Skip to main content

Full text of "The welfare effect of an additional child cannot be stated simply"

See other formats


„«/'^/VERsiTY  OP 


Digitized  by  the  Internet  Archive 

in  2011  with  funding  from 

University  of  Illinois  Urbana-Champaign 


http://www.archive.org/details/welfareeffectofa80simo 


Faculty  Working  Papers 


THE  I^LFARE  EFFECT  OF  AN  ADDITIONAL 
CHILD  CANNOT  BE  STATED  SIMPLY 


Julian  L.  Simon 

#80 


College  of  Commerce  and  Business  Administration 

University  of  Illinois  at  Urbana-Champaign 


FACULTY  WORKING  PAPERS 
College  of  Conmerce  and  Business  Administration 
University  of  Illinois  at  Urbana-Champaign 
January  4,  1973 


THE  WELFARE  EFFECT  OF  AN  ADDITIONAL 
CHILD  CANNOT  BE  STATED  SIMPLY 


Julian  L.  Simon 

j/80 


'M',:.        '.)     U-^n"  .■■4-    "^^i  • 


'i'^    ^.4^ 


.1  1 


Tlie  Welfare  Effect  of  an  Additional 

CKjLld  Cannot  Be  Stated  Simply 

Julian  L.  Simon 

r.  INTRDDUCTItDN 

Analyses  of  tfle  welfare  economics  of  population  growth  make  one  or 
more  of  the  following  assumptions:  Cl)  The  criterion  of  social  welfare  at 
a  point  in  time  is  per  capita  Cor  per  consimer)  income,  C2)  The  effect  of 
a  given  individual  upon  society  is  limited  to  his  own  impact  during  his  own 
lifetime.   C3)   There  are  no  externalities,  or — somewhat  more  weakly — all 
externalities  can  be  handled  by  payments  between  the  parents  and  the  community. 
(4)  Welfare  is  assessed  at  a  single  point  in  time,  or  at  the  same  rate 
along  a  growth  path>  or  without  distinguishing  between  the  various  periods 
of  his  life  cycle.  . 

It  is  the  contention  of  this  paper  that  the  magnitude  and  even  the 
direction  of  the  welfare  effect  of  an  added  child  depends  upon  each  of  these 
assumptions.  That  is,  changing  one  or  more  assumptions  to  equally  acceptable 
assumptions  often  shifts  the  welfare  effect  from  positive  to  negative  or  ^ne 
opposite.  Therefore,  tfie  aim  of  the  paper  is  to  map  out  the  welfare  effect 
of  additional  children  under  many  different  sets  of  these  assumptions. 

The  strategy  of  this  essay  is  to  disaggregate  the  problem  in  two 
directions.  The  first  disaggregation  la  over  time;  Instead  of  asking  for 
a  single  time-discounted  value  that  summarizes  whether  welfare  is  higher  or 
lower,  considering  all  of  the  future  together,  welfare  judgments  will  be 
discussed  for  a  few  separate  segments  of  the  future:  a)  the  added  individual's 


'.■"*-,..    ■  I', 


•'  i .     •- 


T-  2 


childhood;  bi  his  adulthood;  c)  after  the  individual's  death:  Summary 
measures  will  also  he  considered  critically. 

The  second  kind  of  disaggregation  is  bj;  groups ;  Instead  of  only 
a  single  criterion  of  welfare  for  the  community  as  a  whole,  judgments  will 
be  shown  about  al  the  individual's  welfare;  b)  the  welfare  of  his  parents; 
cl  the  welfare  of  all  other  persons  exclxiding  the  added  Individual;  and  d) 
some  overfall  judgments,  as  well. 

The  paper  begins  idLth  the  simplest  situation,  that  in  which  the 
Individual  has  no  negative  or  positive  effects  external  to  his  own  family, 
and  where  he  leaves  no  negative- or  positive  inheritance  of  any  kind  to 
future  generations.  Then  the  paper  moves  on  to  situations  where  there  are 
externalities  during  his  life,  and  then  to  situations  where  there  are 
continuing  external  effects  after  his  death.  These  situations  are  analyzed 
with  various  welfare  functions,  on  various  assumptions  about  the  directions 
of  the  externalities. 

The  results  of  the  analyses  are  summarized  in  Table  1,  and  the  text 
merely  explains  how  some  illustrative  results  in  Table  1  are  arrived  at. 
The  main  point  of  that  table — and  of  the  paper  as  a  whole— is  that  the  welfare 
effects  of  an  additional  person  are  very  mixed  and  are  largely  indeterminate; 
the  judgments  must  depend  upon  special  conditions,  assumptions,  and  choice 
of  welfare  functions.  The  aim  is  to  refute  all  analyses  which  purport  to 
arrive  at  firm  scientific  conclusions  about  the  welfare  effect  of  population 
growth  without  noting  the  sensitivity  of  those  conclusions  to  different 
welfare  functions  and  to  various  possible  economic  ramifications  of  additional 
people. 


.''"  I      6  ■ "  * 


'  :>  •    ■'      ■-i)-.- 


■p 

a 


*-» 

ID 

r-i 
05 

> 

-d 


r 

J 

< 

-(- 

-: 

M 

3 

ii 

-i 

a 

d 

n 

.S 

3 

^ 

t, 

0 

i 

j::  o 

(S 

^ 

3  0 

.^ 

H- 

r^-d 

3 

H   J 

D 
0 

-0 

z  a 

VI 

c  > 

( 

^T3 

-)» 

+ 

t; 

0- 

i 

a. 


v„.„..,....„..., 


5!      33    \| 


'.^  \!. 


list 


1 1 


S     I 


Ii  i,  Ji 

:!    .-1   « 

Is  Ii  n 


©o 


Q 


3     S     S 

si  4  51 
P    sS    »! 

3f  IjC  af 


1~ 


G>-  O 


I  1  1 


is 
i: 


i  11    ii 


ii  I 


ii 
II 


■I  i 


■e> 


S3    as 


-.1    i 


•I  '% 


11 


II  J  1 


H;  I  lis 


•-      •■      ♦ 


e 
0 
© 


■G  .  © 


-Q,- 


Q     .  ©   .00'    o 


I  !  :    ! 

a   ;    1      3 

t  t  t     fr 


i    i 


i    S 


31 
=•3    I 


>_^  i  i 


?    31  J 


•'  ii  ?  5 


1 15= 


ran 


1   35 
3  5! 


ii   il 


il  ;! 

3  9     G  i 


!      is 


I'    I 


s  t 
s  s 

\  ! 


i!  ii 


3  J     S3 

h  1^ 


I  I 
I  I 

!   9 

I ! 


II 


!»    la    i!   'I      .:    .1  :    . 


3     3 


iii 


J  ! 
I  } 

i   3 


13   ll 
!5   tj. 


3     3S    3 


33     3a     39 


r- 


If  I  11  11 


11 


IS 
nil] 

I  nil 


U  =  51 

il  i  .'1 

'{  u  «s 

jl   =3  [i 

h  Ii 


n 
1 1 

3   a 

3     i 


<  ! 

II 

3     35 

t    bl 

111 


-  3  - 


It.  NO  EXTEBNALITIES  DURING  OR  AFTKK  HIS  LITE. 

During  His  Childhood 

If  an  additional  first  child  In  a  family  has  no  effects  external  to 
the  family  during  its  childhood,  then  the  welfare  of  all  other  persona  in 
the  society  is  unaffected  by  his  hirth^ — by   assumption.  The  welfare  of  his 
parents  is  increased  By  the  occurrence  of  an  e^/ent  the  parents  desire. 
Beyond  this,  a  variety  of  welfare  judgments  is  possible  even  in  this  very 
simplest  of  cases,  the  judgments  depending  upon  one's  assumptions  and 
criteria.   Cli  To  start,  the  judgment  about  the  welfare  of  the  child  himself 
depends  upon  one's  assimiption  about  the  human  utility  function,  together  with 
the  facts  of  the  case.  According  to  the  assumption  made  by  Meade  (1955), 
Dasgupta  CX969) ,  Ehrlich  (1968),  and  others,  the  welfare  of  a  very  poor  child 
Is  negative  (column  1,  line  3  in  Table  1)  .  But  of  course  one  can  j;ist  as 
reasonably  assume  that  the  child's  welfare  is  neutral  or  positive  when  he 
is  very  young.   Clater,  after  he  is  old  enough  so  that  one  can  impute 
choice  to  him,  we  can  argue  about  his  welfare  In  a  different  fashion  as 
Will  be  discussed  later-)   (2)  By  the  test  of  pet  capita  income,  general" 
welfare  falls  during  this  childhood  period,  because  the  same  amount  of  product 
(assuming  no  increase  in  labor  by  the  parents)  is  divided  among  more 
people  (column  1,  line  11).   (3)  If  one  uses  as  a  welfare  criterion  the 
sum   of  individual  utilities,  general  welfare  rises  if  the  additional  child's 
utility  is  positive.  The  same  conclusion  can  be  reached  by  a  more  economical 
and  powerful  approach,  that  of  an  expanded  Pareto  optimum:  If  a  person 
whose  utility  is  positive  is  added  to  the  society,  and  if  none  of  the  existing 
people  thereby  have  their  positions  altered  for  the  worse,  this  must  represent 


-  4  - 


an  increase  in  the  society's  utility  function.  The  application  of  this 
criterion  is  unique  to  the  very  simple  case  under  discussionj  however;  even 
the  existence  of  brothers  or  sisters  makes  the  criterion  inapplicable  without 
further  assumptions,  as  we  shall  see. 

Now  for  a  side-examination  of  a  curious  but  not-unreasonable  im- 
plication in  this  simple  situation:  Parents  have  fev/er  children  than  would 

2 

maximize  the  total  utility  of  the  community.   The  reasoning  is  as  follows. 

The  parent  continues  to  have  children  until  he  is  at  his  own  margin,  indifferent 
between  the  birth  and  non-birth  of  another  child.  But  an  additional  child 
would  himself  enjoy  positive  utility,  by  assumption,  and  hence  his  birth 
would  add  his  own  utility  to  the  community's  utility,  with  no  net  utility 
change  to  his  parents . 

Despite  that  families  do  not  choose  to  have  enough  children  to  reach 
the  point  of  zero  net  marginal  social  utility,  without  complete  knowledge  of 
people's  welfare  functions  one  cannot  know  hew  far  from  the  margin  is  the 
lalsser  faire  outcome.  Hence,  it  seems  that  the  only  sensible  course  consis- 
tent with  the  above  conclusion  is  to  let  parents  set  their  own  limits  on 
the  number  of  children,  subject  to  consideration  of  external  costs  and 
conmjunity  values  (to  be  disctissed  immediately). 

With  the  above  analysis  in  hand,  one  ;aay  judge  the  welfare  effect 
of  contraceptive  knowledge  and  of  public  health  measures  to  reduce  infant 
jBortality.  Consider  contraception  first.  In  a  society  where  no  one  dies 
until  old  age,  the  ability  to  practice  contraception  increases  the  welfare 
of  parents  because  it  allows  them  to  achieve  the  number  of  children  that 
will  maximize  their  (parental)  utility.  That  is,  ability  to  contrac'ept 


"  5  - 


Increases  parents'  options,  a  Paretian  baste  wtelfare  gain.  If  lack  of 
contraceptive  knowledge  leads  to  more  children  than  th.e  couple  wants 
ex  ante,  this  ma^  increase  the  total  welfare  of  the  family,  and  hence  of 
the  community.  But  to  argue  that  people  should  he  hindered  from  practicing 
contraception  one  must  argue  that  ai  one  kjiows  the  parents'  and  children's 
utility  functions;  and  b)  by  overcoming  the  parents'  "selfishness"  one  forces 
them  to  a  tiigher  level  of  comiaunity  utility,   (This  is  implicitly  the  position 
of  the  Catholic  Church,  as  I  understand  it.) 

Now  consider  infant  mortality.  If  the  main  thrust  of  this  section 
is  correct  -  that  welfare  is  maximized  by  there  being  at  least  as  many 
children  as  parents  desire,  subject  to  community  values  and  external  costs  - 
and  if  parents  iare  able  to  control  fertility  accuratelyj  then  infant  mortality 
is  an  unmitigated  evil.  This  is  because  infant  mortality  must  result  in 
the  parents  often  having  more  or  leas  children  than  they  desire,  with  con- 
sequently lower  utility  for  the  parents.  Only  by  luck  will  the  nun^er  of 
children  they  desire  ex  ante  live  to  maturity.  And  even  if  parents  are  luclqr 
enough  to  end  up  ^-rtth  the  number  of  children  they'desirSj  they  will  have 
suffered  the  grief  of  children's  deaths  that  would  not  have  occurred  with  a 
zero  infant-mortality  regime. 

Furtliermore,  because  people  are  generally  risk-averse  when  it  cOmes 
to  the  number  of  children  and  to  the  number  of  sons  they  have,  the  error  will 
likely  be  on  the  side  of  achieving  more  children  than  were  desired  ex  ante, 
as  has  been  shown  vividly  by  Heer  and  Smith  (1968)  and  May  sxtA  Heer  (1969)  . 
Infant  mortality  might  increase  total  utility  by  offsetting  parental  selfishness, 
but  it  might  also  reduce  total  utility  by  carrying  the  process  beyond  the 


'.>.       ',r.'j  \,■^ 


^  6  ~ 


point  of  dljminishing  total  utility.  Whicfi  is  true  cannot  be  known  a   priori^ 

One  migh.t  fault  the  above  conclusion  because  tile  utility  function 
does  not  take  account  of  such,  important  disutilities  as  death  and  suffering. 
But  since  we  do  not  have  any  Intimate  or  metaphysical  knowledge  of  death 
itself,  the  only  disutilities  we  can  sensibly  attach  to  death  are  a)  the 
loss  of  the  utility  tliat  might  have  occurred  if  death  did  not  Intervene,  which 
is  not  an  operative  argument  here;  and  b)  the  suffering  of  survivors.  But 
more  children  might  out -weigh  the  latter.  For  example,  a  family  might  well 
choose  bearing  six  children  and  losing  one  to  accident,  in  preference  to 
being  limited  to  bearing  one  child.  Hence  the  omission  of  the  disutilitiea 
of  death  and  suffering  is  not  a  defect  of  the  analysis. 

The  above  inference  that  parents  have  too  few  children  to  maximize 
community  utility  applies  only  to  the  childhood  period  and  may  well  hold  only 
on  the  assumptions  that  (a)  there  are  no  other  children,  (b)  utility  is 
positive,  and  Cc)  there  are  no  externalities.  It  might,  however,  hold  even 
if  some  of  the  above  assumptions  were  loosened  in  some  ways. 

Kow  let  us  consider  the  cast  in  which  the  additional  child's  welfare 
Is  said  to  be  negative.  No  judgment  about  the  direction  of  the  community 
welfare  effect  can  then  be  made  without  assigning  cardinal  values  to  the 
individual  utilities  of  the  additional  child  and  his  parents,  which  trade 
off  if  the  child's  utility  is  said  to  be  negative  (column  1,  line  13) .  And 
If  one  considers  even  more  complex  welfare  functions,  containing  arguments 
of  per-capita  income  as  well  as  of  total  utility  or  total  population  size 
(e.g.,  Meade,  1955;  Votey,  1969),  they  will  a  fortiori  also  give  indeterminate 
results  in  the  absence  of  cardinal  specification  of  the  utility  function. 


■■  .!     r:\tlj  ».  .     J 


r.-n. 


. ;i<    '  -     :r:»->    v     .  '  Ij.      .11'       T'c    f'lv 


-  7  - 


Wh.en  a  second  or  subsequent  child  is  considered  to  be  the  additional 
child,  rather  than  the  first  child  in  the  family  Ccolumn  2),  things  get 
even  more  complicated,  because  consumption  by  existing  children  will  be 
reduced  by  the  existence  of  an  additional  child.  And  unlike  the  parents, 
there  is  no  reason  to  suppose  that  the  existing  children  desire  the 
additional  child.  Rence,  the  welfare  of  the  previous  children  is  decreased 
on  balance  by  an  additional  child  Cline  ^»   column  2} .  The  welfare  judgment 

then  must  depend  upon  the  assumption  one  makes  about  the  utility  function. 

4 
If  the  functions  of  all  the  children  are  assumed  positive  and  concave  , 

then  the  additional  child  increases  total  utility  of  the  children  in  the 
family  (line  6  column  2) .  If  the  functions  can  be  negative  and/or  have 
inflection  points,  the  welfare  effect  on  the  children  as  a  whole  depends 
on  the  economic  facts  and  the  specific  utility  functions,  and  is  indeter- 
minate without  cardinal  specifications  (line  7,  column  2) .  The  effect 
on  the  family  as  a  whole,  and  on  the  community,  must  also  be  indeterminate 
If  the  effect  on  the  children  is  indeterminate  Qine  12,  column  2) . 

Already  we  may  see  that  even  in  the  very  simplest  case,  and  examining 
only  a  single  point  in  time,  the  evaluation  is  thoroughly  messy  and  generally 
indeterminate. 

During  His  Adulthood 

During  the  additional  person's  adulthood  in  this  simple  world  of  no 
externalities,  his  welfare  effect  depends  upon  which  reference  group  is 
being  considered,  just  as  it  does  during  his  childhood.  A  peasant  in  sub- 
sistence agriculture  affects  his  brothers  and  sisters  negatively  by  reducing 


-  8  - 


their  inheritance  of  land  Qine  21,  column  2),  and  therefore  the  expanded-Pareto 
criterion  no  longer  applies.  If,  however,  one  assumes  that  the  utility  of 
all  the  siblings  is  positive,  and  if  all  their  utility  functions  are  concave, 
the  additional  sibling  would  mean  a  net  welfare  gain  to  the  people  constituting 
the  original  nuclear  family  Cline  25 j  column  2)  and  thence— by  the  expanded 
Pareto  criterion—to  the  society  as  a  whole.  But  if  one  assimes  that  utility 
can  be  negative,  no  such  conclusions  can  be  drawn.   And  of  course  the  per- 
capita-income  effect  is  negative  Qine  23)  . 

Now  let  us  leave  idealized  subsistence  agriculture  and  move  to  the 
more  interesting,  but  still  simple,  case  in  which  the  additional  person 
enters  the  labor  force  but  where  all  markets  are  competitive  and  the  individual 
Is  paid  his  marginal  output  (column  3) .  From  the  standpoint  of  average 
Income,  the  rest  of  the  community  as  a  whole  benefits  from  the  added  person's 
presence  (lines  35,  37,  39,  column  3)  as  Berry  and  Soligo  (1969)  have  shown; 
the  nature  of  the  benefit  is  exactly  the  same  as  the  benefit  that  occurs  when 
one  country  opens  trade  with  another  country.  But  assuming  that  the  incre- 
mental person  is  a  worker,  the  population  of  workers  as  a  whole — and  especially 
the  workers  in  the  trade  he  enters—will  have  lower  wages  because  of  him 
Cline  29) .  And  the  average  income  of  the  entire  community  including  the 
additional  person  will  fall  (line  40) .  But  if  one  assumes  that  all  utility 
fimctions  are  positive  and  concave,  then  the  sum  of  the  individual  utilities 
in  the  community  will  be  higher  than  before,  because  total  output  will  be 
greater  (line  42) .  So  again  we  see  that  even  for  a  single  period — his 
adulthood— and  in  the  simplest  case  of  no  externalities  and  no  inheritances, 
the  welfare  effect  of  an  incremental  individual  can  be  judged  differently 


-  9  - 


from  different  points  of  view.  And  if  one  now  wlsh.es  to  coiaBine  the  judgments 
about  the  welfare  effect  of  the  added  person  during  his  childhood  and  during 
his  adulthood  together,  the  results  are  even  more  mixed. 

We  shall  here  end  the  story  of  the  man  who  does  not  affect  society 
beyond  his  family,  either  during  or  after  his  lifetime,  with  positive  or 
negative  savings  of  any  kind,  except  by  working  in  a  perfect  market. 


III.   EXTEBNALITIES  DURING  HIS  LIFETIME  AND 
BEFORE  RIS  CHILDREN'S  ADULTEOOD 

In  societies  that  have  advanced  economically  beyond  family  subsistence 
agriculture,  an  incremental  child  usually  causes  effects  external  to  the 
family.  These  externalities  can  be  distinguished  into  two  sorts:   those 
whose  effects  can  be  appraised  and  compensated  for  by  way  of  markets,  and 
those  that  cannot.  Tlie  former  are  treated  in  the  next  section,  and  the 
latter  are  treated  in  the  section  after  that. 

Where  There  Are  Compensable  Externalities 

The  main  "compensalile"   externalities  are  in  the  labor  market,   and  in 
social-welfare  expenditures,    e.g.   s<ihooling.        Hie  nature  of  the  effect 
through  the  entrance  into   the  labor  force  of  an  additional  worker  would  be 
difficult  to  agree  upon.     But  both  the  labor-force  and  social-welfare  effects 
of  additional  children  are  calculable  in  principle  even  if  we  cannot  now 
agree  on  how  to  calculate  them.     Standard  welfare-economics  argtanents  suggest 


>-jf'    in. 


;! 


-  10  - 


that  the  total  utility  of  all  adults  in  a  society  at  a  given  time  will  be 
maximized  if  families  pay  for  all  the  services  used  in  raising  children, 
and  to  neutralize  any  labor-market  effect.  That  is,  if  one  considers  a 
median-income  faniily  with  more  than  the  average  number  of  children,  it  would 
pay  taxes  to  cover  Che  "extra"  child-raising  services  plus  the  labor- 
market  effect  of  the  "extra"  children.  The  proof  of  the  optimality  of  this 
policy  is  the  same  as  that  for  other  cases  of  external  effects,  as  shown  in 
a  simple  way  by  Coase  (1960) .  As  long  as  the  parents  pay  the  full  market 
value  of  these  external  effects,  a  larger  number  of  children  produced  by  a 
family  cannot  be  said  to  reduce  community  utility.  And  after  the  labor- 
force  and  social-welfare  externalities  are  taken  care  of,  and  the  utility  of 
existing  adults  may  be  assumed  to  be  maximizedj  the  expanded  Pareto  criterion 
again  may  be  applied;  after  compensation  no  one  except  older  siblings  would 
be  made  worse  off  by  the  added  person  (line. 14,  column  7-10).  Hence,  if  the 
additional  person's  utility  is  assumed  to  be  positive  (and  with  respect  to 
the  first  child  only) ,  parents  stop  having  children  before  the  community's 
welfare  would  be  roaxijnized,  by  the  same  argument  as  was  given  earlier.   (If  the 
added  person's  utility  is  not  assumed  to  be  positive,  or  if  other  children 
in  the  family  are  considered,  no  such  conclusion  can  be  drawn.) 

A  technical  difficulty  which  turns  into  a  major  political  problem 
arises  with  respect  to  compensable  externalities,  however.  It  is  all  very 
well  to  talk  of  parents  paying  nov;  for  the  future  effects  of  their  children. 
But  such  payments  would  have  to  be  discounted  for  futurity.  The  community 
would  have  to  decide  on  an  appropriate  discount  rate,  because  economic  logic 
alone  reveals  none  (or  a  multitude  of  them) .  Even  if  the  community  were  to 


OJ 


; 


•.>J 


•■ri'f    i  '•'!  f- 


^^■;^■    :;■  J    :if:T 


:>!.,-. 


'  ■•    "■•■■      ..  >i:.,.   •■:lfi 


~  11  - 


eventually  arrive  at  agreement  on  such  a  discount  rate,  there  would  be  maji>r 
conflicts  of  interest.  Old  people  without  children  would  want  a  low  discount 
rate  and  high  sums  paid  immediately.  Parents  with  ciany  children  would  want 
the  opposite.   It  might  be  suggested  that  the  externalities  be  paid  for  as 
they  occur;  this  might  work  for  schooling  and  medical  care,  but  it  would 
not  be  feasible  for  the  children's  labor-force  effect.   So,  because  of  this 
discount-rate  problem,  together  with  the  difficulty  of  estimating  the  future 
effects  of  the  children,  it  is  quite  possible  that  the  community  would  not 
arrive  at  agreement  on  an  externality-neutralizing  agreement.  If  so,  it 
would  not  be  possible  for  an  additional  child  to  effect  a  Paretian  welfare  Increase, 
and  the  total  cumulative  effect-in  his  childhood  plus  his  adulthood-is  Parentian 
Indeterminate  (line  14,  columns  11-14)  .  And  if  externalities  are  not 
neutralized,  the  welfare  effect  by  a  total-utility  criterion  is  also  indeter- 
minate during  his  adulthood,  and  hence  indeterminate  for  his  life  as  a  whole 
(lines  12  an.d  43  >  columns  11-14)  . 

Now  let  us  consider  the  per-capit a-i ncome  effect  of  an  additional 
individual  where  there  are  externalities  in  child-services  and  labor  markets. 
The  classical  diminishing-returns  analysis  (same  total  capital  and  more  labor 
yields  a  smaller  average  product)  tells  us  that  the  effect  is  negative  during 
his  adulthood,  as  it  was  during  his  childJriood,  and  the  Berry-Soligo  analysis 
does  not  alter  this  conclusion.  But  in  the  more-developed  world,  it  is  not 
only  possible  but  likely  (Kuznets  1960,  Simon,  19  71)  that  after  some  time 
in  the  labor  force  an  additional  person  will  cause  enough  new  knowledge  and 
enough  economics  of  scale  so  that  per-capita  income  is  higher  than  it  v;ould 
otherwise  be.   If  so,  by  a  per-capita  income  welfare  standard  the  additional 


-  12 


person's  effect  is  positive  for  at  least  the  latter  part  of  his  adulthood 
(column  15) •  And  the  effect  may  be  sufficiently  great  to  make  his  lifetime 
effect  positive  (line  4i,  column  15).  But  given  that  per-capita  income  is 
lower  during  his  childhood  because  of  him»  to  reckon  the  lifetime  per-capita- 
Income  effect  one  would  have  to  specify  the  effects  for  each  year  and  choose 
a  discount  rate.  A  high  enough  discount  rate  could  of  course  be  chosen  so 
that  the  later  positive  effect  would  matter  little,  and  hence  the  lifetime 
effect  would  be  negative.  But  with  a  lower  discount  rate  the  lifetime 
effect  might  well  be  positive  if  there  are  positive  externalities  from 
knowledge  and  economies  of  scale  during  the  additional  person's  adulthood — 
as  there  Is  reason  to  believe  there  are. 

Non-Market  Externalities  and  Community  Values 

Still  confining  the  discussion  to  the  lifetime  of  the  additional 
person,  let  us  now  consider  externalities  that  realistically  would  not  be 
compensated  through  taxes  and  subsidies. 

As  Professor  Arrow  has  made  clear,  there  may  be  "a.   difference  between 
the  ordering  of  social  states  according  to  the  direct  consumption  of  the 
Individual  and  the  ordering  when  the  individual  adds  his  general  standards  of 
equity  (or  perhaps  his  standards  of  pecuniary  emulation)."   (1951-1969, 
p.  153).  The  latter  states  Arrow  calls  "values",  la  contrast  to  the  former 
which  he  labels  "tastes".  And  the  "market  mechanism. .. takes  Into  account 
only  the  ordering  to  tastes".  Hence  it  may  be  appropriate  for  the  community, 
acting  together „  to  make  such  laws  -  which  may  include  taxes  on  or  subsidies 
for  children  -  as   will  achieve  the  sort  of  society  that  its  members  want. 
For  example,  someone  might  suggest  that  the  community  hold  a  referendum  as 


lo 


!..'> 


-  13  - 


to  whether  there  should  be  a  tax  of  100  shekels,  say,  on  parents  for  each 
child  after  the  third.  People  might  rationally  vote  for  such  a  measure  if 

they  believe  that  a  lower  birth  rate  will  increase  the  rate  of  economic 

8 
development  and  if  they  put  a  positive  value  on  economJ.c  development;  or  if 

they  believe  that  infant  mortality  will  decrease  if  each  family  has  fewer 

children  and  they  get  disutility  out  of  neighbor's  children  dying;  or  if  they 

get  disutility  out  of  other  people's  children,  e.g.  because  of  the  noise;  or 

other  reasons.   If  people  vote  unanimously  for  the  tax  it  would  imply  that 

each  person  would  be  willing  to  have  fewer  ciiildren  if  his  neighbors  also  had 

f^jer  children. 

Similarly,  a  community  mj.ght  have  a  positive  value  for  a  larger 

number  of  children  in  the  community  than  people  otherwise  choose  to  bear, 

given  their  ovm  tastes.   Israel  may  be  an  example:   Je^s  there  may  feel  that 

the  continuation  of  the  historical  tradition  and  the  values  of  Judaism  can  be 

better  served  by  more  people  rather  than  fewer,  and  they  may  be  prepared  to 

vote  subsidies  to  children,  just  as  a  man  may  try  to  bribe  Ms  married  son 

to  have  more  children  to  carry  on  the  family  name.  If  people  get  positive 

utility  out  of  their  neighbors'  children  and  so  vote,  a  subsidy  on  children 

would  be  indicated.   Or,  people  may  believe  that  a  larger  population  will 

contribute  to  economic  growth  within  a  short  enough  time  span  so  that  their 

subjective  discount  rate  (which  might  be  zero,  as  was  Frank  Ramsey's)  will 

make  the  immediate  social  costs  less  than  the  discounted  benefits;  this  is 

now  the  state  of  belief  in  Australia,  as  it  was  in  the  Western  United  States 

in  the  past. 


14 


The  mechanism  for  decision — majority  vote  or  monarchy  or  whatever-==^' 
will  depend  upon  the  group's  constitution.  Any  population  policy  may  then  be 
consistent  with  welfare  economics ,  if  voted  in  accordance  with  the  constitution. 
The  likeliest  cause  of  distortion  with  respect  to  a  democratic  constitution 
is  a  population  policy  initiated  and  executed  by  bureaucrats  who  impose  their 
own  values  upon  the  community  while  asserting  that  the  rationale  for  the 
policy  is  the  "scientific"  finding  that  the  policy  in  question  is  "provedly" 
better  than  non-interference  and  governmental  neutrality  with  respect  to 
parental  decisions  about  family  size.  I  believe  that  this  danger  is  great 

because  the  officials  or  legislators  may  not  recognize  that  their  beliefs 

9 

and  values  are  values  and  beliefs  and  are  not  scientifically  proven  truths. 

In  the  past  decade  so  many  scientists  have  made  it  clear  that  they  favor  lower 
birth  rates  that  one  can  easily  come  to  think  that  lower  birth  rates  have 
Indeed  been  shown  to  be  scientifically  better  for  society  in  every  way,  though 
in  fact  no  such  finding  has  been  or  could  be  scientifically  arrived  at 
because  of  the  value  considerations  involved. 

IV.  EFFECTS  AITER  THE  ADDED  PERSON'S  LIFETIME 

Jtjst  as  a  person  may  affect  his  society  for  good  or  bad  during  his 
lifetime,  so  may  he  have  effects  after  he  dies.  Economists  are  accustomed 
to  dismissing  very-long-run  effects  because  of  their  small  weight  in  calcula- 
tions made  with  interest  rates  of  15%,  10%,  or  even  5%.  But  the  society  itself 
is  more  ambivalent  about  the  long-run  future  and  sometimes  gives  relatively  heavy 
weight,  as  the  current  environmental  controversy  shows.    It  may  well  be  that  the 


.j; :  I . 


.'  J  r: 


-  15  - 


average  man's  total  effects  on  posterity  are  more  important  than  his  total 
effects  on  his  contemporaries — ^who  are,  after  all,  smaller  in  number  than  his 

posterity. 

There  are  many  sorts  of  effects  one  can  have  on  posterity.   The 
simplest  and  most  surely  positive  is  the  savings  that  one  leaves  to  his 
heirs;  usually  they  exceed  his  debts,  as  we  know  from  the  fact  that  society's 
total  capital  generally  grows  over  time.  One  may  also  leave  knowledge  behind 
him; ■'"■'■  the  knowledge  might  be  satanic,  but  usually  knowledge  is  positive  for 
the  economy,  as  we  know  from  the  higher  rate  of  productivity  now  than  in 
former  millenia.   Still  another  effect  is  the  children  that  the  added  person 
leaves.  At  first  the  effect  of  children  seems  very  complicated.  But  consider 
that  the  effect  of  each  child  is  expected  to  be  the  same  as  the  effect  of  the 
added  parent  aside  from  his  children.   Therefore,  the  welfare  judgment  one 
makes  about  the  added  person  is  not  changed  by  his  having  children — aside 
from  their  different  positions  in  history,  of  course,  which  can  be  ignored 
unless  there  is  special  information  about  the  course  of  history. 

Another  post-life  factor  is  the  delayed  efconomies-of-scale  effect 
associated  with  the  creation  of  additional  infra-structure,  and  with  changes 
in  the  nature  of  society— perhaps  especially  in  less-developed  countries. 
Aa   an  example,  the  population-density-induced  changes  in  land-tenure  laws 
and  cropping  systems  shown  to  occur  by  Boserup  (1965)  can  have  long-run 
IKJSitlve  effects  on  productivity.  " 

Let  us  now  get  more  specific  in  welfare  terms.  If  the  added  man 
leaves  anything  at  all  to  posterity  and  if  he  has  no  children — that  is,  if 
his  contribution  to  subsequent  economic  growth  exceeds  his  contribution  to 


-  16 


population  growth,  then  his  welfare  effect  on  posterity  is  positive  (column  16, 
lines  48  and  50) .  If  he  does  have  children,  and  he  and  his  lineage  add 
proportionately  more  to  saving  than  to  population  growth,  then  the  effect 
on  per  capita  income  of  posterity  is  positive.   If  he  and  his  heirs  each 
leave  something  positive,  but  what  they  leave  contributes  less  (marginally) 
to  growth  than  this  lineage  contributes  to  population  growth,  the  effect 
on  posterity  then  is  negative  in  terms  of  per  capita  income  unless  during  his 
lifetime  he  contributed  greatly  in  knowledge  and  otherwise.  In  such  a  case, 
the  effect  in  terms  of  total  utility  is  likely  to  be  positive,  however,  given 
a  reasonable  distribution  of  income  and  no  negative  utilities.  If  the 
additional  individual  leaves  a  negative  inheritance,  then  his  effect  on 
posterity  is  negative. 

Each  of  the  sorts  of  impacts  classified  above  could  be  combined  with 
Impacts  of  the  same  or  opposite  sign  in  earlier  periods;  if  the  latter,  the 
overall  evaluation  of  the  added  man's  welfare  impact  is  indeterminate  without 
numerical  specifications  of  all  impacts  and  an  explicit  choice  of  discount 
rates . 

One  might  ask  whether  the  possibility  of  a  positive  inheritance,  and 

expecially  an  inheritance  proportionately  as  large  as  the  population  growth 

12 

he  causes,  is  just  a  theoretical  nicety  wiiich  may  be  disregarded.    I  think 

the  answer  is  clearly  "No,"  the  inheritance  effect  may  not  be  disregarded. 
In  less-developed  countries,  of  which  pre~20th  century  China  is  the  best 
documented  example  at  present,  per~capita  income  remained  at  much  the  same 
level  secularly  over  700  years,  though  it  sank  seriously  during  some  periods 
of  rapid  population  growth.  This  suggests  that  the  added  person  set  in 


u 


U.TCi     '■  I  _      iO 


■1":  o 


-  17  - 


motion  trains  of  events  that  increased  saving  temporarily.  And  at  some  time 
later,  posterity  was  no  worse  (by  a  per-capita~income  test)  for  the  added 
person's  having  lived.  On  the  other  hand,  it  is  also  possible  that  in  some 
places  increased  population  keeps  an  economy  in  stagnation,  preventing  change 
and  improvement. 

In  more-developed  countries  there  is  secular  growth  in  per  capita  income. 
If  population  had  not  grown  to  something  like  present  population  size,  con- 
temporary per-person  income  would  be  far  lower  in  more-developed  countries  than 
it  now  is.  That  is,  people  leave  an  amount  of  productive  power  to  the  next 

generation  that  is  proportionally  greater  Cperhaps  two  or  three  times 

13 
greater)  than  the  population  increase  they  leave  behind.    This  means  that 

the  added  man  could  leave  aii  inheritance  considerably  smaller  than  average 

and  still  leave  proportionally  more  than  the  population  growth  his  lineage 

contributes , 

This  raises  the  question  of  whether  the  added  man  would  contribute 

an  inheritance  anywhere  near  as  great  as  the  average  person  would  contribute 

without  him,  i.e.  whether  the  marginal  contribution  to  posterity  is  far  below 

the  average  contribution.  First  of  all,  there  is  no  reason  to  suppose  that 

he  himself  is  less  endowed  with  intelligence  or  chance  in  life  than  is  the 

average  person,  unless  one  assumes  that  he  is — and  I  can  think  of  no  special 

reason  for  assuming  so.  If  his  endowment  is  average,  then  the  only  factor 

causing  him  to  lower  the  average  inheritance  would  be  the  lesser  physical 

and  educational  capital  endowment  per  person  at  labor  force  entry  that 

population  growth  probably  implies.  Given  that  the  average  rate  of  inheritance 

in  more-developed  countries  is  much  greater  than  the  rate  of  population  growth 

(in  proportional  terms) ,  this  classical  capital-diluting  effect  could  be 


■  C    I  ./    1 


'>  ..'...  I . 


18  - 


of  sizable  magnitude  without  making  the  marginal  inheritance  smaller  than 
the  population  growth  contributed  by  the  added  person.  Furthermore,  there  are 
very  solid  reasons  to  agree  with  Kuznets,  as  noted  earlier »  that  the  knowledge 
and  economies -of-scale  effects  lead  to  a  higher  per-capita  income  before  the 
end  of  his  work  life  than  if  he  had  not  been  born.   If  so,  the  average 
Inheritance  left  at  the  time  of  his  death  will  be  greater  than  if  he  had 
not  been  born,  which  is  a  positive  effect  on  posterity  by  any  welfare  test. 
Of  course  this  happy  result  is  much  less  likely  in  a  less-developed  country 
than  in  a  more-developed  country,  but  this  only  proves  once  again  the 
impossibility  of  making  sound  _a  priori  welfare  judgments  about  population 
effects  without  detailed  specification  of  the  conditions,  asstjmptions ,  and 
criteria. 

V.   SUMMARY  AND  CONSLUSIONS 

•     There  is  no  single  calculable  welfare  effect  of  an  additional  person. 
The  welfare  effect  depends  upon  which  point  in  Iiis  life-cycle  one  refers  to, 
whether  he  is  expected  to  have  a  positive  effect  upon  his  particular  sort  of 
economy  and  society  during  and  after  his  lifetime,  and  most  of  all, 
on  the  kind  of  welfare  function  used.  Furthermore,  no  matter  which 
welfare  function  is  used,  the  welfare  effect  of  an  added  individual 
summarized  oyer  time  is  even  more  sensitive  to  the  particular  assumtpions 
made. 


Footnotes 

1.  Here  and  elsewhere  in  this  paper  it  is  assumed  that  children  are  brought 
into  life  because  their  parents  desire  them,  and  no  more  children  are 
born  than  parents  want.   To  persuade  the  doubter  of  the  reasonableness 
of  this  assumption  takes  more  evidence  and  argument  than  I  have  room 
for  here.   The  interested  reader  may,  however,  consider  Firth  (1939, 

pp.  36-37),  Carr-Saunders,  (1922,  p.  230),  Krzywicki  (193A),  or  my 
suirvey  (Simon,  1971a).  The  monetary  and  psychic  costs  of  controlling 
fertility  are  ignored  here.   I  also  ignore  non-economic  welfare  benefits 
such  as  the  value  of  liberty. 

2.  Notice  that  the  grounds  used  here  to  reach  this  conclusion  are  quite 
different  than  the  grounds  on  which  Phelps  (1969)  reached  a  somewhat 
similar  conclusion  from  a  welfare  function  that  would  maximize  utility 

of  the  parental  generation.   His  grounds  were  essentially  a  Berry-Soligo- 
type  International- trade  argument  plus  consideration  of  savings  ratios. 
3.'  Now  in  a  matter  that  may  be  passed  over  by  all  except  the  most  demanding 
reader:   In  a  full  formal  treatment  it  is  necessary  to  distinguish  between 
(i)  the  utility  that  the  parents  get  from  the  utility  the  children  get 
from  consigning  resources,  and  (ii)  the  utility  of  the  children  to  the 
parents  for  the  parents'  own  sake.   The  distinction  might  be  phrased  as 
the  difference  between  the  parent's  utility  from  the  parent's  "consumption" 
cf  the  child,  and  the  parent's  utility  from  the  child's  own  consumption. 
For  example,  a  father  takes  pleasure  in  his  newborn  son,  it  would  seem, 
not  because  he  believes  that  the  child  now  enjoys  life,  but  for  the 
father's  own  sake.  On  the  other  hand,  it  is  clear  that  parents  can  feel 


■J    .;  ■ 


.'    :,.,  <..i 


,f."-.   -f   '.    .   '■- 


*!':■  :    t;     .■     » ■■:.:> T-r.T    .  :ii/ 


' :'     it     ,  hnj- 


happy  because  they  believe  that  the  children  are  happy,  e.g.,  the 
sensation  the  parent  feels  as  the  child  eats  a  piece  of  cake.   "I  feel 
happy  for  you"  is  the  expression  we  use  to  describe  this  situation.   I 
shall  assume  that  the  utility  a  parent  gets  from  the  utility  the  child 
derives  from  consumption  of  the  Income  the  child  uses  is  less  than  the 
child's  own  utility  from  that  consumption.   This  need  not  be  true  a  priori, 
of  course.   A  parent  might  believe  very  strongly  in  the  value  and  im- 
portance and  joy  of  life,  and  hence  bring  a  child  into  the  world  despite 
the  fact  that  the  parent  himself  does  not  expect  to  get  any  personal 
pleasure  from  beholding  the  child,  but  on  the  contrary,  expects  the 
child  to  be  only  a  burden  to  the  parent.   If  in  fact  that  child  also  gets 
little  joy  from  his  life,  one  could  imagine  that  the  child's  positive 
utility  is  less  than  the  parent's  negative  utility  from  the  child,  giving 
a  net  negative  balance.   But  it  seems  reasonable  to  me  that  a  parent 
•generally  gets  less  utility  from  a  child's  constanption  of  resources  than 
does  the  child  himself,  which  justifies  this  assumption.   I  am  painfully 
aware  that  this  distinction  is  vague,  perhaps  impossible  to  measure 
sensibly,  and  at  least  bordering  on  the  metaphysical.   But  one  cannot 
get  around  such  a  distinction  unless  one  wishes  to  assume  that  the  parent's 
utility  from  the  child  is  ail  his  own.  pleasure  of  the  senses  in  "consuming" 
the  child,  rather  than  "indirect"  utility  derived  from  the  child's 
pleasure  in  life.   And  if  one  does  wish  to  so  assume,  all  conclusions 
of  this  paper  are  the  same  as  otherwise,  and  are  arrived  at  even  more 
directly. 


4.  Such  an  assumption  is  not  at  ail  inconsistent  with  the  Friedman-Savage 
hypothesis,  as  those  authors  themselves  agree  (1952). 

5.  I        think  that  the  notion  of  negative  utility  is  quite  indefensible 
after  a  person  is  old  enough  to  maVce  serious  choices,  for  technical  and 
empirical  (as  well  as  moral)  reasons.  Meade's  concept  (1955,  Chapter  VI) 
of  a  "welfare-subsistence  level"  of  income,  below  which  a  person  is  as- 
sumed to  have  negative  utility,  is  inconsistent  with  consumer-preference 
theory.  By  the  standard  logic  of  consumer-preference  theory,  the  avail- 
able evidence  tells  us  plainly  that  life  does  have  positive  value,  be- 
cause people  almost  invariably  choose  life  in  preference  to  death,  no 
matter  what  their  economic  circumstances.  Life  seems  to  have  more  value 
than  does  death  for  a  destitute  toothless  widowed  crone  who  lives  —  until 
the  police  evict  her  —  in  a  rag-and-newspaper  tent  by  the  side  of  the 
road  in  India,  just  as  your  life  seems  to  have  value  for  you.  The  rate 

of  suicide  is  everywhere  sufficiently  low  that  it  is  clearly  an  exception 
when  life  ceases  to  have  positive  value.  Therefore,  to  assume  that  some 
people  are  sufficiently  poor  that  their  lives  have  negative  value  is 
quite  incompatible  with  the  basic  concept  of  modern  economics:   That 
which  is  chosen  is  defined  to  be  better.   Without  this  concept  all  modern 
welfare  economics  falls  apart.   This  should  be  reason  enough  to  eschew 
Meade's  point  of  view  in  a  discussion  of  welfare  economics.  But  for  me 
as  for  many  others,  the  positive  value  of  all  human  life,  adults  and 
children,  too,  is  also  a  point  of  faith. 
5a.  If  he  is  paid  his  marginal  output,  there  is  some  increase  in  total 
productivity  minus  his  consumption.  Hence,  total  saving  will  rise 
somewhat,  but  this  can  be  disregarded  for  now. 


,.,;•>■;    vf':A. 


J  ( '  I :;    »• ,, 


';.;  (■:   y) 


WSiiOoi^     (1 5 


'JIU-    -J.    -       i-    .1         ■*< 


'.,..,'    t  ;.'  .';>n    ,  ;. 


:-;j'';    ,,  '  ;v    1 


•■■...f|i    TV),     -.m:"  -^i 


6.  I  assume  here  that  the  society  charges  the  full  cost  for  all  consumption 
products,  including  the  cost  of  physical  pollution  prevention  and  removal. 
This  assumption  may  be  well  on  the  way  to  becoming  fact. 

7.  This  includes  the  use  of  natural  resources  as  raw  materials  in  production, 
and  is  supported  by  the  finding  by  Barnett  and  Morse  (1963)  of  no  increase 
in  natural-resource  scarcities.  The  over-all  basis  for  the  positive 
effect  of  more  people  in  more-developed  countries  is  the  "residual," 
which  at  once  sums  up  the  effects  of  natural  resources,  knowledge,  and 
economics  of  scale.  For  a  quantitative  estimate  of  the  interaction  of 
this  force  with  the  classical  capital-dilution  effect,  see  Simon  (1971). 

One  might  argue  that  the  concept  of  GNP,  which  underlies  all  previous 
reckoning,  does  not  measure  over-all  economic  utility  sufficiently  well, 
because  it  leaves  out  some  "quality  of  life"  features.  Perhaps  so. 
But  in  the  absence  of  calculations,  or  at  least  cogent  reasoning,  about 
the  results  of  using  the  wider  measure,  there  is  no  reason  to  assume  the 
results  would  be  different  in  any  particular  way  from  work  based  on  GNP. 

8.  Please  notice  that  though  the  effects  people  are  interested  in  may  occur 
after  the  added  person's  lifetime  is  over,  the  values  of  other  people 
are  held  and  acted  upon  during  (or  before)  his  lifetime.   Hence  the 
placement  of  this  discussion  in  this  section. 

9.  "There  is  a  personal  bias  that  colors  one's  view  of  the  (relatively) 
poor  which  comes  from  appraising  others*  Incomes  against  the  standard 
of  one's  own  aspirations.  This  bias  is  Implicit  in  many  conventional 
economic-welfare  judgments,  and  it  seems  to  me  to  be  both  indefensible 
and  in  fact  without  defenders.   This  is  merely  shoddy  practice,  not 
doctrine."   (Weeks tein,  1962,  p.  137.) 

10.  Many  of  the  long-run  worries  of  the  contemporary  environmentalists  may 
not  be  real  threats,  of  course,  as  was  the  coal  shortage  foreseen  by 
Jervons  (1865).  The  point  here  is,  rather,  the  social  discount  rate. 


..'ii'.l 


fyiti'^r'  l^'A/'X-     v^^; 


7l>0.^r-57  if:f:..i    :,.,;■•••"     ■'! 


vvii 


11.  The  argument  that  some  classes  of  people  are  likely  to  contribute  to 
knowledge,  while  others  are  not,  will  not  be  considered  here.  One  reason 
is  that,  as  a  first  approximation,  this  paper  assumes  the  same  proportional 
change  in  fertility  for  all  classes  of:    the  society;  this  is  certainly 

not  unrealistic  for  the  U.S.,  where  the  poor  clearly  do  not  account  for 
most  of  population  growth.  A  second  reason  is  that  I  have  been  persueded 
by  Kuznets'  argument  (private  communication)  that  all  segments  of  a 
society  are  crucially  implicated  in  the  growth  of  knowledge,  and  not 
just  the  intellectual  elite. 

12.  In  fact,  the  opposite  possibility  — •  that  more  people  nO'W  mean  a  negative 
inheritance  for  the  future  —  is  simply  assumed  by  such  writers  as 
Meade  (1955)  and  Votey  (1969). 

13.  Growth  theory  assumes  that  savings  equal  population  growth.   But  the 
life  cycle  is  usually  not  distinguished  into  parts  in  such  growth 

. analysis,  so  that  work  can  mostly  be  disregarded  here. 


References 
Harold  J.  Barnett  and  Chandler  Morse,  Scarcity  and  Growth:  The  Economics 

of  Natural  Resource  Availability  (Baltimore:  Johns  Hopkins,  1963). 
R.  Albert  Berry  and  Ronald  Soligo,  "Some  Welfare  Aspects  of  International 

Migration,,   Journal  of  Political  Economy,  Vol.  77,  September/Octoberj 

1969,  pp.  778-794. 
Ester  Boserup,  The  Conditions  of  Agricultural  Growth  (Chicago:   Aldine,  1955). 
A.  M.  Carr-Saunders,  The  Population  Problem:   A  Study  in  Human  Evolution 

(Oxford:   OUP,  1922). 
Colin  Clark,  Population  Growth  and  Land  Use  (New  York:   St.  Martins,  1967). 
Ronald  H.  Coase,  "The  Problem  of  Social  Cost,"  Journal  of  Law  and  Economics, 

Vol.  3,  October,  1960,  pp.  1-44. 
P.  S.  Dasgupta,  "On  the  Concept  of  Optimum  Population,"  The  Review  of 

Economic  Studies,  XXXVI,  July  1969,  pp,  295-318. 
Paul  R.  Ehrlich,  The  Population  Bomb  (New  YorkJ  Ballantlne,  1968). 
Raymond  Firth,  Primitive  Polynesian  Economy  (London:   Routledge  Kegan, 

1939,  1965). 
Milton  Friedman  and  Leonard  J.  Savage,  "The  Expected-Utility  Hypothesis 

and  the  Measurabllity  of  Utility,"  Journal  of  Political  Economy, 

60,  December  1952,  pp.  463--?4. 
David  M.  Heer  and  Dean  0.  Smith,  "Mortality  Level,  Family  Size,  and  Popula- 
tion Increase,"  Demography,  Vol.  5,  No.  1,  1968,  pp.  104-121. 
W.  Stanley  Jevons,  The  Coal  Question  (London:  MacMillan,  1865). 
Ludwik  Krzywicki,  Primitive  Society  and  Its  Vital  Statistics  (London: 

MacMillan,  1934). 


(  ,  '  ■■'■ 


,.vir;"MV  ,••    i  ■■■.\:/^ 


ivM 


Simon  Kuznets,  "Population  Change  and  Aggregate  Output,"  in  Universities — 

National  Bureau  of  Economic  Research,  DEMOGRAPHIC  AND  ECONOMIC  CHANGE 

IN  DEVELOPED  C0W5TRIES  (Princet:on:   PUP,  1960),  pp.  324-340, 
David  A.  May  and  David  M.  Heer,  "?on  Survivorship,  Motivation  and  Family 

Size  in  India:   A  Computer  Simulation,"  Population  Studies, 

Vol.  XXII,  July,  1969,  pp.  199-210. 
James  E.  Meade,  The  Theory  of  International  Economic  Policy,  Vol.  II, 

Trade  and  Welfare  (New  York:   Oxford  University  Press,  1935). 
Edmund  S.  Phelps,  "Population  Increase,"  Canadian  Journal  of  Economics, 

Vol.  1,  August,  1968,  pp.  497-518. 
Frank  P.  Ramsey,  "A  Mathematical  Theory  of  Saving,"  The  Economic  Journal, 

38,  (1928),  pp.  543-59.   Reprinted  in  K.  J.  Arrow  and  T.  Scitovsky, 

Reading  in  Welfare  Economics  (Homewood:   Irwin,  1969),  pp.  619-633. 
Julian  L.  Simon,  "The  Effect  of  Population  Growth  on  Per-Worker  Income 

in  More  Developed  Countries,"  mimeo,  1971. 
Julian  L.  Simon,  "The  Effect  of  Economic  Conditions  Upon  Fertility:  Review, 

Analysis,  and  Prediction,"  m.meo,  1971a. 
Harold  L.  Votey,  Jr.,  "The  Optimum  Population  and  Growth:   A  New  Look," 

Journal  of  Economic  Theory,  1,  October,  1969,  pp.  273-290. 
Richard  S.  Weckstein,  "Welfare  Criteria  and  Changing  Tastes,"  American 

Economic  Review,  Vol.  LII,  March,  1962,  pp.  133-153. 


<'<.■*.'. 


■^:\'    :r^;^ 


sVl