Usener H. Epicurea. Leipzig, 1887. 

Usener H. Variae lectionis specimen primum. Jahrb. f. class. Phil. 
CXXXIX (1889) p. 377. 

von Wilamowitz-Mollendorf U. Memoriae Oblitteratae. Hermes XI 
(1876) pp. 291-304. Corrigendum ad Hermae Tom. XI p. 304, 
Hermes XI (1876) p. 515. 

von Wilamowitz-Mollendorf U. Lesefriichte. Hermes XXXIV _ (1899) 
p. 636 f. 


Fhe - 


BOOK I. 


We have five fragments of the first book, one of seven columns, the 
others containing one column each. If we may make a rather large 
generalization from so small a section we might say that the first book 
contained an outline of the whole work. I have therefore reconstructed, 
partly from references, partly by inference the following outline of the 
book. The fragments which we possess come from the latter part of 
the book. 

The first book contained: 


t. Dhe dedication to Gaius. | Ci. I, 223) 5. 
2. A statement of the purpose of the work: to criticize various views 
of rhetoric, 
a. those of its supporters, 
b. those of its opponents, 
c. those of the extreme Epicureans who denied that sophistic 
rhetoric was an art, thus running counter to the doctrines 
of Epicurus, Hermarchus and Metrodorus. Cf. I, 12. 
3. A discussion of the relation of the arts to one another, and of the 
nature of an art, with especial reference to the errors into which both 
supporters and opponents of rhetoric fall. Cf. I, 1, ff. 


First a division of arts and sciences according to the relative necessity 
of natural ability and training (@vo.s and doxnors), 


Some sciences depend entirely on natural ability and need but 
little practice; some accomplish their purpose of and by them- 
selves, granted that the workman has the natural endowment 
common to all the human race; no practice is necessary; some 
do not need natural ability but only practice. 

In the case of some arts, their purpose can be accomplished 
partially and reasonably well by those who have not studied the 
principles of the art; in other cases only the person technically 
trained can succeed. 

Some say that an art must have definite rules, e. g. grammaticé, 
others that an art is merely wisdom or skill (coda), others require 
that it have a definite purpose, e. g. Plato'; others demand that 
it shall tend to improve life.” 


* Gorgias 503E. 
* Possibly Critolaus, cf. Sextus Empiricus Adv. Rhet. 10-12, 20. 


Sudhaus 


ee aly aires, IEW 
== Supplies 


Le ty eit 
= Suppl. 
4, I. 


Dea tt. 


I = Suppl. 


4, 8 


L, 4 Col. 


I = Suppl. 


4, 17: 


Col. III. 


Col. IV. 


266 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


Those who define art fall into the error of expecting that one 
definition will cover all arts (or rather that all arts fulfil equally 
all the requirements of the definition), in order to obtain what 
they call the union of arts (o%vderpnos). Then when they find an 
art which has some characteristic not shared by the others, as is 
frequently the case, they exclude it from the position of an art. 

In the sciences there is frequently an interchange of function: 
two sciences produce the same result. But this does not prove 
that they are not arts.* It is not unheard-of for the same result 
to be accomplished by two arts, and perhaps this is the best way 
of distinguishing the merely useful from the necessary art. 

Objections can be made to most if not all of the arguments 
here mentioned (i. e. in the gap between fr. I and Col. 1). The 
worst class of arguments are those which act as boomerangs and 
demolish the position of the disputant. As far as these argu- 
ments are concerned no one can object to the opponents’ saying 
that there are perfect artists and imperfect ones as well. (It is 
unfair to blame the perfect artist for the failures of his imper- 
fect colleague. But that is what the present critics are doing. 
The end of rhetoric is to persuade in a speech; consequently it 
is idle to mention other means of persuasion, such as beauty. 
If laymen sometimes persuade by means of a speech it does not 
follow that they persuade better or more frequently than the 
trained rhetor.° 

Apart from the aforementioned obscurities you will find that 
many of the arguments overstep the bounds of the facts under 
discussion and are built up on double meanings of words. Many 
of the arguments do not differ in validity, but by a variety of 
examples display the fertility of the inventors. Then, too, in 
these arguments there is a great deal of bare assertion, entirely 
unsupported by argument (dxatdoxevov, KxatacKevy — constructive 
argument ). 


*E. g. Sculpture and music both produce pleasure. 

*Philodemus seems to use émioryun and Téxvn interchangeably. 

°If Philodemus here as elsewhere, notably in Book II, seems to cham- 
pion the cause of Rhetoric it is because he is refuting the arguments 
against rhetoric in order to show that they are inadequate, and that the 
only true answer to the claims of rhetoric comes from the Epicurean 
school. 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 267 


The following error is found in almost all the arguments: they 
assume from the lack of technical treatises at a given time or 
place that no art then existed. But it is hardly to be expected 
that we can find technical works in a period in which the art of 
writing had not been invented. 

Most, if not all, the arguments do not prove what they claim 
to prove even if the premises be granted. For if the art of 
music does not produce the ability to read and write, it may still 
be the art of other things. Similarly if they assume that sophistic 
rhetoric does not produce political science or practical rhetorical 
ability, they are right, but that does not preclude the possibility 
that sophistic is an art.® 

“Just as dialectic is an art, but accomplishes nothing unless 
combined with ethics or physics, so rhetoric is an art, but accom- 
plishes nothing unless combined with politics.” There are many 
other errors in the arguments, but we do not intend to take them 
up in detail. 

Those Epicureans are to be censured who assume that sophistic 
is not an art, and thus run counter to the teachings of Epicurus, 
Metrodorus and Hermarchus, as we shail show later. Such 
Epicureans are almost guilty of parricide.? 


BOOK. IT. 


In the second book Philodemus discusses the question: Is rhetoric an 
art? The fragments fall into two classes. The first consists of one 
papyrus in ten short fragments and a continuous passage of very consider- 
able proportions, contained in Volume One, pages 13-146, most of which 
has been incorporated by Sudhaus in the Supplementum pages 11-62. .-The 
second group consists of many fragments mostly unconnected, collected in 
Volume Two pages 65-130. The content of the first group may be 
expressed schematically as follows: 


°Here we get the first statement of Philodemus’ favorite distinction 
between coguotixy pyropixy on the one hand, and moderexy and €umpaxtos pyropixy 
on the other. 

7 This paragraph gives an interesting glimpse of the passion for ortho- 
doxy which was characteristic of the Epicurean school. It also reveals 
the intensity of the feud between Zeno-Philodemus and the other branch 
of the sect. 


Col. V. 


Col. VI. 


Col] Vike 


268 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


I. Arguments advanced by others. 

1. Arguments against rhetoric refuted. 

2. Arguments in favor of rhetoric refuted. 

3. Criticism of the views of Epicureans on rhetoric. 
II. Philodemus’ constructive arguments. 


The book is thus seen to be a critique of various works about rhetoric. 
The Epicurean triad, Epicurus, Hermarchus and Metrodorus provide most 
of the material for the last two sections. Among the opponents of 
rhetoric to whom prominence is given are Diogenes of Babylon and Crito- 
laus. The work of Critolaus has been discussed by F. Olivier, De Critolao 
Peripatetico, Berlin 1895, and by Radermacher in the introduction to 
Sudhaus’ Supplementum. In general I follow their conclusions, although 
‘I am not prepared to go as far as they do in crediting Critolaus with most 
of the ideas expressed in this book. In the notes I have indicated briefly 
my judgment on the sources of the principal ideas without entering into 
an extended discussion for which the reader is referred to the excursus at 
the end of this volume. 


SECTION I[-1. 
Refutation of arguments against rhetoric. 
Ser Afr-SNy. The arguments are quoted in direct form without introduction, and are 


, 16, fr. IX. followed by a brief criticism. The first is fragmentary but may be recon- 
structed as follows: 


—— 


(a) “The Spartans and Romans expelled rhetors.”” This does 
not prove that it is not an art, for states have expelled physicians, 
musicians and even philosophers.? 


I, 19, Col. I The argument which is criticized at the beginning of column I is miss- 
= Suppl. 11. ing, but must have run somewhat as follows: “An art always produces a 
beneficial result.’* 

But the captain sometimes loses his ship, the 
physician kills his patient. We must either deny that navigation® 
and medicine are arts, or abandon the demand that all arts must 
always be beneficial.* 

(c) “Different arts do not attain the same end, but gram- 


*See note 5 on page 266. 
*Cf. the similar discussion in Sext. Emp. Adv. Rhet. 20-25. It was one 
of the commonplaces of current educational argument; Sextus records. 
>| that it was used by Critolaus, and by the Academics, Clitomachus and. 
. Charmadas; v. Excursus p. 370. 
* For a similar passage cf. Quint. II, 17, 23 ff.; v. Excursus p. 378. 
“Ci, Book I, ir. III. 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 269 


marians and dialecticians attain the end of rhetoric.’ Others 
do persuade, but the end of rhetoric is not to persuade but to 
persuade in a rhetorical speech. The philosopher persuades by 
force of logic, Phryne®’ by her beauty; neither persuades 
rhetorically. 

(d) “An untrained person should not be able to excel one who 
has been trained in an art, but in rhetoric this sometimes occurs.” 
The untrained man may excel the trained man at times in a 
conjectural art (croyaorixy), but never in an exact science. But 
if the layman without experience be compared with a man trained 
in the schools the comparison does not justify the conclusion that 
sophistic and politics are not arts. 

(e) “In other arts the rules are true, in rhetoric they are 
false.”® (The reply is fragmentary but seems to mean) : The same 
statement might be made about philosophy or medicine. In those 
some lay down principles which are not true, but the error of 
some individuals does not prove that the whole subject is not an 
art if properly treated. 

- (f) (a) “The artist does not deny that he is an artist, but the 
rhetor does.” The major premise is false. Some artists do deny 
that they have an art. 

(B) “And yet if the meanest artists do not deny that they have 
an art we should not expect the sophists to deny it.”* But as 
a matter of fact philosophers, geometricians, poets and physicians 
sometimes do deny it, thinking thereby to allay the suspicions of 
those who expect to be deceived. 


®*For Phryne cf. Quint. II, 15, 6 and 9; Athen. XIII, 590, 5901; Sext. 
Emp. Adv. Rhet. 4; Plut. Vit. Hyper. p. 849E. The story runs that 
Phryne was accused of impiety, a capital charge, by one Euthias, and 
defended by her lover Hyperides. When the latter saw that the jury was 
likely to bring in a verdict of guilty he rent Phryne’s robes and exposed 
her breast, and thus won a verdict of acquittal As we see from the 
employment of this illustration by Quintilian in a similar context, this was 
one of the stock arguments against rhetoric. Alciphron seems to be 
answering this argument in Ep. I, 31, Bacchis to Phryne, when he says: 
poe tots Aéyovol cor, Briel pi Tov YXiTwWHLTKOY Tepipnéayévyn TA pacTdpLia Tots 
OikacTais érederéas, ovdev 6 pytwp wpéder, weifov. Kal yap avrd rotro iva év Kayp@ 
yévnral co, 7 éxelvov mapécxe cuvnyopia. 

°For illustrations of the false rules of rhetoric v. Sext. Emp. Adv. 
Rhet. 10-12; Quint. II, 17, 18 ff; v. Excursus, p. 375. 

* This continues the thought of the quotation in the preceding paragraph. 


Ly 19}, 12:it- 


) ET 


Suppl. 12, 6ff. 


AA, Wie at, 


Suppl. 


Toit 


12, 


23 Ante 


Suppl. 13, 
7 ff 


I, 25, 32 ff. 
= Suppl. 14, 
16 ff 


Te2G sary tt. 
— Supple 15; 
6 ff. 


270 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


(y) “They deny that they possess the so-called sophistic 
rhetoric, and say that it is not a separate kind of rhetoric. 
However they do lay claim to the possession of experience in 
practical affairs reduced to a system, and ability to discuss these 
matters, and boast of it; a good example is Demosthenes.” It 
is a disgrace for them to be ashamed of their art. However as 
sophistic offers no system for public speaking, how can it produce 
public speakers ? 

(8) “Therefore it is plain that some criticize the art as having 
no characteristic which distinguishes it from other arts.” In 
the case of other arts, too, which are really or apparently harm- 
ful, some criticize the teachers not for what they profess to know, 
but for what they do not even desire to accomplish. 

(g) “Every artist professes to accomplish a result, the rhetor 
does not profess to persuade.” By no means all artists profess 
to accomplish the end of their art at all times. All who deal 
with conjectural arts, as, for example, physicians and pilots, 
sometimes fail in their purpose. The rhetor does profess to 
accomplish his purpose, which is not to persuade always, but to 
persuade better than one who has not been trained. 

(h) (Fragmentary and obscure.) “Every artist claims the 
province of the art as his own peculiar field (1. e. as belonging 


- to the trained man and him alone); but the earliest speakers 


2753 the 
= Suppl. 55, 
12 ff. 


1b, 27h (Otis — 
Suppl. 15, 
7k 


possessed the power of rhetoric before the art of rhetoric was 
formulated.” On this principle we. have to reject the art of 
medicine because men healed before Asclepius. 

(i) “A rhetor never charges others with lack of art, but with 
being in a state of mind which prevents them from seeing the 
connection of events.” Therefore we must say that rhetoric is 
not a matter of practice or experience.6 For they would have 
claimed the results of practice for themselves. 

(j) “Men spoke better before manuals of rhetoric were written 
than they have since.” The facts are granted, but inasmuch as 
rhetoric is not entirely subject to the rules of art, but demands 
much practice and natural ability, it is not surprising if there 
were once better rhetors than now, just as there were better 


8 For toroplay Sandys in Class. Rev. IX (1895), p. 359, proposes to read 
éumesplav, as Tpx8y and éurepla are coupled in the Gorgias to which Philo- 
demus refers several times. 


7. 2 hn pe 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. ry a 


philosophers. By this reasoning we should have to deny the 
position of an art to medicine and poetics. Then too, one might 
claim that there are good rhetors now. However sophists did 
not flourish before the technical treatises, but the arts were 
introduced by the statesmen, not by those who had made no 
study of the subject; and there are other arts about which 
nothing has been written as is the case in many parts of the 
barbarian world. 


SEcTiIon I-2. 
Refutation of arguments in favor of rhetoric. 


Having now discussed the arguments against rhetoric’s being 
an art we shall now take up the arguments in its favor. 


General criticism of these arguments. 


(a) They assert that it is an art without establishing the pre- 
liminary principles on which their statement rests. 

(b) They fail to see that not only is art required for some 
purposes, but practice is required for others, and think that the 
same training is adequate for sophistic and politics, whereas 
there is no art of the latter. 

(c) If they apply the term “art” to the state of mind adapted 
for making rhetorical speeches, how can this be the property of 
only a few? 

Let us take up the arguments one at a time. 

“Tf the rhetors did not use a method we would not find many 
paying money for their courses.” This argument rests on the 
supposition that rhetoric is an art of politics. This is con- 
tradicted by Epicurus in his treatise [epi ris pytopuxps in which 
he says: “Those who study in the rhetorical schools are deceived. 
They are charmed by the tricks of style, and pay no attention to 
the thought, believing that if they can learn to speak in this 
style they will succeed in the assembly and court of law. But 
when they find that this style is wholly unfitted for practical 
speaking they realize that they have lost their money.” In this 
respect rhetoric may fittingly be compared to the art of prophecy. 

“Not a few who were unable to speak in public have gained 
ability by studying in the rhetorical schools.” But some come 
out of the schools worse than when they went in. And if some 
improve, it may be from other causes which we shall discuss 


“ec 3” 


Ie ZONAL: 

== Suppl 1640 
15 ff. 

Dest, 3 die 
Suppl. 17, 

20 ff. 

eS cee hehiy—— 
Suppl. ro, 

ik pie 


esi ee ake 
= Sttppl. 10, 
ff. 


e) 


I, 40, 18 ff. 
= Supple 2, 


7. th 


I, 42, 17 ff. 
= Suppl 22, 
8 ff. 


272 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


elsewhere; :and we shall also discuss elsewhere why they fre- 
quent the schools. This improvement does not demonstrate that 
rhetoric is an art for it is possible for speakers to improve by 
practice and experience. 

[lf it were not an art] “the majority of the students would 
not become good, but inefficient.” Yet we see at times some 
without art producing more and better speakers than those who 
possess accurate knowledge; this proves that it is not an art. 
Some leave the study of sophistic to the child, and afterward 
give the youth the benefit of association with those who have 
had practical experience in the assembly and courts. Then if 
they succeed they are said to have studied with sophists, and 
the sophists get the credit for giving them the training which 
they have received from another source. 

“Lawyers and statesmen send their sons to the sophists to 
pursue those studies which gave them their ability.” In the first 
place some insist that they wasted the time which they spent in 
study with the sophists, and send their sons to their own 
teacher—the people. However if they do send them to the 
sophists it is because they do not want their sons to be deprived 
of any possible advantage to be obtained at the rhetorical schools, 
but they do not expect the school to produce a trained statesman. 
Some send their sons to the rhetoricians merely for a liberal 
education, putting rhetoric on a par with other studies. 

“As in music and grammar so in rhetoric there is a transmis- 
sion of knowledge from teacher to pupil, and the training is not 
without method.” There may be a transmission of knowledge 
which is not connected with an art but acquired by experience 
and observation. The statement that “the training is not with- 
out method” is mere assertion without any argument to support 
it. If the statement means that sophistic is an art of practical 
speaking it is entirely wrong. (Lacuna.) In publishing tech- 
nical works they are like the Chaldaeans and prophets who give 
out dreams to deceive the people, and are themselves deceived. 
If we grant anything we grant that sophistic is an art; but not 
even those who teach it believe that it is an art of politics. 

[If there were no art of rhetoric] “none of those who speak 
powerfully and intelligently would speak artistically.” We may 
turn the argument around and say that if some speak artistically 
before the court or the assembly the graduates of the schools 


a 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 273 


do not share any of their good qualities. However we may be 
accused of using language loosely and failing to distinguish 
between what comes with art and what without. For we use the 
word “artistic”? in our everyday speech in a loose way, e. g. one 
plays games artistically. 

“On seeing a beautiful statue you would say without argu- 
ment that it was the product of art; you will pass the same 
judgment after investigating the acts of statesmen.” One might 
acknowledge, that the works of the panegyrists are the products 
of art. But inasmuch as the acts of a statesman deal with a 
subject which cannot be reduced to the rules of art how can they 
reveal that they are the products of art. 

“If it were not an art those who have studied it would not 
practice proof (or demonstration). Not only is one who has 
not studied an art unable to do the work of an art, but one who 
has not practiced and observed cannot reap the benefits. By 
studying what pleases the crowd and practicing, one can become 
skilled in politics. This is a strong proof that sophistic is not 
the art of politics.® If it is, let him who has studied the technical 
treatises go before the people and speak! 


SEcTION [-3. 
Criticism of the views of Epicureans on rhetoric. 


The Epicureans who claim that rhetoric is an art of writing 
speeches and delivering epideictic orations make the error of 


*Here Philodemus seems to be attacking “sophistic” which he else- 
where admits as an art. The inconsistency is only apparent, however, as 
will be plain if we examine closely the meaning of “sophistic’ as defined 
by Philodemus. The “sophists” are in his language the professional 
teachers of rhetoric, and sophistic is the subject taught in these schools. 
This subject matter is called “rhetoric” by those who teach it, and it is 
claimed that it trains for deliberative and forensic oratory, and therefore 
is an art. This Philodemus denies. The ability to persuade in a speech 
whether in law court or in public assembly, he says, is the result of natural 
endowment and facility acquired by practice; it must be acquired by each 
individual and cannot be set down in the form of rules and imparted from 
teacher to pupil; hence it cannot be called an art. In so far, then, as the 
professors of rhetoric attempt to teach the principles of public speaking 
and the laws of politics with a view to producing statesmen, they fail, for 
sophistic is not an art of politics. Later he sets the limits of sophistic— 
it is the art of epideixis and nothing more. 


I, 44, 161f 
Suppl. 23, 
Bate 


~ 


I, 45, 13 ff. 
== Suppl. 23; 
20 ff. 


Age. Efe 
Suppl. 24, 
10 ff. 


hao; ratte: 
= Supply 25; 
D5iit. 


274 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


applying the term rhetoric to what should properly be called 
sophistic. Those who admit that sophistic is an art, but deny 
that there is an art of forensic and deliberative oratory because 
sophistic is not the art of these branches, have failed to prove 
that there is no art of forensic and deliberative oratory. There 
may be a method of these branches; but all they have shown is 
that some do succeed by means of natural ability and experience 
without the aid of rhetoric. Nor have they established beyond a 
doubt, as they should, that sophistic is the art of epideictic. The 
treatise on rhetoric ascribed to Polyaenus we have already shown 
to be spurious. 

Those who say it is an art, but requires ability and practice, 
not to acquire it but to attain the end completely, have utterly 
failed. They have not made the division between the different 
parts of rhetoric (i. e. sophistic and practical rhetoric) which 
was made by Epicurus and his immediate successors. Epicurus 
demonstrated that sophistic is an art of writing speeches and 
delivering epideictic orations but is not the art of forensic or 
deliberative oratory; accordingly they say that sophistic is an 
art; his successors likewise have said that there is no art of 
politics. They certainly leave no place for any science of politics. 

Moreover their statement that ability and practice are needed 
to learn the art of sophistic is false, or we must make the same 
statement about philosophy. Their illustration from the art of 
grammar turns against them. For natural ability is required for 
rhetoric just as much as it is asa foundation for grammar. In the 
case of grammar natural ability and practice are required in order 
to acquire the knowledge of the subject, not to attain the end. 
Consequently if rhetoric is similar to grammar we must admit 
that ability and practice are needed to acquire rhetoric. When 
they say that ability is required for delineation, for making 
suitable gestures, etc., and experience is needed to judge the 
proper occasion for speaking, what have they left for art? They 
ought to show what is needed to acquire the art if ability and 
practice are not needed. 

Those are wrong who claim that rhetoric is not an art on the 
assumption that an art must have method and a transmission of 
definite knowledge, if on the other hand they allow medicine 
which is conjectural to be an art. 


z eh ae ae - 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 275 


(a) Their expression e tis zpoe/Anpe assumes that one can define 
art as one chooses.*® 

(b) While criticizing those who do not make proper divisions, 
they fail to differentiate between the several parts of rhetoric. 
(c) Politics is an art according to their grouping of the sciences 
and this is false. For it has no method, nor is it even a con- 
jectural art. This can be proven by passages from Epicurus 
and Metrodorus. (Some of which are quoted.) 

(d) It is stupid to say that the rhetors have observed the ele- 
ments which generally persuade, and have reduced them to a 
system, and that we persuade by use of prooemium and narrative 
and the other parts of an oration. 

A fourth class'! present arguments which are a combination of 
the last two, and are open to the same objections. Their defini- 
tion of art is “a state of training acquired as a result of observa- 
tion, by which the proposed end is obtained generally and with 
reasonable probability.” This removes the distinctive character- 
istic of an art which is its method and general principles applying 
to the individual cases. The practical skill acquired by observa- 
tion is not called an art by the Greeks except that sometimes in a 
loose use of language people call a clever woodchopper an artist. 
If we call observation and practice art we should include under 
the term all human activity. 

They say that politics is not an art, and yet they claim that 
rhetoric i. e. wodAutixy pytopixy is helpful in practical life. How 
can rhetoric be called an art when it does not help the artist but 
sometimes makes him inferior to the layman. Dialectic and 
eristic may be arts by their definition, but in differentiating 
between them and rhetoric they prove that rhetoric has no 
method. The other differences which they point out all go to 
show that rhetoric is not an art. These points of difference are 
(1) when it contributes anything it is something insignificant 
and accidental; (2) it is not necessary, a layman can do as well 


* Philodemus has in mind in this criticism his purpose to base his judg- 
ment of rhetoric on the definition of réxvn accepted by usage. Cf. such 
passages as I, 69, 2= Suppl. 35, 1: @oTw rolvuy cai Néyerau mapa Tots“ EAXAnow * 
I, 590, 19 = Suppl. 30, 7 ff. 7 cvvjdea rSv “ENAjvwr - I, 68, 7 = Suppl. 34, 14; 
KaTa Thy cvvnbeav. 

* Possibly these were followers of Diogenes of Tarsus, who derived 
their arguments from his ’Emt\exro: Zxodal. 


I, 57, 23 ff. 
= Suppl. 20, 
15 ff. 


276 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


as an artist; (3) its principles are easily acquired; (4) it depends 
largely on practice and memory. In short rhetoric has no method. 

I, 64, 11 ff. Bromius in his discussion of the arts passes over sophistical 

ie UPD. 3; rhetoric on the ground that it is not regarded as an art either by 
people in general or by Epicurus. The only art that he will 
allow in this connection is politics. How can he do this when 
sophistic is an art and is so considered by the leaders of our 
school? If he considers sophistic to be no art why does he not 
prove his statement? How can he make the claim that the 
good statesman has calculated the means of arousing the emo- 
tions, and of persuasion, and uses these continually? Any suc- 
cess which the speakers attain they attain because of practice, 
but they do not succeed universally. Furthermore, his statement 
that the technical treatises of the rhetoricians are not entirely 
barren is in direct contradiction to the teachings of Epicurus 
who says that all such treatises are useless for producing the 
political faculty. 


Secrion II. 
Philodemus’ theories about rhetoric. 


I. 68 1ff— We shall now present our own views under the following 
Suppl. 34, heads: 
Tear, 


(a) Definition of art according to usage. 

(b) Epicurean doctrine declares that sophistic rhetoric is an art. 
(c) Sophistic is an art of epideixis and writing of speeches, but 
not of forensic and deliberative oratory. 

(d) Politics depends on investigation and practice, but has none 
of the essentials of an art. 


SeEcTION II-a. 
Definition of ‘art? 


An art, as the term is commonly used, is a state or condition 
resulting from the observation of certain common and elementary 
principles, which apply to the majority of cases, accomplishing 
such a result as cannot be attained by one who has not studied 
it, and doing this regularly and certainly and not by conjecture. 
For the moment we may leave out of the discussion whether or not 
a looser use of the word sanctions the inclusion under the heading 
‘art’ of all occupations depending wholly on practice. This 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 277 


definition applies both to the exact sciences like grammar and 
music which have certain definite rules, and to the conjectural 
which are in possession of certain common elements affecting’’ 
individual cases, although these common elements may not have 
been completely mastered, and the result may not be accomplished 
always but only more frequently than by those who do not possess 
the art. 

(There follows a passage which cannot be restored.) 

If rhetoric has no method it is not an art. We apply the terms 
‘experience,’ ‘observation,’ ‘practice’ when one has failures 
as well as successes; but we never call this art, for the essence 
of art is to accomplish the result always. 

[Another lacuna; apparently, A dancer] has observed the 
proper way of producing a beautiful effect, i. e. how to stand, 
how to walk, etc., but he has no method or elementary principles 
to impart as has the musician. The same statement applies to 
acrobats. If we class these occupations as arts we shall include 
practically everything. To sum up; these which we now say 
are arts we say have a certain character which is possessed by 
grammar and sculpture; and those which we deny are arts lack 
this character and are characterized by observation. On the basis 
of this definition we declare sophistic to be an art and politics not. 


Section I[I-b. 


Epicurean doctrine declares that sophistic is an art. 


We now turn to the statement: We are not responsible for 7 _. s6 ¢ 
the statement that sophistic is an art and that politics is dependent = Suppl. 38, 


on observation and practice, but this comes from the founders 
of our sect, not from us.t® I shall show where in the works of 
Epicurus Zeno found the expression of this doctrine. In the 
first place what would one make of the continual use by Epicurus 


“There is a difference between the principles of the exact arts or sci- 
ences and those of the conjectural; of the former it is said that they 
accomplish the result did Tivos maparnpjoews oroixelwy Tivdy dinkdyTwy dia 
Thebvwv Tov KkaTd wépos - of the latter that they possess Kowdy Tivwy dia- 
TELvovTwY Eis TO KATA [LEpos. 

“By jets Philodemus means himself and his master Zeno. They had 
been engaged in a controversy with another group of Epicureans who dis- 
puted the claim that Epicurus considered sophistic an art. 


14 ff. 


, 26 ff 


I, 78, 19 ff. 
= Suppl. 39, 
5 ff. 


I, 81 


sweetie 
Suppl. 40, 
Berit. 


I, 82, 24 ff. 
— Supple Al, 
TO fk, 


104,31 — 
Suppl. 42, I. 


. 85, 2 
Suppl. 42, 
14. 


278 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


in his book ,on rhetoric of expressions like this: “schools of 
rhetoric,’ “the ability produced by the schools,” “profession,” 
“instruction about speeches and enthymemes” and the like? 

Turning to Hermarchus, we find the same opinion in an epistle 
to Theophides. Alexinus in his work on education criticized the 
rhetorical sophists for wasting their time on investigation of use- 
less subjects, such as diction, memory, and the interpretation of 
obscure passages in the poets. He added, “We can grant that 
they try to speak about useful subjects, by which it is possible 
to settle questions of philosophy; for if they do not possess 
emotypn they do use conjecture which is the instrument of the 
rhetor.” .To this Hermarchus replied, “If by speaking about 
useful subjects he means speaking about such matters as will 
bring them pecuniary reward, he is insane.” 

Hermarchus then continues [Lacuna in which was shown the 
uselessness of these so-called useful subjects which the rhetori- 
cians discuss:] “It is better to lose one’s property than to keep 
it by lawsuits which disturb the calm of the soul.” 

Nor can we praise the rhetors for teaching their pupils to give 
advice on public questions. Hermarchus says: “If he says that 
the rhetors deserve admiration for being useful statesmen his 
statement will not stand the test. For cooks and carpenters give 
useful advice which need not be put in the form of a speech. 
Similarly any farmer without rhetorical training, even without 
elementary education can discover what is useful for the state. 


Furthermore, what are we to make of Alexinus’ statement that - 


rhetorical speeches depend not on knowledge but on experience 
and conjecture? He cannot mean that they have no dialectical 
syllogisms. At any rate he rebukes Eubulides for despising 
speeches without syllogisms.” 

We have given these last quotations in case anyone desires to 
have them, realizing that they will seem to have been written 
about some other subject than the one under discussion.** 

Metrodorus in the first book of his Mepi rounudtrwv seems to 
indicate clearly that rhetoric is an art. Speaking with one who 
had written on poetics he says, “Until some proof is brought 


“In this remark of Philodemus we have a naive admission of the weak- 
ness of his case. His attempt to find exact statements in Epicurean 
authorities to support his position is not particularly successful. 


——_— 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 279 


in regard to the art of the rhetoricians, it can hardly be said that 
it produces rhetors.” Then he adds, “Callistratus and others 
spoke satisfactorily before the assembly about the public interests 
without having studied the réxvy of Thrasymachus or of any one 
else.” Elsewhere he says that those who teach the art of speak- 
ing do not speak themselves; it is ridiculous to suppose that one 
man possesses the theory, and another the power, of speaking. 
(Lacuna ) 

A little later he says, “(One who purposes to speak in public will 
not seek the teacher who after giving theoretical instruction is 
not able to see the next step; but with an eye solely to the task 
to be accomplished will fulfill by himself the purpose of the art, 
and will let no chance escape of becoming a better orator.” 


An outline of the history of the controversy which Philodemus dis- 
cusses in the next section may enable the reader to understand some of 
the points to which he alludes in very obscure language. Philodemus was 
the pupil of Zeno, an eminent Epicurean who taught at Athens in the 
latter part of the second and early part of the first century B. C., and 
attained great eminence among his contemporaries, if he was not actually 
head of the school. Cicero attended his lectures at the advice of Philo, 
and admired his style; Non igitur ille, ut plerique, sed isto modo, ut tu, 
distincte, graviter, ornate. De Nat. Deor. I, 21, 59. His style is alluded to 
by Diogenes Laertius, VII, I, 35, Kal vofica nal épunvetoa cadys' he was 
evidently interested in style, and this interest served to distinguish him 
from the average Epicurean. Philodemus shared his master’s interest in 
elegance of style as we may conclude from Cicero’s remarks; (In Pis. 
28,68) Homo . ... humanus .. . Est autem hic, de quo loquor non 
philosophia solum, sed etiam ceteris studiis quae fere ceteros Epicureos 
negligere dicunt, perpolitus; poema porro facit ita festivum, ita concin- 
num, ita elegans nihil ut fieri possit argutius. It was this literary interest 
which led Zeno to make a collection of passages from Epicurus, Her- 
marchus and Metrodorus, which he thought proved that the leaders of 
the school considered sophistic rhetoric an art. He limited the province 
of the art, however, so as to include only the writing of a speech, par- 
ticularly of an epideictic oration such, for example, as the orations of 
Isocrates, and excluded all power of rhetoric to persuade in the fields 
of forensic and deliberative oratory. The quotations, as far as they can 
be recovered from Philodemus, are not convincing; still it must be 
acknowledged that while Zeno might not have been able to quote chapter 
and verse from Epicurus in support of his view, he was in spirit true 
to Epicurean principles. For Epicurus, at least in his exoteric writings, 
paid attention to clearness if not, indeed, elegance of style.® 


*y. Usener, Epicurea, p. XLII. 


eo. Lr 
Suppl. 44, 4. 


025510 == 
Suppl. 45, 
16. 


280 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


Zeno had nat published his views, but Philodemus had published anony- 
mously a Hypomnematicon which was not intended for general circula- 
tion. A copy of this fell into the hands of an Epicurean of Rhodes who 
wrote a reply criticizing Philodemus’ pamphlet as heretical, and also 
assuming that it had been written by Zeno. The next section is an answer 
to this attack. 


Some Epicureans now resident at Rhodes write that when in 
the course of their teaching at Cos and again at Rhodes they 
were upholding the thesis, “Rhetoric is not an art,’ some stu- 
dents recently come from Athens asserted that this position was 
not agreeable to the teaching of Epicurus. Being asked to quote 
their authority, one said that a definite statement on this point 
was to be found in the! Symposium or in the Lives; the other 
said he did not know where the statement was to be found, but 
knew that this view of sophistic was held by the Epicureans in 
Athens.** The philosopher darkly hinted at in the latter phrase 
is Zeno; the fact that he had written nothing on the subject 
does not prevent the opponent. from writing a reply to him. 
Frequently in this treatise he says that he found in Epicurus no 
trace of a statement that rhetoric is an art, but countless state- 
ments that no part of it is subject to the principles of art. Now 
we shall not hesitate to set forth in the future at greater length 
wherein we think this philosopher is wrong. For the present we 
shall give a brief outline of our criticism. 

The opponent says that Epicurus and Metrodorus considered 
that the political and forensic branches of rhetoric needed prac- 
tice and experience and a certain experimental knowledge, 
whereas the panegyrical branch depended on practice and expe- 
rience and a certain habit of expression without any knowledge 
of facts. Moreover the leaders of the school believed there 
was no art of persuading large bodies of men; that the afore- 
mentioned practice and experience do not suffice to persuade even 
in a majority of cases, and those trained in panegyric are less 
able to face the tumult of the assembly than those who have no 
rhetorical training; Epicurus and his followers knew that rexvac 


* Philodemus is careful not to mention names, though describing the 


opposing parties by phrases which would be intelligible to his audience. 
- The Rhodian school represents the author who had criticized Philodemus’ 


work, thinking it to be Zeno’s; the philosophers at Athens are Zeno and 
Philodemus. 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 281 


had been written, and referred to these works by this name with- 
out granting that they accomplish their purpose; if any one 
possesses the power of persuasion, it is responsible for evil and 
not good. With these arguments he thinks that he proves that 
those who believe any part of rhetoric to be an art are inconsistent 
with Epicurus. 

I wonder at the perplexity of the pupils of that “philosopher 
of Athens.” If they cared to know where this doctrine was laid 
down they might have consulted the philosophers at one of the 
meetings of the school on the twentieth of the month, or any of 
the regular associates of Zeno, who lives in Athens, not in Persia. 
In order to satisfy their desire we have presented the passages 
which we claim prove that the so-called sophistic rhetoric is an 
art, and is not a part of rhetoric; for the divisions of rhetoric 
are not as he assumes throughout his work, panegyric, political 
and forensic any more than the genus dog is divided into the 
species sea-dog and land-dog. 

We forgive the man for having written so much against our 
position; we should not have mentioned it except to show what 
strange things philosophers sometimes do. “But I desire to 
know,” you will say, “who wrote that book’? Not Zeno.1* 

Our claim that the Isocratean orations and those of like char- 
acter are not composed without method is especially attacked in 
the passage, “Epicurus believed that there was no art of per- 
suading large bodies of men; that those who are not rhetoricians 
sometimes are more persuasive than the rhetoricians; that those 
trained in panegyric are less able to face the tumult of the 
assembly than those who have no rhetorical training; that 
Epicurus spoke of arts, and said that those acquainted with them 
were benefited, but did not mean that this enabled them to attain 
the end; if anyone possesses the power of persuasion it is 
_ responsible for evil and not for good.” 

But the arguments of Epicurus which prove that there is no 
art of politics do not prove that the sophists do not possess 
some other art. We shall select certain passages from the 
Symposium of Epicurus which support our view. 

In order to represent the young man as being refuted when 


* Philodemus was the author of the book (his Hypomnematicon) 
which had been attacked on the supposition that its author was Zeno. 


I, 00, 5b= 
Suppl. 48, 
I5. 


L108) 03 — 
Suppl. 50, 
17. 


IP, Aor 
Suppl. 53) 5: 


282 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


he claimed that his rhetorical study gave him power to deliver 
panegyrics and engage in politics, Epicurus makes Idomeneus 
beg pardon for his youthful presumption, and represents some 
one addressing him thus; I quote word for word, “It is strange 
that you are not prevented by your youth from surpassing older 
and famous men in the power of rhetoric’; by which he means, 
“It is strange that you are not prevented by your youth from 
excelling in rhetoric, which seems to require practice, while it 
is possible for you to be prevented by your youth from partici- 
pating in philosophical discussions which depend more on 
knowledge than on practice.” 

“This,” says the opponent, “is a cledr statement from Epi- 
curus; he makes a hard and fast distinction between émornpy 
and rp8y, and considers that all rhetoric, not merely the political 
and forensic divisions, depends entirely on experience. If 
rhetoric were wholly or in part an art, Epicurus’ statement would 
become an absurdity meaning, ‘If that which is produced by 
method can be attained by a youth, much more can that be 
obtained which is produced by method.’ ” 

To assume that this statement of Epicurus refers to rhetoric 
as a whole, and not to the political part alone violates both the 
letter and the spirit of the Symposium. If sophistic rhetoric is 
an art, as it really is, requiring much practice (for the Epi- 
cureans acknowledge that some sciences need practice) how is 
Epicurus absurd? If the political form or division of rhetoric 
requires practice, and the sophistic, knowledge only, how is this 
absurd? The statement which our opponent thought to reduce 
to an absurdity, really means, “If that which is produced partly 
by method can be obtained by a young man, much more so, that 
which is produced by method alone.” 


Our opponent now proceeds to discuss the phrase 6 doxe? rpiBis elvar (I, 
103, 6= Suppl. 50, 12). The passage is so fragmentary that the meaning 
can be restored only partially. Philodemus has been arguing that the 
phrase meant that a part of rhetoric employed method and art, and a 
part depended on practice and experience. The opponent insists that the 
phrase Joke? rpiBijs eivae expresses Epicurus’ view of rhetoric as a whole, 
and that doxe? eivac is merely a milder expression for éo7rw, a form of 
expression which Epicurus uses even when making a positive statement 
about philosophy. If doxe? rpiBis elvac applies to the political branch of 
rhetoric dSoxee must be equivalent to éorw with the implication that 
gopioTikh pnropixy also depends solely on tpi84 and so Philodemus’ position 
is refuted. To this Philodemus replies: 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 283 


This is foolish. For it is not like Epicurus to hesitate to speak I, 109, 7= 
the truth. However an obscure statement as to its being an art Suppl. 54, 
is characteristic of the leading Epicureans. One ought not to 
insist on the letter, but rather follow the spirit of the passage 
as revealed by comparison with other passages. 

[Opponent.] “Do you not then admit that he agrees with those 
who declare that rhetoric is not an art, if you admit that he spoke 
without reservation?” No, for in other places he clearly says 
that it is an art. 

[Opponent.] “But we claim that Soxe? applies also to rodutiKy.”’ 

(The implication is that if the use of doxe? instead of éore allows 
one part of rhetoric, viz., sophistic to be an art, it also allows 
us to consider politics an art, and this is acknowledged to be 
false.) We grant this, and even grant that doxe? applies to 
sophistic; for Epicurus did not wish to settle the question by 
this one passage, and in many others he says that it is an art. 

If anyone should ask Epicurus just what he considered an art 
and what not, he would say that the uncertainty of the premises 
makes the conclusion uncertain. He is in doubt whether all 
rhetoric depends on practice; he agrees that it requires much 
practice. 

Again we say, “If he considered it to be only a matter of I, 112,7= 
practice and experience, he would not have added doxeéi.” They play a 
said that our interpretation did not give the right meaning, or 
that it did not give the only meaning. If the first is true we do 
not understand Greek; if the second, why do they, too, use 
obscure language in attacking us? 

I shall show that Epicurus is obscure in the passage on ¢povynors I, 112, 
when he says, ov paAAov ay ddfeev eriotHpn aitia eivar nrep TpLBy* also Pe 
that he shows that rhetoric is the result of knowledge and prac- ~ 
tice, but more of practice than of knowledge; that philosophical 
theorizing is the result of both, but more of knowledge than 
of practice; second, that he shows that philosophical theorizing 
is the result of both, but of one in a greater degree than the 
other, while rhetoric is the result of one alone; third, that phi- 
losophical theorizing is the result of knowledge and not of 
practice. The opponent chooses one of these interpretations at 
random. But suppose we substitute éore for doxe? eivar so that 
the sentence reads, 30 pév ovk éfelpyou TH pytopiKy duvajer tpoexewy, 0 
TpiBys éote Kai ovvnfecas toAAns- How can this mean that rhetoric 


40. 


284 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


is not the result of art, but of practice alone? We might say 
TroAANs dirorovias ort dnAovore TO hirocodeiy Kal 7 pirogodia, but no 
one would assume that philosophy is the result of labor alone. 
So by odAjs éorw 7 pytopiKy TpLBis Kat ovvnfeas Epicurus means 
deirar ToOAAHS TpPLBAS Kal Gvvneias. 

Furthermore, from the words that this man has used it is 
uncertain whether Epicurus assumed that rhetoric was the result 
of practice alone, or of art and practice, or largely but not 
entirely of practice. for in the sentence, ®avpacrov 67, & od 
pev ovbev eLeipyou dua THv HAtkiav ev TH pyTopiKyH Svvayer mpoexew 0 
doxei TpiBys eivar Kal ovvnbeias modAjs, does 0 doxel xrrX. refer to 
pytopixy Suvaywer Or trepéxev? It is possible to take this to mean 
that the power of rhetoric can be acquired by art, but to surpass 
all in it requires practice. This, however, I do not hold to be 
true. If you wish to consider how the author of the book 
understood this, he will say that doce? refers no more to trepexew 
than to pytopiuxy, but you have rejected my plain statement, and 
use the tricks of the sycophant against me. 

[In a fragmentary passage Philodemus promises to discuss 
later passages from Metrodorus. | 

Epicurean authorities hold that sophistic rhetoric does not 


- perform the task of practical and political rhetoric. This can 


be proved by passages from Epicurus, Hermarchus and Metro- 
dorus. The ability to speak in assembly and court comes from 
practice and observation of political events. 


Section II-c. 

Of the third section only the title can be determined with certainty. 

Sophistic rhetoric is an art of epideixis, and of the arrangement 
of speeches, written and extemporaneous. 
To which we may add the passage 

Sophistic is not the knowledge of political rhetoric; this sec- 
tion we shall take up in the Hypomnematismus'* which is to 
follow. In that will be demonstrated that political ability cannot 
come from these sophistical schools any more than from the 
common schools or from the philosophical schools; that often- 
times the possession of it is responsible for no small mischief, 
and does not even bring success in actual law cases. 


8 He refers to the third book, now lost. 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 285 


Section II-d. 
Politics depends on investigation and practice. 


We now pass to the last section. No system of politics has 
ever been imagined except that offered by the rhetorical sophists. 
Now since sophistic contributes nothing to produce political 
ability, it follows that those who possess this ability have acquired 
it without the help of scientific principles. 

After I, 122 the papyrus is so mutilated that no continuity between 
columns remains, and often the meaning of any one column is doubtful. 
I have given the only important passage in the last few columns. For the 
sake of completeness I append a synopsis of the other columns. 

it follows necessarily that the experience of the sophists 
is transmitted not without method. 1. 24 
among many peoples, Euphranor, Nicias, 
Hegesias’® and many others. 

Prooemium, narration, demonstration, exception?® and sum- 
mary. 

Unless he said that the Panegyric of Isocrates or the Pana- 
thenaic or the Busiris and the Helen and the Peace?’ were 
without method. 

What is true of the most inconsequential arts is true of 
rhetoric. In these one with a suitable nature, who acquires the 
principles and adds to them practice is able to produce the result ; 
one who does not learn the principles, either from others or 
from manuals, even if he aims at the desired goal always is 
incapable of producing any of the results. So in rhetoric. 

A clever man without studying the technical works of the 
sophists can study some sophist’s speech and so learn to imitate 
them. But how can he imitate it if it is a long way off? “How 
can he help imitating it if it is very near?,’ says Epicurus.?? 
1. 16. How can they expect that there will be differences in the 
written works when the art is the same? How will they persuade 
in medicine and many other sciences? But, as I said, the kinds 


those emulated 
Nicomachus and 


*®For Hegesias we should probably read with Wilamowitz, Hermes 
XXXIV (1899), p. 636, Pausias. 

” Reading in 1. 5 treéaipécews with Fuhr, Rhein. Mus. LVII (1902) p. 432. _ 

* Reading 1. 24 rév repieipyvns with Sandys, Class. Rev. IX (1895), p. 359. 
The thought is the same as I, 100, Io (v. p. 20). 

For a better understanding of this column compare II, 251. 


130420 
Suppl. 61, 
19. 


L124, cole 
XXV. 


iio" col: 
XXVI. 


Inare7ecols 
XXVII, 
1. 20. 


Ize cols 
XXVIII, 
1. 9. 


I, 130, col. 
XXIX. 


Teere24,. col. 
SO A 


ieenaaeecol. 


XXXI 


le 97. col. 
XX XIII, 
leven 


ieteon col. 
XXXIV. 


I, 144, col. 


XXXIX. 


LOZ cole 
TEAL 


286 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


of principles of such arts are very few, and differ from the 
sciences. . 

They say that the art applies to deliberative and forensic ora- 
tory. ‘Therefore when it is demonstrated that they are capable 
of neither, it is made plain that they have no art. 

to write imitations of forensic, deliberative and ambas- 
sadorial speeches. In addition to this, other imitations of 
speeches must be made to deceive people into thinking that this 
implants the political faculty, i. e. to demonstrate that it is an 
art. For not without system could one persuade the majority 
that he knows what he does not know. 

Certain arts have been transmitted to men in writing, e. g. 
architecture, ship-carpentry, navigation, painting. All these arts 
had methods in olden time. 

No man was able, whether induced by philanthropy or vain- 
glory, to impart to his contemporaries or to posterity [the 
principles of politics] unless he employed the political rexvac 
of the philosophers. 

[One] oftentimes advises a man to be just and rich or poor 
and humble or magnificent or beautiful, matters in which it is 
madness to speak of art; and the statesmen probably are better 
guessers than others. Why not? They have more access to the 
people.?* 


FRAGMENTS OF Boox II. 


The very considerable disconnected fragments of Book II are collected 
by Sudhaus in vol. II pp. 65-130. A certain grouping is possible, and has 
been worked out by Sudhaus in the introduction to vol. I pp. XX VII ff., 
which I have used as a basis for my own arrangement. In the case of 
most of the groups it will be apparent to what part of the book they 
belong, and-what relation they bear to the larger continuous fragment. I 
have thought it wise to indicate in case of the obscurer passages my own 
conjecture as to their position. The meaning of most of the passages, 
however, will be clear to one who has read the preceding pages of the 
second book.” 


If some say that the faculty of speech comes by practice, the 
majority say that practice alone produces poor speakers. 


* Reading with von Arnim (Hermes XXVIII (1893) p. 153) in 1. 16 
Zouxev eivar 1, 20 oravlws  mpdcodos. 

“The following fragments are so inconsiderable that I have not 
attempted to include them in this abstract: 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 287 


“The technical element they [i. e. rhetoricians] borrow from 
other arts e. g. from dialectic, and adorn themselves with bor- 
rowed plumage.” But [the philosopher] borrows from many 
sources, for according to Euripides one can get his proofs out 
of the air without toil. 

It is absurd to agree with Diogenes that rhetoric is not an art, 
and unworthy of a freeman. On this principle he would have 
to exclude many arts.”° 

i proves that politics and sophistic are the same. He 
may have proved that politics and sophistic do not produce states- 
men, but he does not realize that sophistic is not practice, but 
that every artist has his theoretical principles. 

Some speak without having had the benefit of instruction, but 
this does not prove that rhetoric is not an art. 

He**® says clearly that Demades did not study rhetoric, and 
the same applies to Aeschines. All of Demosthenes’ opponents 
claim that he was an artist and Critolaus does not deny it. In 
addition to this, our statement that they gained little from the 
art supports [the theory]. For hit-or-miss methods succeed only 
rarely; no one will say that the continued success of Aeschines 
and Demades is a proof that there is an art of rhetoric. 

If he instances Aeschines and Demades as good orators, this 
does not prove that sophistic is not a science. 

“Rhetoric is not an art, for every art aims at a correct (or 
successful) procedure; now hit-or-miss methods do not produce 
correct results, but we know that rhetors have been successful 
without instruction.’’?* 


IE G5. fre: 1 MeO. e rt. 1,06, tn. Vil I aie 155 PSNI 
65s. ir. LIL Gy, sree lit o8, fr. IX Tien tree 
(lope anes FAGp) atiey ALIN OO) fs Xx T22 ie ule 
665 ir: VI S84, fs. VILL 00; tr el 7200s Dies 
67) track 86, fr. XII Go; thal SF as @ AVA 

Be Gaudi wal ri, sine, OSIM QO} tra Ul T29 hit eV 
Cex aise, AD& gl, fr. XIX? TOA, fre 120 neti ee Vill 
73, ir. X® OG sural TOS hice even 
Tek nce Al Cow rie Vie Wig, Hine <I 
5 jai ee 96, fr VP TI, fire eee 


Pte Ih gsectr. IV, 
* This is aimed at Critolaus or Charmadas; v. Excursus, p. 371. 
7 This argument: is like that which proves that there is no art of 


WIS Gio) oane 
VIL. 


ID sakole em oop 
Orang 


Me yA, singe 
VITI. 


IW 60; ta W 


ey atta hse 
WAMME 


77h LON: 
Sar lll bye igi tins 
fr. XXII 

We ae her 
XVI, 8 ff. 


TTS seth. 
WANs 


le yacente 
Xow 
106, fr. 
XIII, XIV. 


0127, hr, 
XM. 


es I27 te 
oe ——n. 
Gin ies 1M 


II, 83, fr. 
VII, 


ate has 8 oA 
XI. 


288 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


Probably all that Homer meant was that they surpassed the 
other heroes in charm of conversation. 

Speaking of heroes who were able to speak, and kings 
able. 

This argument assumes that sciences are the same in different 
localities, but that rhetoric differs in different countries and 
cities. 

The sense of the following passages runs somewhat as follows: Rhetoric 
has been criticized for being all things to all men, so that it could be com- 
pared to the polypus which adapts its color to the rock on which it rests.* 
Philodemus’ answer is an analogy drawn from medicine; the rhetor must 
consider the needs and character of his audience, just as the physician 
must take into account differences of climate and constitution in regulat- 
ing the diet of the patient. Fr. XIV, p. 106 views the same subject from 
a different angle. A rhetor cannot be expected to be equally successful in 
all countries. A great Italian physician if transferred to Egypt would 
“send many mighty souls to Hades,” through failure to understand all 
the local conditions. 

art does not vary with locality, and does not adapt itself 
to different peoples, consequently he demands that rhetoric shall 
not change. 
demands that the perfect orator be also a good man 
and a good citizen.*? But such a combination is not required in 
the case of any other art; a good musician may be a villain. 

“Every art receives suitable pay; rhetoric does not.” But 
dialectic does not receive large fees, nor does medicine; so by 
this reasoning these should not be considered arts. 

Grant that the artist alone attains the end, or does so more 
than anyone else. If the rhetor is said to succeed alone or more 
than anyone else, that does not prove the sophist a rhetor. But 
this does not prove that politics is not an art, but the point would 
be proven if in law court and assembly no one of them suc- 
ceeded more than those not rhetors. If it said that one skilled 
in trials attains the end, this remark is ridiculous. For in some 
arts, those untrained can attain the end. 


rhetoric because the heroes were rhetors before any treatises on rhetoric 
were written. Cf. I, 27, 6= Suppl. 15, 17.. Also ll,76, tr. Lie ae 
demus seems to be arguing with a Stoic; cf. Sudhaus I, p. XXX. 

(Chi, “Aaierepenaniey Ais ai 

” This is the Stoic position. Probably he is quoting Diogenes of Baby- 
lon; cf. Radermacher, Rhein. Mus. LIV (18099) p. 290. 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 289 


They will say that the art is independent, but requires much 
natural superiority,*° and practice in actual political life in which 
the art is deficient; and that those who are acquainted with the 
principles of the art are impotent if they do not have these 
external aids. 

Having considered the arguments of this philosopher, we must 
next take up those of the Cyrenaic Theodorus and his followers. 

“Tf the rhetors deceive, they are themselves deceived by their 
own instruments, just as in the case of sight and hearing. For 
if one deceives he can be deceived; therefore they deceive no 
more than they are themselves deceived.” First, how does this 
prove that rhetoric is not an art? I do not see why he says that 
the rhetors are deceived, and that they do not merely deceive.** 

When the rhetors deceive they deceive with a deception of 
others, not of themselves; as when a soldier strikes down his 
opponent, and says that he defeated him with defeat, he means 
his opponent’s defeat, not his own. 

When a man sees, he is not therefore seen; the same applies 
to hearing. Therefore rhetors are not deceived because they 
deceive. 

One who deceives is also deceived himself; consequently 
capable rhetors are deceived in trials fully as much as they 
deceive. I wonder if Theodorus did not frequently deceive many ; 
he had the power to deceive, and does not acknowledge that he 
was led astray. 

The third syllogism is more endurable but no less absurd. For 
the physician can cure even if he uses barbarisms and soloecisms, 
and does not speak in rhetorical style. 

Persuasion is purely a matter of guesswork. 

He says that the end of rhetoric is to persuade the hearer. 

We shall say nothing to those who say that the end of rhetoric 
is to be able to find possible arguments on questions; or as some 
state it, to find the arguments for every question, and to refute 


40 aporépnua means ‘superiority’ as in Polyb. III, 80, 9: 4» dé ra rporephuara 
‘Pwyalwy, dxkatarpirta xopyyia kal yepSv mrIO0s. 

* Quintilian has a list of examples to prove that the deception practiced 
by the orators does not involve self-deception. II, 17, 18-2r. 

* Cf. Aristotle’s definition of rhetoric, I, 2: dtvayis epi Exactov Tod Oew- 
phoa TO évdexduevov midavor, 


Oy aettes 
XIV. 

JUL, Ale), sire 
IDS, 

MIG Colo sae 
Xavi —— ale 
L215) tials 
Te Sos tes 
XVII 

ID, 83; 58. 
XVI. 

IE ais} aie: 
Ve 

II, 88, fr. 
WAL 
Le ont, sire 
xelexe—s le 
TLOs tie 
VIII. 

ULL ye aie 
ox——s ile 
T2AL erie Valet 
I Tosh hie 
Nar 


My oa tes 01 


== UT, 20; 
the ven 


Tio7, str: 
Vil 


II, 100, 
DTT, 


iearo2: 
VI. 
II, 102, 
VII. 
II, 105, 


< 


IT, 105, 
XII. 
Ll eTOy: 
AV 
II, 108, 
XVI. 


ee 


rr. 


iG. 
tee 


290 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


(A refutation of an argument against rhetoric based on the 
mutual recrimination of orators.) If Aeschines charges Demos- 
thenes with using @avpara instead of pypara*® of what use is that 
as an argument? Do not the philosophers revile one another ?% 

This fragment yields nothing of importance except the distinction 
between practical orators, Demosthenes and Lycurgus, and sophists, Iso- 
crates and Matris. Cf. II, 233, 1s. 

This deals with the argument that rhetoric is not an art because it has 
been excluded from some cities.” 

Phocion studied the political art with Plato or Aristotle, and 
became a statesman. 

Rivalry between Critolaus and the rhetors. 

The next argument is: “All practice and observation and 
training has some end to which all the parts ought to tend; 
rhetoric has no such end.” 

[Rhetoricians] were not in good repute at the very beginning, 
in Egypt and Rhodes and Italy. 

We shall next consider the statement that every art is invented 
for some useful purpose, but rhetoric tends [to deceive].*° 

[I think that he wishes to] say that they do not have theoretical 
acquaintance with all subjects, but only with some; that the 
speakers in actual debates discuss many political problems, and, 
therefore some are able to speak to the point, others not; and 
that those who have a theoretical acquaintance with all subjects 
are good speakers.** 


* Aesch. III, 167. 

“For @avuaowvpylay 1. 6 Fuhr, Rhein. Mus. LVII (1902) p.-431, pro- 
poses to read “avuaroroiay, 

SCE yet, Eee 

“Cf. I, 2, 6, ff. = Suppl. 4, 4, ff. Possibly this is the opinion of Crito- 
laus; cf. Sext. Emp. Adv. Rhet. 10-12. 

“It is impossible to determine the identity of the person from whom 
Philodemus quotes this opinion. It may be of interest to note, however, 
that a similar opinion of the need of universal knowledge in oratory was 
warmly supported by Cicero. The most striking passage for purposes of 
comparison with Philodemus is in the De Oratore, I, 5, 17: Est enim 
scientia comprehendenda rerum plurimarum; but the thought is elaborated 
in a large number of passages which I have collected.in my dissertation— 
The Influence of Isocrates on Cicero, Dionysius and Aristides, pp. 20 ff. 
It would be rash to make the claim that Philodemus was aiming at Cicero, 
for Philodemus in spite of his long residence at Rome, and his close con- 
nection with a prominent Roman family is entirely Greek in his literary 


$833 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 291 


They do not show that rhetoricians were contemporary with 
the physicists. The fact that there were political rhetors before 
the technical treatises of the sophists were written, does not 
prove that political rhetoric is not an art. 

The same form of argument could be used with damaging 
effect against its author; there were certainly statesmen before 
Plato and Aristotle wrote on politics, and it can be proven that 
philosophy is not an episteme, for there were good men before 
Zeno, Cleanthes, Socrates and Aristotle. 

If we consider that he (i. e. Homer) was the founder (cipérys) 
of philosophy, as he is held to be not by the Critics alone but by 
the philosophers of all sects, it is just as reasonable to hold that 
he was the founder of rhetoric.** 

Does rhetoric help body or soul ? 

Let us now take up the statement of these same people that 
political rhetoric is an art, but less so than others; for they agreed 
that a few who had reached the top would be capable speakers. 

He who says that the end of rhetoric is to persuade, does not 
persuade himself but his neighbor. 

He holds the art to blame for the mistakes of those who are 
only partially acquainted with it. 

If many are able to attain an easy end, oftentimes better than 
the artist, still artists are to be admired, and are able to attain 
difficult end. For a physician who can cure ten out of a hundred 
difficult cases cannot be said to succeed in the majority of cases, 
yet we might call him a good artist. 

There is no method by which one can persuade the multitude, 
either always or in the majority of cases. 

and they say that Isocrates and Gorgias and Lysias 
acknowledged that they did not possess science. This is incred- 
ible and impossible, since they professed to be artists, and to 


references. Cicero’s opinions, however, were not unique but merely repre- 
sentative of the revival of the ‘philosophic rhetoric’ of Isocrates, which 
is represented on the Greek side by Dionysius, and, as we know from the 
introduction to his Attic Orators, by many others, some of whom may 
have been in the mind of Philodemus. Furthermore, any reference to 
Cicero is excluded by the probability that the Rhetorica of Philodemus 
antedates the De Oratore. 

* Wilamowitz, Hermes XXXIV (1899) p. 636, reads 1. 10 oby ind 1. 13 
aipécews and explains xpitik@v as the school of Crates. 


II, 100, fr. 
XIX. 


Lento: it 
XX. 


| ELS ee te 
XXI.- 


Eiri. trees 


ESTES sire 
able 


hia 
ee AE 


Serio) ioe 
XVI. 


II, 10, fr. 
XVIIL. 


Iisi2e. irs 
XIX. 


Ti 1225ei 
IV. 


ie Tes 
pee AV 

(EE ie i oe 
VI. 

DL 2665 ti. 
LV. 
Pras; air. 
EXE. 
i126, chr. 
XI. 

II, 109, fr. 
XVIII. 
TOTO Stites 
IWG oe 
LiSodveir 
II. 

ME om ar: 


4X\4 


292 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


teach others. Isocrates left technical treatises, and so did many 
other sophists, and declare it to be a wonderful art. 

But [the rhetoricians] do not know how to make laws, or 
govern according to their manuals. 

Inasmuch as rhetors persuade some people by kisses, let us not 
say that others are artists who do not possess the rhetor’s faculty. 
He demands that every science have its own subject matter with 
which it is concerned, and tries to show that rhetoric has no such 
subject matter.*° 

we use the principles of grammar; and using the same 
line of argument, if we are to heal we shall use the principles of 
medicine, and so in the case of the other arts. 

We take up next the argument that every art attains the end 
either always or generally, but rhetoric falls into neither of these 
classes, but succeeds rarely, and then by the use of elements 
common to all men.*° 

(Summary of the arguments against the Stoics.) They use a 
poor definition which excludes all the conjectural arts; they 
make false accusations against rhetoric, which really accom- 
plishes much by definite principles; many other criticisms might 
be made against them. We now pass to the next group, 
Ptolemaeus. : 

How can one teach vocal culture unless one has a trained voice, 
or medicine unless one is a physician? 

Gladly would I learn why only occupations fit for a free man 
can be considered arts. How could rhetoric be called unsuit- 
able, if I pass by for the moment the statement that 
[the rhetors themselves] do not wish to have it considered an 
art; for Demosthenes and Pericles claimed [to possess] rhetoric, 
and usage [accepts it as an art]. 

No less in error is the next argument which runs as follows; 
if the theorems of the art ought to be of such a nature, one must 
not do this. However one must not draw the conclusion which 
they direct. (What follows refers to periods.) 

Epicurus has stated explicitly in his Wept pyropixjs that their 
knowledge of sophistic does not give them theoretical knowledge 
[of politics]. 


* Cf. Sext. Emp. Adv. Rhet. 48 ff., Quint. II, 21; -v. Excursus p. 374. 
“ Cf. Sext. Emp. Adv. Rhet. 13-15. 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 293 


One who spells Dionysus is not more grammatical than one 
who spells Theodorus“. . . . The physician and grammarian 
attempt to impart certain things to others, and to instruct stu- 
dents of grammar and medicine; similarly, the rhetor 

Let us say that music and medicine and Epicurean philosophy 
are not arts. Consequently they will say that there is no char- 
acteristic exercise in the arts, and judge that the assistance that 
comes from the arts : 

It is quite incredible that Isocrates accomplished any such 
result with this faculty.* 

If the Spartans and Romans manage their governments without 
ie aid of rhetoric®™”.° ; 348 


BOOK III. 


At the close of the second book Philodemus remarks: “Sophistic is 
not the knowledge of political rhetoric; this section we shall take up in 
the Hypomnematismus which is to follow. In that it will be demon- 
strated that political ability cannot come from these sophistical schools 
any more than from the common schools or the philosophical schools; 
that oftentimes the possession of it is responsible for no small mischief, 
and does not bring success in actual law cases.” 

This is the only certain indication that we have of the contents of the 
third book. Sudhaus thinks that some of the fragments of the Hypom- 
nematicon may belong to this book, but the two works overlap so much 
that the question cannot be settled with certainty. 


BOOK IV. 


The contents of this book may be deduced from the closing paragraph, 
Neepoercols XIU lla: a *Arorebewpnudvwy Tovyapovv, & Tdie Tat, amdvrwy & wépyn 
pact twes kal diddyuara THs pyropiKns Wrdpxev, Ore TA pev KaTéWevoTa, Ta 8’ 
ovdév xXpnoimever Tols un TA PHTOpLKa GopiaTEvoucr, OHov STL ToumeveTar Tap av’rots 
76 pntépa TOv palnudrwv Kal Tov Texvev eivae Kai Ti evOixnv Kal dderhpiov Thy 
PyTopixyny Kal uaGddov ere pera THs TeHovs NauPavoméerny. It was a criticism 
of rhetoric, following the divisions of the ordinary rhetorical techne. 
All that remains is the treatment of Aé&s or ppdows, and brédxpiors, with 
a short digression on the province of the orator. The study of the book 


“I. e. different words have different spellings, and different arts have 
different principles, but one is an art just as much as the other. 

“Isocrates is representative of sophistic. The sentence means: It is 
incredible that sophistic trains for practical rhetoric. 

“Ci. the use of the same argument in the larger fragment, I, 14, fr. V. 


PE 88, tes 
XV. 


Mee Sas fits: 
Wile 


erent! 
VI, 31-44. 


IDEN olan, Jl. 


eps tg 
col. if 
L147 col: 
inte 

I, 148, col. 
1 


294 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


may be facilitated by prefixing a short outline of its present contents to 
the detailed treatment of the fragments. 

The main body of the book is devoted to \é&s. The first two columns 
however, do not have any connection with this subject. Column I, vol. I, 
p. 147 deals with vous, column II with the meaning of ¢Aocopla. The 
connected fragment begins with column III. III-X discuss the meaning 
of kad) as applied to \é&s. XI-XIX treat of faults of style, soloecism, 
barbarism and obscurity. The second group of fragments (I, p. 162 ff.) 
begins with a discussion of homoioteleuton (col. I) and collision of 
vowels (col. II). Col. III outlines the following discussion of ¢pdous 
dividing it into tpéros, cxfua and mAdoua. The first part of the discussion 
of tpéros is too fragmentary to permit of any restoration. X-XXII criti- 
cizes the rhetorical treatment of metaphors, XXIII introduces the subject 
of allegory, and there the fragment ends; the sections on cxjma and 
m\doua are entirely lost. The next group of fragments, continuing the 
criticism of text books of rhetoric, denies that rhetoric can claim the 
credit for teaching men to avoid faults of speech (col. I@-XI*). XI?- 
XIX* makes a similar criticism of the rhetorical claims to teach vréxpiccs. 
XX*-XXX® attacks the rhetorician’s claim of ability to speak on all sub- 
jects. XXX*@-XL* criticizes the sophistical use of epideictic, denying that 
the sophistical encomia possess moral value. XLI has a brief remark on 
Demetrius’ peculiar fourfold division of oratory. The book concludes 
with a summary (XLII-XLIV). 


They agree with us regarding what is naturally and truly 
advantageous. Therefore he who has learned what is naturally 
good and bad, and intermediate and indifferent, and has acquired 
the practical and theoretical means of producing this 


The restoration of this column is very uncertain. I cannot understand 
the use of eiov (1. 7) with éxdédouy following in 1. 11 without a connective. 
The meaning seems to be that the rhetoricians, claiming that their pro- 
fession was a philosophy and an art, meant that it was a philosophy in the 
sense in which Isocrates used the term, 1. e. the study of the whole of 
human activity from the standpoint of the orator, and not with the inten- 
tion of parallelling the Peripatetics and Stoics by propounding a peculiar 
system of thought. This claim that rhetoric is the most comprehensive 
of studies is noticed again at the end of the book, I, 223, 11 quoted above, 
Pp. 37. 

This fragment is part of a discussion of the meaning of aA} as applied 
to Aé&s or Ppdows. One possible definition is that cay dé&is is one which 
can present proposals which shall seem advantageous’ in such a way as to 
win the audience. This definition is mentioned only to be rejected. 


* For, the thought cf. Sext. Emp. Adv. Rhet. 56:  didmep Gravy éyerae 6 
pytwp Kadfs éEews elvar katacKevacTixds, ro. KaTa ToUTO éyeTat Kabd Thy TH 


cuupéepovta mpayuara Snodcav NéEwv karacKevaver.... ol Te 6é Kad THY TA CUUPEpoVTA 
mpdyuata unviovcayv + ovdev yap toace mepl TovTwy TOv mpayudTwr oi prHropes. 


a 


ete A 


Cann a he i eee 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 295 


Kady Ppaos belongs to the Epicurean philosophers, but is not 
even remotely connected with the rhetoricians or sophists. For 
if by xaAy one means the use of words in their proper meaning, 
why should the philosophers take second place? 

Any “imitation” of things by words is impossible. In the 
beautiful style of Isocrates, or the grand style of Demosthenes 
we do not find this attempt to fit sound to sense. 

If there were no naturally beautiful style, it might be neces- 
sary to be content with one established by arbitrary authority. 
But as there is a naturally beautiful style it is a shame to seek 
for another. For the arbitrary style is not accepted by all, nor 
is it always the same in the same author; some imitate the style 
of Isocrates, others that of Thucydides.? 

Whom then shall we imitate, especially since it is so formidable 
a task? Perchance we might imitate all who have been success- 
ful at any time or place. One cannot even say that all rhetors 
adopt one style. : 

Only two or three at the most imitate Isocrates, and some 
say that the style of Isocrates is not uniform in all his works. 

Therefore the grammarians and philosophers who refuse to 
follow these rules, but write in simple style and not in the 
ridiculous style prescribed by the manuals [write better than 
the sophists]._ We have now discussed every possible phase of 
the subject. 

Now in regard to a correct use of the Greek language which 
some say consists in observing the local peculiarities of speech 
(dialectical peculiarities), and in the avoidance of soloecism and 
barbarism*—some call the failure to observe the local peculiari- 
ties soloecism, still others make a distinction between barbarism 
and incorrect pronunciation, e. g. a mistake in aspiration or 
accent—it is not convenient to speak at present.* 


*Radermacher, Rhein. Mus. LIV (1899) p. 365, quotes Maximus 
Planudes, Schol. Hermog. vol. V, p. 440, 25W; 6 6€ ye Emixoupos év r@ rrepl 
pyropixns avOadécTepoy oiwar Néywv gyolv avrds pdvos evpnkévac TéxVNY ToNTLKOY 
Noywv - rods dé GdAous drockopakitwy pHropas éavTw ws waxdueva éyer - Pos ydp 
éoTw 7 KaTopHovca Néoyous, Tex vy ovdeuia.- Apparently he thought that Epicurus 
was a rhetorician! 

* Reading in 1. 11 muydé for of 5€ as suggested by von Arnim, Hermes 
XXVIII (1893) p. 153. 

* The distinction between barbarism and soloecism which is given by the 
later grammarians when the theory had become crystallized was. that 


I. 149, 
IV. 


col. 


col. 


52, col. 


I, 154, 


col. 


col. 


XII 


I, 158, col. 


XVI. 


Ie nse; (col. 


296 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


The sophists commit more soloecisms than anyone else. There 
is no art of style, such as they desire, and as is found in other 
lines of study. To sum up the question of style—one style is 
common to all. (I. e. the natural.) 

Obscurity is of two kinds, intentional and unintentional. It 
is intentional when one has nothing to say, and conceals the 
poverty of his thought by obscure language that he may seem 
to say something useful. [Connected with this] is the use of 
many digressions, poetic images, recondite allusions and archaic 
language. Soloecisms prevent the hearer from understanding 
many things. Only the true philosopher is free from these 
faults. Unintentional obscurity arises from not mastering the 
subject, or not observing the proper formation of periods either 
in writing or speaking, and in general from failure to use pure 
Greek, and from. believing that words are in harmony with 
things.® 


barbarism was a mistake in a single word e. g. in the use of a wrong 
ending, while soloecism was a mistake in syntax. The two overlapped 
somewhat, and it remained a question whether to use hanc meaning a 
man, was a soloecism or barbarism. (Cf. Quint. I, 5, 34 ff., Diomed. 
455K.) Quintilian with his usual good sense decides that this is a soloe- 
cism. : 

Quintilian and later authorities include under barbarism mistakes in the 
use of the aspirate and in accent, which some teste Philodemo preferred 
to. make a separate class. (Quint. I, 5, 19; I, 5, 22; Donat. p. 392K.) 
The definition of €\\nuouds here given is parallelled in Herodian, De 
Soloecismo et Barbarismo, Nauck, Lex. Vindob. p. 311, 9; ‘Epwrnfels ris 
Tl éorw €dAXnuopds, En, ‘TO Tdoats Tats dtadexTals 6pOGs xpHoGa. In their 
origin there seems to have been no distinction between soloecism and 
barbarism. Aristotle uses the terms interchangeably (Soph. El. III); 
Hegesias has the same confusion (ap. Dion. Hal., De Comp. Verb. 18, p. 
82,5 U. et R.). The first clear statement of the distinction which after- 
wards became fixed is in Diogenes of Babylon ap. Diog. Laert. VII, 1, 59. 
But the question was far from being settled by his dictum, as this passage 
from Philodemus shows. 

* Reading ciudlwra] for cuudlav#] lines 24, 25. Does he refer to the 
doctrine, elaborated by the Stoics though not originated by them, of the 
onomatopoetic origin of language? Cf. Arist. Rhet. II], 1, 8; Plato Crat. 
423A; August. Princ. Dialect., VI (I, 1412M). Of the Stoic position the 
latter says: Stoici autumant, quos Cicero in hac re irridet, nullum esse 
verbum, cuius non certa ratio explicari possit. Et quia hoc modo sug- 
gerere facile fuit, si diceres hoc infinitum esse; quibus verbis alterius verbi 
originem interpretaveris, eorum rursus a te originem quaerendam esse 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 297 


[Obscurity also arises] from ignorance of the proper mean- 
ings of words, their connotation, and the principles on which 
one word is to be preferred to another. 

In addition to these there is a fault treated separately by the 
theorists, namely the too frequent use of hyperbata, and failure 
to make the gap between the separated words short enough when 
it is necessary to use this figure; and the separation of correlated 
conjunctions by too large an interval.® 

One should use ordinary expressions appropriately, and not 
express onesself inaccurately, nor vaguely, nor use expressions 
with double meaning.’ 

They (the sophists) have not explained the intricacies of 
subject matter. [This belongs to the philosophers. | 

(A discussion on the choice of words has preceded.) The 
most important of the rhetorical sophists err in their too great 
devotion to homoioteleuton and similar figures, and pay little 
heed to the use of words. 

Collision of vowels is rather frigid, but sometimes not inop- 
portune. However they (the sophists) do not define each case 
(4. e. when it is to be avoided and when permitted), but they 
depend entirely on subjective tests. . . . If, then, the observa- 


I, 159, col. 
XVII. 


I, 160, col. 
XVIII. 


I, 161, col. 
YD 


iP 162, col. Ie 


tion of the principles laid down by them involves anything HI 


extraordinary, and there are present 746) and 76y and the other 
characteristics of artificial speech, I wonder if a satisfactory 
‘form of expression has not been moulded from the vulgar speech. 
This artificial speech they divide into three parts: tpozos, oxjpa, 
mAacpo.: tporos includes metaphor, allegory, etc.; oxjpa, periods, 
cola, commata and the combinations of these; wAdcpa refers to 


donec perveniatur eo ut res cum sono verbi aliqua similitudine concinat, 
ut, cum dicimus, aeris tinnitum etc. . . . Sed quia sunt res, quae non 
sonant, in his similitudinem tactus valere, ut si leniter vel aspere sensum 
tangunt, lenitas vel asperitas litterarum ut tangit auditum, sic eis nomina 
peperit. . . . Lene est auribus, cum dicimus, voluptas, asperum est, cum 
dicimus, crux. . . . Haec quasi cunabula verborum esse crediderunt, ut 
sensus rerum cum sonorum sensu concordarent. Hine ad . . ._ simili- 
tudinem . . .  processisse licentiam nominandi. . . . Inde ad 
abusionem ventum est. . . . Innumerabilia enim sunt verba, quorum 
ratio reddi non possit; aut non est, ut ego arbitror, aut latet, ut Stoici 
contendunt. 

ete oAtist, het. ITI, 5, 2. 

N@ie Awist, lenet. (1, 22, 12) 


], 166-169. 


erg. 2) 


col. XII. 


I, 273, col. 
XIV. 


i 174, col. 


= 


eels col: 


DOL I; anger 


col. XVIT. 


lia Coll 
SOWA 


lle 170), <erolll, 
XX. 


I, 180, col. 
XXI. 


298 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


the distinction between grand and plain and middle or smooth 
style.* It is foolish to apply the term wAdopa to everything which 
transgresses the bounds of plain speech. 


Cols. V—IX are too fragmentary to permit a restoration of a complete 
sentence. It is evident from such phrases as perapépew Tas dvouaclas 
(167, col. VII, 6), wreloras év rots rpdyuacww omowdrnras évvoety Kal diaopds 
(168, 24), merapopats (169, 16), that they are devoted to a discussion of 
tporos (cf. col. II1). Apparently in col. VIII there was some discus- 
sion of the propriety of metaphors in deliberative oratory. Col. X 
sub fin. and col. XI discuss some plan for a scientific classification of 
metaphors, the details of which are not clear. He continues (coll. XII, 
XIII) with a criticism of the common rhetorical doctrine of metaphors. 
The rhetoricians are content to classify and describe metaphors, 
e. g. animate objects are compared to animate, or animate to 
inanimate, inanimate to animate etc., but they give no practical 
working instructions. 

They will ridicule a metaphor without explaining why it is 
faulty or how a good metaphor is to be invented. While they 
divert the attention of young men from philosophy they do not 
give specific instructions when to use metaphors and allegories, 
for they consider that the use of metaphors is of advantage 
only to teachers, but to one engaged in the intercourse of active 
life they are superfluous baggage. If the use of literal expres- 
sions is extended over so wide a field, every art will be silent 


because deprived of the helpful assistance of metaphors. Some 


even apply opprobrious epithets to those who call in the aid of 


figurative language. 

The language again becomes fragmentary. Apparently the charge is 
made that the sophists use metaphors even more freely than the poets, not 
to mention the other writers of prose. Other fragments of these two 
columns are almost too small to notice. 

Some say:that they use metaphors for the sake of the compari- 
son or resemblance; not however resemblance per se, but 

This column deals with the far-fetched metaphors of which two 
examples are given. These were criticized by persons whose own use of 
metaphors was not above reproach on this score. 

Many who have received an education, and who are acquainted 
with the sciences, use metaphors nearly as much as the sophists. 


“For méyedos 1. 4 read meodrnra with Radermacher, Rhein. Mus. LIV 
(1899) p. 361, n. I. 


egy 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 299 


It is strange then if we are to avoid metaphors, wholly, or 
in part, while the sophists use them constantly. 

Col. XXIII is the beginning of a discussion of allegory, dividing it into 
three parts, alvyua, mapoumia, eipdvea, disregarding for the present such 
subdivisions as yptgos and doretouds, 

The first five columns of this section are disconnected fragments. The 
subject is the avoidance of faults of style. In column IV® the thought is, 
“But the avoidance of these faults is not the result of technical training in 
rhetoric.” Various faults to be avoided are mentioned in column III®’; 
viz. the use of rhythm in prose, obscure use of metonomy, and omission of 
the second of two correlating particles. The continuous section begins 
with column IV® 1. 5a. 

The sophistical training does not prevent faulty speech. Those 
who compose these technical treatises would have us believe that 
nobody observed these errors in speech before they wrote, and 
that they speak more correctly than other people. 

How can he (i. e. some rhetorician whose statement of the 
above tenor has just been quoted) say that these faults were not 
observed by the famous statesmen and philosophers who pre- 
ceded Zopyrus and Antiphon, who avoided most if not all of 
them? He did not allow himself any loophole for escape, such 
as allowing “rhetoric” in his statement to be interpreted as 
meaning stich instruction as Phoenix is reputed to have given 
Achilles, for he will not allow natural ability in speaking to be 
called rhetoric. And he made his statement more emphatic by 
saying, “before the study of rhetoric became firmly established.” 
Consequently both Thucydides the son of Stephanus’? and 
Thucydides the son of Olorus were guilty of these faults of 
style. For the systematic study of rhetoric began in their day, 
but can hardly be said to have been firmly established. And yet 
the introduction of these studies has made no difference in the 
way people speak. I hesitate to say that no one except a ditch 
digger and Maison talks in the way which he criticizes, but I 
think that such language as he condemns is characteristic not of 
an uneducated man, but of one lacking in common sense. 
Therefore let us not wonder at his statement that the technical 


°It is probable that col. [V* should precede col. III*. Then col. III? and 
col. V® are continuous reading; é¢y® mév to’Twy moda Kayaba memoink , 
avrds wor xdpuv ovK dmodébwxev, thus illustrating the omission of 6é after peév. 
This is the suggestion of Sandys, Class. Rev. IX, p. 359. 

* Apparently a slip for Melesias. 


I, 180, col. 
KORTE 


Iesanerenrefoll 
SGI 


I, 182, col. 
Ja—I, 186, 
col. V2, 


TL 188icoll 
VIIa, 


I, 180, col. 
VIIIa, 


Ieerg0; colt 
TX, I, ror, 
col. X84. 


T, 192, col. 
<[2, 


I, 193, col. 
ele. ire: 


I, 194, col. 
XIITa, 


300 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


treatises on rhetoric are the sole standard of correct speech. 
If he called rhetorical speech the only correct speech, his state- 
ment would be consistent. And that is what he actually appears 
to mean when he says that at the time poets and educated men 
flourished in Greece all were inferior to the sophists in correct- 
ness of speech. He does not permit us to understand him to be 
speaking of ordinary conversation, because he cites examples of 
faults in diction, and corrects them. If he said that the rhetors 
were successful in rhetoric he was speaking either with reference 
to the dialectician (a position which we refute) or with reference 
to other educated persons or artists, each of whom understands 
the principles of his profession better than a layman, as for 
example he himself has represented Philo the architect address- 
ing the people about the arsenal.1‘ But study of technical 
rhetoric has never advanced anyone. 


Section II. 
Delivery. 

Of the six, or as some say seven, parts of rhetoric, Athenaeus 
says that the most important is delivery,’? and we agree that a 
good delivery lends dignity to the speaker, secures the attention 
of the audience and sways their emotions. But if'? it is more 
the task of rhetoric to teach this than it is the task of dialectic 
or grammar one would desire to learn it. One teaches how to 
argue, the other how to read. If they claim that delivery in 
drama comes under the head of rhetoric, we congratulate them 
on their sense. But if actors do not need assistance from the 
rhetorician why do they not allow us, too, to. decide on the delivery 
proper to our own sphere? The fact that, uncertain in the 


* On Philo the architect cf. Cic. De Orat. I, 14, 62. The use which the 
rhetorician made of Philo may be estimated from the words of Cicero, 
Neque enim, si Philonem illum architectum, qui Atheniensibus arma- 
mentarium fecit, constat perdiserte populo rationem operis sui reddidisse, 
existimandum est architecti potius artificio disertum quam oratoris fuisse. 
Is otros avrés Demetrius of Phalerum? See the discussion by Fuhr in 
Rhein. Mus. LVII (1902) p. 434. 

*T adopt the emendation of Gomperz, Sitzungsb. d. k. Ak. in Wien, vol. 
CXXIII, p. 33, quoted in Sudhaus’ apparatus. 

* Reading in 1. 25 e for od with von Arnim, Hermes XXVIII (1893) 


p. 153: 


“y 


toe 


Bieta Cae 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 301 


beginning, they take refuge in this, that the actors try to rival 
the delivery taught by the rhetoricians, is not consistent with 
their magnifying the art of rhetoric because of delivery, and 
claiming that for this reason it is better than philosophy. If 
they say that they are the only ones who have formulated an 
art of delivery, they do violence to the plain fact that the poets 
and writers of prose have a theory of delivery even though they 
have not committed it to writing. 

Much of delivery is the natural and unconscious bodily expres- 
sion of the emotions. Delivery depends, too, on natural endow- 
ment, beauty of voice, grace of body, selfpossession, qualities 
the lack of which caused Isocrates to refrain from public 
appearances. But Demosthenes said that delivery was the first 
thing in oratory, and the second and the third, and actors say 
that it is everything in their art. However it was ridiculous to 
say that this element which is of assistance to all is of more 
account in rhetoric than in other forms of prose. Although 
Demosthenes was in the first rank of rhetors, still he is criticized 
by Aeschines for his shrill voice, and again for loudness,’ and 
by Demetrius of Phalerum for being too theatrical, and not 
simple and noble in his delivery. Moreover most of the sophists, 
judged by their writings, seem to have had a poor delivery. 
Their long periods are hard to pronounce, teste Demetrio.® 
Hieronymus also criticizes Isocrates. His orations he says are 
easy to read, but hard to deliver in public; there is no fire in 
them; everything is monotonously smooth. He sounds like a 
boy speaking through a heroic mask. Sophists of the present 
day have somewhat improved in delivery. 

The formal instruction in delivery is a product of recent 
foolishness; however many of the heroes had an excellent 
delivery. What the technographers have done is to make plain 
what had been kept secret before by the statesmen, viz. that 
they have a system for making themselves appear dignified and 
noble, and for misleading their audiences. This system is not 
needed by any other artist, certainly not by the philosopher. 
The fact is, each profession has its own peculiar delivery. 


“ Aesch. 2, 157: évrecvduevos thy déetay Kal dvdciov dwviv. 106, avaBoa 
Twappeyébes Anuocbévns. Cf. 86; In Ctes. 218. 


* For Isocrates’ own opinion on the way people delivered his orations 
v. Panath: 17, Phil. 25-20. 


I, 195, col. 
XEV= 8: 


Col xy 


I, 198, col. 
XVII2, 23. 


I, 200, 
XVIII2, 18. 


I, 201, col. 


XX, 12. 


I. 202; cal. 


XXIa, 


I, 204, col. 
XXII@, 16. 


I, 204, col. 


XXIII, 


I, 206, col. 


DOVE, 


I, 207, col. 


XXVI2, 


302 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


Sophists with common sense confine themselves to a discus- 
sion of political questions, and do not claim to discuss the form 
of introduction, narration etc. suitable to every question.‘® The 
latter is reserved for the thick-witted crew who fail to distinguish 
whether 1) only political questions can be treated in these divi- 
sions, or 2) all questions can be so treated, and that they are 
the only ones who outline methods adapted to all questions, or 
3) they are the only ones who have published such treatises. 
All three positions are unsound, for 1) almost all questions are 
treated according to this division, 2) the technographers have 
given us no treatises on philosophy or music, 3) other professions 
have laid down rules for presenting their subject matter. 

The same confusion of thought is found in the claim that the 
end of rhetoric is to find the possible arguments on any subject, 
and that rhetoric is alone or almost alone in doing this.** In 
the first place this is nothing more or less than “invention.” 
In the second place if rhetoric can discover the possible argu- 
ments in questions relating to medicine, music, etc. the rhetori- 
cians are immediately put into rivalry with the experts in each 
of these professions. As it is impossible for a philosopher to 
discover the best possible arguments for some other sect, how 
can one in a totally different line of activity discover these 
arguments ? 

Each profession has its own facts and principles, and is alone 
competent to argue about them. But grant that the end of 
rhetoric is to find the possible arguments on every rhetorical 
subject; the phrase “on every’ needs restriction. 

Besides let us say that no good can result from being able to 
discover arguments, even if it is valuable to have the state of 
mind which could discover them. For it is clear that he who 


* This paragraph is an attack on followers of Isocrates such as Cicero, 
who claimed for the orator the right to speak on all subjects. Cf. De 
Oratore, III, 20, 76, as an illustration of the principle, although Philodemus 
probably wrote before Cicero: Illa’ vis autem eloquentiae tanta est ut 
omnium rerum virtutum offciorum omnisque naturae, quae mores homi- 
num quae animos, quae vitam continet, originem vim mutationesque teneat, 
eadem mores leges iura describat, rem publicam regat, omnia quae ad 
quamcumque rem pertineant ornate copioseque dicat. 

“This is substantially Aristotle’s definition, Rhet. I, 2, 1: erw 6H pyropixh 
Svvayus Tepl EKagToV TOD DewpRoar Td Evdexbuevov mibavor, 


—_ 


ie ee is 


aud 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 303 


discovers the inherent arguments must know those which are 
cogent, and those which are only plausible; but they are far 
from knowing what is plausible and what is necessary. Nor 
do they know what is possible and impossible; their natural 
philosophy is of no help to them. Then they need a criterion of 
truth, and it is folly to think they possess this. If they say 
that what appears true to the crowd is true, they say nothing 
more than that the statesman can discover the inherent political 
arguments; secondly, the majority does not always abide by 
the same standard of judgment. Perhaps some one will say 
that a happy life has no need of politics and rhetorical sophistic. 
I assert that the sophists can, at least as far as their technical 
treatises are concerned, discover not the slightest argument 
pertaining to politics. 

Again another will object that the great sophists have no 
ability in sophistic, as is shown by the published treatises. I 
say that the arguments of the sophists and statesmen are mostly 
false. To discover all the arguments requires a deeper and 
more philosophic understanding. 

Rhetoricians divide their subjects into three parts: forensic, 
(duxavixa), deliberative (cvpPovrAevtixa), and encomiastic (Ta epi Tovs 
€raivous kal Woyous). We will omit for the present, discussion of 
the first two, except to say that some use the term d:xaorypiaxoy 
instead of duavkov, and that deliberative oratory gives advice 
only on matters affecting the common welfare, and that this 
advice is not the product of the sophistic art, but of quite a 
different art. 

In regard to the encomiastic branch of oratory, let us say that 
political orators frequently employ passages of praise and 
censure but they do not use them after the fashion of the 
sophists, nor do they claim to be the only ones able to praise or 
censure. That is the pretension of the sophists whom we now 
proceed to answer referring directly to their published works. 
If they mean that they alone have the power to praise or censure 
all things, it is right to inquire whether they praise or censure 
the same object indifferently, or only praise what is praiseworthy, 
and censure what is blameworthy. If the former, aside from the 
impossibility of praising that which is blameworthy, there are 
some things which do not admit of either praise or censure; 


I, 208, col. 
XXVIIA. 


Ie 200; 4col: 
XXVIII2. 


[2ro col: 
XXIXa, 


| 


L205, ,G0l: 


XXX1V8, 


I, 216; col. 
XXXV28, 14. 


Peere col: 
XXXVIIB8, 
19. 


I, 220, col. 


XXXIX2, 4. 


I, 220, col. 
XLa, 


I, 222°°6: 


304 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


if to the second, they arrogate to themselves the knowledge of 
what is useful or harmful. If they profess to write encomia of 
gods and heroes, and to praise some men and censure others, 
we say that the gods do not need any praise of men, especially 
not the unseemly praise of the sophists. Their praise of brute 
beasts does no good, for one can not change the nature of 
animals by this process. 

They say that men are turned to virtue by their encomia, and 
dissuaded from vice by their denunciations. But the sophists 
by their praise of Busiris and similar characters, persuade men 
to become villains. And when they do praise a good man they 
praise him for qualities considered good by the crowd, and not 
for truly good qualities. If they had real philosophic insight 
into the nature of virtue and vice, they would seek virtue and 
avoid vice themselves. 

Not only do they fail at times to praise anything useful, but 
they frequently praise bad things, and by lavishing praise on 
matters of small account they incline us to treat all subjects 
lightly, and by their praise of men to their faces lead to great 
confusion. They are ignorant, too, of the proper time to praise, 
which we discuss in our work Ilepi ézaivov. 

Furthermore, no one can believe the encomiasts, because they 
praise bad men, and often praise and censure the same person. 

The sophists do not excel the poets in their ability to praise, 
nor even some of the philosophers. In fact any one can do what 
they claim as their sole possession. We grant that they may 
have a monopoly of such encomia as are in common circulation. 
That they do any good thereby, we deny. 

Demetrius adds a fourth class to those mentioned. This he 
calls évrevxtixov dracw. (obtaining favor with all).** If he means 
that which obtains favor with the multitude, and with potentates, 
let him have his point for the present; later we shall see what 
comes of it. But he errs in assigning this and the sophistical 
branch of rhetoric to the same individual. If he takes the search 
for truth from the philosophers and gives it to the rhetoricians 


* Cronert, Kolotes und Menedemos, p. 60, refers this to Demetrius of 
Phalerum. Diogenes Laertius gives among the works of Demetrius (V, 
5, 80, 81) Snunyopiay re Kal mpecBedv... ouvvaywyal, and IIpecBeurixés, 
and his fourth class may be speeches of ambassadors. 


1 ee ee 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 305 


he is transferring the power he once had in political affairs to 
investigations which require proof. 

After considering all the divisions of rhetoric and its claims, 
Gaius, and recognizing that some are false, and others are of 
no use to one who does not make a profession of rhetoric, it is 
plain that their claim that rhetoric is the mother of the arts 
and sciences is a vain pretense. In another place we shall dis- 
cuss the charge that it is based on deceit, and therefore harmful. 
We differ from them when they say that the students of rhetoric 
become better than their contemporaries. If they mean that 


‘they become better in their private lives they are utterly wrong.” 


If they claim that it gives them more practical power than other 
arts, we retort that all do not obtain power, but some are 
banished and hated. Gorgias’ statement °° that the rhetorician 
is more artistic than any other artist we shall consider later. 


BOOK V. 


This book consists of three groups of fragments. The first group is 
contained in vol. II pp. 131-143, and is designated as A by Sudhaus in his 
introduction; the second group is in vol. II pp. 143-167, designated as B 
by Sudhaus; the third group, vol. I pp. 225-270, comprises eight uncon- 
nected fragments, and a more or less continuous series designated as C. 
The contents of this book are foreshadowed at the close of the fourth 
book by the statement, “We postpone to another time the discussion of 
the claim that rhetoric is harmful because based on deceit.” A large por- 
tion of the fifth book is occupied with a presentation of the disadvantages 
of rhetoric. This is, however, only a foil to the praises of Epicurean 
philosophy which are given in the form of a comparison of rhetoric and 
philosophy. In a portion of the book, at least, Philodemus discusses a 
treatise in praise of rhetoric, the statements of which are taken up and 
refuted one by one. 

Briefly stated the contents of the book are:—Rhetoric is harmful, and 
useless in actual practice in public life; it is no protection against syco- 
phants, but a trained speaker is even at a disadvantage before a jury 
because they expect to be deceived by his specious arguments. If a man 
expects to use it as a means to public preferment he should remember that 


* The claims of rhetoric here refuted are perhaps the common claims of 
Philodemus’ own day. However they are at least as old as Isocrates, 
whose statement of them is perhaps the best; v. the chapter on Isocrates 
in the author’s, The Influence of Isocrates on Cicero, etc. 

” Cf. Plato, Gorgias, 456C. I. e. better able to discuss medicine than 
the physician. 


Ie, 222, ‘col: 
GAN E 


i222" col: 
XLIMI2. 


IME, nee ie IE 


le seks silce 
| 


T 


Il, 134, 
ities Ae 


306 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


statesman suffer death, exile and dishonor from the people they try to lead, 
and that if they succeed in avoiding popular displeasure, very few attain 
eminence; the toils of rhetoric more than counterbalance its advantages. 
The rhetorician’s claim that the promises of rhetoric are possible of ful- 
fillment, and those of philosophy, impossible, can hardly be meant seri- 
ously; if rhetoric promises to satisfy all one’s desires, the philosopher 
replies that most of these desires are unnatural and impossible of satis- 
faction; the true way is to apply the teachings of philosophy and so limit 
one’s desires. If it be asked what benefit philosophy confers on a State, 
we reply, it makes men good citizens, content with their lot; philosophy 
is the only true benefactor. 

Rhetoric claims to be able to “sail the deep seas” i. e. to speak at length 
on any subject, while the philosophers use the dialectic method. But the 
philosophers can use both methods when they desire; the real difference 
between the two is that the philosophers use strict logic, while the rhetori- 
cians use only probabilities and guesswork. But moral questions cannot 
be settled by guesswork. 

The rhetoricians say that there is no morality except that established by 
popular opinion, and that the philosophers try to establish a new morality, 
like a new coinage. This is not true of the Epicureans. They agree with 
the people that the end of all conduct is pleasure, but they differ on the 
means to be employed to attain the end. It is really the statesman who 
differs from the popular conceptions. 

The rhetoricians say that a virtuous man unable to defend himself from 
malicious attacks is a miserable sight; rhetoric defends a man, virtue does 
not. But the disgrace falls on the attackers not on the virtuous man. 
Philosophy provides everything necessary for a happy life. 


(Quoting from some Epicurean? author)—he adds that the 
training given by the sophists does not prepare for forensic or 
deliberative oratory. 

(Fres. II and III are hopeless.) 

To tell the truth the rhetors do a great deal of harm to many 
people, and incur the enmity of powerful rulers, whereas phi- 
losophers gain the friendship of public men by helping them 
out of their troubles. Ought we not to consider that men who 
incur the enmity of those in authority are villains, and hated by 
both gods and men. 

[Those trained in other arts, without training in rhetoric] 
can speak, not, to be sure rhetorically, but as laymen or dia- 
lecticians or philosophers. What is the loss incurred by inability 
to speak rhetorically? I do not mean to say that one trained to 
be a soldier, a gymnast or a dialectician could not possess a 


> A igne 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 307 


knowledge of rhetoric, but that many would not. If they did 
not abandon the deceit involved in practical rhetoric they 
would not be able to acquire such rhetorical ability as even 
philosophy provides. . . . Sophistic style is suited to epideictic 
oratory and written works, but not to actual practice in forum 
and ecclesia. 

More men are acquitted because of the lack of rhetoric than 
by means of it; nay even stammering is more persuasive than 
any other form of speech. For it is well said that the juryman 
is not affected by any form of speech as much as by the just and 
prudent actions of the uneducated, and in trials they fear being 
misled by the rhetor. In speaking one should not resort to 
ignoble rhetorical tricks; these have less effect than a straight- 
forward character. 

Speeches of this sort are no disgrace, if the object of forensic 
oratory be to set forth the facts, and not to show one’s power. 
It is certainly not true that rhetoric is a weapon to be used 
against sycophants. 

Suppose one to have an abundance of delicate food and drink, 
but to be suffering great physical or mental torment, could one 
enjoy them? : The implied comparison is: one cannot enjoy the power 
and wealth which are the prizes of rhetoric, if one has to endure its 
toils. It is this thought, apparently which is worked out in fr. X. 

If they spend all their time about the courts, and start many 
lawsuits because of their knowledge of that sort of life, when 
they are brought to trial themselves they are ruined (because of 
the prejudice against professional speakers); if they make a 
sparing use of their professional knowledge in order to appear 
modest, they lose some of their power, and at the same time 
forfeit that peace of life and solidity of character which 
contribute most to success. 

Every good and honest man who confines his interest to phi- 
losophy alone, and disregards the nonsense of lawyers, can 
face boldly all such troubles, yea all powers and the whole world. 

We do not claim that rhetoric is bad in itself, even if it fur- 
nishes weapons for wicked men, but. it does not indicate what 
use is to be made of the power it gives, so as to fit in with our 


paceerutist bet Lit, 1, 5; I, 7,.36-37. 


IL, 136; ir: 


VI 


PE 37, ir 
Vit. 


TE 138> in 
IX 


Lil 130; ine 
Be 


Il, 140, iri 
XII, 


BIS TAS vir: 
XIIt. 


D1, tae te, 
LY. 


TT, 343, fe. 


ily id, tr. 
Il, 


Ul; tas, fr. 
iT, 


ET). 2475008. 
IV. 


iT, 
fr. V. 


308 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


principles of justice and honor. Rhetoricians are like pilots, 
who have a good training but may be bad men. . 

Those who are troubled with the itch make it worse by scratch- 
ing. If they would only endure the annoyance of the itch, and 
think less about it they would get better. So with those who 
suffer from sycophants.” 

[Giving everyone rhetorical ability with the idea that he will 
use it only in self-defence] is like giving a brigand or slave a 
sword, and bidding him strike only those who attack him. 

But this does not apply any more to philosophy and the 
Epicureans who refrain from such things, than the remarks of 
those who combine contradictory principles in their instruction 
affect medicine. 

[ Men are lured away from their home towns; the small towns 
have to sacrifice their best to the large cities.] Many are 
attracted by Athens with its enthusiasm for philosophy, and the 
opportunity to enjoy the siren song of the philosophical schools; 
some are detained by great capitals, Alexandria and Rome, 
either by necessity (as hostages?) or by the fact that they can 
derive therefrom some great advantage for themselves or their 
country. This I say in excusing philosophers [for going to live 
in great cities]. But perchance, some one else might be rude 
enough to pray that many of the rhetors be compelled to reside 
the rest of their lives in a foreign land, because the cities they 
leave will be better off than those to which they go. 

Let us now take up the comparison of rhetoric and philosophy 
in another fashion. One statement—that the promises of 
rhetoric are possible of fulfillment, whereas the promises of 
philosophy seem to be made only in jest, and are so far from 
actuality that few have ever followed them. 

Many rhetors have been banished or executed for many strange 
reasons, even for insignificant reasons. All this risk they run, 
and yet only two or three of them can speak brilliantly, the 
majority disgracefully. There follow examples of rhetors who met 
with disaster, Themistocles, Alcibiades and Callistratus. 

This remark praises rhetoric because it strengthens the wicked, 


*I should read in 1. 14 cvxopavrias. The thought then parallels that of 
fr. VII. Sycophants are not to be fought by heir own weapons, but by 
paying no attention to them. 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 309 


on the assumption that it would not deserve praise if it merely 
tried to hinder them and punished them if they did not obey. 

Fragment VI is not substantial enough to enable us to form an opinion 
of its meaning. Fr. VII and VIII answer the argument that rhetoric 
gives men higher pleasures and greater power than ordinary people 
possess. 

It is not necessary or even possible to satisfy unnatural and 
cultivated appetites. But the natural desires can easily be satis- 
fied in all pure men—not merely in great rhetors like Pericles; 
consequently philosophy which teaches us how to limit our 
desires is better than rhetoric which helps us to satisfy them. 

I do not believe that even the greatest rhetors can accomplish 
all they wish even in their own cities, for then they would be 
tyrants. Rather it is true that men held in great honor by the 
people, when they try to restrain them from following their own 
pleasures are humiliated, fined and killed.* 


From the mention of players on the cithara, and physicians and painters 


II, 150, fr. 
VII. 


Wis di Sa 
VIIL. 


JU Een pre 


I judge that this is part of a comparison of the value of these professions IX 


and sophistic to a city. The passage, however, is sadly mutilated. Frag- 
ments X and XI are hopeless. 

-Rhetors find their public friendly until they have received 
civil honors at their hands, and then find it hostile. For the 
mob is envious of those whom it has honored, and always thinks 
that its heroes make an inadequate return for the honors they 
have received. Consequently it is better not to receive public 
preferment. 

It is objected (by the rhetoricians) that philosophers do not 
help their country. That is the reason why Critolaus’ advice 
to a philosopher not to join a colony was not regarded as ridicu- 
lous. But if philosophers do not enter politics, yet they help 
their native land by teaching the young to obey the laws; nay 
more, by teaching them to act justly even if there are no laws, 
and to shun injustice as they would fire. 

[They say] that not only Lycurgus and Pittacus, but also those 
who established constitutions were of this nature (i. e. rhetors?). 
But not even those who had rhetorical ability were like these, 


* Fuhr, Rhein. Mus. LVII (1902) p. 431, proposes these emendations in 
te VIS Kakdoewy OF aripwoewy, Snuctoewv or Puyadedy. 


IF, 154) is. 
XII. 


II, 154, fr. 
XIII. 


Er. Fe5s is: 
XIV. 


UL, TR iY, 
XVII. 


Suite 


II, 15 
XVII 


Ny 


II, 158, fr. 
le 


Lf, 50,644: 
bO.S 


II, 160, 


XXI-XXV. 


Li e162 etre 
XXVII. 


I Tey a9 
XXIX. 


310 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 

but with different intent, and with varying experience they 
turned to managing the public revenues and other matters of 
administration, and were quite inferior to Callistratus and 
Demosthenes.* 

(Fragments XV and XVI are hopeless.) 

It is better to learn (from philosophy) to care for oneself, 
than (from rhetoric) to care for the multitude of common people 
in all sorts of conditions. A rhetor is like a magician; able to 
bring down the moon, but what good does he get from it? 

[An opponent says] “No philosopher qua philosopher could 
benefit anyone.” If he had added that the philosophers refrain 
from speaking their mind freely whether at home or in exile, 
he would have brought his impudence to the proper conclusion. 
For by their lives, their conversation (they benefit their fol- 
lowers). 

A complete investigation of the causes destructive of friend- 
ship would reveal that politics is the worst foe of friendship ; 
for it generates envy, ambition and discord. 

If we throw them (the philosophers) some small change we 
find them satisfied, not affecting a proud and haughty attitude 
like the rhetors. If we are right in considering externals of 
little importance, and the soul more important than anything 
else, then philosophy is the only true benefactor. Moreover the 
rhetors charge for the help they give, and so cannot be considered 
benefactors; the philosophers give their instruction without cost. 

(Fragments XXI—XXV are hopeless.) 

Furthermore we must add that philosophers are not really 
hated by all men, for they live in peace and justice and tried 
friendship; those whom they find opposed to them they quickly 
soften. 

They acquired the inability to speak rhetorically from the 
ability. You can not rightly say that anyone acquired inability 
in war from rhetorical ability. That one derives the inability 
to speak rhetorically from the ability is not correct, nor merely 
that he acquired that as being able to accomplish something in 


*The meaning would be plainer if we had the beginning of the first 
sentence. Apparently Philodemus is combating the claim that rhetoric 
produces great statesmen. Many, he says, have to content themselves with 
menial tasks. - 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 311 


contests of speaking, but that he acquired the inability to speak 
rhetorically. 

(First part obscure.) It is impossible to check up the relative 
success of speakers rhetorically trained and those not so trained. 
No one has ever counted all the cases, not even those in his own 
lifetime, or in a single year; and yet you have the confidence to 
say that more persuade by rhetorical means than by the simple 
processes of nature. 

There remains the subject of “proof,” of which Anaximenes 
says . . . “Speech is the best means to persuade the soul.” 
In the first place this is false, for money and a thousand other 
things persuade more powerfully than speech. 

In a picture all is light and shadow; painting cannot produce 
a living being. 

Epicurus has this in dialogue form; “First let us agree on 
the end for which we do everything, in order that we may 
know. : 

It is worth our while to consider what sort of a life those 
have lived who have spent it all in prosecution and defence. 
Even when priding themselves on their profession they admit 
that it is well not to pass one’s whole life in such occupation; 
but just as it is possible not to have any experience in law courts, 
so it is desirable not to be idle, or to see children or friends 
suffer, or suffer misfortune in marriage, or lose money, or suffer 
similar misfortune. 


Philosophy is more profitable than epideictic rhetoric, espe- 
cially if one practice rhetoric in the fashion of the sophists. . . 

The philosopher has many réro concerning practical justice 
and other virtues about which he is confident; the busybody 
(i. e. the rhetorician) is quite the opposite. Nor is one who 
does not appear before kings and popular assemblies forced to 
play second part to the rich, as do rhetors who are compelled to 
employ flattery all their lives. 

The instruction given by the sophists is not only stupid but 
shameless, and lacking in refinement and reason. 

(Fragments I1V—VIII and col. II are hopeless.) 

He makes an incredible statement when he claims that one 
skilled in such subjects (viz. philosophy) could not be of noble 


II, 164, 
XXX. 


it 


Pe 165, ir: 


XXXI. 


IT, 166, 


fr 


XXXII. 


iem2ore 


I 226; 
wie. J 
I, 223, 
lente 


I, 237, 
Ill 


ite 


fr; 


I, 234, col. 
IV. 


I, 234, 
coll V. 


I, 235, col. 
Vi. 


VII 


1,237; col: 


Vill 


I, 230, col. 
IX. 


Ie 230,7col- 


312 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


character, and that such studies bring’ no one happiness, and that 
no one except a madman would be interested in them. For apart 
from the knowledge an educated man ought to have, he should 
obey the laws, realizing that they apply to him. 

If the goodwill of one’s country is esteemed the fairest crown 
of victory, the defeated also ought to fare well. A common 
country should bestow benefits in common. But as we see in 
one country a rhetor neglected rather than crowned, and in 
another country one is banished, tortured and insulted, let us 
without claiming a share in the ability to manage a city by per- 
suasion, be content [to live the quiet life of a philosopher]. 

Very few if any of the [tyrants] have been overthrown by 
their mercenaries, whereas many statesmen have been rejected 
by their fellow citizens, and slaughtered like cattle, nay they are 
worse off than cattle, for the butcher does not hate the cattle, 
but the tortures of the dying statesmen are made more poignant 
by hatred. 

It is claimed for rhetoric that it protects property like a strong 
tower. First if we are not rich we do not need rhetoric. Sec- 
ondly it is much better to lose one’s wealth if one can not keep 
it otherwise, than to spend one’s life in rhetoric. 

But Cephenides (Drone) the rich man is a prey to slaves 
and prophets as well as to sycophants. 

they are unable to make the multitude friendly to them, 
as the crowd of politicians can. 

The philosophers are not vexed if people, like foolish sheep 
or cattle, attend to an inferior, but are satisfied that what they 
say, particularly about the attitude of the common people, shall 
please the few; and in action they are most blameless, nor do 
they as slaves of all, try to rule everything for themselves. 
For they do not expect to satisfy their wants at the expense of 
the public. But those philosophers who envy other’s property 
while they pretend to need nothing, and are detected being coy, 
these men the people despise, but consider them less wretched 
than the rhetors, because so many obtain the same result that 
the rhetors obtain. 

It is numbered among the glories of rhetoric that it can “sail 
the deep seas”’® while those who speak briefly are rejected like 


5 a tex poneyetv (Gnie the drecicsion of ee ee in Plato, 


Gorgias 449B; Prot. 334C—338B; Cic. De Orat. III 36, 145; Quint. XII 
proem. 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 313 


small boats unable to sail far from shore, because they accom- 
plish nothing brilliant. If by “sail the deep seas” they mean 
“make long speeches,’ then rhetoric is a crazy profession.’ If 
by “sail deep seas” they mean treat at length a subject needing 
detailed treatment, and arrogate to themselves alone this power, 
not even then are they in their right minds; for the philosophers, 
or any one else with sense can treat a subject in this manner. 
However if they examine a subject minutely by their “deep 
sea’? method, then the rhetors are mistaken in thinking they 
speak only about large subjects. . . . 1. 26. They borrow the 
dialectic method from the philosophers, and pride themselves on 
something which they reject as a principle. 

For the method of question and answer is necessary not only 
in philosophy and education, but often in the ordinary inter- 
course of life. The method of joint inquiry frequently demands 
this style. Moreover this method is adopted by the rhetor in 
the assembly as well as in the court of justice. “Rhetoric enables 
a man to be a guard of metics, a friend of citizens and a pro- 
tector of those of lesser rank.”’ Therefore one could not say 
that a rich man does not possess happiness unless he knows 
rhetoric, but that he is much better off without it. For he ought 
not to fortify himself, but to free himself from paying ransom to 
speechwriters. 

Consequently though both methods are useful, they neglect 
one of them. Those who say that the rhetors use the method 
of question and answer in its highest degree cannot prove that 
this method is peculiar to them, nor that they rather than the 
philosophers wrote technical works about it. Neither the 
modern sophists in their teaching, nor the ancients in their pub- 
lished works attained such distinction in dialectic as have the 
philosophers. 

They say that the rhetor does not seek pleasure from such 
foolish subjects as geometry, but producing arts and sciences 
of daily life, he directs men to that path which leads to the city 
and place of assembly, which they themselves follow. It is 
ridiculous for them to say that geometry produces pleasure and 
glory. Certainly we do not claim to devote our whole life to 


*Col. IX 21-34 is a dittography of col. X, 1-14. 
“Cf. Schneidewin, Studia Philodemea, p. 10, n. 26. 


I, 240, 
col. X. 


I, 241, col. 
XI. 


I, 242, col. 
XII. 


I, 244, col. 
MITE. 


I, 245, col. 
1 ACD Fie 


I, 249, col. 
XV 


314 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


it. . . ., The philosopher* is versed in the characters and 
methods of living which result in faction and exile, through a 
knowledge of which it is possible most correctly to govern the city 
and the assembly. The sophists have unawares, made a simile 
which applies to themselves; for it is their profession which does 
not enter into the civil life and the assembly, and is of no help 
to human life. So it is reasonable that some do not care at 
all for what they say, but refuse to accept rhetoric and sophistic 
and politics even cursorily, considering one foolish, the other 
most inimical to peace of mind. 

If the remarks following directly after these were intended to 

apply to the dialecticians—they are no concern of ours; if they 
apply to us they are mere chatter, because when we claim to 
speak accurately as the rhetors cannot because their speeches 
are composed of probabilities, they proceed to say that spider 
webs are finer than cloth but less useful; similarly the finespun 
subtleties of the philosophers are useless for practical purposes 
because no one in deliberating uses syllogisms, but probabilities. 
So that if we use syllogisms, what appeared advantageous at 
one time would not remain so; whence there is no one possi- 
bility which will be advantageous if brought to pass, but the 
only thing left is to guess on a basis of probability. 
After assuming that speeches can be made according to strict 
logic, they proceed to use in ‘both deliberative and forensic 
oratory, nothing but probabilities, and often the less probable 
rather than the more; besides they seek broad effect rather than 
accuracy and systematic treatment, as is natural since they have 
no method, but depend entirely on observation, and quickly dis- 
card their observations because of the changes of the populace 
which are quicker than those of the Euripus.® But the 
philosophers do not restrict themselves to rigidly logical 
argument. : 

The nature of justice and injustice—that one is always advan- 
tageous and the other never, can be settled entirely by strict 
logic. Anyone who applies guesswork to such subjects is simply 


®* For the emendation v. Schneidewin p. 12 f. 
°On the Euripus as a type of fickleness cf. Plato, Phaedo, 90C; Rhet. 
Gr.W. I, p. 591, 21. 


JA mre ras 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 315 


foolish. Then their talk about spider webs, bits and saws for 
cutting millet seeds is nonsense.*° . . . It is clearly proven 
that the art of the rhetor is of no assistance for a life of 
happiness. 

[The sophist says] it is better to estimate roughly on large 
subjects than to treat accurately of some small subject of no 
importance. Perhaps we can add to the accomplishments of 
rhetoric that it can talk in a general way about subjects of no 
importance. The comparison of great and small subjects is kept up 
at the end of the column in the reference to fishing for tunnies and 
sprats. 

.- to one who wonders why they can see clearly into a 
dark and difficult subject, and are unable to see what is in plain 
sight of all, they apply the figure of the owl. Such remarks as 
they made about oaths and counsels, not only no philosopher but 
not even a man of ordinary taste would. . . . The doctrines 
of the philosophers are not too finespun for practical life, and 
the doctrines of the rhetors are not suitable, so that having 
demonstrated that the doctrines of the politicians are like one or 
the other—they compare us to owls. 

Their next statement is that there is no distinction between 
justice and injustice except that commonly accepted by the people, 
and that those who assume a different standard are like those 
who seek to substitute a coinage of their own for that established 
by the state; the new coinage is useless, for it will not pass 
current and the maker’s life would not be safe. 

By rhetoric neither [is accomplished] as it seems, but political 
science is not investigated or taught by the rhetoricians, either 
exclusively or to a higher degree than by others. 

The philosophers of our school agree with of roAAof on a 
question of what is just and good, differing from them only in 
this that they arrive at their conclusions by logic as well as by 
feeling, and never forget these conclusions, but always compare 


I, 250, col. 
p-OVAUUE 


Ip2r2acor 
XIX. 


I, 253, col. 
XIX, 1. 35. 


I, 254, col. 


the chief good with things indifferent. They do differ from XXI 


oi roAAot about the means to attain happiness, and do not think 
that offices, power, conquests and the like are proper means 


x = 


? Following the restoration of Schneidewin, p.14; . . . Tpumdvwy kal 
arpiovwy oloticw Kéyxpous Kal Ta ToLAITAa TpyTGor Kal dearplover, 


I, 256, col. 
XXII. 


en 7 col 
XXIII. 


I, 258, col. 
XXIV. 


I, 258, col. 
XOVE leo: 


I, 259, col. 
>. OVE 


316 ; Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


to the end. Similarly the principles derived by them from 
“notions” we judge to be just and noble; but we differ from 
the common opinion as to what corresponds to the “notion.” 
(I. e. what produces the end—pleasure—which is perceived by 
all.) 

Not only some philosophers differ from the popular ideas of 
right and wrong, but all statesmen do. For in their period of 
office they are wholly concerned to change popular opinion on 
questions of right and justice and advantage. If this is so, how 
do we resemble those who scorn) current coinage, and seek for 
substitutes? Apart from the fact that we do not despise theories 
based on “notions,” how could we be said to be acting in this 
way if we assume the true principles of right and wrong? For 
some of these are helpful to them as well as to us whether they 
grant it or not; others are really established customs, and will 
not allow themselves to be used unless we assume them in keep- 
ing with the former principles. For if they do not have the 
true idea of hot and cold, it is not our authority which they 
oppose. It is possible for a fate to befall them like that of those 
who differ (with their states) about coinage—and how can their 
search be called useless if there is really anything better—if the 
cities will not accept the innovations, and the inventor’s life is 
not safe. For it makes no difference to those truly well. if 
others will not adopt hygienic measures, nor to those who avoid 
fire or snow, if others refuse to acknowledge the natural qualities 
residing in them. It is astounding for them to say that the 
natural means of safety will not protect them. 

Some things are just or unjust by nature. and never change, 
others vary according to locality and condition. Laws which 
are not of this nature, but are established for various reasons 
ought to be obeyed, or if the philosophers do not think that 
they can live well under these laws they ought to leave the 
country. They can be social to a high degree by observing 
those principles which make for likeness and not for difference ; 
we can do this without being observed as well as with publicity ; 
with pleasure and not under compulsion; steadily and not in 
an uncertain fashion. 

If rhetoric imparts an experience of these things, so that it 
is the only road to the happy life, yet it does not lead to courts 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 317 


and assemblies, where there are more wrecks than ever at Cape 
Caphereus. 

[Rhetoricians say that this art makes men good] for one 
will wish to seem prudent and just in order to obtain favors from 
the people.” 

[It is strange that one would not endure to be taught virtue] 
whereas if he were sick he would endure being forced to undergo 
treatment. But their interjection of the argument that virtue 
cannot be taught is untimely. For Socrates showed that political 
virtue cannot be taught, proving his case by the inability of 
Themistocles, Aristides and Pericles to train their sons to be 
their equals. By the same means one could prove that sophistic 
rhetoric cannot be taught. 1. 30 But “rhetoric would be able 
to benefit a man who by its help can persuade the people that 
he is of high character.” Quite the contrary; even if a man 
be virtuous otherwise, he is considered a scoundrel because he 
is a rhetor. They say that we ought to believe that there is 
something better than truth which does not persuade, on the 
testimony of Euripides who says; ‘Mortals’ coin is not only 
shining silver but virtue” (i. e. virtue in the commonly accepted 
sense). At any rate they purchase many things by character, 
as well as by money. But why should a philosopher pay atten- 
tion to Euripides, especially since he has no proof . . . ? 
Some say they pursue virtue not expecting to receive anything 
from it; others desire safety for the sake of happiness. 

“Suppose a virtuous man made the object of a slanderous 
attack, and unable to persuade the jury of his innocence; he 
would be punished, not pitied and honored.” Certainly. But 
worst of all is not to recognize exalted virtue, but to consider 
it wickedness. According to the argument of the rhetors one 
ought to study the reputable rather than the monstrous—and 
that when the greatest statesmen bring to the bema things which 
should be associated only with the vilest of men.| The so-called 
virtuous men when they are called to account before the people 
refuse to stand trial. They think they are to suffer a treatment 


™ Cape on Euboea where a fleet returning from Troy was wrecked. Cf. 
Vergil, Aen. XI, 256-260: Propert. III, VII, 39-40. (Quoted by Gros.) 

“Cf. Isoc. Ant. 278: dow rep div Tis Eppwpevertépws érBuuy metBev Tods dxovovras, 
TogoUTw UaAKov aoKjoe Kahds Kayabds iva Kal mapa rots oNirats evdoKimerv. 


e261, cole 
XXVI. 


I, 264, col. 
XXVIII. 


I, 265, col. 


XXIX. 


I, 266, col. 


XXX. 


I, 268, coi. 


XXXII. 


I, 260, col. 


XXXII. 


318 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


much worse than that accorded to the sick, much less acquire 
virtue, just as if virtue were not a real good, or there were no 
real cure which the people apply when they judge a man in the 
wrong. 

“Furthermore it has been said that we (i. e. the rhetoricians) 
fight not against external enemies at whose hand it is honorable 
to die, but against internal enemies at whose hands it is disgrace- 
ful to die; that/we have nothing to do with virtue—for that did 
not save Socrates ;—nor with medicine—that saves men from 
disease, not from prison; nor with any other profession than 
rhetoric which helps those who strive not only for their lives 
but to obtain money, and to prevent disfranchisement and exile.” 

However we shall repel our enemies with their own weapons. 
Virtue did not help Socrates because when he was led to court 
it was lacking in some people. Medicine and other professions 
help even in prison. If a philosopher falls a victim to such a 
death, it is not a disgrace to him but to those who kill him. 
However he does not live in fear of meeting such a fate. For 
the superstitions of the common people do not disturb one who 
is persuaded that he shall have no existence after death. 

If for these reasons persuasion was reasonably considered a 
good by them, she would have been deified by philosophy. The 
fact that through it no little harm is done is not true of phi- 
losophical persuasion, but of rhetorical which Pisistratus used; 
wherefore it does not belong to the category of the greatest 
goods as they perversely say,!® nor to the special categories of 
power and wealth. If one does not use these well, he would 
receive much harm. Philosophy shows us how to find and use 
everything necessary for a happy life. 


BOOK VI. 


In the sixth book Philodemus attacks the philosophical schools which 
advocated the study of rhetoric. The extant portion discusses Nausi- 
phanes and Aristotle. The attack was extended to others as we can see 
from II, 64, col. LVIII, but the identity of the persons attacked cannot be 
determined. In this book as in many others, Philodemus is merely para- 


“Reading for kat ws 1, 15 Kkaxk@s with von Arnim, Hermes XXVIII 
(1893) p. 154. 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 319 


phrasing the works of earlier Epicureans; the criticism of Nausiphanes 
seems quite clearly to be based on Metrodorus’ IIpds rods dwd puawwdoylas 
Aéyorvras dyabods eivac phropas. The fragments are of very uneven value; 
there are large sections of connected argument, in which the relation of 
the pages can be clearly demonstrated; but many of the pages stand by 
themselves, and the trend of the thought is not always clear. However by 
a judicious piecing together of the several parts we can at least gain an 
idea of the tenets of Nausiphanes. As the present arrangement of the 
fragments in Sudhaus separates ideas which belong together, it may assist 
the reader if a résumé of Nausiphanes’ doctrine is given here with a 
brief statement of his position in the controversy over rhetoric. 

Nausiphanes was a natural philosopher (@vorxéds) of the latter part of 
the fourth century, a pupil of Democritus and teacher of Epicurus. 
Although Epicurus must have owed much of the foundation of his own 
system to Nausiphanes, he took pains to deny any connection with him, 
and even abused his master in no uncertain language. The feud thus 
instituted by Epicurus was continued by Metrodorus and is reéchoed in 
Philodemus. The chief tenet of Nausiphanes, that a study of natural 
philosophy (¢vo.doyia) is the best training for an orator, sounds like an 
absurd freak. Absurd it may have been in the effort to connect natural 
philosophy and oratory, but it was a natural product of the educational 
tendencies of the time. The educators of his period were afraid of a 
divided authority. Some way must be found to enable one teacher to 
guide the higher studies of the youth. As the ideal of education was for 
the most part preparation for public life, and as oratorical ability was 
indispensable for the aspiring politician in the Greek state, Nausiphanes 
was compelled in self defence to show how a study of natural philosophy 
could train an orator. As presented in Philodemus he appears ridiculous ; 
we may perhaps be justified in believing that here as elsewhere, Philo- 
demus has not been too scrupulous in presenting the views of his 
opponents. Disentangled from the maze of Philodemus’ polemic the 
principles of Nausiphanes may be stated as follows: the study of natural 
philosophy produces orators; the natural philosopher derives from his 
study of nature the knowledge of the causes of pleasure, and so is able to 
guide his audience toward the true end of all action. Contrary to the 
Epicurean view he holds that the philosopher should enter politics. The 
style of the natural philosopher is plain iike that of the average man, and 
so is better adapted to explain a difficult case than the elaborate style of 
the rhetoricians. The orators use of logic is the same as that of the 
dialectician and the philosopher; Tapddevyua = éraywyh, evOdunua = ovd- 
hoyioubs, the only difference is in the manner of presentation. Finally a 
study of science produces in the student a political state of mind, so that 
every natural philosopher is potentially an orator." 

The discussion of Aristotle begins with the well known parody of the 


*For a full discussion of Nausiphanes and this portion of Philodemus 
v. von Arnim, Leben und Werke des Dio von Prusa, pp. 43-62. 


I, 270. 


I, 276. 


I, 283, 


col. II. 


320 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


verse from the Philoctetes; alexpdv cwmrdr, ‘Iooxpdrny 5 éav déyev, by 
which Aristotle justified his excursion into rhetoric. It resolves itself 
into a comparison of philosophy and rhetoric, and a vilification of Aris- 
totle for choosing the lower of the two professions. This polemic like 
the preceding is part of the inheritance of the Epicurean School; Epi- 
curus, we know, was particularly bitter against Aristotle.” Perhaps the 
most remarkable part is his exaltation of Isocrates; “while Aristotle 
descended from philosophy to rhetoric, Isocrates rose from rhetoric to 
philosophy.” This passage must rest on a misinterpretation of Isocrates’ 
use of ¢iAocodia, a misinterpretation which must be deliberate on the part 
of Philodemus, and not due to any love of Isocrates, but to a desire to 
take a fling at Aristotle. Beside the general criticism of rhetoric which 
forms the bulk of the passage, Philodemus gives three reasons alleged by 
Aristotle for the study of rhetoric and politics: it wins friends, it helps 
produce a stable government which is favorable to philosophy, the present 
evil conditions in politics demand the help of the philosopher. The first 
two are answered and the third is under discussion when the fragment 
ends.* 

Of fragments I-X VII the only parts that give even a gleam of meaning 
are fr. XI and XII. Here from the contrast of dvadéyerfar and Adyor 
éxretvat it appears that the discussion is turning on the relative merits of 
rhetoric and dialectic, which we found discussed at some length in Book V 
(rwedaylgev, xT. I, 239) and which appears below, col. XLIII. A little 
light breaks through in fr. XVIII. This is the end of a paragraph. 
Philodemus sums up with ‘There is no art which treats of forensic 
eloquence, corresponding to the art of music. (From here to 
fr. XXX nothing consecutive can be made out.) 

It is evident that het used the word ‘rhetoric’ with reference 
either to sophistic or to political rhetoric, or to the power to 
decide on an advantageous course of action. Grant that as many 
erroneously think, rhetoric is the ability to select an advantageous 


course of action. 


*Cic., De Nat. Deor. I, 33, 93: Cum Epicurus Aristotelem vexarit con- 
tumeliossime. 

“For details v. Sudhaus, Aristoteles in der Beurtheilung des Epikur und 
Philodem, Rhein. Mus. XLVIII (1893) pp. 552-564. Gomperz, Zeit. f. d. 
ost. Gymn. XXIII (1872) p. 31, holds that Philodemus may have had 
before him Aristotle’s dialogue, Politicus. Philodemus also criticizes 
Aristotle in the Ilept roumudrwr, on which v. Gomperz in Wiener Eranos 
(1909) 1-8. 

*Sudhaus, Rhein. Mus. XLVIII (1893) p. 334, thinks that Philodemus is 
quoting from Metrodorus IIpds rods ard gvowdoylas Aéyovras ayabods elvac 
phropas. 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 321 


If some of the rhetorical sophists because of their political 
insight or experience can choose an advantageous course, we 
must not assign the credit to rhetoric but to some other source. 

It is not plain how one is to pass from general truths to the 
application of these truths in particular instances.° 

evOvpyynpata differ from onpeta and muotwpara. 

The relation between truth and its opposite is not the same 
as between two probabilities, one more probable than the other. 
We must have either truth or falsehood. Would one accept 
probability in place of truth except in cases where truth is 
impossible of attainment? 

A man should examine carefully and search for truth, and not 
use vain enthymemes. For it is clear that one who states the 
actual good points of which the accuser denies the existence, 
and thus lessens the exaggeration in the minds of the judges, 
would attain the useful result of expressing the full content of 
the argument which comes from a study of nature. 

A study of nature does not give one a knowledge of the 
eeoad.. the. true’ or the .“just.” 

One who claims that a knowledge of what course of action to 
pursue comes from a study of the universe, ought to specify 
[how it is done]. 

It is necessary to make choices with a view to happiness, and 
not with some vain hope. They ought to show that ¢vowdoyia 
leads to happiness, because most people think that ¢vovdroya 
is far removed from what is useful in life. 

In the interval between the publication of the first and second volumes 
Sudhaus discovered that this papyrus formed the upper half of the orig- 
inal, and that the lower half was Hercul. Voll. coll. alt. tom. VII, fol. 
44-67. He combined the two fragments in the second volume. From this 
point therefore I follow vol. II. 

He (Nausiphanes) said that the natural philosopher and the 
“wise man” will persuade their audience. He left no doubt 
that by wise man he meant himself. But the essence of method 
lies in concealing the method. 

Certainly he will not expect such a task to belong to the 
rhetorical sophists or the statesmen. 


°T. e. how a knowledge of the laws of nature derived from a study of 
science can enable one to decide a particular point of political policy. 


I, 284, col. 
III. 
I, 284, col. 
IV. 


I, 285, col. 
We desley 
col, VI. 


I, 286, col. 
VII. 


lee267cols 
WAL 


I, 287, col. 
IX. 


I, 288, 
coll X. 


ieee cols 
x 


ie 2colee2) 


IT, 7, 


< 


Lz; 


col, 


col. 


col. 5. 


col. 


col. 6. 


322 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


If the hearer comprehend with sufficient intelligence and zeal 
the one who knows how to lead the argument in any direction 
he chooses, there is a science and faculty [of guiding the argu- 
ment] not whither the speaker, but whither the hearer wishes.® 

Who can persuade with the help of natural philosophy? 
Nausiphanes says, ‘Rhetoric strengthens and supports in time 
of trouble.‘ 

A man blames his neighbor for his own troubles ; consequently 
people will hate the rhetor for their political ills. Nausiphanes 
did not dodge this; for he says that the philosopher will prac- 
tice rhetoric or statesmanship [if his audience is intelligent] 
[This method then applies] only to the intelligent and interested 
(cf. col. XII). The majority of people are not interested in all 
-methods of persuasion, and they have not the patience to wait 
for the great blessing promised by the rhetor, but want something 
immediately.® 

Aside from this they are ill disposed to one who has such 
power, and fear that his tricks of reasoning will serve them ill. 
For he does not say, “I wish to persuade you to do what is 
for your good,” but he merely says® that he can persuade his 
audience to do what he wishes. 

An audience to whom such an announcement is made would 
never be persuaded by the speaker. Even if he made a logical 
presentation they would distrust him. Again, how does a knowl- 
edge of human nature enable the natural philosopher to per- 
suade? Does he know of what elements we are composed? 
How can it be that when one speaks of persuading the multitude 
one would persuade them by leading them to this (i. e. a con- 
dition of trustfulness) when after meeting with many misfortunes 
the people will refuse to be persuaded again? 


°This is Philodemus’ answer to the claim of Nausiphanes that the 
scientist can lead the audience whither he will—provided that the audience 
is intelligent. 

“Von Arnim reads (p. 50) BeBaodrar ev, pyolv, év Tots kaTa mpoalpeciy petvat 
pOnv, év 5€ Tots weylarous KaKols Kouplverac kal dvamvetrat, pytopiKhs dv Te mpoorondy, 
Ouvduews. 

® Reading with von Arnim, p. 40, 006° €orw brws TO copH Kayab@ mpocpetval 
Te moujoa TO mbppwhev ody Scov auvdpa cvvaicOnoe mpocdokjoal TL peyaNeloy, aN 
HOn Te BovdovT exeuv. 

* Reading Néyer for deve 1. 12, with Fuhr, Rhein. Mus. LVII (1902) p. 
434. 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 323 

What does this sort of persuasion amount to except a knowl- 
edge of pleasure and pain in a given case? It means treating 
men like animals. 

The persuasive element is the knowledge of the source of 
advantage. 

What about desires in particular cases about which men plan 
well or ill? If you ask directly, “Do you desire pleasure or 
pain?”, all will say, “Pleasure.” The difficulty is to know their 
desires in particular cases. 

They are vexed [says the natural philosopher] that the natural 
philosopher alone knows what nature desires, and is able to speak 
and argue relative to man’s desires. 

One cannot know what to do to please the people, for there 
are many things to change their minds quickly. And if the 
natural philosopher always has the same end in view, why does 
he not [succeed] ? 

If their art is a power of persuasion, it cannot depend on 
arguments from physical facts. They however deny that it is 
conjectural; for then there is no need of presenting a case 
persuasively. 

If they desire everything which the people wish, then it is 
impossible to ascertain the desires of the majority. 

He (i. e. the natural philosopher) cannot acquire any power 
to speak. For they will say that the rhetor speaks accurately 
and favorably if they will agree to obey him, or it is impossible 
to escape (the logic of his words). How can the natural 
philosopher know the opinion of his audience? 

Furthermore they will not listen to him even if he seem to 
speak according to their desire; much less will they follow 
whatever he says. For they will be troubled at the thought of 
recurring disaster because his advice has already resulted 
unfavorably. 

If he means that they try to say what the people wish, and 
what will not cause them to repent, he is foolish. For it is hard 
to know that the people will not repent, even if an action has 
been performed to suit them. They cannot see what serious 
mistakes we make in our own affairs. 

They do not say that if they are fully persuaded in their own 
thinds they will find many to agree with them; but simply that 
by the art of persuasion they can persuade an audience to do 


HT, .8; col. 
XVI. 


IE to) cole 7 


Dl, owcolk 


XVII. 


II, ro, col. 8. 


Le in veols 
MOVIL 


lipia2icolt 
XIX 


Ii 3p 
col. 10. 


Il: 13h col: 
XX. 


Ih ae! 
COle sit 


De 1s. cok 
XXII. 


lie t6y col: 
XXII. 


li 17, colt 
XXIII. 


118; 
col. 14. 


Col. XXIV. 


ILS. yo}, 
col. 16. 


Le 21 col: 
2LOMWAL 


22 cole 
XXVII. 


324 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


what they ‘wish. Nor can one know what the populace rejoice 
in as they depend on opinion and not on the natural end or 
object; nor if we could know it could any one persuade them.. 
For the mob changes and repents quickly. 

This column is practically hopeless. Von Arnim has a highly doubtful 
restoration on page 55. 

Their proposition to persuade reduces to a knowledge of 
justice and advantage which he (i. e. the natural philosopher) 
is best able to adapt to the common advantage.’® In the first 
place he cannot observe the relations of the subject, but will 
be excelled by one who has been engaged in public affairs and 
has practiced pleasing the people and advising them to do things 
that are within their power. Yet this resembles the doctrine of 
Nausiphanes. 

On the length of time one must spend with another in order to know 
him thoroughly." 

| And he seems to agree with us] for he says that persuasive 
power comes from knowledge of affairs rather than from 
personal investigation. But enough of him. 

Let us take up the next division. It is supposed that the 
natural philosopher is the best rhetor inasmuch as it is possible 
for a study of natural philosophy to give political experience 
and skill. “If,’ he says “he should add experience in political 
affairs, and learn the habits of the people as the philosopher 
studies natural philosophy.” Does this art produce ability to 
make political speeches by giving experience from which one may 
deduce what is of advantage to the people, or do they think it 
produces immediately a state of mind, so that the natural phi- 
losopher needs no practice or further study? If the former is 
the case they ought to show that one can become a political 
rhetor by experience. But no one would grant that any one 
who had acquired a knowledge of natural philosophy can make 
political speeches. We must understand the statement as if we 


= @fercol, LW: 

“Tf one has a natural philosopher living with him for a year and 
associating with him for a considerable time each day, he will be able to 
acquire such a knowledge of affairs as to make him a rhetor.” This is 
von Arnim’s interpretation of an exceedingly obscure passage. I do not 
feel at all sure that the details are right, or that we can assert more about 
the meaning of the passage than is given above. 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 325 
were examining some of the natural philosophers and not the 
art or products of the art. For we are not examining politics, 
but exhibiting what has been done by others; nor is his state- 
ment true that the natural philosopher will be best able to use 
the Aes didaxtuxy when that is needed to explain some difficult 
question to the people.’* The political scientist (so-called) has no 
experimental knowledge of the peculiar facts of politics; so 
when he attempts to make a speech he [goes astray] because 
he does not take due account of 76, and 7é6y. How can a 
natural philosopher become a politician and rhetor? He is 
exactly like a sophist who has no fundamental principles. 
Nausiphanes then 

“How is it possible that if one has the power to govern the 
state he will not desire to do so."* 

[The art of rhetoric] does -not lead to ease nor does it produce 
the best in the life of its possessor, nor incline him to 
improvement. 

partly from custom imposed from without, partly 


from the motions of the spirit within, there results a condition, 


which forces our language to say what is false and empty. 

“He did not imitate the common metaphors of those foolish 
men who have nothing better to do than listen to contests in the 
schools of oratory.’’™* 

Amazing is the style of the natural philosopher “composed 
for the delight of his audience, adorned with metaphors best 
designed for explaining the new subject, not in an empty style 
fixed by rule, but according to nature and sanctioned by custom,” 
a style which we found neither useful nor practicable, but vicious 
and almost deadly. Wherefore not even if the philosopher has 
something better to say will the people listen to him. For the 
speech of the philosopher does not differ from that of the states- 
man in its adaptation of the useful to the common needs of 
the city, but in its relation to the individual. 

The soul of the ordinary man is blind to it (the “natural” 
style of the natural philosopher) and so it has no power over the 


*T adopt the reading of von Arnim for 1. 9; kal unde 76 oddapds SidaxTixfs 
AéEews arropety. 

* This is the argument of Nausiphanes. 

* A quotation from Nausiphanes. 


IE 22) cok 
XXVIII. 


Li23acol 
XXIX. 


Ee 24-col: 
XXX. 


II, 25, col. 
XXXI. 


I Ae 
coll 17: 


lie, 26,-col: 
> OO 


II, 27, 
col. 18. 


TT, 28, cols 
XXXIII. 


Tee 20: 
col. Io. 


LT, 30; 
col. 20. 


Tai .cols 


XXXV. 


INE site 
col. 21. 


iees2=col. 


XXXVI. 


i, 33; 
col. 22. 


Ii s3) col: 
XXXVII. 


IT, 34, 
col. 23. 


326 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


multitude. : But this is no disadvantage, unless it can be called 
a disadvantage that they are not adapted by nature to receive 
the highest life. 

The philosopher does not choose his profession for the same 
reason that one chooses military or political power. The latter 
with a slowly acting mind is willing to accept any power, while 
the former by syllogisms and memory of resemblance and dif- 
ference, and a consideration of consequences, and especially by 
the use of his sharpness of intellect, rejects everything that does 
not tend toward happiness, and shares in them only as he uses 
the necessary arts for the tasks that arise. For to say positively 
that military and political power is the result of geometrical 
reasoning is vicious and is the product of a system that cannot 
reason or produce happiness. The philosopher is not of such 
a character but in every matter uses his keen mind, with which 
he is able to see when the ambition or idleness of men goes 
wrong, and neglects everything which is not useful for happiness. 

The aforementioned makes a foolish argument because in 
asking if the philosopher is adverse to lawmaking or military life 
or political economy he sees none of the advantages of wisdom, 
nor considers for what evils a man is responsible himself, and 
for what his neighbor is responsible. Nor has he stated in 
what respect the philosopher is adverse to such subjects, nor 
distinguished how far the multitude can be helped, and in what 
way man is superior to the animals; but thinking that what the 
opinion of the people honors in political cleverness and virtue 
falsely so-called is the only thing to be sought, he considers 
that to have led one to that condition is the best proof of sound 
reasoning. On this assumption he tries to show that some 
advantage is contributed by the so-called politicians, and at the 
same time attacks the lawmaking of the ancients, which was 
the cause of men’s living together justly. Moreover it is neces- 
sary to purify the desires; this cannot be accomplished by 
statement and patterns or guidance by political principles and 
laws, but by reasoning about wholes starting from the first clear 
evidence. 

On account of the various faults of mankind it is right = 
the rhetor to guide and correct the community . . .% 


2° On the phrase at the end of the column of rods véuous kal ras modirelas 
ypapovres Tav copictSv Gomperz, Zeit. f. d. 6st. Gymn. XXIII (1872) p. 32, 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 327 


To sum up; by no means should the philosopher acquire 
political experience, or rhetoric of that sort. 

It is evident that it is the height of folly to say that a study 
of nature produces a e&is of political oratory, especially since 
they introduce into the scheme of philosophy example and 
enthymeme, and in political speeches use syllogism and induc- 
tion which the dialecticians pride themselves on using accurately. 
If he thinks that philosophical and political arguments differ only 
in form why does he not show that the political rhetors who 
have learned the truth according to nature, agree with the phi- 
losophers in thought and differ only in the form of their argu- 
ments? What is the value of syllogism and induction if they 
are equivalent to enthymeme and example? Did they think 
that in a case in which one can properly use example and 
enthymeme, the philosopher will be able to use syllogism and 
induction equally well, or did they think that the geometrician 
is the best statesman since such forms of reasoning are used in 
geometry? 

But, as it seems, if one is to consider political questions, the 
first requisite is a knowledge of affairs; consequently he must 
add that the natural philosopher possesses a knowledge of 
statecraft. For even though he seems to himself to be acting 
like a statesman, he wili not necessarily produce the same results 
as a statesman. He may use procedure analogous to geometry, 
but he will not be a geometrician. For everyone who studies 
some obscure problem by means of his senses, reasons out the 
obscure by means of the evident. Statesman, physician and 
geometrician use the same form of syllogism, but one cannot 
solve the other’s problems. How then, if he has sense can he 
say that reasoning from the evident and existent to the future 
[and unknown] is always useful, and that the ablest political 
leaders use this form of reasoning. 


compares Isoc. Phil. 84; rots véuors kai Traits wodirelats rats brs TS cogicT ev 
yeypaumévats, which is an attack on Plato. He thinks that Philodemus 
may have used the attack on Plato and Aristotle made by the Isocratean 
Cephisodorus; v. Numenius ap. Euseb., Prae. Ev. XIV, 6, 9-11, 270, 12-13 
Dind. I am inclined to consider that Philodemus is referring to the activ- 
ities of some of the followers of Isocrates who continued their master’s 
practice of broadening their instruction in rhetoric by theoretical work on 
the science of government of which the works mentioned form a part. 


[esse veol: 
XXXVIII. 


II, 36, 
col. 24. 


EE 36; col 
XXXIX. 


EV 37; 
COl25: 


II, 38; col: 
col oie 


TH, 38; 
col. 26. 


II, 41, col. 


XLII. 


Di an, 
col. 29. 


Mi, 42) colt 


Boul we: 


esac: 
cole. 


II, 44, col. 


XLIV. 


Il, 45, 
cole 32. 


ie Ascol: 


MLV: 


328 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


On investigation we shall find that what they call enthymemes 
are mere padding and provoke applause because the multitude 
is foolish (col. 27). How can he consider that reasoning from 
the evident to the obscure in political matters is the same process 
as interpreting the evident from the past, so that he has left 
no form of reasoning for any speech except strict induction. 

How do they dare to say that they will interpret political 
facts better if we philosophers use example instead of induction. 

The idea (i. e. the fundamental facts) are partly common to 
all partly different for each city and nation.'® 

Something about the effect of division of speeches. 

Therefore the rhetor is like the dialectician, For the one 
who is able to use successfully a long connected speech, will be 
best able to use the method of question and answer, and vice 
versa; for knowing how long to continue speech to make the. 
idea clear to the audience is equivalent to being able to know 
how long to make the series of questions which lead the 
respondent to grasp the new idea. 

Experience is the only guide to forecast the future. 

A philosopher (apparently Metrodorus v. infra col. 32) says 
that it is a nuisance to observe all these rules about divisions 
and length, and commends his own philosophy, the reward of 
which is not pay but freedom from false opinion, which will 
bring happiness to everyone.’’ Therefore Metrodorus consider- 
ing the claim that the same condition enables one to be both 
(natural philosopher and statesman) and ridiculing those who 
consider the dialectic method more accurate, says, “In the case 
of statesmen and natural philosophers the difference is not the 
same but the statesman cannot solve the problems of the natural 
philosopher nor the natural philosopher those of the statesman.” 
What! in accordance with that foolish change will the statesman 
make example become induction, or the philosopher do the same, 
if the subject matter is the same and only the words differ? 
But in their zeal for such things they laid claim to this, and at 
the same time they say that these men are not statesmen, so that 


“On the meaning of dééa cf. the author’s The Influence of Isocrates 
etc. p. 6 ff. 

“This is largely imagination on my part. 
apy |, 21? 


What is the antecedent of 


The KRhetorica of Philodemus. - 329 


one wonders what state of political knowledge the philosopher 
has reached. We do not deny that we lead our pupils in a dif- 
ferent direction from politics, but they are led astray by sophists 
and pay them money merely to get the reputation for political 
ability. For “effect” and “deduction from premises” must be 
subsumed under the knowledge of the wholes, and can come 
in no other way. Nor does he show how he can know to what 
extent the audience understands by means of experience, and to 
what extent by means of dialectic, the man having been pre- 
viously wretched and obscure.’* For all such things are derived 
from physics, and from a weighing of the obscure and reason- 
ing from the existent, and by no other means; so that they travel 
along a regular route, and are not guided by the experience of 
some who have no knowledge of affairs. He did not analyze 
the next point. It should run as follows; “One may be poten- 
tially a rhetor if not actually one. For we say that the power 
of building resides in others besides the actual builders when 
we regard not the performance of the act but one’s ability to 
use the builders’ tools; the same is true of medicine and other 
professions. Consequently why should we not say that rhetoric 
is the attendant of the natural philosopher if when subjects are 
proposed he can speak as well as any statesman or rhetor?”?® 
Perchance he might reason about them as well as the rhetors, 
but he could not make as good an appearance in public as an 
experienced rhetor. The experienced man can speak when he 
wishes, the theorist only after long practice. Furthermore the 
one does many things by the rules of his art—for one cannot 
learn the carpenters trade otherwise—the other does nothing by 
rule; for they say that the ability comes from philosophy, not 
from the political activity itself. 

After due consideration of the mad proposition of Nausiphanes 
we must conclude that he does not provide a proper philosophical 
introduction to rhetoric. 

Now let us take up the story about Aristotle, that he taught 
rhetoric in the afternoon, saying, “’Tis a shame to be silent and 
allow Isocrates to speak.” He showed his opinion clearly enough 


* Practically all the important words in this sentence are conjectures; 
the sense is, to say the least, obscure. 
* The passage is much mutilated, and not at all satisfactorily restored. 


Il, 46, 
Colaay 


ee acols 
XEME 


Il, 48, 
col. 34. 


II, 48, col. 
XLVII. 


LE 49, 
col, 35. 


II, 49, col. 
XLVIII. 


IE op 
col. 36. 


es 1 
col. 37. 


Tiesn cole 
MLIX, 


i, 52; 
col. 38. 


IT, 53; 
col. L. 


VS) St, 
col. 30. 


cole ie, 


Il, 55; 
col. 40. 


cols Wt: 


eas Gy 
col, 41. 


330 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


by writing treatises on the art of rhetoric, and by making politics 
a branch of philosophy. 

He alleged many reasons for engaging in politics; first, that 
one who has no knowledge of what is done in governments finds 
them unfriendly to him; secondly, that a good government will 
be favorable to the growth of philosophy; thirdly, that he was 
disgusted with most of the contemporary statesmen and their 
continual rivalry for office. One banished to a country where 
the people admire rhetoric but lack®® the most necessary edu- 
cation (1. e. philosophy) if he had some experience in rhetoric 
might lead them in a short time to the realms of philosophy.?* 
But we object that to practice rhetoric is toilsome to body and 
soul, and we would not endure it. [Rhetoric] is most unsuit- 
able for one who aims at quiet happiness, and compels one to 
meddle more or less with affairs, and provides no more right 
opinion or acquaintance with nature than one’s ordinary style 
of speaking, and draws the attention of young men from phi- 
losophy the true horn of Amalthea and directs it to the sophistical 
rhyton.2? . . . If he knew that he could not attain the highest 
position or become a philosopher because of various hindering 
circumstances, he might propose to teach grammar, music or 
tactics. For we can find no reason why anyone with the least 
spark of nobility in his nature should become a sophist, as one 
could find reason for pursuing practical rhetoric; for the claim 
that the former leads to the latter is ridiculous. Consequently 
Aristotle’s practice and his remark were not philosophic. Why is 
it more disgraceful to be silent and permit Isocrates to speak than 
to live in a city and allow Manes to dig, or to stay on land and 
allow the Phoenician trader to be tossed by the waves, or to 
pass one’s life in safety as a private citizen and allow Themis- 
tocles to enjoy the perils of a general? He ought to have refused 
to rival Isocrates, in order that he might not seem to be acting 
from envy. Either he judged it disgraceful by the standards of 
the multitude, or by natural standards. If by the latter why did 
he not consider it naturally disgraceful to speak on the public 
platform like a hired rhetor, rather than to speak like the divine 


» Reading 1. 4, 5, |évras dé] TA[v dvay[K]alwy [é]rdee?[s]. 
*t Still the argument of Aristotle. 
The rest of the sentence seems to lack coherence. 


— 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 331 


philosophers. Why did he abandon his exhortation of the young, 
and attempt the road to ruin which was followed by Isocrates’ 
pupils and by other sophists? Why did he prefer to make col- 
lections of laws, constitutions, etc., in short to be a polymath and 
teach all manner of subjects? In this he was less noble than 
the rhetors, in that the rhetors try to provide power, and offer 
rhetorical hypotheses not merely for the calm of the soul but 
also for the health of the body. In short he became a more 
dangerous and deadly foe of Epicurus than those who openly 
engaged in politics. If he was searching for truth, why did he 
choose Isocratean rhetoric rather than political rhetoric which 
he considered different from that of Isocrates? If it was the 
political branch that he was practicing, it was ridiculous for 
him to say that it was a disgrace to allow Isocrates to speak, if 
he did not intend to speak like him. I do not mention the fact 
that none of his pupils could succeed in either art, because 
Isocrates had forestalled him; and Isocrates after teaching 
rhetoric devoted himself to the quieter and as he said, more 
wonderful study—philosophy. He had strange reasons too for 
urging them to a study of politics. First that if they acquired 
experience and undertook a political career immediately, because 
of their occupation in it they would appear lacking in a proper 
philosophical training. But if they had no experience they could 
not be statesmen unless they studied a very long time, and if 
they waited for the state to become orderly they were neglecting 
the means of making it orderly (viz. philosophical politics). 

Not even a woman would be so foolish as to choose the worse 
when the better is present. He urged Philip not to aspire to be 
king of Persia. 

There is no use for one who rules badly what is near him, and 
can rule well what he is not permitted to rule. Of the reasons 
why he urges that one who has the ability to govern should go 
into politics, the first applies to himself rather than to one who 
takes no thought for the community. For if he thought that 
one who took no interest in current events would have no friend, 
as a matter of fact he had none, or could not keep a friend any 
length of time. Philosophy does not prevent a man’s advance; 
it did not prevent Aristotle. If prevented from obtaining any- 
thing, philosophy is not brought into contempt, because it needs 
no help from any man. 


LS 57, 1col 


LITI 


ITE ate 
col. 42, 


colhelhvye 


II, 59, 
col. 43. 


II, 50,-col: 
JEW/ 


IT, 60, 
col. 44. 


litvorucols 
ILWALS 


El 62; 
col. 45. 


II, 63, 
col. 46. 


col. LVIII. 


ee loy, Sire. 
VIL. 


ie $3276 shies 
WAKE 
e327) cin: 
XI. 


eS2Suett 
XII. 


I, 329, col. 
LONE 


332 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


His second reason was dissatisfaction with political conditions. 
But the golden age is past and sudden improvements are 
impossible. 

We shall answer, if opportunity offers, his remarks on Aes 
directed against us, dividing the problems about these subjects 
and all connected with them. 


BOOK VII. 


This book offers little that is new to one who has perused its prede- 
cessors. Its theme is a comparison of rhetoric and philosophy, and after 
the fashion of Philodemus the discussion is largely a criticism of other 
works on rhetoric. Mention is made of Aristo (I, 328, fr. XII, 360, col. 
LXXI), and of Diogenes (Babylonius), (1, 346, col. XLVII, 347, XLIX, 
355, LXIV) and a considerable portion of the book appears to be a dis- 
cussion of the Stoic attitude toward rhetoric. Another section deals with 
the kinds of proof, those subject to the rules of art, and those not so 
subject, and this seems to be a criticism of Aristotle. But the fragments 
are too scanty to allow us to trace the details of the argument. In brief 
it is as follows: rhetoric finds its only field for usefulness in public, 
and there rhetors are of more hindrance to a state than advantage; phi- 
losophy, however, leads the way to a happy life in private, removed from 
the cares of politics. 


He said emphatically at the beginning, “One must pursue that 
which produces a painless life.” 
There is no art of persuasion. 
the former (1. e. questions of advantage and disad- 
vantage considered abstractly) they will consider the task of 
philosophy, the latter (1. e. persuading the people) the task of 
rhetoric. However the questions of advantage which he men- 
tions are questions of interest to the people if it is a question 
of turning the city over to the enemy, or of confiscating the goods. 
of the powerful citizens, and this cannot be decided by a 
philosopher. 
he appears to have spoken briefly and unsatisfactorily 
about rhetoric, and in treating of philosophy to have relied on 
some of the works of Aristo. 
to be able to praise persuasively a mode of life which 
we prefer, and again to censure the same mode of life if we see 
fit; so that the argument that the mode of life which we advise 


| 
| 
| 
| 


/ 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 333 


is healthful persuades, or rather that mode of life persuades 
one who wishes to be well. Such power might be useful to one 
who is to practice medicine, but does not make one healthy. 

if few of the statements depending on opinion are 
true—we ought to say on vain opinion—his remarks are foolish, 
“not referring to clear evidence” and “the rhetors are not 
wholly lacking in this.” But for treating the subject under 
discussion his example from music seems of no value. 

The arguments of philosophy are not conjectural but rigorous. 

Speeches may be pleasing and beautiful, but one would not 
care for them unless they are useful. 

Encomium may be a proper field for guesswork, but cannot be 
called a science. 

All their training is directed toward speaking before crowds 
and courts. But none of them practices saying anything for 
himself or his kin. If they have an action involving five minas 
they study and strain to persuade; but the one who is going to 
spend a talent on evil pleasures because of vanity, and waste 
himself as well as the talent, [him they do not try to persuade]. 

For they profess to make new statesmen, and useful to the 
state and their friends; in the same breath they defend their 
art by saying that the art is not bad, but errors come from those 
who use it badly, as if it were possible for men who fulfill the 
ideal of usefulness to city and friends to use the power of 
rhetoric unwisely. 

Imagine a general planning the strategy of the battle of 
Marathon. “You have visited Marathon?’ some one asks. 
“No.” “You have a detailed description of the place?” “No.” 
“Then why do you try to plan strategy when you do not even 
know if the place exists?” Such are the counsellors who seem 
to be clever in cities. 

[A rhetorician says] sometimes some wicked men use the art. 
But if they fulfil the ideal of being useful to city and friends, 
it is impossible for them to use it unwisely, nor can the unwise 
and scoundrels and receivers of bribes be useful to city and 
friends. 


Discusses whether or not a rhetorician is a philosopher. 


The rhetors never having served as generals are not thought 
likely to conquer, so that some speak more distinctly than 


I, 329, col. 
Walia 


Pe 2aoncol: 
VILI. 
Ie 33rcok 


“X\. 


cole: 


I, 332) col 
XV. 


Ieesa3. cols 
XVII. 


1:.333. cole 
XVIII. 


I, 334, col. 
XIX. 


a35 col 
XXI. 


iees30n cole 


Fe.o Ate 


ly 337, col. 
XXIX. 
I, 337, col. 
Oe, 


38, col. 


Ling 
pekocl: 


cols. 
XXXII- 
2, ©, @.OVAE 


I, 340, col. 


XXXVITI. 


L343, col. 
XXXVIII. 


Fr, 941,..col. 
XL. 


L342, col: 


ALI, 


1,343, col. 
Il. 


334 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


For we do not know of anyone very brilliant before Pericles 
and Callistratus and Demosthenes, unless he calls impressiveness 
brilliance. 

We insult the gods as Oileus did. 

We must see that none of the young lose their desire for 
rhetoric. 

they do not profess to put justice into operation but 
to be able to follow what anyone demands. Not only do the 
rhetors not profess this but many, both of former generations 
and the present, are not able though willing and conversant with 
what is just and true. 

(Nothing intelligible. ) 

by making the science subject to rules of art, and 
making similar concession to philosophy, not being able to help 
himself otherwise 

If rhetoric produces bold, daring, shameless men, or teachings 
which lead to these qualities, he can find no occasion for the art, 
and is left in the lurch. 

says that shamelessness is an important aid to rhetoric; 
this remark was not ironical. 

In his speech about judges he mentions the man who appeared 
without pay for Aristippus, since he could not speak for him- 
self; to one who asked Aristippus what good Socrates had done 
him he replied, “Enabled me to have such men appear in my 
behalf as will please my fellow philosophers.” 

{Many who have composed such treatises] are outdone, not 
only in action but in speech by laymen; nothing is so persuasive 
as truth and experience in affairs. 

It appears to me that the most ignoble thing of all is to per- 
suade the weakness of the crowd, and concoct some reason for 
doing anything. 

The philosophers though able [to do these things] order them 
passed on to those who have toiled and danced,’ to publicans and 
sinners. If he had said not to yield but to claim their results 
as our own 

Rhetoricians quarrel and philosophers are wicked. 

It is [not] proven that the art of medicine does not produce 
health when the e physician: are outdone by Dias who have 


* Referring to Aeschines says Sudhaus in we index, s. v. xopevw. 


Se 


"7 oa == —— 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 335 


discovered some specific for disease. The rhetors of marked 
ability are not often outdone in speaking by laymen, but are 
frequently outdone in action. 

It is not rhetors but Diogenes and his like who say that only 
the philosopher is a rhetor. For they have seen what is truly 
advantageous to the state. 

Demetrius of Phalerum made a distinction between the acts 
of the two Philos. 

Also on the difference between an experienced rhetor and an inexperi- 
enced political philosopher. 

[Some] are deceived by Diogenes and others who speak in his 
style; the rhetors do not lead men astray but persuade them 
aright. 

Someone collected instances of failure [in rhetoric]. 

Speeches bolder than those of pathics, as Aristophanes says, 
expressing it lewdly, as was his wont. Therefore cities often 
make serious errors when they listen to such advice. 

The great ancient rhetors maintained their position by means 
of political intelligence. 

On the proper preparation for public office. 

Xenocrates says that the Athenians alone are able to be silent, 
and alone know how to speak. For it takes the same man to 
do both. Good heavens! We must certainly believe that 
Xenocrates spoke thus before Antipater as Demetrius of Phalerum 
has recorded in his [epi pyropixis.’ 

The greatest of the practical statesmen, Pericles and Demos- 
thenes for example, received assistance from philosophers; and 
to associate with Socrates was better for Alcibiades and Critias 
than to study an art. 

The [sciences] introduce no reasoning which is aimed to 
deceive, but all the principles of the rhetoricians are aimed 
exclusively at that, and according to Heraclitus rhetoric is the 
prince of liars.’ 


* This passage is discussed by Crénert in Kolotes und Menedemos, p. 
67{. comparing II, 173, fr. XII, and Papyr. ined. 453, fr. IV, also Plut., 
Phoc. 27: éreira Neyer dpiduevov od~ Urouévwr, ad dvTixpovwy kal dvtKodalywy 
érolnoev drocwmjoa. Xenocrates’ speech displeased Antipater, and he was 
ordered to be silent, hence the taunt in this passage. 

*On the meaning of xoris v. Gomperz, Zeit. f. d. dst. Gym. XVII 
(1866). p. 608. : 


I, 346, col. 
XLVII. 


I, 346, col. 
XLVIII. 


I, 347, col. 
XLIX. 


I, 347, 
col 

I, 348, col. 
JA 


I, 348, col. 
Ee: 


I, 349, cols. 
Lie weve 
Ie350; col: 
Ve 


I, 350, col. 
TEVae 


I, 351, col. 
LVII. 


E; 353; col. 


I, 353, col. 
I 


Ie acasicol. 


I= 350. col: 


1, 357;.col. 


LXVII 


I, 358, col. 


exV IIL. 


55, col. 


336 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


.that each one be confused and excited; wherefore 
Aristophanes compares them to pathics. 

to one starting to write history he seems to offer the 
history of an ignoble man. He roused not only Alexander, but 
the comic poet who began it all by mentioning this attack on 
rhetors. 

attacking unexpectedly and for the nonce adopting the 
philosophic style, he presses the philosopher into a quandary. 
But we shall put a damper on such arguments if we are com- 
pelled by these people to answer them. 

To say that there is no harm in knowing how to make the 
worn appear new, and how to cut purses, but that one should 
not use this power against men except when need arises, is the 
same as saying that there is nothing 

The [sciences] introduce no reasoning which is aimed to 
deceive, but all the principles of the rhetoricians are aimed 
exclusively at that, and according to Heraclitus rhetoric is the 
prince of liars. How is it possible to say anything apart from 
showing that all their arguments tend toward that end? 

perhaps it gives some an occasion to deceive the 
audience. But, some one objects, arms do not give occasion to 
deceive. “We ought not, then,” I shall say, “to claim that this 
is the characteristic of all the principles of rhetoric, but of some.” 

Many things such as wealth, strength, beauty, offer an oppor- 
tunity for wrong-doing, but are honored for the good they do, 
and are called useful even by Diogenes. 

How is it possible for the Stoics—not to mention all the phi- 
losophers—to claim to be of this character, and to demonstrate 
that some rhetors are not of this character? 

| Rhetors are the cause of much trouble] as he charged that 
rhetors were shown to be in Lacedaemon. I pass over the fact 
that he could show that some with philosophical training have 
been guilty as well as innocent of the same charges. They will 
be able to show that rhetors have replaced tyrannies by democ- 
racies, and performed similar good offices. 

Nor if he says that at Athens rhetoric was a strong bulwark 
against tyrants, where there were more rhetors than in the whole 
world put together, can it be said truly that no democracy has 
been replaced by a tyranny through the aid of a rhetor. 

If Aeschines rebuked the Athenians because they did not treat 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 337 


Demosthenes like the captain of a capsized ferryboat, but 
refused to try him for capsizing Greece, they will say that 
Diogenes is wrong in saying that the Athenians do not use the 
same rhetors repeatedly. 

They will try to show that the statements of Demosthenes and 
Lycurgus about the acts of Harpalus are false, and to copy their 
statements from the most trustworthy historians; and they will 
assert that he was insignificant and shameless. 

If some cities have forbidden the entrance of rhetors, not to 
mention receiving advice from them, yet others continually avail 
themselves of their services. And not all rhetors are boastful. 

But we have got more out of this than perhaps was fitting, 
even if the book of Aristo is longwinded. 

He says that one should not abstain wholly from rhetoric, 
only from excess in it, nor wholly from politics. And he says 
that the rhetor should not pretend to be a pilot. His position is 
that of a boatswain. 

He says that the whole system depends on deceit; conse- 
quently a veracious person should avoid it. In reply I say that 
leaving out of the question sophistical rhetoric, even if I could 
speak about it, and the Technae of Aristotle—and yet I could 
show that others of his followers have written against him with 
all the trickery of sophistical rhetoricians—the rhetoric of Pericles 
and Callisthenes and Demosthenes 

If he meant “probable conjecture” or “an approach to truth,” 
he used the word zifavev to denote what could not be true. On 
which subject, as the rhetors say, | am ashamed of not producing 
a demonstration. 

Boldness and impudence are the offspring of rhetoric. 

At least rhetoric is the ability to persuade the people in assembly 
and forum. 

Rhetoric provides the necessities of life; by means of rhetoric 
men become famous. 

Inasmuch as they think the philosopher should enter public 
life, on the principle that politics is philosophy he claims that 
rhetoric [is also philosophy]. 

Their remarks are not consonant with their opinions concern- 
ing political activity; these they abandon and support their 
position by the other activities of philosophy. 

Prudent jurors are rare. | 


nCOl: 


col. 


cols 


col. 


1. 361,.col. 
LXXIII. 


I, 362, col. 
LXXIV. 


Le s63h cal: 
LXXV. 
I, 363, col. 
LXXVI. 


I, 364, col. 
LXXVII. 


I, 364, col. 
IL2ZOW AOL 


I, 365, col. 
10,1 DE 


IeSsO5sicol: 
LXXX. 


I, 366, col. 
EXeex 0, 


[eesO7.col. 
LXXXIII. 


T3607, 0COl- 
LXXXIV. 


ik, siete Call. 
LXXXV. 


I, 368, col. 
LXXXVI. 


I, 369, col. 
LXXXVII. 


I, 370, col. 


LXXXVIII. 


I, 370, col. 
LXXXIX., 


eee 7iencol: 
XC, 


338 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


[This must be used] in general if the practical rhetors con- 
sider it opportune, but not immoderately; and in the eyes of 
those who know he urges to avoid generally that kind of 
pleasurable appeal in order to save exertion. 

[ Adapting oneself to the refutation for which they say they 
have explained the details] the rhetor is able to praise and blame. 

Why should we not marvel at them? For they will not say 
that the statesman [gets his power from experience] or if they 
acknowledge this why do they not show that his experience 
differs from that of the rhetors. 

| How can he say that the statesman who] speaks about advan- 
tage is master of others and the rhetorician master of none, if 
he is of the same character?* For he is acquainted with all> 
such forms of advantage as is the thoughtful statesman, and 
with the popular ideas of honor and justice. 

The largest part of this depends on natural ability; what 
comes from study and instruction cannot be imparted “in the 
brief portion of a day.” Of a like nature are the remarks about 
attention. And since the chief virtue of the narrative is clear- 
ness, and the clearest narrator is the one who has studied most, 
rhetoric [cannot be of] immediate [use] to the rhetor. 

The wioreas arexvo. are common to all; 
probability, and sign, and necessary inference are not the 
property of the rhetoricians, but the sign is peculiar to one who 
has followed a particular calling; e. g. in diseases it is known 
by the physician, in storms at sea by the captain etc. Probability 
can be ascertained by one who has considered how 

In regard to za6y and 76y which move juries, the most impor- 
tant part is to know how these emotions are aroused and allayed. 
This alone, judging that it is none of their business, the rhetors 
have not borrowed from Aristotle, though they have borrowed 
everything else. 

. . like those who try to heal the sick by foolish means . . 
not claiming to persuade all, since they do not add themselves or 
lover or friend, for these they say are friendly. 

to a fitting character® which as a result of its peculiar 


of the riores evrexvoe 


*Punctuating the sentence ending in I. 8 as a question. 
® ravrwy for moditov; or should we read modcurexdv? 
*Reading ¢vow instead of obcar, 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 339 
nature is with a person for all the rest of his life, and does 
not come “in the brief portion of a day.” 

possible to say that he is going to make even the people 
understand him in a short time. We may wonder that if he 
knows this, he did not likewise see that there is a difference 
between the educated and uneducated in that a clearer statement 
must be made to the latter. 

Consequently, expecting to hear similar statements about other 
forms of expression when he says that the wiores drexvo. such 
as evidence, torture. are the common property of all, let us say 
that the knowledge of these belongs to laymen, but their use 
depends on opportunity, not on knowledge. 


For just as the physician knows what is probable in disease, I, 373, col. 
and the pilot knows what is probable in weather, so the rhetor a. 
considers the course of political events, when something is going 
to occur in the state, and from this knowledge he says he is 
going to persuade the people. 

The rhetor does not combine his proofs after the fashion of a_ I, 373, col. 
dialectician or philosopher; for probably this would be dis- oi 
pleasing to the multitude. 

If they bring means able to rid them of many troubles they I, 374, col. 
will have the philosopher in agreement with them. Making XCV. 
them such offers, those who give advice or plead before a court, 
then express pity and anger. 

with whom the ad tae wish to include the rhetor I, 374, col. 
because of his cringing; for he says, “Let him persuade justly XCVI. 
and wisely, let him divert their desires, calm their passions and 
persuade them individually as friends.” 

Rhetors prefer to live in a democracy, the worst form of I, 375, col. 
government. eS 

[A competent pilot] who did not know where or how or when I, 375, col. 
to sail would be dangerous, fully as much so as the rhetor [who pseN LT 
should try to sail a boat in a storm]. For he could fiot reason 
about advantage and harm, as such, even if some one has 
charmed him into thinking that power over all is teachable. 

[If instead of this] he claims that rhetoric is an art because 1, 376, col. 
the rhetor produces a certain effect on the emotions, then his IC. 


shift is not honorable, because it is false that the rhetor pos- 
sesses universal knowledge, since all poorer artists have wiser 
men to judge them. 


I, 361, col. 
XG; 


lea72y cok 
XCIl. 


1) 3873 


cole: 


col. 


col. 


col. 


col. 


col. 


col. 


col. 


340 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


It is idle to introduce the phrase “wiser men to judge them” 
whom the rhetor was unwilling to serve, and toward whom his 
faculty is useless. For he will introduce as a reply a similar 
remark applying to the statesman who has experience in these 
matters, alluding to the art which produced Themistocles and 
Pericles. 

Potentates even more than democracies pity and almost admire 
those whom they subdue if they possess the charm of these 
virtues, e. g. Philip and Python,’ Ptolemy and Demetrius of 
Phalerum. 

In addition let it be said that the most powerful speech is that 
with rigorous proof, i. e. with the characteristics of philosophy 
rather than of rhetoric, since “most powerful” seems to mean 
“most powerful in reference to some object.” 

so that to exclude these [qualities] is to exclude politics, 
and like rhetoric few things, and these decisive, have these 
[qualities]. 

In regard to the third point let it be said that even if the 
speech be very persuasive, if the possessor of this power does 
not know how and whom and when to persuade, he is as useless 
as if he were a rudder. 

For even if Pericles easily persuaded the people to do what 
was lawful, another would not in turn succeed in currying the 
favor of the mob, and the populace would never endure 
philosophy. 

For he says it is as if a runaway slave expelled the master of 
the ship, and let it drift down stream with the boldest 
to serve as pilots and please the passengers. 

Since he is like one who feigns grief for the loss of property 
he never possessed, no one would pity him. But we know of 
masters and pilots who have even been killed as well as banished 
by fugitive slaves.® 

by the statute laws not of philosophers but of rhetors. 
But what sort of philosophers does he mean? If we urge him 
to indicate one of the political [philosophers] they cannot be 
considered statesmen. 


7 Probably the pupil of Isocrates and orator of distinction who acted as 
Philip’s emissary to Athens in 343 B. C. 
® Runaway — rhetorician; masters = philosophers. 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 341 


they guided states aright, and the philosopher could Le col, 
not rule these. ; 
. Philosophers are unable to help cities, nor have they 1, 383, col. 
: fe ae exe 
ever framed any laws with all their virtue. 
Power of persuasion is not helpful but destroys the persuader P. 38s. 
himself with his city. 


FRAGMENTA INCERTA. 


The fragmenta incerta do not contribute much of Philodemus’ thought 
that is new. I have deemed it worth while, however, to include a trans- 
lation of the most important of them, as they contribute interesting bits 
of information, and have been the occasion for some of the most brilliant 
conjectures that Philodemus has brought forth. 


a 
(Nothing. ) Ti; 168; fr. 1 
According to the philosophers this ought to be known, but fr. II. 
because of our ignorance, as they are always dinning in our ears, 
it is impossible and inconsistent with life for everything to be 
predestinate. . . . For the philosophers like to have their 
joke and imagine a community of cities and friends and goods 
and wives and children. 
For one would not say with Anaxagoras that everything exists II, 160, fr. 
in everything, nor with the Chian Metrodorus' acknowledge that Ls 
he knew nothing, nor even that he knew nothing, nor with 
Parmenides and Melissus that the universe is one, and because 
perceptions are false. 
exhorting to what is noble and of advantage 


dissuading from what is shameful and harmful. ae ag 
Philosophers have been found flattering their states. Ge 
(Nothing. ) fr. Vo 
fr. VI 


For all these reasons, if they chance to be distinguished for 
any cause, one would not trust their statements; if through 
mistaken reasoning or under compulsion of a lover, they intrust 
such matters to children, certainly Persaeus and Eudemus and 
Lycon and the like. 


*In 1. 5, Wilamowitz, Hermes XXXIV (1899) p. 636, restores Myrpas a 
shortened form of Metrodorus, comparing Antiphanes p. 129, Meineke. 
A Metrodorus of Chios is mentioned in Diogenes Laertius IX, 10, 58, 
Ss €heye und advrd rodr eldévac bre over olde. 


1g 
fr. 


ut 


IX 


hes 
1g 


10 
XI 


i; 
XIII 


Hires 


iD; 
XV 


tte 


A 


VELL. 


Te: tr. 


X. 
XI. 


TB, atts 
iI 


7Abe tte 


. 


XIV. 


XVI- 


XVII. 


Dieen76; fro a. 


T7 Sethe 


342 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


it is an indication of fair speech; perchance that is 
the meaning of the wand or heralds staff. For he says, “golden, 
with which he charmeth the eyes of men whom he will, and 
others sleeping he waketh.” Wherefore Amphiaraus was one of 
the seven leaders against Thebes, Nestor of those against Troy. 

A sophist at the games, catching sight of an idle rich youth, 
said to his companions, “There is my treasure chest.” In a 
similar way, when Aeschines was an actor and a clerk he was 
poor, but when he took up rhetoric he became a great entertainer, 
and awfully rich. | 

(Nothing. ) 

Some philosophers openly advise community of wives and 
children.? 

voted that he should speak among the first because of 
his age and rhetorical experience. But Xenocrates addressed 
Antipater in the same style that he was wont to use in a phi- 
losophical discussion in the Academy, and Antipater rejected his 
plea.* 

‘ punishing those who misappropriate public funds or 
do some other wrong, opposing even potentates on the most 
important matters. 

Philosophers teaching in a corner.* 

A hare cannot be safe among dogs, according to Aristotle, 
nor can one keep a surly and contemptuous attitude among men. 
Philosophers always appear like this; therefore they are liable 
to the attacks of sycophants and undesirable citizens. 

( Nothing.) 


B 


If one should seize you and drag you to prison, claiming that 
you are guilty, though you are innocent, you could not help 
yourself, but would stand giddy and agape, not having a word 
to say; and though your accuser be a mean fellow and not good 


Gi ard. 

*I follow the restoration proposed by Crénert, Kolotes und Menedemos, 
67; 1. 2 daly] ploacOa. 1, 3, év mpwros, 1. g, deEép|XerPar Kal rd[v, 10, Noyor 
mpos To]v Avrlra[rpov vrép THs wodews ov Sel|Eaue[ vou 5é daroruyxeiv. 

*Cf. Plato, Gorgias 486, Cic. De Orat. I, 13, 57, Fuhr. Rhein. Mus. LVII 
(1902) p. 436. 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 343 


for much, you would die.® How is it wise if an art takes a 
noble man and renders him worse. 
We should not hate and banish the teacher—for he taught I, 177, fr. 
with a proper object in view—but it is right to kill the one who i 
uses it improperly. Polus in the rest of his defense explains 
about the art.® 


Nothing. fry 
\ g:) fr, IV=fr. 
Veale ros 
y 
Isocrates received from the Cyprian twenty talents, and from A need fe 
Timotheus the son of Conon he received ten more.” IX, II, 172, 
(Nothing. ) II, 179, fr. 

: Il. 
Rhetoric alone makes laws.® fr, EDT: 
They (rhetors) have been and are our counsellors in war and i. ie 

peace. fr, V. x 
A slave on being scourged informed against Anaxagoras, and II, 180, fr. 

Cylon of Crotona had Pythagoras fined and banished, and iE ce 

burned his disciples in a body; and Socrates® . . . 174, fr: VIL 


Therefore let us pass over this unless there are more sensible [T, 380, fr. I. 
comparisons to be made between philosophy and rhetoric. It is 
the height of folly to maintain that rhetoric is the science of 
choosing between what is advantageous and disadvantageous, 
and of deciding questions of music and geometry. 
(Nothing. ) TI, 181, ir 
He was still more ridiculous in adding comparisons between ¢,° yyy, 
rhetoric and philosophy. 
Men persuade in a variety of ways; by beauty, by music . . . yy 182, 
by appeal to the ear. fro LVe 
Some of the sophists would not allow rhetoric to be called a ¢. y 
condition productive of success; and those who say they have 
political ability. 
(Nothing. ) fr. VI. 


°Cf. Plato, Gorgias, 486A, B. 

*Cf. Plato, Gorgias, 456D, 457B, 461B ff. 

7 Cf. Fuhr in Rhein. Mus. LVII (1902) p. 430; Hubbell in Class. Phil. 
XI (1916) p. 407. 

* Cf. Isocr., Antid. 253 ff. 

*This is part of a list of unfortunate philosophers compiled by some 
rhetorician. Cf. Radermacher in Rhein. Mus. LVI (1901) p. 214. 


Li tse tr. 
Wali: 


pee VLE, 


TP ST SAS tic: 
I-III. 
ie TW 


bey WAS 
bey WATE 


ines WAI 
ey Velie 


fr. [X—fr. 


XIV. 


lik, Tisza 
ile 


IT, 188, fr. 
INO 


ines JW 


ie, WAL 


344 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


Therefore we must say that the rhetor is not a flatterer, and 
rhetoric is not flattery; for the statesman was said to practice 
what would help all the citizens.’° 

[Plato] showed that rhetoric produced pleasure, and shared 
this quality with cookery and personal adornment, and showed 
in addition that one produced something not noble, and another 
something disgraceful." 


(Nothing. ) 

I pass over the fact that they criticize Gorgias, and ask him to 
submit to an examination on Greek usage, since all sciences 
depend on words for their power."? 

( Nothing. ) 

he knows what weaving and music and medicine deal 
with, but inquires about rhetoric, because he does not know. 

( Nothing.) 

Plato in the Gorgias. 

( Nothing. ) 


4 
Sardanapallus deeds in war. And yet some mythog- 
raphers introduce stories about him.’* 
Themistocles** that marvelous wall around the city as 


Sardanapallus surrounded Anchiale and Tarsus. For if they 
pride themselves on this, every man would be a statesman. 
One thing I do not think worthy of notice, that he considers 
it not to be the task of a statesman to make a small city great. 
This grammarian having observed what has escaped notice 
everywhere, has not failed to collect examples of cocks who 


™ Cf. Plato, Gorg. 463A, 464B. 

™ Cf. Plato, Gorg. 462C. 

“Cf. Plato, Gorg. 450D. 

% The phrase 7uépa mia which I have not translated refers to the 
building of Anchiale and Tarsus in a single day; Arrian, Anab. II, 5, 4; 
Strabo XIV, 5, 9, p. 672; Athen. XII, 530b quoted by Fuhr, Rhein. Mus. 
LVII (1902), p. 420, and previously by Gomperz, Zeit. f. d. dst. Gymn. 
XXIII (1872) p. 24. 

4 @euoro| k\éovs. He is also referred to in fr. IV infra wéduw éx puxpas 
mojoat weyddnv. The restoration was made independently by both Wil- 
amowitz, Hermes XXXIV (1899) p. 636, and Fuhr, Rhein. Mus. LVII 


(1902) p. 420. 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 345 


lower the crest and look at the tail. Let us praise him because 
he attends to the slanders of the opponents of Demosthenes who 
did not receive a fifth of the votes, and does not attend to the 
Athenians who disfranchised the accuser.*® 


!) 

Beating his father or refusing him food or shelter. 

The prolepsis of rhetoric is less limited. 

He did not make his investigation systematic, but either by 
the lack of differentiation of the idea which he has subordinated 
to the names or : 

They thought that most of the philosophical rhetors devote 
their energy to this one part and the following part; that those 
who attack rhetoric insist that it is no art. 


6 
art is the art of beautiful speech, by which they mean 
persuasive speech; and the art was the art of beautiful speech, 
so that speech came by nature, but beautiful speech by art. 

How when they have come thus far, can they profess to teach 
that few arts involve imitation? 

To speak in any random way is the work of nature; to speak 
beautifully is the work of art. This seems true to me, and you 
also hold the same opinion. . . . All the so-called conjectural 
arts 

One may accidentally speak beautifully now and then; but to 
attain this end frequently requires art. 

6 

About the end of art, and whether it is theoretical or empirical. 

(Nothing. ) 

Metrodorus teaches in regard to rhetoric that it does not arise 
from a study of science. 

(Nothing. ) 


4% Gomperz |. c. p. 25 suggests that the anonymous author here quoted 
had collected all derogatory passages in Aeschines, and that reference is 
here made to Timarch. cap. 23, 25 (about cock fights). Wilamowitz I. c. 
reads xXlivovtas for xaivovras quoting Phrynichus fr. 16 1. 5 érrné’? adéxtwp 
dovAov ws KNwvas TTepor. 

* This section is erroneously designated by Sudhaus as ¢. 


TI, 180; fc. 1. 


fey JUNI 
Ii 190; 
frVs 


frcViE. 


I Toes fra le 


BLY 16%, irs 
BIT: 


ey AWA 


iieeT@2: 
ie, WE 


INL, ee are I 
Die 193; ir: 
Il. 

fey JOEY. 


ire EVs 


i; 194, 
ene We 


tre V0, Vil, 


II, 198, 
ie) AWS 
re, WI SIDX 
e190; 
ities Oe 


1 OIL 
II, 200, fr. 
XII 


fr. X11 


fhe, SMI 
INL, Ao abs 
XV. 


fr. XVI. 
fies DWE 


II, 202, 
Cole. 


346 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


Since this is so what do they mean by trusting to foreign . . . , 
or what has Anacharsis said on this subject? For we acknowl- 
edge that rhetoric is of foreign extraction. 

( Nothing.) 

HyPOMNEMATICON. 

For a statement of the relation of the Hypomnematicon to the Ilepi 
pnropuxjs see the Introduction p. VII. 

(Nothing. ) 

No artist can perform the task of another artist; a com- 
mander of cavalry cannot command a ship, ete. 

Theophrastus lived all his life in the privacy of phi- 
losophy, ignorant of the affairs of kings.* 

[| Rhetoric is] the best assistant for all the villainy in this world. 

( Nothing. ) 

Advantage and disadvantage. . . . It is evident that we 
shall find that the argument amounts to this; “The wise man 
has knowledge of these and other things.” 

( Nothing.) 

( Nothing. ) 

Critolaus, it seems, taught strategy, the duties of kings, equi- 
tation and navigation. 

(Nothing. ) 

If they search for the mighty rhetors, surpassing all others, 
they are carried back to the time of Corax in whose day 
Themistocles and Aristides flourished. The ability possessed by 
Odysseus, Nestor, Solon, Themistocles and Pericles we do not 
call rhetoric ; 

( Nothing.) 

Se they happened to have conversed intelligently, 
powerfully and nobly. 

Coll. I-XXIV attack the Stoic doctrine that the philosopher is the only 
orator. Passages are quoted from Diogenes of Babylon and refuted in 
turn. 

According to Diogenes there has never been a perfect states- 
man, such as you? say they ought to be, not even Phocion whom 
Demosthenes called the pruning knife of his speeches.’ 


*Or, more probably ‘of political affairs, reading rodrix]dv in 1. 8. 

* Addressing the Stoics. 

* Wilamowitz, Hermes, XXXIV (1899) p. 637, reads in line 26 o¢[aylda]. 
For the anecdote cf. Plutarch: Phoc. 5, Dem. 10: Demosthenes said of 
Phocion as he mounted the bema, % Tv éudv Ndywr korls avlorarat. 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 347 


The rhetor imagined by the Stoa has never existed, and will 
never exist. 

After this he* makes the following incredible statement: “We 
see that statesmen like Cimon did not waste time or money on 
such things, nor subject themselves to professors of such sub- 
jects.” How this can be true I do not see. For the noble rhetors 
who have successfully held the preéminence in their states have 
spent time and labor and endured hardships to gain their posi- 
tions. One could instance Themistocles who walked in front 
of the generals quarters at night,> and could not sleep for the 
trophy of Miltiades; or Pericles who in order to be a successful 
statesman spent much time, and studied with the philosophers 
of his generation; Demosthenes who was said to have studied 
with Plato and Eubulides, and set up a cheval-glass, and 
reproached himself because he slept until aroused by the sound 
of artizans, and turned his lisping into correct speech; many 
others might be mentioned who have toiled to become prominent. 
However success in some lines requires a suitable length of time, 
and expense and subjection to masters; others demand time 
only; now all require time, and not all require expense or sub- 
jection to masters—and one of these is politics. 

that Demades took those who wished to study with 
him to the true teacher, i. e. the people. 

As for saying that the rhetors spend all their time in examin- 
ing and being examined, and serving what is bitter in the 
character of mankind—we know that the distinguished rhetors 
have brought others to examination and submitted to examina- 
tions themselves, and such is the natural condition of political 
life. But the philosophers also examine one another in order to 
arrive at the truth. 

If Diogenes said that no rhetor was ever systematic,® but 
acted strictly from a desire to please, distributing the public 
money in theoric funds, he speaks as one who has never inves- 
tigated the lives of the rhetors. Some of them have been as he 


*“Diogenes—from whom the following quotations also are drawn. 

° Fuhr, Rhein. Mus. LVII (1902) p. 429, compares Cic. Tusc. IV. 19, 44, 
noctu ambulabat in publico Themistocles, and restores, 1. 28, wxrwp mpd 
Tov oTpaTnylov. 

“I. e. no rhetor ever followed a definite consistent course of conduct, 
but simply strove to satisfy the momentary desires of the people. 


II, 203, col. 
i: 


II, 204, col. 
II 


E2075 
cok Wi, 


ITI, 208, col. 
VI 


II, 209, col. 
VII. 


Uiormrcol: 
VIII. 


II, 212, col. 
1X. 


348 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


describes, but the majority have given practical advice showing 
deep thought, and have acted with great boldness in opposition 
to those who favored such distributions, and history will bear 
us out. 

After this he says, “The statesman ought to be able to fill 
the offices in the state; the rhetor cannot do this, and is not 
fitted for statesmanship.” 

The term statesman, properly used, is not stretched to include 
the general or admiral; similarly, one able to advise, and plead 
causes receives his name from his possessing this particular form 
of experience, even if he is not able to speak well. But if, as 
oftentimes happens, one called a statesman in the narrow mean- 
ing, knows how to be a general, or fill other offices, he will not 
receive the power in this line, nor does the ability in this pro- 
fession far removed from his own come to him as a result of 
his political ability.’ 

(Diogenes speaks:) “The philosopher is not only a good 
dialectician, grammarian, poet and orator, in short skilled in all 
arts, but knows what is useful to cities, not Athens alone but 
Lacedaemon. For in the philosophic state there is no law, but 
the divine precepts of the philosophers and truth prevail. The 
philosopher will be general and admiral, treasurer and tax-col- 
lector, and can fill all offices, since the statesman must have a 
knowledge of all these matters.” 

But if we must express our opinion about this, the successful 
statesmen who have never studied the Stoic philosophy® seem 
possessed of rhetorical ability; Pisistratus and Clisthenes were 
orators, and Themistocles the greatest general of them all, and 
Pericles who made Athens powerful and rich and famous, and 
Pausanias who won the battle of Plataea, and Cimon who showed 
by his victories on land and sea how to increase the power of 
the state, and Alcibiades who defeated the Peloponnesians, and 
Timotheus the pupil of Isocrates.® 


7 The implication is that neither does rhetorical ability imply any military 
ability, a denial of the claim of Isocrates for rhetoric; cf. De Pace 54, 
Panath. 143. 

®T should prefer to read at the beginning of col. IX, Thy Lrakjy 
pXocopiay, and make this Philodemus’ reply to the Stoic argument of the 
preceding column. 

® Tiuddeos 6 pabnrys was suggested by Fuhr, Rhein. Mus. LVII (1902) 
p. 430. 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 349 


Some select the deliberative branch of rhetoric, others the 
forensic, others that which pertains to experience in principles, 
as is the case in medicine and other arts. Demosthenes and 
Demades worked out the deliberative and forensic branches. 

They ought not to judge Callistratus and Pericles and other 
political rhetors by the technical treatises written by those who 
are also called rhetors. 

“The Lacedaemonians,”’ he says, “expelled rhetoric, and man- 
aged all their affairs with the help of their natural ability in 
speaking.” In the first place one will not grant that the Lace- 
daemonians managed all their affairs with the help of their 
natural ability in speaking, nor were they successful ambassadors, 
nor for this reason would one grant they did not study rhetoric, 
but this is a careless remark of Diogenes. And if we grant that 
they were successful ambassadors, how does this prove that 
they did not study rhetoric? 

“Nothing is more puerile than the speeches of the ambassadors 
trained in the rhetorical schools, who still keep up the ancient 
pride in the Tyndaridae and Atridae. Rhetoric claims to be 
able to persuade in diplomatic negotiations by speech, not by 
power or bribes or dignities or anything else an ambassador 
might possess.”’ What if the Spartans possess natural aptitude 
with which they persuade in diplomatic negotiations? Shall we 
say that rhetoric is of no assistance to them in speaking as 
ambassadors? 

If some who are not rhetors make good ambassadors, how 
does that prove that the art of rhetoric is not the art of politics? 

“Even the Athenians, though fond of rhetoric are tired of 
periods, and those who savor of art and school rhetoric.” It is 
ridiculous to say that the Athenians are tired of this. Why are 
they more tired now? 

“But not all of them savored of art and school rhetoric, 
Aristophon and Aeschines for example, and they did not use 
loose sentence structure.’’’° 

[Since] there are philosophers who are accustomed to talk 
nonsense—men like you and Critolaus—listen to [Zeno?] say- 
ing; “The experience of political rhetors which depends entirely 
on opportunity, teaches one at one time to make a lengthy speech, 


For dedvuévacs Sudhaus made in the index kexuuévats. Radermacher, 
Rhein. Mus. LIV (1899) p. 356, suggests xarayvupévais. 


JW eaiee 
col, X. 


ie2rs col. 
ae 22: 


II, 216, col. 
XII. 


II, 217, col. 
XIII. 


riers cole 
XIV. 


E2106, cok 
XV. 


Div22r cole 


XVI. 


i222 ncol: 


XVII. 


Us 222) col. 


XVIII. 


ey22acrcol!: 
XIX. 


If, 225, cal: 
XX. 


Il, 226; col. 
XXI. 


350 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


at another to make a short discussion (or dialogue), and again 
not to say anything.” Therefore as he takes away from science 
and experience what they especially have to give, when one 
fails he himself is ridiculous.” “Why! if they are able to 
reconcile cities and make alliances they ought to be better able 
to reconcile friends who have quarreled, or sundered families ; 
for the same experience will serve to unite two individuals as 
well as multitudes; just as the same skill is required to tune one 
harp or many.” How can they reconcile a wife to her husband, 
as they persuade the multitude? Only a man who knew little 
philosophy would think that the two tasks were the same. 

( Nothing.) 

Quite the contrary; Socrates knew how to reconcile indi- 
viduals, but could not win the multitude for one man;"! neither 
could Antisthenes nor Zeno nor Cleanthes nor Chrysippus. If 
he says that [the rhetor] will be able to stop quarrels and wars 
between states, as the musician can tune one lyre to harmonize 
with many, we should say that the rhetors do not aim at abolishing 
wat. 

“Scarcely a single ambassador,” he says, “has been of service 
towhis state,’ 

He slanders the Greeks—thousands of whom have been use- 
ful ambassadors, were prudent in their advice, were not the 
cause of disaster, did not speak with an eye to gain, and were 
not convicted of malfeasance in office. 

“Why not one of them is recorded as having been a good 
citizen ie 

Not only many rhetors, but many private citizens as well have 
become good political rhetors without philosophy. 

“Many, you say, if not all are wretched, not one is upright. 
kind, patriotic or distinguished by ordinary virtues, let alone the 
higher ones.” Yet given natural endowment and training it is 
granted that one can become a political rhetor without philosophy. 

“Not one,” he says, “rhetorical 

men may become great artists. Whence they say that 
the rhetor cannot guide the state successfully without philosophy, 
even if he has experience. Pericles, who, he said, was the most 
endurable of the rhetors, studied under Anaxagoras and other 


™ Ts he thinking of Alcibiades? 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 351 


philosophers, but he never studied Stoicism, but principles con- 
trary to these. According to Diogenes, only Stoicism makes 
good citizens.” 

If we cannot call Pericles a tolerable citizen I do not know 
whom in the cities he called good. 

One should not attend to the doctrines of the Stoics, but study 
with good men. 

Now that this subject is finished, perhaps some one will 
say , 
says that Demosthenes, Callistratus and Themistocles 
and all the other rhetors were not statesmen. After this he 
says that the Epicureans make clever speeches on many sub- 
jects, and these are they who have experience in leading cities ; 
and he grants earnestness to the rulers of cities, and does not 
class them with the wicked. 

At the end of col. XX XI p. 230 is found a phrase which by comparison 
with I, 122, 17 can be restored to read, “From a study of political affairs 
we can discover what is of advantage to the multitude.” In I, 122 this is 
part of a quotation from Metrodorus’ work attacking the views of Nausi- 
phanes. Nausiphanes’ doctrine recurs in col. XXXII “The best rhetors 
are trained by a study of natural science,” to which Philodemus (Metro- 
dorus) replies: “It is foolish to say that natural scientists make the best 
rhetors.” The name Metrodorus occurs again in col. XXIII,-1. 20, coupled 
with Epicurus. A part at least of coll. XXV-XXXI dealt with Nausi- 
phanes’ principles, and an idea of its contents may be gained from Book 
VI, particularly vol. II, pp. 24 ff. What follows is fragmentary up to 
p. 240. 

Demosthenes, Lycurgus and Demades are not classed as 
statesmen. 

What is more violent than saying that rhetoric promises 
nothing except the power of speaking. It is plainly false that 
the power of speaking cannot include any of the other qualities 
which it professes to include. . . . rhetoric is better designed 
for the transaction of private than of public business. 

Power of speech can be considered from different standpoints. 
When he mentions Themistocles and Pericles he means states- 
men like Phocion; if he named Isocrates and Matris he makes 


* On the relation of this theory to Cicero and Quintilian v. Rader- 
macher, Rhein. Mus. LIV (1899) p. 290. Diogenes originated the idea of 
the orator as being wir bonus dicendi peritus, and so starts a succession 
which extends to Quintilian. 


Ii227,.col 
Pexain 


II, 228, col. 
XXIII. 


II, 220, 
WADUE, aroik 
89, 

col. XXIV. 


li 23 cole 
XXXII. 


il, eae eoll 
LOOGIIE 


Nimeseecol: 
XXXIV. 


iilee2edt cole 


XXXV. 


Ill eter, Call. 


XXXVI. 


liies7sicol: 


XXXVII. 


II, 238, col. 


XXXVIII. 


Ii, 230; col: 


XXXIX, 


2 


ligeeatercol: 
ie 


352 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


a partial error. For Themistocles and Pericles have always been 
considered consummate rhetors. If Matris and his school are 
called rhetors, as he said, he ought not to apply this term to the 
political rhetors but to the other class, just as we would confine 
the term rhetors to Demosthenes and Callistratus and others of 
their class, who are said to have possessed political power, of 
whom we spoke in another section. 

Now changing our subject we shall show that the so-called 
sophists seem to us to have more power in political rhetoric 
than the theorists in politics. Now we have already treated in 
a previous section the idea that sophistic or panegyric or what- 
ever it may be called, by means of which some exercise the power 
of speech in assembly and forum, may easily be called rhetoric. 
That statement “He is a good rhetor” simply means that he is 
experienced and skilled in speaking. For as we say “good 
rhetor” we say “good artist” meaning “skillful”; “good rhetor” 
might also mean “morally good.” 

( Nothing. ) 

of those who were statesmen and had acquired this 
faculty, and of those who do not have it but succeed by dint of 
experience, of these many are better in character, many are very 
good, some have private virtues; some who have studied phi- 
losophy are justly considered more attractive than these. 

In examining political matters he is not accurate, as we have 
shown in the passages referring to his statements. And when 
he considers rhetoric and the rhetor equivalent to politics and 
the statesman, he is inaccurate. 

We shall inquire whether rhetoric is politics, and if there is 
a faculty which produces rhetors and statesmen; and again 
whether politics is exactly equivalent to rhetoric; and we shall 
make a careful inquiry as to whether the art of rhetoric is also 
the art of politics. We meet these questions as follows; 
sophistical rhetoric does not include a study of politics, and it 
is not political science; the rhetorical schools do not produce 
the political faculty or statesmen prepared for practical speak- 
ing and success in ecclesia and other public gatherings; and 
rhetoric qua rhetoric is not politics, and the rhetor is not a 
statesman and public speaker; and by no means do we agree 
with the statement made by some that rhetoric is politics; and 
we deny that the rhetor is always a statesman, not even in the 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 353 


narrower sense of the word among the ancients by which every 
one who spoke before the people was called a rhetor. Each of 
these topics we shall try to explain more fully. 

Now it is made clear by Epicurus in many passages in his book 
Ilept pyropuxns written with reference to those who are able to 
persuade, and by Metrodorus in the first book epi woumparwv 
that by rhetor the masters of the Epicurean school’* understand 
a person possessing technical training who has political expe- 
rience, and is able to discover what is of advantage to states. 
But we are content with the passage quoted just above (i. e. 
in the gap coll. XXV.-XXXI) against Nausiphanes, in which 
to a certain extent the word is used in accordance with accepted 
usage. For he divided the term rhetoric, and made it refer to 

panegyric, and to the faculty, “by which from experience and 
investigation of political events one could perceive well what 


is advantageous to the multitude.” . . . the phrase “as such” 
is added, and besides the phrase “there is no need of much 
argument.” . . . We shall prove that if by rhetor he con- 


sidered one who has political experience, if he adds the sophist’s 
art to his equipment, it is plain from mere examination that 
rhetoric possesses something over and above politics, and the 
rhetor something over and above the statesman—namely effec- 
tiveness of speech; he certainly possesses experience in politics. 
According to Greek usage one does not call Demosthenes and 
Callistratus and the like statesmen more than rhetors, and in 
that they are called rhetors they are called statesmen; but those 
who deliver epideictic orations and speeches more charming than 
theirs are not called rhetors in the same sense that these are 
called rhetors, or if they are so called it is because one speaks 
after a common form of concept. Consequently why is it not 
possible to call all rhetoric politics, in so far as it is rhetoric, and 
to call the rhetor a statesman? Why not call a rhetor gua 
rhetor a dypynyopos. For the phase “in short he is a Symnyopos”’ 
means in so far as he is called dyunydpos, and not differently from 
the rhetor, in as much as the dynunyepos is also called rhetor. 
Therefore Metrodorus says that Callistratus and Demosthenes, 
in so far as they possessed rhetoric were dyunyepo; but in the first 


® By Tovs dvdpas |, 18 he means the great Epicurean authorities particu- 
larly Epicurus, Hermarchus and Metrodorus. 


II, 242, col. 
SEI; 


II, 244, col. 
PIU 


II, 245, col. 
XLIII. 


Wiee2a7col. 
XLIV. 


II, 248, col. 
EWE 


II, 249, col. 
XLVI. 


354 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


book Ilepi zounndrwv he appears to disagree saying, “There is no 
faculty and science of persuading the multitude.” 

The art of politics then is understood to be experimental 
knowledge of constitutions and laws, and a knack which enables 
one to accept the guidance of states. Rhetoric is considered to 
include along with this the equipment and faculty for speaking. 
Now whoever has this experience, but lacks effectiveness in 
speaking, evidently possesses the political faculty and is a states- 
man, but he cannot be a rhetor, because though they possess 
experience in government and much greater knowledge of con- 
stitutions and laws and revenues and other things which pertain 
to the management of states, than the rhetors have, and actually 
do govern their countries, many who possess this experience do 
not possess the rhetorical faculty or such equipment as do those 
who are properly called rhetors; many in fact have no rhetorical 
ability at all. 

The rhetors on the other hand would not seem to anyone to 
lack rhetoric, which is the proper possession of a rhetor. For 
none of those called by common consent powerful and noble 
rhetors can be found without political experience and faculty. 
But it is not one of the attributes of sophistical rhetoric qua 
rhetoric to be the art of politics, nor is the sophistical rhetor, 
qua rhetor, a statesman; nor is the statesman qua statesman, a 
rhetor, as is evident from what Epicurus says in his Iepi pytopuxjs 
and Metrodorus in the first book Mepi zouparwv, and Hermarchus 
in an epistle to Theophides. 

Now if every art has its own peculiar field, we shall not expect 
navigation to produce geometricians and grammarians, nor is the 
knowledge of these sciences an attribute of a sailor. Why should 
we any more expect that statesmen or men prudent, courageous 
and highminded should be produced by this rhetoric qua rhetoric, 
and that such qualities are peculiar to rhetoric? For as we 
certainly would not say that the majority of people possess these 
qualities in so far as they possess the rhetorical faculty, but that 
they are good geometricians and grammarians, brave and just, 
and philosophers in a greater rather than in a less degree than 
those who possess the rhetorical faculty; and that many who 
have the advantages of rhetoric plainly lack the abovementioned 
sciences; in similar fashion, since many who not only have not 


_— 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 355 


acquired the rhetorical faculty, but have not studied at all with 
the sophists, nor have acquired a technical knowledge through 
practical study with a rhetor, still speak powerfully in public, 
and to use the term in its common meaning are artists and pos- 
sess technical ability [whereas many from the schools can not 
speak successfully]... . . Many of those trained in sophistic 
after the fashion of Isocrates have no political capacity or expe- 
rience, and are unable to speak in public. If they ever attempt 
it the audience die a-laughing; since this is true, as geomeiry 
and grammar have no need of rhetoric, and it cannot produce 
these sciences, so the art of politics is not the property of the 
rhetorical sophist, and they do not produce statesmen. 

Some one will say, “If because some are able without study 
of rhetoric to speak ably, we separate statesmanship from rhetoric 
on the ground that it is not peculiar to rhetoric, take away too 
the panegyric style of rhetoric which the rhetoricians practice 
both in writing and in the spoken word. . . . For many could 
imitate this, though they have not studied with the sophists, but 
merely because they are talented; and without having the tech- 
nical treatises composed in the schools, would imitate the work 
of some sophist.” 

“Charm really helps in public speaking. Some who have 
acquired a rhythmical style from these schools have become 
considerably more pleasing in public assemblies.” 

The same is probably true of studies in poetry and philosophy. 
Some would certainly be harmed by rhetoric; certainly many 
sacrifice their natural gifts and character, and what they learn 
in the schools is not persuasive or successful with their audience. 

Such is our discussion of the subjects mentioned. If anyone 
reproaches us with poverty, we shall be content with what we 
have, and shall not take up rhetoric to make money. 

But when they say, as Anaximenes does, that people would 
not pay the rhetoricians for instruction unless they acquired 
completely the power to speak in public they speak stupidly. For 
by this line of reasoning one could prove that soothsaying 
and . . . are arts, and have greater right to be called arts 
than philosophy because the professors of these arts receive 
larger pay than the philosopher. It is senseless to compare 
faculties in this way, nor does the fact that some pay money to 


It 2525cols 
XLVIII, 
e2ae 


iaraeor 
> GBD. 


MeS2cae hie 
col. XLIX, 
22 aie 
cole TEE. 


II, 256, col. 


IIIa. 


is267, «col: 


Via 


Ils Abstey 
col. V2. 


INL, ARO) Cell 
VIa, 


356 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


rhetors'* prove that statesmen are produced by rhetoric. One 
must not think that we have mentioned this proof merely for 
the sake of talking, but that it is true, and that those are mis- 
taken who pay money to sophists. Epicurus says, “Whenever 
they listen to their displays and panegyric speeches, and are be- 
guiled because the speech is not about a contract nor public policy 
as it is in assembly and court (for in these they pay close atten- 
tion to the speaker, because they have something at stake in the 
assembly, and they are bound by an oath if they are sitting on 
the jury, whereas in the case of sophistical displays they care 
nothing for the oath, for they have not sworn to judge fairly 
nor do they care whether what is said is advantageous to the 
state or not, for it is not a question of war and peace, such as 
they have to vote on at times; and if the speech deals with war 
or peace or some other subject discussed in assemblies, it does 
not deal with a timely or pressing question, consequently they 
listen to displays without any feeling of anxiety) whenever they 
listen to such a speech they give no heed whether it is advan- 
tageous or disadvantageous, or even true or false, but are be- 
guiled by the sound and the periods, parisoses and antitheses and 
homoioteleuta, and think that if they could talk like that they 
would succeed in assembly and court, failing to recognize that 
they would not endure anyone who spoke like that in assembly 
or court. That is why they spend money on sophists. Then im- 
mediately they recognize that they have lost their money, for 
they get no result but hard feeling and worry; hard feeling 
because they have been trained in rhetoric, and if their speech is 
successful they are thought to mislead the jury; but if they fail 
they think they have paid the sophist in vain; they are anxious 
about these very points, and still more how they will seem to 
come off with the speech, or about not misleading the jury by 
appearances. They have these troubles, and besides they have 
to attend carefully to conjunctions and cases, not abiding by their 
own rules but by those of others. For these and other reasons 
some study with the rhetoricians; in some of these they are de- 
ceived more than in others as we have stated above. 

The rhetors among the sophists behave no better, not even 
when they say that one can prove that their art produces states- 


“Here pijrwp apparently is equivalent to pyropixds or copiorys. 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 357 


men from the fact that some of their pupils are able to plead 
causes and conduct themselves properly before the assembly, in 
the same way that one could prove that the art of grammar pro- 
duces people able to read and write from the fact that those who 
have attended the school can do this. Their argument works 
against them rather than for them, since everybody who studies 
the art of grammar learns to read and write, and no one learns 
without studying. But many who study rhetoric cannot speak 
in public, in fact this is true of the majority, and many who have 
not studied can speak—they outnumber those who have studied. 
Therefore we must agree that those who have studied and are 
statesmen, are such not by virtue of acquiring the faculty which 
the sophist professes to impart, but from other reasons. Such 
would be remarkable natural ability for acquiring the rhetorical 
faculty, and ardor in practicing in politics when once they have 
shown themselves desirous of rhetorical instruction, and have 
filled themselves with political speeches which involve a con- 
siderable degree of imitation, and, last of all, a spirit of meddling, 
which is the source of most political experience. There are 
many other causes, consequently their statement is unsound. 
And so, although there is such a connection between these 
studies, nevertheless rhetors skilled in swaying the passions are 
not produced by these studies any more than by such studies as 
grammar and philosophy. It thus appears vain to claim that 
these studies produce the political faculty; just because some 
statesmen come from these schools one cannot claim that rhetoric 
produces them. So much for that. 

When they ask, who is a statesman if we cannot call the 
rhetors statesmen, it is easy to answer, laymen, but they are not 
the only ones or the majority, but the rhetors are the statesmen, 
however these are not the panegyrical rhetors, but those who en- 
gage in real contests; also many are statesmen who are not 
rhetors but possess the political faculty. But it is foolish and 
senseless to inquire what this faculty is, to say that it is the 
faculty which produces statesmen, and then to add that rhetoric 
is the art of politics, and produces statesmen. 

When they argue as follows: “It is the task of the statesman 
to govern the state, to advise, to have experience in embassies, 
constitutions, decrees, etc., and the rhetor understands all this,” 
grant that this can be proven, and let us allow for the sake of 


II, 260, col. 
VIIa, 


I, Bow, Cell. 
VIII, : 


RS 262 "cole 
1Xa, 


INE, Aer. 
col. X4, 


II, 266, col. 


Te, 


M267; ‘colt 


xls 


II, 268, col. 


SQ URES 


358 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


argument that rhetors qua rhetors possess knowledge and ability 
in these matters, yet it must be objected that some statesmen 
who are not rhetors possess all these qualifications. If by 
rhetors they mean those trained in the schools, we shall simply 
laugh at them; if they mean the practical rhetors, they will not 
find us opposing them. For they claim for themselves nothing 
ridiculous. 

When they say that it is ridiculous to separate the political 
faculty from perfect rhetoric, for it is included in the concept 
of rhetoric, just as those skilled in the art of medicine possess 
a knowledge of what is healthful and harmful, they are exceed- 
ingly amusing. For how can that which is not acknowledged 
to include politics be granted to include politics by preconception? 
But the announced claims of rhetoric do not include this; only 
a confusion of thought includes this with rhetoric without 
proving that it belongs to rhetoric. There is no need of fur- 
ther argument in reply to the claim that states have been man- 
aged by rhetors. For even if we grant that it has been done by 
the political rhetors, gua statesmen, we shall not grant that it has 
been done by the rhetoricians, and if by them, not qua rhetori- 
cians. It is the same way with the claim that it is the rhetors, not 
the philosophers, who have busied themselves with political af- 
fairs. They may use this argument against others, we grant 
that philosophy does not produce statesmen. Some babblers they 
produce who use the same words that the statesmen use, but not 
for that shall we grant that it produces the political faculty. If 
we worked on this principle we should soon be granting every 
thing which they profess to write about. 

Now that we have finished this chapter, it remains for us to 
discuss the question whether the rhetor because of his rhetoric 
would become a good statesman. As for the rhetor produced 
by the schools, how could we say that qua rhetor he could become 
a good statesman, seeing that qua rhetor he is not a statesman 
at all? In regard to the political rhetor we think the case stands 
thus: the phrase “good statesman” means either a capable and 
experienced statesman, or one morally good. According to the 
former interpretation, qua rhetor, we say that he is a good states- 
man, just as we call the artistic flautist, qua flautist, an artistic 
flautist, and so a good flautist. According to the second inter- 
pretation we no longer say that the rhetor qua rhetor would be a 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 359 


good statesman. In the first place he is estimated according to 

his experience in what is advantageous to the state, and in speak- 

ing, just as the physician is estimated according to his knowledge 

of what is healthful and unhealthful. If he possesses this, no 

matter what his character is, there is nothing to prevent his. 

being a rhetor. The same must be understood of one who is II, 270, col. 
not a rhetor but a statesman. There would be objection if he AG 
had to be good, qua rhetor. For the expression qua rhetor 

means that in this he is a rhetor, and from the same condition 

and no other can a rhetor arise; but it is plain to all that many 

are capable rhetors, but bad morally. “Qua” is of this nature; 

if it is added it cannot be removed. Since this is so, we do not 

consider the political faculty by itself useful either to those who 

possess it or to the states, but that it is often the cause of ir- 

reparable dissensions in the sense that what gives the impulse 

is the cause. If it is accompanied by uprightness of character 

it often contributes great blessing to states, and sometimes 

greater good to its possessors than to private citizens, but often- II, 271, col. 
times greater woe, as is proven by their lives. And if anyone oe 

says that the good statesman ought to have many virtues, and 

that states are saved not by rhetors qua statesmen, but by good 

statesmen, he will be right. It would be well if the statesman 

studied philosophy in order that he might be more actively good, 

and for this reason we say that philosophy if it were associated 

generally with the political state of mind and in individual cases 

made suggestions applicable to political management, would pro- 

duce a wonderful improvement. He would be a good rhetor and 

statesman who possessed kindness, uprightness and temperance 

in his private life, education, wisdom which is the outgrowth of II, 272, col. 
his natural ability, and combined with all these, astuteness. XVIA 


Fragmenta Hypomnematici 


a 
(Nothing. ) II, 273, fr. I. 
When mentioning such a statesman he says that he is experi- fr. II, 
enced in what is helpful and harmful, and possesses all virtues, 
and that the rhetors know none of these things, and do not claim 
to know them, but possess simply boldness and garrulity. Tae fe 
. . . by this line of argument how could Lycurgus, Demos- Ij,‘ 


‘ 


fi) IT, Et 


XVII. 

IIL ASH athe 
XVIII. 

fr. OLX. 


fit 
XXI. 
MO. @ Wena 
XXII. 


Ge eT, 


e270; 


Serine 


ig 


py Ll 


360 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


thenes and Hyperides be considered practical? In the first place 
not only was any appearance of order lacking in the speeches 
which they delivered, but it did not appear even in their writings, 
and it is plain that they did not avoid empty talk. Quite the 
opposite; if any have talked discreetly and powerfully. . 

The public speakers say that the political art is nothing but 
rhetoric. Critolaus says that the art of politics demands 
only time. 

( Nothing.) 

Anyone with common sense would say that the rhetors wrote 
the laws, and that now states do not entrust lawmaking to 
philosophers, but to rhetors. If any philosopher ever 
made any laws he must have been one of the old philosophers. 
He certainly had no conpection with the Peripatetics. 

( Nothing.) 

Sardanapallus (cf. II, 188). 

Separate politics and rhetoric (cf. II, 66, col. X*) . . / . there 
is no use for it in politics; for persuasion is not needed for 
everything. 

(Nothing. ) 

Many rhetors will be found who have performed proper and 
righteous acts. 

(Nothing. ) 

B 

If he takes from rhetoric experience in what is advantageous 
to the state, and assigns it to philosophy, let us not be vexed. 
Yet to turn to something with which they agree . . that 
the rhetors have need of a knowledge of character, and acquire 
this from philosophy, which some said was to be acquired from 
the sophists . . which Demosthenes. . 

(With zapwpixevar tas éeriOvpias cf. II, 271, fr. I.) 

. nevertheless as such he is better than the majority of 
rhetors, by nature . . however one who is called a good artist 
is not of this nature. 

. possessing one part of the science, but lacking the other. 
“According to these, and those who speak as befits themselves, 
rhetoric cannot produce men just and prudent.” 

( Nothing.) 

Justice is not peculiar to a state, but belongs to any association. 

But experience, speaking plainly testifies that they do not wear 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 361 


out states by selling their interests. Now states have recog- 
nized their ability, for the power of the state is increased under 
their rule. 

The first is false. What he has not learned himself how could 
he teach another who has never studied the question of advan- 
tage? How could one refrain from accepting bribes, and from 
base gain and deceit? 


y 


The rhetor ought to be earnest. The perfect statesman is 
acquainted with what is advantageous to the state. 

(Nothing. ) 

Demosthenes . . Aristodemus.*® 

—Diogenes seems to have seen this; for all their attempts, 
so to speak, are reducible to this one demonstration, that the 
statesman always possesses all virtues. . 

Thus they will try to say that rhetoric is the same as the art 
of politics, however it is not selfsufficient for successful states- 
manship, but needs some assistance in calming the passions. 

The huckster and the pilot ought to be vigorous and brave, 
éven if one adds “good.’?* He will be in still greater error, 
and will run equal risk if he judges from the lives of those only 
partly trained in philosophy who have lived wickedly, that 
philosophy does not produce a happy life. 

If it is advantageous and proper for the statesman to be just 
and brave, the statesman would wisely be just and brave and 
prudent. Likewise he demonstrated a third point, as follows: 
One cannot be a statesman, unless one is brave and just, and 
in the possession of all virtues. 

The rhetors executed Socrates, by making most wicked 
charges against him, as Plato says in the Apology— 

(Nothing. ) 

Management of states in the hands of cobblers. 

[Having shown] that rhetoric is not an art... .. . we shall 
now try to present the common faults found in most speeches, 
some of them perhaps in all. Our manner of refutation will be 


* Gellius, XI, 9, tells the story of Demosthenes receiving a bribe from 
Miletus and boasting of it to Aristodemus. 
ener. El, 233: 


lire Ds alll: 


Heese. tee 


fie, 1 
res JULI 
fre LW 


II, 284, 
lity Wo 


ines WAL, 


JUS esis, ais 
WALI. 


II, 286, fr. 
Viti, 


fre, 1D S— sl 


[LE 280; tr; 
XIIIa. 
ft. X'R0b: 


M200; tn. 
XIV. 


ey 2o 1" sit 
Fi 


Xx 


LIS2ory ine 
XVI. 


te, 2cV i. 


Wl ADA ane 


XVIII. 


e202) Sirs 
XIX. 


fr. XX. 


II, 293, fr. 
XXI. 


fr. XXII. 


362 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 
more methodical if we proceed from some principles in making 
our divisions. . 

No philosopher is able to speak in public. 

The rhetor ought to possess Hermes’ wand “with which he 
soothes the eyes of men whom he will, and others sleeping he 
and the embroidered girdle of Aphrodite “in which 
there is love,” i. e. speech which is not without charm, which 
is the peculiar product of rhetoric. And he ought to be ac- 
quainted with constitutions, laws, edicts and customs, and in ad- 
dition to this decisions reached in assembly and court. 

Rhetoric has said nothing to us about freeing us from love 
of glory, but rather increases it by praising its advantages, and 
holding out glory as a prize. : 

the aforesaid logographers and the comic poets of ‘dae 
day, and the writers of biography. They demonstrate that these 
men have been servants of their own states and of the rest of 
Greece. 

If the rhetor cannot guide his own household, consisting of 
wife, children, slaves and free servants, how can he control the 
greater ship, the state, consisting of more children and women? 

( Nothing.) 

It takes the same skill’? to tune one lyre as to tune many in 
unison, and the results are evident. Scarcely one of these is 
recorded to have served his country well on an embassy, some 
are convicted of malfeasance, and others, if they accomplish 
anything, do not accomplish anything useful. 

In order that some may not think that we pass over in silence 
what has been written, matters of no importance or small points 
savoring of Stoic toil, we shall present the arguments on both 


awakes,” 


sides. 

(Nothing. ) 

He will say what is advantageous ; 
is advantageous is good, and the same for private citizens and 
communities; contrariwise, what is harmful is evil. But only 
philosophy possesses the knowledge of these subjects, and it 
must be said that this is not productive of statesmanship. 

(Nothing. ) 


and will agree that what 


GE Wal, 221.223) 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 363 


But one who cannot guide his own skiff successfully, would 
not be able to pilot the triremes of the state.*® 

( Nothing.) 

When they write as if there were need of both we shall make 
the proper reply when we think the explanations given by the 
other worthy of fitting answer. 


(Nothing.) ‘ 


Constitutions and laws and customs and the like. For it is 
clear that some of them manage their states by means of their 
acquaintance with these things. Many are willing to depend on 
mere sham, as will be evident when we come to that section... . 

While they say that the political faculty is not the political 
art unless it is conjoined with philosophy, they do not deny that 
there is need of philosophy, but you do not disprove that rhetoric 
involves the political faculty. In another way they will not be 
at a loss even according to Stoic principles to give a character- 
istic answer. 

Neither physician nor pilot nor painter is an artist, for they 
have no proper (special) knowledge, nor do they possess the 
faculty, because often they do not attain their desires: the 
pilot does not save but wrecks his ship, the painter does not 
produce beautiful but ugly pictures. 

Just as a physician can be good, and so can an architect and a 
pilot, so a statesman can be good. 

( Nothing.) 

€ 

Just as we speak of inexperience and ignorance in relation 
to philosophy, so we speak of people as good in relation to 
character. 

If he wishes to consider that statesmanship is not a part of 
philosophy, he will be right. We agree with him. 

He says that philosophy does not produce artists. 

As among the Gauls those unable to bear arms became trump- 
eters, so those who cannot manage political affairs become 
sophists, and blow their trumpets in the midst of crowd. 

Pericles is said to have been the disciple of Anaxagoras. 

(Nothing. ) 


piel 2o0 fr. xX VL. 


M2045 te: 
XXIII. 


fr. XXIV. 


leone fr: 
XXV. 


I Aoys, aie. 
VE 


ttle 


fr, Vip 


IT, 208, 
fp ke 


ties, LEE 


JUL eon ake 
IV. 
fire Vile 


fra, V LI. 
tr VITE, BS 


ne 
ele 


Vile 
302, X°, 


fol. 67-70, 


Ets 


it. 


fr. 


igle 


Ni 


VI. 


VY 


364 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


( Nothing.) . 

“The Athenians though fond of oratory are offended by peri- 
ods, and those who savor of scholastic rhetoric. 719 "There is. 
need of opportunity in diplomacy. 

Since every virtue, not that which existed in the time of the 
heroes, but in the time of Pythagoras and men of earlier gen- 
eration. . 

( Nothing.) 


EXCURSUS. 


The rise of teachers of the art of oratory in Greece marks the 
beginning of a movement in Greek literature which is of the 
highest importance in determining the course of Greek thought 
for the succeeding centuries; in fact through its influence on 
Rome and those modern literatures which derive largely from 
Rome it has shaped much of the thought and expression of the 
modern world. The movement seemed destined from the very 
first to be unusually significant. The enthusiasm with which the 
new study was welcomed by the youth of Greece showed that 
the sophists had accurately judged the needs of their public. 
The importance of the new teaching is shown no less by the 
violent opposition which it encountered. It was an unerring 
instinct which led the enemy of Athenian democracy and Euri- 
pidean tragedy to direct one of his most vigorous attacks against 
the teaching of the power of speech which was so intimately con- 
nected with the other objects of his aversion. Aristophanes is 
our sole extant example of a feeling which was general in the 
latter part of the fifth century among conservative classes that 
the teaching of the sophists was a detriment to the community. 
Tricky and even lying speech there had always been, and would 
always be, but it seemed incredibly monstrous that men should 
undertake to train others in the art of deception. 

At first the attack was couched in general terms, and was 
aimed at the immorality of the new profession without attempt- 
ing to analyze its principles or methods. But the growing skill 
and subtlety in argument, and a more precise limiting of the 
spheres of the professions by specialization gave to the con- 


UG lb, ek 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 365 


troversy a technical character which it was not soon to lose. It 
is to Plato that we owe the origin of this as of so many other 
lines of thought. In attempting to set off for himself the field 
of “philosophy” he is led in the process of defining the limits 
of his field to exclude rhetoric. In doing this he introduces a 
new turn to the attack by denying that rhetoric is entitled to be 
called a réyvye We may suppose that the sophists had referred 
to their occupation as a réexyvy, in the broad use of the word 
which is nearly equivalent to the English “occupation.” Cer- 
tainly their written works on rhetoric were styled réyva or 
“systematic instructions.” The tacit assumption in all this is 
that speaking proceeds by certain rules and can be reduced to 
a system in the same manner that stone cutting or carpentry can. 
Plato, therefore, goes to the heart of the matter by declaring in 
the Gorgias and Phaedrus that rhetoric is not réyvy, but éeurepia 
or tptByn. He does not define “art” in the precise fashion of 
his successors, but implies clearly enough that the prerequisites 
for art are a knowledge of the nature of the “materials’— 
whether animate or inanimate—treated by the art, and of prin- 
ciples of action based on scientific acquaintance with cause and 
effect; to this he adds that an art always aims to produce a 
beneficial result. Tested by all of these principles rhetoric is 
found wanting. At the same time he grants the possibility of a 
true rhetoric which aims to produce justice in the souls of the 
people. In a sense Plato merely continues the old popular 
prejudice against rhetoric as a pursuit detrimental to the best 
interests of the community; but by introducing the question 
whether rhetoric deserves to be called an art, he opened the way 
for a controversy which extends through several centuries. It 
is a controversy in which some of the philosophical schools are 
at times found on the side of rhetoric, but in the main, the divi- 
sion between philosophers and rhetoricians, initiated by Plato, 
remains throughout the life of the philosophical schools. In all 
its ramifications it is an interesting and ofttimes puzzling chapter 
in the history of human thought, on which much has been written ; 
much more however waits on the discovery of a new papyrus, or 
a new interpretation of an old fragment. It is my purpose in 


*Gorgias 501A. 
* Gorgias 504D. 


366 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


this excursus to discuss merely certain phases of that part of the 
controversy which deals with the question whether rhetoric 
deserves to be called an “art.” 

Aristotle’s attitude toward the question of “art” admits of 
some dispute. True in his extant work there is no doubt that 
he regards rhetoric as an art; in fact the Rhetorica is a scientific 
treatise on rhetoric along the lines laid down by Plato; it rests 
on a study of psychology, and discusses the means of arousing 
the emotions and convincing the intellect. It differs from Plato 
in that it takes little account of the question whether the art is 
beneficial; a natural difference since Plato regards rhetoric as 
the art of persuasion; one who professes to persuade his people 
makes himself responsible for their welfare; whereas Aristotle 
extends the field of the art only to include the discovery of the 
persuasive elements in any case. So far the position of Aristotle 
is plain. But in his lost dialogue, Gryllus, he attacked the right 
of rhetoric to be called an “art.” Quintilian, who is our authority 
for the contents of the dialogue, suggests that it was a mere tour 
de force, an attempt to maintain a paradox.* This seems some- 
what improbable, and I should suggest three possible explana- 
tions of the inconsistency between the Gryllus and the Rhetorica. 
1) The Gryllus may have been a dialogue in which both sides 
of the question were presented, with the conclusion that rhetoric 
is an “art.” This seems hardly deducible from Quintilian’s 
words, which imply that Aristotle’s position in the Gryllus needed 
to be harmonized with that of the Rhetorica. 2) The Gryllus 
may have been an attack on certain phases of the contemporary 
teaching of rhetoric, certain perversions of the art, as Aristotle 
may have thought. Here again Quintilian’s words might mean 
this, but are more naturally taken to mean that the attack was 
unqualified. 3) The Gryllus may be from the earlier period of 
Aristotle’s teaching. We know that rhetoric was a relatively late 
addition to the curriculum of the Lyceum, whether or not we 
credit the story that he was driven to adopt it by the competition 
of Isocrates. It may well be that in his early career, while still 
under the influence of Plato, he wrote against rhetoric, and later 
adopted the position which he holds in the Rhetorica. 


“c 


“ec 


®TI, 17, 14; Aristotles, ut solet, quaerendi gratia quaedam suptilitatis 
suae argumenta excogitavit in Gryllo: sed idem et de arte rhetorica tris 
libros scripsit, et in eorum primo non artem solum eam fatetur etc. 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 367 


The post-Aristotelian schools differed somewhat in their atti- 
tude toward rhetoric. The Peripatetics followed the lead of 
Aristotle until Critolaus broke with the tradition of the school, 
and ranged himself with the Academics who had remained true 
to the Platonic position. The Epicureans consistently opposed 
rhetoric, with a slight inclination to favor the epideictic branch 
with the honor of being an art. The Stoics from the very begin- 
ning regarded rhetoric as an art, but with a Stoic reservation 
which nullified much of their concession. The hundred and fifty 
years following the death of Aristotle were, however, not pro- 
ductive of much controversy on this point. The most influential 
of the philosophical schools had included rhetoric as a part of 
their philosophical system; men were more interested in the 
novel tenets of new philosophical sects than in the rehearsal of 
old controversies. But a more important reason for the lack of 
conflict was the decline of the rhetorical schools. The effort of 
Isocrates to maintain rhetoric on a par with philosophy had been 
in vain, and the rhetoricians sank into mere declaimers, scarcely 
deserving an attack. It is not until rhetoric begins to assume 
once more its old vitality that the controversy begins again, this 
time conducted with even more subtlety and much greater ani- 
mosity. The period is the second century before our era; the 
Rhetoric of Hermagoras is only one, though perhaps the most 
influential one of many works which placed rhetoric once more 
in a position to be considered a worthy successor of the “phi- 
losophy”’ of Isocrates. As soon as rhetoric raised its head once 
more, the philosophical schools opened fire. The old arguments 
are furbished up, and the Platonic method of definition is pressed 
to its limit. The dispute turns largely on the old question 
whether rhetoric is to be regarded as an art. The addition which 
two centuries of philosophy have made is that the definitions 
of art are much more precise, and that the debate is very largely 
a series of quibbles. Verbi enim controversia iam diu torquet 
Graeculos homines contentionis cupidiores quam veritatis. 

The history of this later stage must be gained by piecing 
together notices in many later authorities, of which there are 
four of prime importance: the rhetorical fragments of Philo- 
demus, particularly the first and second books; Cicero’s De 
Oratore, Quintilian’s Institutio Oratoria, and Sextus Empiricus 
IIpos pyjropas. The material here presented was discussed some 


368 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


years ago by Olivier in his dissertation De Critolao Peripatetico, 
and more'systematically by Radermacher in the preface to Sud- 
haus’ Supplementum Philodemi. My excuse for a renewal of 
the discussion must be found in the fact that Radermacher did 
not take into account the notices in Cicero, and was thus led to 
assign to Critolaus a share in the debate which is larger than he 
seems to deserve. It is with the idea, therefore, of supplement- 
ing the work of Radermacher rather than of joining issue with 
him on his main thesis that I present the following pages. A 
comparison of the arguments used by our four authorities will 
reveal that they drew from common sources, some of which 
can be identified, but most of which must be classed as part of a 
store of commonplaces which were familiar to all educated people. 
So well known was the general form of argument employed that 
as Radermacher acutely observed, Lucian could base one of his 
richest parodies—Hept zapacirov—on the old lines of the discus- 
sion whether rhetoric was an art. 

At first sight the discussion appears more than unusually 
futile. Of what account was it whether rhetoric was texvy 
or tprBy? But the question was evidently felt to be of vital 
importance, and we may not be far from wrong in assuming that 
the bread and butter of many a philosopher and rhetorician was 
at stake. So long as the rhetorician was a mere declaimer, there 
was little danger that he would attract any considerable portion 
of the student class. But the rejuvenated rhetoric of the last 
days of the Roman republic claimed to be a complete education 
in itself, supplanting philosophy, or at least reducing phi- 
losophy to the position of a handmaid of rhetoric. To combat 
the new rival philosophy put forth its utmost strength. The 
question of “art”? was of vital importance, for it was assumed 
that only “arts” can be taught; once it was proven that rhetoric 
was not an art, it followed that the rhetoricians had nothing to 
offer the prospective student. The situation offers some parallels 
to certain educational questions much debated a few years ago, 
and still, I believe, not entirely settled. It was once the fashion 
to claim that certain studies offered exceptional “mental disci- 
pline,’ or general training of the mind. Investigations in 
psychology have tended to show that there is no “general” 
discipline, but only special disciplines. Mathematics, for example, 
does not increase the ability to study law, but only improves the 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 369 


mathematical faculty. This theory, whether correct or not, was 
seized by the opponents of certain studies to claim that in the new 
light of psychology these studies could no longer claim a place 
in the curriculum. Substitute “mental discipline” for réxvy, 
and many of the arguments of Philodemus have a remarkably 
modern sound. 

Those who denied that rhetoric was an art took two positions. 
The milder group granted that there were some principles of 
rhetoric which could be imparted from teacher to pupil, but 
that they were the result of the teacher’s observation and expe- 
rience, and needed the supplement of the pupil’s own observation, 
and were thus subjective and individualistic, and did not possess 
that generality which characterized the arts. This is the position 
of Philodemus toward the forensic and deliberative branches of 
thetoric.* This is the view which Cicero puts in the mouth of 
Antonius when he wishes to represent him as all but granting 
that rhetoric is an art.2 On the other hand the more severe critics 
of the art termed it a xaxoreyvia or perversion of art.® 

Philodemus and Quintilian have in common the well known 
argument from design: the perfect product implies the existence 
of the artist and the art. If a vase is evidently the product of an 
art, much more must the sublime products of the orator be the 
result of art.’ There is no indication in either author of the 
source from which they drew. 


“I, 40, 18 = Suppl. 21, 7, Some unnamed rhetorician is arguing that in 
rhetoric there is a transmission of knowledge from teacher to pupil; 
‘"Oomep éu movotky Kal Ypaumatixn Tapaddces Tivay elory dyvooumévwy, otTws Kal él 


Philodemus replies, Iapadécers 
ayvooupévwy dtvavral Tuves eivar, Kav uy KaTad TLva TéxvnV evyivwvTar, KaTa dé 


pntopixys, Kal ovK duébodos 7 pehérn ylverat.’ 


ioroplay 7) mapaTnpyow 7H TLva ToLoUTOY TpbTroY. 

*De Orat. II, 57, 232; Observatio quaedam est earum rerum quae in 
dicendo valent. Cf. I, 23, 109; Sin autem ea quae observata sunt in usu 
ac tractione dicendi, haec ab hominibus callidis ac peritis animadversa ac 
notata, verbis definita, generibus illustrata, partibus distributa sunt—id 
quod video potuisse fieri—, non intellego, quam ob rem non, si minus illa 
suptili definitione, at hac volgari opinione ars esse videatur. 

°Sextus Emp. 12, 49, and 68. It is ascribed by him to Critolaus and 
Plato. The same expression was used by Epicurus teste Ammiano Marc. 
30, 4. 

eOnmte 1. 17, 3; Philod: I, 44-16 8; = Supplh- 23.75 ff. Quintilian 
repeats the idea in summing up the arguments for rhetoric, II, 17, 42. 


370 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


An argument was based on the relatively late appearance of 
formal treatises on rhetoric. There were orators, they said, 
before Corax and Tisias, and better orators, too. The implica- 
tion, carried out somewhat fully by Quintilian, is that if there 
were orators without the so-called “artistic” training, men might 
still become orators without studying with a rhetorician, or 
reading any of the manuals of rhetoric. If a speech can be 
produced without the “art,” then the pretensions of the “art” 
are false, there is no art. This appears in Quintilian and Philo- 
demus, and is answered by both in the same way. I give the 
passages in parallel columns. 


Phil. i 27), 6 Quint. ae 17, vA 


IIpd Tod KataBAnOjvae tas réxvas Deinde adiciunt illas verborum 
BéArevov épytdpevov, ef ois 8& ovv- Cavillationes, nihil quod ex 
éornoay xéipov. arte fiat, ante artem fuisse; 
atqui dixisse homines pro se et 
in alios semper; doctores artis 
sero et circa Tisian et Cordes 


, ‘ \ -~ \ 
Tovtw pev yap TO TpoTw Kal THY 
, \ 
TOLTUKHVY «Kal THY laTpiKynVy Kal 


mokAds ddAas ovK eivae Téxyvas 


Notaiien primum repertos ae 
tollatur medicina . . 3 Gee 
fabricar sit “arse’ {39 Gee 
musica. 


Such must have been the original kernel of the argument. and 
the regular reply of the rhetoricians. Philodemus, however, 
almost obscures the reply by interpolating his favorite argument 
that rhetoric is the product of natural ability plus experience, 
hence one might expect the ancients to be better than the moderns. 
For Philodemus is an enthusiastic laudator temporis acti. 

An argument of similar nature is drawn from the fact that 
there have been successful orators who have had no rhetorical 
training. This occurs in Philodemus, Quintilian, Sextus, and 
Cicero, with just enough suggestion as to its ultimate source 
to make a puzzling problem. I give in parallel columns the 
passages from Philodemus, Quintilian, and Sextus, reserving 
Cicero for a separate discussion. 


The 


Quintilian 

1h 87) Ea 
Quo illud quoque ex- 
cluditur, quod dicunt, 
non esse artis id, 
quod faciat, qui non 
didicerit: dicere au- 
tem homines et qui 
non didicerint. ad 
cuius rei confirma- 
tionem adferunt De- 
maden remigem et 
Aeschinen hypocriten 
oratores fuisse. 


Rhetorica of Philodemus. 


Philodemus 
iNoyait. VIIL 
Sap@s yap Eye ore 

Aynpadyns ovx euaber, 
as 8 attas Aioyxivys 
nto Kal map aAAwv 7 Ov 
avtav Ta peodiKa THS 
PyTopiKns ovT amAaTa TO 
TANGos OvTa TpOTKAapTEpH- 
cews Te TOAANS Ov Seopeva.. 
Tov pev yap Anuoobevnv 
TAVTES KEKpayacL OL Kat’ 
aQvTOV TEXVITHV Elva, Kat 


KputoXaos otk arapveiras. 


Sextus 
Adv. Rhet. 16 
Eirep te evdexerau ye- 
veoOar pytopa pay perta- 
PyTopLKys 
TeXVYS, OUK ay ein TIS 


TXOVTA = THS 
TEXVY PyTopiKy. evdéxeTaL 
d€ ye ikavOs Kal KaTa TOV 
pyntopevev ua) 
PETATXOVTA PYNTOPLKNS, WS 


TpoTrov 


kal wept Anpadov ma- 


peArn paper. 


‘ Bt c a ” 
yap ov w@podroyetrar apt- 


KwITNAGT NS 


\ 
OTOS yeyovevat pyTwp, Kal 
ovv ToUTw GAA TapTAY- 


Geis. Toivuv otk €ate TEXVN 


7 pyTopiKy- 


The similarity of thought is striking, and the employment of 
Demades as an example by all three, and Aeschines by two of 
our authors makes it almost certain that we are dealing with 
material drawn from a common source. There are two possi- 
bilities to be considered. Philodemus mentions Critolaus in the 
sentence following the reference to Demades and Aeschines. 
This sentence is to the effect that Critolaus did not deny that 
Demosthenes was an artist. This seems to imply that Critolaus 
did deny that some orators owed their success to art, and hence 
it is a plausible conjecture that the preceding statement that 
Demades and Aeschines were self taught is also part of the 
argument of Critolaus. 

The situation is somewhat similar in regard to the passage in 
Sextus. Critolaus is not specifically mentioned as the author of 
the argument, but he is mentioned shortly before (10) and 
immediately after (20). This in itself is not sufficient ground 
for supposing that the argument under discussion is also derived 
from Critolaus, but the combination of the references in Philo- 
demus and Sextus led Radermacher to infer that he was the 
source from which they both drew. But the occurrence of the 
name Critolaus in section 20 of Sextus does not lend as much 


372 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


support to his view as appears at first sight, for Sextus adds the 
names of two Academics, Clitomachus and Charmadas. The 
case for Critolaus is thus to some extent weakened. If the 
argument from juxtaposition means anything, the thought we are 
considering might derive from Charmadas as well as from 
Critolaus. And this possibility receives support from the pas- 
sage in the De Oratore alluded to above. The passage is the 
long speech of Antonius beginning at the eighteenth section of 
the first book. He narrates a debate which he had heard at 
Athens between the champions and opponents of rhetoric. The 
incident may be true, or more likely, merely a fiction designed to 
establish a personal connection between Cicero and Charmadas 
from whose published works he is drawing the material for his 
argument.* Cicero represents Charmadas as making the prin- 
cipal attack on rhetoric. His argument that we are so consti- 
tuted by nature as to be able to be orators without the assistance 
of “art” was supported by examples of successful orators who 
had never studied in the schools of rhetoric. The argument is 
the same that appears in Sextus, Philodemus, and Quintilian; 
the only point we miss is the reference to Demades and Aeschines. 
I suspect that the lack is due to a definite purpose of Cicero’s 
in adapting his sources. Antonius is represented as one who 
looks with mild contempt on the learning of the Greeks. Hence 
the scornful nescio quo with which he dismisses Corax and 
Tisias (91). It is in keeping with this assumed indifference that 
he sums up the examples of Charmadas with innumerabilis 
quosdam. In place of these Greek examples he makes Charmadas 
substitute a Roman example, Antonius himself. This is Cicero’s 
trick of working over his Greek source so that it appears as if 
it were really composed for a Roman audience. This method 
may be illustrated, and our conjecture on this passage supported 
by comparing a passage in the long digression in the third book 
of the De Oratore. Cicero is developing the thought that before 
the rise of the Socratic schools the term philosophy was not 
confined to abstract speculation, but covered the whole field of 
intellectual activity, so that the oratorical power of a Pericles, 


® This method is used more than once by Cicero; for other instances 
see Hendrickson, Literary Sources in Cicero’s Brutus and the Technique 
of Citation in Dialogue. Amer. Journ. Phil. XXVII (1906) p. 184. 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. B78 


or the shrewd statesmanship of a Themistocles were as much 
the products of “philosophy” as the mathematical subtleties of 
Pythagoras. Cicero is drawing from a Greek source which 
ultimately goes back to Isocrates. From this source he derives 
a triad of Greeks who combined deep speculations with power 
of speech. They are Lycurgus, Pittacus, Solon. (De Orat. III, 
15, 56.) He parallels these by a list of Romans, Coruncanius, 
Fabricius, Cato, Scipio, thus clothing the thought in Roman 
dress. This same method he has followed in the passage in the 
first book, by putting into the mouth of Charmadas a Roman 
example, Antonius, instead of the Greek examples, Demades and 
Aeschines which Charmadas really used. 

Cicero thus distinctly points to Charmadas as the source of 
this thought; Sextus may be interpreted to favor either Char- 
madas or Critolaus; Philodemus is slightly in favor of Critolaus, 
but not enough so to outweigh the definite statement of Cicero. 
The possibility must be considered, however, that both Critolaus 
and Charmadas may have used the same line of thought and the 
same illustrations; Quintilian implies that the kernel of the 
thought “rhetoricen . . . observationem quandam esse, non 
artem’”’ is as old as Lysias, hence it would be common property 
by the time of Critolaus and Charmadas. Moreover the rapid 
rise of Demades from a common seaman to a position of political 
leadership was well enough known to pass into a proverb. At 
least this is the most probable origin of the expression, “A76 Kw7ns 
éxt Bnua, From the oar to the rostrum, found in Apostolius III, 
65. I am inclined to believe, however, that whatever may have 
been the ultimate origin of the idea, the form in which it appears 
is due to its use in an attack on rhetoric published by Charmadas. 
It is quite likely that this was in dialogue form, and that the chief 
persons were Critolaus, Diogenes, and Carneades, the master of 
Charmadas. Such a debate would be highly natural, suggested 
perhaps by their association on the embassy to Rome. More- 
over the assumption of such a dialogue removes any difficulty 
that may be felt in regard to the references to Critolaus in our 
Greek authorities, which have given some color to the claim 
that some work of his was the source of this argument. Cicero 
refers to Charmadas, because he was known to be the author of 
the dialogue, and the ideas might be assumed to be his also; 
Sextus and Philodemus mention Critolaus because these argu- 


374 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


ments had been put into his mouth in the dialogue. It is possible, 
also, that the quotations from Diogenes in the second book of 
Philodemus come from the same work of Charmadas. The two 
detailed accounts of the embassy are in Cicero, De Oratore II, 
37, 155 ff., and Gellius VI, 14. Both deal with the rhetorical 
aspect of the embassy, and discuss the three styles as exemplified 
by the three philosophers. Cicero and Gellius evidently draw 
from a common source, and a source which contained technical 
discussions of style. This fits in with our hypothesis that 
Charmadas used the philosophical embassy as a setting for the 
presentation and discussion of current views on rhetoric. 

After proceeding to a certain length in his discussion of this 
question Quintilian attempts to confine himself to the most general 
forms of argument; the opponents of rhetoric, he says, are many, 
Critolaus, Athenodorus, Agnon, Epicurus; their arguments are 
numerous, but reducible to a few general lines of thought. At 
the head of these arguments he puts the question of the sub- 
ject matter, or “raw material” of rhetoric. In brief this is that 
every art has some definite material with which it works; the 
carpenter works in wood, the smith in metals; the orator, say 
the critics, has nothing which is peculiarly his own; if he dis- 
cusses medicine he is invading the field already occupied by 
another art; if he discusses either politics or ethics he is met by 
the claim that these belong to the philosopher. Quiuntilian dis- 
misses the subject with a curt “quod esse falswm in sequentibus 
probabo,” a promise which he fulfills in the twenty first chapter. 
He follows Cicero in holding that the field of rhetoric is all 
subjects which at any time arise for discussion; not that the 
orator is by virtue of his rhetorical training acquainted with the 
subject matter of all arts, but that if he has to speak about music, 
for example, he can acquire the necessary facts from the musician, 
and present them in a form which will be more persuasive than 
the crude statements of the unlettered musician. So much for 
the main outlines of the thought. It is, as Quintilian says, a 
commonplace of the rhetorical controversy; we have seen it 
in Cicero from whom Quintilian derives his main arguments ; 
it appears in Philodemus, quoted from an unnamed philosopher ; 
II, 123, fr. VI. H&élwoe zacav emorynpnvy exew idiav vAnv, wepi Hv 
atpeperar, THv d€ pyTopiKny ereparo deKviev ovdeuiay Exovoav VAyv. 
In Sextus it is given one of those queer twists which were the 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 375 


result of the intensity of controversy. From the very beginning 
of the discussion there had been a division of opinion as to 
whether words or things were the subject matter of rhetoric. 
But the rise of the sceptical philosophy made it more advan- 
tageous for the purposes of polemic to assume that rhetoric dealt 
with words. Accordingly Sextus disregards all phases of the 
question except this. He assumes that rhetoric deals with 
words (48), and on the lines of the sceptical philosophy he proves 
that as words are composed of syllables, and syllables do not 
exist, therefore words do not exist, and as there can be no art 
of a nonentity, there is no art of rhetoric. (Adv. Grammaticos, 
Persp it.) 

In the collection of arguments which Philodemus has assembled 
in his second book there is one which appears also in Sextus, 
and which is confused by Quintilian with another similar but 
different argument. In Philodemus it runs as follows: “In 
other arts the rules are true, in rhetoric they are false’; to 
which Philodemus replies that the same phenomenon occurs in 
medicine or music which every one grants are arts; and even in 
philosophy men sometimes enunciate principles which prove to 
be false, but that does not vitiate all philosophy.® This passage 
may be illustrated by comparison with Sextus 10-12, who gives 
the reason why rhetoric cannot be an art if its rules are false. 
He adopts the Stoic definition of art; Maca tot reyvyn cvornpa 
€oTw €k KaTadjWewv ovyyeyvpvacpevwv Kal emt TéAOS EvxpyaTov TH Biw 
AauBavovtwy tHv avahopav (10). The second part of this definition, 
that an art is useful, agrees in thought with Plato’s requirements 
given in the Gorgias 501B, and was recognized as fundamental 
Academic doctrine (Sextus 43). Sextus continues to argue that 
rhetoric is not an art because it is not a ovornpa éx xatadrjewr, 
for there can be no perception of the faise, but the rules of 
rhetoric are false—wevdn d€ éote Ta AEyoueva THS pyTopiKHs elvar 
Gewpypata. He then gives examples of the false rules ovrw 
Taparectéov Tovs dikacTas Kal dpynv KiwyTéov 7 €AEov Kal poixw 
ovvnyopntéov 7) icpoovAw. 

The other argument occurs in several places in Philodemus, 


°T, 22, col. III = Suppl. 12, 18; ‘‘xard rds G\dNas réxvas Ta Oewphuara eorw 
aAnOR, Yevdq O€ Kara Thy pyropixyjy.” Acad TovTo ovdé THY Pirocodlay TEx vnY pyTéov 
ovdé THY laTpikny KTH. 


Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


all in fragments of the second book. The sense of them all is 
as follows: rhetoric aims at times to deceive; but the rhetorician 
is just as liable to be deceived as he is to deceive. A single 
example will illustrate: II, 90 fr. XVIII, 1. 12 és odxi rév éfFs 
erifavpaces Toodvtov irdpxovta; “eizep amat@ow ot pyTopes, Kal adTot 
orm arataow, aratOvrat, arep 00d GAAws yiveTat ev Opace ovo aKovoel’ 
ci yap GAAw cupBEBnxev 7 ardry, Kal abtos dmatarau + od padAov ToLvuy 
For the answer to this argument cf. II, 


> 2 3k , Noy Ee > ov , ‘ 
GAN’ @ cvpPEBnKev TO Opav, OVX EVEKA TOVTOV KAL 


arat@ow 7) aratovrat ’. 
88,. ie) XVE 
airs bparat + TO 8€ avo Kal eri THs axons ovd dpa da Tov Tos PyTOpas 
dmarav Kai aitol dratévra. So much for the argument in Philo- 
demus; it does not occur in Sextus, and appears in Quintilian 
in combination with the preceding argument. This ‘“contamina- 
tion” will now require our attention. 

Quintilian starts by quoting the first argument that no art rests 
on false principles, because there can be no “perception” of 


what is false. Section 18 is a close parallel to Sextus Io. 


Quintilian II, 17, 18 Sextus 10 


altera est calumnia nullam Ilaca rotvuy téxvn ovoTnpa eat 


artem falsis adsentiri opinioni- 
bus, quia constitui sine percep- 
tione’® non possit, quae semper 
vera sit; rhetoricen adsentiri 
falsis, non esse igitur artem. 


> / c “B! « \ 3 

ex katadnWewv.... 7 O€ PyTopLK? OK 
” 4 > 4 c 

€oTL ovoTnMa eK KaTarAnWewv, ws 
TapacTycomev + ovK apa eoTW W 
pyTopLKy- 
Katadnwes, yevdy d€ €ot. Ta eyoueva 


Gv yap Wevdar od eal 
Tov yap Wevowv ovK Etat 


THS pyTopiKys <ivar Oewpypara. 


The proper sequence to this argument in Quintilian is a discus- 
sion of the Oewpyyara or opiniones of rhetoric to prove that they 
are true. This would be parallel to the claims of Sextus that 
such principles as ovrtws dpynv xwytéov (11) are false. But 
Quintilian replaces this by the reply to the argument which we 
found in Philodemus that rhetoric deceives and is therefore 
deceived. His general reply is (19) ego rhetoricen nonnumquam 
dicere falsa pro veris confitebor, sed non ideo in falsa quoque 


“ Perceptio is the translation of xardé\nyis as is shown by Quintilian’s 
translation of this definition later in the chapter, section 41; artem con- 
stare ex perceptionibus consentientibus et coexercitatis ad finem utilem 
vitae; and by Cicero’s equation in De Fin. III, 5, 18. Rerum autem cog- 
nitionem quae vel comprehensiones vel perceptiones, vel si haec verba aut 
minus placent aut minus intelliguntur, xarad#pes appellemus licet. 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 377 


esse opinione concedam, quia longe diverstuim est ipsi quid videri 
et ut alii videatur efficere. This he supports by several examples: 
Hannibal tricked Fabius into believing that the Carthaginians 
were retreating, but he did not deceive himself; Theopompus 
put on his wife’s clothing and passed his keepers without being 
detected; Cicero befogged the jury in the Cluentius case, but 
he saw the truth clearly enough himself. These are all answers 
to the claim that rhetoric is not an art because it deceives; but 
by a confusion arising from the use of falsa to represent the 
Greek words Wevdn and drarévrac Quintilian has been led to com- 
bine what were originally two separate arguments. 


Quintilian cites and discusses several arguments which are’ 


found in the De Oratore. The first two are closely related; (30) 
nullam esse artem contrariam sibi, rhetoricen esse contrariam 
sibi; nullam artem destruere quod effecerit accidere hoc rhetorices 
operi. Both of these are alluded to in passing by Antonius in 
rejecting the claim that rhetoric is an art (II, 7, 30). The argu- 
ment is utilized by Sextus (68) who reduces it to the question 
whether rhetoric can decide between the true and the false; (71) 
axoAovbel TO Kal emiotypyv aitiv GAnOov Te Kai Wevddv yiverOar, Tod 
Tpaypatos py ovtws €xovtos. In none of these three discussions 
is there any indication of the ultimate source of the argument. 

Quintilian next quotes from Cicero the rest of section 30 of 
the second book of the De Oratore in which Antonius adds to 
the statements previously quoted the claim that an art must 
depend on knowledge, whereas rhetoric is concerned wholly with 
opinion. This claim is treated at greater length by Cicero in 
the first book (I, 20, 92). Artem vero negabat esse ullam, nisi 
quae cognitis penitusque perspectis et in unum exitum spec- 
tantibus, et numquam fallentibus rebus contineretur. Haec 
autem omnia quae tractarentur ab oratoribus dubia esse et incerta 
etc. This is marked as a quotation from Charmadas. So far as 
I know, no trace of this line of thought occurs in Philodemus 
or Sextus. 

Beginning at section 22 Quintilian discusses two charges which 
are closely related: 1) that rhetoric has no “goal” as all true 
arts have, and 2) that if it has a goal it seldom reaches it, whereas 
an art should reach it always or in the majority of cases. We 
have parallels to this in Philodemus in two small fragments of 
the second book. 


\N 


w 
~ 
co 


Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


Il, 105,:fr. XI, 1, 4 UWdons tpiBijs cat raparnpyoews ere b€ dokyjoews 
€otw Ti TEAos, eh 0 TavTa TA MEepy TVVEvE OpeEireL, THS SE PHTOpLKHs ovdEV 
éot. TéAos”. This corresponds to the first argument in Quintilian. 
The other fragment in Philodemus is evidently the second in a 
series of quotations unfavorable to rhetoric, and inasmuch as it 
is the counterpart of the second argument in Quintilian, it seems 
reasonable to suppose that it belongs after the fragment just 
quoted. It runs as follows: II, 125, fr. IX, Torys 6€ THs 
TpwoTyns amodeLews mepukvias BAererar TO Suppaptnpevov Hon Kal THS 
exdexopevns, Kab’ Hv éd€yeTo raoa Téxvy TvyXdvew det TOD TéAOUS 7) KATA TO 
tAelatov, 7 S€ pyTopiKy pydeTepov yevous peTexelv KTA. 

The same thought occurs in Sextus 13—15; in none of the 
three places however is there any hint of the source from which 
they come. The two illustrations which Quintilian uses to prove 
that rhetoric deserves to be called an art are drawn from navi- 
gation and medicine; the captain and physician as well as the 
orator have a definite end in view; whether they attain or not 
may depend on circumstances beyond their control, but they 
nevertheless work “artistically” when they do all in their power 
to attain the desired end. These illustrations occur again in 
Philodemus, I, 19—Suppl. 11, 1 “Eviore yap oixoddpos oixiav 
katapbeipea kat Cwypados tivaka Kat vadv Tepitpere KUBepvyTysS Kat iatpos 
avOpwrov aroKteivea pefoduxOs ktrX. The close parallelism of examples 
suggests that they are replies to the same argument. Now the 
passage just preceding this in Philodemus is too fragmentary 
to prove anything. It is worth noting, however, that one of the 
few distinct words, xatopOotv, (I, 18, 28) might very well cor- 
respond to Quintilian’s praestabit (hune finem) (23). I am 
inclined to believe therefore that this passage in Philodemus 


follows II, 125, and that the three fragments thus put together. 


form a complete parallel to Quintilian. 

Sudhaus thought that Critolaus was the author of the argu- 
ment which is answered in I, 19. He inferred this from Sextus 
10—12. But Sextus refers there to Plato as well as Critolaus 
as author of the argument which he discusses; and furthermore 
it is very doubtful if the thought of Sextus 10-12 is a proper 
prelude to the answer given in Philodemus I, 19. Sextus argues 
that rhetoric is not a system of “perceptions,” that its principles 
are false and deceptive. That does not seem to fit Philodemus’ 
answer so well as the following paragraph in Sextus: 13-15 


ee es ee 


PSS 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 379 


kal pay eel Taca Téxvn ATO EoTHKOS ExEL TO TEAOS Kal TayLoV, ws piAogO- 
dia Kai ypappatixy, 7) Tod ws TO TOAD exopevov, KaBdrEp iaTpLKy TE Kal 
KuBepyytixy, dejoe. Kal Tiv pyTopLKyV, ElTEp ETTL TEXVN, TO ETEPOV TOUTWV 
erayyeAr\coOar. If it be assumed that Philodemus is answering 
this argument, as I think I have shown above is reasonably 
probable, then there is no indication of the source, for Sextus 
gives no hint of the anthorship of this particular form of the 
argument. 

Philodemus and Sextus supply us with the next argument. 
It is stated like so many others in the form of a syllogism. 
States do not expel those who practice arts; some states, notably 
Sparta and Crete, have banished rhetoricians, therefore rhetoric 
is not an art. This appears in Philodemus four times, in each 
case in a short and incomplete fragment.** But it is given at 
considerable length in Sextus (20-26) who reveals the course 
of the controversy. The argument originated with Critolaus, 
and was adopted by the academics Clitomachus and Charmadas. 
The rhetoricians countered by attacking the major premise; 
cities do banish artists says Philodemus. “The Spartans put 
the ban on perfumers and dyers; and physicians, musicians and 
even philosophers have been considered harmful enough to be 
banished.” Sextus attempts to answer this, but has difficulty 
in making a plausible defence. It is not philosophy as a whole, 
he says, which suffers indignity, but only certain sects; for 
example the Epicureans are banished because they teach 
hedonism. But when he acknowledges that Socrates was the 
victim of popular judgment about the value of “arts,” he 
practically destroys his own case. 

Sextus in section 51 advances the argument which is based on 
the definition of rhetoric as émorypy Tod e& Aeyev, a definition 
formulated by Xenocrates and adopted by the Stoics (Sextus 6). 
Every artist can speak well, he says, about his own art, but this 
speaking does not make him a rhetorician. The argument is an 
old one; it is hinted at in the Gorgias, but not fully developed. 
Just what was the history of the argument till the time of Philo- 
demus we can only conjecture, for none of our authors mention 


soeeerotr Vs FT 16; fr. Des) ES Og. te. Ih: “EE “100, fr. EEE" ae Geeues 
also in Quintilian II, 16, 4 in connection with the discussion of the useful- 
ness of rhetoric, but without reference to its bearing on the controversy 
over Téxv7. 


380 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D., 


a source. At some time, however, the principle has been illus- 
trated by the speech of Philo the architect on the arsenal at 
Athens. We know from several sources that this was erected 
during the administration of Lycurgus and that the speech 
referred to was in the matter of accounting for the work. Philo- 
demus seizes this instance of a man apparently without rhetorical 
training who was capable of making a creditable speech on his 
special line of work, and uses it to back his claim that rhetorical 
training is not necessary for effective speaking.’ Philodemus 
is quoting from an author whom he refers to as ovros airds, 
who had introduced into his work this speech of Philo. Who 
this was we are not told, but as he states in another passage 
(I, 346, Col. XLVIII, 1) that Demetrius of Phalerum discussed 
a Philo in his treatise on rhetoric, it may be that he was the first 
to use Philo as an illustration. The turn which Philodemus 
gives to the argument must, however, be due to some philosopher 
unfriendly to rhetoric, and it can hardly be original with Philo- 
demus, because the use of Philo the architect as an argument 
against the necessity of a knowledge of rhetoric was known to 
Cicero.‘* Now it is hardly to be maintained that Cicero was 
answering Philodemus; the case is rather that Philo had become 
a stock illustration to use when attacking the claims of rhetoric. 

The definition of rhetoric as the power of persuasion which 
Plato ascribes to Gorgias contained an ambiguity which gave 
an opportunity for reply. Other things, the opponents said, 
persuade,—wealth, beauty, reputation. Hence rhetoric cannot 
be an art, for an art has an exclusive field (v. Philodemus I, 
19, 12 = Suppl. 11, 7). Phryne whose beauty. did more toa 
her case than the pleading of Hyperides, became a stock illustra- 
tion for this phase of the controversy. She is cited by Philo- 
demus, Sextus and Quintilian,‘* who give the natural and normal 


“TIT, 192, 15. Ov why adda Tods pryjropas ef KaTopOoby év Tots pyropiKots Eheyev, 7 
mpos Tov OvaexTiKdy, Neyer, o0 Toy ~EXeyXOV Troloduev, 6 O° pn Mpocdencecbar THs 
pnropixjs, 7) mpds Tods &dous memadevpévous, “UaAdov dé Kal Texvelras bws, ot TA 
Tovavra Kal wrelw ToUTwY év Tots ldlors PuAdTTETAar mavOdvovaty, ws Kal Pi\wva Tov 
apxXiTeEKTOva TeEpi THS TKEVOOHKHS OUTOS adTos Elanyayev OnuNnyopovrTa, 

® De Orat. I, 14, 62; Neque enim si Philonem illum architectum, qui 
Atheniensibus armamentarium fecit constat perdiserte populo rationem 
operis sui reddidisse, existimandum est architecti potius artificio disertum 
quam oratoris fuisse. 

“ Philod. I, 20, 4; Quint. II, 15, 6-9; Sextus, 4. 


The Rhetorica of Philodemus. 381 


answer that it is not persuasion but persuasion by speech which 
is the end of rhetoric. In the absence of any indication of origin, 
we must regard Phryne with Philo as part of the common store 
of illustrations. 

Philodemus quotes several arguments which appear in none 
of our other authors. They are of little interest or importance; 
none of them can be traced to a source, and they can best be 
classed with that mass of arguments which Quintilian assigns 
without distinction to Critolaus, Athenodorus and the other 
philosophic opponents of rhetoric.1® 

Both Quintilian and Philodemus devote sections of their dis- 
cussion to proofs that rhetoric is an art. In a way this division 
of the discussion into refutation and confirmation is artificial, 
for most of the arguments in favor of rhetoric have been 
exhausted in replying to the attacks of its enemies. In fact it 
is hardly conceivable that any rhetorician was ever concerned 
to prove that he possessed an art until the philosophers began 
to question his position. Consequently all the pleas for rhetoric 
are colored more or less by the criticisms of it. For example 
Quintilian undertakes to show that rhetoric conforms to all 
definitions of art. It has “method,” it is based on a body of 
perceptions applied to the attainment of a useful end, it involves 
investigation and practice. But all these definitions were formu- 
lated for controversial purposes if not for the express purpose 
of excluding rhetoric. It has been shown how Sextus employed 
the Stoic definition to refute the claims of rhetoric, and the same 
argument has undoubtedly been used before. 

Philodemus carries the debate one step further than Quintilian, 
for while the latter aims to prove that rhetoric is an art, Philo- 
demus is equally interested in refuting arguments pro and con; 
for his position is that all theories of rhetoric whether advanced 
by rhetorician or philosopher are false except those proposed by 
his group in the Epicurean sect. There is one line of thought 
which perhaps deserves more than cursory attention, as its 
course can be traced with some distinctness. That is the relation 
of rhetoric to dialectic. Aristotle had said that rhetoric was the 
counterpart of dialectic, and made the grouping, ovAdoywpos év- 
Ovipnpa, eraywyn mapaderypa. The same idea underlies Zeno’s 


euihey are’ Suppl. 12/65. 13S, gg 2usi4. 107 Wb ga te. Vie 


382 Harry M. Hubbell, Ph.D. 


example; closing his fist and then opening it he said the first 
was dialectic, the second, rhetoric (Sextus, 7; Orator, 32, 113, 
and elsewhere). Quintilian, however, seems to have been the 
first to revert to the argument from the similarity of the two 
subjects, that if dialectic is an art, as all acknowledge, then 
rhetoric must be also. 

In following the course of the debate as exhibited in our 
principal authorities, we have come upon a few names such as 
Critolaus, Charmadas, who can be safely designated as the 
originators of certain phases of the argument. More arguments 
are assigned to less definite sources, Academics, Stoics, Peri- 
patetics, without any designation of persons. And still a larger 
share while common to several of our authors are entirely 
anonymous. The reason is as I have intimated before, that the 
chief points in the controversy were developed very early, and 
became commonplaces of literary discussion everywhere; the 
only room for originality was in varying the expression and 
illustration of the arguments, and as we have seen in the case 
of Phryne and Philo, these, too, soon became stereotyped. 


TRANSACTIONS OF 


erenHk CONNECTICUT ACADEMY 


OF ARTSo AND SCrlewCcES 


VOLUME 23 | SEPTEMBER 1920 [ PAGES 383-416 


The Principle of General 
Relativity and Einstein’s 
Theory of Gravitation 


BY 


EETGH PAGE, Phe: 


Assistant Professor in Physics in Yale University. 


NEW HAVEN, CONNECTICUT 
PUBLISHED BY THE 
CONNECTICUT ACADEMY OF ARTS AND SCIENCES 
AND TO BE OBTAINED ALSO FROM THE 
YALE UNIVERSITY PRESS 


Us 


ee ¥ RDA ae 


y 
1 = ; i 
e a4: Bo os 208 15) 
y i. } J : ay : fabs Saas ‘4 a : 
Srp See ANT Sis a ae canal he 

Gi Ri be ROR DS” hy Gat SABMSE 
= 2 a rel 4 cm Le ‘. * I fv 

<< e ae ‘ee ee! ey See : _ oe 

- - a! ie pF a vs - we Feat ; oa 

4 


Te Tee’ «1 


“ae (54; ie bak HUE 435% 


to nat tale rt. 


Atay Rie tor Bee. 
. Vi4 


THE PRINCIPLE OF GENERAL RELATIVITY 
AND 


EINSTEIN’S THEORY OF GRAVITATION 


Einstein’s theory of gravitation has presented difficulties to 
many readers on account of the complicated analysis involved. 
The object of this paper is to present the mathematical part of the 
theory in as simple a form as possible, and at the same time to 
translate Einstein’s tensor analysis into a notation more closely 
resembling the vector analysis of Gibbs, in the hope of making 
this very remarkable theory more readily intelligible to the 
average physicist. 


(a) THE PRINCIPLE OF GENERAL RELATIVITY. 


A moving element is defined as a point—whether in a material 
body or at the head of a light signal—which can be continuously 
identified. Every physical measurement, when analyzed, is found 
to consist of observations of coincidences of two or more moving 
elements. Thus the measurement of temperature by means of 
the mercury thermometer consists in noting a coincidence between 
the top of the mercury column and a certain division on the 
scale beside it, or, more strictly, a coincidence between the light 
rays coming to the observer’s eye from these two points.. A 
physical phenomenon, then, may be defined as a coincidence in 
time and space of two or more moving elements. In order to 
specify the place and time of a physical phenomenon, it is neces- 
sary to have a set of reference elements each of which locates 
a point in space, and with each of which is associated a device 
for assigning numerical values to the times of occurrence of 
successive events at that point. A reference system is an as- 
semblage of such reference points filling all space for all time. 
A physical phenomenon is specified relative to a given reference 
system by the identification of the reference point at which it 
happened, and the time at that point of the occurrence. 

The determination of a physical law involves the measurement 
of space and time intervals between a number of phenomena. 
Consequently a device is needed for measuring the distance be- 


386 Leigh Page, 


tween two, points in a reference system, and synchronizing time 
at these points. In order to be of value in comparing coinci- 
dences, this device must be subject to the following conditions, 
though otherwise its nature is quite arbitrary: 

(a) Two points which are in synchronism with a third are 
also in synchronism with each other. 

(b) The distance between two points is independent of the 
time at which it is measured. 

Evidently the motion of a moving element may be described 
relative to an infinite number of reference systems, which are 
themselves in various states of motion relative to one another. 
However, these systems are not, in general, of the same signifi- 
cance. For let A, B and C be three systems from which the 
motion of the moving element P may be observed. Suppose it 
is found that the motion of P relative to A is conditioned by 
that of B, but is independent of that of C. In such case the 
motion of P is said to be related to B, which is known as a related 
reference system. C, on the other hand, is.an unrelated or ideal 
reference system. Thus for the motion of a shot, the gun from 
which it is fired constitutes a related reference system. The 
velocity of a sound wave is determined, not by the motion of the 
source, but by the characteristics of the medium through which it 
passes. Hence in this case, the source determines an ideal 
reference system, while the medium is a related. one. 

In the case of propagation of a disturbance through empty 
space it has been recognized for a long time that the source does 
not constitute a related reference system. The Michelson-Morley 
experiment has shown the same to be true of the “ether.”” Hence 
it may be inferred that 

For the motion of an effect which travels through empty space, 
such as a light wave or one of the moving elements which form 
an electromagnetic or a gravitational field, there is no related 
reference system. 

If this statement be granted, the question arises as to how the 
law connecting a group of related physical phenomena may differ 
when determined in terms of the space and time intervals of 
different reference systems. Evidently, 

If a law governing physical phenomena which are conditioned 
solely by those effects which travel through empty space, is deter- 


—————— 


SS ———- = 


ll el dC 


maw 


+ Ralre, 


= TT pT a Rr Oe ye Lae, Arey, | VHF 


General Relativity and Einstein’s Theory. 387 


mined from observations made in two different reference systems, 
the form of this law and the values of the constants entering into 
it can differ in the two cases only in so far as the geometry and the 
devices for measuring time and distance together with the units of 
these quantities may differ in the two systems. Their relative 
motion can in no way affect either the form of the law or the 
values of the constants involved. ‘This is the principle of general 
relativity. 

Consider two reference systemis which have the same geometry, 
devices of the same character for measuring time and distance, 
and interchangeable units of these quantities. Such systems may 
be called reciprocal. If follows that 

A law governing physical phenomena which are conditioned 
solely by those effects which travel through empty space, has the 
same form and its constants have the same values for two 
mutually reciprocal systems. ‘This is the restricted principle of 
relativity. 

Consider two reciprocal Euclidean systems S and 5S’, such that 
all points of S’ have the same constant velocity v relative to S. 
Let light travel in straight lines in S with constant speed c. Then 
the restricted principle of relativity requires that light shall 
travel in straight lines in S’ with the same constant speed c. 
Moreover, the laws governing physical phenomena must have the 
same form in terms of the space and time intervals of S” as in 
terms of those of S. Investigation shows that the coordinates 
and time in S” are related to the corresponding quantities in S by 
the familiar Lorentz-Einstein transformations. 

As systems S and S” are entirely equivalent, and the only 
velocity of either which has any significance is that relative to 
the other or to a third system, the question arises as to whether 
acceleration is not also relative. Let S and S” be two reciprocal 
Euclidean systems in which light travels in straight lines with 
the constant speed c. Then investigation shows the only possible 
state of motion of S” relative to S to be that in which every point 
of S” moves with the same constant velocity relative to S. A 
system accelerated relative to S would have a non-Euclidean 
geometry if the velocity of light were constant relative to it. 
Hence the objectional terms “constant velocity system”? and “un- 
accelerated system” may be avoided by describing the systems 


388 Leigh Page, 


involved in the original relativity principle as Euclidean systems in 
which light travels in straight lines with constant speed c.1 

The simplest type of reference system is that in which light 
travels with the same speed ¢ at all points, all times, and in all 
directions. A more general type is that in which the speed C 
of light is the same in all directions at any one point and time 
but differs from point to point and from time to time. Subse- 
quent consideration will be limited to systems of this degree of 
generality, since no experiment has yet indicated the need of 
referring observations to a still more generalized type of system. 

Let S and S” be two systems of the degree of generality just 
defined. Unprimed letters will refer to quantities in S and 
primed letters to those in S”. Let O’ and P’ be two nearby points 
fixed in S$’. Let O be the position of O’ and P that of P’ ims 
at the time ¢. At this time let a light signal be despatched from 
O toward P’. Let P, be the position of P’ and t + dt, the time 
in S when the signal reaches this point. At the instant of arrival 
of the signal at P, let a return signal be despatched toward O’. 
Let O’ be at O, in S when the return signal reaches it, and denote 
the time of this event in S by t-+ dt,-+dt,. Since the speed of 
light at any point in S” is not a function of direction, the times 
dt,’ and dt,’ taken by the light signal to pass from O’ to P’ and 
back again will be equal. 

Denote by dr, and dr,’ the distances OP and O’P’. With O 
as origin choose rectangular axes* XYZ in S so that the X axis 
is parallel to the velocity v of O’ relative to S. Denote the co- 
ordinates of P by dx,, dy,, dz, Then those of P, will be 
dx, -+ vdt,, dy,, dz,, and those of O, will be v (dt, + dt,), 0, o. 


Therefore 


Oe Or or od" 
dt(= tat v al dt, a doe, dy _ 
and 
at ot oa or’ at 
at =(5, +o aa -) dt, ee he oy ay. — ae mL 


*This paragraph answers a criticism of the relativity principle put 
forward by Sir Joseph Larmor. Proc. Nat. Acad. Sci. 4, 334, 1918. 

? Over a small region it is always possible to use rectangular codrdinates, 
even if space is curved, provided no singular points are present, 


| 


General Relativity and Einstein’s Theory. 389 


Equating these two expressions, 


‘Od Oe’ ORI eye” foe dt’ \ dt, — dt, 
ae tit a Bit 3g = (57+ pele 
and adding them 
Pay Os de’ \ dt tdt, 
at, =(F4 2g) oe. (2) 
Now 
C*dt,? = (dx, + vdt 1)? + dy,’ + d2,’, 
C?dt,? = (dx, — vdt,)? + dy? + dz,?, 
whence, solving for di, and dt,, 
2u 
dt, — dt,= ma Me, (3) 
a a= AI ar, (4) 


where v, is the component of wv perpendicular to dr,. Substitut- 


ing in (1) and equating to zero the coefficients of dx,, dy, and 
dz,, it follows that 


The time interval di’ between two points as measured in S’, 
when the space and time intervals between these two points are 
dx, dy, dz and dt in S, is epider’ 


ie 
dt’ =o dnt yD +o e+ = dt, 
since t’ depends only on +, y, 2, and ¢. 
Substituting for the differential coefficients the values found 
above, 


C’ oe" v 
Cue x — Geet cat |. (<) 
From (2) and (4) it follows that 
af = Cy 
Cd 


3, V Saas adr,, 


sae: 


390 Leigh Page, 


where v, is the component of v perpendicular to dr, Giving dr, 
the values dx,, dy, and dz,, and choosing axes in S’ parallel 
respectively to those in S, it follows that 

dx’ Cdr’ 

oni Gare 
dy’ wy Cer y? 
by C oF Vv ye 


Os ee Cor’ / v" 

By, or eae 
all the remaining partial derivetives with respect to +, y and g 
vanishing. Moreover 


Ox’ Ox’ 
Or ” Ox 
fap ag lee 
i, OE ok 
oy’ 
Cpa 


Therefore the space intervals dx’, dy’ and dz’ between two 
» ay 

points as measured in S’, are given in terms of space and time 

intervals in S by the expressions 


an Coe , | 

ax — Cc OE [ @ — vat | ) (6) 
paCr Or ey Tass? 

OS c.g: te ee e 
RSC cn Paes 

aaa ae a 2 (8) 


Hence, from (5), (6), (7) and (8) 
dr? SC? dit = fe | (-&)| (dr°—C? dt’), (9) 


and conversely 


= sarees C dt\, ae 1 12 gla 
ei 0b = [ (ara) (7-73) | (d@r°—C™ at”), (10) 


where 


FOR ie TE ae 


General Relativity and E1nstein’s Theory. 391 


If S and S’ are reciprocal Euclidean systems characterized by 
a constant light velocity c, such that every point in S’ has the 
same constant velocity v relative to S, 


CS0E6) 
Sa. 
ot’ Diez 
Vt! Wee? 


and integration of equations (5), (6), (7) and (8) gives the 
Lorentz-Einstein transformations of the restricted principle of 


relativity. 
Put l=t1eb, 
=a 
nS 
14! oa 
—_— - = V I--a> 
k=nh. 


Then if S” is a Euclidean system characterized by the constant 
light velocity c, (9) becomes 
dr’? + dl’? — h? (dr?+ n?di*) 
—h? dr? +- kdl’, CFF) 
in which greater symmetry has been obtained by replacing the 


variable t by 7. Put 
ds? = dr’? + dl’. 


As S’ is a Euclidean system points may be located in it by 
means of rectangular codrdinates +’, y’, e’. Therefore, if x’, y’, 
z’ and I’ are interpreted as the rectangular codrdinates of a point 
in a four dimensional representative space, every moving element 
describes a path through this space, of which ds is an element 
of arc. Minkowski was the first to use this representation, and 
the path of the moving element is called by him its world-line. 
It has been noted that a physical phenomenon is a coincidence in 
space and time of two or more moving elements. Such a coinci- 
dence is represented by the intersection of the world-lines of the 
moving elements concerned. Therefore all physical measure- 
ments are confined to the observation of such intersections, and 
all representations which make these intersections occur in the 
right order are equally valid in describing the results of experi- 
mental science. 


392 Leigh Page, 


If a particle is at rest in the system S’ under discussion its 
world-line ‘is a straight line parallel to the L’ axis. Therefore 
ds =i, 
and the linear element ds is a measure of the time elapsed relative 

to the system 5S” in which the particle is at rest. 

If a particle has a constant velocity v’ relative to S’, its world- 
line is a straight line inclined to the L’ axis by an angle whose 
tangent is 

= . 
t 

Let S be a Euclidean system reciprocal to S’.. Thert (11) be- 

comes 

ds? = dr? + di? =dr - dF; (12) 

and S can differ from 5S’ only in the orientation of the axes. 
Hence every point in S must have a constant velocity relative to 
S’, bearing out the statement previously made that if S and S’ 
are two reciprocal Euclidean systems characterized by the light 
velocity c, all points in one of these systems must have the same 
constant velocity relative to the other. 

In particular consider the case where the Y and Y’ axes and 
the Z and Z’ axes coincide, and the X axis inclines toward the 
L’ axis so as to make an angle a with the X’ axis, where 


tan == 
c 
=--1£. 
Then 
ee 
<7 
ae et ee 
= z 
aah pcere (13) 
y=), 
= 2, 


which are the Lorentz-Einstein transformations for the case 
where the relative motion of the two systems is in the X X’ 
direction. 

It is of interest to inquire what systems are possible in which 
h and k are functions of x, y and zg but not of J. For simplicity, 
consideration will be confined to motion in a straight line, i. e. 


—- 


Oe 


ZF il CE TE Oe IT TO ae PE 


General Relativity and Einstein’s Theory. 393 


to the X L plane. Let S denote the system under investigation. 
If the transformations between S and a Euclidean system S’ with 
constant light speed are sought, (11) takes the form 


ds? = dx’? + dl’? = h*dx? + kdl. (14) 

Without loss of generality, it is possible to put 

dx’ = pdx + nqdl, 

dl’ =—q dx + npdl. (15) 

h? = p+ @, 

be = 0 PP ae). 
Making use of the fact that h,and k are not functions of /, and 

that dx’ and dl’ must be exact differentials, it follows that 


Then 


fe ax 
LAL aay on 
p qi é COS: 
(16) 
{4 
2 om eats 
g=—e a Naini 


where 4 and a are constants, and the square of the linear element 
becomes 


2 ax 
ee Se ee 2 2772 
oe (dx? + n*dl’) . (eq) 


nm 


These values of p and q define the only type of system for 
which h and k are not functions of J, other than the group of 
Euclidean systems reciprocal to S’ which have already been dis- 


‘cussed. It will be shown now that if a is positive the system S 


defined by (15) and (16) is accelerated in the negative X 
direction relative to S’. Consequently a point at rest in S’, or in 
a system reciprocal to S’, appears to be accelerated in the positive 
X direction when its motion is referred to the reference frame 

ofS: 
For (2), 2 
al} x’ p a’ 


394 Leigh Page, 


Hence, to an observer in S, the velocity of a point in S” is 
given by ° 


v=—icn tan — 
a 
ct ct 
a a ( 
e —e 
= C —____ 18 
ct ct’ Ce 
a a 
e +e 
and its acceleration by 
n n 1 
=< °"_— ma>— tan’ — 
i ( pee we ayes ‘| 
EVE 8 
z a a 
4a (Cs 
: —e 
VE ie oC aM 
“A She MaMa dx ct ct 
a a ih 34 xk Pee 
eé +é e +e 
C v ame Ok 
=—Cli-—-— —, C—. I 
fc (1— Flt alg. (19) 


In a similar manner it may be shown that the acceleration of 

a point in S, relative to system 5S”, is given by 

! ONG 

fen-y(r—"2)", (20) 

where y is a positive constant. . 
The expression (19) gives the acceleration which bodies at 
rest in S”, or in a system reciprocal to S’, appear to have relative 
to an observer in S. This apparent acceleration is due to the 


fact that system S is itself accelerated relative to S’, and conse- 


quently an observer fixed in S finds that bodies at rest in S” are 
accelerated in the opposite direction when referred to his refer- 
ence frame. The observer, not realizing that this apparent ac- 
celeration is due to his own motion, may attribute it to a field 
of force. Such a field of force is known as a geometric field. 
Now, the world line of a particle at rest in S’, or in a system 
reciprocal to S”, is a straight line in the X Y Z L four dimensional 
space. As a straight line is the shortest distance between two 
points, it is defined by 
bf as =o. (21) 


" _ 
er . EE 
a 


General Relativity and Einstein's Theory. 395 


Therefore the motion of a body at rest in S’, or in a system 
reciprocal to S’, is described relative to any possible reference 
system by (21), provided ds is expressed in terms of the para- 
meters 4, y, 2, / defining the particular reference system relative 
to which observations are being conducted. Thus the motion 
of a body at rest in S’, or in a system reciprocal to S’, is described 
relative to the accelerated system S by 


af V Geer a =o. (22) 
where _ 2 fa 
— A, a n 
72 
and Ve ax 
a 7 
k=Ae 


That this expression gives for the acceleration the same value 
(19) already obtained is easily verified. For put 


H=VE ERO, 


where Wax 
ae: 
Then 
S/H adl=o, (23) 
and the corresponding Lagrangian equation is 
2(OH\ dH 
a9 =! eam 


Differentiating, it is easily found that 
dU _k 26 pp age 5") 


ae ax Py mr Cy (24) 


\ 


Substituting for h and ek their values, 


aU ya i ,Zf an 
de an EE ie ec 
which leads to (19), when it is remembered that 
_dU 
f= ae 7 
p aes uv 
Ue 


396 Leigh Page, 


Consider for a moment a body moving in the geometric field 
defined by (24). If the body’s velocity is small compared to 
that of light, the second term of this expression will be negligible 
compared to the first. Moreover, h and k will never differ much 
from unity except in the case of extremely strong fields. There- 
fore the quantity k plays much the part of the potential in ordi- 
nary gravitational theory. As the derivative of makes itself 
felt in the case of greater relative velocities, it is natural to con- 
sider both h and k as generalized potentials determining the 
nature of the geometric field. 


(b) THE EQUIVALENCE HYPOTHESIS. 


The equivalence hypothesis states that a permanent gravitational 
field is identical with a geometric field produced by the acceler- 
ation of the observer’s reference frame relative to the bodies 
observed. 

For example, consider an observer stationed out in space far 
away from any gravitational field. Let there be present in his 
neighborhood a number of bodies, which, according to Newton’s 
first law of motion, are either at rest or moving in straight lines 
with constant velocities. Now let the observer be given a constant 
acceleration of 32 ft/sec?. Not realizing that he is accelerated, 
he will refer observations to a reference system carried along 
with him, and conclude that all bodies observed. have an acceler- 
ation of 32 ft/sec? in the direction opposite to his true (?) 
acceleration. So far as the motion of material particles is con- 
cerned, this geometric field is exactly equivalent to the gravi- 
tational field near the earth’s surface. Now Einstein extends 
this equivalence to all phenomena, and postulates that a gravi- 
tational field is identical in all respects with a geometric field. 
For instance, a ray of light would follow a curved path in a 
geometric field of the type described. Hence it must be deflected 
by a gravitational field. 

The above crude example is only very approximate, as no 
account has been taken of differences in the geometry, standards 
of length and time, etc. of the two mutually accelerated systems 
under comparison. A more exact investigation brings to light 
many difficulties. 


> 


General Relativity and Einstein's Theory. 397 


The problem to be solved consists in finding a geometric field 
which (a) conforms to Newton’s law of gravitation as a first 
approximation, and (b) has the properties of a Euclidean system 
with constant light velocity c at great distances from gravitating 
matter. As the properties of a permanent gravitational field do 
not change with the time, the values of 4 and k in the expression 
for the linear element in terms of the coordinates and time of the 
equivalent geometric field must not involve /. But it has been 
shown that if 4 and k are not functions of J, the only possible 
form which the linear element can take, (other than (12) ), is that 
given by (17). The acceleration of a body moving through 
this geometric field is given by (19). If the velocity of light 
is constant, this expression gives a constant acceleration (for any 
given value of the velocity). Consequently this geometric field 
may simulate a uniform gravitational field in so far as the motion 
through it of material bodies is concerned. 

The consideration of radial fields, however, brings to light 
serious difficulties. For (19) approximates the acceleration in a 
radial gravitational field only if the velocity of light varies 
inversely with the square of the radius vector. If such were the 
case, however, the properties of the geometric field would fail 
to approach those of a Euclidean system with constant light 
velocity c at great distances from gravitating matter. Hence, 
under the limitations imposed by the nature of the X Y Z L 
space, there exists no geometric field which approximates a 
radial gravitational field. 

The question arises as to how the nature of the four dimensional 
representative space may be modified so as to impose less stringent 
restraints. Consider for a moment the X L plane. The form of 
the linear element defined by (14) shows that the families of 
curves 


+ = const, 

b= const, 
must be orthogonal. Now the number of mutually orthogonal 
families of curves on a plane is strictly limited. If the plane, 
however, may be replaced by a curved surface in three dimen- 
sional space, much less restraint is imposed upon the character of 
orthogonal families of curves on the surface. Such consider- 
ations suggest that the desired geometric field may be found, 


398 Leigh Page, 


provided the straight or homoloidal® representative space here- 
tofore employed is replaced by a cutved four dimensional surface 
in homoloidal space of higher dimensions. 

It has already been noted that physical measurements are con- 


fined to the observation of intersections of world-lines. All that 


experimental science can tell is the order in which these inter- 
sections occur. There is no a priori reason that the results of 
experiment can be more conveniently represented by plotting 
world-lines in a homoloidal four dimensional space than in a 
curved or warped space. Therefore when Einstein found that 
the equivalence hypothesis could not be applied to a radial gravi- 
tational field so long as Minkowski’s homoloidal space was re- 
tained, he was entirely justified in replacing this straight repre- 
sentative space by a four dimensional space which is warped in 
homoloidal space of higher dimensions. 

On a curved surface it is not generally possible to use rectangu- 
lar coordinates, or any other system of codrdinates, such as polar 
coordinates, which are derivable from rectangular codrdinatés 
by a mathematical transformation. Therefore the linear element 
ds must be given in terms of a set of curvilinear coordinates 7,, 
%y, V3, ¥, by an expression of the form 


TR ORS | 

where the g’s may be functions of the +’s. For example, in 
locating points on a two dimensional spherical surface of radius 
FR, such as that of the earth, it is necessary to use codrdinates 
such as the co-latitude @ and longitude ¢. In terms of these the 
linear element of the spherical surface has the form 

ds? = R*d & + R?* sin*6 d ¢°, 
for which case it appears that 

dt, = 00, dt, =a, 

fu=F’, So = R? sin? 8, S12 =) 50s aes 

Now transformation (11) between a system S’ characterized 

by the constant light speed c and any other system S must hold 
no matter whether the four dimensional representative space is 


>The term homoloidal as applied to space of four or more dimensions 
has the same significance as the word Euclidean applied to three dimen- 
sional space. 


dt= ie dw dx, Si Se t, J= 1, 2,3, 4, (25) , 


General Relativity and Einstein’s Theory. 399 


homoloidal or not. Therefore, just as in the case of Minkowski’s 
homoloidal representative space, we put 
ds? = dr’? + dl”. 
Comparing with (25), it is seen that if +,’ is identified with /’, 
ar = 2g a, aS P BOG aS oR 
Therefore, if the four dimensional representative space is 
curved, system S” is no longer Euclidean, and points in it cannot 
be located by means of a rectangular coordinate system. More- 
over, the world-line of a particle at rest in S”’ is no longer a 
straight line, through, since the coefficient of dl’ is not a function 
of x,', x,', x,', it is a geodesic, or curve of minimum length, like 
the arc of a great circle on a sphere. 
If it is desired to compare a system S with S’, (11) gives 
ds? = dr’? + dl’* = h*dr? + kdi?, (26) 
where, if x, is identified with J, 


Vida? = Rs yj@n ee, cn 3 2. oe (23) 
Sas =F, S14 = Sra = Sy = 9. 


and the three dimensional geometry of S, like that of S’, is non- 
Euclidean. 

Now, just as the world-line of a freely moving particle in 
Minkowski’s homoloidal representative space is a straight line, 
Einstein assumes that a freely moving particle describes a geodesic 
in the warped four dimensional space which he employs. The 
acceleration of such a particle in the geometric field equivalent to 
a radial gravitational field is due to the fact that observations 
are being referred to a system S in which the / curves are not 
geodesics. Relative to this system the world-line of a freely 
moving particle is given by 


pe 
ass : eet 
fv ii ia Gr 6 fa 22 a (28) 


where the g’s, like h and k in the simple case treated at the end 
of section (a), may be considered as generalized potentials de- 
termining the nature of the geometric field. . 

For reasons already stated, the g’s must not be functions of /. 
Even so, they cannot be determined unless further restricting 
conditions are introduced. These necessary limitations on their 


400 Leigh Page, 


values are evidently expressible by means of a set of equations 
containing ‘the g’s and their derivatives. Now these equations 
have a two-fold significance. In the first place, the g’s determine 
the nature of the curved four dimensional representative surface 
in homoloidal space of higher dimensions. Therefore the equa- 
tions relating them specify certain absolute properties of this four 
dimensional space which are independent of the particular refer- 
ence frame to which physical observations may be referred. 

Viewed from another aspect, the g’s have a rather different 
significance. It has already beeti pointed out that they are the 
potentials of the gravitational field which they specify. Conse- 
quently the differential relations connecting them may be inter- 
preted as the law of gravitation of the field. Now, the principle 
of general relativity requires that this law shall differ when 
referred to different reference systems only in so far as the 
geometries and devices for measuring time and space together 
with their units may differ in these systems. But the metrical 
properties of a system are defined by the values of the g’s. Hence 
the law of gravitation must have the same form in terms of the 
g’s and «’s of one system S as it has in terms of the g’s and #’s 
of any other system S”. 

Furthermore, the law of gravitation must reduce to Laplace’s 
equation as a first approximation. Reference to (24) shows that 
this equation has the form 


Ok WR, OR 
Ox? aig Oy’ TA — 


which suggests that as a first approximation 


where r is the radius vector and m is a constant proportional to 


the mass of the attracting body. The small quantity = is evi- 


dently a measure of the divergence of the geometry of the four 
dimensional representative space in the neighborhood of an 
attracting mass from the homoloidal geometry of this space in a 
region where no matter is present. 


(c) THE LAW OF GRAVITATION. 


In seeking the law of gravitation, the following requirements ~ 


serve as guide. First, the law must be a differential relation 


General Relativity and Einstein’s Theory. 401 


between the g’s which satisfies the principle of general relativity, 
i. e. it must have the same form in terms of the g’s and «’s of one 
system as in terms of the g’s and #’s of any other system. 
Secondly, it must reduce to Laplace’s equation as a first approxi- 
mation. As this equation is linear in the second derivatives of the 
potential, it is to be expected that the exact law will contain no 
derivatives higher than the second, and will be linear in the 
latter. Moreover, as the exact law specifies the values of more 
than one potential, the desired relations must be more than one 
in number. Hence they may be expressed by equating to zero a 
vector, or perhaps a dyadic. In this way four, or sixteen, scalar 
equations will be obtained. The methods of building up an equa- 
tion, or set of equations, of this character, which satisfy the re- 
quirements of the principle of general relativity, will now be 
considered. 

Consider two systems S and S’. Choose orthogonal coordi- 
nates in each system. The codrdinates 4,, +,, x, and time 4+, 
in S will be related to the corresponding quantities in S” by four 
equations of the form 


—— (x,', a's X, ? x,'). 


Differentiating, 
- 
2 2 oXq Se!) 
ia ai ax, : (29) 
pe 
and conversely 
2 Pe 
(iia Migs 
ae B ox ad (30) 
B 
Ox" Dx 


in the determinant formed 


where ~~ is equal to tl i f 
3x , 18 equal to the minor of + 7 
by giving B and 1 the values I, 2, 3, 4 respectively, divided by this 
determinant. 
Moreover 3 oxy PS) 


Ia = 3 Ox g xv” (31) 
and 
deat auld 
ee eo (32) 
p [By ee 


Let k,, k,, k,, k, be unit vectors in S parallel respectively to 
the 7,, %, #3, *, axes. As these axes may be curvilinear, k, etc. 


/ 
402 Leigh Page, 


may change in direction from point to point, but the meaning of 
these quantities at any one point is perfectly definite. While 
Gibbs’ vector methods will be followed, it is necessary to make 
a slight change in the notation generally used in order to avoid 
ambiguity in the expression for the scalar product of a vector 
with a polyadic of order higher than the second. For if 
apy ~ “apy *akeky 
a By 

the usual notation provides no way of expressing the dot product 
of a vector with the middle vectors of this triadic. Consequently 
we shall adopt the convention that the dot product is always be- 
tween those vectors whose suffices are the same. Thus the dot 
product of a vector P with the middle vectors in the triadic H is 
represented by 


a Fay’ 


With this convention the order in which vectors and polyadics 
appear is immaterial; in fact the dot itself is superfluous, for 
whenever the same suffix appears twice dot multiplication is 
indicated. However, the dot will be retained as a reminder of 
the analogy of the notation employed with Gibbs’ three dimen- 
sional analysis. Obviously the suffices employed in dot multi- 
plication are dummies, 1. e. 

Pe Map, 
and 

ae ey 
mean exactly the same thing. Hence we are at liberty to replace 
a repeated suffix by any other letter which does not appear as a 
suffix inthe same term. An additional advantage of the proposed 
notation lies in the fact that the number of letters in the suffix 
shows at a glance whether the quantity under consideration is a 
vector, dyadic, triadic, etc. 

Now consider the dyadics 


= > oa: f 
Be an SER a (33) 
Ve OS Oxy 


eS vB ax gy ae (34) 


General Relativity and Einstein’s Theory. 403 
Since Ix, OX,’ ‘ 
2 a) A =I or Oaccording as »=v or p+, 
a. cue XxX 4 
it follows that 
Be "9", 
a 
where I’ is the idemfactor 
V=23:r'k’, 
a a 
Also 
1 i Bt 
Now let 


ao: = a ae 


be a vector element (four dimensional) in S. This is a general- 
ized type of vector, and does not necessarily represent a directed 
element of length. For instance, in polar codrdinates in a plane 


dp. = k. adr + kg ao. 


Let dp” be the same vector as measured by an observer in 
S’. Then it follows from (33) and (34) that 


dp” = B : ap, (35) 
dp = Be * dpe (36) 


Consequently it is seen that Dp and Di are transformation 


dyadics which enable us to determine the measured value of a 
vector in one system from its value in another system. 


Consider the vector differential operator, 
9 


DS sees 
B B B OX g 
Evidently 
Dae ae (37) 


It is seen that the transformation used here is the reverse of 
that employed in the case of dp*. The transformation of (35) 
and (36) is known as contravariant, and dp* is called a contra- 
variant vector. On the other hand, the transformation defined 
by (37) and (38) is covariant, and the vector Dg is a covariant 


404 Leigh Page, 

vector. Contravariant vectors and polyadics will be provided 
with superior suffices, while covariant ones will be distinguished 
by inferior suffices. A dyadic, like Dp: which is partly contra- 


variant and partly covariant, will have suffices of both types. 
More generally, if 


a 1a. 
P =D, Fs (39) 
Pp” is a contravariant vector, and conversely 


D’: P° = bed D! 2 Fh) 
a Qa 


pe 
= l P BS 
=p" (40) 
Similarly, if 
put Leis , 
eee sie (41) 
Pe is a covariant vector, and 
Recs eee , 
Pao (42) 
If the transformation of a dyadic is considered, it is clear that 
qf Di en Telia (43) 
is a contravariant dyadic, while 
AES ra Rey, 
Gig Pao Ga. (44) 


is covariant. Now, the form of Laplace’s equation suggests that 
the exact law of gravitation may be expressed by equating to zero 
a covariant dyadic involving the g’s and their first and second 
derivatives, the equation being linear in so far as the second 
derivatives are concerned. Our problem, then, is to build up a 
dyadic satisfying these requirements. 

Now the square of the linear element ds is 


. i=, Sa ax et (45) 
Therefore, if the self conjugate dyadic G.8 is defined by 
G.8 = Zfap a kg, 
it follows that 
Bile Ga Pip dp, (46) 


General Relativity and Einstein's Theory. 405 


As ds? is an invariant, the right hand member of this equation 
is also an invariant. But it is evident that if the scalar product 
of two dyadics is an invariant, and one of these dyadics is con- 
travariant, the other must’ be covariant. Hence as 


eae 


is contravariant, G, B must be covariant. 


ap 


If 
7 ‘ 
is the reciprocal of G B then 
VB i 
G G.8 =I, 
and 
of, a 
GY Gigs 


showing that G” is a contravariant dyadic. 

In ordinary vector analysis a covariant dyadic may be con- 
structed from a covariant vector P by forming the open product 
VP. When the g’s are functions of the coordinates, however, 
a dyadic so consreteied would not ke covariant. For it follows 
from (40) that 


Dies) iB iy DY: D,P.+ Di ie (47) 


€ 


the presence of the second derivative on the right hand side 
destroying the covariance of the dyadic. The value of the term 
involving the second derivative may be found by constructing 
and combining triadics as follows: 

As 


B 
G' y= Di, DY, : Gig 


a if iP 02 8B ,) 'Y iB. 
Bay G,,:(D! Dy, +p! py +b‘ D' ied Dy Gg (48) 


in which some of the dummy suffices have been replaced by other 
letters, and use has been made of the fact that 


G Bas G, B 
iene G.8 is self conjugate. If similar expressions for 
D * Gin 


406 Leigh Page, 
and DG Hie 


are written down, and if (48) is subtracted from the sum of 
these two, it is found that 


{ ! ' / Ul eek ! ne ¢ pial 5 iB ra 
(DG) 7 DG Da a a oe 
us 


ae a \:p7 p” p& 
+4(D, Gg, +DgG,,—D, Gg): D), D', D (49) 


Forming the dot product of ee. D’, and (49) it follows that 


Ap ‘ ’ ' ' ' a ' ’ 5 (ST: "e 
iG’? (DG), 7, 8 Gas DG) Be 
TE oy = : pi pF 


Christoffel’s triadic is defined by 


—— Ap . ! ! ! 4 es ' ! 
Pept =a7G (DG yt D, Gy D') G',,): 
Hence 
I /€ rae /OL ! 
aa DS Bor DP yt snes B.D ee 
or ( ! t aS ve OL 1 . p 
[HY, pj Pains ion P.+D% De: {a8,«}*P.. (50) 


Subtracting this equation from (47), 
' re Nia (fe Tash be 10. Bky LOT he 
DP us el Po DD, (Der, (28:8) eee 
showing that the dyadic on the left hand side is covariant. 
Therefore the expression 


D,— {a pj 1h (52) 
is a covariant differential operator when applied to a vector wt 
Now consider the triadic 
ae We Spates oye bes a 
Q,(D,P, | Vs Ps Ps) + Lean OED a {ov, T} Q,.) 
os DP ies) (BY; pi t BOs (OV, ih Q. Py 
As it is made up of sums of products of covariant vectors and 


dyadics, it is covariant. Hence the differential operator 


D,— lve} Ts — tov. th Tr (53) 


T 


produces a covariant triadic when applied to the dyad FiQe But 


a dyadic is merely the sum of a number of dyads. Hence this 
differential operator forms a covariant triadic when it acts on any 
covariant dyadic. 


—- ES 


--. -: 2. ee 


el rR yet Fa OR ee oe 


General Relativity and Einstein's Theory. 407 


Starting with the vector P,, we may form a covariant dyadic 
by applying (52), and by operating on this dyadic with (53) 
a covariant triadic is obtained. This triadic, which we shall 
denote by A, will contain first and second derivatives, and be 
linear in the latter. Evidently 


» Ce. o 
Aig (Dy, [Hae , Lae a ee r. ‘) (Di ers ut ")P, 
— TT? { ine ati lige caries l. 

=D nae P Sone | ie | TV- Ts Ba | Ty €5 sD ES 


‘ : ie cate. ie ie 
+ {py, pj" op, €} P_+ioM 7) {Ty €} Pi Dior €) P. 


(3 


Now interchange of p and y will have no effect on the first 
five terms. Therefore 
Bag Buys = (17): (res e} — Lom 7h > [rvs e} + 

D, {oy} —D,low,¢})- P,, 

and 
eG fov, tT} {rp,€} — lop, Th Ty, €} me Or e} — Dior, e} (54) 
is a tetradic which is partly covariant and partly contravariant, 
as indicated by the suffices. Obviously, if the four dimensional 
representative space is homoloidal, the g’s defining the line ele- 
ment may all have the constant value unity. Therefore, as every 
term in this polyadic contains a derivative of one of the g’s, it 
will reduce to zero in this case. Conversely, it may be shown that 
if this polyadic vanishes, the representative space is homoloidal. 
Therefore the equation obtained by equating B to zero cannot 
represent the law of gravitation. 

A less stringent equation is obtained by equating to zero the 
dyadic formed from B by putting a dot between k_ and k 


This equation, 1. e. 
Bia == Lov, Tl: inp, vi) — flop, T}°{ TV; yh Devs vi =D; ‘op, v} 
=i (55 
is taken by Einstein for the law of gravitation. Evidently it 
satisfies all the necessary conditions, and it is probably the simplest 
equation which does. 
Equation (55) may be somewhat simplified. For 


r 
Ea © (D, Gyr D, a Dy G,,) 


1k PD 
=3G 7 D,G,) 


408 Leigh Page, 


ra ae D, s 
. ro) 
=D_log Vg 
where g is the determinant of G,. Therefore 
Bie ‘ov, th (rp, vy} Dy {omy} — [om 7}*D log¥g+D" ,logv gs 
=0 (56) 


This equation may be interpreted either as defining the char- 
acter of the curved four dimensional representative surface in 
homoloidal space of higher dimensions, or as the law of gravi- 
tation. It is of interest to follow its significance a little further 
from the first aspect. Let the rectangular codrdinates w,... 
w, of five dimensional homoloidal space be so chosen that w, is 
perpendicular to this surface at a given point, and that w, . ... W, 
have the directions of the lines of curvature at this point. Then 
if k, ... k, are the principal curvatures, 

2w, = k,w,? + kw,” + kw, + k,w,? 
in the neighborhood of the given point, which has been chosen as 
origin. If this relation is used to eliminate w,, the linear element 


; S 2 
as =— dw? 
Z Z 


becomes 

ds? = (1+ k, 2w,?) dw +...-+ 2k, k.w,w.dw,dw,... (57) 

Now consider the scalar 

G Be Be: 

. po 

As it is an invariant it vanishes when calculated in terms of 
the ¢’s defined by (57) as well as when expressed in terms of h 
and k. Its value at the origin is particularly easy to determine, 
for there : 

: 65 =C. =i, DG. =9; 
Te V. 
and consequently we have 
SGT eg 1 yt, 9. og D’, log¥ g =o. 


Substituting for the polyadics their values 
Rik, + Roky + Rgky + kyky + Rak, + Ryky = 0. (58) 
The left hand member of this equation measures the curvature 
of the four dimensional representative surface in much the same 


ee a ee ee 


a a a Te a ee nl 


General Relativity and Einstein's Theory. 409 


way that the total or Gaussian curvature k,k, specifies that of a 
two dimensional surface. If the four dimensional space had been 
homoloidal, each of the terms in (58) would have vanished, and 
the nature of the representative space would have been too re- 
stricted to be capable of representing a radial gravitational field. 

Before converting (56) into a set of scalar relations between 
the spaces derivatives of the g’s, it must be recalled that the warp 
we have given to space makes it impossible to represent even 
ordinary three dimensional space in the neighborhood of a gravi- 
tating body by rectangular coordinates (or by any codrdinates, 
such as polar coordinates, which are reducible to the rectangular 
form). We may, however, use rectangular codrdinates for an 
approximate mapping out of that portion of space which is not 
too close to the center of attraction. Consequently if +,, +, 43 
in the linear element 


—— - 2 v2 - 2 - 2 
ds” = 24,41? + Sood HQ" + a,d%57 + SdH, 
are identified with the rectangular coordinates +, y, z, we are 


justified in computing the g’s to the first order of approximation 
only. The coordinate +, represents the time /, and evidently 


Take the origin at the center of attraction in the radial field 


under discussion, and put 
r 


V Jee et 


9 oV 
J 


> 


d and y being functions of 

only, and very small compared to unity at all points not too near 
the center of attraction. As the coordinate system assumed 
holds only approximately, terms in (56) involving squares or 
products of the first derivatives of A and v must be neglected as 
compared with terms which are linear in the first or second 
derivatives of these quantities. Hence the first and third terms 
of this equation may be omitted, leaving 


Bike my! lov,v} + D* logY g =o. (59) 
Substituting their values oe the symbols, it is found that 
Bi r' 
Be LY Shy at me | =o, (60) 


410 Leigh Page, 


where the primes denote differentiation with respect to 7, and 
similar expressions in y and ¢ for B,, and B,;. Also 


' 


By=v"p25=0. (61) 


All other components of Ne vanish. As (60) is true for all 
values of x, these four equations reduce to three independent 
relations, to wit: 

rN : 
yet: go te — op 
V+ y' 


7 


AU + vis 


ery ? 
y’ 
y't2—-=0, 
> 


from which it follows that \’ =-—v’, and as A and v both vanish 
at infinity, A=-—v. 
Integrating the last of the three equations above, 
a MW 
pee 
‘if ‘ 
where the constant of integration m, as will appear later, is the 
mass of the attracting body (i.e. the sun) in astronomical units 
divided by the square of the velocity of light. 
The linear element, then, is given by 


W mM 
2 — 2— 


de=e ” (dx+aextdt)te "al? (62) 
to the first order of approximation. 


b) 


(d) PHENOMENA IN A RADIAL FIELD. 


The equivalence hypothesis requires that the motion of a par- 
ticle in a gravitational field shall be given by 


8 fds =0,j 
where ds may be expressed in polar codrdinates by 
ds? = h? (dr? + r°dé? + r?sin?6 do?) + kdl?. 
Hence. i 


HV + her? + h?r6? + h2r?sin26g? (63) 
where eee , a0 Ve ope 
ap = ee 


it follows that 
of Hdl = a. 


General Relativity and Einstein's Theory. 41 


The corresponding Lagrangian equations are 


ad (oH OH 
lage dens? 
d a sey) 
al\ 06 ely ; 
d (OH Opell 
gal op 


Evidently every term in the last equation will contain either 
¢@ or ¢ Hence if the codrdinate system is so oriented that ¢ is 
initially zero, @ will be zero, and therefore the motion will be 
confined to the r @ plane. Forming the derivatives involved in 
the first two equations, and solving for 7 and 6, 


as Bs hh c RB! A’ a /h 
ae ea PSS che fai tee ie oy rap 
r—ré Re +7 ( Z 7) + r’?é Bo 


Substituting the values of h and k contained in (62), and 
changing the independent variable from / to ¢ by means of the 
relation : 


l=ict, 
it is found that 
para (rag) EN Gra rh), (64) 
64+ b= 4rd. (65) 


Multiplying (64) by + and (65) by 726, adding, and integrating, 
4 (7 + Fn 6°) = ( — ‘) —2m'c (5 — ) aa gn f- stadia ar, 
4 1G € 


7 a r 


if the velocity of the particle is zero when r equals a. Taking 
the first term on the right as an approximation to value of the 
left hand member, substituting in the integrand of the last term 
on the right, and integrating, 
a si W ged 9 A 6 ve 
ot 2 2 92) — 25 fore Sen Cy earns 3 a 
L(+ 7° 6) = me ¢ ‘) mc (2 oa + >) (66) 
Comparing this integral of energy with that obtained on the 
Newtonian theory, it is seen that mc? is the mass of the attracting 
body (the sun in the case of the solar system) in astronomical 
units, i. e. the unit of mass being taken as that mass which exerts 


412 . Leigh Page, 


unit force on a like mass at unit distance. The dimensions of m 
are evidently those of length, and a simple calculation gives the 
value of this constant for the sun as 1.47 kilometers. 

Integrating (65), it is found that Einstein’s theory eivenl in 
place of Kepler’s law of constant areas the relation 


rb=ep(1- 4"), (67) 


where / is the constant of integration. 
To find the equation of a planetary orbit, write (66) in the 
form 


i A alg@eu ‘(F—Z)- a eae z 
fe +, ey sega eh a amo "\ ee | 


Substituting the values of @ from (67) and writing wu for the 
reciprocal of 7, 


au * ! me m. m 2m m 
(“%) = —uUu (= or) +2 u(t— 2m) _ pitts) 


=—Awv+2Bu—-C . (68) 


where 
ee 
a2%(2—2"), 
Pp a 
2m a =) 
St char 
Put 
= oes EB AE. 
U=tu A? = oe 
Then 
GO SP = 
pa Oe ’ 


which gives, on integration 


zr BV — ACcos(V4A6+4+ 38) 
ro A ; 


Substituting for A, B and C their values, 


eit r+ 1—2© cos| a )e+8! 
Madeg ee h e 


? 


mM 


(69) 


General Relativity and Einstein’s Theory. 413 


This is the equation of an ellipse with eccentricity 


/ 2 

/ 2p 
A) VE Oe 
4 am?’ 


whose perihelion moves forward through the angle 


me I27m 


do = 627 = = A 
me ali —e*) 


(70) 


each revolution. The distance a is equal to the major axis of the 
elliptical orbit. 

The following table gives the discrepancies in ed between 
observation and theory, both for the Newtonian theory and 
Einstein’s theory, together with the probable error of the obser- 
vations. The units are seconds of arc per century. 


Newtonian Einstein Probable Error 
Mercury +8".24 —o".58 +-0”.29 
Venus — 0.06 — OI! Sep Org 
Earth * + 007 0.00 = 0.09 
Mars + 0.64 + 0.51 ee 0:23 


It is seen that Einstein’s theory not only removes the large 
discordance in the motion of Mercury’s perihelion, but does not 
introduce any new discrepancies in the case of the other planets. 
This is, of course, due to the relatively greater eccentricity of 
Mercury’s orbit. 

As the ratio of velocity of light C at any point in a gravitational 
field to its constant value c in a region free from gravitational 
effects, is equal to the ratio of k to h [compare (9) and (11)], 
the expression (62) for the line element shows that 


WM 


— 2D 


C— ae ‘ 
WM 
=e(7-27), (71) 


Consider a ray of light passing through the sun’s gravitational 
field, (Fig. 1) so as to come when nearest within a distance 
R of the center of the sun. 


414 Leigh Page, 


Big ck 
If n be measured normal to the ray, the deflection dD taking 


place in a distance ds is given by 
roc 


OD = 


C On 
2 2 90C ar 
Cron dn 


=—2 - cos 6286. 


Therefore the total deflection is 


(72) 


As m= 1.47 kilometers for the sun, a star seen close to the 
limb of the sun (J? = 697,000 km) should suffer an apparent 


displacement 
= yas 


Observations made at x eclipse of May 2oth, 1919, confirm 
this prediction of the theory, and even show that the deflection 
decreases with the inverse first power of the distance from the 


0 Ie alee er a ee 


General Relativity and Einstein’s Theory. 415 


center of the sun. It is interesting to note that the deflection 
(72) is double that which a material body shot through the sun’s 
field with a velocity close to that of light, should suffer according 
to Newton’s law. 
It is of interest in this connection to investigate the motion of 
a material particle which enters a radial gravitational field with 
a velocity comparable to that of light. In this case the term on 
the right hand side of (64) which involves the inverse cube of r 
is negligible compared to the remaining terms, and equations 
(64) and (65) give for the energy integral 
a S B (7 — 6”) oye 
a 


j/2 


4 


(73) 


where f is the ratio of the velocity v of the moving particle at 
infinity to that of light. This equation shows that if 8 = 1/ V3 
the velocity of the particle will be unchanged in magnitude by 
the gravitational field, and that when B exceeds this value, the 
field changes from an attractive field to a repulsive one. 

The orbit of a particle moving with the velocity of light is 


easily determined. For this case (73) reduces to 


i dr\* 2 ) An 2h ae “) 
(Gtr eae ee 


Eliminating 6 by means of (67), 

adu\* : m ii 

(5) = — x nt ge ps (74) 
which has- the same form as (68). Therefore the equation of 


the orbit is 
LT ml Ti 
er 6 ry 5 
2 gait ge CONE agS) (75) 
if terms in m? are neglected. If the particle comes closest to 
the center of attraction when 6 + 38 is zero and ¢ has the value R, 


ve 


ML 


WM we 
= 2 mt g(t? 72) cos (0-+3) 
or, in rectangular coordinates 
25 V0 HF (7 — 2)y epi 


The asymptotes to this curve are obtained by making x very 
large compared to y._ They are 


r 


m 
> = 


Mm 
£2 at(s— “y= 


416 Leigh Page, 


and are inclined to each other by an angle 
Mm 
f PR: 

Therefore the deflection of a material particle traveling with 
the velocity of light is the same as that of a light ray, as indeed 
the equivalence hypothesis requires. 

Consider a vibrating atom momentarily at rest near the surface 
of the sun, but free to move in the gravitational field. Let dt 
be its period of vibration. Then 

ae = — 0 (. =S a) ai™, 


Now, if d?’ is the period of this atom as measured in the system 
with geodesic time curves in which it is permanently at rest, 
9 r MM 
ds? = = Ot? = — (, —2 ) ae 
. 
If an atom of the same kind be in vibration at a greater distance 
from the sun (say at the surface of the earth), 


‘ F = A 
12° SC arr SS ir =o aes 
\ Le 
Therefore at, ait ) 
—=r—m(———}), 
at eae a 


ee | (76) 


Therefore an atom at the sun’s surface should vibrate more 
slowly than one at the surface of the earth, resulting in a shift 
of the solar lines toward the red. This shift, which amounts to 
less than one hundredth of an Angstrom unit in the visible spec- 
trum, has been sought by St. John, but not found. 

It should be noted that the two predictions which have been 
verified by observation are consequences of Einstein’s law of 
gravitation, whereas the shift of the Fraunhofer lines is deduced 
not so much from this law as from the theory on which it is 
based. While the assumptions from which the theory is built 
up are open to criticism—particularly the equivalence hypothesis 
—there can be little doubt that Einstein’s law represents a closer 
approximation to the facts than Newton’s does. 

The author wishes to express his thanks to Professor L. P. 
Eisenhart, of Princeton University, for his kindness in examining 
the differential geometry involved in this paper. 


= a? a 

~ ra) Ce ee. < ay “ Vor 
re. » » Me hte: , 

ar CF he 6 ere 


He tan net 2 


Q Connecticut Academy of Arts 
11 and Sciences, New Haven 

c9 Transactions 

Ve 23 


Physica! & 
Applied Sci. 


Seriais 


PLEASE DO NOT REMOVE 
CARDS OR SLIPS FROM THIS POCKET 
a ML 
UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO LIBRARY 


STORAGE 


Ane See ee a ees 28 ar err a en ee a eee o Sibtemetaliae oe okie ih OHO bt ak ade odek+' Pee acetate" ry Oe - o oe TET eR ~~ reise el ethene Ry Or WE pg 8 76. sees * >a — eae a" 
ve berm manre reer tary ie erik tree ath TTS i a ah mpi pecan Sw tm) a 2k Ae Shah ae Kein rh ie eae ee iat aes ave Noe ha) oot tal a a a Sa a ere rink been te aa 
— 3 ig - 7 ae 2 M : ’ - : . , = naa 


po ne OU I